Asian-European Journal of Mathematics
Vol. 16, No. 1 (2023) 2250233 (15 pages)
c World Scientific Publishing Company
DOI: 10.1142/S1793557122502333
Left rays of groupoids
A. Rezaei
Department of Mathematics, Payame Noor University
P. O. Box 19395-3697, Tehran, Iran
rezaei@pnu.ac.ir
H. S. Kim
Department of Mathematics
Research Institute of Natural Sciences
Hanyang University, Seoul 04763, Korea
heekim@hanyang.ac.kr
J. Neggers
Department of Mathematics, University of Alabama
Tuscaloosa, AL 35487-0350, USA
jneggers@ua.edu
A. Borumand Saeid∗
Department of Pure Mathematics
Faculty of Mathematics and Computer
Shahid Bahonar University of Kerman, Kerman, Iran
arsham@uk.ac.ir
Communicated by P. Corsini
Received December 5, 2021
Revised March 4, 2022
Accepted March 18, 2022
Published May 7, 2022
In this paper, we introduce and study the notion of a (positive implicative) left ray
in groupoids, and we show that every normal subgroup of a group is a left ray of a
group, and in every finite group, left rays are normal subgroups. Further, left absorptive
subsets of groupoids are discussed and several examples for these definitions provided.
The relationship between left rays and zero semigroups is discussed.
Keywords: (Positive implicative) left ray; left absorptive; left ray; complete; left coset
partition property; ray homomorphism; N -property.
AMS Subject Classification: 20N02, 06F35
∗ Corresponding
author.
2250233-1
A. Rezaei et al.
1. Introduction and Preliminaries
Given the category of groups and homomorphisms, normal subgroups are kernels
of homomorphisms and the fundamental theorem of homomorphisms established
an isomorphism between the image group and the quotient of the domain group by
the kernel of the homomorphism (see [4, 6]). In establishing a theory of groupoids
(binary systems) it is of interest to develop analogs of such a situation, which in
the case of groups and homomorphisms reduces to the situation described above.
In the situation described below that is the program we shall follow, i.e. we identify
the kernel objects for given groupoids and from this identification we derive the
proper class of associated mappings so that the image groupoid is “isomorphic” to
a quotient groupoid involving the kernel object in a “natural” manner. Given that
this “scheme” may potentially be developed in more than one way, we consider a
theory of left rays of groupoids to be an example of such a theory, as is the theory
of groups and normal subgroups as the kernel objects of group homomorphisms.
Bruck [2] published a book, A Survey of Binary Systems discussed in the theory
o
of groupoids, loops and quasigroups, and several algebraic structures. Boruvka [1]
stated the theory of decompositions of sets and its application to binary systems.
Nebeský [12] introduced the notion of a travel groupoid by adding two axioms to
a groupoid, and he described an algebraic interpretation of the graph theory. A
groupoid (X, ∗) is said to be a right zero semigroup if x ∗ y = y for any x, y ∈ X,
and a groupoid (X, ∗) is said to be a left zero semigroup if x ∗ y = x for any
x, y ∈ X. A groupoid (X, ∗) is said to be a rightoid for ϕ : X → X if x ∗ y = ϕ(y)
for any x, y ∈ X. Similarly, a groupoid (X, ∗) is said to be a leftoid for ϕ : X → X if
x∗y = ϕ(x) for any x, y ∈ X. Note that a right (left, respectively) zero semigroup is
a special case of a rightoid (leftoid, respectively). A groupoid (or semigroup) (X, ∗)
is said to be right cancellative (or left cancellative, respectively) if y ∗ x = z ∗ x
(x ∗ y = x ∗ z, respectively) implies y = z (see [3, 9]).
Researchers proposed several kinds of algebraic structures related to some
axioms in many-valued logic for investigation in many-valued logics. Y. Imai and K.
Iséki introduced two classes of abstract algebras: BCK-algebras and BCI-algebras.
The motivation of this notion is based on both set theory and propositional calculus
(see [5, 7, 8, 10, 11]). As a generalization of these notions, the notion of d-algebras
has been introduced by Neggers and Kim (see [13]). A d-algebra is a nonempty set
X with a constant 0 and a binary operation “∗” satisfying the following axioms:
(I) x ∗ x = 0,
(II) 0 ∗ x = 0,
(III) x ∗ y = 0 and y ∗ x = 0 imply x = y for all x, y ∈ X.
In this paper, we introduce and study the notion of a left ray in groupoids. The
relationship between left rays and normal subgroups is discussed, and we show that
every normal subgroup of a group is a left ray of a group. Moreover, we show that
if N is a left ray of X having the left coset partition property, then the mapping
2250233-2
Left rays of groupoids
ϕ : (X, ∗) → (X/N, ⊛) is a homomorphism of groupoids. Further, the concept of
left absorptive subsets of groupoids is defined and some new results are investigated.
2. Positive Implicative Left Rays
In this section, we define positive implicative groupoids, and then consider positive
implicative left rays of a groupoid. Also, left absorptive subsets of groupoids are
discussed and several examples for these definitions provided.
