1
Author version. Please cite final published version here:
https://muse.jhu.edu/pub/23/article/926818
The Things of Order
Affect, Material Culture, Dispositif
Donovan O. Schaefer
Introduction: Affect and Ceremony
In early 2016, a high school student in Charlottesville, Virginia, petitioned her city council
to remove a monument in a local park. The bronze equestrian, erected almost one
hundred years earlier, depicted Confederate general Robert E. Lee. The student argued
that the statue made the park forbidding and alienating to the city’s Black residents. A
year and a half later, a coalition of neo-Confederates and far-right activists—reacting to
the council’s vote to remove the statue in the wake of this petition—stormed the park and
its surrounding neighborhood, ultimately murdering a counter-protestor in the ensuing
violence. In July of 2021, after a series of legislative actions and court challenges at the city
and state levels, the council removed the statue. Two years later, the Charlottesville Lee
monument was melted down by the Swords Into Plowshares project, a Charlottesville
community organization that, as of this writing, intends to reuse the bronze for a future
monument that reflects antiracist values (Armus and Green). The location of the foundry
and the names of its proprietor and workers were kept secret for their safety. 1
Commenting on Frantz Fanon’s account of the material culture of colonialism,
Achille Mbembe describes the colony as a war zone, a contest of forces, in which “sensory
life”—the continuum of bodies, objects, and landscape—is itself a battlefield. “Colonial
domination,” he writes, “requires an enormous investment in affect and ceremony and a
significant emotional expenditure that few have analyzed until now” (Mbembe 2017, 114;
emphasis added). In the contemporary moment, monuments and memorials have
become flashpoints in the culture wars smoldering across the face of the globe. From
Johannesburg to Charlottesville to Oxford to Sydney to Kyiv, public material culture is
now the scene of a collision of competing agendas as activists seek to reshape sweeping
assemblages of power. As Mbembe predicts, this has everything to do with the ongoing
force field of conquest, colonization, and racism. Disputes about public culture become
contests about who has the capacity to project themselves as publics—and who is
sidelined, denied access, and excluded. Monuments become nodes of race and power,
affect and ceremony.
The controversies around Confederate monuments in the twenty-first century are
often framed as if statues are, in essence, three-dimensional speech. After the New Orleans
1
2
city council voted to remove statues of Lee and other Confederate figures in 2015, a group
calling themselves the Louisiana Landmarks Society sued the city on the grounds that
their First Amendment right to free speech—“which they exercise by maintaining and
preserving the historic character and nature of the city of New Orleans, including their
monuments”—was being infringed upon (Landrieu, 186). Construed as information in
metallurgical form, statues earn special protection as “free speech,” with their destruction
condemned as “censorship.” Others argue that Confederate monuments serve an
educational purpose, and that they should be left standing to preserve vital historical
knowledge about the past. As we’ll see below, even some critics of Confederate statues
take this approach, calling for “recontextualization” of offending monuments by, for
instance, placing informative signs or plaques nearby.
These analytic frames, I suggest, reflect an essentially liberal understanding of how
publics are created and maintained. For the purposes of this essay, I will define liberalism
as an approach to power in which the sovereignty of individuals is held sacrosanct,
especially as expressed through the vocabulary of “rights” held by individuals against
external entities, such as “states.” 2 The liberal paradigm also retains a secondary
conviction that power operates primarily through physical force, rather than through
fields of power. In this idiom, rational individuals encounter the public sphere as an
ongoing dialogue or debate in which ideas are presented for rational scrutiny, considered,
and then coolly accepted or refused. This framing goes hand in hand with the tendency to
construe public material objects “symbolically” and therefore shield them as, essentially,
speechlike functions. Objects are compressed to a single dimension—information—and
processed through rational reflection. The individual is fundamentally detached from the
objects around them, engaging things through an intellectual prism and translating them
into bits and bytes of data. Politics is the sum total of the contributions rational
individuals return to this conversational public sphere. And a statue is interchangeable
with a plaque, sign, posted document, flyer, or other text that happens to live on a
landscape.
But this approach is inadequate. The deadly urgency of the controversy around
Confederate monuments—both on the part of those who seek to remove them and those
who seek to maintain them—directly evidences how much more these statues are than
crystallized information. The Charlottesville student’s petition states that “many people,
including myself, feel very uncomfortable in the park and we don’t visit it,” before adding,
“there are events that I don’t attend simply because they take place in that location” (B.).
Mbembe proposes that such monuments are “sculptural extensions of a form of racial
terror” (Mbembe 2017, 128). The ferocious response to monument removal campaigns has
led to threats, intimidation, armed protest, and murder. Rather than strictly
“informative”—let alone ornamental—monuments are fully integrated with and necessary
to the projection of colonial power. The hegemony of liberal styles of thinking has left our
political vocabulary woefully unequipped for this conversation. What is needed is a
terminology that allows us to diagnose publics as formed not just by intellectual tissue
but by material objects that have their own capacities to exert force independent of the
register of information and ideas.
To redress this gap, this essay argues for a reappraisal of the work of Michel
2
3
Foucault—one of the most trenchant critics of liberal political thinking—as offering a
theory of material culture. Material culture tends not to be considered as a topic that falls
within Foucault’s purview. But although he is sometimes misrepresented as “essentially a
theorist of discourse” (Peltonen, 207), Foucault’s work actually sets the stage for a
sophisticated analysis of the nexus between bodies, power, public material culture,
discourse, and affect. This essay charts a way of attaching the expansive conversations
that have unfolded from Foucault’s work on power to the analysis of material culture,
offering support to Mbembe’s call for an attention to “affect and ceremony.”
The essay proceeds in two phases: first, it reviews Foucault’s late theory of power
and his corresponding idea of the dispositif. The dispositif is the instrumentation of
power. Not just discursive, it is a heterogeneous assemblage of bodies, discourses, and
material things—including specific objects like the scaffold and the panopticon. The
article then puts Foucault’s approach to material culture in conversation with two strands
of contemporary critical thought—New Materialism and affect theory—to show how a
fully fledged analytics of power–matter–affect might emerge. What Foucault calls the
“analytics of power” is, in fact, a way of studying affect and ceremony—the streams of
force that constitute subjectivity above, beneath, or behind language. 3 Criticisms of
colonial material culture in the work of scholars like Fanon and Mbembe dovetail with
this analytic approach.
A material Foucauldian frame, combined with an attention to affect, allows us to
diagram the limitations of a liberal framework in which the political effects of material
objects—such as monuments—are flattened to the dimension of information, speech, or
semiotic meaning. Contra the prevalent view of Foucault as exclusively preoccupied with
discourse, a reconsideration of the dispositif shows that Foucault’s analytics of power
enhances our understanding of the role of material culture in guiding political affects.
Part I: Power–Matter–Affect
Foucault’s Analytics of Power
In May 2017, four Confederate monuments were removed from the streets of New Orleans
in the dead of night and under heavy police protection. A few days later, Gary Shapiro, a
philosopher at the University of Richmond, published an op-ed arguing that monuments
honoring the Confederacy should remain standing. Shapiro’s assessment was not based
on the assertion that the statues were benign, as some defenders claim—that they were
“heritage not hate.” Shapiro’s premise was the opposite: that the statues and the
Confederacy they celebrated were unambiguously reprehensible. He expressed sympathy
for the “refreshingly clear” logic of the “iconoclasts” who wanted to level the monuments.
His argument, instead, was that “the statues are undeniable signs of [Southern] history—
of what has been done and suffered here” and that “mere erasure would be a form of
historical denial” (Shapiro).
