View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk
brought to you by
CORE
provided by Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies (JCACS)
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning
Belief After Historical Loss
LISA FARLEY
York University
In Northern British Columbia, there is a grassy hillside that overlooks
Fraser Lake. It is on this hill that the Lejac Residential School once stood,
though today, most physical traces have been destroyed. While the
structure of the school itself is no longer, the collective memory of the
school – and the students who attended – persists in the form of an
annual pilgrimage to the site. Every July, close to one thousand travelers
make their way there. They are seeking after traces of a former student,
Rose of the Carrier First Nation, who many believe to be an Aboriginal
Saint. Like her peers, Rose entered the residential school and was
expected to convert to Catholicism, even though we also know that
youth found many creative strategies to resist passive compliance.
Unlike her peers, however, Rose chose to remain at the school after her
graduation, where she tutored younger generations who entered. In
1949, at the age of thirty-three, she became increasingly weakened by
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
Volume 8 Number 1 2010
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
tuberculosis, the disease that had killed thousands of Aboriginal people
before her in the Canadian colonizing project that John Milloy (1999)
rightly names, “a national crime.” By her own request, Rose’s body was
buried in a cemetery near the school. (Every Residential School was
faced with the question of where to bury the dead). Rose’s experience of
the residential school is, in these ways, unremarkable even as it also
depicts the massive injustice of Canada’s history of education.
It was not until two years after her death that Rose of the Carrier
became the legend it now is. In yet another instance of dislocation, the
construction of a railway line in 1951 forced the excavation of the
cemetery at Lejac. The story goes that during the excavation, the lid of
Rose’s coffin accidently fell open. Rose’s body, so the legend goes,
looked exactly as she had the day she was buried, her clothes untouched
and tidy, her skin still smooth and plump with life, as one elder relays,
“no decay.”1 Today, the soil surrounding Rose’s grave is said to carry
miracles. The legend of Rose is a powerful one that raises questions
about the persistence of painful histories and their preservation in
memory, both individual and collective. This body of “no decay” signals
the raw wounds of past trauma and the lingering force of un-claimed
experiences that persist in the minds and rituals of generations
afterward. On the hillside overlooking Fraser Lake, the history that was
forcibly removed from the landscape seeps into the soil in the form of
miracles. The pilgrims who go there believe this.
In late June 2010, I telephoned St. Andrew’s Parish in Fraser Lake. An
answering machine picked up my call and the crackly recording of
Reverend Vincent James instructed me to leave a message at the tone.
Just before the beep, however, he added a coda: If I was calling about the
2010 Rose Prince pilgrimage, this year’s event would be held on the
weekend of July ninth to the twelfth. Almost without thinking, I booked
a plane ticket that same morning that would fly out of Toronto and into
Prince George, which is just two hours driving distance east (and slightly
7
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
south) of the pilgrimage site. From there I would make the trek, by the
modern convenience of a rental car, to Fraser Lake. As I thought more
about the journey, I came to understand that there would be no way
around my outsider status, and that my itch to travel was far from
innocent: The same Imperial era that invented the Residential School
coincided with the expansive itineraries of exploration travel, and the
rise of modern tourism. Neither Aboriginal nor Catholic, I felt more like
a tourist than a pilgrim, even as I wondered about the grey area between
these positions. Indeed, Zygmunt Bauman (1996) names tourism as one
of “the pilgrim’s successors” insofar as both forms suggest a human
resistance to “being bound and fixed” (p. 26). In light of Bauman’s notice
of this human longing for freedom, another conflict emerged on the
horizon: after all, I was traveling to a place marked by a history of forced
migration and detainment.
It is precisely these kinds of tensions that inform discussions of place
in curriculum study. The particularities of a place contextualize
knowledge: “A novelist or a historian cannot remove a story from a
particular place; it would no longer be the same story” (Kincheloe &
Pinar, 1991, p. 5). So too it is with curriculum. “Without such a
perspective,” write Joe Kincheloe and William Pinar, “curriculum theory
operates in isolation, serving to trivialize knowledge, fragmenting it into
bits” (1991, p. 5). Locating curriculum “in place” returns knowledge to
the particular context of its construction and that endows its significance
(Burbules & Berk, 1999; Bekerman, Burbules & Silbermann-Keller, 2006;
Chambers, 2008; Ellsworth, 2005; Gruenewald, 2003; Robertson &
Radford, 2010; Rone, 2008). Indeed, educational theorists of place
convincingly point to the risks of tearing bodies from knowledge, feet
from ground, and curriculum from community. The example of the
Residential School graphically illustrates such terrible risk. From the
perspective of place, knowledge cannot be thought of in isolation from
the places and people who put it to use, or misuse.2 Precisely because
8
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
“places of learning implicate bodies,” we are urged to consider not only
how the particularities of a place shape us, but also how we, in turn,
affect the routes we travel (Ellsworth, 2005, p. 6; see also Chambers,
2008). Celia Haig-Brown describes this double influence as a capacity to
“inhabit border worlds,” which, for her, involves an awareness of how
layers of history interact with each other and that are, in turn, shaped by
the footprints our researches leave behind (2008, p. 14).
Ironically, in bringing distant lives and losses into the realm of the
palpable and concrete, place also brings us face-to-face with the inchoate
– what Deborah Britzman (2000) calls “difficult knowledge” – that resists
immediate or direct engagement. A related irony is that despite the
speedy ways in which we can now glide the globe, our searches for a
pure or authentic “reality” necessarily come up short. On this point,
Judith Robertson and Linda Radford (2010) suggest that the pilgrim’s
feverish return to sites of lost objects always finds those objects on the
horizon, “not quite catchable” (p. 208). This phenomenon is echoed in
Barbara Kirshenblatt-Gimblett’s observation that travelers to sites of
memory tend to locate “truth” not in the material objects they find
abroad, but “more often in what cannot be seen, in the invisible heart and
soul of the site” (p. 168, emphasis added). In searching for the real, there
is simultaneously an awareness that the object of one’s desire does not as
such exist. Indeed, to not be satisfied with the material may be one of the
most powerful drives behind the pilgrimage. One of the Aboriginal
organizers of the Rose pilgrimage illustrated this irony in distinguishing
the Fraser Lake event from the lures of material culture: “We do not
want the Rose Pilgrimage to be St. Anne de Beaupre.” (At the St. Anne
Basillica, objects of piety are available for purchase in the Shrine’s
souvenir shop.) At the grave of Rose Prince, this pilgrim reminded us,
miracles are available for all through the immaterial currency of belief.
In this paper, I offer a reading of the pilgrimage to Rose of the
Carrier’s grave as a compelling example of how both material landscapes
9
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
and the immaterial, imperial wishfulness and transcultural reparation
come together in the “need to believe” at sites of history’s lost objects.
Two seemingly contradictory dimensions to belief concern me here: First,
is Sigmund Freud’s (1927) sense of belief as “illusion” that defends the
ego against the anxieties that follow from loss (p. 39). Second, I turn to
Julia Kristeva (2009) for whom belief is not solely a defense but a
condition needed to testify to experiences that reside beyond the
perceptible limits of what can be immediately known. This pre-religious
need appeals to belief because it asks others to “take our word for it”
despite what can be indicated in more certain terms.3 Kristeva will make
from her critique of Freud a complex of belief: the very same condition
the ego uses to defend against losses of humanity and history is also
needed to give meaning to – and represent – the core of what is lost.
