Journal of Pragmatic Constructivism (2022) Vol. 12, No. 1, 101 - 107
JOURNAL OF
PRAGMATIC
CONSTRUCTIVISM
What’s the Problem? On Problems in Problem-based
Research and Problem-based Learning
Lars Bo Henriksen
Department of Planning, Aalborg University; lbh@plan.aau.dk
‘A problem is not an objectively existing thing. It cannot be found in the world. We do not know what a
problem looks like. We do not know if it is black, noisy, dancing or sleeping’
H. Nørreklit, 1991, p. 38
Prologue
Being a young and hopeful PhD student in the early 1990s, it was kind of a revelation to meet professor
Nørreklit’s work on problems and problem recognition (H. Nørreklit, 1989 & 1991). Here we found some of the
answers to a very specific problem; how to do proper research in an action- and problem-oriented research setting?
Professor Nørreklit skechted out a conceptualising method, where we could see ourselves and our research in a
paradigm with a theory and some methods that were much better suited for the kind of research problems we were
confronted with. That was theory and method that was much better suited to our projects, than the kind of semipositivist, deductive and naïve realist methods offered by the traditional business school establishment. By taking an
outset in real-life problems and looking at them through the lens of the conceptualising method, it was possible to do
proper research that simultaneously could benefit the field in question. Our university (Aalborg University) pride itself
of being a university where problem-based learning and problem-based research are at the centrepiece of all teaching
and research activities and our projects followed that problem-oriented path. Therefore, the analysis of the problem as
we found it in professor Nørreklits’s work came in handy. Finally, we had something that we found meaningful,
relevant, and useful in a problem-oriented research context.
In the following I will take a closer look at the problem of problem and show how problem can be
conceptualised and through that form the basis for problem-based research and problem-based learning.
1 Introduction
The concept ‘problem’ is central, even constitutive, to any research project. However, it appears to be much
more equivocal how this pivotal concept of ‘problem’ should be understood. The question addressed here, therefore is
how this ‘problem’ is and, further, how can it be conceptualised? What is the nature of a problem that can form the
basis for problem-based research and problem-based learning leading to potentially successful research and learning
processes and outcomes? By ‘successful’ here, I mean that the participants, the students or the researchers, actually
learn something scientific or pedagogically useful both in terms of form and of content. By ‘form’ here I mean methods;
by content I mean curricula or the subject matter in a research project.
The ‘problem statement’ is deemed central to most research projects and to most PBL models. However, it
appears from the extant literature on problem-based learning, that there is a problem with the problem; it is rather
confusing, because what is in the problem? Or rather, how can ‘problem’ be conceptualised? According to the Oxford
Learner’s Dictionary, a problem is something that is difficult to deal with or to understand. ‘Problem’ literally means to
throw something forward, just as the word ‘project’ does. This is, I think, interesting as problem-based learning and
research are most often based on some kind of project work. The word problem is derived from the Greek ‘proballein’
which means to 'throw’ or ‘submit' of 'pro' and 'ballein', to throw (same word as ‘ballistics’). Project, on the other hand,
102
L.B. Henriksen
Journal of Pragmatic Constructivism 12 (2022) 101 - 107
has entered into the Danish language via German from New Latin ‘projectum’, formed by French ‘projeter’ 'plan', and
further back the Latin ‘project’, to 'throw forward'. We have the same words in Danish and German where ‘udkast’
(Danish) or ‘Entwurf’ (German) literally means ‘to throw’ but in both languages these words are used metaphorically as
sketch, preliminary plan, draft, or design. Thereby both problem and project become something that dynamically
concerns the future and are something that we should work on, in a process, which makes it perhaps easier to see that
any project in a problem-based setting should consist of both project and problem as there is this close, and processual
or correlative even, connection between the two.
The problem is important in any phase of any problem-based project. As in the initial problem where the
students or researchers show or demonstrate why a certain project is deemed to be important and worthy of attention,
especially in the problem analysis, where students and researchers analyse and try to conceptualise the true nature of the
problem, they want to work with and somehow learn from. The problem analysis should then lead on to the problem
statement where the research questions are finally put into words which should then be able to guide the research
process throughout the remainder of the project’s analyses and conclusions by coming up with reasonably plausible
answers to the problem statement. All this is well known from the PBL literature. What is less well known, and the
central focus of this paper, is the status of the problem that is the cornerstone of the entire problem-based endeavour.
