Reframing Beauty: Body,
Environment, Art –
An Introduction
Andrej Démuth – Lukáš Makky
What is beauty? This is probably the most enduring question in the history of
aesthetics, one that remains unsatisfactorily answered even after 300 years of
modern aesthetic research. Despite attempts by some theoreticians to classify
it (Scruton, 2009; De Clerque, 2013; Zangwill, 2013), we lack a generally
acceptable and unambiguous definition of beauty. Why it is so? The answer is
not straightforward; every period, theoretician, and phenomenon has its own
criteria and position based on the ‘situation’ of art, society, and culture.
More complex answers are suggested in the papers composing this issue of
ESPES. The Slovak Journal of Aesthetics. They prompt related and equally
important inquiries, such as the relevance of this question today, the necessity
of defining beauty, its role in aesthetics and everyday life, and what insights
current scientific research offers on beauty. However, readers familiar with
the development of aesthetic thought in the 20th century may wonder about
the significance of this return to the issue of beauty, not just the category of
beauty itself, but the notion and the attempt to define/reframe beauty in
the 21st century after the so-called ‘century without beauty’.
Probably due to the decline of modernism and postmodernism, which
minimized the importance of beauty in art, and the attempts to base
(neuro)aesthetics on scientific foundations (Chatterjee, 2015; Ramachandran
and Hirstein, 1999; Zeki, 1999), beauty was brought once again to the forefront
of aesthetic research at the end of the last century. Examples of this
rehabilitation of beauty can be found in Danto (2003), Sartwell (2004),
Nehamas (2007), Scruton (2009), Figal (2010), and others. Their works revealed
that the classical concept and understanding of beauty required intense
revision
and
reframing
(e.g.,
Mothersill,
1984),
akin
to
Derrida’s deconstruction. Theorists found it necessary to go back to the source
Vol. 12/2
2023
5
of the issue and phenomena, analyzing it step by step. Danto (2003) pursued
a similar approach but ultimately failed to find new criteria of beauty or
reframe beauty itself, lingering in the past while attempting to replace beauty
with a different category.
The last decades have witnessed a growing interest in beauty, evident not only
in the aesthetics of everyday life (e.g., Parsons and Carlsons, 2008; Saito,
2017), environmental aesthetics (e.g., Berleant, 1992; Sepanmaa, 1993;
Carlsons and Lintott, 2008; Lehtinen, Kuisma and Mäcklin, 2019), and
somaesthetics (e.g., Shusterman, 1999) but also in empirical research within
empirical aesthetics (e.g., Menninghaus et al., 2019) and many other areas.
The convergence of new approaches and acceptance of different aesthetic
phenomena prompts further questions: Are we prepared for a re-evaluation of
beauty – a reconsideration of the role of beauty in art and everyday life? Is the
topic of beauty still relevant and attractive in aesthetics?
The first serious question addressed in this issue of ESPES is whether we are
truly aware of what the common yet aesthetically compelling concept of
‘beauty’ signifies. Although we intuitively know its meaning, a closer reflection
reveals that the concept is multi-layered, ambiguous, and sometimes even
unclear and indefinite. It is one of those ‘strong’ notions, according to Ricœur
(1974), i.e., notions which mean too much and therefore they mean nothing or
mean too many things at the same time, resulting in conflicting applications.
The presented studies in the journal problematize the concept of beauty
among philosophers, aestheticians, or art theorists, as well as in the everyday
language of art-untrained users. The papers contemplate what this ‘umbrella
concept’ refers to and how its various semantic dimensions can be mapped.
Do we designate the same thing with this term? Is there a way to verify it?
The question arises whether such a conceptual understanding of the concept
of beauty is necessary at all. The need for a pragmatic use in linguistic
approach is also highlighted, for its crucial role in our understanding and use
of a given notion, not restricted only to theoretical discourse alone – nontheoretical uses also influence, from a pragmatic perspective, the use of the
notion as such (see e. g. Mandelbaum, 1970).
