European Journal of Analytic Philosophy
EuJAP | Vol. 19 | No. 1 | 2023
https://doi.org/10.31820/ejap.19.1.7
Is ConsCIousness Gendered?*1
sophie-Grace Chappell1
1
The Open University, UK
Discussion - Received: 24/11/2022 Accepted: 12/12/2022
AbstrAct
We can ask whether there anything it is distinctively like to be
female or male (a question about sex). And we can ask whether
there anything it is distinctively like to be feminine or masculine (a
question about gender). I think the answer to both these questions
is “Obviously yes”. Why yes? And why obviously? Consciousness
is gendered, and obviously gendered, because the political realities
of what it is like to be masculine, and what it is like to be feminine,
are distinctively different. Moreover, consciousness is sexed too, and
obviously sexed, because the physical realities of what it is like to be
male, and what it is like to be female, are distinctively different. And
that is why the answer to our two questions is not just “Yes”, but
“Obviously yes”.
Keywords: consciousness; gender; sex; body; transgender.
* This paper is an extended version of an article (Chappell 2022) originally published by AiA in
January 2022. Thanks for comments to Imogen Chappell and James Holden.
© 2023 Sophie-Grace Chappell
Correspondence: sophie-grace.chappell@open.ac.uk
(SI8)
euJAP | Vol. 19 | no. 1 | 2023
special issue Women in Philosophy:
Past, Present and Future 7
“What is it like,” a man might ask, “to be a woman?”
“Well, what is it like,” a woman might retort, “to be a man?”
What-is-it-like questions are always intriguing. And, some might add
(perhaps the two in this dialogue), impossible to answer. For if a woman
could say what it is like to be a man (or vice versa), that would have to
mean that she could occupy his very viewpoint on the world. It would
mean that his consciousness, his subjective viewpoint, could turn into her
consciousness.
But how could that happen? My “subjective viewpoint” is not a literal
viewpoint, like the summit of Arthur’s Seat, that I can occupy, or vacate to
let you see the view from there. Nor is consciousness like a virtual-reality
headset that anyone can wear. I can’t just hand over to you the eye-goggles
and the ear-phones of my experience, so that you can experience as directly
as I do what it is like to be me.
But even if my consciousness was like a virtual-reality headset that you
could just put on, what would you get by wearing it? You wouldn’t get my
experience. You’d get your experience of my experience. But when you
asked “what it was like to be me”, that evidently wasn’t what you were
after.
“Come to our musée folklorique at Artisanal-en-Provence!” say the tourist
brochures, “Come and have an authentic experience of life as a French
peasant!” “Hmm”, says the philosopher (in her exasperating way).
Whatever else a tourist may find to delight her in Artisanal-en-Provence,
it seems a good bet that it won’t be that. If things go well for her there,
she will end up thinking “Wow, so this is what it is like to be an authentic
French peasant”. But by definition, this is a thought that would never even
occur to an authentic French peasant. At least, not to an authentic authentic
French peasant.
Despite this line of objection, we should keep hold of an important truth
that philosophy has often obscured. This is that at least sometimes others’
consciousnesses, their mental lives, are known to us just by looking and
seeing. Since at least Descartes’s time, most philosophers have taken for
2
sophie-Grace Chappell: Is consciousness gendered?
granted “the privacy of the mental”. But sometimes mental states are as
public as anything else. When you hit your thumb with the hammer I see,
directly, that you are in pain. When the cabinet minister staggers out of
Downing Street I see, directly, that he is blind drunk. When the school
bully humiliates the shy pupil in front of the whole class, her anguished
embarrassment is not private, as most of her previous mental states were.
Being shy, she is a specialist in hiding. But that is precisely her torment
as she faces the bully’s jeers: this mental state of hers is public, directly
visible to everyone.
Connectedly, there is such a thing as vicarious proprioception. As I
watch the climber reach for the crucial elusive hold, my finger-muscles
clench. When the pianist reaches the last few excruciatingly difficult bars
of Chopin’s Nocturne 9.2, I hold my breath in anticipation. When I see a
toddler’s parent step on a lego-brick lurking in a patterned carpet, I feel his
pain—quite close to literally. In these and many other cases, the mental
isn’t private at all; not at least if “private” means “unobservable”. Despite
Descartes, when we ask what-is-it-like questions, our questions needn’t
always be unanswerable; or even hard to answer.
