INTS402H
220086769
Defining contemporary neoliberalism:
An Australian case study
Matthew Ryan
A thesis submitted in partial requirement for the degree of Bachelor of
International Studies (Honours) at the University of New England, 2014.
1
INTS402H
220086769
Table of Contents
Acknowledgements .............................................................................................................................. 3
Declaration ............................................................................................................................................ 4
Introduction .......................................................................................................................................... 5
Chapter One
Neoliberal theory and practice: An empirical approach ...................................................................... 14
Chapter Two
Neoliberal variation: Against universal conceptions ........................................................................... 37
Chapter Three
Neoliberalism as power: The political implications of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ .................... 54
Conclusion .......................................................................................................................................... 63
Appendix ............................................................................................................................................. 66
References ........................................................................................................................................... 72
2
INTS402H
220086769
Acknowledgements
Just as Polanyi asserted that the economy does not exist in isolation from its social and
political context, the writing of this thesis did not occur in isolation. There is no doubt that I
would not have reached this point without the guidance, inspiration and support of many
others.
First and foremost, I would like to thank my supervisor, Dr Tim Battin. Tim has a
wonderful ability to guide, without simply providing answers. He encouraged me to find my
own answers – a gentle supervision style which brings out the best in people. For his
guidance, encouragement, and the occasional coffee in ‘Bool’, I thank him. Tim, you are an
incredible asset at this university.
Many other staff at the university have supported and encouraged me along the way. I
am grateful to each and every one of my teachers, but thanks go especially to Dr Amanda
Kennedy and Dr Tony Lynch whom I also count as friends.
Thanks also go to all the men and women whose names appear in my reference list.
Many of these scholars – Chang, Stilwell, Cahill, Blyth, Mirowski, Klein, Peck, and others – I
have been reading for years. While I haven’t met them all, I certainly could not have written
this thesis without their years of work.
I would also like to thank my family: my father, who impressed on me the values of
academia and public service from a young age; my mother, who has listened, encouraged, but
never pushed me; and even my over-achieving brother, who keeps me modest.
Finally, I would like to thank Earle Page College, and the many friends I have here.
‘Page’ has been my home for four years, and the myriad of experiences I’ve had here have
made me who I am today.
Matthew Ryan
3
INTS402H
220086769
Declaration
I certify that this work does not incorporate without acknowledgement any material
previously submitted for a degree at any University, College of Advanced Education, or other
educational institution, and that to the best of my knowledge and belief it does not contain
any material previously published or written by any other person except where due reference
is made in the text.
Matthew Ryan
4
INTS402H
220086769
Introduction
The mainstream conceptualisation of ‘neoliberalism’ is centred on ‘free markets’ and ‘small
states’:
The neoliberal approach stresses the efficacy of the free market, and
insists on the inefficiency and/or counter-productiveness of state
intervention… and its prescriptions for most economic problems
consist largely of deregulation and reducing the economic role of the
state to that of a ‘night-watchman’ (Chang, 2003: 36).
This understanding of neoliberalism – ‘free market neoliberalism’ – is widespread, within
both academic and popular circles.1 An example of this definition of neoliberalism in a less
academic setting is provided by Kevin Rudd, in an article published in The Monthly:
… neo-liberalism – that particular brand of free-market
fundamentalism, extreme capitalism and excessive greed which
became the economic orthodoxy of our time (Rudd, 2009: 1).
This quotation from Rudd holds particular significance. Not only have academics
characterised neoliberalism as a ‘free market’ doctrine, but, more importantly, so too have the
ostensible political opponents of the neoliberal project. A keenly contested concept, however,
this is not the only definition of neoliberalism. Against these mainstream definitions of ‘free
market’ neoliberalism this thesis falls within the broad and interdisciplinary – yet heterodox –
body of literature, one which notes the significant ‘disjuncture’ between neoliberal ‘theory’
and ‘practice’. While theoretical projections of neoliberalism may present the normative
ideals of free markets and small states, neoliberal practice is something else entirely. And so
here we look to provide a more satisfactory definition of neoliberalism.
1
For popular examples, see: Bowen (2009); Rudd (2009); Orr (2013); Large (2014); Monbiot (2013); and
Monbiot (2014). For academic examples, see: Nozick (1977); Haggard and Kaufman (1992); Calhoun (2002);
Jessop (2002); Hart-Landsberg (2006); Overbeek and van Apeldoorn (2012); and Steger and Roy (2010).
5
INTS402H
220086769
This approach to conceptualising neoliberalism emphasises that ‘neoliberalism’ is not a
singular or monolithic doctrine or practice. Its nature is better understood as a shifting,
multifaceted, amorphous and overwhelmingly contradictory form of economic, social,
cultural and institutional restructuring – one which is defined by ‘variegated’ spatial,
temporal and spatio-temporal geographies of praxis.
Many of these analyses emphasise a ‘disjuncture’ between neoliberal ‘theory’ and
neoliberal ‘practice’ (Peck and Theodore, 2002; Harvey 2005; Cahill 2010). In this approach,
the above characterisations exemplified by Chang (2003) and Rudd (2009) are seen to be
engaging – albeit critically – with neoliberal theory.2 These neoliberal ideas are taken as
representative of the policies introduced in their name by successive neoliberal governments
Rather than assuming that neoliberal ideas and practices are synonymous, the approach here
sees these theoretical expressions as distinct from neoliberal ‘practice’ – or, as some scholars
describe it, ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ (Brenner and Theodore, 2002; Cahill, 2010):
Contrary to popular opinion, the free-market doctrine has never
guided the policies and practices of neoliberal supporters. State
interventionism in favour of capital has been the driving force behind
the perpetuation of [neoliberal capitalism] (Porfilo, 2007, online).
Disjuncture is compounded by the spatial and temporal variations associated with the
process of neoliberalisation.3 All of this contributes to a simple reality: defining neoliberalism
is incredibly difficult. Regardless of how this disjuncture – a ‘cleavage between theory and
practice’ (Dunn, 2012, p. 233) – is understood, it is a significant feature. Any accurate
analysis of our contemporary political economy rests on an appropriate understanding of
what neoliberalism is or is not. Even the seemingly simple question, ‘can our national
political economy be described as neoliberal’, must rest on such conceptualisations. In the
Discussed further in Chapter One, neoliberal ‘theory’ is taken to imply the theoretical writings of neoliberal
ideologues such as Friedrich Hayek (1973; 1978) Milton Friedman (1962; 1980), Robert Nozick (1977), and
members of the ideationally-formative institution of the Mont Pelerin Society (Mirowski, 2009; 2013).
3
This will be discussed further in Chapter Two
2
6
INTS402H
220086769
context of ‘the strange non-death of neoliberalism’ during the tumult of the global financial
crisis (Crouch, 2011; Dunn, 2012), an adequate understanding of the concept is necessary
before research can hope to answer the question of how neoliberalism survived a crisis which
ostensibly invalidated it as a theory and practice. And so the purpose of this thesis is twofold: first, differing conceptions of neoliberalism will be considered; second, these theoretical
understandings will be considered within the scope of a specific case study. Thus there will
be a two-directional relationship between theoretical conceptualisation and the empirical case
study, with each informing a deeper understanding of the other. Finally, this thesis will
develop a characterisation of the contemporary Australian political economy as a neoliberal
one, which will lend weight to those scholars who emphasise ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ as an appropriate way to understand neoliberalism.
A Case Study
The rise of neoliberalism in practice within the Australian political economy has been
associated – by some – with Malcolm Fraser’s ‘campaign to put an end to Keynesian-style
‘big government’’ (Steger and Roy, 2010: 21). Others would suggest that the beginning of the
Australian neoliberal era should be associated with the Hawke-Keating governments
(Quiggin, 1996; Bell, 1997; Stretton, 1993). While arguments concerning its genesis in
Australia can be made either way, the key point is that Australia’s political economy has been
dominated by hegemonic neoliberalism for more than three decades (Cahill, 2007).
It is with this history of neoliberal dominance in mind that we turn to consider recent
characterisations of Australia’s current government, led by Tony Abbott; these
7
INTS402H
220086769
characterisations see Abbott’s government as the continuation – and even the entrenchment –
of this neoliberal norm:
The Hockey budget betrays an ideological drive toward US-style
small government (Swan, 2014).
The Abbott government has a plan to have no plan and it’s really
committed to it. That’s the point of neoliberalism. It sees the world as
a market and solves every problem through it (Aly, 2014).
These claims are controversial, and – as outlined above – they rest on a certain definition of
what ‘neoliberalism’ is. The purpose of this thesis is to take those political characterisations,
and test them in an academic context. The ambiguous meaning of ‘neoliberalism’ makes these
labels of Abbott being a ‘neoliberal’ all the more contentious. In testing the nature or extent of
the neoliberalism of the Abbott government many of these implications will need to be
isolated and considered.
The application of contesting conceptualisations of ‘neoliberalism’ to the case study of
contemporary Australian politics presents an opportunity to improve our theoretical
understandings. As such, the task at hand can be summarised with two questions: which
theoretical understanding of neoliberalism, if any, provides a useful analysis of the Abbott
government? And what implications – if any – can be drawn from this case study to enrich the
broader critical literature surrounding ‘neoliberalism’?
As mentioned above, this thesis does fall into a broader context; these bodies of
literature directly inform another key political economic issue – the durability of
neoliberalism in the face of crisis. One’s understanding of ‘what neoliberalism actually is’ is
key in explaining the ‘strange non-death of neoliberalism’ (Crouch, 2011). Some suggest that
the division between theory and practice is itself a mechanism which allows the survival of
neoliberalism in the face of ongoing crises (Baker, 2009; Mirowski, 2013). This question, so
8
INTS402H
220086769
far, is one without a satisfactory answer, and is much outside of the scope of this thesis to
answer. The discussion of neoliberalism, within the case-study of contemporary Australia,
will, however, offer a modest contribution to that ongoing debate, suggesting that while
‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is the most useful way to conceptualise neoliberal practice,
this does not diminish the importance of ideas. This is due to the role that ideas play in
creating and re-enforcing hegemony.
Methodology
Here the consideration is whether the current Australian federal government can be
characterised as neoliberal; or, perhaps more importantly, ‘which conceptualisation of
neoliberalism is most useful in understanding this case study’. Thus one key task at hand is to
consider contrasting explanations of neoliberal inconsistency between ideas and practice
within the frame of the Australian national case study. More generally, mainstream
understandings of ‘free-market’ neoliberalism will also be tested against the Abbott
government’s policies. Considering the controversial nature of this subject matter, however,
questions of bias and objectivity arise. Consequently, it is important, within the introduction
of this thesis, to establish an epistemological and methodological basis which accommodates
these realities.
While the purpose of this thesis is not to criticise the policies or the politics of the
Abbott government, political evaluation is inevitable – this study cannot be divorced from
values. This speaks to broader disciplinary concerns, such as the ‘positivist’ revolution in
(particularly American) political science, and with the methodological prescriptions that
accompanied the rise of neoclassical economics as the dominant school within that discipline.
9
INTS402H
220086769
Perhaps more broadly defined as the trend of ‘scientism’ within the social sciences, there
have been various pushes at different points in time to achieve objectivism and ‘scientificness’ in our methodologies and epistemologies (Crick, 1954; Stretton, 1969; de Shalit, 2009;
King, 2014). Adherents to such methodologies would dismiss research which encompassed
judgement of current political actors as inherently flawed, ridden with subjectivity, bias and
value-judgements, and empirically un-verifiable.
In the present study such criticisms are to be rejected. Consider the following rejection
of scientism in the social sciences:
Social evils can survive without excuses, whether by apathy, honest
mistake or selfish intent... Scientistic selection avoids the radical
imagination or discovery of poor men's chances for social choice or
change or conservation (Stretton, 1969: 431).
Or, simply take Grant’s question:
Can we know what is worth knowing about politics through scientific
research methods alone? … Is research in political theory worth
doing, or can politics be adequately understood without it? (Grant,
2002: 578).
The answer to both of these questions is surely ‘no’. Fundamentally, if we, in our discipline,
limit those questions which we allow ourselves to consider by particular methodological
boundaries, it will lead to the poverty of the discipline, and to the diminution of our societal
relevance. Subjectivism should be accepted, made explicit, and then worked around.
The implication of this for this thesis is that claims of complete objectivity cannot be
made. The simple task at hand is to consider an established literature of critical neoliberal
scholarship within the scope of the contemporary Australian political landscape. The aim
here is to achieve an appropriate mix between objectivity and subjectivity. Allowing
subjective evaluations to frame research questions does not itself exclude empiricism from
the methodology to be employed – that which can be measured or proven with empirical
10
INTS402H
220086769
methods will be.4 The key point of this methodological framework is simply that a desire for
the legitimacy accorded to scientific research will not limit this inquiry – the legitimacy of
this approach is grounded in a deeper social science epistemology.
Outline
The argument presented here is separated into three chapters. Chapter One contrasts
neoliberal theory with neoliberal practice. This chapter challenges those conceptualisations of
neoliberalism which assume that both theory and practice are dominated by free market ideas.
Contrary to theoretical postulates, an empirical approach reveals that ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ – or, more simply, neoliberal practice – is better defined as a process which
involves active state intervention in the economy. The ‘free market’ of neoliberal theory is
substituted for the deliberate creation and recreation of market-like structures in some areas,
whilst in others market discipline is repressed through tools such as corporate welfare. The
overall outcome of this is upward wealth and income redistribution, directly benefiting the
interests of capital.
After considering this dichotomy of ideas and practice generally, Chapter One then
considers this perspective within the frame of the Australian case study. The position reached
is that while the rhetoric of the Coalition does conform to neoliberal theory, the state
continues to play a significant role in practice – if ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is the
conceptualisation of neoliberalism adopted, then the Abbott government can indeed be
characterised as neoliberal.
4
See Chapter Three and the Appendix.
11
INTS402H
220086769
Chapter Two develops the framework established in the first chapter, by expanding to
encompass spatial and temporal aspects. This chapter stands against singular, universal and
monolithic definitions of neoliberalism, instead stressing that neoliberal practice is marked by
extensive variegation across different iterations and political economies. This variegation is
driven by the interaction between the process of neoliberalisation and the unique context in
which it is being ‘embedded’. Within this chapter, the Australian case study is interwoven
with theoretical analysis. The ‘variegation’ approach builds upon a particular reading of Karl
Polanyi which sees the economy as ‘always embedded’ rather than going through the ‘double
movement’ of embedding and disembedding (Block, 2003; Cahill, 2012). The temporal facet
of neoliberal variation builds on the Polanyian nature of spatially variegated neoliberalism by
also incorporating the concept of ‘crisis’ as neoliberalisms historical method of entrenchment.