Before turning to the example of Rose, I consider in the next section how
belief frames my reading of it. The following questions matter to this
inquiry: Why think of belief as a statement of and for history? How
might belief orient us toward – and away from – the difficult realities of
the traumatic past? Can we think of the pilgrimage – and the beliefs that
drive it – as a form of history curriculum?
A Psychoanalytic Account of Belief: On Illusion, Need and
Learning to Speak
In his “The Future of an Illusion,” Freud offers a critique of religion that
finds its girth in an ancient philosophical claim: belief is rooted in
illusion quite apart from knowledge.4 As he writes, “we call a belief an
illusion when a wish-fulfillment is a prominent factor in its motivation”
(1927, p. 39). The height of Freud’s objection is that belief is at bottom
driven by what we wish the world to be, not as it actually is. In his
words, belief “comprises a system of wishful illusions together with a
disavowal of reality, such as we find in an isolated form…in a state of
10
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
blissful, hallucinatory confusion” (1927, p. 43). Freud (1927) further links
this wishful state to the Oedipal relationship that is both life-giving and
threatening, where the ego “attaches itself to objects that promise to
satisfy [its] needs” (p. 130). But this passionate attachment is also
ambivalent: moving as quickly from the realm of pleasure to the
inevitable frustrations that accompany the prohibition against desire. In
such moments, we encounter the radical vulnerability of the human
condition. We learn that we cannot have all we want, and that substitute
satisfactions depend on others. For Freud, this fact of dependency
produces a conflict: We ascribe to others the power to protect us from the
anxiety that accompanies feeling vulnerable, but it is this relation that recreates the very condition of powerlessness we hope to get a handle on.
Freud casts this complex into two statements, which for him, are the
grounds of religious belief: In the first, Freud writes, “the motif of
yearning for the father is identical with the need for protection against
the consequences of human powerlessness” (p. 130). That is, we invest in
another (“the father”) to protect us from vulnerability. In the second
statement, Freud notes a complex of fear and protection that he
understands to underlie the belief in God: the ego resolves the problem
of vulnerability by giving power away: “creating for himself gods of
whom he is afraid…and to whom he nevertheless assigns his protection”
(p. 130).
There is something paradoxical, and regressive, about belief as Freud
constructs it. The believer represses instinct (and fear) that becomes
invested in the illusion of an all-knowing father. Of course, Freud
explained a range of psychical processes on precisely this logic: that is,
the repression of instinct sat at the bottom of even the most rational
processes. But what concerned Freud about religion in particular was the
way its doctrines tended to work against critical faculties of thought,
investigation and judgment. In short, Freud worried that the ambivalent
grounds of being – and the inevitable doubts of contemplation and
11
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
thought – were exchanged for the false certainty of belief. Freud’s
critique of religion is far too complex and wide-ranging for these basic
points do it justice. But suffice it to say here that one of Freud’s chief
objections pointed to the regressive features of religious belief: he saw it
as a wishful retreat from encountering the magnitude of uncertainty that
constitutes human reality.5 Freud thus emphasized the value of
constructing understanding and making psychological significance from
the uncertainties, flaws and misgivings of human existence, which he
saw as our best hope for solace.
Freud’s skeptical views on religion sparked much debate in
psychoanalytic discussions. One of those debates is documented in his
correspondence with his friend Romain Rolland, who thought that
Freud’s emphasis on regression and wishfulness had missed something
important about religion.6 What Freud missed was an analysis of the
“oceanic feeling,” a term that Rolland had developed through his study
of Eastern Mysticism. By this term (and while too complicated to do it
justice here) Rolland meant to give language to a peculiar feeling –
particularly discernable in literature – of limitlessness or restlessness
associated with being in relation to a world beyond the small orbit of the
ego. Rolland penned his thoughts on Freud’s omission in a letter to
Freud on December 5, 1927. It would take Freud two years to respond,
perhaps an indication of the anxiety – or at least restlessness – the
concept roused in him. On July 14, 1929, Freud finally addressed his
much-esteemed friend: “Your letter…containing your remarks about a
feeling you describe as ‘oceanic’ has left me no peace” (p. 388). What was
giving Freud “no peace” was the seemingly tranquility of his friend’s
concept, which, akin to his critique of religion, worked on the false
promise of being’s continuity and that defended against more difficult
human drives that disrupted those seams: aggression, destruction, and
death.7 And yet, in these early paper disagreements, it would seem that
something of a commonality had been missed: both Freud and Rolland
12
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
were interested in describing a stark sense of being born into a world
beyond one’s immediate control or perceptible grasp.8
Freud would return to Rolland’s question about feelings “oceanic” in
the opening pages of his Civilization and its Discontents (1930), published
three years after the 1927 essay that drew his friend’s initial comments.
In this work, Freud credits the concept “oceanic” to an anonymous
friend, a gesture intended as a “hint” to Rolland (1929, p. 388). And then
Freud goes one step further, perhaps taking a leap of faith, trying out the
idea of the oceanic on his own (non-religious) terms. In a typical
Freudian move, he turns to literature:
If I have understood my friend correctly, what he has in
mind is the same as the consolation that an original and
rather eccentric writer offers his hero before his freely
chosen death: “We cannot fall out of this world.”9 It is a
feeling, then, of being indissolubly bound up with and
belonging to the whole of the world outside oneself. (1930,
p. 4)
The belief that “we cannot fall out of this world” enables us to tolerate –
to find meaning in life – in light of the fact of our inevitable death.10 The
language of illusion and wish is here supplemented with the notion of
creativity and memory. We may need to believe that our creative
capacities – such as in literature, in learning and in love – will matter
after our existence, a self after self, a symbolic form of life after death.
The terms of this debate between psychoanalysis and religion have
recently re-surfaced in Julia Kristeva’s book, This Incredible Need to Believe
(2009). Echoing Rolland, she begins with a disagreement with Freud.
Kristeva re-iterates the idea that belief is neither an illusion nor neurosis,
but a condition of surviving the fact of finite existence (and here we can
see her agreement with Rolland). As Kristeva (2009) writes: “Whether I
belong to a religion, whether I be agnostic or atheist, when I say ‘I
believe,’ I mean ‘I hold as true’….It is a matter of truth…that I hold for
13
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
vital, absolute, indisputable, a truth that keeps me, makes me exist” (p.
3). Loosening the congealed relation between belief and religion,
Kristeva takes as her model of belief the figure of the adolescent. The
adolescent is a model of belief in her desperate search for a “jubilant
certainty of belonging to the world” that does not exist per say, but that is
needed to feel as if one exists (p. 10). For Kristeva, then, the adolescent
need to believe is a reprieve of the “oceanic feeling” – that feeling of
something larger than me – which the adolescent uses, at one level, in the
service of survival: to “not fall out of this world.” The adolescent, like the
believer, seeks belonging through the idealization of the erotic object:
whether this is a person, an idea or an idol (p. 14).
Far from being herself hallucinated by belief, Kristeva seems to agree
here with Freud’s worries about the capacity for “blissful, hallucinatory
confusion.” Indeed, Kristeva is deeply aware of the human capacity for
extremes: because belief is driven the passionate search for the erotic
object, it can just as easily tip into urges to destroy, passions for
ignorance, attacks on linking, suicide or shoulder-shrugging nihilism.