One classic modern source for what-it-is-like questions is Thomas Nagel’s
famous journal article “What is it like to be a bat?” (Nagel 1974). Nagel
thinks that it is obviously true that there is something it is like to be a bat;
there are facts about what it is like to be a bat; bats have consciousness, just
as we do. But bats and humans have very different kinds of consciousness.
So, for example, echolocation plays for bats roughly the function that sight
plays for human beings. But even though they are functionally analogous,
it seems obvious that there must be differences between the subjective
experiences of seeing and echolocating. Or again (I would add; this isn’t
in Nagel), bats have a natural urge to take wing and fly through the night
sky, scanning it for moths and midges to gobble up as they go. Humans
have no such urge; or at least, none of the humans I’ve met have. (Perhaps
humans who do feel that urge don’t live long enough to be easy to meet.)
Conversely bats, as far as I know, display no natural urge to create works
of art, or to fight wars.
These truths about perception (and, as I add, desire) make it a fact that bat
consciousness is very different from human consciousness, just as it is a
3
euJAP | Vol. 19 | no. 1 | 2023
special issue Women in Philosophy:
Past, Present and Future 7
fact that bat bodies are very different from human bodies. How do the facts
about consciousness relate to the facts about bodies? Nagel thinks that this
is rather a deep philosophical mystery: a mystery that we might also call
“the mind-body problem”. On the one hand, we can’t easily explain how
if at all the two kinds of fact are connected. On the other hand, neither can
we just deny the existence of either kind of fact. The mind-body problem
leaves us scratching our heads. Perhaps it even should leave us that way.
Alongside “What is it like to be a bat?”, we might equally ask the two
questions I began with: “What is it like to be a man?” and “What is it like
to be a woman?” Is there anything that it is distinctively like to be a man
or a woman, as there is something that it is distinctively like to be a bat,
or a human (or a dog, or a llama, etc.)? At the level of our consciousness,
is there “a man’s world” and “a woman’s world”? Are there two separate
realms of consciousness here, each with its own particular flavour?
Sex is distinct from gender; I’ll say how in a moment. So this question also
can be divided in two. We can ask whether there anything it is distinctively
like to be female or male (a question about sex). And we can ask whether
there anything it is distinctively like to be feminine or masculine (a
question about gender).
I think the answer to both these questions is “Obviously yes”. Why yes?
And why obviously?
There is something it is distinctively like to be male or female, because
a crucial—and overwhelmingly obvious—aspect of what it is like to be
human is bodiliness. (On this aspect of what it is like to be human, see
my Epiphanies, 4.4-4.5 (Chappell 2022); on what it is like to be human
in general, see the whole of Chapter 4.) Our consciousness of our own
bodies is fundamental to nearly all the rest of our consciousness. (There are
“out of body experiences”, apparently; but they are exceptional.) The form
of our bodies, and our awareness of our bodies from “inside them”, is an
essential condition of the form of our phenomenology: what it is like to be
human is, in key part, what it is like to have a human body. (Notice how
this point can help us with Nagel’s initial question “What it is like to be a
bat?”, and also with Nagel’s further question how facts about bodies relate
to facts about consciousness. Notice too how it can’t help us with those
two questions.)
4
sophie-Grace Chappell: Is consciousness gendered?
But male and female bodies differ, and in distinctive ways. As male and
female they are typically differently shaped, e.g. in genitalia, in having or
lacking breasts, in distribution of body-fat and body-hair, in size, and in
musculature. They are subject to different sensibilities: females feel the
cold more, males are less good at coping with sleep-deprivation. They
are affected by different hormonal secretions, and on different timescales,
and these different hormones have different effects on their moods and
their inclinations. Very crudely, females (or most of them within a certain
age-range) experience the menstrual cycle, while males (same caveat)
experience (…) testosterone. Male and female bodies even smell different
(I gather this is related to the hormonal differences).