The result of this is that neoliberalism refuses to be defined in static or universal terms.
Definitions which fail to appreciate these spatial and temporal nuances leave themselves
vulnerable to criticism, as they rarely correlate to empirical reality.
This brings us to Chapter Three. As mentioned above, the broader context of this
thesis is the apparent durability of neoliberalism in the face of crisis. When this is taken
together with the empirical actuality that the neoliberal project benefits only a select few, its
established hegemony raises some key political questions. Why does neoliberalism present as
such a contradictory amalgam of theory and practice? How has this project managed to secure
the support of many whose interests are undermined by neoliberal dominance, and how has
this project avoided effective criticism? These are some of the key political economic
questions of our time. While conclusive answers are far from being reached, some
methodological precepts are here suggested as a starting point for further research.
12
INTS402H
220086769
Argument
The Abbott government has been characterised by some as ‘neoliberal’. These descriptions
are based on the ‘free-market’ conceptualisation of neoliberalism, and do not reflect the
material realities of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’. When neoliberalism is understood more
deeply, emphasising the ‘disjuncture’ between neoliberal ‘theory’ and ‘practice’, the current
Australian government can indeed be described as neoliberal – albeit, an instance of
neoliberalism which is variegated spatially and temporally from other established examples
of neoliberalism. Thus, this case-study underscores the importance of theoretical
conceptualisations of neoliberalism that emphasise the difference inherent between neoliberal
theory and practice. A better way to conceptualise neoliberalism is by considering the
material interests served. Neoliberalism, here, is understood as the ongoing political project
to re-establish the power of capital after the brief challenge of the ‘long boom’.
This conception leads, finally, to the normative implication for Australian politics, and
progressive politics in general: for political opposition to be effective, it must engage with
neoliberal realities, rather than neoliberal mythologies.
13
INTS402H
220086769
Chapter One
Neoliberal theory and practice:
An empirical approach
Introduction
Neoliberal theory and neoliberal practice differ in many significant respects: the role of the
state, the nature of the market, the universality of application, and especially in the material
outcome of neoliberalism. First, consider the core, overarching contradiction between
neoliberal ‘theory’ and neoliberal ‘practice’ – that contradiction lies between the theoretical
ontological nature of the market, and the ontology implied by ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ (or, synonymously, neoliberal ‘practice’). Neoliberal theory presents ‘the
market’ as a spontaneously occurring, natural institution (Hayek, 1973; Mirowski 2013: 69).
In direct contrast to this, neoliberal practice has been defined by constant efforts by the state
to create – and re-create – these theoretically spontaneous markets (Porfilo, 2007, online).
Further, many of the normative prescriptions advocated by neoliberal thinkers diverge
significantly from the materialist history of global neoliberal hegemony. A key example of
this is the ‘size’ of the state; neoliberal doctrines largely advocate a ‘small state’, and yet an
empirical appraisal of this goal shows that ‘neoliberal’ governments have often grown, rather
than shrunk. These examples of issues surrounding ontology and the realisation of utopian
normative visions speak to a broader issue – the distinct disjuncture between neoliberal
theory and practice, not only in policy, but also in outcome. The approach in this thesis will
be to emphasise the material realities of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’.
14
INTS402H
220086769
Thus the methodological approach employed here will be materialistic – an emphasis
empirical actuality (Blackburn, 2008). This stands in direct contrast to a more ‘ideas-centric
approach’:
[the] ideas-centred conception of reality… interprets human society as
a reflection of the dominant ideas used to explain it, and views ideas
as the main drivers of political and economic change. More
importantly… such idealist assumptions about neoliberalism do not
withstand scrutiny against empirical evidence (Cahill, 2014: viii).
As Cahill goes on to say, mainstream definitions and criticisms of neoliberalism engage
primarily with the idea of neoliberalism. It will be detailed here that there is a significant
disjuncture between what neoliberalism says it does, and what it actually does. This
disjuncture has its root in ontological tensions and contradictions, as is emphasised in
Mirowski’s analysis (2009; 2013); these theoretical contradictions are, however, further
compounded by the material realities of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ (Brenner and
Theodore, 2002; Peck and Tickell, 2002). The need for this empirical approach is clearly
articulated by Martijn Konings:
In order to uncover the nature of neoliberal practices we need to shift
to a conceptual register not shaped by neoliberal free-market discourse
– to a framework that allows us to see what such practices affect and
do rather than say and project (Konings, 2012: 55).
Solidifying the case for this methodological approach, David Harvey suggests that a focus on
ideas, to the exclusion of material realities, hampers the nominal opponents of neoliberalism;
it is not just intellectual integrity which demands considering the ideational and material
together, but also the improved possibility of political change:
The mutual development of theory and of historical and geographical
reconstruction, all projected into the fires of political practice, forms
the intellectual crucible out of which new strategies for the sane
reconstruction of society can emerge (Harvey, 2006 [1982]: 451).
15
INTS402H
220086769
The first task in this chapter will be to define neoliberal ‘theory’, and then neoliberal
‘practice’. Several essential neoliberal tenets will be tested, with particular emphasis on the
material interests served by such a policy.5 Within this test, the ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ thesis will be either illustrated or challenged. This approach can generally be
understood as ‘materialist’. Certainly, any assessment of the Abbott government, as
‘neoliberal’ or not, will rest on one’s methodological approach – ideational or materialistic.
The conclusion of this chapter highlights the clear disjuncture between neoliberal
ideas and practices. This ‘cleavage’ is too severe to be explained by the inevitable
‘messiness’ of translating a political philosophy into practice (Dunn, 2012: 233), instead
suggesting that these neoliberal ideas play some other role – one of legitimisation, rather than
normative projection. The simple reality that there is no such thing as a free market highlights
the impossibility of the neoliberal utopia. Neoliberalism, in practice, is as involved in
constructing markets as more progressive movements are in attempts to de-construct them.
The implication of this theoretical discussion for the Australian case study is that when
neoliberalism is defined as ‘actually existing neoliberalism’, the Abbott government can
indeed be characterised as a neoliberal one.
Neoliberal Theory
Neoliberal theory is the collective term given to the utopic normative vision promulgated by
thinkers such as Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman, and Robert Nozick. This theory presents
5
While the key consideration is the current Coalition government led by Prime Minister Tony Abbott, this is an
analytical piece, not a partisan one. Many of the comments made about neoliberal policy could also be applied
to previous Labor governments as well. For the sake of brevity, this case study focuses on the Abbott
government, but further research could apply the same construct to other recent Australian political experiences.
16
INTS402H
220086769
the market as not only the most efficient way to organise society, but also as the most moral.6
Flowing on from this portrayal of the market as an omniscient information processor that will
ensure an optimal distribution of goods and services is an argument to limit or remove forces
that could distort this market utopia – i.e. state intervention in the spontaneous and
benevolent market.
First, let us consider some primary examples of neoliberal theory:
Adam Smith’s flash of genius was his recognition that the prices that
emerged from voluntary transactions between buyers and sellers – for
short, in a free market – could coordinate the activity of millions of
people, each seeking his own interest, in such a way as to make
everyone better off (Friedman & Friedman, 1980, in Argyrous &
Stilwell, 2011: 120).7
Here the market is portrayed as the ideal way to organise society, and this is perhaps the most
defining aspect of neoliberal theory. This has been noted by critical scholars, such as David
Harvey, as in his A Brief History of Neoliberalism (2005):
Neoliberal [theory]… proposes that human well-being can best be
advanced by liberating individual entrepreneurial freedoms and skills
within an institutional framework characterised by strong private
property rights, free markets and free trade (Harvey, 2005: 2).
Another tenet of the neoliberal doctrine is the assertion that, if left alone, the market
will also reach a state of equilibrium. The idea of equilibrium is central to the neoclassical
school of economics. Take Eugene Fama as an example typical of the neoclassical efficient
markets hypothesis:
In an efficient market, competition among the many intelligent
participants leads to a situation where, at any point in time, actual
prices of individual securities already reflect the effects of information
based both on events that have already occurred and on events which,
as of now, the market expects to take place in the future. In other
words, in an efficient market at any point in time the actual price of a
security will be a good estimate of its intrinsic value (Fama, 1965: 76).
The ‘moral’ value of the market was emphasised particularly by Friedman and Nozick. Hayek’s work was
more ‘amoral’, focusing on efficiency and (negative) unintended consequences.
7
The reference to Adam Smith is a contentious one. Many argue that Smith was not the ‘free-market’ advocate
he has since been made out to be. In this sense, Milton and Rose Friedman may be reading too much into The
Wealth of Nations, and not focussing enough on his Theory of Moral Sentiments.
6
17
INTS402H
220086769
This tenet of neoclassicism is found in almost every introductory economics textbook (e.g.
Crompton, Swann, Hopkins and McEachern, 2004; Mankiw, 2014). The relationship between
neoclassical economics and neoliberal theory is often one of vulgarisation – oversimplifying
neoclassical theories and hypotheses, in order to support neoliberal normative prescriptions.
An example of this mistreatment of neoclassicists is in the following argument by Larry
Summers against the regulation of the financial sector: ‘the parties to these kinds of contract
are largely sophisticated financial institutions that would appear to be eminently capable of
protecting themselves from fraud and counterparty insolvencies’ (Summers, 1998, online).
Importantly, equilibrium is one of the ontological values attributed to the market by
neoliberal ideologues, along with spontaneity and utopic distribution.
Leading on from these values attributed to the market, the key normative prescription
associated with neoliberal theory is the removal of the state from economic affairs, as any
attempt to plan or effect outcomes will negatively affect price signals and the ability of the
market to clear. As such, the role of the state is limited such:
These then are the basic roles of government in a free society: to
provide a means whereby we can modify the rules, to mediate
differences among us on the meaning of the rules, and to enforce
compliance with the rules on the part of those few who would
otherwise not play the game (Friedman and Friedman, 2002 [1962]:
25).
A complete account of the history of neoliberal thought is outside the scope of this thesis, but
the above quotations serve as an outline of the theory. The policies associated with neoliberal
theory – free trade, deregulation, reducing the imposition of taxation, the privatisation of state
assets, etc. – are all drawn from these central premises of price signals and equilibrium
resulting in a harmonious market society.
As outlined in the introduction to this thesis, and in the outline above of the historical
materialist approach, the vast majority of critics of neoliberalism proceed as if these
neoliberal ideas reflect existing neoliberal practices. The political significance of such
18
INTS402H
220086769
engagements will be developed later in this thesis. Here we will merely consider some
examples of ‘free-market’ conceptions of neoliberalism, in order to contrast with neoliberal
practice. Take examples of such criticisms:
neoliberals across the globe share a common belief in the power of
‘self-regulating’ free markets to create a better world (Steger and
Roy, 2010: x).
Neoliberalism – or the belief in the sufficiency of markets to secure
human welfare – [is] the age’s default ideology (Kunkel, 2009,
online).
Neoliberalism advances individualism in terms of making choices and
taking initiatives, the primacy of the market in laissez faire
conditions, minimal state intervention in economic matters…
(Zafarullah & Huque, 2012: 21).
These are examples of the orthodox understanding of neoliberalism within critical spheres.
As a result, many of the criticisms levelled at neoliberal policy focus on the theoretical and
material failings of, say, ‘small government’, ‘free trade’, or ‘perfect information’.
Finally, neoliberal theory is crucially and misleadingly based on a singular,
monolithic vision. As much of this thesis will emphasise,8 neoliberal practice is marked by
uneven spatial and temporal development. Neoliberal variegation should be seen in contrast
to the way neoliberal theory is presented as universal, and as such another example of
disjuncture:
[N]eoliberal doctrine is premised upon a “one size fits all” model of
policy implementation that assumes identical results will follow the
imposition of market-oriented reforms, rather than recognizing the
extraordinary variations that arise as neoliberal reform initiatives are
imposed within contextually specific institutional landscapes and
policy approaches (Brenner and Theodore, 2002: 353).
Neoliberal theory is entirely distinct from neoliberal practice. It is to that material reality of
‘actually existing neoliberalism’ that we now turn.
8
Chapter 2, in particular
19
INTS402H
220086769
Neoliberal Practice
Neoliberal ‘practice’ – ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ – is incredibly varied. Across its
varied iterations, however, one commonality is its disjuncture from the utopic imagery of
Hayek and Friedman. The term ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ originates in the work of
Neil Brenner and Nik Theodore (2002) and Jamie Peck and Adam Tickell (2002). The term:
highlight[s] ways in which neoliberal ideology systematically
misrepresents the real effects of such policies on macroinstitutional
structures and evolutionary trajectories of capitalism (Brenner and
Theodore, 2002: 353).
Put more simply, neoliberal ideology (or theory) represents something entirely different from
the actual policies and institutional frameworks shaped during the ‘neoliberal period’. The
most fundamental divergence from theory is in the role allocated to the state in creating and
recreating neoliberal markets (Porfilo, 2007, online).
This is, however, no surprise when the development of capitalism is viewed through a
historical lens – ‘an historical approach reveals that states have been integral to the
development and expanded reproduction of capitalism’ (Cahill, 2010: 306). Two scholars
who, at different times, have emphasised the essential role of the state in capitalist
development are Karl Polanyi (2001 [1944]) and Ha-Joon Chang (2010). Polanyi’s The Great
Transformation was a critique brought to the nineteenth century experience with ‘laissez
faire’ capitalism. While that period is often characterised as largely free of regulatory
involvement by the state, Polanyi’s empirical approach revealed ‘an enormous increase in
continuous, centrally organised and controlled interventionism’ (Polanyi, 2001 [1944]: 146).
A similar argument is presented by Chang, who makes the claim that ‘there is no such
thing as a free market’ – ‘A market looks free only because we so unconditionally accept its
underlying restrictions that we fail to see them’ (2010: 1). Many of the fundamental tasks of
20
INTS402H
220086769
the contemporary state make the realisation of a truly ‘free market’ impossible. Even the
most strident neoliberal would not argue that children should be re-introduced to the workforce. Standard controls over immigration directly influence the labour market. Even the way
in which money is created and supplied shapes and influences the market – let alone the
social values and relationships, which inform all market transactions, the origins of which are
outside of the ‘market’. Chang, like Polanyi before him, recognises that the market is
embedded in a complex social, political and institutional context which ultimately defines
and shapes it. It is in this sense that neoliberal theory is utopic; it represents an unrealisable
social organisation. What is surprising is the way in which this utopic imagery – the ‘free
market’ – has come to so fully dominate our economic debates, both domestically and
globally.