Kristeva’s turn to the adolescent as a metaphor of belief is, in this way,
akin to Freud’s turn to the infantile. Through this figure, she argues that
the “need to believe” is a recurring human motif that wards off the sting
of loss – what Freud called powerlessness – that marks the core of being.
As Kristeva insists: “the shadow of the ideal has fallen over the adolescent and
crystallized in the need to believe” (p. 19, her emphasis). Belief staves off,
momentarily and precariously, the disappointment of life that faces us
with the loss of idealization, the impossibility of absolute knowledge,
perfect love and authority.
While Kristeva agrees (with Freud) that the idea of belief conducts
wishful idealizations, she also points to it as an essential feature of
symbolization, needed to engage reality: Our very first efforts in language
depend on a belief that the world can persist in symbolic form in spite of
the inevitable loss of material relations (such as the mother/baby dyad)
14
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
and the immediate gratifications afforded there. This is a world that
exists in symbolic form and that serves as a placeholder for the actual,
but is no less real for it. Belief is on these terms a condition for making
language from loss, and is not far away from Jacques Derrida’s
discussion of testimony as a pledge beyond concrete evidence: “For one
can testify only to the unbelievable. To what can, at any rate, only be
believed; to what appeals only to belief and hence to the given word,
since
it
lies
beyond
the
limits
of
proof,
indication,
certified
acknowledgement [le constat], and knowledge” (1998a, p. 20). As the
grounds for symbolization, belief is needed not to sustain illusion (as
Freud would have it), but rather to face a truth of loss that is forcibly felt
beyond the realm of “concrete evidence.”
Kristeva traces our first encounter with loss to a time of infancy. She
argues that the baby’s greatest challenge is to tolerate the lack that
accompanies the absence of immediate gratification at the breast. Belief is
needed to survive the inevitable dissatisfactions of this relation without
breakdown: it puts survival, and satisfaction, on the horizon in times of
hunger, or lack. Belief is a condition the baby needs to tolerate waiting –
a placeholder that tides one over until gratification comes. And yet, for
Kristeva, belief is also needed to create satisfying substitutions – in the
form of knowledge and representation – which eventually replace the
early (and lost) gratifications of the first object-relation with the mother.
Kristeva has this idea in mind when she notes that belief opens “another
corrosive and liberating capacity: the desire to know” (Kristeva, 2009, p.
xii). That is, in the face of loss, and because of it, the child begins to use
questions to fill spaces of hunger, or curiosity. In short, she can ask for
reasons, for what she wants, or for another possibility, even if the
answers she seeks can never fully satisfy the desire that made the
question in the first place. Belief, in this context, enables one to survive
the frustration that is lack as well as the equally insulting limits of the
signs we use to bridge the gap.11 And it is here where belief comes to
15
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
matter in a very particular way, for while speech is a substitute for lack,
it depends first on the belief that what one says can matter, and is
possible at all, even in the anxious awareness that these linguistic efforts
are always already subject to slippage, ambiguity and disarray.12
Kristeva’s (2009) theory of speech stems from both the everyday
traumas of growing up, which include “birth, separation frustration and
various kinds of lacks” (p. 79) – as well as the “catastrophic suffering”
that emerges from violent designs to jar language from people, and
generations from each other (cited in Guberman, 1996, p. 23). Belief is, for
Kristeva, needed to speak about un-named experiences that, without the
distance afforded by language, would otherwise persist, “no decay,” in
congealed and injurious form. The power of language to transform
experience depends, however, on another paradox; the power to name
one’s own experience is rooted, first, in the fact of dependency. One
“internalizes” the discourse of another. The good news is that this
internalized discourse is never an exact repetition of the other. In
Kristeva’s argument, belief is once again the grounds for creation; it is,
needed to transform speech into something other than mere imitation,
for it helps the speaker risk new combinations that push back and revise
the words we internalize. “Endlessly, solely through the ordeal of
language that refines language and renders it sensitive to the unutterable
by questioning the very conditions of speech, including the need to
believe” (Kristeva, 2009, p. xvi, emphasis added). The irony is thick here:
belief is needed for speech that can question not only the stories we are
told, but the very conditions of language, including belief itself. Belief is
not here a matter of giving over one’s critical faculties to the authority of
an idealized, all-knowing other. Quite the contrary, and critically, it takes
belief to ask, why (not) believe?
But where does this leave us in terms of thinking about travel,
memory and history education? For the pilgrim, what purpose may
belief serve? And what might the pilgrim teach us about the need for
16
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
belief in learning from loss? Freud’s work, I think, makes it possible to
consider belief as bound to nostalgia for an imaginary point of origin that
defends against the necessary ambivalences of loss and that, particularly
for non-Aboriginal pilgrims, would mean facing one’s implication in this
violent history. On the other hand, Kristeva’s work allows for an
understanding of belief as a human need that is not necessarily an escape
from the difficult realities of history (and so the fact of death), but rather
a condition for speaking about its disquieting and lingering impact in the
present, or what remains. Belief is needed, in Kristeva’s view, to persist
in this radically un-homely state, lest we lose ourselves to the abyss of
non-meaning, un-concern and, at the furthest extreme, the memorial
death of amnesia. The dual terms of the Freud/Kristeva debates
highlight in uncanny ways the conflicted terrain of belief at play on the
pilgrimage to Fraser Lake, and that I turn to in the next section. As we
will see, this site of historical loss is characterized by a wishful turning
away from the fact of loss, even as it bears witness to the “unutterable
truth” of trauma (Kristeva, 2009, p. xvi) and “the unbearable nature of its
survival” in the present (Caruth, 1996, p. 7).
“Curiositas”
Implied in my discussion thus far is a debate about what form of belief
works toward creative survival and what kind works in the service of
repetition, or compliance.13 In the context of Rose of the Carrier, the
beliefs that fuel the pilgrim’s footsteps could be read as functioning in a
wish-fulfilling way. From this vantage, we can think of the tendency to
believe in the miracles of Rose of the Carrier as a wishful avoidance of
the fact of history’s irredeemable losses – those wounds that will not
heal. In this wishful state, there may also be a belief in bringing about a
new kind of future that, in actual fact, repeats the colonial discourse that
the ritual seeks to overcome. Rose’s own belief in a Christian God and
17
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
the Christian denomination of the pilgrimage may well be evidence of
this conflict. That is, the belief in the miracles of Rose Prince repeats the
terms of the colonial history to which it also responds. The inclination to
believe is a trace of the lingering and insidious effects of colonization,
where the reincarnation of eternal goodness in the image of Rose
sustains the force of Christianity without the acknowledgement of
religion as an instrument of violence. The wish-fulfilling quality of belief
works here as a deceptive promise: to believe in the miraculous recovery
of goodness risks turning away from the violent losses that constitute
this colonial history as well as the pain of transforming one’s relationship
to such loss, however much that transformation is needed, or longed
for.14 In her study of the figure of Rose, Jo-Anne Fiske (1996) argues that
it is understandable – or more precisely, “forgivable” – to take this
position, especially in light of Rose of the Carrier’s denomination-specific
representation (p. 670).
On my journey to Fraser Lake, I found this position impossible to
ignore. After all, one of the earliest reasons for undertaking a pilgrimage,
at least in the Middle Ages, was to expiate oneself of some great crime
(Sumption, 1975). In the context of the modern pilgrimage, and the Rose
pilgrimage in particular, this fact turned into a terrible irony when
church leaders set up outdoor confessional areas around the pilgrimage
site to offer confession to pilgrims, including former students of Lejac.