Considering the string of Confederate statues dotting Monument Avenue in
Richmond, Virginia, Shapiro argued for a “contextualist” position. He proposed leaving
the statues in place but surrounding them with new text (and new monuments) that
would reorient the “meaning” of the original objects. “Destroying or removing the
structures,” he wrote, “eliminates opportunities for productively using our past.” He
3
4
proposed adding “plaques concerning the war itself, disputes over slavery, Richmond’s
and Virginia’s roles in the Confederacy, Reconstruction . . . , African-American
disenfranchisement, [and] the blatant racism surrounding the statues’ planning and
dedication” (Shapiro).
This contextualist position is the liberal position. It is isomorphic with the position
of the British Conservative Party in dealing with statues of enslavers and colonial despots,
which calls for a policy of “retain and explain” (Massing). Its philosophical premise, I
would suggest, is shared by partisans of the statues, who similarly frame the Confederate
monuments as an iteration of the free play of ideas. As we saw above, the Louisiana
Landmarks Society challenged the New Orleans city council’s decision to remove several
Confederate monuments in court, claiming an infringement of their First Amendment
right to free speech (Landrieu, 186). Confederate apologists have written that Confederate
monuments were fundamentally about white Southerners “making their voices
permanently heard in the immediate wake of Reconstruction” (Johnson 2009, 66).
Advocates of Confederate commemoration will even go so far as to characterize their
fight as an extension of the civil rights movement—with white Southerners now cast in
the role of victims having their rights clipped and in need of liberation (Maurantonio,
151). This paradigm aligns with the prevalent “Lost Cause” narrative deployed by partisans
of the Confederacy, which narrates the secession of the enslaver states as an extension of
the liberal demand for individual rights and limited government first advanced by the
American Revolution (Pollard, 35). Another Confederate apologist makes this link crystal
clear, stating that Confederate soldiers deserve monuments because they were “fighting
for America, Americanism, the Constitution, and the aims of the Founding Fathers: small
government, limited government, self-government, and above all, states’ rights”
(Seabrook, 29).
Regardless of the evaluation of the monuments themselves, these approaches share
a common assumption about the nature of public material culture: that it is, in essence,
information. In the case of monuments, this is information that happens to have been
rendered in three dimensions and conspicuously posed in the public sphere. But these
monuments are fundamentally forms of speech, no different from text on a billboard.
This is what I’m calling the liberal position (a usage that does not necessarily map onto
the loose sense of “liberal” and “conservative” in US popular discourse). The liberal
response to information (or misinformation) lodged in the public sphere is either to
protect it as free expression or to counter it with more and better information. The
thinking subjects that are the elemental unit of the liberal polity will sift the expanded
collection of facts available to them and choose the better argument. It is exactly this
style of thinking that Foucault seeks to overturn in his new approach to power. 4
In History of Sexuality, Vol. I, Foucault lays the groundwork for this reframing.
This requires sweeping away what he sees as a mistaken understanding of power
associated with liberal subjects, whose self-sovereignty is infringed upon by incursions
from a range of external forces—states, laws, other people. Foucault’s model of power
takes us beyond the liberal axiom that power is fundamentally about the dynamic of
thoughtful subjects affirming their sovereignty, in which resistance against external force
is always privileged. Foucault labels this the juridico-discursive template of power: power
4
5
patterned after the form of a law as declared by a sovereign (Foucault 1990, 83). This is
power as proclamation from on high: “It speaks, and that is the rule” (83). Power as law is
both a discourse and a univocal current of force laying siege to the liberal subject.
Foucault rejects this picture, proposing instead that power needs to be understood
as a multidimensional field enfolding and forming bodies into subjects from the outset.
Rather than an imposition on self-sovereign subjects from the exterior, power defines
subjectivity from the inside. Rather than just denying a preexisting free subject his due,
power is productive of the horizon of what we want—and even what we imagine as
“freedom” (94).
Not only that, the juridico-discursive model of power overstates the extent to
which power is about implementation of a legal rulebook—a contraption of linguistic
assertions. “Whether one attributes to it the form of the prince who formulates rights,” he
writes, “of the censor who enforces silence, or of the master who states the law, in any
case one schematizes power in a juridical form, and one defines its effects as obedience”
(85). For Foucault, individual action is shaped by things (discourses, groups, objects,
institutions) that make subjectivity. Relations of power, Foucault writes, “are not in
superstructural positions, with merely a role of prohibition or accompaniment; they have
a directly productive role, wherever they come into play” (94). Extreme forms of the
exercise of power—such as forceful confinement or the constant threat of deadly
violence—are, for Foucault, bad templates for a general theory of power (88). Yet it is
these narrow templates that liberals reach for in conceptualizing forces outside the
individual as essentially violent. Foucault suggests instead that we need to think of power
as productive—as eliciting responses from bodies not only by dictating but by activating,
enticing, and creating. 5 Rather than the diktat of a monarch—or even an abstract
“state”—power is everywhere, enfolding bodies and defining the parameters of how they
interact with the world.
The Dispositif: Foucault’s Theory of Material Culture
What Foucault calls the “analytics of power,” then, diagrams a massive ensemble of fields
of force that are productive of subjectivity. Foucault characterizes his oeuvre as moving
through three phases: the archaeology of knowledge, the genealogy of embodied power,
and ethical self-formation (1982, 208). In the earliest phase, Foucault was primarily
concerned with questions about the establishment of discursive regimes through the
composition of categories (“madness,” “illness,” “man”). This approach—identifying the
role of discourse in power—has been so effective that Foucault is often presented as a
thinker exclusively concerned with power in linguistic form—sometimes even as a kind of
discourse reductionist who sees language itself as the raw material of subjectivity. Matti
Peltonen calls these renderings of Foucault as “essentially a theorist of discourse” the
misbegotten “textbook image” of his thought (207). Moving on from this conception
allows us to recognize the capacity of Foucault’s thought to assess material culture and
power.
In the genealogical phase of his work, Foucault turned his attention to bodies as
sites where power converges to discipline and transform subjects (1977, 24). This included
a new fascination with material culture itself. “Space,” Foucault writes, “is fundamental in
5
6
any form of communal life; space is fundamental in any exercise of power” (1984, 252). As
Jim Gerrie proposes, Foucault ended up aligning himself with philosophers of technology
who reflect on the ways artifacts shape and influence their human creators. Not just
crystallizations of our intentions, the objects we create also form us as subjects in ways
that both extend and exceed our own ideas about them (66). Power is distributed not
only by words and ideas, but through a network of objects and practices (68).
This set of concerns led Foucault to articulate a new key term, dispositif, first used
in a 1975 interview given shortly after the publication of Discipline and Punish (Rabinow
2003, 49). Variously translated in English as “apparatus,” “deployment,” “construct,”
“alignment,” or “positivity,” John Pløger suggests the best rendering may be “assemblage”
(Peltonen, 206; Pløger, 55). This is because a dispositif, in Foucault’s own words, is “a
thoroughly heterogeneous ensemble of discourses, institutions, architectural forms,
regulatory decisions, laws, administrative measures, scientific statements, philosophical,
moral and philanthropic propositions—in short, the said as much as the unsaid.”
(Foucault 1980b, 194; emphasis added) Foucault’s dispositif concept is specifically
designed to index the heterogeneity of power—its capacity to operate through multiple
crisscrossing channels, discursive but also bodily and material.
Ronjon Paul Datta notes that dispositif becomes a central organizing term in
Foucault’s genealogical phase, just as “discursive formation” and “episteme” were in his
earlier archaeological phase (294). The new prominence of the dispositif is why objects
emerge as a more pointed—if unannounced—concern in the main texts from this period,
Discipline and Punish and History of Sexuality, Vol. I. But secondary scholarship still tends
to downplay the material dimensions of the dispositif. Gilles Deleuze’s influential
misreading of Foucault’s work is a possible source for this error. In his commentary,
Deleuze zeroes in on dispositifs as “forms of discourse” or as philosophical premises that
make links between the “visible” and the “articulable” possible (1992, 165; 1988, 38) In this
line of interpretation, no attention is paid to actual objects. Similarly, some framings of
the dispositif informed by hermeneutics flatten objects back down to a sign or “text” to be
“read in multiple ways,” on the grounds that “the social field is a field of multiple beings
or ‘readers’” (Pløger 2008, 59). Paul Rabinow’s discussion of dispositifs focuses on
“relationships” and “laws,” not on material things 6 (2003, 52).
