2022FHAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 12 (3): 686–700
SPECIAL SECTION: ELEMENTARY WORDS
OF POLITICAL LIFE
Towards a critical ethnography
of political concepts
Anastasia P I L I A V S K Y , King’s College London
Judith S C H E E L E , EHESS: École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales
This special section approaches “politics” from a specifically ethnographic point of view. It does this by privileging ethnographically derived political concepts rather than more familiar preestablished and supposedly universal categories of political analysis. This introduction offers a general theoretical framework for doing this, and establishes a shared language of analysis. It
situates current developments in relation to the history of political anthropology and of the broader discipline, and proposes
a definition of the domain of political anthropology through an emphasis on politics as collective ethics. It then reflects on
the relationship between language and concepts, and the articulation of different “global” hierarchies of value.
Keywords: political anthropology, political theory, concepts, language, hierarchies of value
In 2008, Bjørn Thomassen (2008: 263) pointed towards
a “paradox” in current political anthropology: while the
discipline as a whole had grown increasingly “political,”
political anthropology itself had “faded away,” due to its
“implicit refusal to define the political” as anything other
than life itself (Candea 2011: 310; see also Curtis and
Spencer 2012). Having set aside the excesses of an earlier,
functionalist tradition, and eager to refute it, political
anthropologists since the 2000s have tended to draw primarily on European political theory in their analyses
(Marcus 2008: 61), understood to be more appropriate
for the recognition of power relations on all levels, and
for anthropology’s own difficult position within them.
The very categories that used to be at the heart of political anthropology were now seen as the tools or even the
results of political domination leading to misrecognition
(of power as “authority,” for instance). However productive (and necessary), this shift ultimately resulted in a
conceptual distancing of political anthropology from
ethnography—from the ways in which people, the world
over, conceive and carry out their political lives.
This shift in analytical vocabulary has had two effects.
On the one hand, it has diminished the potential for political anthropology to contribute anything of substance
to political philosophy. Despite calls for “cosmopolitan
political thought” (Godrej 2011) and the growing dissatisfaction with uniquely text-based projects of comparative
political theory (Jenco 2007: 744; Thomas 2010: 672),
few political theorists today look to political anthropology for conceptual insights, even as they are drawn
towards ethnography as a method (Schatz 2009; Longo
and Zacka 2019; Simmons and Smith 2019). On the
other hand, the confidence (or should we say arrogance)
with which midcentury anthropologists dismissed Western political philosophy as Eurocentric folklore (Fortes
and Evans-Pritchard 1940: 4) has vanished. Today, political anthropologists are closer to the historical anthropologists of the 1960s (Cohn 1980), who treated ethnography
as “reservoirs of raw fact” (Comaroff and Comaroff 2012:
114) rather than the source of analytical insights. As a
result, plenty of good ethnography stands alongside, or
is improbably squeezed into, a (rather limited) set of analytical terms derived from Western folk models: state,
liberalism, public sphere, civil society, governmentality,
or whatever else.
Should this have been the case in any other domain, it
would have caused outrage among anthropologists. There
is something about the language of politics, however, that
HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory, volume 12, number 3, winter 2022. © 2022 The Society for Ethnographic Theory. All rights reserved. Published by The
University of Chicago Press for the Society for Ethnographic Theory. https://doi.org/10.1086/723216
687
makes it work differently. As Walter Gallie (1955) noted
long ago, few political concepts are merely descriptive;
most are also evaluative—think of “democracy,” “dictatorship,” “populism”—making any recognition of difference morally suspect. It is thus not surprising that, as
sophisticated as anthropologists are at discerning cultural nuances in religious or economic processes, when
it comes to politics, they often demote deep conceptual
differences to qualifiers of global political institutions
(local variants of the state, democracy, secularism, toleration), or else to a false exoticism that demeans our
interlocutors in the face of putatively universal standards.
The language of politics is in fact made to do double service: to speak of actually occurring political interactions
on the ground, as and how they are defined locally; and
as an analytical metalanguage to describe the power relations within which any field of action is by definition situated. This is not in itself problematic—anthropology, as
a discipline, has long thrived on the scaling of concepts,
and on the intentional blurring of the specific and the
universal, while people in their local politics everywhere
draw on different kinds of metalanguages. Yet these operations need to remain legible. When “politics” as understood ethnographically dissolves into politics as an
overarching analytical stance, specificity is all too easily
seen as obfuscation, as an obstacle to truth.
Here we plead in favor of the opposite approach: to
take the inherently evaluative—and therefore ideological
and ethnographically specific—dimensions of political
language not as a shortcoming, but rather as privileged
entry points into politics on all levels. We proceed from
the premise that all political action is shaped by conceptual thought grounded in fundamental assumptions
about the nature of social relations and moral order, and
ideas about the world as it is and as it ought to be, and
that this should be the starting point of analysis. That
politics is, in other words, encompassed as much as it
is encompassing, and that we need to hold these two
aspects apart analytically even as we acknowledge and
pursue their interdependence. This is not a way of evacuating the histories of struggle and oppression that
make these assumptions what they are, of silencing dissenting voices, or of glossing over the differences and relations of domination they might mask on the ground.
Rather, it is to claim that we cannot understand even the
seemingly most straightforward history of political struggle unless we first pay due attention to the terms in which
it is fought. Some of this is captured in a language of values, whose definition and prioritization Graeber (2013)
TOWARDS A
CRITICAL ETHNOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS
identified as the ultimate goal of political struggle everywhere. Here, we would like to broaden the scope of analysis to the basic assumptions from which these values
derive, and to the terms in which they are debated, rejected,
and transformed.
Our aim, then, is not to merely acknowledge practical political diversity but to understand the conceptual
apparatuses and ethical assumptions that underpin it.
This not so much in order to bring different assumptions into dialogue (thereby ultimately resolving their
difference, as proposed by Dallmayr 2004), nor to state
their irreducible or even “ontological” distinction (which
we do not believe to exist; see also Sopranzetti, this special section). Rather, it is to contrast concepts across
political traditions in an exercise of “reciprocal comparison” (Austin 2007), in order to mutually enrich and
clarify them. Each article in this special section therefore
focuses on one or a set of such concepts as they emerge
from ethnographic research, and attempts elucidate
them, comparatively and with regard to their broader
historical and ethnographic context. These concepts
are not necessarily geographically bounded, as it is in
the nature of (political) language to travel, move and
morph, and to be a nonrespecter of boundaries; and as
few people even in “the West” live their political lives
through the “universal” language of political sciences
or philosophy. Nor are they “local” in any but a contingent sense, as political traditions answer to conceptual
regional hierarchies which in turn impose their own universal aspirations or “substantially different cosmopolitan or transnational projects” (Li 2009: 426). Instead, the
distinction is between currently dominant terms of analysis (whose universal applicability is all too often taken
for granted), and those we are less familiar with (whose
application in any other context than their own sounds
decidedly odd). Paying more attention to the latter, we
hope, will not only help us understand political life
throughout the world in more appropriate terms, but
also enrich and revise current political theory’s limited
range of analytical concepts. After all, as Chris GotoJones (2011: 88) concludes, “taking the rest of the world
seriously might mean exploding current conceptions of
political theory altogether.” We can but try.