Skeptical, I wondered, whose great crime is to be expiated here? What
difficult knowledge was being avoided in the name of confession? At the
same time, confession was not the only reason for the pilgrimage. On my
journey, for instance, one mother told me that she hoped the soil she
collected from Rose’s gravesite would improve her son’s speech
impediment. I watched another pilgrim as he asked a few boys to scoop
the radiant soil, explaining that he hoped to get some relief for pains that
he couldn’t quite locate. Still another came to see old friends. I suppose I
would count myself within a category of pilgrim known as curiositas
18
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
(which also dates back to the Middle Ages), and that echoes the “oceanic
feeling” insofar as it references a restless curiosity about a world beyond
the confines of the self, and yet that does not claim to enter into the realm
of an after-world. Scorned by Christian doctrine because of its corporeal
motivation (Korte, 2000, p. 26), the “curious” pilgrim, then and now, may
be thus characterized by an interest in the surprising qualities of the
extant world, the horizons of meaning opened through migration and
the intimate relations made with strangers en route (Rudolph, 2004, pp.
5, 18).
It was a group kid pilgrims who helped me think about the idea of
curiositas and its relation to questions of trauma, travel and working
through. Perhaps themselves motivated by curiositas, a small group of
giggling girls followed me across the grounds of the pilgrimage in my
bid to find a Diet Coke. Somewhere along the way, I stopped and spoke
to one survivor of the school who said that she has been attending the
pilgrimage for eight years. It helped her “not get too lost” in the bad
memories that came when she reflected back on her experiences in the
absent school that still loomed so large. She asked where I was from.
When I said “Toronto,” she looked surprised. “You mean we’re that
big?” Together, we shared a laugh about this familiar assumption about
the city as indicator of things important. I also shared my curiosity about
the pilgrimage. “I’m interested in the history of the school, and about
Rose,” I offered. Her reply assured me that there was “a lot to learn and
people will help you.” Just then, another pilgrim handed me the ice cold
drink I had ordered from the stand. My temporary companion ordered
the same. I held “as true” her assurance of that complex balance between
not knowing and asking for help. We smiled and parted ways.
I strolled further into the grounds and came across a wooden
platform that was attached to a stairwell. Peering over the edge, I saw
that the stairs led down to a walking path faced by a flat hill face where
planks of painted white wood spelled out the endpoint of the
19
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
pilgrimage: “ROSE.” Adjacent to this wooden announcement sit the train
tracks. Climbing down the stairs, I remember thinking to myself that the
tracks marked the former site of the cemetery where Rose was originally
buried. I wondered about its exact location, but this was impossible to
tell. “How old do you think I am?” someone asked. I turned around to
see that the group of giggles had grown from two to three. “If I could
guess?” was my weak reply. “Yea, just guess!” she was excited now,
pointing to each of her friends and disclosing their ages. Clues. “I think
you might be around 11 years old,” I tried. “Almost!! I’m 14 but
everyone thinks I’m younger.” Everyone thought about that. A train
clacked by. The girls asked the customary question of where I was from.
“I love Toronto!” the age-guessing-initiator gushed: no, playfully
mocking. They did not ask the reason for my journey. Over the course of
our conversation, I learned that all three had been traveling the
pilgrimage as long as they could remember.
One girl was from Winnipeg, and had come with her mother and
father on a tour organized by their church group. They had made the trip
collectively on a Greyhound bus. Another girl had driven with her mother
and grandmother “for about 2 hours” in a rented van from her
community on a nearby Lake. The third girl was quiet, as was I. And
then I asked something else: “Did your grandmother go to the school
that used to be here?” This question was met with a long silence: No
answer of any kind. My mind turned over in the silence to consider that
familiar methodological problem of unequal power: Who was I and what
did I want from the other’s story? There is embedded, as well, a question
of community and of cross-culture: What, if anything, could I “know”
about this collective inheritance of history? It was clear to me, in the most
basic terms, that these kids didn’t trust me. Or, as Kristeva might say,
they didn’t believe me. Standing on those wooden stairs, our interaction
lacked the belief needed to speak of an unutterable history that could not
simply be shared on demand. At the same time, these little pilgrims did
20
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
believe that their silence could communicate something else to me, such
as changing the subject. “Is it true they shoot Twilight here?” one of them
ventured. She followed this with an explanation that my adult status
seemed to require: “It’s a movie about vampires.” I confessed I didn’t
know. They all agreed it was possible.
This little scene returns us to Kristeva’s view that belief is needed – a
bridge – across which to give language to what fails to easily signify, to
experiences that do not neatly or simply fit within an answer. For Fiske,
too, this is precisely why it is not sufficient to read the narrative of Rose
of the Carrier solely as a symbol of colonial power that her followers
passively accept. What gets forgotten in this reading are the ways that
meaning “is also negotiated by the colonized, who seek, even as the
colonizers seek, to render the others' humanity in their own terms”
(Fiske, 1996, p. 665). Where Fiske describes the meanings the colonized
“seek,” I might add, following Kristeva, the meanings the colonized
“speak.” The idea here is not to erase the radically different positions of
power held by the colonizer and colonized, but rather to note the
struggles to assert a voice in a context that both constructed and sought
to silence it.15 Fiske (1996) emphasizes the transformative power of this
irony in relation to the Rose pilgrimage: the historical conditions of
colonial oppression that worked as “an erasure of difference” now
support the Aboriginal belief in the miracles of Rose and through which
pilgrims seek to transform this very history (p. 670).
What is important about this last point is that it takes seriously the
post-colonial insistence on viewing colonized subjects, both Rose of the
Carrier and her followers, as implicated in “transculturation:” or, reciting “given” meanings that give way to the possibility of resistance,
and the generation of meanings through the co-optation of old forms.
But it is also the case that Rose’s iconic status is not simply evidence of
Catholic conversion, however creatively pilgrims may re-cite this
religious legacy: Her power may also derive force from existing Carrier
21
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
beliefs. Before encountering white culture, for instance, female prophets
abound in Carrier (creation) myths: a virgin mother who gives birth to a
creator hero (Estas), heroines who use medicinal powers to rescue entire
villages, and girl characters who consistently represent the importance of
Carrier women in the survival of culture, generation and power (Jenness,
1934). The point here is that the need to believe in the miracles of Rose
may hook into an earlier need that pre-dates the Catholic form it now
takes. For Fiske, Rose of the Carrier is iconic because she embodies the
tensions of identity lived by Aboriginal followers who believe in her:
these are tensions between Carrier beliefs and colonial beliefs (the latter
often “legitimated” over the former in the name of “religion”), between
empowerment and paternalism and between traditional ways of life and
engaging an uncertain future of becoming and belonging.16 Belief may be
the condition from which to risk speaking about the elusive quality of
living these tensions.
The central question that emerges here is not whether or not we can
do away with belief to get mourning “right,” but rather to ask what
forms of belief might allow us to tolerate the crisis of faith that loss can
set into motion. Indeed, to dismiss belief as an illusion may itself be a
defense against the force of loss and its psychical effects. Freud’s letter
correspondence with Rolland, together with Kristeva’s contemporary
discussion asks us to recognize just such a chain of psychical events: the
very same condition of belief that defends against the anxiety of loss is
also what enables one to venture forth into the unknown, and to tolerate
the anxiety that such a journey sets into motion. Psychoanalytically, the
question may be thus: What is the difference between a wishful turning
away and the belief needed to encounter the losses that face us in facing
history?