Definition 2.1. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid. An element n ∈ X is said to be positive
implicative if
(x ∗ n) ∗ (y ∗ n) = (x ∗ y) ∗ n
for all x, y ∈ X.
Example 2.2. Let Z be the set of all integers. Define a binary operation “∗” on
Z by x ∗ y := max{x, y − 1} for all x, y ∈ Z. Then every element of Z is a positive
implicative element of Z. In fact, for any n ∈ Z, we have
(x ∗ n) ∗ (y ∗ n) = max{x ∗ n, y ∗ n − 1}
= max{max{x, n − 1}, max{y, n − 1} − 1}
= max{max{x, n − 1}, max{y − 1, n − 2}}
= max{x, y − 1, n − 1}
= max{max{x, y − 1}, n − 1}
= max{x ∗ y, n − 1}
= (x ∗ y) ∗ n,
which shows that n is positive implicative
Example 2.3. Let K be a field with char(K) = 2. Define a binary operation “∗”
on K by x ∗ y := 12 (x + y) for all x, y ∈ K. Then every element n ∈ K is positive
y+n
1
implicative. In fact, for any x, y ∈ K, (x ∗ n) ∗ (y ∗ n) = 12 [ x+n
2 + 2 ] = 4 [x + y + 2n]
and (x ∗ y) ∗ n = 12 [x + y + 2n]. Hence, n is positive implicative.
Proposition 2.4. Let (X, ∗) be a right cancellative semigroup. If n is a positive
implicative element of X, then n is a right identity of X.
Proof. Since n is a positive implicative element of X, (x∗n)∗(y ∗n) = (x∗y)∗n for
all x, y ∈ X. Since (X, ∗) is a semigroup, we have ((x ∗ n) ∗ y) ∗ n = (x ∗ n) ∗ (y ∗ n) =
(x∗y)∗n. It follows from (X, ∗) is a right cancellative semigroup that (x∗n)∗y = x∗y,
and hence x ∗ n = x for all x ∈ X, proving that n is a right identity of (X, ∗).
Corollary 2.5. Let (X, ∗, e) be a group with identity e. If n is a positive implicative
element of X, then n = e.
2250233-3
A. Rezaei et al.
Proof. Assume (X, ∗, e) is a group and n is a positive implicative element of X.
Since every group is a right cancellative semigroup, by Proposition 2.4, n is a right
identity of the group (X, ∗, e), i.e. x ∗ n = x, for all x ∈ X. If put x := e, since e is
an identity we get n = e ∗ n. On the other hand, since n is a right identity, we get
e ∗ n = e, and so n = e.
Definition 2.6. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid. A nonempty subset N of X is said to
be a positive implicative left ray of X if
(LR1) (x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ) ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N for all x, y ∈ X,
where x ∗ N := {x ∗ n | n ∈ N }.
Note that if N = {n} is a positive implicative left ray of a groupoid, then n is
a positive implicative element of the groupoid.
Example 2.7. Let N := {1, 2, 3, . . .} be the set of all natural numbers and let “+”
be the usual addition on N . If we define Aa := {a, a + 1, a + 2, . . .} where a ∈ N ,
then Aa is a positive implicative left ray of N . In fact, given x, y ∈ N, a ∈ N , we
have
(x + Aa ) + (y + Aa ) = {x + α|α ∈ Aa } + {y + β|β ∈ Aa }
= {x + y + α + β|α, β ∈ Aa }
⊆ {x + y + γ|γ ∈ Aa }
= (x + y) + Aa .
Example 2.8. Let D4 := {ρ0 , ρ1 , ρ2 , ρ3 , µ1 , µ2 , δ1 , δ2 } be the fourth dihedral
group [4]. If we take N := {ρ0 , ρ2 , δ1 , δ2 }, then it is easy to show that N
is a positive implicative left ray of (D4 , ∗) and N C = {ρ1 , ρ3 , µ1 , µ2 }. We see
that µ1 ∗ N C = {δ1 , δ2 , ρ0 , ρ2 } and δ1 ∗ N C = {µ1 , µ2 , ρ1 , ρ3 }. It follows that
(µ1 ∗N C )∗(δ1 ∗N C ) = {ρ1 , ρ3 , µ1 , µ2 }. Since µ1 ∗δ1 = ρ3 , we obtain (µ1 ∗δ1 )∗N C =
ρ3 ∗ N C = {ρ0 , ρ2 , δ1 , δ2 }. It follows that (µ1 ∗ N C ) ∗ (δ1 ∗ N C ) (µ1 ∗ δ1 ) ∗ N C .
Hence, N C is not a positive implicative left ray of (D4 , ∗).
Theorem 2.9. Let {Ni }ı∈I be a family of left rays of a groupoid (X, ∗). If N :=
i∈I Ni is nonempty, then it is a left ray of (X, ∗).
The union of two positive implicative left rays of a groupoid need not be a
positive implicative left ray of the groupoid.
Example 2.10. In Example 2.8, if we take A := {ρ0 , µ1 } and B := {ρ0 , ρ2 },
then it is easy to see that they are positive implicative left rays of (D4 , ∗). Since
A ∪ B = {ρ0 , ρ2 , µ1 } and µ1 ∗ δ2 = ρ1 , we have (µ1 ∗ δ2 ) ∗ (A ∪ B) = {ρ1 , ρ3 , δ1 }.