Even after considering the linguistic/analytic/terminological approach,
the notion of beauty is still not charted in its complexity and opens new
questions, as the ‘reframing’ of beauty is not fulfilled. Is beauty a matter of
things, of their objective qualities and forms? Or is it rather a property relating
to our perceptions, judgments, and experiences? Is it something empirically
real, or is it 'just’ an idea, a concept, or an entity of our thinking and
experiencing? Does it exist independently of us, and does it make sense to
think about it only through the perspective of the beholder? Is it necessary to
learn to perceive it, or is it instinctively obvious? Is there a universal beauty, or
are there countless diverse and incomparable types? How do the idea and ideal
of beauty change over time, and how do political, social, cultural, and other
geopolitical factors influence them?
ANDREJ DÉMUTH – LUKÁŠ MAKKY
Reframing Beauty: Body, Environment, Art – An Introduction
6
Some phenomenologists (e.g., Heidegger, 1985, p. 242) believe that beauty
opens the possibility for us to see concealed aspects of reality – that beauty
attracts and unveils ‘knowledge’ about things that would otherwise remain
hidden from us. It is thus an initial, transitional station toward understanding
things in their unhiddenness. However, Gadamer (1960, p. 481) argues that
beauty reveals itself to us without the need for any conceptual preunderstanding. Beauty is visible, evident in itself, and immediately accessible
through contemplation. Its value does not need to be illuminated by concepts.
This allows it to simultaneously claim, in a Kantian sense, its general validity
and obligatoriness. According to these phenomenologists, beautiful things
assume they are beautiful for everyone and not just subjectively pleasing to
somebody. Beauty, therefore, only needs to be shown, and those who are not
blinded by it can (must?) perceive it. But is it truly so?
It seems that the most common way to think about beauty is through its
ostentatious presentation – encountering it significant examples. Literature,
museums, galleries, or concert halls are spaces where we often confront what
other people generally consider beautiful. These are places where beauty can
be glimpsed, sometimes in its timeless form and other times as a reflection of
the contemporary and contextual perception, but always in the most
concentrated form and in its evident presence. However, understanding beauty
extends beyond grand concert halls and exhibition spaces to encompass every
kind of aesthetic reality.
Beauty is part of our everyday life. We surround ourselves with it, seek it out,
beautify ourselves (Davies, 2020), and our dwellings (ESPES 11/2, 2022), and
choose things based on whether we like them or not. This happens in partner
selection, fashion, the media industry, architecture, utility design, and more.
Beauty has always influenced and still influences (Davies, 2020), our
preferences even where we might not expect it (Schellekens, 2008).
On the other hand, this everyday and often common beauty becomes banal or
less visible due to its obviousness. Compared to it, we seek extraordinary ‘high’
or conversely ‘deep’ beauty that shakes, touches, and moves us. It is this kind
of beauty that Scruton describes as an experience of transcendence,
the perception of the value of Being (Scruton, 2009). It is precisely this
extraordinary beauty that we seek from time to time.
Despite some theorists suggesting beauty may have somewhat disappeared
from the center of artistic production, beauty remains an important part of our
existence and may have even evolved and taken new forms. We believe – and
the following papers may illustrate this claim sufficiently – that with an
increasing saturation of other life needs, beauty is once again coming to the
forefront of our interest and desire. It is only natural that with changes in the
world, the forms of beauty we produce and long for, as well as our
understanding of ourselves and our needs, are changing. With new knowledge
and possibilities, the need for a reassessment of beauty and its meaning to us
arises.
ANDREJ DÉMUTH – LUKÁŠ MAKKY
Reframing Beauty: Body, Environment, Art – An Introduction
7
The approach to review and reframe beauty can focus on three areas: 1/ The
notion of beauty as a linguistic form (Démuth and Démuthová), 2/ Aesthetic
properties of an object or phenomena that make it beautiful (Focosi and
Corvino, Furia, Kirwan, Kišoňová, Nacif, Raccanelli), 3/ A special kind of
experience necessary to experience beauty (Furia, Kirwan, Kolditz).