An example from the pilgrimage to Rose of the Carrier’s grave
illustrates this key difference, and which constitutes the final turn of my
paper. In a radio documentary about the pilgrimage to Lejac, producer
22
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
Betsy Trumpener focuses on the narrative of one pilgrim, Frances Rose,
who becomes, both for Trumpener and for me, a touchstone for thinking
through the question of belief after historical loss. Frances Rose, the
“second” Rose, is introduced as the daughter of a survivor of Lejac,
whose mother possibly knew the “first” Rose, though Frances isn’t quite
sure. As Trumpener understands it, Frances is “an almost reluctant
pilgrim” because she is uncertain about the possibility of the redemptive
narrative that promises healing through faith in miracles, especially
through a colonial lens of Christianity. In this sense, Frances Rose offers
an implicit critique of Fiske’s argument discussed above, for her
reticence points to the risks of repeating the colonial terms of belief that
had a hand in producing the wounds that the pilgrimage looks to heal.
But Frances Rose has not lost faith entirely. She translates into the radio
waves a conflict invoked by her own journey: on the one hand, a desire
to re-connect (or re-legere)17 with the generation that precedes her and on
the other hand, an anxiety about the irredeemable losses that this desire
may forget.
Occupying this conflicted terrain, Frances Rose, this “reluctant
pilgrim” yearns for the possibility of healing and raises bold questions
that point to the limits of this wish:
I’m kinda shocked because it was quite emotional, and
[tearful], yeah, I’m just kinda shocked, by the, the strength
of the emotion behind it. And, and I’m actually, it was a
little bit of a struggle when my friend Betsy asked me to
come and meet her here, ‘cause, I know it, like physically,
physically it’s a very beautiful area, but, um, my mom
went to Lejac. And it was a very painful place for her to go
and. I guess I’m just, um, like [addressing the Bishop]
what do you think that, um, do you think that there’s, can
be more that can be done to bring healing to the
communities, because of what was done here, because,
23
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
like, do you see more of a role of the church?
For this second Rose, the journey is not so much a planned itinerary that
she follows to the endpoint of absolute Truth – whether facts or miracles.
It is more a journey into a site of conflict in which to raise questions
about what “more” there is to do because of “what was done,” and what
it can mean to remember horror in beautiful places. If the Rose
pilgrimage on the surface promises wishful absolution, for Frances Rose,
it feels more like an awakening to the irreparable wounds that haunt the
land.18 The difference here may be a difference between belief as a
wishful turning away from reality and imagining a form of reparation
that can admit the impossibility of redemption.
But there is more, for Frances Rose also shows the work of belief in
becoming a speaking being after historical loss. Here, she speaks of the
loss of her mother tongue in the language of the colonizer: a lingering
trace of her mother’s residential school experience. In speaking of this
loss, Frances Rose herself breaks down, and in some ways the break in
her speech enacts the trauma of her mother’s forced silence. But Frances
Rose is also compelled to speak at precisely this moment where words
fail:
My mom was, um, came here earlier than her actual
schooling would have really begun. I think she was about
three or four. It was very terrifying, it was very lonely.
Um, and it was made harder because she wasn’t allowed
to speak her own language. Um, they were physically
abused, if [pause, crying] if they talked in their native
tongue. And then she said it would be scary too, because
there were times when she would hear screaming in
different parts of the school, not knowing what it was all
about and, you know, growing up with my sisters, you
know we heard about the pain.
24
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
Frances struggles with an internal conflict: while no words feel quite
right, she also seems to believe in the possibility – the duty – to speak
across this generational divide. There is something of a “miracle” in
finding words that speak to the loss of her mother tongue. In spite of this
loss, but also because of it, she risks narrating the force of this
“unclaimed” history.
The documentary closes with Rose Prince’s re-definition of “a
miracle” that exceeds the confines of the church. “It’s hard to believe,”
Frances Rose says, “that this is the same place that caused so much, so
many generations of, of hurt and pain in our First Nations
communities…that there’s seagulls flying around in the air, and kids
laughing and playing, and you know the sun is shining and there’s a
beautiful gentle breeze.” Laughing, she adds, “That could be a miracle
whether the church acknowledges it or not.” Frances Rose does not say
that it is impossible to believe, but that it is “hard to believe.” For Frances
Rose, and perhaps many post-memorial survivors of her generation, it
may be “hard to believe” not because the history at stake is untrue, but
because it implicates the self, in its very being, in a truth that disrupts the
very boundaries we have to protect the ego from pain. That is, it may be
“hard” to “hold for vital” the truth of trauma as the grounds of existence.
From Frances Rose’s vantage of the grassy hilltop at Lejac, belief is
not simply an illusion, but needed to survive the rupture of
acknowledging what is painful about the past, and contemplating the
many and lingering effects of its losses in the present. The figure of the
“reluctant pilgrim” may be a close cousin of the curiositas discussed
above: both are characterized by a spirit of inquiry into a world that is
larger than the self, and yet without the wishful seeking after miracles in
the hereafter. Indeed, this “reluctant pilgrim” may look very much like
the young woman from Winnipeg who I spoke to on the staircase
leading down to Fraser Lake, the one who, in refusing my question,
asked her own.
25
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
Risking Belief: Traveling the Historical Unconscious
It is tempting to conclude this meditation with a cautionary tale that pits
belief against historical thought. Indeed, there is a stubborn quality to the
pilgrim’s belief – what Jonathan Lear (2006) calls a “thick concept” (p.
108) – that suggests this temptation may well be warranted. As Kristeva
(2009) admits, the need to believe is always, “potentially fundamentalist”
(p. 14). When we follow in the footsteps of lost others, there may be a
need for absolution – in Freud’s words, an “illusion” – where none exists.
But, as Frances Rose teaches us, it is this same need for belief that also
enables one to tolerate, and even risk a relation with that which is most
uncertain, and unsettles the self. This may be the fine risk of mourning,
where the initial need to preserve history exactly as it was, unremittingly
safe from “decay” may give way to its working over in thought and in
memory. In this way, I think the figure of the “reluctant” pilgrim may be
an ironic model of belief: neither a wishful turning away from reality nor
an equally dismissive nihilism, but a risky relation that plunges one into
the conditions of thinking itself: where it is possible to symbolize a
relation to experiences that are otherwise “un-named,” yet to be spoken,
yet to be history.
In a time when the Canadian government has officially sought to
redress the devastating effects of the residential school in its Truth and
Reconciliation Commission, news of the Rose of the Carrier pilgrimage is
particularly apt, for it suggests something about the unofficial and
embodied ways memory persists, working itself through very specific
relations and between generations.19 Tracing the footpaths of pilgrimage
points to the affective and lingering presence of memory that takes shape
in the restless inclination to recuperate losses that one cannot simply
leave behind. It is to notice, as well, that history is not simply a matter of
arriving at consciousness, but acknowledging what about history makes
consciousness so fraught and so painful. I think of the silence by the
26
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
railway, and about the terrible reversal of Priests offering confession in
place of taking responsibility. But I think also about the seagulls, the
games, and even about movies. The question the pilgrimage left behind
in me is not simply how people, students and pilgrims alike, can
remember better or even more, but perhaps: is belief a kind of grief? The
reluctant pilgrim offers a response to this last question, admitting as she
does that to believe in traumatic history is not simply miraculous but
“hard:” Particularly in a field organized around understanding, such
that education tends to be, it is hard to speak in terms that pierce the
disciplinary boundaries we typically use to ward off the uncertainties
that knowledge ushers in.
