970
Book Reviews
the numbers and statistics he uses, suspecting (rightly) the different sources to be biased.
He is brought about to develop salutary margins of caution in everything he says, showing
that a scientist’s work cannot be abstract neutrality,
but on the contrary, critical
impartiality.
Roux’s book is a major contribution
to the study of the Albanians in the Balkans
(although it mainly deals with ethnic Albanians in what used to be Yugoslavia) a major
contribution
to the history of the integration of a part of the Balkans (Bulgaria, Greece,
Turkey and Albania are excluded, when a reference to them is not instrumental to the
topic), as well as a significant contribution
to the history of the (dis)integration
of
Yugoslavia as a whole.
Rada IvekoviC
Universitt! de Paris-8
Wittgenstein’s Centenary Essays, ed. A. Phillips
University Press, 1991), E10.95 P.B.
Grifliths
(Cambridge:
Cambridge
This is a collection of essays based on the 1989-1990 series of Royal Institute of
Philosophy
lectures given in London to mark the centenary of the birth of Ludwig
Wittgenstein (1889-1951).
The collection is mixed, both in substance, style and quality. Notable contributions
range from Crispin Wright’s relatively specialised
discussion
in ‘Wittgenstein
on
Mathematical
Proof to Jacques Bouveresse’s historical discussion about Wittgenstein’s
attitude to the political world in which he lived in “‘The Darkness of This Time”:
Wittgenstein
and the Modern World’. John Shotter’s ‘Wittgenstein
and Psychology’
discusses the social aspect of Wittgenstein’s later work in light of the cognitive-oriented
psychology
practised
widely today. And Frank Cioffi’s ‘Wittgenstein
on Freud’s
‘ “Abominable Mess” ’ is a detailed piece which seeks to clarify Wittgenstein’s accusation
that Freud has conflated reasons and causes. The rule-following
considerations
of
Philosophical Investigations, which have been brought to attention in the last lO- 12 years
by Crispin Wright and Saul Kripke, are discussed by Shotter, Wright, Trigg, Grayling and
O’Hear. Peter Winch’s ‘Certainty and Authority’ and Renford Bambrough’s ‘Fools and
Heretics’ both advert to remarks Wittgenstein makes in On Certainty and relate them to
questions
about the nature of political authority
and the resolution
of conflict,
respectively.
I cannot begin to elaborate all of the essays presented in this collection, so I shall limit
myself to giving some brief examples of the diverse matters discussed, and attempt to draw
attention to questions which might arise from these discussions.
I shall focus most
attention on Wright’s article.
Roger Trigg’s ‘Wittgenstein and Social Science’ argues that ‘Wittgenstein’s emphasis
on the social character of concepts makes the task of sociai science. . . an impossible one’,
and that ‘in rooting our reason in society, he makes it impossible to reason about society’.
Trigg’s discussion is thought-provoking
but unfortunately
remains at the rather abstract
and non-penetrating
level of the above-expressed
thought. What, for example, is a claim
that the social scientist wants to make that is precluded by Wittgenstein’s
dismissal of
History of European Ideas
Book Reviews
metaphysics? Trigg claims that social scientists have to do more than describe how their
subjects conceive the world, or else ‘everything would be apparent at the surface of
society’. But this is an odd claim. One would have thought that uncovering
the
assumptions, expectations,
or ‘rules’ by which societies function would be an immensely
complicated
undertaking,
even if one merely restricted one’s task to description.
In
particular, if it is an alien society, then the interpreter’s own descriptions, though perhaps
not ‘unbiased’ in a way natural scientists aspire to, is none the less informative to those in
the interpreter’s
own culture. These are merely preliminary
thoughts, but the issues
discussed here certainly bear deeper and perhaps more philosophical
scrutiny.
In ‘Certainty and Authority’, Peter Winch attempts to bring to bear questions about the
nature of practical rationality that Wittgenstein
considers in On Certainty to ‘deep’
questions in political philosophy regarding the nature of the state’s authority, and the role
of consent. He argues that Wittgenstein has given us insight on the traditional puzzle of
reconciling the notion of a state’s authority with the notion of (individual) agency, in so
far as Wittgenstein has showed us a way of rejecting the assumptions that make it a puzzle:
So far from its being the case that all recognition of authority derives from the
exercise of practical reason on the part of the recognizer, the notion of practical
reason itself requires at many points a recognition of the authority of others that
is primitive.