Babies and bathwaters
We are not the first to note and regret the conceptual
paucity of current political anthropology (e.g., Spencer
1997; Marcus 2008; Thomassen 2008; Candea 2011),
Anastasia PILIAVSKY and Judith SCHEELE
but it might still be worth asking how and why it came
to this. After all, politics and a budding political anthropology was at the heart of the postwar discipline, at least
in the United Kingdom. Following the publication of
Meyer Fortes and Edward E. Evans-Pritchard’s African
political systems in 1940, “a work that, in a single blow,
established modern political anthropology” (Lewellen
2003: 7), research on indigenous political ideas, processes
and institutions flourished, preoccupying a whole generation of what came to be the founding fathers (more
rarely mothers) of British anthropology.1 And this is
perhaps where it went wrong: political anthropology
became too closely associated with structural functionalism and its classification of political systems in terms
of their presumptive functions, a taxonomic obsession
that Edward Leach famously derided as “butterfly collecting” (1961: 5)—unable, moreover, to see the imperial forest for the ethnographic trees.
Fixating on modeling and typologizing political
“systems,” political anthropology grew more and more
mechanical and “anti-cultural . . . a micro-study of instrumental behaviour” that treated political action as “a
source of social facts at their most thing-like,” in the
process growing so dull that it eventually “died of boredom” (Spencer 1997: 3, 5). Imperial connections, divergent opinions, internal dissent and dynamics of change
had no place in this, and most political anthropologists
of the postwar generation tended to dodge new political
institutions that were all too plain to sight: courts, elections, bureaucrats, political parties, and rallies (Spencer
1997: 3). The Manchester School, despite its clear antiimperial stance and emphasis on process and dispute, did
little to remedy this, mired, as it was for the most part, in
the strongly empiricist assumptions of the extended case
method (Kapferer 2005: 104). As such, political anthropology could not survive the postcolonial turn, having
since been dismissed as at best naïve or (politically) in
the wrong. And so, by the 1980s, there was no “political
anthropology” left to speak of (Lewellen 2003: ix).
Political anthropology rose from the ashes a decade
later, wary of past transgressions, and therefore doubly
keen to adopt a resolutely “modern” outlook. “Modernity” was achieved by heeding Spencer’s warning, and
by turning away from “small-scale” societies and indigenous political institutions towards those exported
1. Developments in the United States and in France were
somewhat different: see Lewellen (2003: 10) for an outline.
688
from Euro-America, centrally the nation-state. Empirically, this was a necessary move because most, if not all,
of the so-called small-scale communities studied in the
heyday of British structural functionalism were in fact
nothing of the kind, but were part of larger, never entirely local, political orders (Asad 1973: 269). Nor were
most of them isolated from state bureaucracies, however hostile relations with these may have been. It does
not, however, follow analytically that all politics everywhere was now encased in the logic of Westphalian
statehood, nor that it was not henceforth possible to
study political life in terms other than those of “the state”
and its satellite processes and institutions (international
organizations, NGOs, civil society activism). Nor should
we forget that many of the concepts that constitute “Western political theory” are themselves the result of long,
entangled, and complex histories, and are therefore
“Western” mostly in name.2
It was thus, paradoxically, calls for the analytical
opening of anthropological theory—for its release from
former certainties and its decolonization—and the
expansion of the range of political anthropology’s subject matter that ultimately generated a drastic closure in
its theoretical vocabulary. This was by no means a necessary outcome of the postcolonial critique: kinship
studies followed a similar trajectory at roughly the same
time, but emerged all the more sensitive to local variation and vocabulary. Nor does a focus on nonstate concepts and institutions necessarily evacuate questions of
power and domination. Yet if, to put it bluntly, by the
2. Anderson (1983) famously showed that the modern
nation-state emerged in the Spanish colonies. Buck-Morss
(2000) argues that the central tenets of Hegel’s political
philosophy were inspired by his initial sympathy for and
sustained interest in the Haitian Revolution. The question
of freedom and inequality was brought into European
Enlightenment debate by Native American thinkers (Graeber and Wengrow 2021: chapter 2). Leibniz, in his late
seventeenth-century musings on “enlightened despotism,”
was deeply influenced by Jesuit reports on China (Lach
1945). Centuries later, Palmer and Winiger (2019) propose
a particularly Chinese trajectory for what they call “neosocialist governmentality.” The list here is potentially endless;
nor is there any reason, of course, to think of somebody
like Machiavelli (who will be further discussed below) as
an “Italian philosopher” any more than as a sixteenthcentury Mediterranean, closer in time and space to Ahmad
al-Mansūr (see Scheele’s contribution to this special collection) than to Thomas Hobbes.
689
1990s post-biological relatedness was seen a cultural
achievement, the state and its acolytes still stood triumphant as markers of political maturity, or even of “modernity” itself (Jonsson 2018: 7).
This peculiar pattern of demise and rebirth might
explain why, as Joel Robbins puts it in his contribution
to this special section, the substantivist/formalist debate
that had kick-started economic anthropology and that
“continues in new guises” today (Hann 2018: 13) never
happened in political anthropology.3 In this debate, the
“formalists” defined economic activity in terms borrowed from the academic discipline of economics (the
market, capitalist production, self-maximizing interest),
while the “substantivists” argued that its terms are set
by a given society’s norms, that the economy is socially
“embedded.” Whatever the outcome of this debate—
the conclusion, mostly, that “all economies are mixed
economies” (Hann 2015: 317)—it meant that all economic anthropologists became aware of the peculiar
provenance of their analytical terms, particularly the historical extraction (or “disembedding,” in Polanyi’s terms)
of “the economy” from otherwise social life in Euroamerica. Louis Dumont, who wrote at length about this
process (1977), noted that “the political” was in fact segregated prior to “the economic” (1971: 32), but attempted
no such genealogy. Nor, to our knowledge, has anybody
else.4 Economic anthropology was moreover fortunate to
have had a founding text, Mauss’s Essai sur le don (1923),
and an apparently easily identifiable topic, “exchange”—
3. If it did—perhaps during the Gluckmann/Bohannan debate in the 1960s about the applicability or otherwise of
“Western” legal terminology in other contexts—it certainly
did not have the same lasting impact on the discipline.
4. With the exception, perhaps, of Lefort (1986) and
Mouffe (1993). In his (in)famous formulation of The
concept of the political (Der Begriff des Politischen,
1932), Carl Schmitt attempted to do the exact opposite:
he assumed that there always had been an autonomous
political domain, and that it needed to be defended
against recent developments, primarily that of the welfare state (or “liberalism” more generally). His ideas were
highly influential, not least through the fascination they
exerted, among others, on Hannah Arendt. All of these
authors’ reflections on “the political,” however, are substantially different from ours, inasmuch as they are normative. We are, instead, calling for a closer ethnographic
and historical attention to how and where the political
might (or might not) be constituted as an autonomous
domain, and what the implications of this are.
TOWARDS A
CRITICAL ETHNOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS
both comparable to and different from market transactions—from which to launch its substantivist challenge.5
“Politics” or “the political” is nothing as cogent an idea as
the market or even exchange, and there has never been
clarity among scholars of politics, nor even explicit discussion, much less agreement on what politics actually is.