2250233-4
Left rays of groupoids
It follows that µ1 ∗ (A ∪ B) = {µ1 , µ2 , ρ0 } and δ2 ∗ (A ∪ B) = {δ1 , δ2 , ρ3 }, and
hence
(µ1 ∗ (A ∪ B)) ∗ (δ2 ∗ (A ∪ B)) = {ρ1 , ρ3 , δ1 , δ2 }.
This shows that
(µ1 ∗ (A ∪ B)) ∗ (δ2 ∗ (A ∪ B)) = {ρ1 , ρ3 , δ1 , δ2 } {ρ1 , ρ3 , δ1 }
= (µ1 ∗ δ2 ) ∗ (A ∪ B),
i.e. A ∪ B is not a positive implicative left ray of (D4 , ∗).
The following example shows that every positive implicative left ray may not
be a sub-algebra in general.
Example 2.11 ([5]). Let X = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4}. We define the binary operation ∗ on
X by Table 1.
Table 1.
Groupoid (X, ∗, 0).
∗
0
1
2
3
4
0
1
2
3
4
0
1
2
3
4
0
0
2
3
4
0
1
0
3
4
0
0
2
0
2
0
0
0
0
0
Then (X, ∗, 0) is a positive implicative BCK-algebra and so a groupoid. If we
take N := {3, 4}, then it is easy to check that N is a positive implicative left ray
of X, but not a sub-algebra of X, since 4 ∗ 3 = 2 ∈ N.
Definition 2.12. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid. A nonempty subset N of X is said to
be left absorptive if
(LR2) x ∗ n = x ∗ m and n ∈ N imply m ∈ N for all x ∈ X.
Example 2.13. In Example 2.8, it was proved that N C = {ρ1 , ρ3 , µ1 , µ2 } is not a
positive implicative left ray of (D4 , ∗). Since the Dihedral 4-group (D4 , ∗) satisfies
the cancellation laws, we see that N C is left absorptive.
Proposition 2.14. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid and let N be a left absorptive subset
of (X, ∗). If X\N = ∅, then X\N is also a left absorptive subset of (X, ∗).
Proof. Assume X\N is not a left absorptive subset of (X, ∗). Then there exist
n ∈ X\N and m ∈ X\N such that x ∗ n = x ∗ m. It follows that m ∈ N
such that x ∗ n = x ∗ m. Since N is left absorptive, we obtain n ∈ N , a
contradiction.
2250233-5
A. Rezaei et al.
Proposition 2.15. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid and let N, M be left absorptive subsets
of (X, ∗). Then N ∪ M and N ∩ M are left absorptive subsets of (X, ∗).
Corollary 2.16. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid and let N, M be left absorptive subsets
of (X, ∗). Then N \M is a left absorptive subset of (X, ∗).
Proof. Since N \M = N ∩ M C , by applying Proposition 2.15, we obtain N \M is
a left absorptive subset of (X, ∗).
3. Left Rays of Groupoids
In this section, we consider left rays (respectively, right rays) of groupoids, and new
results and examples on these new concepts have been investigated. The relationship
between left rays and normal subgroups are discussed.
Definition 3.1. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid. A nonempty subset N of X is said to be
a left ray of X if it is both a left absorptive subset of X and a positive implicative
left ray of X, i.e.
(LR1) (x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ) ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N , for all x, y ∈ X,
(LR2) x ∗ n = x ∗ m and n ∈ N imply m ∈ N , for all x ∈ X,
where x ∗ N := {x ∗ n | n ∈ N }.
The concept of right rays is a natural dual. Thus, a nonempty subset N of
a groupoid (X, ∗) is said to be a right ray of a groupoid (X, ∗) if it satisfies the
following conditions:
(RR1) (N ∗ x) ∗ (N ∗ y) ⊆ N ∗ (x ∗ y), for all x, y ∈ X,
(RR2) n ∗ x = m ∗ x and n ∈ N imply m ∈ N , for all x ∈ X,
where N ∗ x := {n ∗ x | n ∈ N }.
If (X, •) = (X, ∗)op where y • x = x ∗ y, then a left ray of (X, ∗) is a right ray
of (X, •) = (X, ∗)op , while a right ray N of (X, ∗) is a left ray of (X, •) = (X, ∗)op .
Note that if (X, ∗) is a commutative groupoid, i.e. x ∗ y = y ∗ x for all x, y ∈ X,
then left rays coincide with right rays.
Example 3.2. Let R be the set of all real numbers and let N := [α, ∞) where
α ≥ 0. Then N is a left ray of (R, +). In fact, given x ∈ R, we have
x + N = x + [α, ∞) = [x + α, ∞).
For any x, y ∈ R, we have
(x + N ) + (y + N ) = [x + α, ∞) + [y + α, ∞)
= [x + y + 2α, ∞)
2250233-6
Left rays of groupoids
= (x + y) + [α, 2∞)
⊆ (x + y) + [α, ∞)
= (x + y) + N.