The problem, of course, for any political theorist faced with the claim that our recognition
of the authority of others is primitive, is how to reconcile this with the very deeply-rooted
intuition that at least in certain cases the authority recognised seems perverse, and cries
out for justification.
But if justification
is not appropriate
here since recognition
of
authority is primitive, how can the (intuitively compelling) possibility of unjust authority
be understood?
In ‘Fools and Heretics’, Renford Brambrough
also discusses passages from On
Certainty in which Wittgenstein discusses ‘pivots’ or the state reached in a conflict where
the disputants in the conflict seem able only to reject one option or the other, but not
reason itself. In an essay that was originally a lecture presented at Swansea, Bambrough
urges us to see that inner (intrapersonal)
and outer (interpersonal)
conflict share a
common structure. In order for conversion to occur, the converted must be a single
person. In order for conflict to be resolved the ‘two parties to the conflict should share
some beliefs and understanding
that are relevant to the making of a decision’. He
concludes from this that no conflict is total, and that conflict presupposes shared belief in
such a way that ‘there is inexhaustible scope for further enquiry’.
Wright’s article, ‘Wittgenstein on Mathematical Proof attempts to explore whether the
rule-following
considerations
of the Philosophical Investigations and Remarks on the
Foundations of M athematics can be used to understand
Wittgenstein’s
apparently antirealist views on logical necessity. Wright begins by articulating an intuitively plausible
philosophy of mathematics-mathematical
realism -according
to which the mathematician is a type of explorer. He uses proofs as a kind of tool to make up for his cognitive
deficiencies (limited memory capacity, limited time) to investigate the infinite totalities to
which he has no other recourse. To investigate infinite totalities the mathematical realist
need not be committed to the existence of a platonic substrate of mathematical
objects:
It is enough if we are capable of creating, in thought, a sufftciently definite
concept of the series of natural numbers to give substance to questions about its
characteristics
which we may not know how to answer.
Wittgenstein’s
view, by contrast,
is that
Volume
18, No. 6, November
1994
972
Book Reviews
mathematics is not a project of exploration and discovery, mathematical proof is
not an instrument
whereby we find out things
. .; there is no external
compulsion upon us when we ratify proofs-we
are driven, but not by cognition
of an external, normative constraint, and insofar as there is a special sureness
about at least some mathematical
propositions,
it does not amount to a
superlative genre of knowledge-such
propositions
do not enjoy a zyxwvutsrqponmlkjih
cognitive
certainty at all.
Wright reconsiders an earlier suggestion of his (also made by Kripke) that the rulefollowing
considerations
of the Philosophical Investigations and Remarks on the
Foundations of M athematics throw light on Wittgenstein’s
philosophy of mathematics.
Wright argues that neither a Kripke-style meaning scepticism, nor even a more modest
interpretation
of the rule-following considerations
that does not question the factuality of
meaning but questions, very roughly, the idea that our getting the meaning correct can
constitute a cognitive achievement,
can explain or account for all of Wittgenstein’s
remarks on the philosophy of mathematics.
The reason, simply, is that the factual or
epistemological
challenge manifested by the discussion on rules infects all discourse. But,
as Wright maintains, Wittgenstein wanted his remarks about mathematics to indicate a
distinct thesis about the status of proofs.
For Wittgenstein, proofs are, importantly,
not like experiments and do not provide us
with the means of making discoveries in that sense. But, if the discussion on rules has the
global consequences that Wright describes, Wittgenstein will not be allowed to retain the
contrast between discovery and invention that he needs.
According to Wright:
In Wittgenstein’s
view, the internal relations
which articulate
the interconnections within a proof are acknowledged
by way of institution or custom,
following on empirical findings. And this background of unreflective custom is
not something
in which our participation
is imposed by purely cognitive
considerations.
So a faultless understanding
of each of the notions in play in a
proof and a full empirical awareness of its detail underdetermine
assent to it; one
needs, in addition, to be party to the relevant practices . . . [thus] proofs are not
instruments of discovery.