The literature on PBL is surprisingly sparse when it comes to discussions on the ‘problem in problem-based learning’.
O’Grady et al (2012), for example, inform us that:
‘PBL is an educational strategy where learning is driven by a problem. The problem could be a
challenge or a description of a difficulty, a curious outcome, or an unexpected happening. It could also
be an incident where there are interesting elements, or an episode or occurrence that requires either a
solution or some explanation.’
(O’Grady et al., 2012)
This piling up of metaphors, however, does not bring us any closer to the problem, even if words like challenge,
difficulty, and so on could be interesting contributions to any investigation into the problem of problem. In similar vein,
Savin-Baden & Howell (2004) asks ‘what is a problem?’ Instead of answering their own question, however, they
provide us with some, admittedly interesting and necessary, examples but still seriously lacking the requisite insight
demanded to somehow solve the problem of problem. That is, they rush on to something else leaving their question
unanswered (Savin-Baden & Howell, 2004: 59).
Holgaard et al (2014), drawing on Adolphsen (1985), provide something more substantial in distinguishing
between theoretical problems and practical problems. Practical problems are problems as they are found in our everyday
lives. These may be very trivial problems, or they could be more complex, such as are found in our everyday lives in
business, in organisations outside the university and problems which, for the most part, we may already know how to
solve; they are ‘no big deal’ – solutions are usually readily available. Theoretical problems, on the other hand, are
problems as they are found inside the university, in academia. Theoretical problems can take many forms. They could,
for example, precent themselves to us when our theories do not fit the data gathered from the outside world, or our data
do not fit any known theory. This is sometimes called an anomaly and calls for theoretical refinement or development.
We could also discover that our theory might have some kind of inconsistency which we need to do something about. In
both cases these are, of course, problems and even problems that can form the basis for the understanding of problems,
but as we shall see, we need more.
Pedersen (2003: 27) brings in hermeneutical prejudice to stress the importance of pre-knowledge in order to be
able to make or construct a proper problem statement. Problems are not simply stated out of ignorance but can only be
made relevant on the basis of substantial investigations into the subject matter at hand. With the distinction noted above
between theoretical problems and practical problems, and by drawing attention to the importance of pre-knowledge
within people’s or students’ lifeworlds, we are getting somewhat closer to the issue of ‘problem’: these insights,
however, notwithstanding their strengths, have their own flaws and it is argued here that they remain insufficient, albeit
necessary, when it comes to conceptualising the problem in problem-based research and problem-based learning. Both
practical problems as well as theoretical problems, and pre-knowledge of the actors’ lifeworlds, do play a vital role in
conceptualising the problem; but more is again needed as I discuss below. Holgaard et al (2014) were correct when they
distinguished between practical and theoretical knowledge and Pedersen (2003) was correct to point to the importance
of hermeneutic prejudice and the unavoidable nature of pre-knowledge in conceptualising any problem; but we need to
take both somewhat further and deeper to gain the core insight that we are seeking here. I will do this by introducing the
concept of real problem, as laid out by L. Nørreklit (1978) and H. Nørreklit (1989, 1991), and I will take Pedersen’s
(2003) idea of the Gadamerian hermeneutic prejudice further into an analysis of the importance of the question of the
problem of problem addressed here.
In what follows, I will first analyse the problem in problem-based learning through the lens of pragmatic
constructivism - language games, lifeworlds, abstractions, and concepts (Henriksen, 2016, 2019a; Nørreklit et al, 1983;
L.B. Henriksen
Journal of Pragmatic Constructivism 12 (2022) 101 - 107
103
Wittgenstein, 1953/2009). Any human lifeworld is only possible with a language game to go with it – lifeworld and
language game are each other's prerequisite - both are constitutive of each other. A human lifeworld cannot exist
without a language game and a language game is always embedded in a lifeworld and in the pre-knowledge of its
members. In our language games we use abstractions and concepts. Abstractions are words emphasising certain aspects
of reality, neglecting others, while concepts are words that are able to describe a reality while considering all aspects of
that reality (Henriksen et al, 2004: 22). The ‘tool’ to do this is consequently a conceptualising method (Henriksen,
2016). In our case, the task here is to take the word ‘problem’, as an abstraction, and turn it the ‘problem’ into a
concept. The question addressed here now becomes: how can we turn problem into a useful concept that can form the
basis for a successful problem-based research project or a successful problem-based learning experience? In the
second part, I then turn my attention to Gadamer (1962/1992) and his analysis of the question. As very clearly and
rightly pointed out by Pedersen (2003), we need pre-knowledge or prejudice in order to be able to find a proper problem
statement. I could continue here with discussion of Gadamer’s entire analysis of hermeneutic understanding, but space
does not allow for such a detailed philosophical discussion. Instead, I will concentrate on the role of the question in the
process and in the attempt to conceptualise ‘the problem’. In a final part I will seek to find out what this plausibly
means for problem-based research, for problem-based learning, and for research and science in general.