In the current issue, all three areas are present. The issue begins with the
paper by James Kirwan, titled To What Does the Word ‘Beauty’ Refer?. He starts
with a short but crucial comment: we need to focus on the aesthetic properties
of objects considered beautiful and perceive them through aesthetic
experience. According to him, beauty is not something causing an aesthetic
experience. This position is important in the understanding and critical
evaluation of later papers, for example that by Brit Kolditz. In defining beauty,
Kirwan tries to base his analysis not on common features of beautiful
properties (as is customary in finding necessary and sufficient conditions) but
on different characteristics of aesthetic properties. He builds his essay on the
idea that “although an aesthetic property exists only in attribution, what
property is attributed will depend on the presence of certain objective
properties: properties that are necessary, though not sufficient, to arouse
a particular feeling about the object.” His paper is a complex contribution to
the discussed issue that disputes the need for a universal formula of beauty
and comments on the issue of beautiful objects, e.g., a human face.
Andrej Démuth and Slávka Démuthová contribute to the issue with the paper
On the Indeterminacy of the Concept of Beauty and the Reasons for its Use.
The ambiguity of the notion of beauty is the central issue of the paper,
creating a paradox in its usage. The aim of the paper is to find reasons for
using the notion despite the lack of valid and clear rules of applying the word
itself. The authors proceed from a linguistic-semantic (epistemological,
semantic, conceptual) and empirical analysis of the connotations of the
concept of beauty to uncover evolutionary, existential, and transcendental
reasons for applying the category of beauty.
A case study about one possible conception of beauty is proposed by Fillipo
Focosi and Pier Francesco Corvino in their paper Another look at Jared S.
Monroe’s Comprehensive View of Beauty. At its core, the paper is not a historical
analysis aimed at re-interpreting one text from a different point of view. Even
if it provides an overview of the 1942 paper Beauty as Harmony by Jared S.
Moore, the main reasons both authors choose this piece is
Moore’s understanding of classic theories, which he finds defective. Both
authors view Monroe’s approach as a modernization of the classic theory of
beauty and, therefore, as an actualization and reframing of the concept itself.
This reframing could be inspiring even for the present time and deserves more
attention. Focosi and Corvino understand the analysed paper as
a modernization of the formalist account of beauty, narrowing the notion to
help define the class of beautiful objects.
Another methodological yet thematic piece, the first paper in the field of
environmental aesthetics is present in the paper Beauty Between Space, Place,
ANDREJ DÉMUTH – LUKÁŠ MAKKY
Reframing Beauty: Body, Environment, Art – An Introduction
8
and Landscape: Recovering the Substantive and Normative Character of Beauty by
Paolo Furia. The central idea of the paper is “that the geographical concepts of
space and place are the locus of a possible recuperation of the relationships
between the beautiful and the good”. The interchangeable use of the notion
space and place is criticized, with a focus on the importance of beauty. Both
terms are discussed not only from an aesthetic point of view but also from the
position of spatial theory, with the aesthetic approach, through the category of
beauty, being crucial. The leitmotif of the paper, yet not the final conclusion, is
that beauty is a determinant responsible for a change of space into place.
This argument is later developed in the context of the environment.
A second, slightly unconventional contribution to environmental aesthetics
(or atmosphere discourse) is offered by Brit Kolditz with his paper Focusing on
the Loss of the Sky-Blue Environment. This paper is implicitly more
environmentally focused in the meaning of the engaging approach used, but
the category of beauty is used comprehensively, placing the beauty of the blue
sky at its center. The central issue of this paper are the changing aesthetic
properties of the blue sky, possibly escaping our perception. Kolditz wonders
why the sky is not a part of broader discussions and realizes that we are only
able to it from a distance and not directly participate in it. This may be one of
the reasons why this huge, visible part of our everyday life is not also to this
extent present in the aesthetic discourse. The main focus of the author is to
create an inspirational paper intended ‘to stimulate aesthetes and
aestheticians to have their own lived experiences and to look up to the sky’,
and at the same time, to stimulate further aesthetic thoughts.