Given x, m ∈ R, if n ∈ N with x + n = x + m, then m = n ∈ N . Hence, N is a left
ray of (R, +).
Example 3.3. Let (X, ∗, 0) be a d-algebra and let N be a left ray of X. Let n0 ∈ N .
Given m ∈ X, since (X, ∗, 0) is a d-algebra, we have 0 ∗ m = 0 = 0 ∗ n0 . By (LR2),
we obtain m ∈ N . This shows that N = X.
Proposition 3.4. (i) Let (X, ∗) be a right zero semigroup. Then every nonempty
subset N of X is a left ray of X.
(ii) Let (X, ∗) be a left zero semigroup. If N is a left ray of X, then N = X.
Proof. (i) Let N be a nonempty subset of X. Given x, y ∈ X and a, b ∈ N , we have
(x∗a)∗(y ∗b) = x∗y = x = (x∗y)∗a ∈ (x∗y)∗N . Hence (x∗N )∗(y ∗N ) ⊆ (x∗y)∗N ,
i.e. N is a left ray of (X, ∗).
(ii) Assume N is a left ray of (X, ∗) such that N = X. Let m ∈ X\N and n ∈ N .
Since (X, ∗) is a left zero semigroup, we have x ∗ m = x = x ∗ n for all x ∈ X. Since
n ∈ N and N is a left zero ray of X, we obtain m ∈ N , a contradiction.
Proposition 3.5. Let (X, ∗, e) be a group and let g ∈ X. If N := {g} is a left ray
of X, then g = e.
Proof. Let N = {g} be a left ray of (X, ∗, e). Then (x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ) ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N
for all x, y ∈ X, i.e. (x ∗ g) ∗ (y ∗ g) ∈ {(x ∗ y) ∗ g}. If we take x := e, y := e, then
(e ∗ g) ∗ (e ∗ g) = (e ∗ e) ∗ g. Hence g 2 = g, proving that g = e.
Theorem 3.6. Every normal subgroup of a group is a left ray of the group.
Proof. If N is a normal subgroup of a group (X, ∗, e), then x ∗ N = N ∗ x for all
x ∈ X. It follows that, for any x, y ∈ X, we have
(x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ) = x ∗ [N ∗ (y ∗ N )]
= x ∗ [(N ∗ y) ∗ N ]
= x ∗ [(y ∗ N ) ∗ N ]
= x ∗ [y ∗ (N ∗ N )]
⊆ x ∗ (y ∗ N )
= (x ∗ y) ∗ N.
Since every group has the cancellation laws, N is a left ray of a group (X, ∗, e).
2250233-7
A. Rezaei et al.
Proposition 3.7. Let (X, ∗) be a leftoid for ϕ, i.e. x ∗ y := ϕ(x) for all x, y ∈ X.
If N is a left ray of (X, ∗), then N = X.
Proof. Given x, m ∈ X and n ∈ N , since N is a leftoid of (X, ∗), we have x ∗
n = ϕ(x) = x ∗ m. Since N is a left ray of X, we obtain m ∈ N , proving that
N = X.
Proposition 3.8. Let (X, ∗) be a rightoid for ϕ, i.e. x ∗ y = ϕ(y) for all x, y ∈ X.
If N is a left ray of X, then ϕ(ϕ(N )) ⊆ ϕ(N ) and N = ϕ−1 (ϕ(N )).
Proof. Let N be a left ray of (X, ∗). Then (x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ) ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N for all
x, y ∈ X. It follows that ϕ(ϕ(N )) = ϕ(N ) ∗ ϕ(N ) = (x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ) ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗
N = ϕ(N ).
If m ∈ ϕ−1 (ϕ(N )), then ϕ(m) ∈ ϕ(N ) and hence ϕ(m) = ϕ(n) for some n ∈ N .
It follows that x ∗ m = ϕ(m) = ϕ(n) = x ∗ n for all x ∈ X. Since N is a left
ray of (X, ∗) and n ∈ N , we obtain m ∈ N . Hence ϕ−1 (ϕ(N )) ⊆ N , proving that
ϕ−1 (ϕ(N )) = N .
Theorem 3.9. Let {Ni }ı∈I be a family of left rays of a groupoid (X, ∗). If N :=
i∈I Ni is nonempty, then it is a left ray of (X, ∗).
Proof. (LR2) Given x ∈ X, if we let x ∗ n = x ∗ m and n ∈ N , then n ∈ Ni for all
i ∈ I. Since Ni is a left ray of X, we obtain m ∈ Ni for all i ∈ I, i.e. m ∈ N .
(LR1) Given x, y ∈ X, if α ∈ (x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ), then there exist p, q ∈ N such that
α = (x ∗ p) ∗ (y ∗ q). Since N = i∈I Ni , we obtain
α = (x ∗ p) ∗ (y ∗ q) ∈ (x ∗ Ni ) ∗ (y ∗ Ni )
⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ Ni ,
for all i ∈ I. It follows that there exists u ∈ Ni such that α = (x ∗ y) ∗ u. We claim
that u ∈ N = i∈I Ni . If u ∈ N , then there exists j ∈ I such that u ∈ Nj . Since
α ∈ (x ∗ Nj ) ∗ (y ∗ Nj ) ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ Nj , there exists v = u such that α = (x ∗ y) ∗ v.