2 The real problem
We met theoretical problems and practical problems above. Theoretical problems are as we know them from the
university: we have collected some data and we try to analyse them through a theoretical lens, maybe in a
Euclidian/Newtonian fashion, and then discover that the theory and the data do not fit, or we discover that the theory
may have some kind of inconsistency. In both cases we then need theoretical refinement or development. In this type of
problem-solving the problem is given, meaning that the problem is a university problem, and the result of the research is
the solution to the problem such as a new theory or the refinement of an old theory. Such theoretical problems relate to
the differences between hypothesised theoretical expectations and reality. In this way, the sciences are developed
internally, independent of the broader society. The research is kept safely within each discipline, that is, theoretical
problems are not really inter- or cross-disciplinary in any way. Such theories reflect reality to the extent that there are no
anomalies involved. In this way the sciences create images of reality – how these images are used is up to politicians,
economic interests, or other powerful institutions to decide. Therefore, theoretical problems are merely abstractions or
symptoms, which encompass only parts of reality, and not what the problem of interest to PBL here fundamentally is;
these, therefore, cannot be the sole type of problem, on which we base our problem-based research, or problem-based
learning (Henriksen et al., 2004, p. 148; L. Nørreklit, 1978, p. 3; H. Nørreklit, 1991, pp. 38).
Practical problems are of a different nature. They are found outside the university, in the broader society.
Practical problems are given, just like theoretical problems are, and the result of the research is the solution to the
practical problem. The research is interdisciplinary simply because practical problems often require different theoretical
inputs from various disciplines. The research is developed from external circumstances and tends to be politically
controlled, especially in projects where external partners as well as external sources of research finance are involved
(Henriksen, 2019b). Under these circumstances the solution to practical problems looks much more like a consultancy
job, than research, as it is just a matter of finding one of the already known solutions or finding the right tool. Thereby
the research is driven by external interests. Other such practical problems in the lifeworld are trivial; people notice them
and simply fix them, no fuss, nothing to see here. Therefore, practical problems are also abstractions which only
encompass parts of reality and, therefore, cannot be the sole type of problem on which we base our research or any
learning. Such practical problems may, however, be actual symptoms of real problems (Henriksen et al., 2004, p. 148;
L. Nørreklit, 1978, p. 9; H. Nørreklit, 1991, p. 44) and this leads us to the core of this paper on addressing the problem
of problem in problem-based research.
Both theoretical as well as practical problems, described here as ideal types, are not to be dismissed in PBL or
problem-based research. Both can be, and quite often are, important for the research process as they can be vital
starting points of departure for substantial problem-based research and learning process, but only as its initial problem,
as symptoms of something that it is worth investigating further. For example, there is something wrong or not quite
right and we need to do something about it. Both theoretical and practical problems may be the starting points of a
problem-based research or learning project; but neither could be the actual problem to solve, for that we need a real
problem. A real problem is found through a process of problem analyses where the real problem is conceptualised and
re-conceptualised in a final problem statement. A real problem is dynamic, processual, and future oriented; finding and
formulating a real problem is a continuous dialogical process of conceptualising and relating various symptoms into real
problems which can then lead to a plausible problem statement.
An example: In ‘The Company’ there was a problem meeting delivery time. Managers from all departments and
the general manager had agreed, at a meeting, that it was very important to meet delivery times, but even if this was
deemed important, The Company often had to inform their customers that the delivery of orders had to be postponed or
104
L.B. Henriksen
Journal of Pragmatic Constructivism 12 (2022) 101 - 107
delayed. Something had to be done and a researcher was called into action. If the initial problem was delayed deliveries,
intensive research through interviews and scrutiny of cases of delays showed that there was something else at stake. It
turned out that the different departments and the department managers had very different ideas of what ‘on time’ meant.