“Politics” is as hazy an idea in academic writings as it
is in ordinary speech, where “political” can mean anything from things to do with power to matters of state
institutions to being purposefully principled to being,
conversely, unscrupulously instrumental. It is not a coincidence that contemporary political scientists, most of
whom are “formalists,” tend to fall back onto mathematical models developed by economists (rational choice
theory, game theory) to define their subject matter. Political theorists, meanwhile, have long thought of politics
as encompassing everything that a scholar of social life
might see, hence posing problems of definition. Substantivist economists (to return to our comparative case)
cast their net deliberately wide: economics is about how
people provide for themselves or simply the way society
meets their material needs. But what kind of needs, if
any, does politics cater for? Functionalism quickly rises
its ugly head; arguably, looking for political “needs” was
precisely where Fortes and Evans-Pritchard went wrong
in the 1940s. If older anthropologists tended to see in
politics the answer to the universal “problem” of “social
control” (Strathern 1985), today anthropologists think
of it as the domain of “power,” construed along similarly
universal lines. Both answers are redolent of implicit
philosophical assumptions (about human nature and
striving, personhood, social life) whose presumption of
universal validity is deeply problematic.
Power and what it disguises
Notwithstanding, by 2003 even a cautious introduction
to the subject could conclude that “political anthropology . . . consists mainly in the study of the competition
for power, and the way in which group goals are implemented by those possessing power” (Lewellen 2003: 85).
5. Perhaps the fate of political anthropology would have been
different had Mauss produced a companion text on politics. But he did not, or not quite. Mauss’s “La nation”
([1920] 1953–54) remained unfinished and the draft that
does exist makes for dispiriting reading (Fournier 2004).
For a somewhat more enthusiastic response, see Karsenti
(2010).
Anastasia PILIAVSKY and Judith SCHEELE
690
Another popular textbook (Gledhill 1994) put it even
more bluntly: political anthropology is concerned with
Power and its disguises. This was a much-needed corrective at that time, curing anthropological naivety with
regards to the broader geopolitical context of their research (and their own participation in it), as well as
illusions of “happy natives” living in social harmony.
It responded (partially, at least) to feminist, postcolonial,
and decolonial critiques. Ultimately, however, its effect
was both expansive and reductive.
It was expansive, because, following Foucault, power
is “capillary”: it is intrinsic to all social relations and is
indeed what produces them.6 Although Foucault in the
course of his life’s work arguably developed two distinctive notions of power—one all-encompassing, the other
more narrowly concerned with matters of “government”—the two are intimately related, and indeed often
merge, especially in the writings of others who draw on
his work. As Wendy Brown points out, this leaves us,
today, with the necessary work of “delineating anew”
the distinction between power and political life: “theoretical politicization of any activity or relation is not
the same as theorizing the political, just as the presence
of power, precisely because it is everywhere, cannot be
equated with the problem of how we do and ought to
order collective life” (2005: 76). If power is everywhere,
and political anthropology is primarily about power,
then political anthropology dissolves into anthropology
itself; from a subject matter, “politics” becomes an analytical approach, a methodology. As a result, the anthropology of almost anything can now be about “the politics
of . . .” This risks making short shrift of local distinctions
and political aspirations, potentially resulting in a clear
“ethnographic deficit” (Candea 2011: 310).
Reductive, because if politics is primarily about power
relations (“making people do things they otherwise
would not have done” or even “structuring their possible
field of action”), people’s own political ambitions and
projects (anything other than aspiring to power over
others), and the meaning they ascribe to their actions,
can easily appear as an illusion: as “false consciousness”
or misrecognition generated by (symbolic) violence. In
other words, it risks neglecting the assumptions and
principles according to which people order their own
(political) lives, and the social value they might realize
in the process (Graeber 2013: 227, following Turner
1984), however far-fetched and ideologically motivated
these might appear to critical analysts. As a result, “an
unresolved tension persists between attempts to trace
and analyse power across varying scales and contexts,
and attempts to ground description and analysis in
the standpoint of others” (Samanani 2021: 285).7
This tension, however, is primarily of our own making. There clearly is no way in which we can understand
the concepts, principles, and values that underpin the
“standpoint of others” outside the complex histories
of domination, but also of reciprocal engagement, mimicry, negotiation, refusal, and resistance that have produced them. No language, no “ontology” even, is innocent of both far-reaching and intimate power relations
(Castoriadis 1988)—but neither can we understand those
power relations unless we fully grasp what is at stake for
those most concerned. “Power”—just like “politics”—
itself is a concept that is necessarily ethnographically
and historically situated (Archer and Souleles 2021:
198). While anthropological writing thrives on the scaling of concepts, productively blurring the dividing lines
between “vernacular” and “metropolitan” concepts (Fassin 2017: 22–23), between “categories of practice” and
“categories of analysis” (Brubaker and Cooper 2000),
these operations need to be spelled out clearly, and hence
rendered potentially reversible (Curtis and Spencer 2012).
One way to do this is to make our skepticism bear not
only on Fortes and Evans-Pritchard’s functionalism,
but also on the anti-philosophical stance that it implied.
As noted above, Fortes and Evans-Pritchard famously
rejected “Western political philosophy,” dismissing it
as “inductive,” “concerned with how men ought to live
and what form of government they ought to have, rather
than with what are their political habits and institutions” (Fortes and Evans-Pritchard 1940: 4, emphases
in original). While rejecting their functionalism on
the face of it, many political anthropologists have since
followed this empirical stance: political anthropology is
6. Foucault was by no means the only influential writer who
popularized the term “power.” Wolf (1990), for instance,
proposes a fourfold distinction between different kinds
of power. But Foucault’s influence was such that it is virtually impossible today to invoke the word independent
of its Foucauldian interpretation.
7. Ever since Sahlins (1993) first voiced his concern at “the
current neo-functionalism of power,” this observation
has been made repeatedly, even ritually, if only as a way
of sorting “culturalists” from “materialists” (see, e.g.,
Ortner 2016). One of our aims here is to show that this
opposition is unhelpful.
691
about “is” (“power”), not “ought” (“its disguises”)—
while recognizing that “ought” might matter in other
domains, such as “religion” or “ethics.” Here we suggest
a more sustained engagement with “ought” also in the
political realm: we propose to supplement sensitivity to
power relations with an understanding of politics as a
form of ethics, as an evaluative process grounded in an
understanding of the good life as necessarily collective.
This understanding is always shaped by power—“the
moral and ethical domain is a battlefield” (Fassin 2011:
484)—but it cannot be reduced to it; neither can in fact
exist without the other. This would not only sit more
easily with Aristotle’s original conception of “politics,”
but it would also allow us to understand what constitutes and motivates political action (“the labor to live
a good life,” Simpson 2014: ix): to account for values
and principles that orient political pursuits that remain
otherwise unintelligible.
This requires a somewhat different approach to
ethics than that which has recently gained traction in
anthropology and which revolves, following the later
Foucault this time, around the cultivation of virtuous
selves (e.g., Lambek 2010; Laidlaw 2013; Pandian and
Ali 2010). In Fassin’s (2014: 432) words, this “ethical
turn” describes an important and overdue shift from
Kant to Aristotle as a main inspiration, but it neglects
“consequentialism” (the term is Anscombe’s 1958): preoccupation with the social effects of individual action.
In other words, it encourages anthropologists to take
note of Aristotle’s Nichomachean ethics but not his Politics, despite Aristotle’s own insistence that the two be
read together: that Politics is in fact a prelude to Ethics.
This analytical scheme, which sets the individual self as
the ethical telos (structurally, if not always empirically),
reduces broader ethical schemes to the “context” or “audience” (Graeber 2013: 226) of personal striving. It also
marginalizes all sensibilities where individuals do not
feature as elemental evaluative units, as entities that precede social relations. Here collective life, social relations,
and shared ideas are no longer the prerequisite to human
flourishing, but are ancillary to the cultivation of virtuous
selves. Unsurprisingly, such accounts often remain strikingly apolitical (Fassin 2014: 433).