To the extent that the pilgrimage reaches into the realm of history’s
difficult passage, I believe it offers a compelling metaphor for re-thinking
history curriculum. By curriculum, I am referring, of course, not to the
itinerary of Ministry documents, but rather, the history that is produced
through specific contexts and relations, where historical knowledge is
less a matter of what has already happened and more an uncertain
possibility made in relation to another. At issue here is a course of study
not as a set path or pre-given collection of representations, but the
capacity to read history symptomatically, as always saying more than
can be directly spoken. This kind of history happens in schools, yes, but,
also outside of its official walls, such as on a grassy hill overlooking
Fraser Lake, in attending, and believing in, narrative accounts of
historical rupture, and that exceed “concrete evidence.”
The education of history is very much about teaching critical thinking
skills that the historian him/herself uses to analyze documents and piece
together a plausible narrative account. But it is at the same time both
more unruly and subtle than this: history is a matter of attending the
paths people take – and make – off the beaten path as a sign of its
affective and lingering effects. The pilgrimage may thus take educational
theory on a journey that is as far off the beaten path of consciousness.
27
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
The pilgrimage, together with the beliefs that drive it, challenge
educators to notice how curriculum may, at times, wishfully turn away
from the difficulty of history. But it might also be occasion to face
memories that cannot easily be captured in conventional terms of
narration and that exceed efforts to render them “in a straightforward
way” (Caruth, 1996, p. 5). After all, it is one thing to travel – or teach – on
the wish that the “reality” of the past can be miraculously recovered or
re-done better with proper skill or right thinking; it is another to
recognize that something singularly traumatic happened and to attend
its lingering and persistent effects, including the need to believe. It is
precisely such a journey that I think education may itself need to risk
taking, where what is at stake for curriculum is not solely knowledge,
but the need to believe that it is possible to stand in relation to history’s
losses that at the same time threaten to displace this very footing.
What remains of LeJac
Railway beside Fraser Lake
Confessions
Pilgrimage tents and stairwell to left
28
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
Acknowledgements
This paper is part of a three-year research project, “Spaces of Memory:
Between Internal Objects and Tangible Relics in Learning from the Past”
funded by the Social Sciences and Research Council of Canada. I would
like to acknowledge this funding agency for its generous support of
educational research that travels into places of unlikely learning.
Notes
1
Betsy Trumpener, The Miracles of Rose Prince (The Current, Canadian
Broadcasting Corporation, October 2008). Last downloaded on 26 June
2010 from: http://www.cbc.ca/thecurrent/2008/10/october-162008.html
2
David Gruenwald phrases this statement without the shield of
negation: “Power and domination,” he writes, “are inscribed in material
spaces” (p. 6). How one moves, who can move, and where one feels
authorized to go or not go are written into the crevices of a place.
3
Ronald Britton (1998) concretizes the idea: “What is perceived requires
belief to be regarded as knowledge” (p. 13, my emphasis). From the other
direction, however, belief alone is not sufficient, lest it slip into Freud’s
wishful turning away from reality; belief thus requires material evidence,
or “sensory confirmation (reality testing) in order to become knowledge”
(Britton, 1998, p. 13).
4
Plato famously drew this conclusion in The Republic, where he put
forward his idea of an ideal city as one built upon knowledge –
produced through argument and disputation – rather than belief. With
this, Plato proposed to settle the conflict between poetry and philosophy
by choosing reason, and exiling the poets from public life.
5
Freud also described this process as “reality-testing,” where the ego
learns to channel its drive for pleasure in to satisfactions that can be
29
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
attained in actual relations, rather than mere wishes. See this earlier
discussion, though not related to religion, in his essay on the “Two
Principles of Mental Functioning.”
6
While it is often Romain Rolland and Carl Jung who are read as the
imagined readers of Freud’s critique of religion, Paul Roazen argues that
Oskar Pfister, a pastor and practicing analyst, should also be counted in
this readership. Not only were Freud and Pfister in regular letter
correspondence, Roazen notes that when “the full difficulties between
Freud and Jung broke out,” Pfister was exceptional in his decision to
“stick by Freud’s side” (p. 557). He argues that Freud’s 1927 critique of
religion is as much a “break” from Jung as it is a marker of the tightening
of Freud's circle of friends, which included Pfister. I would agree with
Roazen here, adding, of course, Freud’s intensified friendship with
Romain Rolland.
7
Incidentally, Freud had in a letter of 1923 distinguished his own writing
from Rolland’s on precisely these grounds: “My writings cannot be what
yours are: comfort and refreshment for the reader” (Freud, 1923, p. 201).
8
Oskar Pfister would second Rolland’s motion in his 1928 letter of
“friendly disagreement” with Freud. Here, Pfister points out that Freud’s
own searches after truth resembled the very same religious spirit of
inquiry he also denounced: “To be frank about it,” writes Pfister, “I have
a strong suspicion that you do battle against religion – out of religious
feeling” (1928, p. 559.) With this suggestion, Pfister, alongside Rolland,
brings together Freud’s scientific “struggle for truth,” a spirit of inquiry
into the unknown, that brought him closer to religiosity (or at least the
“oceanic feeling”) than he could himself acknowledge.
9
Freud is referring here to Hannibal, with whom he claims a strong
identification. As the ancient story goes, Hannibal was a great leader
30
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
who opened the door of power to the people of Rome by sharing with
them his skills as a warrior that they then used against him (Blatt, 1988).
10
While Freud claims to find “no trace” of the “oceanic feeling” in
himself (1930, p. 4), he does find evidence of the opposite feeling of
“disbelief.” Interestingly, Freud (1936) pens this observation in yet
another exchange with Romain Rolland, a letter that is published under
the title, “A Disturbance of Memory on the Acropolis.” In it, Freud
recounts an overwhelming feeling of “disbelief” as he climbed onto the
base of the crumbling artifact for the very first time. Freud explains the
feeling – what he calls “estrangement” – as a defense against not only the
enormous “reality” before his eyes but a repressed psychical reality that
is at once more elusive and powerful (p. 73). The psychical reality at
stake is an Oedipal conflict of having surpassed his father who had never
traveled so far. It seems to me that, in this letter, Freud is re-opening an
old conversation with Rolland. While Freud decides, once again, on
scientific knowledge of “Oedipal return” it is notable that the idea of
belief still pre-occupies Freud in this late letter to his friend. It would
seem that Freud comes close to the idea of belief through a negation: he
recognizes the refusal to believe as defensive, even if there isn’t yet, in
positive terms, a “need to believe.”
11
Kristeva’s views are close to Jacques Lacan’s here (McAfee, 2004). Both
believe that psychoanalysis is a process of helping patients tolerate the
lack that constitutes being. But where Kristeva departs from Lacan is in
her belief that language can in some ways reach into the unutterable,
what Rolland called “the oceanic” while for Lacan, this realm (what he
called “the Real”) is always outside of our efforts to symbolize it. By
contrast, Kristeva argues that the unutterable experience of loss (both
ordinary and catastrophic) can be spoken (though always incompletely)
31
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
“without,” she argues, “simply saying it is an emptiness or blank” (as
cited in Guberman, 1996, pp. 22-23).