In the case of the sex distinction, male/female, what matters is the
physical; in the case of the gender distinction, masculine/feminine, what
matters is the political. Male and female consciousnesses differ because
male and female bodies differ; masculine and feminine consciousnesses
differ because male and female political roles have differed. So there is
something it is distinctively like to be masculine or feminine, because
a crucial—and overwhelmingly obvious—aspect of what it is like to be
human is political life.
I mean this in a broad sense of “political”. Wherever there are humans,
there are power-relations. One foundation of these power-relations is the
management of expectation. The task of predicting the behaviour of other
humans (whether groups or individuals) is intractably huge. We reduce this
task to manageable proportions via conventions and taboos, expectations
and reliances, contracts and understandings, traditions and rules. From
these, over time, grows ideology.
Central to many of these conventions, etc., is the profiling of other humans.
One obvious way to profile them is by their biological sex (actual or
perceived). From this, over time, grows the ideology of gender: we build
up a story about what kind of social and communal role follows from
membership of either biological sex. Our concepts of “masculine” and
“feminine” are, precisely, stories of this kind. That such stories can and
do encode not only power-relations but also oppression, and that this has
been their function throughout history, is obvious from the beginning of
our culture.
5
euJAP | Vol. 19 | no. 1 | 2023
special issue Women in Philosophy:
Past, Present and Future 7
“But hang on”, some people might object at this point, “consciousness is
just subjective awareness of the world! What does politics have to do with
whether consciousness is gendered?” This objection attributes a false—and
ideologically-driven—unworldly purity to consciousness. The philosophy
of mind is not, pace so many of its contemporary exponents, an ethically
neutral or ideologically innocent study. The philosophy of mind is a part
of “human science”; politics has everything to do with it. When Karl Marx
popularised the phrase “class consciousness” (ger. Klassenbewusstsein),
his use of “consciousness” was not a mere homophony. We humans are
both physical and political beings: our political condition shapes our
awareness of the world as surely as our physical condition.
I remember visiting Bulgaria in the Soviet era, and being forcibly struck by
the difference in people’s body-language from how people held themselves
in England:2 the bowed shoulders, the refusal to meet each other’s eyes, the
way even a walk across a railway-station concourse was a kind of furtive
sidle, the constant sideways and backwards vigilance for the police—
whose body-language was completely different from everyone else’s: it
was the strutting, shameless, crotch-first body-language of the cock of the
walk, the school bully again. It sounds clichéd to say that when you live
under a tyranny you are constantly watching your back; but it is the literal
truth. The reality of ubiquitous surveillance charges your whole experience
with a sense of vulnerability, exposure, nakedness. During my short time
passing through communist Sofia, I not only noticed how everyone else
was, literally, watching their backs; I found myself doing it too.
2
Cf. George Orwell on anarchist Barcelona in 1936, in Homage to Catalonia, Ch. 1 (Orwell 1938):
“When one came straight from England the aspect of Barcelona was something startling and
overwhelming. It was the first time that I had ever been in a town where the working class was in the
saddle. Practically every building of any size had been seized by the workers and was draped with
red flags or with the red and black flag of the Anarchists (…). Every shop and café had an inscription
saying that it had been collectivised; even the bootblacks had been collectivised and their boxes painted
red and black. Waiters and shop-walkers looked you in the face and treated you as an equal. Servile and
even ceremonial forms of speech had temporarily disappeared. Nobody said ‘Señor’ or ‘Don’ or even
‘Usted’; everyone called everyone else ‘Comrade’ and ‘Thou’, and said ‘Salud!’ instead of ‘Buenos
días’. Tipping was forbidden by law since the time of Primo de Rivera; almost my first experience
was receiving a lecture from a hotel manager for trying to tip a lift-boy. There were no private motorcars, they had all been commandeered, and all the trams and taxis and much of the other transport
were painted red and black. The revolutionary posters were everywhere, flaming from the walls in
clean reds and blues that made the few remaining advertisements look like daubs of mud. Down the
Ramblas, the wide central artery of the town where crowds of people streamed constantly to and fro,
the loudspeakers were bellowing revolutionary songs all day and far into the night (…).”
6
sophie-Grace Chappell: Is consciousness gendered?