Machiavelli’s two books
The segregation of ethics from politics is frequently
traced to the sixteenth-century thinker Niccolò Machiavelli, whose manual on government, The prince, is widely
TOWARDS A
CRITICAL ETHNOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS
remembered as a treatise on politics as an anti-ethical,
“Machiavellian” realpolitik. In his article in this special
section Robbins too traces the “ontology of power and
conflict” in contemporary social science to Machiavelli,
and his exemption of rulers and the “interest of the state”
from ordinary Christian ethics. Foucault, Robbins writes,
extended this exemption to everybody, thereby making
individual interest the chief ethical pursuit. With every
man now a Machiavellian prince, an “ontology of power
and conflict” becomes the only possible political telos.
But, as a number of scholars have shown, Machiavelli
never advocated the divorce of ethics from politics, and
his contemporaries explicitly recognized him as a “moralist” (Benner 2009: 3). His writing, instead, was marked
by a “strong Socratic element” (Benner 2009: 6): a tendency to expose competing moral arguments and then
leave it to his readers to make up their minds. Among
those ethical stances were Christian virtue ethics, with
its emphasis on the cultivation and salvation of individual souls, and a collective ethics, which stemmed from
antiquity (Berlin 1979: 45). It is only from the perspective
of a self-centered and strangely disembedded Christian
ethics (which Machiavelli clearly privately despised) that
The prince appears perverse.
This ambivalence is reflected in Machiavelli’s two
major books: The prince and Discourses on Livy. In
the latter, which is by far the more substantial of the
two, Machiavelli described in detail what to him was
the most promising model of state, namely the Roman
Republic. The main concern of any political system, he
wrote, ought to be how the elite’s “natural” disposition
(their “humor”) to dominate others could be kept in
check by “the people”; this could partly be done through
a reliance on popular institutions, but at times required
recourse to tyranny (McCormick 2015). In other words,
if The prince was about how to rule, Discourses was about
how to avoid being oppressed. The two books (and different voices within them) adopted two necessarily irreconcilable perspectives; “politics” was situated in the irreducible field of conflict between them. There has been
much debate over the tensions between Machiavelli the
advocate of tyranny and Machiavelli the republican
(Pocock 1975; Skinner 2000), and, more recently, Machiavelli the radical democrat (McCormick 2011; Pedullà
2018), with an occasional reference to Machiavelli the
proto-fascist (Femia 2004). Whatever the outcome of
these debates, their very intractability brings into high relief two concerns that are ever-present in anything that
we may think of as “politics.” One is a concern with
Anastasia PILIAVSKY and Judith SCHEELE
directive action and the other with curbing its excess,
through popular institutions and collective judgment,
which are in turn necessary for living together well—
and which any successful ruler has to take into account,
and, indeed manipulate if he or she wishes to stay in
power. One can never be reduced to the other, and both
pose fundamentally ethical conundrums. Neither, moreover—as Machiavelli forcefully reminds us—can ever be
consensual.
Pace Robbins, Machiavelli, then, in his insistence on
the inherent superiority of collective over individual
judgment (McCormick 2011: 76–77), in fact encourages
us to move away from politics as conceived uniquely
in terms of dyadic power relations, towards politics
conceived of as collective action. We need to grasp both
aspects—“embrace,” as Lefort (2012: 109) argued Machiavelli challenges us to do, “several thoughts at once,”
and articulate the tensions between them. For this, our
tools of analysis must be suitably diversified, combining, on the one hand, a form of critique addressed at
unveiling power relations (which in much current anthropology corresponds to what we have earlier called
“politics as a metalanguage”); on the other, an approach
more closely inspired by genealogical modes of reasoning, a careful reconstruction of the categories of thought,
principles and assumptions that bring institutions into
existence and make it possible for them to evolve collectively (Owen 2002). As David Owen shows, such an approach is equally “critical” inasmuch as it frees us from
“aspectival captivity,” i.e., the assumption that any given
“picture” or “perspective” on the world—the “system”
that governs what counts as true or false—is the only
one possible, or indeed appropriate to the situation at
hand (see also Hage 2012: 287).
Tensions between these two forms of analysis have
given rise to apparently intractable anthropological debates, which hinge not so much on the ethnographic
evidence as on the relevant analytical frame. David
Sneath (2018: 327), for instance, suggests that Malinowski’s Trobriand ethnographies and Evans-Pritchard’s
The Nuer should both be read as accounts of aristocratic
rather than egalitarian political orders. Analyses of Nuer
gender relations had long come to similar conclusions
(McKinnon 2000), while others point quite simply towards the large number of slaves in their ranks (Southall
1976), or to differential access to cattle (Burton 1981) to
render assertions of egalitarianism not only naïve but
quite simply unforgivable. They are right, of course,
but this does not mean that we can simply dismiss both
692
authors’ insistence that the Nuer and the Trobrianders
themselves assert that they are equal—or at least, that
the best of them ought to be so, and that Nuer political
action and rhetoric has to take this into account. Any
notion of equality always implies exclusion on some
level, and what matters here is rather how “the people
who count” (Sneath speaks, somewhat anachronistically,
of “full citizens” [2018: 329]) are defined, and the basis on
which the others (women, slaves, outsiders, clients, the
chronically poor) are defined out (this was of course also
the case in the European democratic archetype of classical Athens; Ismard 2015). In an older anthropological
language, equality in such a setting is prescriptive rather
than descriptive: exceptions are simply defined away.8
This does not mean that the voices of those who are
“defined out” do not count; but rather that we need to
understand precisely what they are deprived of, in their
own terms, and how, and how this fits into broader
assumptions about personhood and collective life.
Answers to this are never just local and immediate,
but require a close attention to regional connections
and history. By the time Evans-Pritchard arrived, the
Nuer had long lived in the periphery of two aggressive
and expansionist empires, Ethiopia to the east (Johnson
1986) and Ottoman Egypt to the north (Sacks 1979),
whose armies came to the region to hunt slaves who
in turn would become soldiers who would come back
to hunt more slaves. The neighboring Shilluk kingdom
had been instrumental in facilitating slave raids (Mercer
1971), but also in procuring iron and other trade goods
for the Nuer (Howell 1947). Nuer insistence on their
own nobility and egalitarianism, their emphasis on martial virtues, their refusal of overall leadership, and their
large-scale practice of slavery, was not directly produced
by this, but needs to be understood, ethnographically
and historically, in this context. Conversely, these values, practices and assumptions clearly informed the subsequent history of the region, including Nuer involvement in the many civil wars that have shaped their
lives, much of which would otherwise be unintelligible
(Jok and Hutchinson 1999).
In a similar fashion, a focus on particular political
imaginaries might help us understand current political
8. For the legal philosopher H. L. A. Hart ([1962] 1994:
187), this is indeed what sets moral rules aside from
others: they might be endlessly broken without ever losing their validity.