From this Polanyian perspective ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is understood as
disconnected from the impossibility that is neoliberal theory – neoliberal markets are just as
‘embedded’ as other market formations (Cahill, 2012). The task, then, is to consider what
actually characterises neoliberal practice. Across variegated political economic geographies,
the typical policies associated with neoliberalism are deregulation, privatisation and
marketization (Cahill, 2010: 307). Crucially, however, while neoliberal practice has
facilitated the expansion of markets and ‘market-like’ structures, these policies have not
correlated with a reduction of the size or scope of government intervention in the economy;
‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is certainly defined by increasing the scope and frequency of
market-based transactions, but the characterisation of neoliberal practice as involving ‘free
markets’ is incorrect.
Indeed, during the neoliberal period, the state has played a central role in
redistributing income upwards. One simple way in which this is achieved by:
21
INTS402H
220086769
increasing the supply of less-skilled workers (thereby lowering their
wages), while at the same time restricting the supply of more highly
educated professional employees (thereby raising their wages) (Baker,
2009: 1).
Whether through tight control over labour supply,9 or by other means, the state plays an
active role in facilitating upwards redistribution of wealth. Other mechanisms ‘include
corporate welfare’, and cuts to services which disproportionately affect the poor. Often it is
through a combination of such measures that income (and wealth) is funnelled upward.
The growth of the state can be illustrated by the rise in taxation across the OECD
during the rise of hegemonic neoliberalism (Piketty, 2014: 475), coupled with rising wealth
inequality during that same period (see Appendix). This correlation cannot be explained away
with overall growth rates improving government revenue, as the same time period has also
seen stagnation and decline of GDP growth (Piketty: 356). Although causation is difficult to
prove, it is apparent that the normative prescriptions of theoretical neoliberalism fail to
capture neoliberal governance. A better explanation for these empirical facts is that ‘actually
existing neoliberalism’ has resulted in both high rates of state activity coupled with
increasing wealth and income inequality – the effect of this has been upward redistribution of
capital. This policy dynamic of upward redistribution has been apparent historically in
Australia (Wilson and Turnbull, 2001) – it is worth considering if this remains the case in
contemporary Australia.
First, it is necessary to consider more closely the microeconomic policies associated
with neoliberalism: deregulation, privatisation and marketization. Of these, deregulation
immediately seems counter to the central thesis being argued here – that neoliberalism does
not, in practice, involve a retreat of the state toward a ‘freer market’. Surely, if existing
Particularly relevant with reference to the neoliberalisation of international trade – the clear prioritisation of
capital mobility over labour mobility is a significant departure from neoliberal theory, and has a direct impact on
wages and conditions (McEwan, 1999: 35).
9
22
INTS402H
220086769
regulations are being rescinded, then this means a reduction of state purview? This
understanding of deregulation is prevalent in those explanations of the global financial crisis
that focus on ‘risky lending’ and the repeal of the Glass-Steagall Act in the US as key factors
leading to the crisis (e.g. Garnaut, 2009; Krugman, 2013). However, in the US context, the
process of financial deregulation ‘did not entail a withdrawal of the state’ (Cahill, 2014: 141).
Those who see the repeal of a certain regulation – say, the Glass-Steagall Act – as a reduction
in state purview take a narrow view of government controls. From a broader perspective, it is
possible to perceive a token ‘deregulation’ of the state occurring concurrently with a
permissive monetary policy which, when taken together with stagnating wage growth, forces
more working-class families to rely on finance to facilitate a certain standard of living. The
overall effect of this is to create a market where there was not one before – active state
intervention in the economy to create a market, in order to allow further capital
accumulation10.
This example clearly focuses on the US example, but it also speaks to a broader
experience with neoliberalism. That is to say, increases in apparent freedoms in some areas
disguise the ways in which the state continues to set the ‘rules of the game’ in a way that, as
Chang says, is invisible ‘because we so unconditionally accept its underlying restrictions’
(Chang, 2010: 1).
The process of privatisation, too, has heavily involved states. Indeed, as privatisations
take place, new regulations are often created to govern the private enterprises (Cahill, 2010:
307) – this regulation could be seen, too, as offsetting aforementioned deregulation. In a
similar fashion, marketisation of social services is often accompanied by a continued role for
government subsidisation. Due to these processes, individuals certainly rely more on markets
for the delivery of goods and services than during the post-war era. The key point here is that
After all, despite the hardship forced on many families, the securitisation of ‘sub-prime’ mortgages in the US
financial market has allowed a select few to make a lot of money.
10
23
INTS402H
220086769
while there may be some correlation between neoliberal theory and practice, it is only on a
microeconomic level. The stipulated goal of neoliberal theory – the reduction of the role of
government, and the creation of ‘free markets’ – is never delivered in practice; ‘in all of these
cases, state regulation has been used to secure the formal freedoms advocated by neoliberal
polemicists’ (Cahill: 308).
But while deregulation, privatisation and marketisation can be broadly defined as
neoliberal practices, there exists incredible variegation11 between and within particular spatial
and temporal geographies in the way these processes are institutionalised. This variegation
creates difficulty in these policies being used as a litmus test to identify neoliberal
governments and actors. While they are important characteristics, which can be used to
identify neoliberalism in practice, they are, by themselves, insufficient. It is partially due to
the variation caused by the way these dynamic processes interact with existing social and
political contexts that the meaning and utility of the term ‘neoliberalism’ is sometimes
questioned (Norton, 2001; Berg, 2009, Costello, 2009). A simpler, common thread must be
identified.
It is in the material interests served by existing policy, that the ‘neoliberal-ness’ of a
particular political economic geography is to be understood. The simple test is the Latin
saying – qui bono? Who benefits? Here we return to a quotation from David Harvey used in
the introduction of this thesis. Neoliberal practice – or ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is a
‘political project to re-establish the conditions for capital accumulation and to restore the
power of economic elites’ (Harvey, 2005: 19). Thus, one telling piece of evidence of
neoliberalism at work concerns the now-famous graphs and data of Thomas Piketty (2014).12
The ‘long boom’ period of social democracy was but a brief interruption of normal rates of
11
12
‘Variegation’ will be explored further in Chapter 3.
See Appendix.
24
INTS402H
220086769
inequality within capitalism. For neoliberalism should, in practice, be understood as the
process of re-establishing those conditions through the mechanism of the state.
Neoliberal practice does not just differ from theory in its normative prescriptions; it
also differs in effective outcome. The merits of neoliberal theory are argued by suggesting
that their adoption would have preferable results: increased growth, increased employment,
increased efficiency, increased prosperity, and increased freedoms. The actual material
outcomes resulting from decades of neoliberal hegemony are the opposite of these promises.
With the market so much more in control of the global economy now
than fifty years ago, then if [neoliberal theorists] are right, the world
should be a manifestly better place: it should be growing faster, with
more stability, and income should go to those who deserve it (Keen,
2001, p. 2).
When an empirical approach is embraced, not only does ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ not
follow the normative blueprint established by its proponents – the outcome is dislocated from
the theory as well. Indicators of this is are stagnating global growth rates, and increases in
unemployment. It is not controversial to note the failure of neoliberal promises to be
translated into reality, despite the way neoliberal ideas have captured the global discourse.
Australian ‘neoliberalism’
The dichotomy between neoliberal theory and practice will now be considered within the
frame of a case study – the contemporary Australian political economy, and the current
Abbott government. An overarching task of this thesis is to assess claims that Tony Abbott’s
Coalition government should be characterised as neoliberal. In this chapter existing (and
25
INTS402H
220086769
proposed13) policy will be analysed through the lenses of neoliberal theory and neoliberal
practice; can the Abbott government be understood through neoliberal theory, neoliberal
practice (‘actually existing neoliberalism’), or neither?
Neoliberal Theory?
First, let us consider some of the rhetoric employed by Tony Abbott and his ministers. A key
example of the intellectual and philosophical convictions of Abbott was his Address to the
World Economic Forum in January 2014. Many of the tenets of theoretical neoliberalism
were articulated in this Address (Austin, 2014; Jabour, 2014). Take the idea that the market is
ontologically spontaneous and the most preferable way to organise society: ‘As soon as
people have economic freedom they create markets. Markets are the proven answer to the
problem of scarcity’ (Abbott, 2014, online). Going further, another tenet of neoliberal
doctrine – that the state should stay out of the way, and allow the omniscient market to create
employment and growth – was also prominent:
The challenge, everywhere, is to promote sustainable, private sectorled growth and employment – and to avoid government-knows-best
action for action’s sake… Despite the Crisis, worldwide, income per
person is still up by over 60 per cent in the past decade… This
progress is partly… driven by the intellectual and philosophical
conviction that freer trade and smaller government will strengthen
prosperity; the instinct that empowered citizens can do more for
themselves than government will ever do for them (Abbott, 2014,
online).
Ignoring the statistically invalid approach of averaging the entire global population’s income
to indicate progress, this rhetoric clearly correlates with theoretical projections of
neoliberalism. There is even a token line supporting the ‘zombie’ economic idea of ‘trickle
Many of the more controversial aspects of the Coalition’s 2014 budget are yet to pass through a hostile
Senate. That said, while some proposed policies are not yet in force, they still speak to the political persuasions
of the government that proposed them.
13
26
INTS402H
220086769
down economics’ (Quiggin, 2010: 137): ‘Stronger growth requires lower, simpler and fairer
taxes that don’t stifle business creativity’ (Abbott, 2014, online).14
This speech is not an isolated example. Another prominent example of Coalition
rhetoric is now-Treasurer Joe Hockey’s ‘The End of The Age of Entitlement’ speech,
delivered at the Institute of Economic Affairs in April of 2012. He, too, portrays the market
in neoclassical terms, symmetrical power relationships and all:
The modern capitalist economy is centred around the satisfaction of
personal wants and needs… it is a simple and proven formula for
willing buyers to engage with willing sellers… The producer is happy
and the customer satisfied (Hockey, 2012, online).
Beyond these ontological commitments to the market, a prominent theme in Hockey’s speech
is the largesse of government spending, and the need for fiscal ‘sustainability’. Targeted
within the speech – foreshadowing later budgetary measures – were the current Australian
retirement age, pension provision, and healthcare. Such measures, Hockey argues, are
needed, as the goal of a fiscally responsible government must be balanced budgets; cuts to
government spending are the only solution, as increases to taxes would slow growth:
We must rebuild fiscal discipline. Budget surpluses must be restored,
ideally until the debt is repaid. This can only be achieved by cutting
spending or by raising taxes. And given the general acceptance is that
the increased drag from higher taxes would compromise economic
growth, the clear mandate is to lower expenditure (Hockey, 2012,
online).
All of these claims can be drawn back to neoliberal ‘common sense’ (Hall and
O’Shea, 2013), or, rather, neoliberal theory. So, it can be said that neoliberal theory does
indeed accurately characterise the rhetoric of the Abbott government. The question remains,
however: do these intellectual and philosophical commitments translate into practice, or is
there disjuncture within the Abbott government’s ‘neoliberalism’ as has been seen more
generally?
14
For further information on this fallacy, see Quiggin (2010: 137-176).
27
INTS402H
220086769
Neoliberal Practice?
In turning to consider the actual policies of the Abbott government, Hockey provides an
interesting starting point in his claim that ending the ‘Age of Entitlement’ will improve
‘equality of opportunity’ – ‘equality of opportunity rather than equality of outcome is my
preferred model for contemporary society’ (Hockey, 2012, online). Equality of opportunity is
a rhetorical commitment espoused by many liberals, with its roots being in classical
liberalism (Heywood, 2005: 107). When neoliberals suggest they are for equality of
opportunity, however, it is a somewhat more tenuous claim; especially when the claim is
made within a speech which is arguing for widespread cuts to social services. It also stands in
contrast with the historical experience with ‘actually existing neoliberalism’, which is better
characterised as a program which increases inequality of both outcome and opportunity
(Stiglitz, 2013).
The material history of Australian ‘equality of opportunity suggests that, during the
neoliberal period, it has been a ‘myth’ rather than a ‘reality’ (Agry, 2006). That is not to say
that Australia is a fully immobile society. Australia has a certain level of social mobility; that
mobility is not, however, without limits. And most concerning, the trajectory of the past few
(neoliberal) decades has been continued reductions in that mobility. In 2006 Fred Argy wrote
a paper for The Australia Institute, Equality of Opportunity in Australia: Myth and Reality, in
which a variety of data and research was brought together. Interestingly, the conclusion was
that while ‘Australians believe that their society generally performs well on equality of
opportunity’ (ibid: 11), the reality was significantly different – ‘on most conventional
international criteria, Australia does not stand out as a particularly egalitarian society’ (ibid:
11).
28
INTS402H
220086769
One of the key reasons for this lack of social mobility was the negative effect of
inequalities of income and wealth, which served to calcify mobility. 15 By this indicator, any
hope that equality of opportunity might have increased since 2006 are dashed. As research by
Oxfam released in 2014 shows, the wealthiest 1 per cent of Australians own the same amount
of wealth as the bottom 60 per cent combined (Oxfam, 2014, online). The trajectory of wealth
inequality in Australia suggests that this is in no way the ‘high water mark’; inequality of
wealth will continue to increase.
Analysis of the current federal budget by both the Treasury (Allard and Martin, 2014,
online) and independent researchers (Phillips, 2014, online; The Australia Institute, 2014a,
online) suggests that, if implemented, the 2014/2015 budget will increase that inequality of
opportunity directly through its disproportionate impact on lower socio-economic groups.
The bottom quintile of households will pay $2.9 billion through service cuts, while the top
quintile will be $1.7 billion worse off. Not only is this disproportionate in absolute terms, but
as a percentage of earnings, this impost is much greater for those poorer households. It is also
structurally different, when considering social mobility. Those services being cut are the
mechanisms which facilitate upward mobility, whereas taxes on the top income bracket do
not push people lower in the system. Thus several key factors that influence social mobility –
existing inequalities of wealth, in a system where social services are being reduced – are
working together to exacerbate current inequities of opportunity.
The ‘End of the Age of Entitlement’ has seen significant cuts proposed and
implemented across a broad range of the social services provided by the Australian
Government. Service cuts have not only disproportionately affected poorer members of our
society, as is typical of austerity programs (Blyth, 2013: 8), but cuts have been strikingly
15
For a deeper exploration of the causal relationship between inequality and calcified social mobility, see
Wilkinson and Pickett (2009).