It follows that
(x ∗ y) ∗ u = α = (x ∗ y) ∗ v.
Since v ∈ Nj , by applying (LR2), we obtain u ∈ Nj , a contradiction. Thus, α =
(x ∗ y) ∗ u ∈ (x ∗ y) ∗ N . Hence (x ∗ N ) ∗ (y ∗ N ) ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N , proving (LR1). Thus,
N is a left ray of (X, ∗).
Theorem 3.10. Let ϕ : (X, ∗) → (Y, ·) be a homomorphism of groupoids and N
be a left ray of (X, ∗), and let M be a left ray of (Y, ·). Then
(i) ϕ−1 (M ) is a left ray of (X, ∗),
(ii) if ϕ is an epimorphism, then ϕ(N ) is a left ray of (Y, ·).
2250233-8
Left rays of groupoids
Proposition 3.11. Let (X, ∗, e) be a finite group. If N is a left ray of (X, ∗), then
it is a normal subgroup of (X, ∗, e).
Proof. If N is a left ray of (X, ∗), then (e ∗ N )∗ (e ∗ N ) ⊆ (e ∗ e)∗ N , i.e. N ∗ N ⊆ N .
It shows that N is a subsemigroup of X. Since X is finite, N is a subgroup of X.
We claim that (N, ∗) is a normal subgroup of (X, ∗, e). Given x, y ∈ X, n1 , n2 ∈ N ,
by (LR1), there exists n ∈ N such that
(x ∗ n1 ) ∗ (y ∗ n2 ) = (x ∗ y) ∗ n.
(1)
If we take x := e in (1), then there exists n3 ∈ N such that (e ∗ n1 ) ∗ (y ∗ n2 ) =
(e ∗ y) ∗ n3 . It follows that (n1 ∗ y) ∗ n2 = n1 ∗ (y ∗ n2 ) = y ∗ n3 .
−1
′
′
Hence, n1 ∗ y = (y ∗ n3 ) ∗ n−1
2 = y ∗ (n3 ∗ n2 ) = y ∗ n for some n ∈ N . Thus, we
have N ∗ y ⊆ y ∗ N . By symmetry, we obtain y ∗ N ⊆ N ∗ y. Hence, y ∗ N = N ∗ y
for all y ∈ X. This proves that N is a normal subgroup of X.
A left ray N of a groupoid (X, ∗) is said to be complete if
(LR3) i∈I ai ∗ N = a ∗ N for some a ∈ X.
We provide an example of a left ray which is not a subgroup as follows.
Example 3.12. Let Q be the set of all rational numbers and let “ + ” be the usual
addition on Q. Let P be the set of all natural numbers. Then, for all x, y ∈ Q,
p1 , p2 ∈ P , we have
(x + p1 ) + (y + p2 ) = (x + y) + (p1 + p2 ).
It shows that (x + P ) + (y + P ) ⊆ (x + y) + P . Assume x + p1 = x + p2 and p2 ∈ P
where x ∈ Q. Then, by cancellation law in (Q, +), we obtain p1 = p2 ∈ P . Hence,
P is a left ray of (Q, +). Clearly, P is not a subgroup of (Q, +). We claim that P
is complete. If u ∈ i∈I (ai + P ), then u = ai + pi for all i ∈ I where pi ∈ P . It
follows that
u + P = (ai + pi ) + P
= ai + (pi + P )
⊆ ai + P,
for all i ∈ I. It shows that u + P ⊆ i∈I (ai + P ) ⊆ u + P , proving the claim.
Remark 3.13. Note that in Proposition 3.11, the condition finite is necessary and
so we cannot remove it. For this, see Examples 3.2 and 3.12.
Remark 3.14. We give another proof of the completeness of P in Example 3.12 as
follows. First, we claim that if ai > aj , then ai + P ⊆ aj + P . Let u ∈ i∈I (ai + P ).
Then there exist i, j ∈ I such that ai + pi = u = aj + pj where ai , aj ∈ Q and
pi , pj ∈ P . It follows that ai = u − pi and aj = u − pj . Since ai > aj , we have
2250233-9
A. Rezaei et al.
ai − aj = (u − pi ) − (u − pj ) = pj − pi ∈ P . Hence ai = aj + (pj − pi ) ∈ aj + P , and
hence ai + P ⊆ aj + P , proving the claim.
Since u = ai + pi for all i ∈ I, we obtain u > ai . By applying the claim, we have
u + P ⊆ ai + P for all i ∈ I. Hence, u + P ⊆ i∈I (ai + P ) ⊆ u + P .