Foucault himself is explicit that his concern in this period is the “political
technology of the body in which might be read a common history of power relations and
object relations” (1977, 24; emphasis added). Material formations, like architecture, have
always been part of fields of power, he insists, even when it takes time for the “political
literature” to catch up (1984, 239). And he stresses that the definition of a subject as made
within language is inadequate: “It is not just in the play of symbols that the subject is
constituted. It is constituted in real practices—historically analyzable practices. There is a
technology of the constitution of the self which cuts across symbolic systems while using
them” (Foucault 1984, 369). Foucault even goes so far as to announce that dispositif is a
master term that includes epistemes—which he renames “discursive apparatuses”—but
also incorporates all manner of nondiscursive elements (1980b, 197). As Peltonen points
out, a dispositif—like a penal structure—is “not just a bundle of discourses or an illusion
created by them, but something more heterogeneous and tangible” (215). The multiplicity
6
7
of power relations is also a zone of convergence between the material and the semiotic.
In the 1977 interview where Foucault provides his most expansive definition of
dispositif, the interviewers (including the Lacanian Jacques-Alain Miller) are perplexed by
Foucault’s intention to thematize what he calls the “non-discursive.” He ultimately
dismisses their concerns by announcing “my problem isn’t a linguistic one” (1980b, 197).
What many approaches to the dispositif miss is Foucault’s emerging fascination with how
subjects are made by material objects in their materiality—not in their capacity to
“symbolize.” To advance our understanding of Foucault’s relevance for contemporary
studies of material culture—profoundly promising but also tantalizingly
underdeveloped—the following sections revisit his analyses of two specific objects that
become central axes of dispositifs in Discipline and Punish: the scaffold and the prisonhouse. 7 Though Foucault himself only offers the beginnings of a programmatic study of
the nexus between materiality, affect, and power, we can see how the dispositif emerges
in these studies as a promising device for exploring these relationships.
The Scaffold as Proscenium of Terror
In the graphic opening scene of Discipline and Punish, Damiens, the failed assassin of
Louis XV, is tortured in extravagant fashion and then torn apart by horses. Foucault sees
this event as characteristic of a distinctly premodern mode of punishment: public
spectacle as an act of sovereign terror. As Foucault points out, the performance begins at
the door of a church, but most of the pain is visited on Damiens on a specially contrived
object: an elevated platform. In the subsequent chapter, “The Spectacle of the Scaffold,”
Foucault contextualizes the violent destruction of Damiens’s body against the backdrop
of the longer history of public execution in France. This tradition is best understood,
Foucault suggests, “not only as a judicial, but also as a political ritual. It belongs, even in
minor cases, to the ceremonies by which power is manifested” (1977, 47; emphasis added).
The mutilation of a body—forcing a victim to broadcast pain to a public—is part of the
reaffirmation and reiteration of the will of the sovereign. The materiality of punishment
creates the affective current that electrifies a circuit of power.
The scaffold—the physical affordance fashioned by a raised platform—is an
indispensable element of this ceremony. It operates as a stage or proscenium, a mode of
elevating and circumscribing an act of spectacular sovereign violence in order to make it a
focal point, creating the “theatre of terror” (1977, 49). This is why it’s essential that the
public attend these spectacles. “In the ceremonies of the public execution,” Foucault
writes, “the main character was the people, whose real and immediate presence was
required for the performance.” (1977, 57). Sovereign power must be displayed, and this
display is contingent on a particular configuration of the materiality of the space. This
rendered public execution “more than an act of justice; it was a manifestation of force; or
rather, it was justice as the physical, material and awesome force of the sovereign
deployed there” (1977, 50). The political efficacy of a public execution is only possible
because the scaffold has been inserted into the network, allowing the evocation of
“awesome force.” Physical elevation of the ceremony on the scaffold—above the crowd, at
the vertex of every line of sight—makes it visible to a multitude. Just as a speaker climbs a
stage, pulpit, upturned soapbox, or car roof to materially enable an address to an
7
8
assembly, the scaffold instantiates a public. The same could be said about infrastructural
features that allow mass public addresses, like the balcony attached to Mussolini’s office
over the Piazza Venezia in Rome, later emulated by Hitler on the Reich Chancellery in
Berlin.
The stagecraft of the elevated ceremony of punishment is embellished over time
through the establishment of an increasingly elaborate dispositif. The scaffold comes to
be surrounded by a “whole military machine” including “cavalry of the watch, archers,
guardsmen, soldiers” (1977, 50). This bristling display is designed not only to secure the
site but to amplify the visceral impact of the scene by exhibiting the glory and power of
the sovereign (50). Moreover, the aftermath of each execution is meticulously scripted
and choreographed to maximize dramatic impact: “Corpses [are] burnt, ashes thrown to
the winds, bodies dragged on hurdles and exhibited at the roadside” (34). The gibbet is
invented to display the body of the criminal in public for an extended period after
execution. Each improvisation increases the theatrical force of the scaffold. This is why,
Foucault observes, the first public display of the guillotine backfired: the terror of the
condemned—now obscured by the feet of the executioners on the scaffold and the
guillotine apparatus itself—prompted a demand for more visibility from the audience:
“Give us back our gallows” (58). These raw physical elements are crucial affordances for
the creation of a line of sight—an indispensable channel for the operation of the dispositif
as a public network of power.
The Panopticon as Impression Machine
In the second phase of Foucault’s history of punishment, affects and objects remain the
central focus. But modern punishment draws up a more complicated dispositif to corral
and direct these forces. The Quaker-run Walnut Street Prison in Philadelphia, for
instance, was converted into a “penitentiary” in the 1790s. Unlike a prison, which sought
only to inflict hardship, it applied techniques like solitary confinement and workshop
labor to transform inmates on the moral register (124). As Caleb Smith writes, these
practices connected to “centuries of Christian monastic practices and Romantic dreams”
designed to “carry the prisoner from the darkness of living death to the light of rebirth”
by compelling the captive to confront their moral culpability (84). In other words, the
new dispositif invoked fields of power beyond the register of the juridico-discursive—the
sword of the sovereign held up as command backed by violence. It typified power’s
capacity to make subjects by transforming their horizon of action and desire, renovating
subjectivity from the interior rather than menacing it from above.
The new mode of punishment was based on techniques for transforming subjects
developed in education, intentional communities, and martial regimentation. The
penitentiary was an apparatus for training bodies, “an imaginary equipment or techne of
normalization, that work[ed] through its spatial dispositif” (Pløger, 65). Through this
structure, a three-dimensional skein of material traces was drummed into the body,
reconfiguring its capacities. This was not a matter of manipulating “the signifying
elements of behavior or the language of the body,” Foucault writes, “but the economy, the
efficiency of movements, their internal organization.” In the end, he concludes,
“constraint bears upon the forces rather than upon the signs; the only truly important
8
9
ceremony is that of exercise” (1977, 137; emphasis added). Instead of demanding obedience
or contrition—the juridico-discursive command—disciplining the body was about
inserting it into new regimes of action, new ceremonies, new economies of force, and
thereby reconfiguring its future decisions.
Foucault calls this focus on regimentation the “micro-physics of power” (139).