In the end, Wright voices a worry about how Wittgenstein means to invoke customs
here. If he means that without the relevant custom we could have the very same
arithmetical practices while still having the choice of answers to some proposed problem,
then something has surely gone wrong. For understanding
the concept of afunction and its
one-output character is essential to one’s grasp of arithmetic.
But surely Wittgenstein can make the same point about the ‘logical must’ here too. We
have defined adding so that only one solution to some proposed calculation is possible,
and of course we would not consider that anyone was adding who did not respect this
constraint. But this is not because the concept of mathematical
functions is somehow
independent
of the customs which we adopt when we reject the calculation as one of
addition. It seems illegitimate, in other words, to spin counterfactual
situations in which
our intuitions seem to tell against the situation under scrutiny, since, after all, these
intuitions will be the product of our customs.
This collection of essays succeeds in manifesting the diversity of possible applications of
Wittgenstein’s
thought
to issues in, for example, politics, religion, mathematics,
psychology, psychoanalysis
and aesthetics. But there are other essays-Anscombe’s,
for
example-which
attempt merely to explore carefully and even arduously some rather
specific point Wittgenstein attempts to make. And here we get a demonstration
of the
History of European Ideas
Book Reviews
973
method this unique philosopher
cultivated to work his way through philosophical
perplexities. To the extent that the essays are suggestive ofpossible applications, so too are
they provocative,
and invite further reflection and discussion.
Julia Tanney
The University of Sheffield
Pluralism, Socialism and Political Legitimacy. Reflections on Opening Up Communism,
F. M. Barnard (Cambridge University Press, 1991), xii + 189 pp., 527.95 H.B.
Writing philosophical
works is a timeless pursuit. Creating a work in philosophy of
politics is much more bound to mirror the chosen epoch, and reflecting on the ‘openingup’ of communism, as Frederick Mechner Barnard, Professor Emeritus, Department of
Political Science, University of Western Ontario, does in his Pluralism, Socialism and
Political Legitimacy , is an extremely time-sensitive
enterprise. And if the proof of the
pudding is in the eating, then the kind of pudding prepared by the ‘Really Existing
Socialism’ has been eaten up to the last crumb and the proof is, to say the least, at variance
with some of Professor Barnard’s assertions. Or rather with those which the Czech
constitutional
lawyer Dr Vladimir KlokoEka had made many years ago and which
Professor Barnard took at face value.
A preliminary word of explanation
may be needed concerning the structure of the
present book. An appendix of some 30 pages summarises
the views on electoral
confrontation
under socialism, as stated a quarter of a century ago by Dr KlokoEka.’ This
appendix would deserve a special dissertation centred on its Orwellian context. The Big
Brother was indeed closely watching every move by the protagonists of the Prague Spring
and by those engaged-like
Dr KlokoEka-in
several party-appointed
think-tanks
providing the former with ideas, sometimes bold and unorthodox,
sometimes merely
time-serving. Poker-faced, Dr KlokoEka writes: ‘The much-stressed fear of the restoration
of capitalism in developed socialist countries should, in this connection, be seen for what it
is. In our view it is not a real danger. In a developed socialist society, in a state of advanced
industrialisation,
the idea of the restoration
of capitalism is almost an anachronism’
(p. 168). Instead of being taken at its face value, such a statement is crying out for a
circumstantial
exegesis, taking into account both the Orwellian atmosphere of the time
and the spirit of the place of its origin epitomised by HaSek and Kafka.
A philosophical
work might gain the esteem of readers by the rational nature of its
argumentation
and by the persuasiveness of the empirical evidence. While Barnard’s book
does not lack rational argumentation,
often coupled with shrewd insight into the
weaknesses of alternative positions, it is the meagre support by empirical evidence which
makes the whole content of this book so questionable.
It is not easy to summarise a work which the author himself defines ‘as an essay in the
broader understanding
of political philosophy rather than as one of the more specialised,
or more systematic, modes of inquiry into Communist regimes’ (p. xi). He ‘discovered in
the debate of the Prague Spring larger questions about the nature and status of political
Volume
18, No. 6, November
1994