693
processes that do not lend themselves to the exclusive
analytical matrix of power struggle, to grasp why people
may act politically in ways that appear to contradict
their “interests” (for more on this term, see Chiriţoiu,
this special section). It helps to see why some of the
American poor vote for the ultrarich like Donald Trump
(Hochschild 2018), why white English voters might consider themselves an “ethnic group” suffering from discrimination (Evans 2012), why South African youths
seek out dependence (Ferguson 2013), why women in
the Middle East pursue what appears like their own oppression (Mahmood 2001), why Thai middle classes
support the military (Sopranzetti, this special section),
why dreams of new-found Ottoman glory draw crowds
in Turkey (Bargu 2021), or why Indian citizens actively
subordinate themselves to politicians (Piliavsky 2014).
Begriffsgeschichte
In this volume, we approach these underlying ideas
through an analysis of political language. Language is
our privileged entry into political concepts, not because
politics is not also or perhaps primarily about actions,
but because language and action are so closely bound
up with each other that we cannot separate them. There
is, in fact, no social reality independent of its vocabulary:
The realities here are practices; and these cannot be
identified in abstraction from the language we use to
describe them, or invoke them, or carry them out . . .
We can speak of mutual dependence if we like, but really what this points up is the artificiality of the distinction between social reality and the language of description of that social reality. The language is constitutive
of the reality, is essential to its being the kind of reality
it is. (Taylor 1971: 24)
Or, from a historian’s perspective, “language does not
simply store experience that outlasts the specific situation: . . . particular languages delimit these experiences”
(Koselleck 1989: 657). Linguistic anthropology has much
to say on this, and recent formulations treat the adjective
“conceptual” as a near-equivalent of “cultural,” and society itself as a “perduring virtual communicative economy”
(Silverstein 2004: 622). This has the great advantage
of replacing a static with a dynamic concept, and showing just how much “beliefs and values” are always “at the
risk of language use” and therefore “sites of struggle, contestation, domination, hegemony, etc.” Yet this approach
TOWARDS A
CRITICAL ETHNOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS
often privileges indexical over denotative content. Here,
we aim to elucidate the complex relationship between
both, by focusing not so much on a detailed analysis of
particular linguistic encounters, but on the use and content of particular political concepts.
The relationship between concepts and language is
never just one of straightforward equation. Words and
concepts rarely align (Skinner 1989). People can entertain a concept without having a word for it (historians
can thus trace back the emergence of “capitalism” without squabbling over etymology); different words can appertain to the same concept; one word might refer to
several concepts (as with “politics” above); and people
often use words that do not refer to any definite corresponding concept. The meaning and reference of a concept, moreover, need to be treated separately: to talk of
badly disguised dictatorships as “democracy” because
sham elections are held once in a while does not change
the meaning of the concept of democracy, but extends
its range of reference in a way that we can recognize
as wrong. To reduce the concept of “democracy” in everyday speech to North Atlantic political systems does not
change its current reference (although one could of
course argue that it does), but profoundly restricts (and
impoverishes) its meaning. In the same way, “the personal is political” is a powerful statement only as long
as the meaning of “political” is held constant. Lastly,
and perhaps most difficult to trace, the meaning and reference of a concept might remain stable, but its “appraisive force”—its moral valence—might change. Concepts might be edgy at times, and harmless at others.
Like language, concepts are never stable. One thing
we can do, and historians have done successfully, is to
trace the emergence of and changes in concepts, which
often happen in periods of transition when these concepts become all the more visible. The literature on the
emergence of the concept of “state” in sixteenth-century
European political thought is a paradigmatic example
here (see Scheele, this special section). This is often more
difficult to do in contexts such as those that interest us
here, where written sources might be scarcer on the
ground, and where the unit of enquiry appears less obviously given than in Western European history (although
there it is mostly an illusion also). However, it is noticeable that some concepts change more quickly than others;
that some words, although proposed by the politically
powerful, never quite catch on for reasons that might
be extrinsic to their meaning; while others, apparently
anodyne ones, start mobilizing people and ideologies
Anastasia PILIAVSKY and Judith SCHEELE
(see, e.g., Keeler, this special section); while others yet
prove remarkably stable over time. The translation of
European political terminology into Thai, described
by Sopranzetti in his contribution to this special section,
provides ample examples of all of the above scenarios.
Koselleck, one of the founding figures of the German
Begriffsgeschichte (conceptual history) project, put this
down to the structural distance between language and
events. “Semantics” and “events” are subject to different
“rates of change”: “language changes more slowly than
does the chain of events that it helps to set in motion
and that it seeks to comprehend” (Koselleck 1989: 660).
Language thus never quite accounts for events; conversely,
nothing happens that is not already changed by its linguistic interpretation (Koselleck 2006: 13). Add to this
the various “games” people might play to legitimize their
interpretation and appraisal of concepts (Sopranzetti,
this special section), and it becomes clear that we can
never just assume a one-to-one correspondence between
events and concepts, no more than between concepts and
words.
Third, we limit our analysis to political concepts. As
noted above, the term itself is inherently problematic,
and an attempted definition may fill up several volumes,
without necessarily opening a fruitful discussion. More
modestly, we follow two guiding principles. On the one
hand, we are interested in putting Machiavelli’s two books
into dialogue: in how considerations of directive action
articulate with visions of collective life. On the other, we
propose to take the contested nature of “politics” as itself
a productive entry point. “There are concepts which
are essentially contested,” wrote Walter Gallie in 1955,
“concepts the proper use of which inevitably involves
endless disputes about their proper uses on the part of
their users” (Gallie 1955: 169). This is so, he argues,
not because we are confused, and greater clarity would
end all dispute, but rather, because these concepts are
appraisive: they refer to and evaluate ideas that are internally complex, variously describable, persistently vague,
and inherently open. They are, as Alasdair MacIntyre
wrote, “essentially incomplete” because “debate remains
open about which the central, standard, and paradigmatic
instances of the phenomenon are” (1973: 2). In its strong
sense, this “essential contestability” is not merely a matter
of historical or geographical variation, but of philosophical necessity: “its subject matter is in its nature such that
there are always good reasons for disputing the propriety of any of its uses” (Gray 1977: 338), within as well as
between different intellectual traditions.
694
Brimming with polemical possibility, such concepts
are often at the forefront of political rhetoric and they
mobilize lexical and conceptual sets. Political language
defies translation in ways that indicate that it is expressive of basic notions that are complex, multivalent, and
semantically capacious; ideas that people rarely agree
on, but which form shared epistemic frames within
which different political judgments, assertions, and disagreements can be voiced. These ideas are often expressed in words that have a labile semantic range (Skinner 1999) rather than one precise definition which can be
catalogued in dictionaries or traced genealogically over
time. In other words, while not all essentially contested
concepts are political, most, if not all, concepts that have
political purchase are essentially contested, in one way or
another: they are politically potent or durable precisely
because what matters is the point of contention they
carry, not (just) the different meanings that people ascribe to them. Several articles in this collection address
concepts of this kind: “democracy” in Burma (Keeler),
“good governance” in Thailand (Sopranzetti), “respect”
in Amazonia (Walker). This essential contestability of
political concepts is, as Koselleck (1989) insisted, what
differentiates them from the “categories” or “values”
that anthropologists are more habituated to. We here
suggest that this contestation is a fruitful starting point
for ethnographic analysis—much as “conceptual change”
is for historians.