Theorem 3.15. Let N be a left ray of a groupoid (X, ∗) and let M be a left ray of
a groupoid (Y, •). Define Z := X × Y and define (x, y)▽(u, v) := (x ∗ u, y • v) on
Z. Then (N × M, ▽) is a left ray of X × Y .
Proof. (LR1) Given (x, y), (u, v) ∈ Z, we have
[(x, y) ▽ (N × M )]▽[(u, v) ▽ (N × M )]
= [(x ∗ N ) × (y • M )] ▽ [(u ∗ N ) × (v • M )]
= [(x ∗ N ) ∗ (u ∗ N )] × [(y • M ) • (v • M )]
⊆ [(x ∗ u) ∗ N ] × [(y • v) • M ]
= (x ∗ u, y • v)▽(N × M )
= {(x, y)▽(u, v)}▽(N × M ).
(LR2) Let (x, y)▽(n, m) = (x, y)▽(u, v) where (n, m) ∈ N × M and (u, v) ∈ Z.
Then (x ∗ n, y • m) = (x ∗ u, y • v) and hence x ∗ n = y ∗ u and y • m = y • v. Since
n ∈ N and N is a left ray of (X, ∗), and m ∈ M and M is a left ray of (Y, •), we
obtain u ∈ N and v ∈ M . Hence, (u, v) ∈ N × M .
4. Quotient Structures Induced by Left Rays
In this section, we will consider a left ray subset of a groupoid to construct related
quotient structure.
Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid. Let N be a left ray of (X, ∗) and let x, y ∈ X. Define
a relation x ≡ y(mod N ) by x ∗ N = y ∗ N . Then ≡ is an equivalence relation on X.
Let [x]N := {y ∈ X | x ∗ N = y ∗ N } and X/N := {[x]N | x ∈ X}. Define a binary
relation “⊛” on X/N by
where a(x,y) ∗ N :=
u∈[x]N
v∈[y]N
[x]N ⊛ [y]N := [a(x,y) ]N ,
(u ∗ v) ∗ N . Let x ≡ x′ (mod N ) and y ≡ y ′ (mod N ).
Then [x]N = [x′ ]N and [y]N = [y ′ ]N .
If we define [x]N ⊛ [y]N := [a(x,y) ]N and [x′ ]N ⊛ [y ′ ]N := [a′(x,y) ]N , then we have
a(x,y) ∗ N =
(u ∗ v) ∗ N =
(u ∗ v) ∗ N = a′(x,y) ∗ N.
u∈[x]N
v∈[y]N
u∈[x′ ]N
v∈[y ′ ]N
It follows that [x]N ⊛ [y]N = [x′ ]N ⊛ [y ′ ]N . Hence ⊛ is well defined, i.e. (X/N, ⊛) is
a groupoid.
2250233-10
Left rays of groupoids
Example 4.1. Let X := {0, 1, 2, 3}. Define a binary operation ∗ on X by Table 2.
Table 2.
d-Algebra (X, ∗, 0).
∗
0
1
2
3
0
1
2
3
0
1
2
2
0
0
2
2
0
1
0
1
0
0
1
0
Then (X, ∗, 0) is a d-algebra. By Example 3.3, we know that X is the only left ray of
X. We denote it by N . Since 0∗X = {0}, 1∗X = {0, 1} and 2∗X = {0, 1, 2} = 3∗X,
we obtain [0]N = {0}, [1]N = {1} and [2]N = [3]N = {2, 3}. Construct a quotient
structure X/N = {[0]N , [1]N , [2]N } as in Table 3.
Table 3.
d-Algebra (X/N, ⊛, [0]N ).
⊛
[0]N
[1]N
[2]N
[0]N
[1]N
[2]N
[0]N
[1]N
[2]N
[0]N
[0]N
[2]N
[0]N
[0]N
[0]N
This shows that the groupoid (X/N, ⊛, [0]N ) is also a d-algebra.
Proposition 4.2. Let (X, ∗) be a left zero semigroup and let N be a left ray of X.
Then
(i) N = X,
(ii) [x]N = {x} and X/N = {{x}|x ∈ X},
(iii) (X/N, ⊛) is a left zero semigroup.
Proof. (i) Given m ∈ X, since X is a left zero semigroup, we have x∗n = x = x∗m
for all x ∈ X and n ∈ N . By (LR2), we obtain m ∈ N , proving that N = X.
(ii) If y ∈ [x]N , then x ∗ N = y ∗ N . Since X is a left zero semigroup, we obtain
x = y. Hence [x]N = {x}, and so, we get X/N = {[x]N |x ∈ X} = {{x}|x ∈ X}.
(iii) Given x, y ∈ X, we have [x]N ⊛ [y]N = [a(x,y) ]N = [x ∗ y]N = [x]N . Hence,
(X/N, ⊛) is a left zero semigroup.
Proposition 4.3. Let (X, ∗, e) be a finite group. If N is a left ray of X, then
X/N = {x ∗ N | x ∈ X}.
Proof. If N is a left ray of X, then N is a normal subgroup of X by Proposition 3.11. If y ∗ N = x ∗ N , then y = y ∗ e ∈ x ∗ N , and hence y = x ∗ n for some
2250233-11
A. Rezaei et al.
n ∈ N . It shows that
[x]N = {y ∈ X|x ∗ N = y ∗ N }
= {y ∈ X|y = x ∗ n for some n}
= x ∗ N.
Hence, X/N = {[x]N | x ∈ X} = {x ∗ N | x ∈ X}.