29
INTS402H
220086769
absent across the corporate sector (Mansillo, 2014, online). Here we return to the idea of
‘actually existing neoliberalism’ as a structural system of upward redistribution – or, in Dean
Baker’s terminology, the ‘conservative nanny state’ (Baker, 2009).
An ‘actually existing neoliberal’ state does not just allow capital to pursue further
accumulation passively. It actively works to redistribute wealth upwards. One of the key
mechanisms for this is ‘corporate welfare’. Corporate welfare includes a raft of government
measures which support or subsidise the cost of business16 – ‘through tax abatements,
government financing of building projects, improper use of eminent domain, assumption of
corporate liabilities, waiver of regulations, or other supports’ (Nader, 2011: 35). It is in
understanding the quantum of corporate welfare employed by neoliberal governments that the
disjuncture between theory and practice is made most stark; especially in the context of an
‘austere’ budget, which actively cuts social welfare services, the continuation of corporate
welfare highlights the fact that neoliberal practice is dominated not by ideas, but by material
interests.
Corporate welfare has been a feature of successive neoliberal governments in
Australia. ‘Government assistance to industry far exceeds monies spent in unemployment
benefits, yet it is always social welfare that governments scrutinise and cut back’ (Van Dyke,
2003). Due to its amorphous, individualised nature, expenditure on corporate welfare is
difficult to quantify. Some market controls that benefit capitalists – such as control of the
supply of labour, which has a huge effect on profitability (Baker, 2009: 1; Chang, 2010: 2) –
have significant monetary benefits for the owners of businesses, but do not represent a
significant outlay of government funds. This means that state action in favour of capital is not
fully visible through expenditure figures alone. Putting these quantitative methodological
issues aside, research has put the total amount of corporate welfare spending in Australia in
16
This is not to say that government funding for private ventures is inherently a bad thing. Indeed, industry
policy is a key facet of progressive politics. The point is simply that when this is treated as exempt from
spending cuts, there is a direct implication for ‘actually existing neoliberalism’.
30
INTS402H
220086769
2005 at 9 per cent of GDP. This is in contrast to social welfare outlays totalling roughly 14
per cent of GDP (Farnsworth, 2013:16). Social spending may be larger in absolute terms, but
for roughly 40 per cent of government spending to be immune during periods of austerity,
questions must be raised as to why. The ‘qui bono’ test shows quite clearly who is benefiting
from ‘actually existing neoliberalism’.
Let us consider this within the context of the current Australian federal budget.
Treasury estimates place the current budget deficit at $29.8 billion.17 In an apparent effort to
reduce spending, Joe Hockey proposed cutting many social services, and looked to increase
revenue in other areas – such as through a $7 co-payment to visit a GP – totalling $36 billion
of savings (ABC, 2014, online). In this context, it is telling to consider some of the larger
government expenditures toward corporate welfare – taxing mineral extraction at the same
rate as labour (as opposed to the current rate of 13 per cent) would increase revenue by an
estimated $67.8 billion; removing the total of $11 billion dollars of subsidies awarded to the
fossil fuel industry through fuel tax credits, aviation fuel, and mining exploration grants; and
reworking negative gearing so that it no longer facilitates the inflation of a housing bubble
through speculative and investment activities would also save the government an estimated
$15 billion (Mansillo, 2014, online). These corporate welfare expenditures alone total $93.8
billion dollars annually – more than triple the current budget deficit. Other expenditures
which do not benefit corporations directly, but nonetheless benefit the wealthiest individuals
in our society, such as superannuation tax concessions for the rich also work to facilitate
upward redistribution. That savings have been found in social spending, scientific research
and foreign aid (Sydney Morning Herald, 2014, online), rather than in the area of corporate
welfare, speaks to the material interests served by the political project that is neoliberalism.
17
This figure is actually greater, due to write-downs in revenue.
31
INTS402H
220086769
Beyond the mechanism that is corporate welfare, neoliberal practice is defined by
several other tools which work to create market-like18 structures. These include deregulation,
privatisation and marketisation. When considering the case study of contemporary Australian
political economics, these, too, are hugely relevant. To take just two examples, the promotion
of ‘market-like’ logics within the spheres of higher education and healthcare are highly
controversial aspects of the 2014 budget (Etherington, 2014, online; Bundey, 2014). Let us
briefly consider the changes to higher education.
Christopher Pyne, Minister for Education, has proposed (among other changes) to
remove the current ‘cap’ on the fees that universities can charge for an undergraduate degree
(Pyne, 2014, online). Whilst this reform will supposedly ‘free’ universities from burdensome
red-tape – which, unremoved, will apparently cause them to ‘slip into mediocrity’ (Pyne,
online) – this policy package should not be seen as a ‘small government’ proposal. Just as
with US financial ‘deregulation’, the policy here is allowing more freedom with one hand,
whilst also increasing state involvement in market creation with the other. Part of this
package will extend government-financed student loans (HECS) to private tertiary
institutions. The scope and size of government spending and subsidy is increasing in absolute
terms. More importantly, this process should be seen as typical of ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ in the way deregulation is pursued with the effect of actively creating a
market, where before there was none. The effect of this marketisation, as has already been
experienced in the US education system, will be increased opportunities for private
institutions to pursue higher profits. And with the securitisation of student debt now
increasing in the financial sector, the very debt being incurred then becomes another market
for further capital accumulation.
‘Market-like’, for, as discussed above, market discipline is only applied selectively. Socialisation of business
costs does not conform to market logics – it is simply the logic of capital being applied here.
18
32
INTS402H
220086769
Similar analysis could be brought to the introduction of ‘co-payments’ in healthcare,
which will supposedly send a ‘price signal’ to those over consuming this particular social
service. Many other aspects of proposed, effective, and historical policy in the Australian
context also conform to these logics.19 With this understanding of ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ in Australia, however, the important question to ask is: ‘how’ has such an
undemocratic program achieved this level of ‘success’?
Understanding Disjuncture
At this point the ‘disjuncture’ between neoliberal theory and neoliberal practice has been
discussed both generally, and within the frame of the Australian case study. It is evident that
the contemporary Australian experience conforms to the established theoretical
conceptualisation of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’. The key questions this raises are ‘why’
and, perhaps more importantly, ‘how’: why does neoliberal practice diverge so significantly
from its ideational blueprint? And how is that contradiction maintained, allowing
neoliberalism to maintain its hegemony? These questions are emerging as critical issues
within the field of political economy. They are questions which will run throughout the
remainder of this thesis, with a modest contribution to that ongoing debate being offered.
An answer to the first question – ‘why’ – is apparent: neoliberalism does not conform
to the logic of coherence between theory and practice, but rather presents the logic of capital.
The ‘why’ of neoliberal disjuncture is explained by pointing to the clear material benefits to
the capitalist class, while neoliberal theory acts as ideological20 cover, legitimising and
obscuring the class-based project forwarded by ‘actually existing neoliberalism’. While some
As one example from a previous government, Australia’s immigration detention centres are privatised. The
imprisonment of children – illegal under international law – is a for-profit enterprise, with the then-ALP
government paying Serco $1.86 billion in 2013 for the provision of that service (Loewenstein, 2014: 17).
20
In the Marxist sense of the word.
19
33
INTS402H
220086769
might describe out current political systems as oligarchic, the dominance of the wealthy elite
is not yet complete. A prime minister announcing explicitly that the goal and effect of his
policies is to redistribute wealth upwards is not (yet) politically viable. Understanding this
reality, a false consensus is built up around ideas of ‘equality’ and ‘freedom’, which do not
necessarily relate to actual policy or outcomes.
The second question – ‘how’ – is somewhat trickier to answer. If neoliberal practice is
a class-based project to re-establish the power of the capitalist class, as is argued by Marxists
(and others) such as David Harvey (2005), then how do neoliberal agents exercise power so
as to influence the polity to vote for governments which only serve the interests of the few?
While the effect of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is material, material interests rely on
ideational hegemony. It is in this nexus of ideas and material interests that the political
implications of this thesis reside. These questions will continue to be considered throughout,
and examined more closely in Chapter Three.
Conclusion
The purpose of this chapter has been to outline two contrasting characterisations of
neoliberalism – neoliberal ‘theory’, which is understood to be the projection of neoliberalism
being an ideology of ‘free markets’ and ‘small states’; and neoliberal ‘practice’, which
embraces a materialist analysis of neoliberalism. Fundamentally, the assertion that neoliberal
practice is synonymous with neoliberal theory – that markets have been made ‘freer’, and that
the state’s role in economic affairs has ‘shrunk’ – was challenged. In reality, neoliberal
practice is defined by strong state action to create and recreate markets, and promote the
structural conditions for accelerated capital accumulation. Indeed, neoliberalism not only
34
INTS402H
220086769
creates the conditions for passive capital accumulation, but concurrently pursues an active
policy of ‘upward redistribution’.
This materialist analytical focus does not replace the study of ideas and ideology.
Neoliberal theory – or, rather, ideology – plays an important role in the promotion and
continuation of neoliberal hegemony. This will be explored further on.21 The assertion simply
is that an analysis which assumes that neoliberal policy is directly influenced by neoliberal
ideas is one that ignores the material reality of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’.
In accordance with the materialist methodology adopted, these general observations
were investigated more closely in the frame of the Australian context. Through this case
study, it became clear that Abbott’s rhetoric, and that of his Ministers, conforms to many of
the philosophical and ontological commitments of neoliberal theory. ‘Small state’ and ‘free
market’ rhetoric does not, however, accurately represent the effective policy of the current
government. Rather, the role of the state has been prominent, creating and promoting further
capital accumulation and upward redistribution of wealth. This is raising inequality of both
income and wealth within the country, undermining the rhetorical commitment to ‘equality of
opportunity’. Thus Coalition rhetoric can be understood as a form of neoliberal theory, from
which the realities of practice sharply diverge.
Because of its contradictory and variegated nature, to attempt to identify various
neoliberal governments by individual policies is self-defeating. Rather, the analytical test
must be the simple question: who benefits? With continued corporate welfare supporting
large corporations, while cuts are made to social services, the answer to this question is quite
plain. The material interests served by the current Abbott government are those associated
with ‘actually existing neoliberalism’. By this measure, while Coalition policy does not show
21
Chapter 3, in particular.
35
INTS402H
220086769
commitment to the normative ideals of neoliberal theory – that is ‘small states’ and ‘free
markets’ – it certainly can be characterised as a neoliberal government.
36
INTS402H
220086769
Chapter Two
Neoliberal Variegation:
Against universal conceptions
Introduction
It has been argued here that ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is an important
conceptualisation of neoliberalism, in the face of distinct disjuncture between theory and
practice. The purpose of this chapter is to develop that conceptualisation, again with
reference to the experience of contemporary Australian political economics. This chapter will
contrast itself against monolithic or universal conceptualisations of neoliberalism:
Against the monolithic conceptualizations that prevail in most popular
and academic accounts, we emphasize the constitutively uneven,
institutionally hybrid, and chronically unstable character of
neoliberalizing forms of regulatory transformation (Peck, Theodore,
and Brenner, 2012a: 17).
As Peck, Theodore and Brenner suggest, orthodox ‘free market’ conceptions of neoliberalism
treat it as a universally even doctrine – not only between theory and practice, but across
various iterations of practice. The root of understanding ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is a
Polanyian take on political economics – that is, neoliberalism interacts with existing social
and political institutions, as the neoliberal economy is not separate from these contextual
influences. This foundation results in a particular understanding: the process of ‘embedding’
neoliberalism in varied political economic geographies will result in different regulatory
restructurings.
37
INTS402H
220086769
The nature of neoliberalism as a shifting, contradictory, open-ended and variegated
process has led some to criticise the utility of the term. An underlying theme throughout this
chapter (and thesis as a whole) is a defence of the term ‘neoliberal’ against those who would
argue that it doesn’t exist. Indeed, the way in which neoliberal practice diverges from the
theoretical blueprint is one of the reasons Andrew Norton dismisses the term:
“Neoliberalism” simply cannot explain the Hawke or Keating
governments. While they certainly liberalised some parts of the
Australian economy, they were highly interventionist in other areas…
“Neoliberalism” can’t explain the Howard government either. What
neoliberal would go slow on tariff reduction, tie up new forms of
media in prohibitions and restrictions, or reform the tax base so as to
ensure long-term growth in tax revenues?... [The term “neoliberal”]
doesn’t describe an Australian reality… (Norton, 2001: 65).
Simplistic ‘free-market’ definitions of neoliberalism invite this kind of analytical dismissal.22
Herein lies the necessity of developing a conceptualisation of neoliberalism which goes
beyond even the ‘theory-practice’ dichotomy, to develop the spatial and temporal nuances of
‘actually existing neoliberalism’; a robust definition will emphasise an open-ended, uneven,
and ongoing process of restructuring. While some policies, as Norton points out, may not
conform to the theoretical blueprint, the overall direction of this political strategy is to
recreate (and advance from) pre-World War Two conditions of capital accumulation. Similar
microeconomic policies of deregulation, privatisation and marketisation are often employed
to that end, but the policy ‘mix’ is not always the same. This is important to understand when
considering the neoliberalism of the Abbott government. Australian neoliberalism might
create a different institutional and regulatory framework from, say, American neoliberalism.
Similarly, temporal variation between, say, the Hawke/Keating governments, the Howard
government and today’s Abbott government must be noted.
A later example of this is in Peter Costello’s The Costello Memoirs (2009): ‘He [Rudd, 2009] described neoliberalism as “the core theoretical belief in the superiority of unregulated markets – particularly unregulated
financial markets”. Australia did not practise an unregulated financial market under the Coalition. In fact,
Australia set up ARPA as a dedicated prudential regulator to apply prudential controls and supervision over all
aspects of the financial system’ (p. 350).
22
38
INTS402H
220086769
With an appropriately nuanced understanding of neoliberalism that is conscious of
variation between iterations, these seemingly disparate political economies can be
analytically grouped under the broad term ‘neoliberal’. If one assumes that the term
‘neoliberal’ is static and universal, then its application across these varied geographies might
be seen to challenge its usefulness, or even its validity. The conceptualisation of
neoliberalism being advanced here is not a rigid set of policy prescriptions which cannot span
spatial and temporal different – rather the ‘test’ for neoliberalism is a different one. It is
outcome with which we are concerned; as suggested in Chapter 1, neoliberalism is to be
identified by the interests which benefit.