12
Indeed, this may be what Sarah Kofman (1976) had in mind in writing
about an “impervious need to have my words taken up, taken.”
13
The tension between repetition and re-citation hooks into a tension
articulated in cultural and post-colonial studies on shifting conceptions
of melancholia. This literature focuses on melancholia’s “structure of
feeling” not simply in terms of an individualistic experience or illness,
but an “extended capacity for representation” (Eng & Kazanjian, 2000, p.
4). In the face of the catastrophic losses that mark history, these theorists
argue that, “avowals of and attachments to loss can produce a world of
remains as a world of new representations and alternative meanings” (p.
5). But there is debate about how, and whether this psychic condition –
characterized as it is by internal suffering – can be rendered as a
politically and ethically productive category (Brown, 1995). For instance,
Deborah Britzman argues that the tendency to idealize loss and to
reenact the abandonment that loss invokes (also the melancholic’s
tendency) “must be exceeded” if it is to be worked through (p. 33).
Melancholia is “bound to the nostalgia for an idealized and unchanged
world” where mourning is “an ethical struggle with reconstituting the
self as subject to a relation that is no longer” (p. 34). A similar tension
underlies the two dimensions of belief that my paper engages: on the one
hand, there is the belief in the erotic object that one holds as ideal and the
belief in the possibility of speaking of experiences that defy language, of
finding meaning in life in the face of the fact of mortality. My own view
is that these positions are mutually constituting rather than
developmental. That is, the need to believe in the continuity of existence
may be the condition needed to tolerate – and to acknowledge – the
fragility of life, and history.
32
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
14
The wish-fulfilling quality of belief risks turning away from evidence
of the residential school’s many failures as they are convincingly
documented in John Milloy’s, A National Crime. Wish-fulfilling beliefs
proceed without regard for reality, and can, at times, be mistaken for
reality. An instance of this confusion can be found in an account of an
interview following the 2004 pilgrimage posted by St. Andrew’s Church
(downloaded on July 2, 2010 from
http://www.pgdiocese.bc.ca/events/roseprince.htm). The interview
recounts Bishop Gerald Wiesner’s belief that Rose of the Carrier
represents the success of the residential school: “We have a lot of
controversy about the residential schools but Rose Prince was someone
who spent almost her entire life in a residential school and was respected
then and now as someone who excelled in Christian virtue throughout
her life.” This construction of Rose as a Christian ideal cannot tolerate the
idea that the perceived “success” of the school in its religious inculcation
is also its utter “failure” insofar as it signifies as the destruction of an
entire system of belief of another. Belief, here, functions to avoid the
ambiguities of “success,” and how another kind of “success” may be
embodied, as one pilgrim will show, as a creative re-appropriation of
belief to question the church’s own crimes.
15
For Jacques Derrida, this conflict is the conundrum of post-colonial
languages, and perhaps all languages insofar as their origin is always
already “prosthetic.” For Derrida, the conundrum is that the very
language I claim as my own – the language I “have” – is at the same time
“not mine” but my internalization of another (1998a, p. 2).
16
I am here reminded of the tail end of my conversation with the girls at
Fraser Lake, and in particular, their question of whether or not Twilight
was filmed on the grounds of the pilgrimage. It is beyond the scope of
this paper to delve in enough detail into the parallels between the legend
33
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
of Rose and that of the film to which these youth referred. But
straightaway, we can note that Twilight begins with the very same idea of
the “un-dead” in its plotline of vampires and shape-shifters. It is
impossible to know what was wanted from the question uttered on the
steps that summer day, but it strikes me, afterward, that Twilight circles
around themes not unlike those of the story of Rose: this is a show about
crossing cultural boundaries and about the question of conversion. For
instance, Edward Cullen, the show’s vampire, falls in love with a human
named Bella Swan: And, Bella, in turn, makes known her desire to be
converted to a vampire. The story is even more complicated by Bella’s
other pursuer: a young werewolf named Jacob Black whose clan is of
Aboriginal decent. Legend is that the vampires and werewolves signed a
treaty, alleging that werewolves would not disclose to the white man the
whereabouts of vampires on the condition that vampires stop hunting on
werewolf territory. It might be too much to squeeze the complex and
layered events of colonial history into a movie screen, not the least of
which is about vampires. But this young pilgrim’s startling question
haunted me for weeks upon my return home, leading me down an
unplanned path of still more questions: What if we were to read this
pilgrim’s question about Twilight as a screen for the un-spoken (and unchosen) history of Catholic conversion? Which boy – and which history –
ought Bella choose? What does it mean to convert outside one’s clan?
What would it mean to “shift” the colonial “shape” of history? In what
ways might this love triangle offer a screen on which to work through
difficult tensions of colonial subjectivity: between conversion and
tradition, or between inheritance and choice, between cultural death and
the simmering underworld of the un-dead?
17
Here I am making reference to Jacques Derrida, who, in his chapter,
“Faith and Knowledge,” traces the etymology of religion (all the while
34
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
acknowledging what is problematic about etymology). Through this
exercise, he notes “two sources” of religion: “religio,” which implies a
holding back or a being unscathed, safe and sound; and “re-legere,”
which implies a linking up with another not on the basis of
understanding, but a leap of faith into the unknown (1998b, p. 16). Much
like Kristeva, Derrida is trying to understand the “link” that defines
religion prior to the link between man and the belief in a singular God.
Derrida is attempting to “un-close,” as much as possible, the circularity
of belief that confirms itself – in order to open the link as wide as
possible to welcome the Other in the fullest Levinasian sense of “radical
alterity.”
18
One of the Bishops who Rose meets on her journey appears supremely
moved in a similar way. And yet, I wish to submit that his response
avoids the question of what historical responsibility can mean beyond
his own wishes for redemption. By contrast, Frances Rose seeks to return
the listener’s attention to the complexities of “healing” – and the
possibility of a sustained and committed relation to justice – that refuses
any magical redress. Without collapsing what are very complicated
relations between the colonizer and the colonized, I think there is an
important distinction to be made between these positions in thinking
about the return to sites of memory. Edward Said, too, makes a similar
point in his study of British and French pilgrimages of the nineteenth
century. At this time in history, he notes that all pilgrimages, both British
and French, to the Orient promised travelers encounters with
“eccentricities of Oriental life” that depended on unequal relations of
power between European visitors and native dwellers of the land (1978,
p. 166). And yet, he also notes a key difference between the British and
the French pilgrim. For the British, the Orient was India, which means
that his travels took him to the site of “a major colony,” or more
35
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
candidly, “an actual British possession” (p. 169). The French pilgrim, by
contrast, was “imbued with a sense of acute loss in the Orient,” for he set
foot on land where the French, unlike the British, “had no sovereign
presence” (p. 169). For a discussion of the pilgrimage in the Orient, see
Edward Said, Orientalism (New York: Vintage, 1978). Though debates
persist about the meaning of travel writing of this period, Said’s
discussion enables the following questions: What, if anything, is the
difference between the colonizer’s and the subaltern subject’s return to
sites, such as Rose’s grave, that mark the persisting, inter-generational
effects of this historical relation? Of what might this difference consist?