They had very different conceptions of ‘on time’ and this consequently resulted in problems of communication between
the various departments. ‘On time’ is when we have promised the customer said the sales department; ‘on time’ means
when we are ready said the production department; ‘on time’ is when our computer systems tell us said the planning
department. As these three ideas of ‘on time’ are different they, naturally enough, resulted in conflicts. So, when the
company was unable to meet its delivery times, it was only a symptom of something else, of something deeper. There
were problems of ordinary production management, but the real problem was much more than that, as it was also a
question of communication (see Böhme Christensen, 2002). We could say that the real problem was a case of
misconceptions and the language games of the sales, production and planning departments not being aligned with the
broader lifeworld of the factory. The solution to this real problem and the result of the research was not only improved
IT and production management systems, but also a new set of concepts; in the case of ‘on time’, for example, a new and
improved language game conceptualised through research and dialogue between the researcher and participants in all
departments that was able to conceptualise the real problem, leading to a solution. The research was focused on the
totality, not just practical (delivery times) or theoretical (production management) problems. The validity of the
research was secured through its connection to the outside world and the science is developed by permeating the given
abstractions and replacing them with new conceptions and new abstractions.
Therefore, we can say that the real problems that should form the basis for problem-based research and problembased learning can be found through a proper problem analysis, where symptoms of practical and theoretical problems
are thoroughly analysed. Through such an analysis it is possible to get to the idea of, the core of, the real problem. The
real problem can now be described – conceptualised – as something that confronts us when our language games, our
concepts and our abstractions are no longer able to guide us in our lifeworlds. The task, therefore, for problem based
research and problem-based learning is to first identify initial problems or symptoms and then, through a proper
problem analysis to find the real problem, the reason behind the symptoms and find out where the language games fail
and need to be improved, because only in this way is it possible to find and execute the actions necessary to remove the
symptoms, hence plausibly solving the real problem.
It follows from the above that the problem analysis must become the focal point in any problem-based
endeavour, and this brings us to the question of the question, because only through good questions will we be able to
conduct a substantive and fruitful problem analysis that is able to point to the real problem.
3 The question
What is a good question? There is something, for example, that we do not know – our language games do not
appear to fit the situation we are in, we’ve got symptoms and we need a proper problem analysis. Therefore, we need
good questions. Gadamer, in his Truth and Method, addresses the question of the question.
‘The essence of the question is to have sense. Now sense involves a sense of direction. Hence the sense of
the question is the only direction from which the answer can be given if it is to make sense. A question
places what is questioned in a particular perspective. When a question arises, it breaks open the being of
the object as it were. Hence the logos that explicates this opened-up being is an answer. Its sense lies in
the sense of the question.’
(Gadamer, 1962/1992: 362).
This quote from Gadamer points to several important aspects of the question. The question must have sense in
order to be a genuine question: this means that the question has a direction towards a meaningful answer in that it is
future oriented and processual. It is meaningful in the sense that it is possible to find an answer that makes us somewhat
wiser. This requires that the question is open, that it has a kind of openness that makes several answers possible; the
answer is ‘not settled’, it remains ‘undetermined’. This openness is based on the dialectic relation between question and
answer. This, however, does not mean that any answer is possible, because any question is raised within a horizon, and
it is this horizon which decides which answers are possible. On the other hand, a good question should also be able to
go beyond the horizon and even question its limits (op cit. p. 370). After these initial remarks about the question
Gadamer turns to dialogue (op cit. p. 367) and the logic of question and answer (op cit. p. 369).
Gadamer uses the structure of dialogue to show us the importance of the question. In the dialogue, openness,
questioning, listening, and answering are the necessary ingredients. In the case of two people conducting a dialogue, the
dialogue is a two-folk speak, where the interlocutors use language to reach a common meaning, a common
understanding. The dialogue requires a certain element of empathy, even if it is also a change of power (for a more
L.B. Henriksen
Journal of Pragmatic Constructivism 12 (2022) 101 - 107
105
substantive treatment of dialogue see Henriksen et al., 2004, pp. 152; Henriksen, 2019a). The dialogue is situated, it is a
community-of-two and if it is a dialogue the ‘other’ is truly recognised as a ‘thou’.
‘What characterises the dialogue, in contrast with the rigid form of statements that demands to be set
down in writing, is precisely this: that in dialogue spoken language - in the process of question and
answer, giving and taking, talking at cross purposes and seeing each other's point - performs the
communication of meaning that, with respect to the written tradition, is the task of hermeneutics’
(Gadamer, 1962/1992: 368).