Laura Raccanelli brings a critical-based analysis in the paper Varnishing
Facades, Erasing Memory: Reading Urban Beautification with Critical Whiteness
Studies. It is a contribution to urban aesthetics, but at the same time, it could
be classified as a contribution to postcolonial discourse. Her aim is to
demonstrate the role of visibility in the spatial organization of stigmatized
neighborhoods of cities, with an emphasis on the racist configuration of urban
space. This paper focuses on understanding how top-down beautification
operations, masking processes of racial discrimination, mitigate the symbolic
and structural violence inherent in aestheticization operations. Beauty, in her
account, is clearly understood as a canon, a social outcome or fact, that is able
in its normativity to have a negative effect, influencing the form of regulation
of life and potentially becoming a tool of discrimination because beauty is
a discursive construction. She puts urban beautification in connection with
discrimination and addresses it from the perspective of ‘neocolonialism’.
Beauty and beautification are, therefore, understood as something dangerous
when implemented without the knowledge of a special and complex context.
Reacting to Kirwan’s example of the beauty of the human face is Renáta
Kišoňová’s paper titled Beauty of Human Face in Contemporary Interdisciplinary
Discourse. The paper focuses on the analysis of facial beauty in the context of
contemporary interdisciplinary research (especially contemporary cognitive
science, neuropsychology, and evolutionary biology). It explores reasons for
preferences towards some faces, delving into the mechanism of evaluating
ANDREJ DÉMUTH – LUKÁŠ MAKKY
Reframing Beauty: Body, Environment, Art – An Introduction
9
faces and the evolutionary determination of facial beauty perception.
The author proposes three parameters for measuring facial beauty according
to Anjan Chatterjee (2015): averageness, symmetry, and sexual dimorphism,
completing them with the ‘straight profile’ aspect. This paper is mainly
a general analysis of contemporary discourse, offering valuable insight into
a complex but informative contribution.
The thematic section of this issue of ESPES concludes with a short paper,
Hiroshima’s Bag Lady: Increasing the Parameters of the Real by Luciana Nunes
Nacif. Her focus is on fashion designer Rei Kawakubo and her 1981 Paris
collection, with the intention “to question one of the axioms of Western
culture: the French monopoly of elegance…” (Vinken, 2023, p. 20) and
therefore, the monopoly of beauty in the fashion industry. Nacif identifies
three aspects of Kawakubo’s work that are crucial for the issue of beauty:
negative aesthetics, the ‘hack’ of the fashion system, and the concept of
deconstruction in fashion. This deconstruction is visible in the new search for
beauty, in the search for a ‘new’ beauty and the establishment of a novel
relationship between beauty and fashion. Despite its brevity, this contribution
clearly shows the evolving understanding of beauty based on a conceptual and
deeper understanding of phenomena.
The editorial board of ESPES and guest-editor Andrej Démuth aspired to foster
a new discourse on the concept of beauty, contemplating it in new situations
and uncovering fresh perspectives. While the endeavour may have been
ambitious, part of this initiative was to find and identify a ‘new beauty’.
The papers in this thematic issue can be divided into two categories:
a) methodological papers about beauty (Kirwan, Démuth and Démuthová,
Focosi and Corvino), b) discussions and discoveries about new areas of beauty
(Furia, Nacif, Kišoňová, Kolditz, Raccanelli). While the papers did not yield
a definitive definition of beauty for the 21st century, some similar (although
partial) conclusions emerged about the normative nature of beauty. Humans
remain central to understanding and defining the properties of beauty, with as
much diversity identified in people as in the beautiful objects of everyday life
or in art.
Ultimately, determining whether the issue fulfilled the expectations of the
editorial board of ESPES is a challenging task. The evaluation of this
theoretical contribution lies in the hands of other theoreticians and readers of
the journal. As editors, we are convinced that some degree of reframing
occurred. We hope that this issue will serve as at least another catalyst for
future discussions on the subject.
References:
Baumgarten, A. G. (1750/1961) Aesthetica. Hildesheim: Olms.
Berleant, A. (1992) The Aesthetics of Environment. Philadelphia: Temple University
Press.
Carlson, A. and Lintott, S. (2008) Nature, Aesthetics, and Environmentalism: From Beauty
to Duty. Columbia University Press.