Rather than power as a command or decree, this is power at the capillary level, pulsing
through environments and bodies. And the efficacy of this spatial dispositif is, like the
scaffold, a direct consequence of its concrete materiality. Disciplinary techniques
(enclosure, partition, confinement) and buildings (barracks, factories, schools, prisons) all
reiterated the elementary structural unit of monastic life: the cell, a spatial technology of
discipline that could compel rest, exclude temptation or distraction, and force selfconfrontation. Spaces were configured in such a way as to conduct bodies through
carefully designed regimens, assimilating them to systems of exercise and rewriting their
capacities (143). The microphysics of power is resolutely physical. The “ceremony of
exercise” that allows for the transformation of subjects requires an assemblage of
specialized artifacts: curtains, walls, barriers, gates, corridors.
Similarly, the disciplined body itself becomes a node for material interventions,
such as scheduled movements and regimented gestures (151). This includes a meticulous
training of the body’s relationship with particular objects. Foucault quotes at length from
an eighteenth-century manual for soldiers detailing a series of highly precise instructions
for interacting with a rifle. This involved “a breakdown of the total gesture into two
parallel series: that of the parts of the body to be used (right hand, left hand, different
fingers of the hand, knee, eye, elbow, etc.) and that of the parts of the object manipulated
(barrel, notch, hammer, screw, etc.)” and the correlation of these parts “according to a
number of simple gestures (rest, bend)” (153). This “body-object articulation” transforms
the physical capacities of the soldier (153). New object relations, drilled into the body
through training, yield a different subject—with different aptitudes, propensities, and
horizons of action.
The epitome of this dispositif of disciplinary power is Jeremy Bentham’s
panopticon. The panopticon is a radial prison design that placed a sentry tower in the
center of a chamber. Each cell in the panopticon was visible to the sentry tower, but the
sentry tower was configured in such a way that the prisoners could not see in. This led to
a permanent sense of surveillance on the part of inmates, a cultivated paranoia: “He is
seen, but he does not see; he is the object of information, never a subject in
communication” (200). As material culture scholar Ian Woodward writes, the panopticon
is “an object which is the product of historical changes in discourses about punishment,
and which—although ‘inanimate’—as a product of its design ‘acts’ to achieve political and
organisational ends” (14). The prisoner internalizes the felt sense of supervision and so
absorbs the “automatic functioning of power” 8 (201). The panopticon leaves impressions
in the prisoner’s body. These remain intact, shaping the subject’s response to new places
and situations, long after release. 9
The Eastern State Penitentiary in Philadelphia—a successor to the Walnut Street
Prison that refined the “penitentiary” model of incarceration—retains many of these
structural innovations to this day. Although not a panopticon per se, the original building
9
10
was constructed with a central guard chamber serving as an octagonal hub for eight
corridors arranged like spokes radiating outward. The cardinal point at the dead center of
the guard chamber still provides unbroken visibility into all seven original cell blocks (the
eighth spoke is an exit) at once. As the structure was augmented over time, angled
mirrors were added to allow continued direct visibility from the cardinal point. Each cell
had a single light source, a single small door, and an individual toilet, enforcing a rule of
maximum isolation. At the same time, the guards used the system of metal pipes running
through the cells to eavesdrop on prisoners. These fused regimes of sonic and visual
surveillance were only made possible through concrete material forms configured in
highly specific ways.
The panopticon as dispositif illustrates Foucault’s sense of how the power–matter
interface relies on affects. It is not designed to influence prisoners at the level of thoughts
and ideas. There’s no attention paid to persuasion. The prisoners are not given books, nor
are they subject to moralizing lectures insisting on the urgent need for reform. They’re
not even made to understand their incarceration as an awful consequence of earlier bad
actions that they would do well to avoid in the future. Instead, a distinct material
configuration enfolds them, enmeshes them, and rewires their affective circuitry. They
are dyed in the wool by the machine. The prisoner comes to feel differently, to navigate
the world using a different set of intuitive coordinates. Through a material implement,
the panopticon surgically operates on the prisoner’s affects. In being “subjected to a field
of visibility,” the inmate makes power “play spontaneously upon himself” (202), both
“spectacle” and “enclosed” forms of punishment, then, rely on objects. They are different
formations of power, but nonetheless similarly dependent on their proper assemblages of
bodies, ideas, space, and things.
When Foucault turns to the history of sexuality a few years later, he once again
thematizes architecture—of schools and hospitals, for instance—as a conduit for power
relations in excess of discourse: “one can have the impression that sex was hardly spoken
of at all in these institutions,” he writes, “but one only has to glance over the architectural
layout, the rules of discipline, and their whole internal organization: the question of sex
was a constant preoccupation” (1990, 27). By configuring the distances and proximities
between bodies, what was seen and said and by whom, the process of fashioning
sexualized subjectivities was not just discursive but structural. The work, Foucault tells
us, was done by “the builders” (28). Dispositifs reticulate words, walls, books, ideas,
objects, and architecture to project power; material configurations are indispensable tools
to rearrange the affects making subjects.
Part II: Monument Theory
From Foucault to New Materialism
Foucault’s work sets the stage for innovations in contemporary theory that advance a
nonliberal approach to the monument controversies—like affect theory and the New
Materialisms—while also providing untapped resources that can help develop those
conversations further. The remainder of this essay will build these links, reviewing
sources that have drawn on Foucault’s work to address affect (understood as subjectforming impressions) and ceremony (understood as materiality)—and their implications
10
11
for analyzing the dispositif of Confederate monuments.
New Materialist thinking emerges, in part, out of innovations in science and
technology studies. Anthropologist Bruno Latour, for instance, connects a set of
Foucauldian concerns to his studies of “laboratory life” 10 (1999, 192). Extending his
conclusions to other kinds of organizations, he argues that they do not “succeed in
constructing a social relation solidly established on discipline, on verbal coercion, on
printed notices, on warnings or the gentleness of customs” (2000, 19). Discipline requires
not just discourse, but a careful configuration of material elements. He notes that for
Foucault “discipline is impracticable without steel, without the wood of the door, without
the bolt of the locks” (19). The artifacts that comprise a dispositif each bring with them an
irreducible horizon of action that makes their collective functioning possible.
This leads to Latour’s new take on scientific knowledge-production as an effect of
an ecology of artifacts. He reframes science as the mobilization of assemblages or
networks of objects that bring undisclosed features of the world into view in novel ways.
Because the material elements of these dispositifs—microscopes, petri dishes,
centrifuges—are irreducibly necessary to the thresholds of knowledge reached, Latour
argues that we need to think of them as having a form of agency. 11 (1999, 180). This is
knowledge-production not as the operation of a detached mind staring at the world but
as a concert of human and nonhuman forces. Reflecting Foucault’s field model of power,
the liberal divide between subject and object devolves into a heterogeneous complex of
“trajectories and dispatches, paths and trails” (2000, 12).
This, in turn, becomes the template for Latour’s understanding of power,
underwriting his commitment to examining the elements of each political dispositif not
just in terms of human actors, but also material forms—“beautiful shapes, elegant
silhouettes, heroic statues” (2005, 38). Later New Materialist authors like Jane Bennett
extend this insight. Like Latour, she worries that our understanding of political action in
the Western humanist tradition lapses too quickly into a liberal binary frame of subjects
and objects (2010, x). She argues that the relegation of artifacts to the realm of the
politically inert has skewed efforts to theorize politics by rendering invisible the vast
material networks that define the openings and constraints determining human activity.
Her alternative suggestion is to consider what she calls “thing-power”—to “attend to the
it as actant” (3). Each of these actants has its own capacity to project force in the world,
making and remaking frames of power.
But what Bennett and Latour neglect is attention to how these objects become
reticulated into systems of power that are not just enacted, but felt. Affect is a key
concept for Bennett in elaborating thing-power, but she means it in an exclusively nonfelt
sense (Bennett 2010, xii). She invokes Spinoza’s use of “affect” as “that which affects
bodies,” where “body” means literally any material thing—living or not (31; see also
Deleuze 1988). There are advantages to this approach, but it overlooks the specificity of
living bodies as nodes of experience—as feeling, desiring, responding things. For Latour,
as well, his artful personification of objects is a necessary correction (2000, 19), but also
one that zeroes out the possibility of incorporating embodied emotions into networks
(Schaefer 2023). This steers us away from approaching “affect” as the horizon of
experience and feeling.