With this we see the importance of the question when we want to know something, and the structure of the
dialogue can also form the basis for a logic of question and answer. When we want to perform a proper problem
analysis in any potential real problem situation, it should be obvious now that we need good questions. We have some
symptoms (the initial problem in the form of practical or theoretical problems) and we begin to raise questions along the
lines described above. The answers which we find provide more reasons to raise still more questions and answers that,
hopefully, can eventually lead to the real problem. In the case of ‘on-time’ noted above the initial question related to the
failed delivery times and the researcher as part of his problem analysis started to ask questions. He did so by initially
looking into the production system and asking questions related to this system; but he also engaged in dialogues with
people from the other departments, such as sales and planning, along the lines of the dialogue-principles described
above. Through these dialogues, and their inherent question and answer logic, he was able to uncover the reasons
behind the failed deliveries. The concept ‘uncover’ is important here as it points to the hermeneutic truth concept
alethia, meaning to bring into the open, to uncover. What was brought into the open in this example was the real
problem, the failure of communication, of the language games to guide the practices of the factory lifeworld.
With this description of the dialogue and its question-and-answer logic it is now possible to see a possible way
from the initial problem to the real problem and thereby also to the problem statement. But we need more, because if we
have a problem, we also need a solution and the ability to reach that solution, and for this we need a method. In the first
place that solution would be a new language game, new or improved concepts and abstractions, such as when the people
in the factory had to find a common agreed conception of time in order to be able to achieve their customer delivery
goals and targets.
4 Concluding remarks
By now we know what a problem is. We initially face a problem in the form of a practical or theoretical
problem. But these are mere symptoms, and we need a proper problem analysis in order to find or locate the real
problem. The real problem presents itself in the form of a misconception of world and reality and the way to solve the
real problem is through a (research) process of conceptualisation and reconceptualisation, through a process of new or
improved language games. We do this to find new concepts, abstractions and language games that are able to solve the
real problem, thereby removing the symptoms. However, even with this, we still need to ask ourselves some further
serious questions related to this description of the problem. For example, how do we secure the quality of the research,
how do the language games relate to the world and realities where we found the symptoms? This is about validity. And
what about the sciences, like mathematics, physics or chemistry, would the description I have presented above count for
them as well? As can be seen from the small case above, I have so far only operated in the area of social science, but
would this count for other sciences as well?
‘The real problem is always a matter of the possibility of preserving or continuing to construct or develop
a reality’
(L. Nørreklit, 1978: 79).
It takes action to get things done, and if we do not want to stay in the tranquil security of the ivory tower but
wish to contribute something constructive and meaningful to various lifeworlds and realities, then we also need to find
solutions. If the real problem is found through an analysis of a practical problem, the validity of our research is a
confrontation of the real problem and eventually the removal of the symptoms that constitute the practical problem. Not
by applying some already known remedy, because that would not be research but consultancy, but through a valid,
reliable, and transparent research process that addresses the real problem behind the symptoms. This requires and
demands direct involvement with the field of interest, where we need actions, where something needs to be done.
Problem solving cannot simply be reduced to linguistics. This type of research could be termed action research,
participatory research, or whatever. The name here is of minor importance, the key point emphasised here is that the
criterion for validity is the removal of the symptoms through a research process that creates new concepts and language
games, and which leads to actions that are successful (H. Nørrerklit, pp. 44).
106
L.B. Henriksen
Journal of Pragmatic Constructivism 12 (2022) 101 - 107
What about theoretical problems then? Would this description of problems count for them as well and would it
count for the sciences? I think it would. Think of, for example, electricity or gravity. In both cases we had a
phenomenon which we did not know how to handle, but through a process of painstaking research it was possible to
conceptualise new concepts for the phenomena, creating language games that made it possible to handle the
phenomena. In the case of electricity, we got Ohm, Watt, Ampere, Volts etc. and in the case of gravity we got Newton’s
laws. In both cases the sciences got concepts and language games that made it possible to handle hitherto unknown
phenomena, and the validity in such scientific endeavour is precisely this ‘ability to handle’. The claim to validity can
be extended further in the sciences to the correspondence between phenomena and data and the cohesion of theories, but
the validity of the entire endeavour relates to its ‘ability to handle’. Here we could engage a Kuhnian perspective (Kuhn,
1962). That is, to say the scientific task is the creation of new paradigms (language games) that are able to get rid of or
remove the anomalies (symptoms, theoretical problems). However, the creation of new paradigms within the sciences
only happens on very rare occasions. Researchers are most often engaged in puzzle solving within the chosen paradigm,
but even this could be seen as an attempt to develop new concepts and develop the language game that is the paradigm.