ANDREJ DÉMUTH – LUKÁŠ MAKKY
Reframing Beauty: Body, Environment, Art – An Introduction
10
Chatterjee, A. (2015) The Aesthetic Brain: How We Evolved to Desire Beauty and Enjoy Art.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Danto, A. C. (2003) The Abuse of Beauty: Aesthetics and the Concept of Art. Chicago:
Open Court Publishing Company.
Davies, S. (2020) Adornment: What Self-Decoration Tells Us About Who We Are. London
and New York: Bloomsbury Publishing.
De Clarque, R. (2013) ‘Beauty’, in Gaut, B. and Lopes D. (eds) Routledge Companion to
Aesthetics. 3rd Edition. London and New York: Routledge.
Figal, J. (2010) Erscheinungsdinge. Ästhetik als Phänomenologie. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Gadamer, H. G. (1960) Wahrheit und Methode: Grundzüge einer philosophischen
Hermeneutik. Gesammelte Werke Bd.1: Hermeneutik I. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.
Heidegger, M. (1985) Nietzsche: Der Wille zur Macht als Kunst. GA 43, ed. Bernd
Heimbüchel. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.
Lehtinen, S., Kuisima, O. and Mäcklin, H. (2019) Paths from the Philosophy of Art to
Everyday Aesthetics. Helsinki: Finnish Society for Aesthetics.
Mandelbaum, M. (1970) ‘Family Resemblance and Generalization Concerning the Arts’,
in Weitz, M. (ed.) Problems in Aesthetics. London: Macmillan, pp. 181–198.
Menninghaus, W., Wagner, V., Kegel, V., Knoop, C. A., and Schlotz, W. (2019) ‘Beauty,
Elegance, Grace, and Sexiness Compared’, PLoS ONE, 14(6), Article e0218728. https://
doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0218728
Mothersill, M. (1984) Beauty Restored. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Nehamas, A. (2007) Only a Promise of Happiness: The Place of Beauty in a World of Art.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Parsons, G. and Carlson, A. (2008) Functional Beauty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Plato (1925) ‘Hippias Major’, in: Plato in Twelve Volumes, Vol. 9, Translated by W.R.M.
Lamb. Cambridge, (MA): Harvard University Press; London, William Heinemann Ltd.
Ramachandran, V. S. and Hirstein, W. (1999) ‘The Science of Art: A Neurological Theory
of Aesthetic Experience’, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6(6-7), pp. 15–51.
Saito, Y. (2017) Aesthetics of the Familiar: Everyday Life and World-Making. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Sartwell, C. (2004) Six Names of Beauty. New York: Routledge.
Sepänmaa, Y. (1993) Beauty of Environment: A General Model for Environmental
Aesthetics. Denton: Environmental Ethics Books.
Schellekens, E. (2008) Aesthetics and Morality. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
Scruton, R. (2009) Beauty: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shusterman, R. (1999) ‘Somaesthetics: A Disciplinary Proposal’, The Journal
of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 57(3), pp. 299–313. https://doi.org/10.2307/432196
Ricœur, P. (1974) ‘The Problem of Double Meaning as Hermeneutic Problem and as
Semantic Problem’, in Ihde, D. (ed.) Ricoeur, P.: The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays
in Hermeneutics. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, pp. 62–78.
Vinken, B. (2023) ‘The Empire Designs Back’, in Butler, R. (ed.) Rei Kawakubo: For and
Against Fashion. London: Bloomsbury Visual Arts, pp. 19–26.
Zangwill, N. (2013) ‘Beauty’, in Levinson, J. (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 325–343.
Zeki, S. (1999) Inner Vision: An Exploration of Art and the Brain. Oxford and New York:
Oxford University Press.
Andrej Démuth
Comenius University
Šafárikovo námestie 6
810 00 Bratislava 1
Slovakia
andrej.demuth@uniba.sk
ANDREJ DÉMUTH – LUKÁŠ MAKKY
Reframing Beauty: Body, Environment, Art – An Introduction
11
Lukáš Makky
University of Prešov
17. novembra 1
080 01 Prešov
Slovakia
lukas.makky@unipo.sk
DOI: 10.5281/zenodo.10473720
ANDREJ DÉMUTH – LUKÁŠ MAKKY
Reframing Beauty: Body, Environment, Art – An Introduction
12