Global hierarchies of value
We are not the first to propose that language may offer
an excellent entry point into political relations. Carol
Gluck and Anna Lowenhaupt Tsing subtitled their 2009
edited volume on Words in motion “Toward a global
lexicon”; this is echoed, intentionally or not, in 2021 by
Didier Fassin and Veena Das’s Words and worlds: A lexicon for dark times. Nadia Tazi aimed to revitalize Raymond William’s Keywords project from an equally global
point of view, in her multivolume Keywords: Towards a
different kind of globalization (2004–2005). In all three
cases, the authors propose to take dominant concepts
in contemporary social analysis and follow them as they
travel the world. Tazi’s series features volumes on experience, identity, truth, gender, and nature, with chapters
in each on Africa, the United States, Europe, China, the
Arab world, and India, opening up questions both with
regards to the universal validity of the selected terms
695
and the geographic unit through which it is refracted.
Gluck and Tsing are more multidirectional in their
approach, as their aim is to show “how words—and
worlds—are made in cosmopolitan and power-laden
encounters at multiple scales” (Tsing 2009: 15). Still,
most of the selected words originated in Western Europe
or the United States. Similarly, Fassin and Das (2021: 6)
offer geographically diverse perspectives on Englishlanguage terms that are central in current political debates, as a “a chance to refresh our perspective on the
most serious issues of our time.”
Our aim here is somewhat different. While focusing
on politically potent words and concepts, we look for
terms that are not part of standard academic writing,
that are often difficult to translate, and that are rarely
transferred, as models, to other parts of the world—
or only disparagingly so. This does not necessarily imply
that we are focusing on “local” terms. Political language
everywhere is bound up with larger, regional traditions
of thought that are neither internally coherent nor independent of each other. As Andrew March (2009: 437)
observes, “in contrast to the boundaries between countries, societies [sic], or legal systems, the distinctions
between thoughts, ideas, values, norms, arguments, and
traditions are not always clear. Nor is it clear that the fact
of boundaries or disparate origins is [their] most relevant
feature.” What is at stake, then, are not clearly identified
and mutually incomprehensible bodies (sic) of thought,
nor even “traditions” in Asad’s sense ([1986] 2009), with
their limited and agreed-upon set of valid sources of
authority, but competing hierarchies of values (where
“competition” implies not only opposition, but also interrelation, comprehension, and comparability). These
hierarchies of values have no definable boundaries, as
it is in the nature of hierarchies to attempt to absorb their
opposites, and to pretend to have done so successfully;
but they thrive on their own claims to universal validity
and hence incommensurability, which might be empirically false but nonetheless rhetorically powerful.
Hence, when leading Thai politicians are attempting
to control and slow down “lexical immigrants” into Thai
political vocabulary, they acknowledge both the weight
of universalist values as promoted by international institutions, and the moral traction of (empirically incoherent but nonetheless powerful) notions of “Thai traditional
values”—even if, at the end, this means coining new terms
derived from a different and much older hierarchy of
value, that of “Sanskrit cosmopolitanism” (Pollock 1996;
see Sopranzetti, this special section). “Ethnic” boundaries
TOWARDS A
CRITICAL ETHNOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS
here clearly emerge as the result of a project of rule. Similarly, the Arabic vocabulary through which much political life in northwest Africa is refracted can never be confined to any particular locality, but derives much of its
salience from its inscription into a larger universalist
language and its close association with Islam—which
does not make it any less relevant in local settings, but
rather more so (see Scheele, this special section). This
is still the case today, and it is indeed why “global jihad”
is so much more frightening to many external observers
than, say, local uprisings clamoring for “Indigenous
rights,” although both invoke a universalizing political
language.
These different hierarchies of value often have deep
histories; they are not subsumed by states and indeed
in most cases precede and exceed them. They can never
be controlled precisely, and they only rarely overlap
with “culture areas” as proposed by area studies. Mauss
and Durkheim (1913) labeled them “civilizations” (a
word which since has been put to much unsavory
use) and noted that they are made up of different elements, some of which travel more readily and widely
than others. Their boundaries of significance are thus
historically situated, manifold, layered, and contested;
they are internally porous and can accommodate exceptions (see Vitebsky, this special section); they are thoroughly political and a subject of inquiry in themselves,
not mere background. The “cognitive regions” (Pollock
1998: 57) they describe are never morally homogeneous
but are constituted of (shifting) centers of emulation as
well as political and conceptual “backwaters,” with areas
of considerable overlap. Where economic historians
have attempted to trace the shape of one or several economic world-systems, we should admit similar political
connections and formations, not merely as precursors
to current political imperialisms but as a historical reality in their own right. Sahlins (Graeber and Sahlins 2017:
chapter 6, drawing on Cœdès 1968 and Tambiah 1977)
hence wrote of “the cultural politics of core-periphery
relations,” operating through “galactic mimesis,” as in
southeast Asia, for instance, outlying polities copied the
language and ritual of Indic kingdoms. “The effect is a
multicultural order of intercultural relations in which
no participating society is sui generis” (Sahlins in Graeber and Sahlins 2017: 345). This means that peripheral
regions might have wholly “inappropriate” political superstructures, or at least ambitions, and that a purely
“local” study of politics would be empirically and theoretically meaningless.
Anastasia PILIAVSKY and Judith SCHEELE
The aim of this collection is to acknowledge the
interplay of such different “global hierarchies of value”
(Herzfeld 2004, see also Sopranzetti, this special section) that are “global” not so much in their actual reach
as in their aspiration. The reduction of the conceptual
vocabulary in political anthropology that we deplored
at the beginning of this introduction is part of these negotiations and competitions; it is a way of incorporating
distinctive hierarchies of value within one moral frame,
centered on international institutions, the universalizing
language of the political science, and English-language
diplomacy. While, given the moral overdetermination
of all political language, this hierarchical incorporation
might at times appear as a (necessary) compliment or
as a rectification of past error, this is not always so, and
it certainly cannot account for the variety of political
lives led, in Euro-America no more than elsewhere (see
Chiriţoiu, this special section). The papers in this collection are an invitation to unpack these hierarchical incorporations, not in order to develop a more “neutral” or
indeed a “global” lexicon, but in order to revert perspectives, to point out incongruencies or different possible
avenues of thought, and to question the apparent coherence of current analytical vocabulary in the process. This
is what we think an explicitly political anthropology can
best contribute to the discipline as a whole, and to political thought—cosmopolitan, comparative, or simply
contemporary—more generally.
696
Archer, Matthew, and Daniel Souleles. 2021. “Introduction:
Ethnographies of power and the powerful.” Critique of
Anthropology 41 (3): 195–205.
Asad, Talal. 1973. “Introduction.” In Anthropology and the
colonial encounter, edited by Talal Asad, 9–19. London:
Ithaca Press.
———. (1986) 2009. “The idea of an anthropology of Islam.”
Qui parle 17 (2): 1–30.
Austin, Gareth. 2007. “Reciprocal comparison and African history: Tackling conceptual Eurocentrism in the study of
Africa’s economic past.” African Studies Review 50 (3): 1–
28.
Bargu, Banu. 2021. “Neo-Ottomanism: An alt-right formation from the south?” Social Research 88 (2): 299–333.
Benner, Erica. 2009. Machiavelli’s ethics. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Berlin, Isaiah. 1979. “The originality of Machivelli.” In
Against the current: Essays in the history of ideas, 25–79.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Brown, Wendy. 2005. Edgework: Critical essays on knowledge
and politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Brubaker, Rogers, and Frederick Cooper. 2000. “Beyond
‘identity.’ ” Theory and Society 29 (1): 1–47.
Buck-Morss, Susan. 2000. “Hegel and Haiti.” Critical Inquiry
26 (4): 821–65.