11
12
Although Foucault is wary of any vocabulary redolent of a psychic interior—
reiterating his deep-seated hostility to psychology and phenomenology (Foucault
1980a)—he nonetheless clearly indexes affect, feeling, and experience when he talks about
how material objects like scaffolds and prisons articulate bodies to formations of power.
When objects meet bodies, they produce pleasure, fear, exhilaration, paranoia, or other
changes in disposition that reconfigure the junction between bodies and power. The
scaffold is a megaphone of terror. Discipline is about changing the field of feelings around
(living) bodies and so reconfiguring their actions.
Inanimate objects may be actants, but they can’t be disciplined. The ambition of
the panopticon is not to transform the way cots, cell doors, bars, uniforms, sinks, toilets,
plates, and cups act in the world. Similarly, Confederate monuments are of high interest
to human observers, but their thing-power is null to sidewalks, streetlamps, and park
benches. Highlighting the capacity of Foucault’s thought for understanding material
culture and power means keeping the felt conjunction between a dispositif and a
breathing, pulsing body at the forefront of our analysis—reckoning with both affect and
ceremony. This means assessing “bodies” not in the abstract Spinozist sense of all physical
things but as sentient, feeling creatures. The horizon of acting, thinking, and experiencing
is a single continuum.
The Affective Dispositif
This leads us to another field of contemporary thought influenced by Foucault—affect
theory. Affect theory is a profoundly multiform field, with different strains of scholarship
pointing to different definitions of the term “affect” itself (including Bennett’s Spinozist
sense of the word, as a property of any physical thing). I have elsewhere proposed
considering these as different “dialects” and specifically argued against those dialects that
are strongly influenced by Gilles Deleuze’s emphasis on affect as “becoming.” 12 It’s beyond
the scope of this piece to relitigate these debates, but my approach here will follow a
dialect of affect theory closely associated with queer theorist Eve Sedgwick—who
explicitly aligns her work with Foucault’s approach to power while sidestepping Deleuze’s
rigid definition of affect as becoming (2003, 114).
Sedgwick, like the New Materialists, rejects the liberal binarism that sharply
separates subjects and objects. Instead, she insists on seeing objects and subjects as a fully
integrated continuum, mediated by feeling. She proposes that we “address aspects of
experience and reality that do not present themselves in propositional or even in verbal
form alongside others that do, rather than submit to the apparent common sense that
requires a strict separation between the two,” while also refusing to “subsum[e] nonverbal
aspects of reality firmly under the aegis of the linguistic” (6). In this interpretation of
affect theory, we’re made subjects not just through the sedimentation of words and
concepts but through the accretion of affects in our bodies, triggered by things in the
world (including words and concepts) that mold our habits, dispositions, and actions
(62). Sedgwick sometimes uses the term “object” in an expansive sense tinged by the
psychoanalytic context—really as any kind of attachment. 13 But in her final work, she
fleshes out an account of affects and real, touchable objects. The work of Marcel Proust,
she notes, captures this exquisitely. What she calls a “Proustian atmosphere” is an
12
13
affectively saturated space in which objects, people, and places all serve as overflowing
nodes of feeling (2011, 6).
Scholars working on affect in this dialect have directly addressed how Confederate
monuments operate as affective loci. Erika Doss argues that the production of
monuments is concentrated in bursts—periods of “mania”—such as the “statue mania” of
the early twentieth century. This was, Doss writes, “symptomatic of turn-of-thetwentieth-century anxieties about national unity, anxieties unleashed by the rapid
advance of modernism, immigration, and mass culture” (27). The production of publics
through material culture is a response to these volatile political transformations. Doss,
like Foucault, challenges the liberal position by paying attention to public memorials and
monuments not as information, but as “archives of public affect, ‘repositories of feelings
and emotions’ that are embodied in their material form and narrative content” (13). They
are not simply discursive effects. Material culture shapes the public sphere—and the
bodies within it—by conducting affects. 14
However, Doss’s approach sometimes understates the complexity of the contesting
forces that surround these objects. For instance, she writes that the spurt of statue mania
in the US from the 1870s to the 1920s was a response to the “divisiveness of the Civil War,”
creating a thirst for public sculpture that “not only embellished the postbellum public
landscape but encouraged passionate and consensual understandings of nationhood” (20;
see also Johnson 1995, 63). Although helpful in calling attention to the affective elements
of material culture, this approach understates the way public culture unfolds as an
agonism or struggle of competing priorities, particularly around race.
Confederate monuments were part of a white supremacist dispositif, a technology
by which one group asserted its dominance over another. As Vann Newkirk writes,
Confederate monuments “were built in waves that corresponded to the creation of the
‘Solid South’ and backlashes against black political power” (Newkirk 2017). Many
monument-building campaigns emerge in similar circumstances, both fractional and
agenda-driven, designed to amplify one group’s claim on the public sphere at the expense
of others. Examples used by Doss—like the monuments constructed by the Nazis in
Germany or the Baath Party in Iraq, all demolished by American military occupiers—are
efforts not just to collectively “build a nation” but to claim turf. Doss’s approach
inadvertently downplays the fractionalism of public material culture—and in particular
the weaponization of a monumental dispositif by white supremacists against Black
citizens during the post-Reconstruction, Jim Crow, and civil rights eras.
A more textured response comes from a subfield that merges affect theory and
New Materialism, what Jennifer Ladino calls “affective ecocriticism.” In her book
Memorials Matter, Ladino sets out to better understand the relationship between feeling,
subjectivity, and materiality by reflecting on the commemorative sites operated by the
U.S. National Park Service. Like Doss, she marks her goal as “to consider how the physical
environment makes people feel things, how it shapes the ‘flows’ of . . . affects at NPS sites”
(xi). While affirming, with Bennett and Latour, the actancy of nonhuman entities, she
focuses not just on the way they push other pieces of matter around, but the way they
trigger feelings in bodies—and thereby reticulate those bodies into formations of power
(16).
13
14
Crucially, Ladino is especially interested in the way monuments and memorials
produce not just a feeling, but varieties of feeling. The contents of a commemorative
park—vivid backdrop, memorial objects, text of official park publications and signage—
produce a complex agonism of affects. And these sites feel differently for different visitors
(197). Lakota Sioux visiting the disfigured Six Grandfathers mountain, also known as
Mount Rushmore, experience that space in a way that is vastly out of sync with the
feelings of settler-colonists (3). Concurring with the Charlottesville petition that was the
catalyst for the Unite the Right riots, Ladino notes that the Lee statue was experienced
very differently by Black Americans than by non-Blacks (266).
Sara Ahmed, another affect theorist who connects Foucault with
phenomenological philosophy, thinks about this in terms of the politics of orientation.
The question for her is how objects are arranged in such a way as to feel aligned or
misaligned for different bodies. The felt sense of belonging, of membership in a
community, of being welcome in a space, is constituted by the material components of
dispositifs (15). Rather than making a nation, singular, monuments broadcast different
affects for different bodies, and these shape the political contours of the publics that crop
up around them.