This chapter will consider the ways in which localised experiences of neoliberalism
are spatially and temporally variegated. Spatial variegation emphasises the institutional and
philosophical ‘co-existance’ of neoliberalism with ideological others, and will be explored
through comparison between the Australian political economic geography and that of key
international examples. Temporal variation is also significant when comparing contemporary
actors with historical actors within the same national context – this variation over time will be
considered with particular emphasis on the role of crisis in promoting neoliberalisation, and
how this ‘crisis-driven forward momentum’ also shapes institutional change.
Here, tension between ‘uneven’ neoliberalisation and conceptual grouping will be
dispelled, with the material test of ‘interests served’ re-emphasised as the key analytical tool
for the identification of neoliberal projects. With this issue resolved, the characterisation of
Tony Abbott and his government as ‘neoliberal’ will be more robust, and better understood.
Thus, this chapter focuses not just on the empirical case study, but also emphasises the spatial
39
INTS402H
220086769
and temporal nuances of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ which ward against monolithic
conceptualisations.
Spatial ‘Variegation’
First, let us consider the idea of ‘spatial variegation’ between and across various iterations of
neoliberal policy. A comparative approach would arguably reveal that different geographies
that have all been described as neoliberal23 are distinctly variegated in their institutional,
regulatory and political frameworks:
The uneven geographical development of neoliberalism, its frequently
lop-sided and partial application from one state and social formation
to another, testifies to the tentativeness of neoliberal solutions and the
complex ways in which political forces, historical traditions, and
existing institutional arrangements all shaped why and how the
process of neoliberalization actually occurred (Harvey, 2005, p. 13).
Harvey shares this perspective on the interaction between ‘political force, historical traditions
and existing institutional arrangements’ (Harvey: 13) with several other political economic
geographers, including Jamie Peck, Neil Brenner and Nik Theodore (2012). The parallel
between these approaches and the work of Karl Polanyi (2001 [1944]) is immediately
apparent, but it suggests an alternative reading of neoliberalism in relation to
‘embeddedness’.24 An ‘always embedded’ approach leads one to consider ‘always embedded
neoliberalism’ (Cahill, 2012: 116). Contrary to the ontological assertion of (some parts of)
neoliberal theory, not only is the market not spontaneously occurring, but the realisation of
the ‘catallaxy’ utopia is impossible – even a designed free market cannot exist separately
Some examples of contrasting political economies each being labelled as ‘neoliberal’ include: Chile (Klein,
2007), the US (Chomsky, 1999), the UK (Steger and Roy, 2010), China (Harvey, 2005), and Australia (Cahill,
2007).
24
The usual understanding of neoliberalism from a Polanyian perspective is that neoliberalisation is part of the
‘double movement’ – it is the process of ‘disembedding’ the economy from its social and political context
(Blyth, 2002: 152; van Apeldoorn, 2009: 24; Konings, 2012: 57). This idea of economies being either
‘embedded’ or ‘disembedded’ rests on an interpretation of Polanyi which has been described as ‘embeddedness
as a historical variable’ (Gemici, 2008: 25). An alternative (and more useful) interpretation of Polanyi produces
the idea of the economy as ‘always embedded’ (Block, 2003: 276).
23
40
INTS402H
220086769
from its institutional context. It is this ‘embedded’ nature of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’
that creates spatial variation:
The uneven development of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ means
that it cannot conform precisely with a universal neoliberal template
derived from neoliberal theoretical postulates (Cahill, 2010: 306).
As well as interacting with existing institutions and social structures, the praxis of
neoliberalism interacts with existing philosophies and modes of politics. The argument made
by Peck, Theodore, and Brenner is that rather than replacing existing political arrangements,
neoliberalism coexists in a ‘parasitic’25 relationship with those structures:
[neoliberalism] has only ever existed in a range of partial and ‘impure’
forms and messy hybrids… [it exists in] cohabitation with unloved
ideological others… (Peck, Theodore, and Brenner, 2012a: 19).
The sum of these factors results in uneven and variegated neoliberal geographies. Each
process of neoliberalisation plays out in a unique institutional context, interacting with
different structures and existing ideologies, resulting in distinct iterations of neoliberalism.
Through ongoing contestation and compromise with existing ideological, institutional, social
and economic structures, each process of neoliberalisation creates a different instance of
restructuring (Brenner and Theodore, 2002; Brenner, Peck and Theodore, 2010).
Spatial variegation and Australia
Within the scope of the Australian case study, this ideological and institutional co-existence
will be illustrated. The first of these interactions to be considered will be neoliberalism and
nationalism. Although the intersection of these ideologies warrants a thesis of its own, we can
briefly consider how this nexus illustrates the way in which contextual variation results in
25
(Peck, Theodore, and Brenner, 2012b: 274)
41
INTS402H
220086769
spatial variegation. Neoliberal theory ‘does not look with favour on the nation (Harvey, 2005:
105, original emphasis). In the neoliberal normative utopia, atomised entrepreneurial
individuals pursue their own benevolent self-interest; collective groups such as
neighbourhoods, communities, unions or nations are an ideological ‘other’ (Drache, 2008:
11-12). And yet the neoliberalism of John Howard, in particular, relied upon national identity
for legitimisation. Take Howard’s Remembrance Day speech of 1997. Howard spoke about a
collective Australian spirit – ‘A spirit which draws Australians together in times of need’
(Howard, 1997, online) – which runs at odds with the individualism espoused in neoliberal
theory. In this way, neoliberal ideas were forced to co-exist with ‘unloved others’, for the
purpose of electoral success (Maddison and Martin, 2010: 105). This illustrates the contextual
‘embeddedness’ even of neoliberal ideas. Another example of how Australia contrasts with
other political economies is the institutional embeddedness of Australian neoliberalism in
regard to the welfare state.
Although during the neoliberal period there have been repeated attacks on the
entrenched Australian welfare state – the 2014 budget as just one example of this – the state
in Australia still delivers considerably more social services to its citizens than some other
neoliberal states. The welfare state in Australia is still a key institutional feature, in size and
scope (Fenna and Tapper, 2012). When this is contrasted with the mammoth struggle faced
by US President Obama in his attempts to introduce public healthcare provision (McCarthy,
2013, online) – ‘Obamacare’, as it has become known – these two political landscapes would
seem to be significantly disparate. How then can these spatially variegated political
economies be categorised as both ‘neoliberal’? It is for this reason that Peck, Theodore, and
Brenner (2012a) emphasise the conceptual importance of a process of ‘neoliberalization’
rather than a static term ‘neoliberalism’.
42
INTS402H
220086769
The implication of this alternative terminology is that there is no end-state for
neoliberalism; there is no country that has fully realised the utopic neoliberal schema. Rather,
‘neoliberalization’ suggests that each instance of neoliberal restructuring is an ongoing, openended process. It also recognises that the context in which that process takes place will shape
each process differently. In that sense we can conceptualise the US process of
neoliberalisation as ‘further along’, while the social-democratic tradition – or ‘entitlement’ in
the words of Hockey – in Australia is still partially resistant to privatisation and
marketisation. Most importantly, this spatial variegation must not cloud our analysis – both
the US and Australia should be considered neoliberal (Chomsky, 1999; Cahill, 2007).
Temporal Variation
Perhaps one of the most useful conceptualisations of ‘neoliberalism’ is the temporal
extrapolation of the spatial argument – neoliberalism is defined by ‘a churning and
contradictory process of flawed experimentation, albeit with a failure and crisis-driven
forward momentum’ (Peck, Theodore and Brenner, 2012a: 25). Paradoxically, this crisisprone nature of the neoliberal project has not challenged its hegemony; rather, it has promoted
it. As detailed in Naomi Klein’s history of neoliberalism – The Shock Doctrine (2007) – the
process of neoliberalization has always been defined and driven by crisis. Neoliberalism first
creates its own crises, and then uses those crises as an opportunity to push through
undemocratic change – or ‘reform’, as it is called.
The implication of this reciprocal relationship between neoliberal reforms and
increased instability for our discussion here is that this neoliberalism-crisis nexus creates
‘variegation’ through time as well as space. This is another reason that a static definition of
neoliberalism is insufficient. Any adequate understanding of what neoliberalism is – while
43
INTS402H
220086769
asking ‘can the Australian government be characterised as neoliberal’ – relies on a dynamic
conceptualisation. What is more, with this understanding established, the centrality of ‘crisis’
in the Coalition’s rhetoric re-enforces the verdict reached in the first chapter: the Abbott
government has pursued a neoliberal policy program, legitimised not only by neoliberal
ideology, but also now framed as necessary due to an apparent ‘budgetary emergency’.
Temporal processes
The process of temporal variation compounds spatial variegation not only in the levels of
‘difference’ encompassed by the term ‘neoliberal’, but it also involves another layer of
complexity. The process which creates temporal variation has even more ‘moving parts’
compared to the spatial process. As such, there is a need to establish a framework to
understand this varied process more fully. First, consider ‘crisis’. In the school of Marxist
political economy a central concept is that capitalism is prone to crises that will increase in
volatility and frequency over time.26 There are many factors that influence this tendency, but
one key factor is seen to be the over-accumulation of capital (Stilwell, 2012: 103). That is to
say that there is an inherent contradiction within capitalism in its exploitation of labour: to
increase profit, wages are depressed; depressed wages result in a lack of demand. Thus capital
over-accumulates, stagnates, and the only solution is a process of devaluing excess value;
crisis is that process of devaluation (Harvey, 2006 [1982]: 191). It is, of course, not only
wage-demand contradictions that create crisis. The essential point is that a contradictory
dialectic will always (re)produce crisis:
The contradictions of capitalism are generally maintained, but periodically – and increasingly – come to the
fore during periods of crisis. Thus crises, and the management of those same crises, are points of flux during
which the internal contradictions of capitalism are relocated or bypassed (Harvey 1982 [2006]; Jessop, 2006;
Harvey, 2014; Streeck, 2014).
26
44
INTS402H
220086769
Crises are essential to the reproduction of capitalism. It is in the
course of crises that the instabilities of capitalism are confronted,
reshaped and re-engineered to create a new version of what capitalism
is about (Harvey, 2014: ix).
This tenet of the theoretical perspective of Marxist analysis is now taken as our starting point.
Although Marxist analysis often speaks of ‘capitalism’ in general, rather than particular
formations of capitalism – such as neoliberalism – the theoretical lens of Marxism is an
invaluable one when considering questions of crisis and temporal variation.
Take the idea of capitalism (and thus neoliberalism) as crisis-prone. There is also a
significant tension between both neoliberal ideas and practices, and democracy (MacEwan,
1999). Neoliberal ideologues were – and are – wary of the dangers of government for the
people, by the people. As such, Hayek grappled with the philosophical possibility that his
normative program could be totalitarian and liberal: ‘it is possible … that a democratic
government may be totalitarian and that an authoritarian government may act on [neo]liberal
principles’ (Hayek, 1978: 161). This awareness of the fundamentally unpopular nature of
neoliberal reforms has even been conceeded by the Australian Treasurer, Joe Hockey: ‘it is
not popular to take entitlements away from millions of voters in countries with frequent
elections…ultimately the fiscal impact of popular programs must be brought to account no
matter… how popular a spending program may be’ (Hockey, 2012, online). Although
cloaked in the rhetoric of fiscal responsibility, this quotation must be read as essentially antidemocratic: for ‘no matter how popular’, we might as well say ‘with no concern for
democratic values’. Neoliberal reforms are, in practice, fundamentally undemocratic; even as
the material interests gaining through the process are obscured through ideological devices,
the nature of the reform makes them politically unpalatable.
45
INTS402H
220086769
When this anti-democratic nature is taken together with a tendency toward more-andmore frequent crises, we reach an understanding of the role crisis plays in promoting
neoliberalisation:
Particularly during periods of crisis, inherited frameworks of capitalist
territorial organization may be destabilised as capital seeks to
transcend sociospatial infrastructures and systems of class relations
that no longer provide a secure basis for sustained accumulation
(Brenner and Theodore, 2002: 355-356).
Or, put in plainer terms:
[T]he idea of exploiting crisis and disaster has been the modus
operandi of Milton Friedman’s movement from the very beginning –
this fundamentalist form of capitalism [neoliberalism] has always
needed disasters to advance (Klein, 2007: 11).
These then are the mechanisms through which neoliberal governments enact a fundamentally
un-democratic program. Crisis is inherent in such a contradictory system as capitalism, and
those crises will tend to increase in frequency and intensity. It should be noted, however, that
crises need not be simply financial or economic in nature – natural disasters, military
conflicts, or even fictitious emergencies have all been prevalent in the history of neoliberal
development. Periods of crisis are simply exploited to push contentious reform through while
people are in ‘shock’ – hence Naomi Klein’s term ‘the shock doctrine’ (2007).
Temporal Outcomes
Crucially, this contradictory ‘crisis-driven forward momentum’ (Peck, Theodore and Brenner,
2012a: 25) is the process that creates temporal variation in ‘actually existing neoliberalism’.
This can be considered through a ‘micro’ lens – individual, localised crises, and the direct
institutional restructuring achieved during the management of that crisis – but for our
46
INTS402H
220086769
purposes here we will consider the ‘macro’ crises – those crises that were global (or at least
regional) in their scope, which prompted similarly-large institutional responses.
The first of these pivotal points in the temporal development of neoliberalism was late
in the 1970’s, as neoliberalism shifted from abstract intellectualism to political practice, with
the election of Margaret Thatcher in the UK, and Ronald Reagan in the US. These separate
stages in the chronological development of neoliberalism have been labelled ‘proto-’ and
‘roll-back’ neoliberalism: from neoliberalism as an intellectual program, restoring the
centrality of ‘free-market discourses’ to the discipline of economics, to actual policies of
‘deregulation’ and marketization, aimed at breaking up the Keynesian consensus. Importantly,
The backdrop to this shift was provided by the macroeconomic crisis
conditions of the 1970s, the blame for which was unambiguously laid
at the door of Keynesian financial regulation, unions, corporatist
planning, state ownership, and ‘overregulated’ labour markets (Peck
and Tickell, 2002: 388).
Thus this temporal variation in what the term ‘neoliberal’ implies – from ideas to extant
practice – took place in the context of macroeconomic crisis.
A second significant shift occurred in the early 1990s, when social democratic forces
started to push back against the ‘economic consequences and pronounced social externalities’
(Peck and Tickell, 2002: 388) of Thatcher and Reagan’s ‘first-wave’ of neoliberalism.