Consciousness is not a mere bloodless abstraction: it is, among other
things, politically charged. Nor is oppression a mere abstraction: for the
oppressed, it shapes every aspect of how they see their environment, the
obstacles and the affordances, the threats and the opportunities, in their
way. To transpose a remark of Wittgenstein’s (Tractatus 6.43), the world of
the oppressed person is a different world from the world of the free person.
All of this applies as much to oppression via the category of gender as it
does to class oppression. Consider Homer, Iliad 1.431-450 (my translation):
Odysseus came to Chryse with his sacrifice.
Once they were in the deep harbour, then his sailors
took down the sail and stowed it within the black ship (…)
then disembarked and walked ashore through the surf,
bringing the oxen to be offered to Apollo;
and out of the ship there also stepped Chryseis.
Led to the altar by Odysseus of the wiles,
back in her father’s hands, she heard him speak:
“Agamemnon lord of men has sent me, Chryses,
to give you back your child, and to sacrifice
a hundred oxen to appease Apollo,
to stop the wide-wept woes he’s brought the Greeks.”
He spoke and gave her up, and Chryses had back
his daughter, his delight. Swift then for sacrifice
they placed the beasts about the firm-built altar,
with pure hands took the sacred barley up.
And Chryses raised his arms in prayer for them (…).
Chryseis was captured in war by the Greek field-marshal Agamemnon, and
became his slave-girl. Her father, the priest Chryses, begged Agamemnon
to return her to him. Agamemnon rudely dismissed Chryses’ request; the
god Apollo disapproved and sent a plague on the Greek army. So now, to
appease Apollo and end the plague, Agamemnon sends Odysseus as his
envoy to return Chryseis to her father.
The transaction that is going on in the present translation is essentially one
between the war-lords Agamemnon and Achilles, neither of whom is even
present. The transaction is about Chryseis, but she herself is just a piece
7
euJAP | Vol. 19 | no. 1 | 2023
special issue Women in Philosophy:
Past, Present and Future 7
of property; she has no more standing to speak in this transaction than do
the oxen that are brought along with her. (We can do the ideology of the
“human”/ “animal” distinction another time.) In Homer’s text, she does
not even have her own name, any more than do the cattle that she travels
with: “Chryseis” is a patronymic not a proper name, meaning no more
than “daughter of Chryses” (which in turn apparently just means “man of
Chryse (the place)”). It takes a scholiast on Homer (a scholar annotating
the margins of the manuscript) to tell us that she even had a name of her
own, a name that wasn’t just a derivative of her father’s name, and that her
own name was Astynome.3
Before the events described in the quotation, Chryseis (/Astynome) has
watched one man, Agamemnon, kill her family and neighbours, burn her
city down, rape, enslave, and imprison herself. Now she watches another
man, Odysseus, hand her back to a third man, her own father. And through
all of this she herself never says a word. She does indeed keep what Pat
Barker, in the title of a wonderful recent novel about just these Homeric
transactions, calls The Silence Of The Girls.
This is a world where, on the basis of the masculine/feminine gender
distinction, half the human species is treated as subservient to the other
half. It is a world where the reality of women as human people, and as
conscious experiencers, is close to completely erased. It is a world of war
and violence; a world of religiously-sanctioned pillage and rape, and the
fetishisation of possession and status. It is a world (as Simone Weil so
well sees in her famous essay “The Iliad as poem of force”) that is built
upon the possibilities for violence that are present in the human body.
And I agree with Weil, against Nietzsche, that this vision of the world as
a terrible place of violence and oppression, a place where force turns its
victim into a thing, is a vision which is to be wept over not (as Nietzsche
thought) celebrated.
[U]ne telle accumulation de violences serait froide sans un
accent d’ inguérissable amertume qui se fait continuellement
sentir, bien qu’ indiqué souvent par un seul mot, souvent
3
Latinised as Cressida, Chryseis’ name was transferred to a quite different character in the Middle
Ages: Shakespeare’s Cressida is drawn, via Chaucer and Boccaccio, from Benoît de Sainte-Maure’s
twelfth-century Roman de Troie, and has little or nothing to do with Homer’s Chryseis.
8
sophie-Grace Chappell: Is consciousness gendered?
même par une coupe de vers, par un rejet. C’ est par là que l’
Iliade est une chose unique, par cette amertume qui procède
de la tendresse, et qui s’ étend sur tous les humains, égale
comme la clarté du soleil.