Confederate Monuments as Dispositif
How can this attention to power–matter–affect help us better understand the dispositif
within which Confederate monuments operate? Mbembe’s work offers an especially
elegant exploration of these concerns with respect to monuments. Fanon—Mbembe’s
touchstone for thinking about materiality—was acutely concerned with how the affective
dimensions of material culture reinforced colonial regimes. He describes the colonial
world as a “world compartmentalized, Manichaean and petrified, a world of statues: the
statue of the general who led the conquest, the statue of the engineer who built the
bridge. A world cocksure of itself, crushing with its stoniness the backbones of those
scarred by the whip” (Fanon 2004, 15). Colonial power, Fanon insists, manifests not just as
a regime of violence backed up by soldiers, police, prisons, and weapons, but a regime of
degradation that breaks the spirit of the colonized through constant frustration and
humiliation (149). Demeaning the history of the colonized and ostentatiously elevating
the colonizers is the key ingredient—hence decolonization demands transformation of
public material culture (155; see also Mbembe 2019, “Introduction”).
Mbembe develops this line of thinking, writing that “this power structure
depended on a phantasmagoric mechanism without which each repetition of the
founding colonial gesture was bound to fail” (2017, 106). Power, for Mbembe as for
Foucault, necessarily includes a material component—the inscription of the traces of
colonial domination on the space of the colony. And like Foucault, this is not just power
conveyed by force of arms: Fanon documents the material establishment of colonial
publics through “stoniness”—statues and monuments (2004, 15). Flooding a colony with
towering sculptures produces a field of power not just by transfiguring space but by
infiltrating bodies and seeping into the imagination of the colonized.
Mbembe diagnoses this as an ongoing regime of terror. A constant material
replication of the bodies of colonial overseers—in bronze, marble, or granite—is
14
15
meant to ensure that both murder and cruelty, which the dead personify, continue to haunt
the memories of the ex-colonized, to saturate their imaginary and the spaces of their
lives. . . . The statues function as rituals that conjure dead men in whose eyes Black
humanity counted for nothing, which was reason enough for their lack of scruples at spilling
Black blood over a trifle. (2017, 128)
Similarly, Mbembe notes that sacred sites from the precolonial period—such as the
tombs of dead kings—were desecrated and leveled by colonizers (2017, 126).
All of these actions, Mbembe proposes, draw on the insight that
to endure, a form of domination must not only inscribe itself on the bodies of its subjects
but also leave its imprint on the spaces that they inhabit as indelible traces on the
imaginary. . . . The potentate must inhabit its subjects in such a manner that the latter can
no longer see, hear, smell, touch, stir, speak, move, imagine, or even dream except in
reference to the master signifier that weights over them, forcing them to stutter and falter.
(127)
The panopticon watches. But the colony forces the colonized to watch. The new dispositif
occupying the sensory landscape reconfigures the play of affects that circulate in that
space. And this is part of the process of commandeering the fields of power that operate
there.
A similar line of analysis has been explored by Black American commentators since
the Civil War, who have been consistent critics of the use of material culture to glorify
white supremacists and degrade Black bodies through the cult of the Lost Cause of the
Confederacy. A Black journalist relayed the reaction of an elderly Black man watching the
Lee statue rise on Monument Avenue in 1890: “The Southern white folks is on top—the
Southern white folks is on top” (151). In “Growing up in the Shadow of the Confederacy,”
an autobiographical essay published a few months after the New Orleans removals and
ten days after the Unite the Right riot in Charlottesville, Vann Newkirk writes that public
material culture below Mason-Dixon—obelisks, statues, memorials, and flags
commemorating the Confederacy—often creates a sort of shared hallucination, in which
the hazy glory of the Old South sticks to everything. “Plantations might as well have been
wonders of the world, and old battlefields holy places,” he writes. “Part of living in the
South, just as much as eating and breathing were, was partaking in a perpetual
reenactment” (Newkirk).
Newkirk considers a statue on a victory column in his North Carolina hometown,
dedicated a century earlier, according to a plaque at its base, to the glory of ordinary
Confederate soldiers. The statue was a daily presence in his life, welded to the material
landscape, reminding him he “lived in occupied territory” (Newkirk). It was, he notes,
“built two years after the rise of the Second Ku Klux Klan and during a period of
intensifying race riots and lynchings nationwide. As Jim Crow sub-citizens, black folks
could not vote to stop the onslaught of the granite memorials, and they faced crossburnings and lynchings for daring to speak out against the projects” (Newkirk; emphasis
added). In Charlottesville, the Ku Klux Klan burned a cross on a nearby hilltop and
paraded through the streets in May 1924 in the run-up to the unveiling of the Lee
monument. 15 These monuments served as vectors of feeling, relay points in a dispositif of
power–matter–affect. They were sophisticated instruments to consolidate the joy, dignity,
and confidence of whites in their ownership of the public sphere—and implicitly or
15
16
explicitly to marginalize and demoralize Black bystanders. Just like the panopticon and
the scaffold, they performed a disciplining function, terraforming the subjectivity of
bodies moving through their atmosphere.
From this perspective, the liberal contextualist position shows serious cracks. To
“recontextualize” objects that incant their power to degrade and depress by virtue of their
grandeur, mass, height, rigidity, and thickness is to mistake material culture for
information. Newkirk writes that “for my white classmates who wore Confederate flag
shirts to class, even as they assured me that ‘I’m not racist,’ the idea that one could
celebrate the heritage without the hate held currency.” But his own conclusion is that “it
is not possible to both worship at the altar of the Confederacy and fight for the liberation
of people like me.” What Newkirk is identifying is precisely how a particular discourse—
even a set of ardently affirmed discursive commitments to, say, anti-racism—is
contradicted by the materiality of the “altar of the Confederacy.” The affective resonances
of victory columns, equestrian bronzes, vividly colorful battle flags, and Confederate
soldiers in ready position broadcast on a frequency both above and below the juridicodiscursive. An artifact of degradation can’t be so easily debated with point–counterpoint.
A material Foucauldian approach that emphasizes how material dispositifs traffic affects
is better able to map the acute political contests that converge on these artifacts.
Conclusion: Rearranging the Monumental Dispositif
Before its removal in the final weeks of the summer of 2021, the Robert E. Lee statue on
Richmond’s Monument Avenue was transformed by protestors into a very different kind
of object. Covered in paint and slogans, it became the scene of performances by Black
dancers and artists, memorials to victims of police violence, light displays projecting
antiracist writings, a community vegetable garden, and a neighborhood basketball court.
The Lee sculpture itself—too high to be accessed by climbers—sported bursts of color
from a paintball gun. The transfigured monument inverted what Eve Sedgwick might call
the “visceral, operatic power” of the equestrian bronze, repurposing it as a new kind of
affective beacon: an anti-racist dispositif to knock down white supremacy (2011, 66). In
Ahmed’s language, it changed the parameters of who felt oriented in space.
Efforts to render statues as three-dimensional “speech” sidestep the affective
power of public material culture. The liberal stance endorses the continued maintenance
of Confederate monuments on the grounds of their intrinsic value for the purposes of
education or as a kind of information that must be protected from “censorship.” In the
process, this perspective misses the capacity of material objects to conduct affects in ways
that supersede liberal framings of politics as composed by reasoned debate in a
fundamentally linguistic public sphere. But thinking outside liberalism is harder than it
seems. One challenge is the lack of vocabulary for explaining the effects of material
things—a vocabulary that can assess the rapid, rough impacts of monuments not only on
thought but on bodies, affects, and sensory life. Foucault’s dispositif makes intelligible the
shaping of fields of power by material culture. His approach washes out the binary
frameworks that have structured so much thinking on power—not just the binary of the
sovereign liberal subject set against external forces, but the binary of discourse and
matter. Even speech is not just speech. It, too, has material-affective form. What Donna
16
17
Haraway called the “material-semiotic node”—an analytic lens that locates information
and objects on a single interactive plane—can be productively reframed as the material–
affective–semiotic node (200). This is the theater of the dispositif.
Foucault’s call is for a 360-degree picture of power–matter–affect operating
through multiple channels and across multiple layers. The aesthetic response to the
statues, the cognitive response, the affective response, and the political response converge
in a single field of fluid interactions. To flatten statues to the semiotic register is to
misunderstand what they do, how they fix dispositifs, how they lure bodies into
assemblages of power by evoking—compelling—affects. Statues are more than signs.