Definition 4.4. A left ray N of a groupoid (X, ∗) is said to have a left coset
partition property if a ∗ N ⊆ b ∗ N , then a ∗ N = b ∗ N for all a, b ∈ X.
Theorem 4.5. Let (X, ∗) be a groupoid and let N be a left ray of X having the
left coset partition property. Then the mapping ϕ : (X, ∗) → (X/N, ⊛) defined by
ϕ(x) := [x]N is a homomorphism of groupoids.
Proof. Given x, y ∈ X, we claim that [x ∗ y]N = [a(x,y) ]N . If α ∈ [a(x,y) ]N , then
(u ∗ v) ∗ N.
α ∗ N = a(x,y) ∗ N =
u∈[x]N
v∈[y]N
It follows that α ∗ N ⊆ (u ∗ v)∗ N for all u ∈ [x]N , v ∈ [y]N . Since x ∈ [x]N , y ∈ [y]N ,
we have α ∗ N ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N . By applying the left coset partition property, we obtain
α ∗ N = (x ∗ y) ∗ N . Hence α ∈ [x ∗ y]N , i.e. [a(x,y) ]N ⊆ [x ∗ y]N . If β ∈ [x ∗ y]N ,
then β ≡ x ∗ y (mod N ), and hence β ∗ N = (x ∗ y) ∗ N . It follows that
(u ∗ v) ∗ N ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N = β ∗ N.
a(x,y) ∗ N =
u∈[x]N
v∈[y]N
By the left coset partition property, we obtain a(x,y) ∗ N = β ∗ N , i.e. β ∈ [a(x,y) ]N .
Hence, [x ∗ y]N ⊆ [a(x,y) ]N .
Given x, y ∈ X, we obtain
ϕ(x) ⊛ ϕ(y) = [x]N ⊛ [y]N
= [a(x,y) ]N
= [x ∗ y]N
[∵ claim]
= ϕ(x ∗ y)
proving the theorem.
Definition 4.6. A map ϕ : (X, ∗) → (Y, •) is said to have the N -property if there
exists a nonempty subset N of X such that a ∗ N = b ∗ N if and only if ϕ(a) = ϕ(b)
for all a, b ∈ X.
Proposition 4.7. The mapping ϕ described in Theorem 4.5 has the N -property.
2250233-12
Left rays of groupoids
Proof. Assume a ∗ N = b ∗ N where a, b ∈ X. Then [a]N = [b]N , and hence
ϕ(a) = [a]N = [b]N = ϕ(b). Assume ϕ(a) = ϕ(b). Then [a]N = [b]N , and hence
a ∗ N = b ∗ N . Hence, ϕ has the N -property.
Definition 4.8. Let (X, ∗) and (Y, ·) be groupoids and let N be a nonempty subset
of X. A map ϕ : (X, ∗) → (Y, ·) is said to have the subproduct property for N if
(i) (Imϕ, ·) is a subgroupoid of (Y, ·),
(ii) if ϕ(x) · ϕ(y) = ϕ(a(x,y) ), then a(x,y) ∗ N ⊆ (x ∗ y) ∗ N for all x, y ∈ X.
By Theorem 4.5 and Proposition 4.7, the mapping ϕ in Theorem 4.5 has the
N -property and the subproduct property for N .
Definition 4.9. A mapping ϕ : (X, ∗) → (Y, ·) is said to be a ray homomorphism
if there exists a nonempty subset N of X such that
(i) ϕ has the N -property,
(ii) ϕ has the subproduct property for N .
Proposition 4.10. Let ϕ : (X, ∗) → (Y, ·) be a homomorphism of groupoids having
the N -property. Then ϕ is a ray homomorphism.
Proof. Let ϕ : (X, ∗) → (Y, ·) be a homomorphism of groupoids. Then ϕ(x ∗ y) =
ϕ(x) · ϕ(y) for all x, y ∈ X. If we let a(x,y) := x ∗ y, then a(x,y) ∗ N = (x ∗ y) ∗ N ,
which proves (ii) of Definition 4.8. Clearly, (Imϕ, ·) is a subgroupoid of (Y, ·). Thus,
ϕ has the subproduct property for N , and hence ϕ is a ray homomorphism.
By Theorem 4.5 and Proposition 4.7, if N is a left ray having the left coset
partition property, then ϕ : (X, ∗) → (X/N, ⊛) is a ray homomorphism.
Theorem 4.11. Let ϕ : (X, ∗) → (Y, ·) be a ray epimorphism. If ϕ has the N property, then there exists a homomorphism of groupoids θ : (X/N, ⊛) → (Y, ·)
such that the diagram in Fig. 1 commutes.
ϕ
// Y
z==
z
zz
ν
zzθ
z
z
X/N
X
Fig. 1.
Diagram of rays homomorphisms.
Proof. Define θ : X/N → Y by θ([x]N ) := ϕ(x). Then it is well defined. In fact, if
[x]N = [y]N , then x∗N = y ∗N . Since ϕ has the N -property, we obtain ϕ(x) = ϕ(y).