The Iliad’s world is the world of the patriarchy. (Or a world of the
patriarchy, one version of that world.) There is simply no possibility, in
such a world, that masculine and feminine consciousnesses, men’s and
women’s subjective experiences of that world, could be anything but
different.
Consciousness is gendered, and obviously gendered, because the political
realities of what it is like to be masculine, and what it is like to be feminine,
are distinctively different. Moreover, consciousness is sexed too, and
obviously sexed, because the physical realities of what it is like to be male,
and what it is like to be female, are distinctively different. And that is why
the answer to our two questions is not just “Yes”, but “Obviously yes”.
At this point I predict that I will face two objections: one (so to speak) from
the right, and the other from the left. The right-wing objection will be about
what I have just said about masculine/ feminine and political oppression.
It will be: “But that was Homer’s time. You can’t argue that gender is
oppressive now by pointing out that it was oppressive then!” The left-wing
objection, by contrast, will be about what I said earlier about male/female
and physical difference, and it will be: “Wow, innate differences between
males and females on the basis of their bodies? What a sexist you are”.
To the objection from the right, my answer is that gender is an ideology
that oppresses people in our society as surely as it did in Homer’s—though,
to be sure, the oppression is much less extreme now than it was then.
The objection is quite right to draw our attention to the fact of historical
change: a fact that is always relevant when thinking about politics, but all
too apt to go missing when we are doing philosophy. People don’t always
manage to notice that ethics is a study that is conditioned by history and
politics. Even when they do notice that, they are still (as I said before)
very prone to make the mistaken assumption that, in contrast to ethics,
philosophy of mind is an apolitical study. Our inquiries into a question like
“Is consciousness gendered?” can easily be undermined by this mistake.
9
euJAP | Vol. 19 | no. 1 | 2023
special issue Women in Philosophy:
Past, Present and Future 7
There isn’t a timeless fact of the matter that answers this question: gender
is ideological and political, and ideologies and politics change. So even
if consciousness is in fact always gendered, there are different ways for it
to be gendered, corresponding to those different political and ideological
possibilities. And since ideology is not always equally bad or harmful—
since some ideology, indeed, is not harmful at all—it becomes possible for
us to ask the question what a benign ideology of gender might look like.
Are there ways of keeping the, or a, masculine/feminine distinction in our
society that are not harmful, that are perhaps even positively beneficial?
Yes, I think so. To ask whether ideology is always bad is, in a way, to
ask whether politics is always bad; whether it is even possible to have a
more or less harmless politics. Despite some bitter experience, I am not
entirely pessimistic about this possibility. But I just note it; I won’t here try
to explore it any further.
I turn to the objection from the left. This is the objection that it is sexist to
say, as I have said, that consciousness is not only gendered but also sexed,
because there are physical differences between males and females. My
answer is: Not at all, provided we notice that the male/female distinction
is not the only axis of physical difference that we might observe among
human bodies. As well as distinguishing human bodies as male/female, we
can also distinguish them as old/young, well/ill, fat/thin, strong/weak, ablebodied/disabled, and in many other ways as well. If my question had been
“Is human consciousness modified by health/illness?”, my answer to that
too would have been “Yes, obviously”. If it had been “Is consciousness
modified by age?”, the same again. Likewise for fat/thin, strong/weak, and
all sorts of other bodily distinctions that we might draw as well.
In all of these respects I am simply following out the logic of my own
argument. I started by saying that a crucial determinant of human
consciousness or subjectivity is our experience of our own bodiliness: what
it is like to be a human being is determined, in key part, by what it is like
to have a human body. But there are many different kinds of human body.
For very many of the particular kinds of human being that we distinguish
by reference to their bodies, what it is like to be a human being of that
kind has a distinctive nature, determined by reference to the kind of body
in question. One of the distinctions we make about human bodies is, of
course, male/female. But only one. What prompts the allegation of sexism
here is the perception that I have said that the male/female distinction is
10
sophie-Grace Chappell: Is consciousness gendered?
the single key distinction that we make among human bodies. But I haven’t
said that. I didn’t say that at any point; and what I have just said is an
explicit denial of it.