Their effectiveness includes their symbolic dimension but is not reducible to it. As the
protesters in Richmond well understood, the operatic power of the Lee statue on its sixtyfoot-high plinth would not be nullified by a plaque. The Swords Into Plowshares project
in Charlottesville, with its mission of melting down the Lee statue and recasting it as a
new piece of public art, shares the same insight. These interventions aim to transmute
these objects, to redirect and rechannel their power, building new dispositifs out of new
material forms.
Donovan O. Schaefer is associate professor in the Department of Religious Studies
at the University of Pennsylvania. His most recent book is Wild Experiment: Feeling
Science and Secularism after Darwin (Duke University Press, 2022). His current research
project examines affect and race in public material culture, especially Confederate
commemoration.
Acknowledgments
This essay began in the 2018–2019 Wolf Humanities Center Forum on “Stuff” at the
University of Pennsylvania. I’m grateful to all the participants of that seminar for
providing invaluable suggestions when I presented a very early version of this essay there,
especially Sarah Wasserman, Julie Nelson Davis, and Karen Redrobe. Sarah Weicksel’s
excellent response to the paper was especially generative. I’m also grateful for
conversations at the 2022 “Learning with Charlottesville” Summer Institute (hosted by the
Religion, Race, and Democracy Lab at the University of Virginia) and at the University of
North Carolina Religion and Theory Reading Group, where I had the pleasure of
discussing the article with a brilliant group of critics and interpreters. Finally, I’d like to
extend thanks to the editors and two anonymous reviewers at Cultural Critique, whose
thoughtful comments have markedly improved the piece.
Works Cited
Ahmed, Sara. 2006. Queer Phenomenology: Orientations, Objects, Others. Durham: Duke
University Press.
Armus, Teo, and Hadley Green. 2023. “Charlottesville’s Lee Statue Meets Its End, in a
2,250-Degree Furnace.” Washington Post, October 26.
https://www.washingtonpost.com/dc-md-va/interactive/2023/civil-warmonument-melting-robert-e-lee-confederate/
B., Z. “Change the Name of Lee Park and Remove the Statue.” change.org petition.
Accessed February 18, 2024. https://www.change.org/p/charlottesville-citycouncil-change-the-name-of-lee-park-and-remove-the-statue-in-charlottesville-va.
Bell, Duncan. 2014. “What Is Liberalism?” Political Theory 42, no. 6:682–715.
17
18
Bennett, Jane. 2010. Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things. Durham: Duke
University Press.
Bennett, Tony. 1988. “The Exhibitionary Complex.” new formations 4:73–102.
City of Charlottesville. 2016. “Blue Ribbon Commission on Race, Memorials, and Public
Spaces.” Report to City Council. http://blairhawkins.net/RH/2016BRCReport.pdf.
Datta, Ronjon Paul. 2008. “Politics and Existence: Totems, Dispositifs, and Some Striking
Parallels between Durkheim and Foucault.” Journal of Classical Sociology 8, no.
2:283–305.
Spinoza, Benedict, 1996. Ethics. Trans. Edwin Curley. New York: Penguin.
Dean, Mitchell, and Daniel Zamora. 2021. The Last Man Takes LSD: Foucault and the End
of Revolution. London: Verso.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1988. Foucault. Translated by Seán Hand. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
———. 1992. “What Is a Dispositif?” In Michel Foucault: Philosopher, 159–68.
Translated by Timothy J. Armstrong. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Doss, Erika. 2010. Memorial Mania: Public Feeling in America. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Eldeib, Duaa. 2016. “Stateville’s Controversial ‘Roundhouse’ Prison Area Shuttered.”
Chicago Tribune, December 1.
https://www.chicagotribune.com/news/local/breaking/ct-stateville-roundhouseclosed-met-20161201-story.html.
Fanon, Frantz. 1986. Black Skin, White Masks. Translated by Charles Lam Markmann.
London: Pluto Press.
———. 2004. The Wretched of the Earth. Translated by Richard Philcox. New York: Grove
Press.
Foucault, Michel. 1961. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of
Reason. New York: Viking.
———. 1973. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New York:
Vintage.
———. 1977. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Translated by Alan Sheridan.
New York: Vintage.
———. 1980a. “Theatrum Philosophicum.” In Language, Counter-Memory, Practice:
Selected Essays and Interviews, edited by Daniel F. Bouchard, 165–96. Ithaca:
Cornell University Press.
———. 1980b. Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–1977.
Edited by Colin Gordon. Translated by Colin Gordon, Leo Marshall, John Mepham,
and Kate Soper. New York: Pantheon.
———. 1982. “The Subject and Power.” In Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and
Hermeneutics, edited by Hubert L. Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow, 208–26. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
———. 1984. The Foucault Reader. Edited by Paul Rabinow. New York: Pantheon.
———. 1990. The History of Sexuality: Volume One. Translated by Robert Hurley. New
York: Vintage.
———. 2002. Archaeology of Knowledge. Translated by A. M. Sheridan Smith. London:
18
19
Routledge.
———. 2003. The Birth of the Clinic: An Archaeology of Medical Perception. Translated by
A. M. Sheridan Smith. New York: Routledge.
———. 2012. “The Mesh of Power.” Viewpoint Magazine, September 12.
https://www.viewpointmag.com/2012/09/12/the-mesh-of-power/
———. 2021. Confessions of the Flesh: The History of Sexuality, Vol. 4. Edited by Frédéric
Grod. Translated by Robert Hurley. New York: Pantheon.
Gerrie, J. 2003. “Was Foucault a Philosopher of Technology?” Techné 7, no. 2:66–73.
Haraway, Donna. 1991. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women. New York: Routledge.
Johnson, Kristina Dunn. 2009. No Holier Spot of Ground: Confederate Monuments and
Cemeteries of South Carolina. Charleston, S.C.: The History Press.
Johnson, N. 1995. “Cast in Stone: Monuments, Geography, and Nationalism.” Environment
and Planning D: Society and Space 13:51–65.
Ladino, Jennifer K. 2019. Memorials Matter: Emotion, Environment, and Public Memory at
American Historical Sites. Reno: University of Nevada Press, 2019.
Landrieu, Mitch. 2018. In the Shadow of Statues: A White Southerner Confronts History.
New York: Viking.
Latour, Bruno. 1999. Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press.
———. 2000. “The Berlin Key or How to Do Words with Things.” In Matter, Materiality,
and Modern Culture, edited by P.M. Graves-Brown, 10–21. London: Routledge.
———. 2005. “From Realpolitik to Dingpolitik or How to Make Things Public.” In Making
Things Public: Atmospheres of Democracy, edited by Bruno Latour and Peter
Weibel, 14–43. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Massing, Katharina. 2021. “The UK’s Plan to ‘Retain and Explain’ Problem Monuments Is a
Backwards Step.” The Conversation, March 19.
https://theconversation.com/statues-the-uks-plan-to-retain-and-explain-problemmonuments-is-a-backwards-step-156430
Maurantonio, Nicole. 2019. Confederate Exceptionalism: Civil War Myth and Memory in
the Twenty-First Century. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.
Mbembe, Achille. 2017. Critique of Black Reason. Translated by Laurent Dubois. Durham:
Duke University Press.
———. 2019. Necropolitics. Translated by Steven Corcoran. Durham: Duke University
Press.
Newkirk, Vann R., II. 2017. “Growing up in the Shadow of the Confederacy.” The Atlantic,
August 22. https://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2017/08/growing-up-inthe-shadow-of-the-confederacy/537501/.
Peltonen, M. 2004. “From Discourse to Dispositif: Michel Foucault’s Two Histories.”
Historical Reflections 30, no. 2:205–219.