Burton, John. 1981. “Ethnicity on the hoof: On the economics
of Nuer identity.” Ethnology 20 (2): 157–62.
Acknowledgments
This special section started as a day-long panel of the ASA
conference in 2018, followed by a workshop held in Cambridge in May 2019. We would like to thank all participants, contributors and discussants on these two occasions, whether
they are represented in this special section or not. Work on
this piece was further supported by funding from the European
Union’s Horizon 2020 research and innovation programme
under grant agreement No. 853051 for the project on India’s
politics in its vernaculars.
References
Anderson, Benedict. 1983. Imagined communities. Reflections
on the origin and spread of nationalism. London: Verso.
Anscombe, Elizabeth. 1958. “Modern moral philosophy.”
Philosophy 33 (124): 1–19.
Candea, Matei. 2011. “‘Our division of the universe’: Making
a space for the non-political in the anthropology of politics.” Current Anthropology 52 (3): 309–34.
Castoriadis, Cornelius. 1988. “Pouvoir, politique, autonomie.”
Revue de métaphysique et de morale 93 (1): 91–104.
Cœdès, George. 1968. The Indianized states of southeast
Asia. Canberra: Australian National University Press.
Cohn, Bernard. 1980. “History and anthropology: The state
of play.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 22
(2): 198–221.
Comaroff, Jean, and John Comaroff. 2012. “Theory from the
south: Or, how Euro-America is evolving toward Africa.”
Anthropological Forum 22 (2): 113–31.
Curtis, Jessica, and Jonathan Spencer. 2012. “Anthropology
and the political.” In The SAGE handbook of social anthropology, vol. 1, edited by Richard Fardon et al., 168–
82. London: SAGE.
697
TOWARDS A
CRITICAL ETHNOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS
Dallmayr, Fred. 2004. “Beyond monologue: For a comparative political theory.” Perspectives on Politics 2 (2): 249–
57.
Graeber, David. 2013. “It is value that brings universes into
being.” HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory 3 (2): 219–
43.
Dumont, Louis. 1971. “Religion, politics and society in the
individualistic universe.” In Proceedings of the Royal Anthropological Institute 1970, 33–41.
Graeber, David, and Marshall Sahlins. 2017. On kings. Chicago: HAU Books.
———. 1977. From Mandeville to Marx: The genesis and triumph of economic ideology. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Evans, Gillian. 2012. “‘The aboriginal people of England’:
The culture of class politics in contemporary Britain.”
Focaal 62: 17–29.
Fassin, Didier. 2011. “A contribution to the critique of moral
reason.” Anthropological Theory 11 (4): 481–91.
———. 2014. “The ethical turn in anthropology: Promises
and uncertainties.” HAU: Journal of Ethnographic Theory
4 (1): 429–35.
Graeber, David, and David Wengrow. 2021. The dawn of everything: A new history of humanity. New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux.
Gray, John. 1977. “On the contestability of social and political concepts.” Political Theory 5 (3): 331–48.
Hage, Ghassan. 2012. “Critical anthropological thought and
the radical political imaginary today.” Critique of Anthropology 32 (3): 285–308.
Hann, Chris. 2015. “Goody, Polanyi and Eurasia: An unfinished project in comparative historical economic anthropology.” History and Anthropology 26 (3): 308–20.
———. 2017. “The endurance of critique.” Anthropological
Theory 17 (1): 4–29.
———. 2018. “Economic anthropology.” In The international encyclopedia of anthropology, edited by Hilary
Callan. Hoboken: John Wiley.
Fassin, Didier, and Veena Das, eds. 2021. Words and worlds: A
lexicon for dark times. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Hart, H. L. A. (1961) 1994. The concept of law. Second edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Femia, Joseph. 2004. “Machiavelli and Italian fascism.” History of Political Thought 25 (1): 1–15.
Herzfeld, Michael. 2004. The body impolitic: Artisans and artifice in the global hierarchy of value. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Ferguson, James. 2013. “Declarations of dependence: Labour, personhood, and welfare in southern Africa.” Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 19 (2): 223–42.
Fortes, Meyer, and Edward E. Evans-Pritchard. 1940. “Introduction.” In African political systems, edited by M. Fortes
and E. E. Evans-Pritchard, 1–24. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fournier, Marcel. 2004. “Mauss et ‘la nation,’ ou l’œuvre
inachevée.” Sociologie et Sociétés 36 (2): 207–25.
Gallie, Walter. 1955. “Essentially contested concepts.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56: 167–98.
Gledhill, John. 1994. Power and its disguises: Anthropological
perspectives on politics. London: Pluto Press.
Gluck, Carol, and Anna L. Tsing, eds. 2009. Words in motion: Toward a global lexicon. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Godrej, Farah. 2011. Cosmopolitan political thought: Method,
practice, discipline. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Goto-Jones, Chris. 2011. “A cosmos beyond space and area
studies: Towards comparative political thought as political thought.” boundary 2 38 (3): 88–118.
Hochschild, Arlie. 2018. Strangers in their own land: Anger
and mourning in the American right. New York: New
Press.
Howell, P. P. 1947. “On the value of iron among the Nuer.”
Man 47: 131–34.
Ismard, Paulin. 2015. La démocratie contre les experts. Les
esclaves publics en Grèce ancienne. Paris: Seuil.
Jenco, Leigh. 2007. “‘What does heaven ever say?’ A methodscentered approach to cross-cultural engagement.” American
Political Science Review 101 (4): 741–55.
Johnson, Douglas. 1986. “On the Nilotic frontier: Imperial Ethiopia in Southern Sudan, 1898–1936.” In The
southern marches of imperial Ethiopia: Essays in history
and social anthropology, edited by Donald L. Donham
and Wendy James, 219–45. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jonsson, Hjorleifur. 2018. “States.” In The international encyclopedia of anthropology, edited by Hilary Callan. Hoboken: John Wiley.
Jok, Jok Madut, and Sharon Hutchinson. 1999. “Sudan’s prolonged second civil war and the militarization of Nuer
Anastasia PILIAVSKY and Judith SCHEELE
698
and Dinka ethnic identities.” African Studies Review 42
(2): 125–45.
Mauss, Marcel. (1920)1953–54. “La nation.” Année sociologique (1953–54): 7–68.
Kapferer, Bruce. 2005. “Situations, crisis, and the anthropology of the concrete: The contribution of Max Gluckman.”
Social Analysis 49 (3): 85–122.
———. 1923. “Essai sur le don. Forme et raison de l’échange
dans les sociétés archaïques.” Année sociologique 1: 30–
186.
Karsenti, Bruno. 2010. “Une autre approche de la nation:
Marcel Mauss.” Revue du MAUSS 36: 283–94.
Mauss, Marcel, and Émile Durkheim. 1913. “Note sur la notion de civilisation.” Année sociologique 12: 46–50.
Koselleck, Reinhart. 1989. “Linguistic change and the history
of events.” Journal of Modern History 61 (4): 649–66.
McCormick, John. 2011. Machiavellian democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 2006. Begriffsgeschichten. Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp.
———. 2015. “Of tribunes and tyrants: Machiavelli’s legal
and extra-legal modes for controlling elites.” Ratio Juris
28 (2): 252–66.
Lach, Donald. 1945. “Leibniz and China.” Journal of the History of Ideas 6 (4): 436–55.