However this socialised crisis did not result in a challenge to the increasing dominance of
neoliberalism. Rather more ‘humanised’ forms of neoliberal restructuring replaced their
harsher predecessors, in the form of Clinton and Blair’s ‘Third-Way’ governance (Galbraith,
2008: 112; Steger and Roy, 2010: 50-51). This shift should not be interpreted as a departure
from neoliberal goals or strategies. By labelling themselves as a ‘middle-of-the-road’
compromise between old-style Keynesianism and the new Right that was Thatcher and
Reagan, these ‘second wave’ neoliberals incorporated many nominally left progressives into
47
INTS402H
220086769
their movement. A crisis of legitimacy was exploited to co-opt those in opposition to
neoliberalism into neoliberalism.
Many would argue that in the post-global financial crisis context we are going through
another of these ‘macro’ temporal changes to what constitutes ‘neoliberalism’. ‘Austerity’ has
been the orthodox response to the GFC, and yet far from representing a departure from
neoliberal forms of restructuring, the austerity movement – and the institutional restructuring
that has accompanied it – has seen these logics further entrenched (Blyth, 2013):
neoliberalism has been used as a form of crisis management, whereby the power and scope of
neoliberal institutions and class relations have been entrenched and extended (Cahill, 2014:
141).
Certainly, there has been significant ideational and policy change over the past forty
years of ‘neoliberalism’. What is meant by ‘contemporary neoliberalism’ (or, perhaps
‘austerity neoliberalism’) is different from the neoliberalism of Thatcher and Reagan – this is
what is meant by the idea of ‘temporal variation’. As mentioned earlier, some critics see the
difference between individual governments – all labelled as neoliberal – and see that
difference as a reason to doubt the validity of the term in analysing political economies
(Norton, 2001; Berg, 2009). When one understands the fundamental role played by crisis in
the development of this political program, however, varied instances in different temporal
contexts cannot be analytically separated. Ideas and institutional restructurings will certainly
change as the ongoing, open-ended process rolls on. It is the purpose that defines
neoliberalism as a ‘political project’, as it has been defined by David Harvey. Indeed, Harvey
places this dynamic at the core of his definition of neoliberalism:
48
INTS402H
220086769
Crisis creation, management, and manipulation on the world stage has
evolved into the fine art of deliberative redistribution of wealth from
poor countries to the rich… One of the prime functions of state
interventions… is to control crises and devaluations in ways that
permit accumulation by dispossession to occur without sparking a
general collapse or popular revolt (Harvey, 2005: 163).
And so, with this working understanding of the way crisis creates and allows temporal
variation within the ongoing neoliberal project, we can turn to consider how this trend is
illustrated within the contemporary Australian experience.
Temporal Variation in Australia
The Australian case study illustrates both of these dynamics – the exploitation of crisis to
entrench neoliberalisation, and the temporal variation that results from an ongoing, openended program. First, consider the way crisis is used to create the conditions for unpopular
‘reform’. There are several points of flux over the course of Australian neoliberal hegemony
which conform to this method of development, but the example that will be the focus here is
that of the current government, and the ‘budget emergency’ to which their social service cuts
are supposedly a reaction.
The Abbott government’s 2014 budget contained proposals to make many radical cuts
to social expenditure, including: imposing a six month waiting-period for those needing to
receive welfare payments, which has since been questioned on the grounds of basic human
rights (Woodley and Henderson, 2014, online); increasing the age at which one can receive
the age pension to 70; reducing spending on foreign aid by $7.9 billion over five years,
criticised by many aid groups and commentators (Barlow, 2014); introducing a $7 copayment to healthcare services, seen as the first step to undermining the universality of
Australia’s public healthcare system (Bundley, 2014: 58); and reducing the size of the public
sector by 16 500 jobs. By the government’s own modelling, these cuts will result in a $36
49
INTS402H
billion dollar ‘saving’ for the government27
220086769
(Hockey, 2014, online). These budgetary
measures have already been considered in the context of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ in
the first chapter. Here the focus will be on the way crisis has played a significant role in the
justification of these cuts.
As detailed by Klein (2007), the history of neoliberal advance has been marked by the
exploitation of crisis to bring about undemocratic reform. This dynamic can be seen at work
in the context of the Abbott government’s 2014 budget – the case for this budget has been
made on the grounds that Australia faces a ‘budget emergency’. At the conclusion of
Hockey’s budget speech in May, 2014, the justification was that ‘unless we fix the Budget
together, we will leave the next generation a legacy of debt, not opportunity’ (Hockey, 2014,
online). Claims of a budget emergency have been widely rebuked, with one of the most
damning responses being a statement co-signed by 63 leading Australian economists. The
Economists’ Statement on Commonwealth Budgetary and Economic Priorities insists
‘Australia does not face any present or imminent debt crisis… current debt in Australia is
equivalent to 13.8 percent of GDP – less than one-fifth the average debt burden carried by
other industrial economies’ (The Australia Institute (TAI), 2014b, online). They conclude
with a warning against cuts like those seen in the 2014 budget: ‘past policies of austerity in
other countries have had large negative effects on growth and employment. Australia should
not make the same mistake’ (TAI, 2014b, online).
‘Austerity’ is certainly an accurate way to describe Hockey’s budget, though cuts have
not yet been as deep as in Europe. Most importantly, the budget is framed by the rhetoric of
crisis – this is absolutely necessary, as it is quite realistic to assume that such a budget would
be dismissed immediately in a stable, prosperous context. And yet, as detailed earlier, despite
27
The impact of this figure on the overall deficit has already been eroded by write-downs of government
expenditure.
50
INTS402H
220086769
the rhetoric of emergency and cuts, the budget can best be described as ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ in that spending is not significantly reduced:
The budget attempts to introduce to Australia a ‘politics of austerity’
that has become familiar in debt-laden European nations. It has all the
hallmarks of a neoliberal agenda, blending rhetoric about the need to
reverse irresponsible public spending with policies that shift the
burden of adjustment onto vulnerable sections of society while
seeking to increase opportunities for capital accumulation by the
wealthy (Stilwell, 2014, online).
Globally, this shift to ‘austerity politics’ has occurred in the post-global financial crisis
context. As Stilwell suggests, a more resonant interpretation of Australian austerity is to see it
as an attempt to transplant a model of regulatory, institutional and class-relationship
restructuring pioneered in the European context. This perspective allows a clearer perception
of how this process interacts with the concept of ‘temporal variation’ in the neoliberal project.
Indeed, the return of ‘austerity’ politics – which would seem more at home in a Great
Depression context – might be interpreted as the next macro-shift in neoliberalism:
'[The global financial crisis] has been ideologically reworked... a
reworking that has focused on the unwieldy and expensive welfare
state and public sector, rather than high risk strategies of banks, as the
root cause of the crisis. This... is the result of intensive ideological
work... the triumph being a new neo-liberal settlement' (Clarke &
Newman, 2012: 300).
Returning to consider the Australian example, temporal variation can be seen when the
austerity politics of Tony Abbott and Joe Hockey is contrasted with the ‘populist’
neoliberalism of John Howard’s government (Wilson and Turnbull, 2001), or even the ‘Third
Way’ neoliberalism of the Hawke-Keating governments (Spies-Butcher, 2012). A static
definition of neoliberalism would not be able to span these disparate governments, of both the
Liberal and Labor persuasions. That is why any useful definition must emphasise the openended, amorphous and contradictory nature ‘neoliberalism’.
51
INTS402H
220086769
Conclusion
In this chapter the focus has been variegation within neoliberalism in spatial and temporal
terms. The most fundamental assertion here is that any analysis of neoliberalism – whatever
its focus – must reject singular, monolithic or universal conceptualisations. A static or
universal conceptualisation cannot explain the variegated phenomenon that is neoliberalism,
and as such is vulnerable to criticisms such as that of Norton (2001). Such spurious defences
and deflections should not be suffered.
‘Actually existing neoliberalism’, as established by Brenner and Theodore (2002), and
Peck and Tickell (2002), is one such conceptualisation that is aware of difference. Building on
the framework provided by these researchers, difference was considered here in spatial and
temporal terms. Spatially, neoliberalism is shaped by its ‘embedded’ nature – that is to say
through co-existence and compromise, each localised instance of neoliberalisation is shaped
by the social, political, and economic institutions relevant to that context. From this
perspective, it is possible to conceptually group global iterations of neoliberalism that might
otherwise be seen as distinct: for example, the social democratic tradition in Australia has
meant that the form of its neoliberal political economy is one with greater social service
provision than in the United States; despite this, both can be characterised as neoliberal.
Temporal variation is driven by the interaction of capitalism’s inherently unstable
nature, and the undemocratic nature of neoliberal ideas and practices. This dynamic process
of crisis-driven (and crisis-legitimated) neoliberal reform has defined the history of
neoliberalism (Klein, 2007; Harvey, 2005). This process then results in temporal variation:
from ‘first-wave’ neoliberalism, to the ‘Third-Way’ humanisation, through to today’s
‘austerity neoliberalism’. Although these shifts have seen dramatic differences in the size and
shape of neoliberal restructurings – as with spatial variegation – it is important that these
52
INTS402H
220086769
different periods all be defined together as ‘neoliberal’. Both the dynamic of the exploitation
of (in this case, imagined) crisis and in the resulting temporal variation, the Australian case
study again illustrated this theoretical conceptualisation.
The first chapter of this thesis characterised the current Australian government as an
example of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’; that position has been supported and developed
through the course of this second chapter. However two questions raised in the first chapter
still stand un-answered: if neoliberalism is defined by disjuncture and contradiction between
ideas and practices, across space and time, why does this disjuncture exist? And how has
neoliberal hegemony succeeded, despite these defining contradictions between rhetoric and
reality, in both prescribed method and promised outcome? These are the political questions
raised by the first and second chapters. A partial answer has been tentatively suggested for the
first of those questions: disjuncture exists to ideologically legitimise a political project which
benefits a select minority. How that legitimation is achieved is more difficult to answer. The
third and final chapter of this thesis will consider the political implications of ‘actually
existing neoliberalism’, and flowing from that, the normative necessities for progressive
practice.
53
INTS402H
220086769
Chapter Three
Neoliberalism as power: The political implications of ‘actually
existing neoliberalism’
Introduction
The aim of the neoliberal project is to re-establish the pre-World War Two conditions of
capital accumulation which were eroded by the social democratic consensus of the ‘long
boom’ period. Throughout this theoretical discussion, empirical evidence has been provided,
with a particular emphasis on the current Australian government; although distinct from other
political economic geographies, the ‘actually existing’ conceptualisation of neoliberalism
would seem to characterise quite accurately the Abbott government. This third chapter will
take the discussion one step further, (briefly) considering the political implications of this
analysis, and posing some key open-ended questions – the answers to which remain elusive.
When considering neoliberalism in terms of ‘power’, however, Gramsci’s concept of
hegemony will provide a useful starting point.
These questions a working definition of ‘power’ – with that sketched, the second task
will be to sketch the interests at work, and what exactly is gained through neoliberal
dominance. Finally, and most importantly, we will consider how neoliberal hegemony is
created – ideologically, avoiding criticism through temporal change, and finally in the
permeation of common sense.
Above all else, the practices associated with neoliberalism must be seen as the
exercise of power – one group achieving its own interests over the interests of others, with a
direct distributive outcome. Neoliberal theory is essentially a set of ideas which provide
54
INTS402H
220086769
ideological cover for these material interests. That these ideas are widely criticised, despite
their disjuncture from actual policy, is telling of how successful neoliberal ideology is. That
this disjuncture is compounded by heterogeneous instances of spatial and temporal variation
underlines the disingenuous nature of this inherently political project. Only when
neoliberalism is understood in these terms will political change be possible.
Politics and Power
The central concern of politics – the discipline and the practice – is contested. One of the most
well-known definitions of ‘politics’, however, is in the title of Harold Laswell’s book,
Politics: Who Gets What, When, How (1936). In answering the question ‘how’, the concept of
‘power’ must be considered.28 ‘Power’ is the ability to achieve one’s interests above the
interests of other individuals or groups – or, in other words, ‘politics is about power, the
ability to achieve a desired outcome, through whatever means’ (Heywood, 2005: 60). ‘Power’
is the ‘how’ of politics. As argued earlier, the distributive outcome of ‘actually existing
neoliberalism’ is that a very small group of individuals and corporations benefit, whilst the
vast majority are worse off. Understanding ‘how’ the consent of these masses is captured
without threat of violence or coercion is the political question implied by this analysis.
When the ‘how’ of power is considered in the case of neoliberalism, there is no
immediate answer. But an attempt to understand the ways in which neoliberalism exerts
power is absolutely necessary:
28
It is questions such as these that set politics and political economy apart from (neoclassical) economics. As
typified in Robbin’s ‘scarcity definition’ (Robbins, 1932: 15), economics largely describes distribution, whereas
political economy is more concerned with analysing why and how certain structures of distribution prevail.
Indeed, a criticism of Piketty (2014) is that his analysis fails to follow through with political implications
(Kunkel, 2014).
55
INTS402H
220086769
‘[There is an] extraordinary diffusion across the globe of neo-liberal
ideas and assumptions. If this constitutes a mega-instance of
‘hegemony’, an adequate understanding of its impact would seem to
require… an appropriate way of thinking about power’ (Lukes, 2004:
10).
This quotation from Lukes is from an ongoing debate about what does and does not constitute
power – the ‘three faces’ of power. Between Dahl (1957), Bachrach and Baratz (1962; 1970),
and Lukes himself, different conceptions of ‘power’ have been put forward, ranging from
shallow to radical. Bypassing that debate somewhat, the point being made by Lukes is that a
‘radical’ view of power goes further than simply observing political decision-making to
incorporate power through shaping the very values which people bring to a discussion: ‘is it
not the supreme exercise of power to get another or others to have the desires you want them
to have – that is, to secure their compliance by controlling their thoughts and desires’ (Lukes,
2004: 27)?
Lukes was influenced in this conception by the work of Antonio Gramsci, and his
concept of ‘hegemony’: ‘when one social class exerts power over others, beyond that
accounted for by coercion or law… power dependant on the permeation by bourgeois values
of all organs of society’ (Jones, 2009, online). The hegemonic class (or project) relies on
creating consent through shaping the values of society itself:
The ideological superstructure – politics, education, culture, religion –
shaped the framework of perception, understanding, and knowledge.
The result of this socialization process was that the governed actively
consented to their oppression. Class domination was preserved by the
veneer of social harmony – bourgeois relations were internalized and
consequently the possibility of revolutionary activity receded
(Lievesley, 2009, online).