Pløger, John. 2008. “Foucault’s Dispositif and the City.” Planning Theory 7, no. 1:51–70.
Pollard, Edward A. 1890. The Lost Cause: A New Southern History of the War of the
Confederates. New and Enlarged Edition. New York: E. B. Treat.
Rabinow, Paul. 1995. French Modern: Norms and Forms of the Social Environment.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
19
20
———. 2003. Anthropos Today: Reflections on Modern Equipment. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Savage, Kirk. 1997. Standing Soldiers, Kneeling Slaves: Race, War, and Monument in
Nineteenth-Century America. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Schaefer, Donovan O. 2019. The Evolution of Affect Theory: The Humanities, the Sciences,
and the Study of Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 2022a. “Rationalist Nostalgia: A Critical Response to Ruth Leys’ The Ascent of
Affect.” Capacious 2, no. 4:115–135.
———. 2022b. Wild Experiment: Feeling Science and Secularism after Darwin. Durham:
Duke University Press.
———. 2023. “Feeling Material Culture: Affect, Power, Sensation.” Material Religion 19,
no. 1:82–84.
Seabrook, Lochlainn. 2018. Confederate Monuments: Why Every American Should Honor
Confederate Soldiers and Their Memorials. Nashville, TN: Sea Raven Press.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. 2003. Touching Feeling: Affect, Pedagogy, Performativity.
Durham: Duke University Press.
———. 2011. The Weather in Proust. Edited by Jonathan Goldberg. Durham: Duke
University Press.
Shapiro, Gary. 2017. “The Meaning of Our Confederate ‘Monuments.’” New York Times,
May 15. https://www.nytimes.com/2017/05/15/opinion/the-meaning-of-ourconfederate-monuments.html.
Smith, Caleb. 2009. The Prison and the American Imagination. New Haven: Yale
University Press.
Vargas, Therese. 2023. “Lee’s Statue Is Gone. What It Unleashed Remains.” Washington
Post, October 28. https://www.washingtonpost.com/dc-md-va/2023/10/28/leestatue-threats-remain-charlottesville/.
Woodward, Ian. 2007. Understanding Material Culture. London: SAGE.
Notes
1 News of the meltdown triggered a wave of threats directed at the Swords Into Plowshares leadership. (Vargas
2023) Although many Confederate monuments in urban centers have been removed, monuments in rural areas,
especially in the Deep South, remain standing. Meanwhile, advocacy groups like Monuments Across Dixie are
actively campaigning to raise new Confederate statues and flags, often on privately owned land but in view of
the public.
2 Duncan Bell has convincingly argued that “liberalism,” as an analytic and philosophical category, has been
applied in different ways to different groupings of ideas over the course of its history, and that in its
contemporary usage it is more often advanced as a term of abuse than a precise intellectual taxon. I use
“liberalism” here to delimit a narrow set of philosophical parameters, which neglects by design the massive
overdetermination of the word in contemporary usage.
3 As I have noted elsewhere, Foucault’s early interest in power–knowledge (1977, 27) was later expanded in History
of Sexuality, Vol. I to include attention to “power–knowledge–pleasure” (1990, 11) or what I suggest we can
20
21
productively rename “power–knowledge–affect” (2022b, 58).
4 There is a salient counterargument to this characterization of Foucault as antiliberal, in that Foucault, while
pushing back on certain elements of classical liberal philosophy, is also invested in a project of liberation—
sometimes phrased in individualistic terms. In “What Is Enlightenment?” for instance, he invokes a “new
impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undefined work of freedom.” (Foucault 1984, 46) This has led to
criticism of Foucault as a thinker sympathetic to certain aspects of “neoliberalism.” Mitchell Dean and Daniel
Zamora note that Foucault’s fascination with neoliberalism descends from his observation that the neoliberal
homo oeconomicus is not a subject defined by innate qualities (a “criminal,” for instance) but an economic
maximizer who makes decisions based on advantage in any given moment. (Dean and Zamora, 160) This
interest in individual choice (as an aggressive antidote to essentialism) seems to align Foucault with other
aspects of “liberalism” broadly conceived, including, as Dean and Zamora note, “opposition to any organized
socialist or social democratic project” (235; and see n.2 above). I would respond to this in two ways. First,
Foucault is not an immaculately consistent thinker. “Do not ask who I am and do not ask me to remain the
same,” he growls in Archaeology of Knowledge, before adding: “leave it to our bureaucrats and our police to see
that our papers are in order’” (2002, 19). The question is how different elements of his thought can be elevated,
elaborated, and applied to different problems. Equally important, however, is to note that Foucault is himself
working out the paradoxes of his own thought. As Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick observes, Foucault’s History of
Sexuality, Vol. I, for instance, is ultimately a book “divided against itself in what it wanted from its broad,
almost infinitely ramified and subtle critique of the repressive hypothesis” (2003, 10) affirming the importance
of a multilateral model of power in Parts I through IV but retrenching in a basically top-down picture of power
as state-driven “biopolitics” in Part V. Reading Foucault as antiliberal is, I would argue, ultimately a more
productive interpretation of the broader currents of his thought, but there are undoubtedly strands of his oeuvre
that could be drawn in the opposite direction.
5 Foucault repeatedly emphasized, in his late writings, that he worried about the tendency to interpret power as
strictly top-down that had been superimposed on his early work (1999, 162; Foucault 1984, 245).
6 But see also Rabinow 1995, which thematizes the relationship between power and urban planning.
7 An inventory of other objects that prefigure the analysis of dispositifs in Foucault’s work would include the ships
carrying the mad in Madness and Civilization (1961); the painting “Las Meninas” in The Order of Things
(1973); the “silent world of the entrails” in Birth of the Clinic (2003, xi); public baths as “cathedrals of
pleasure” in “Space, Knowledge, and Power” (1984); the hypomnemata notebooks in the final “On the
Genealogy of Ethics” interview (1984); classroom desks arranged in rows in “The Mesh of Power” (2012); and
the reflection on Clement’s “regimen”—“the manner of drinking . . . luxury in furnishings . . . talk about
perfumes and crowns, then shoes . . . then diamonds”—in the opening chapter of Confessions of the Flesh.
(2021, 9).
8 This is not the same as the “exhibitionary complex” proposed by Tony Bennett, in which the display of objects
makes bodies into reflective, self-governing subjects (76). That framing presupposes that the cardinal thing we
do when we look at objects is “think” about them. It is exactly this intellectualized model of subjects, I suggest,
21
22
that Foucault’s dispositif concept steers us away from.
9 In 2016, the final prisoners were transferred from one of the only panopticon units in the United States, Stateville
Correctional Center’s “roundhouse,” originally constructed in 1922. According to prison reform advocate
Jennifer Vollen-Katz, the design of the prison wing led to an open echo chamber in which every sound
reverberated through the room, creating a “sensory nightmare” (Eldeib). The failure of the panopticon model,
then, lay in its inability to manage the sonic relay system created by open plan incarceration. The lack of
partitions, doors, and corridors converted the room into a torture chamber.
10 See Woodward, 13.
11 To differentiate these networked material agents from autonomous agents in the classical sense, Latour renames
them actants. This reconstitution of the locus of agency in actancy fragments Enlightenment models of the self
as a sovereign agent, so it would be misleading to stress a binary frame of agents/actants, though that’s
sometimes how Latour seems to talk about it.
12 Schaefer 2019; Schaefer 2022a.
13 This is the sense deployed by Melanie Klein, for instance.
14 So, too, does language, by conducting affects, leave its own warping effect on the public sphere. This is just as
invisible to the liberal perspective as the shaping force of material culture.
15 City of Charlottesville, “Blue Ribbon Commission on Race, Memorials, and Public Spaces, Report to City
Council (December 19, 2016),” 121, http://blairhawkins.net/RH/2016BRCReport.pdf
22