Laidlaw, James. 2013. The subject of virtue: An anthropology
of ethics and freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Lambek, Michael. 2010. Ordinary ethics: Anthropology, language, and action. New York: Fordham University Press.
Leach, Edmund. 1961. Rethinking anthropology. London:
Athlone Press.
Lefort, Claude. 1986. Essais sur le politique (XIXe–XXe siècles).
Paris: Seuil.
———. 2012. Machiavelli in the making. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
Lewellen, Ted. 2003. Political anthropology. Third edition.
Westport, CT: Praeger.
McKinnon, Susan. 2000. “Domestic exceptions: EvansPritchard and the creation of Nuer patrilineality and
equality.” Cultural Anthropology 15 (1): 35–83.
Mercer, Patricia. 1971. “Shilluk trade and politics from the
mid-seventeenth century to 1861.” Journal of African History 12 (3): 407–26.
Mouffe, Chantal. 1993. The return of the political. London:
Verso.
Ortner, Sherry. 2016. “Dark anthropology and its others:
Theory since the eighties.” HAU: Journal of Ethnographic
Theory 6 (1): 47–73.
Owen, David. 2002. “Criticism and captivity: On genealogy
and critical theory.” European Journal of Philosophy 10
(2): 216–30.
Palmer, David, and Fabian Winiger. 2019. “Neo-socialist
governmentality: Managing freedom in the People’s Republic of China.” Economy and Society 48 (4): 554–78.
Li, Darrel. 2009. “A universal enemy?: ‘Foreign fighters’ and
legal regimes of exclusion and exemption under the ‘global
war on terror.’” Columbia Human Rights Law Review 41:
355–427.
Pandian, Anand, and Daud Ali, eds. 2010. Ethical life in
South Asia. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Longo, Matthew, and Bernardo Zacka. 2019. “Political theory in an ethnographic key.” American Political Science
Review 113: 1066–70.
Pedullà, Gabriele. 2018. Machiavelli in tumult: The Discourses
on Livy and the origins of political conflictualism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1973. “The essential contestability of
some social concepts.” Ethics 84: 1–9.
Piliavsky, Anastasia, ed. 2014. Patronage as politics in South
Asia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mahmood, Saba. 2001. “Feminist theory, embodiment, and
the docile agent: Some reflections on the Egyptian Islamic
revival.” Cultural Anthropology 16 (2): 202–36.
Pocock, J. G. A. 1975. The Machiavellian moment: Florentine
political thought and the Atlantic republican tradition.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
March, Andrew. 2009. “What is comparative political theory?” Review of Politics 71: 531–65.
Pollock, Sheldon. 1996. “The Sanskrit cosmopolis, 300–
1300.” In The ideology and status of Sanskrit, edited by
Jan E. M. Houben, 197–247. Leiden: Brill.
Marcus, Anthony. 2008. “Interrogating the neo-pluralist orthodoxy in American anthropology.” Dialectical Anthropology 32: 59–86.
———. 1998. “India in the vernacular millennium: Literary
culture and polity, 1000–1500.” Daedalus 127 (3): 41–74.
699
TOWARDS A
CRITICAL ETHNOGRAPHY OF POLITICAL CONCEPTS
Sacks, Karen. 1979. “Causality and chance on the Upper
Nile.” American Ethnologist 6 (3): 437–48.
order and the landed estate.” History and Anthropology 29
(3): 324–41.
Sahlins, Marshall. 1993. Waiting for Foucault. Cambridge:
Prickly Pear.
Southall, Aidan. 1976. “Nuer and Dinka are people: Ecology,
ethnicity and logical possibility.” Man 11 (4): 463–91.
Samanani, Farhan. 2021. “Power in a minor key: Rethinking
anthropological accounts of power alongside London’s
community organisers.” Critique of Anthropology 41 (3):
284–302.
Spencer, Jonathan. 1997. “Post-colonialism and the political
imagination.” Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute N.S. 3 (1): 1–19.
Schatz, Edward, ed. 2009. Political ethnography: What immersion contributes to the study of power. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Schmitt, Carl. 1932. Der Begriff des Politischen. Munich:
Duncker & Humblot.
Silverstein, Michael. 2004. “ ‘Cultural’ concepts and the
language-culture nexus.” Current Anthropology 45 (5): 621–
52.
Simmons, Erica, and Nicholas R. Smith. 2019. “The case for comparative ethnography.” Comparative Politics 51 (3): 341–59.
Simpson, Audra. 2014. Mohawk interruptus: Political life
across the borders of settler states. Durham, NC: Duke
University Press.
Skinner, Quentin. 1989. “Language and political change.” In
Political innovation and conceptual change, edited by Terence Ball, James Farr, and Russell L. Hanson, 6–23. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1999. “Rhetoric and conceptual change.” Redescriptions: Political Thought, Conceptual History and Feminist Theory 3 (1): 60–73.
Strathern, Marilyn. 1985. “Discovering ‘social control.’” Journal of Law and Society 12 (2): 111–34.
Tambiah, Stanley. 1977. “The galactic polity: The structure
of traditional kingdoms in Southeast Asia.” Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences 293 (1): 69–97.
Taylor, Charles. 1971. “Interpretation and the science of
man.” Review of Metaphysics 25 (1): 3–51.
Tazi, Nadia, 2004–2005. Keywords: For a different kind of
globalization. New York: Other Press.
Thomas, Megan. 2010. “Orientalism and comparative political theory.” The Review of Politics 72 (4): 653–77.
Thomassen, Bjørn. 2008. “What kind of political anthropology?” International Political Anthropology 1 (2): 263–
74.
Tsing, Anna Lowenhaupt. 2009. “Worlds in motion.” In
Words in motion. Toward a global lexicon, edited by Carol
Gluck and Anna Lowenhaupt Tsing, 11–17. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
———. 2000. Machiavelli: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Turner, Terence. 1984. “Dual opposition, hierarchy and value:
Moiety structure and symbolic polarity in central Brazil and
elsewhere.” In Différences, valeurs, hiérarchies: Textes offerts
à Louis Dumont, edited by J.-C. Galaty, 335–70. Paris: Éditions de l’EHESS.
Sneath, David. 2018. “Commonwealth, inalienable possessions, and the res publica: The anthropology of aristocratic
Wolf, Eric. 1990. “Facing power—old insights, new questions.” American Anthropologist 92 (3): 586–96.
Anastasia PILIAVSKY teaches anthropology and politics at the India Institute in King’s College London. She writes
about hierarchy, banditry and democracy. She is editor of Patronage as politics in South Asia (Cambridge University
Press, 2014) and author of Nobody’s people: Hierarchy as hope in a society of thieves (Stanford University Press,
2020).
Anastasia Piliavsky
anastasia.piliavsky@kcl.ac.uk
Judith SCHEELE teaches social anthropology at the École des Hautes Études en Sciences Sociales (EHESS) in Marseille.
She writes about mobility, politics, and Islam in northwest Africa. She is the author of Village matters: Knowledge,
Anastasia PILIAVSKY and Judith SCHEELE
700
politics and community in Kabylia (Algeria) (James Currey, 2009), of Smugglers and saints of the Sahara: Regional
connectivity in the twentieth century (Cambridge University Press, 2012), and, with Julien Brachet, of The value of
disorder: Autonomy, prosperity and plunder in the Chadian Sahara (Cambridge University Press, 2019).
Judith Scheele
judith.scheele@ehess.fr