These are just some explanations of politics and power from a very broad literature dealing
with these questions – a comprehensive analysis is beyond the scope of this thesis. But with
this brief sketch of ‘power’ and ‘hegemony’ provided, we can go on to consider that
neoliberalism achieves its dominance through more subtle and insidious means;
‘manipulation’ rather than ‘force’ or ‘authority’ (Allison, 2009, online).
56
INTS402H
220086769
There are two reasons why ‘hegemony’ and Lukes’ ‘third face of power’ have been
emphasised here. First, neoliberal theory has become so widely accepted so that it functions
as ideological cover, obscuring the material interests which gain through the dominance of
these ideas: ‘[there is a] global acceptance of neoliberalism… that such policies29 seem
‘natural’ and ‘common-sense’ is an indication of the hegemonic power of neoliberalism’
(Hobden and Jones, 2011: 139). But the second is found in a deeper reading of Gramsci
himself.
The criticism of broad definitions of power is that they become more and more
difficult to verify through empirical means; it has proved difficult to clarify ‘what such beliefs
mean or what would constitute proof or disproof of them’ (Allison, 2009, online). But
Gramsci provides a useful test for identifying genuine consensus, or hegemonic exploitation.
Evidence of a ‘dis-juncture’ between rhetoric and reality, for Gramsci, is evidence of
hegemonic forces in action: ‘… thought and action, i.e. the coexistence of two conceptions of
the world, one affirmed in words and the other displayed in effective action (Gramsci, 1971:
326). This is why ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ must be understood as the exercise of
power, and why the disjuncture between neoliberal theory and practice must be seen as a
deliberate political action. The divergence between the two goes far beyond that which can be
explained by the inevitable difference between a philosophy and its practice. When the central
theoretical tenet of the ideology is directly contradicted in practice, we must look more
critically at the purpose of this divergence. Through a Gramscian lens, the only possible way
to interpret neoliberal disjuncture is the deliberate masking of material outcomes to secure
legitimisation.
This is a mainstream ‘free market’ understanding of neoliberalism, which doesn’t differentiate between theory
and practice.
29
57
INTS402H
220086769
Cui bono?
Neoliberalism, encapsulating both theory and practice, is a political project to facilitate capital
accumulation by the capitalist class. The disjuncture between theory and practice can be
understood through the lens of ideology and hegemony. Neoliberal theory is the set of ideas
which dominates the public discourse, legitimising neoliberal practice, despite the fact that
practice is distinctly different from theory. All of this is in service of specific material
interests. But what is the material outcome of neoliberal hegemony? Several examples have
been provided during the course of this thesis, but here we will return to consider the
empirical case for the contention that power is at work.
For evidence of the increasingly inequitably distribution of income and wealth in the
developed world – and, of course, Australia – refer to the Figures in the Appendix. First are
two graphs from the work of the now-famous Thomas Piketty (Figures 1.1 and 1.2), which are
particularly useful in illustrating an historical perspective on now-growing inequalities.
Following Piketty are his colleagues, Saez and Zucman (Figure 1.3), who provide more detail
on the composition of US inequality30. This trend of growing inequality over the neoliberal
period is then seen in the Australian context, as evidenced by the work of several researchers:
Stillwell and Jordan (Figures 1.4 and 1.5); Grieg, Lewins and White (Figures 1.6 and 1.7);
and finally Fletcher and Guttmann (Figures 1.8 and 1.9). Detailed discussion of these Figures
will not be included here – the purpose of these graphs is simply to illustrate the assertion that
capital accumulation was undermined by the World Wars, and the Long Boom that followed,
and that the neoliberal period has seen these conditions re-established.
30
By illustrating that growing inequality has largely been driven by the top 0.1 (and even 0.001) percentiles,
Saez and Zucman show why more traditional measures of inequality, such as the GINI coefficient, are diluted in
neoliberal wealth distribution. By averaging the wealth of the top 20 percent, the GINI coefficient diminishes
the wealth of the rich, by including what are largely ‘middle class’ individuals. While this does not render GINI
useless, it should be understood in this way.
58
INTS402H
220086769
These graphs (Appendix) are just some indicators of what the material impact of
neoliberalism is. Most importantly, they suggest an answer to the question ‘who benefits’. In
addition conceptions of neoliberalism relying on particular policies (or lack thereof),
identification of neoliberal political economies must also rest on the material outcome of the
policies. While it is true that the US financial sector was subject to new regulations in the
wake of the global financial crisis, the altered situation should not be seen as a departure from
neoliberal logics, because neoliberalism is a project. If that project is still succeeding – and
the distribution of post-GFC gains shows that it is – then it is inaccurate to suggest that those
policy changes represent a departure from neoliberalism. As has been emphasised many times
throughout this thesis, the crucial question to ask when identifying neoliberalism is ‘cui
bono’.
In Australia, the top 1 percent of individuals own more than the poorest 60 per cent
(Oxfam, 2014a: 1). As is illustrated by Figures 1 and 3 in particular, this inequality has
increased over the neoliberal period.31 This comparative graph also works to illustrate the
earlier spatial variegation thesis – Australia is nominally more egalitarian than many other
neoliberal political economies. And yet, the same trajectory is being traced. Further, the
debate around the necessity for inequality to promote growth cannot be properly considered
here, but many economists now recognise that while some inequality is needed, too much
becomes a drag on growth, due to the consequent drop in demand (Stiglitz, 2013). But this is
a peripheral issue to the key consideration here, which is simply to illustrate that there is a
clear distributive outcome associated with neoliberal hegemony, and that that outcome is
counter to the interests of the majority.
31
The author is aware that this comparison is between total wealth and income share. Wealth follows a parallel
trajectory to income, as is illustrated by The World Top Incomes Database
(http://topincomes.parisschoolofeconomics.eu/).
59
INTS402H
220086769
The Mechanisms of Hegemony
Neoliberalism, in its disjuncture, variation, and material outcome is quite clearly an example
of power and hegemony. ‘Why’ would neoliberalism present contradictory characteristics of
disjuncture between theory and practice, as well as spatial and temporal variation? Quite
simply, because there is a great deal to be gained, as the previous section illustrates. Here we
will go deeper into ‘how’ this feat is achieved. Neoliberal disjuncture is not only illustrative
of the deliberately hegemonic nature of the project, but it is itself a mechanism which allows
its continuation. We have spoken briefly of legitimisation, but this should be developed
further.
At the very introduction of this thesis we considered some ‘mainstream’
understandings of neoliberalism. A key example of this conceptualisation was in the words of
Kevin Rudd:
… neo-liberalism – that particular brand of free-market
fundamentalism, extreme capitalism and excessive greed which
became the economic orthodoxy of our time (Rudd, 2009: 1).
The issue here is that too much critical ‘left’ discourse engages with neoliberal theory. This
allows easy deflection by proponents of the neoliberal movement to point to actually existing
policy as a way of avoiding criticism. While critics engage with the way neoliberalism is
projected, they cease to engage with the actually existing. Criticisms will continue to be
ineffectual while they engage with an illusion. The political implications of this discoursecapture are explained by James Galbraith:
For while the right wing in power has abandoned the deeper
philosophical foundations of its cause [theoretical neoliberalism],
liberals [the left] remain largely mesmerized by those foundations…
Until they break the spell, they will not be able to think or talk about
the world in terms that relate effectively to its actual condition. Nor
will they be able to advance a policy program that might actually work
(Galbraith, 2008: 11-12).
60
INTS402H
220086769
A similar message is presented concisely by Dean Baker: ‘Unless the debate is reframed in a
way that more closely corresponds to reality, [neoliberals] will continue to be successful in
their agenda of using government intervention to distribute income upward’ (Baker, 2009: 4).
Compounding this inability to reframe the debate in terms that reflect material
realities, temporal variation through crisis also works to further embed neoliberalism and
defuse effective criticism. Neoliberalism ‘changes its stripes’ through temporal variation. This
allows current neoliberals to join in the chorus disparaging its earlier iterations, whilst
identifying itself as ‘something else’. Tony Blair differentiated himself from earlier
neoliberalisms, labelling his politics as a ‘Third Way’, while still forwarding a central
neoliberal goal of the state creating markets and entrenching the conditions for capital
accumulation. Or, speaking more generally,
Real-world experiments with neoliberalization routinely – indeed,
predictably – fail. But they typically fail in such a way as to engender
new rounds of experimentation, generally oriented toward the same
market-disciplinary agendas that underpinned earlier forms of policy
reform – and associated policy failure(s) (Peck, Theodore and
Brenner, 2012a: 19).
It is in this way that we can understand the paradox of neoliberalism both causing the GFC,
and then also being applied as the primary logic of crisis management after the GFC.
Conclusion
The purpose of this final chapter has been to consider neoliberalism in political terms. It is
important to understand neoliberalism beyond simply reconceptualising it in ‘actually existing
terms’. This conceptualisation is enhanced when considered through a Gramscian lens; not
only does this help to explain neoliberal disjuncture, but hegemony is a powerful way to
61
INTS402H
220086769
understand the role of neoliberal ideas, and their durability. This opens up ground for further
research, which is far outside the scope of this thesis. While comprehensive answers cannot
be provided in this brief discussion, that limitation has not been allowed to exclude these
considerations from this analysis completely. Simply by considering a potential starting point
in the search for these answers, the implications of the first two chapters are better
understood.
While much is contested and uncertain – especially the idea of ‘power’, which has
been the centre of ongoing debate since the time of the classical political thinkers – it can be
said that neoliberalism is fundamentally an example of power, as it is a project that enables
specific groups to benefit over others in distributive terms. Hegemony also provides a useful
perspective, in the sense that neoliberal ideology can be seen as legitimising ‘actually
existing’ neoliberal policy. And in the cases where neoliberalism is challenged, disjuncture
and temporal change provide mechanisms through which neoliberal hegemony is maintained.
Until critics start to engage with what neoliberalism does, rather than what it says, or what it
says it does, there will be no possibility of progressive change.
62
INTS402H
220086769
Conclusion
The mainstream conception of ‘neoliberalism’ sees it as being about ‘free markets’ and ‘small
states’. This simplistic understanding led to many premature proclamations of its demise in
the wake of the Global Financial Crisis:
Neoliberalism has self-destructed. The thirty year long global march
of free market ideology has come to an end (Birch and Mykhnenko,
2010: 255).
The fall of Wall Street is to neo-liberalism what the fall of the Berlin
Wall was to communism (Grusenbauer, 2008, online).
More perceptive thinkers have instead labelled the crisis ‘the strange non-death of
neoliberalism’ (Crouch, 2010; Dunn, 2012). This ‘strange non-death’ is not the first such
death-defying act in the history of neoliberalism, but simply the first crisis which drew the
attention of the developed world. The crisis-driven forward momentum of neoliberalisation
has been felt most keenly in the developing world for more than three decades: first through
debt, then through structural adjustment, then again through contagion in financial markets.
The GFC simply brought neoliberalism into question more broadly. This is the context into
which this thesis falls: the growing body of literature which grapples with the incredible
durability of the neoliberal project in the face of crisis. This thesis does not provide an answer
to that paradox. But any answer to that question rests on an appropriate understanding of what
neoliberalism actually is.
The task of this thesis has been to conduct a critical overview of several different
conceptualisations of ‘neoliberalism’. This was considered both theoretically, and within the
scope of an Australian case study. One finding of this investigation is that there is a distinct
63
INTS402H
220086769
disjuncture between neoliberal ideas and the reality of neoliberal practice. Neoliberal practice
does not follow the blueprint laid out by neoliberal theory; rather it is better understood as
‘actually existing neoliberalism’. ‘Actually existing neoliberalism’ is defined by active state
involvement in the creation and re-creation of market-like structures in some areas, and active
suppression of market discipline in others, all working to re-create the conditions for capital
accumulation, and even effecting upward redistribution of wealth through the mechanism of
corporate welfare.
Understanding neoliberalism has been made more difficult by spatial and temporal
variegation, and an analytical tendency to rely on static, universal definitions. The tendency
has been to theorise singular, universal and monolithic definitions of neoliberalism. These
definitions have been subject to much criticism. An appropriately nuanced understanding of
neoliberalism is conscious of both the spatial and temporal variations apparent between
different political economic geographies. Spatial variegation is driven by the ‘embedded’
nature of neoliberalism; that is to say, neoliberalism in practice exists in a unique context of
institutions, societies, cultures, ideas and philosophies. Neoliberalism co-exists with
contradictory currents of thought and practice, creating spatially variegated iterations.
Similarly, temporal variation is driven by embeddeness interacting with the dynamic of crisisdriven neoliberalisation. In periods of crisis (often of its own making), neoliberalism is
remade into a new variation. It is this crisis-driven process of reform that allows neoliberalism
to bypass the often-undemocratic nature of its policies.
Each of these facets of the conceptualisation of ‘actually existing neoliberalism’ is
evident in the contemporary Australian political economy. It is this basis in empirical reality
that makes this conceptualisation so important in the ongoing debate surrounding the term. In
its free-market rhetoric, active state creation of markets, and upward redistribution through
64
INTS402H
220086769
corporate welfare, the Abbott government can quite accurately be described as ‘neoliberal’, if
neoliberalism is understood as ‘actually existing’. The way in which ‘free market
neoliberalism’ fails to describe accurately both current and past Australian governments
shows the analytical weakness of that particular conceptualisation.
This leads us to the third and final chapter of this thesis. Others have labelled Abbott
as a neoliberal, but too often they have done so implying the ‘free-market’ definition of the
term. Two examples of this come from Wayne Swan and Waleed Aly:
The Hockey budget betrays an ideological drive toward US-style
small government (Swan, 2014).
The Abbott government has a plan to have no plan and it’s really
committed to it. That’s the point of neoliberalism. It sees the world as
a market and solves every problem through it (Aly, 2014).
These two indicative examples speak to a much broader problem; neoliberal hegemony
through ideological legitimisation and control of discourse. Neoliberal ideas now permeate
society to the point they are accepted as ‘common sense’ (Hall and Oshea, 2013). As such
they not only legitimise neoliberalism for many people whose interests are actively
diminished by its hegemony; these ideas also shape the debate surrounding neoliberalism –
even its opponents criticise neoliberalism on (and with) its own terms. The political
implication of this ‘thought capture’ is that the debate becomes focused on something that, in
practice, does not exist. Meanwhile the interests of the few are being preferenced over the
interests of the many. It is for this reason that the overarching understanding of neoliberalism
adopted here is that of David Harvey – neoliberalism is best seen as a political project, which
seeks to re-establish the pre-World War conditions of capital accumulation. Or put more
simply, it re-establishes the briefly-eroded power of capital itself.