What histories do travelers bring with them to sites of memory? For Said,
the distinction between colonizer and the subaltern subject is deeply
significant, for it is one thing to travel with a sense of entitlement and
quite another to be confronted with a sense of displacement – of
desperately seeking a home – on the journey. To return to the case that
frames this section, Said gives us pause to wonder whether the Bishop’s
desire for reparation has more to do with an attempt to re-find footing in
the face of the lost idealism of the church, than with the sense of “acute
loss” and dislocation that faces, and “kinda shocks,” Frances Rose.
19
It is not without significance that the Lieutenant Governor of British
Columbia addressed the pilgrims of the 2010 pilgrimage.
36
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
References
Bauman, Z. (1996). “From Pilgrim to Tourist: Or, A Short History of
Identity,” in S. Hall & P. Du Gay (Eds.), Questions of Cultural Identity
(pp. 18-36). London: Sage.
Beckerman, Z.; Burbules, N C.; and Silberman-Keller, D. (Eds.). (2006).
Learning in Places: The Informal Education Reader. New York, Peter
Lang.
Blatt, D. S. (1988). “The Development of the Hero: Sigmund Freud and
the Reformation of the Jewish Tradition,” Psychoanalysis and
Contemporary Thought, 11: 639-703.
Britton, R. (1998). Belief and Imagination: Explorations in Psychoanalysis.
London, UK: Routledge.
Britzman, D. (2000). “If the Story Cannot End: Deferred Action,
Ambivalence, and Difficult Knowledge,” in R.I. Simon, S. Rosenberg
& C. Eppert (Eds.), Between Hope and Despair: Pedagogy and the
Remembrance of Historical Trauma (pp. 27-57). Lanham: Rowman &
Littlefield.
Brown, W. (1995). States of Injury: Power and Freedom in Late Modernity.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Burbules, N. & Berk, R. (1999). “Critical Thinking and Critical Pedagogy:
Relations, Differences and Limits,” in T. Popkewitz & L. Fendler
(Eds.), Critical Theories in Education (pp. 45-66). New York: Routledge.
Caruth, C. (1996). Unclaimed Experience: Trauma, Narrative, and History.
Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.
Christensen, L. & Crimmel, H. (2008). Teaching about Place: Learning from
the Land. Las Vagas: University of Nevada Press.
Chambers, C. (2008). “Where are we? Finding Common Ground in a
Curriculum of Place,” Journal of the Canadian Association of Curriculum
Studies, 6(2): 113-128.
37
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
Derrida, J. (1998a). Monolingualism of the Other: Or, the Prosthesis of Origin
(Trans. P. Mensah and Eds. M. Bal & H de Vries). Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Derrida, J. (1998b). Religion (Trans. S. Weber). Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Ellsworth, E. (1997). Teaching Positions. New York: Teachers College
Press.
Ellworth, E. (2005). Places of Learning: Media, Architecture, Pedagogy. New
York: Routledge.
Eng, D.L. & Kazanjian, D. (Eds.). (2000). Loss. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Fiske, J.A. (1996).“Pocahontas’s Granddaughters: Spiritual Transition
and Tradition of Carrier Women of British Columbia,” Ethnohistory
43(4): 663-681.
Freud, E. L. (Ed.), (1960). Letters of Sigmund Freud (Trans., T. Stern & J.
Stern). New York: Dover.
Freud, S. (1911/1991). “Two Principles of Mental Functioning,” in J.
Strachey (Trans.) & A. Richards (Ed.), On Metapsychology (pp. 29-44).
London, UK: Penguin.
Freud, S. (1927/2004). “The Future of an Illusion,” in J. A. Underwood
(Trans.) & A. Phillips (Ed.), Mass Psychology and Other Writings (pp.
109-164) London: Penguin.
Freud, S. (1930/2002). “Civilization and its Discontents,” in D.
McLintock (Trans.) & A. Phillips (Ed.), Civilization and its Discontents
(pp. 1-82). London: Penguin.
Freud, S. (1936/2005). “Letter to Romain Rolland (A Disturbance of
Memory on the Acropolis,)” in S. Whiteside (Trans.) and A. Phillips
(Ed.), On Murder, Mourning and Melancholia (pp. 233-245). London:
Penguin.
Gruenewald, D.A. (2003). “The Best of Both Worlds: A Critical Pedagogy
of Place,” Educational Researcher 32(4): 3-12
38
“The Reluctant Pilgrim:” Questioning Belief After Historical Loss
FARLEY
Guberman, R. (Ed.). (1996). Julia Kristeva Interviews. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Jenness, D. (1934). “Myths of the Carrier Indians,” Journal of American
Folklore, 47: 97-257.
Haig-Brown, C. (2008). “Taking Indigenous Thought Seriously: A Rant
on Globalization and Some Cautionary Notes,” Journal of the Canadian
Association of Curriculum Studies, 6(2): 8-24.
Kincheloe, J & Pinar, W. (1991). Curriculum as Social Psychoanalysis: The
Significance of Place. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Kirshenblatt-Gimblett, B. (1998). Destination Culture: Tourism, Museums,
and Heritage. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
Kofman, S. (1976/2008). “My Life and Psychoanalysis,” In G. Albert
(Trans.), Selected Writings (pp. 250-251). Stanford: Stanford University
Press.
Korte, B. (2000). English Travel Writing from Pilgrimages to Postcolonial
Explorations, trans., Catherine Matthias. London: MacMillan Press.
Kristeva, J. (2009). This Incredible Need to Believe. New York, NY:
Columbia University Press.
Lear, J. (2006). Radical Hope: Ethics in the Face of Cultural Devastation.
Cambridge, UK: Harvard University Press.
Milloy, J. (1999). A National Crime: The Canadian Government and the
Residential School 1876-1986. Manitoba: University of Manitoba Press.
Nouzeilles, G. (2008). “Touching the Real: Alternative Travel and
Landscapes of Fear,” in J. Zilcosky (Ed.), Writing Travel: The Poetics
and Politics of Modern Travel (pp. 195-210). Toronto: University of
Toronto press.
Pfister, O. (1928/1993). “The Illusion of a Future: A Friendly
Disagreement with Prof. Sigmund Freud, edited with an introductory
note by Paul Roazen” International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 74(3): 557579.
Plato. (1987). The Republic. (Trans. D. Lee). London, UK: Penguin.
39
Journal of the Canadian Association for Curriculum Studies
Robertson, J. & Radford, L. (2010). “The Private Uses of Quiet Grandeur:
A Meditation on Literary Pilgrimage,” Changing English: An
International Journal of English Teaching, 16(2): 203-209.
Rone, T. R. (2008). “Culture from the Outside In and the Inside Out:
Experiential Education and the Continuum of Theory, Practice and
Policy, College Teaching, 56(4): 237-245.
Rudolph, C. (2004). Pilgrimage to the End of the World: The Road to Santiago
de Compostela. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Said, E. (1978). Orientalism. New York: Vintage.
Sumption, J. (1975). Pilgrimage: An Image of Mediaeval Religion. London:
Faber & Faber.
Zilcosky, J. (2008). (Ed.), “Writing Travel,” Writing Travel: The Poetics and
Politics of Modern Travel (pp. 1-21) Toronto: University of Toronto
Press.
40