Let me say it again: there are lots of ways of distinguishing among human
bodies; the male/female distinction is just one of those many distinctions;
to take this to be a distinction is both natural and reasonable; to take it to
be the only distinction that matters is neither inevitable nor even correct. It
is, in fact, a dangerous piece of ideology, and one that has been absolutely
crucial to the process whereby the physical distinction male/female has
normally been deployed to rationalise the political distinction masculine/
feminine. According to the ideology of gender that still dominates our
world today, biology itself vindicates the idea of a world that is and must
be authoritatively and definitively binarily divided between the masculine
and the feminine. But biology itself does no such thing. Biology certainly
recognises a distinction between the male and the female bodies; but
biology also recognises distinctions between rhesus-positive and rhesusnegative bodies, left-handed and right-handed bodies, tall bodies and short
bodies, and so on as above. Which of these distinctions between bodytypes we choose to foreground, and which to pass over as less important or
not important at all, is not a biological decision; it is a political one.
My question has been: “Is consciousness gendered, differentiated by the
masculine/feminine distinction?” My answer is “Yes; and consciousness
is sexed too, differentiated by the male/female distinction”. But it is also
differentiated in lots of other ways by lots of other distinctions. Which of
these distinctions we decide to treat as more or less important is not settled
by biology. It is settled by us.
As a postscript: there is another distinction that you might expect me to
make here, at least if you happen to know a bit about me personally. This is
the cis/trans distinction, the distinction between those who are transgender
and those who are not. We have been asking whether consciousness is
gendered. What about whether it is transgendered? Is there, in other words,
anything that it’s specifically and distinctively like to be transgender?
Speaking as a trans woman, my answer is “Yes, there most certainly is”.
To be transgender is to stand in a very distinctive relation both to the
masculine/feminine divide, and to the male/female divide. As I experience
11
euJAP | Vol. 19 | no. 1 | 2023
special issue Women in Philosophy:
Past, Present and Future 7
it, it is to find myself at odds with both those classifications. My own story
is about finding myself classified both as masculine and as male when what
feels right and natural to me, and what I want for myself, is to be classified
on the other side of both distinctions—as feminine, and as female. This
is certainly a story about finding, among many other things, that my
consciousness has a particular and distinctive quality that clearly isn’t there
in other people’s consciousness—except when they too are transgender.
There are other possible transgender stories. (Even for trans women; trans
men and gender-non-affirming people are moving in other directions
again.) For instance, someone might care only about moving from male
to female, and reject the masculine/feminine distinction altogether (i.e.
she might regard it as bad ideology that should just be abolished). Or she
might care only about moving from masculine to feminine, and reject
the male/female distinction more or less altogether (i.e. she might regard
it as unimportant biology that should not be foregrounded in the way we
organise society or think about ourselves). But at any rate some trans
women, including me, think that both the male/female and the masculine/
feminine distinctions are capable of being given positive and non-harmful
political expressions. And we think that we ourselves would do better on
the other side of both distinctions from where we started out.
Now on the whole, people (including transgender people) are demonstrably
correct in their judgements about what would be better for them. And
we live in a society where everyone is supposed to have a wide latitude
of freedom to choose what they think is better for them even when they
aren’t correct. So it is not easy to see why anyone would struggle to
allow transgender people the same simple right of self-determination that
cisgender people take for granted.
However—welcome to the UK, 2023.
12
sophie-Grace Chappell: Is consciousness gendered?
references
Barker, Pat. 2018. The Silence of the Girls. London: Hamish Hamilton.
Chappell, Sophie Grace. 2022. Epiphanies: An Ethics of Experience.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chappell, Sophie Grace. 2022. “Does Consciousness Have a Gender?” IAI
TV - Changing How the World Thinks. January 24, 2022. https://
iai.tv/articles/does-consciousness-have-a-gender-auid-2033.
Nagel, Thomas. 1974. “What is it Like to be a Bat?” Philosophical Review
83 (4): 435-450.
Orwell, George. 1938. Homage to Catalonia. London: Victor Gollancz.
Weil, Simone. 1939. “The Iliad, or the poem of force.” https://
theanarchistlibrary.org/library/simone-weil-the-iliad
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1921. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London:
Routledge Kegan Paul, with translation by C. K. Ogden.
13