In problem-based research, it should be possible to solve real life problems through a thorough (valid, reliable,
and transparent) research process; its purpose is finding and solving real problems. In this we cannot just use known
methods to solve known problems, as this would not qualify as proper problem-based research. In problem-based
learning it is somewhat different; in PBL we can, and do, use practical and theoretical problems as pedagogical devices:
however, we must also demonstrate and emphasise to our students the significance of real problems. We should not
expect students to bring up new paradigms or to always make symptoms go away; something less than that is acceptable
in a learning setting. But if students could come up with a problem analysis and a reasonable (real) problem statement,
point to useful methods and suggest some plausible solutions in the form of new or improved concepts, then they have
really learned something very valuable. Similarly, in science classes we should not expect students to solve theoretical
problems through creation of new paradigms; this would of course be simply too much to ask. But through problem
solving (Kuhn’s puzzles), it is possible to present scientific problems, theories and methods for students and thereby
lead them successfully into the world of science. In both cases the students are presented with scientific methods, and
they learn to ask good questions and handle problems, practical, theoretical as well as real problems. This is our
problem-based task.
References
Adolphsen, J. (1984). Problemer i videnskab: en erkendelsesteoretisk begrundelse for problemorientering (Problems
in science: a theory of knowledge for problem orientation). Aalborg Universitetsforlag.
Böhme Christensen, J. (2002). Order fulfilment, coordination and social logic: a critical perspective on operations
management. Aalborg: Centre for Industrial Production.
Gadamer, H.-G. (1962/1992). Truth and method. Continuum
Henriksen, L.B. (2016). Change, concepts and the conceptualising method. Proceedings of Pragmatic Constructivism,
6(2): 29-33. https://doi.org/10.7146/propracon.v6i2.25112
Henriksen, L.B. (2019a). Language games, dialogue and the other. Proceedings of Pragmatic Constructivism, 9(1): 2530. https://doi.org/10.7146/propracon.v9i1.113631
Henriksen, L.B. (2019b). New rules of research – report from the post-modern university. Proceedings of Pragmatic
Constructivism, 9(2): 4-12. https://doi.org/10.7146/propracon.v9i2.117565
Henriksen, L.B., Nørreklit, L., Jørgensen, K.M., Böhme Christensen, J., & O'Donnell, D. (2004). Dimensions of
change. Conceptualising reality in organisational research. Copenhagen Business School Press.
Holgaard, J.E., Ryberg, T., Stegeager, N., Stentoft, D. & Overgaard Thomassen, A. (2014). PBL: problembaseret
læring og projektarbejde ved de videregående uddannelser (PBL: problem-based learning and project work in
higher education). Samfundsliteratur.
Kuhn, T. (1962/2012). The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press.
Nørreklit, H. (1989) Virksomhedens problemerkendelse. (The company’s recognition of problems) - PhD, thesis, HHÅ
Nørreklit, H. (1991). Virksomhedens problemerkendelse (The company’s recognition of problems). Jurist- og
Økonomforbundets forlag.
Nørreklit, L. (1978). Problem orienteret forskningspraksis og den reale virkeligheds konstitution (Problem oriented
research practice and the constitution of the real reality). Aalborg University Press.
Nørreklit, L., Prangsgaard, B., & Pedersen, S.L.(1983). Aktørsmetoden (The actors’ method). Aalborg
Universitetsforlag.
O'Grady, G., Yew, E., Goh, K.P.L., & Schmidt, H. (Eds.) (2012). One-day, one-problem - an approach to problembased learning. Springer.
L.B. Henriksen
Journal of Pragmatic Constructivism 12 (2022) 101 - 107
107
Pedersen, K. (2003). Problemstilling og problemformulering (Problem and problem statement). In P.B Olesen & K.
Pedersen (Eds), Problemorienteret projektarbejde – en værktøjsbog (Problem oriented project work – a tool
book). Roskilde Universitetsforlag.
Savin-Baden, M. & Howell, C.M. (2004). Foundations of problem-based learning. McGraw-Hill.
Wittgenstein, L. (1953/2009). The philosophical investigations. Blackwell.