We claim that θ ◦ ν = ϕ. For any x ∈ X, we have (θ ◦ ν)(x) = θ(ν(x)) = θ([x]N ) =
ϕ(x). We claim that θ is a ray homomorphism. Given [x]N , [y]N ∈ X/N , we
2250233-13
A. Rezaei et al.
obtain
θ([x]N ⊛ [y]N ) = θ([a(x,y) ]N )
= ϕ(a(x,y) )
= ϕ(x) • ϕ(y) [because ϕ is a ray homomorphism]
= θ(ν(x)) • θ(ν(y))
= θ([x]N ) • θ([y]N )
proving the theorem.
Example 4.12. In Example 3.12, if we let N := P , then it is a left ray of (Q, +).
We claim that a + N = b + N if and only if a = b where a, b, ∈ Q. In fact, assume
a < b with a + N = b + N . Then a + 1 ∈ a + N = b + N , and hence there exists j ≥ 1
such that a + 1 = b + j. It follows that a = b + (j − 1) ≥ b, a contradiction. Using
this claim, we see that N cannot have the left coset partition property. In fact, if
we assume 7.5 + N = 5.5 + N , then we get 7.5 = 5.5, a contradiction. Moreover,
using the claim, we obtain [x]N = {y | x + N = y + N } = {x} for all x ∈ Q.
Given x, y ∈ Q, there exists a(x,y) ∈ Q such that [x]N ⊛ [y]N = [a(x,y) ]N . Since
[x]N = {x} for all x ∈ Q, we have a(x,y) + N = u∈[x]N (u + v) + N = (x + y) + N ,
v∈[y]N
which implies [a(x,y) ]N = [x + y]N . Hence, [x]N ⊛ [y]N = [x + y]N . Define a map
ϕ : (Q, +) → (Q/N, ⊛) by ϕ(x) := [x]N = {x}. Then ϕ(x) ⊛ ϕ(y) = [x]N ⊛ [y]N =
[a(x,y) ]N = [x + y]N = ϕ(x + y) for all x, y ∈ Q. Hence, ϕ is a homomorphism of
groupoids. We claim that ϕ has the N -property. In fact, if a + N = b + N , then we
obtain a = b by the above claim. Hence ϕ(a) = ϕ(b). Suppose ϕ(a) = ϕ(b), then
[a]N = [b]N and hence {a} = {b}. It follows that a = b and a + N = b + N . By
Proposition 4.10, ϕ is a ray homomorphism.
Remark 4.13. In Example 3.12, if we let N := {0}, then we have a + N = b + N
if and only if a = b. Hence, [x]N = {y ∈ Q|x + N = y + N } = {x}. It follows that
the map ϕ : (Q, +) → (Q/{0}, +) defined by ϕ(x) = {x} is a ray homomorphism
and a homomorphism of groupoids.
5. Comment
Although we have studied “kernels of morphisms” in a most general setting, involving the usual notions from universal algebras, as a particular kind of equivalence
relation, the constructions given above correspond more closely to the notion of
“normal” subobject (as in normal subgroup of a (finite) group identified as left
ray, i.e. a subset N which satisfies both (LR1) and (LR2) conditions). This justifies
consideration of left rays N of groupoids (X, ∗) as interesting subsets of (X, ∗) and
of interest for further investigation. The special cases of left rays N = {n}, identity
elements of (X, ∗) which behave not unlike left identity elements to some extent
2250233-14
Left rays of groupoids
and which have an influence on the overall structure of the groupoids to which they
belong.
Acknowledgment
We wish to thank the reviewers for excellent suggestions that have been incorporated into the paper.
References
o
1. O. Boruvka, Foundations of the Theory of Groupoids and Groups (John Wiley & Sons,
New York, NY, USA, 1976).
2. R. H. Bruck, A Survey of Binary Systems (Springer, New York, 1971).
3. H. F. Fayoumi, Locally-zero groupoids and the center of Bin(X), Commun. Korean
Math. Soc. 26(2) (2011) 163–168.
4. J. B. Fraleigh, A First Course in Abstract Algebra (Addison Wesley, 2003).
5. Y. Huang, BCI-Algebras (Science Press, Beijing, 2006).
6. T. W. Hungerford, Algebra (Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc., New York, 1974).
7. Y. Imai and K. Iséki, On axiom systems of propositional calculi. XIV, Proc. Japan
Acad. 42 (1966) 19–22.
8. A. Iorgulescu, Algebras of Logic as BCK-Algebras (Editura ASE, Bucharest, 2008).
9. H. S. Kim and J. Neggers, The semigroups of binary systems and some perspectives,
Bull. Korean Math. Soc. 45 (2008) 651–661.
10. J. Meng and Y. B. Jun, BCK-Algebras (Kyungmoon Sa, Seoul, 1994).
11. A. Najafi and A. Borumand Saeid, Fuzzy points in BE-algebras,, J. Mahani Math.
Res. Center 8(1–2) (2019) 69–80.
12. L. Nebeský, Travel groupoids, Czechoslovak Math. J. 56 (2006) 659–675.
13. J. Neggers and H. S. Kim, On d-algebras, Math. Slovaca 49 (1999) 19–26.
2250233-15