65
INTS402H
220086769
Appendix
Figure 1: The top 0.1% income share in Anglo-Saxon countries, 1910-2010
SOURCE: Piketty, 2014: 319, ‘Figure 9.5’.
Figure 2: Wealth inequality: Europe and the U.S., 1810 – 2010
SOURCE: Piketty, 2014: 349, ‘Figure 10.6’.
66
INTS402H
220086769
Figure 3: Top 0.1% wealth share in the United States, 1913-2012, and Top wealth
shares: decomposing the top 1%
SOURCE: Saez and Zucman, 2014: 49, ‘Figure 1’.
67
INTS402H
Figure 4: Wages share of total income in Australia, 1960-1 to 2005-6
SOURCE: Stilwell and Jordan, 2007: 22, ‘Figure 2.1’.
Figure 5: Profits share of total income in Australia, 1960-1 to 2005-6
SOURCE: Stilwell and Jordan, 2007: 22, ‘Figure 2.2’.
68
220086769
INTS402H
Figure 6: Distribution of wealth in Australia
SOURCE: Greig, Lewins and White, 2003: 97, ‘Table 5.1’.
Figure 7: Distribution of income in Australia
SOURCE: Greig, Lewins and White, 2003: 97, ‘Table 5.2’.
69
220086769
INTS402H
220086769
Figure 8: Income share of top 1, 0.5 and 0.1 per cent in Australia from 1921-2010
SOURCE: Fletcher and Guttmann, 2013: 46, ‘Chart 8’.
70
INTS402H
Figure 9: GINI coefficient of OECD nations, 1995 and 2010
SOURCE: Fletcher and Guttmann, 2013: 46, ‘Chart 9’ and ‘Chart 10’.
71
220086769
INTS402H
220086769
References
Abbott, T. 2014, ‘Address to the World Economic Forum, Davos, Switzerland’, 23 January,
available at < https://www.pm.gov.au/media/2014-01-23/address-world-economic-forumdavos-switzerland-0>.
Australian Broadcasting Corporation, 2014, ‘Foreign aid cuts make up one fifth of budget
savings’, 22 May, available at < http://www.abc.net.au/news/2014-05-20/tim-costellcorrect-on-budget-foreign-aid-cuts/5452698>.
Allard, T. and Martin, P. 2014, ‘Budget cuts hit lowest-income earners hardest, says
Treasury’,
3
August,
Sydney
Morning
Herald,
available
at
<http://www.smh.com.au/federal-politics/political-news/budget-cuts-hit-lowestincomeearners-hardest-says-treasury-20140803-zzwhz.html>.
Allison, L. 2009, 'power', in I. McLean & A. McMillan (eds), The Concise Oxford Dictionary
of Politics (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press: Oxford.
Aly, W. 2014, ‘Tony Abbott’s plan is no have no plan at all’, 7 March, Sydney Morning
Herald, available at: <http://www.smh.com.au/comment/tony-abbotts-plan-is-to-have-noplan-at-all-20140306-349xa.html>.
Anderson, G. and Heir, K. 2007, Encyclopedia of Activism and Social Justice, SAGE
Publications Inc.: Washington DC.
Argy, F. 2006, Equality of Opportunity in Australia: Myth and Reality, The Australia
Institute, Discussion Paper No. 85.
Argyrous , G. and Stilwell, F. (eds), Readings in Political Economy: Economics as a Social
Science (3rd ed.), Tilde University Press: Prahan, VIC.
Austin, A. 2014, ‘Abbott’s Davos disaster’, 25 January, Independent Australia, available at:
<http://www.independentaustralia.net/politics/politics-display/abbotts-davosdisaster,6098>.
Baker, D. 2009, The Conservative Nanny State: How the Wealthy Use the Government to Stay
Rich and Get Richer, Center for Economic and Policy Research: Washington, DC.
Bachrach, P. & Baratz, M. 1962, 'Two Faces of Power', The American Political Science
Review, vol. 56, no. 4, 947-952.
Bachrach, P. & Baratz, M. 1970, Power & Poverty: Theory and Practice, Oxford University
Press: London.
Barlow, K. 2014, ‘Budget 2014: Aid groups vent anger over cuts to foreign aid spending’, 14
May, ABC News, available at: <http://www.abc.net.au/news/2014-05-14/budget-2014-aidgroups-vent-anger-over-cuts-to-foreign-aid/5451264>.
Baylis, Smith S. and Owens, P. 2011, The Globalisation of World Politics (5th ed.), Oxford
University Press: Oxford
72
INTS402H
220086769
Bell, S. 1997, Ungoverning the Economy, Oxford University Press: Melbourne.
Berg, C. 2009, ‘Keeping Up with Kevin: Kevin Rudd’s Testosterone Technocracy’, The
Institute of Public Affairs Review, vol. 61, no. 1, pp. 8-13.
Birch, K. and Mykhnenko, V. 2010, The Rise and Fall of Neoliberalism: The Collapse of an
Economic Order (eds), Zed Books: London.
Blackburn, S. 2008, ‘historical materialism’, The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (2nd rev.
ed.), Oxford University Press: Oxford.
Block, F. 2003, ‘Karl Polanyi and the writing of The Great Transformation’, Theory and
Society, vol. 32, no. 2, pp. 275-306.
Block, F. and Somers, M. 2014, The Power of Market Fundamentalism: Karl Polanyi’s
Critique, Harvard University Press: Harvard.
Blyth, M. 2002, Great Transformations: Economic Ideas and Institutional Change in the
Twentieth Century, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.
Blyth, M. 2013, Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea, Oxford University Press:
Oxford.
Bowen, C. 2009, ‘Neo-liberalism is dead as people realise markets need regulation’, The
Sydney Morning Herald, 6 May 2009, available at: < http://www.smh.com.au/federalpolitics/neoliberalism-is-dead-as-people-realise-markets-need-regulation-20090505atwi.html> .
Braithwaite, J. 2005, Neoliberalism or Regulator Capitalism, Occasional Paper 5, Regulatory
Institutions Network, Australian National University: Canberra.
Braithwaite, J. 2008, Regulatory Capitalism: How it works, ideas for making it work better,
Edward Elgar Publishing: Cheltenham, UK.
Brenner, N. and Theodore, N. 2002, ‘Cities and Geographies of “Actually Existing
Neoliberalism”, Antipode, vol. 34, no. 3, pp. 349-379.
Bundey, F. 2014, ‘Putting the $7 Co-payment in context: Australia’s increasingly
financialised system of healthcare’, Journal of Australian Political Economy, Issue 73, pp.
58-75.
Cahill, D. 2007, ‘The Contours of Neoliberal Hegemony in Australia’, Rethinking Marxism,
vol. 19, no. 2, pp. 221-233.
Cahill, D. 2010, ‘Actually Existing Neoliberalism’ and the Global Economic Crisis’, in
Labour and Industry, vol. 20, no. 3, pp. 298-316.
Cahill, D. 2012, ‘The embedded neoliberal economy’, in D. Cahill, L. Edwards, and F.
Stilwell (eds), Neoliberalism: Beyond the Free Market, Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK,
pp. 110-130.
Cahill, D., Edwards, L. and Stilwell, F. 2012, Neoliberalism: Beyond the Free Market,
Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK.
73
INTS402H
220086769
Cahill, D. 2014, The End of Laissez-Faire? On the Durability of Embedded Neoliberalism,
Edward Elgar Publishing: Cheltenham, UK.
Calhoun, C. 2002, ‘neoliberalism’, in C. Calhoun (ed.), Dictionary of the Social Sciences,
Oxford University Press: Oxford.
Calhoun, C. 2002, Dictionary of the Social Sciences, Oxford University Press: Oxford.
Castree, N. and Gregory, D. 2006, David Harvey: a Critical Reader, Blackwell Press: Oxford
Chang, H-J. 2003, Globalisation, Economic Development and the Role of the State, Zed
Books: London.
Chang, H-J. 2010, 23 Things They Don’t Tell You About Capitalism, Penguin Books: London.
Chomsky, N. 1999, Profit Over People: Neoliberalism and Global Order, Seven Stories
Press: New York.
Clarke, J. and Newman, J. 2012, ‘The alchemy of austerity’, Critical Social Policy, vol. 32,
no. 3, pp. 299-319.
Costello, P. 2009, The Costello Memoirs (2nd ed.), Melbourne University Press: Melbourne.
Crick, B. 1954, 'The Science of Politics in the United States', The Canadian Journal of
Economics and Political Science, vol. 20, no. 3, pp. 308-320.
Crompton, P., Swann, M., Hopkins, S. and McEachern, W., 2006, Macroeconomics: A
Contemporary Introduction (3rd ed.), Thompson Learning: Southbank, VIC.
Crouch, C. 2011, The Strange Non-Death of Neoliberalism, Polity Press: Cambridge, UK.
Dahl, R. 1957, 'The Concept of Power', Behavioural Science, vol. 2, no. 3, pp. 201-215.
de Shalit, A. 2009, 'Political philosophy and empirical political science: from foes to friends?',
European Political Science, vol. 8, pp. 37-46.
Dunn, B. 2012, ‘The strange non-death of neoliberalism: the case of the missing corpse’, in D.
Cahill, L. Edwards, and F. Stilwell (eds), Neoliberalism: Beyond the Free Market, Edward
Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, pp. 231-250.
Drache, D. 2008, Defiant Publics: The Unprecedented Reach of the Global Citizen, Polity
Press: Cambridge.
Edwards, L., Cahill, D. and Stilwell, F. 2012, ‘Introduction: understanding neoliberalism
beyond the free market’, in D. Cahill, L. Edwards, and F. Stilwell (eds), Neoliberalism:
Beyond the Free Market, Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, pp. 1-14.
Etherington, B. 2014, ‘Anemic Academics Surrender to Marketisation’, 20 August, The
Australian <http://www.theaustralian.com.au/higher-education/opinion/anemic-academicssurrender-to-marketisation/story-e6frgcko-1227029640095>.
Fama, E. 1965, ‘Random Walks in Stock Market Prices’, Financial Analysts Journal, vol 51.
No. 1, pp. 75-80.
74
INTS402H
220086769
Farnsworth, K. 2013, ‘Bringing Corporate Welfare In’, Journal of Social Policy, vol. 42, no.
1, pp. 1-22.
Fenna, A. and Tapper, A. 2012, ‘The Australian Welfare State and the Neoliberalism Thesis’,
Australian Journal of Political Science, vol. 47, no. 2, pp. 155-172.
Fletcher, M. and Guttmann, B. 2013, ‘Income Inequality in Australia’, Economic Round-up,
no. 2, pp. 35-54.
Friedman, M. 1962, Capitalism and Freedom, University of Chicago Press: Chicago.
Friedman, M. and Friedman, R. 1980, Free to Choose, Penguin: Harmondsworth.
Friedman, M. and Friedman, R. 2012 [1982], ‘The Power of the Market’, in G. Argyrous and
F. Stilwell (eds), Readings in Political Economy: Economics as a Social Science (3rd
edition), Tilde University Press: Prahan, VIC.
Galbraith, J. 2008, The Predator State: How Conservatives Abandoned the Free Market and
Why Liberals Should Too, Free Press: New York.
Garnaut, R. 2009, The Great Crash of 2008, Melbourne University Press: Melbourne.
Gemici, K. 2008, ‘Karl Polanyi and the antimonies of embeddedness’, Socio-Economic
Review, vol. 57, no. 11, pp. 1-17.
Gramsci, A. 1971, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, International Publishers: New York.
Grant, R. 2002, 'Political Theory, Political Science, and Politics', Political Theory, vol 30. no,
4, pp. 577-585.
Greig, A., Lewins, F. and White, F. 2003, Inequality in Australia, Cambridge University
Press: Cambridge.
Gusenbauer, A. 2008, ‘La Strada on Wall Street’, Project Syndicate, 6 October, available at:
<http://www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/la-strada-on-wall-street>.
Haggard, S. and Kaufman, R. 1992, The Politics of Economic Adjustment: International
Constraints, Distributive Conflicts and the State, Princeton University Press: Princeton.
Hall, S. and Oshea, A. 2013, ‘Common-sense neoliberalism’, Soundings: A Journal of politics
and culture, Issue 55, pp. 8-24.
Hall, S., Massey, D. and Rustin, M. 2013, ‘After neoliberalism: analysing the present’,
Soundings: A Journal of politics and culture, Issue 53, pp. 8-22.
Hart-Landsberg, M. 2006, ‘Neoliberalism: Myths and Reality’, in Monthly Review, vol. 57
no.11, pp. 1-17.
Harvey, D. 2005, A Brief History of Neoliberalism, Oxford University Press: Oxford.
Harvey, D. 2006 [1982], The Limits to Capital (2nd edition), Verso: London.
Harvey, D. 2014, Seventeen Contradictions and the End of Capitalism, Profile Books:
London.
75
INTS402H
220086769
Hayek, F. 1973, Law, Legislation and Liberty, Volume 1: Rules and Order, University of
Chicago Press: Chicago.
Hayek, F. 1978, New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas,
Routledge & Kegan Paul: London.
Heywood, A. 2007, Political Ideologies: An Introduction (4th ed.), Palgrave Macmillan: New
York.
Hobden, S. and Jones, R. 2011, 'Marxist theories of international relations', in J. Baylis, S.
Smith, and P. Owens (eds), The Globalisation of World Politics, Oxford University Press:
Oxford, pp. 132 – 146.
Hockey, J. 2012, ‘The End of the Age of Entitlement’, Address to the Institute of Economic
Affairs, London, 17 April, available at: <http://www.joehockey.com/mediafiles/speeches/ContentPieces/100/download.pdf>.
Hockey, J. 2014, ‘Budget Speech 2014-15’, Address to the Australian Parliament on the
Second Reading of the Appropriation Bill (No.1), 13 May, available at:
<http://www.budget.gov.au/2014-15/content/speech/html/speech.htm>.
Howard, J. 1997, ‘Remembrance Day 1997’, Address at the Memorial, 11 November,
available at: <https://www.awm.gov.au/events/talks/anzac-1997/>.
Jabour, B. 2014, ‘Does Tony Abbott always make the same speech?’, The Guardian, 24
January,
available
at:
<http://www.theguardian.com/world/australia-newsblog/2014/jan/24/tony-abbott-davos-speech-wordle>.
Jessop, B. 2002, ‘Liberalism, Neoliberalism, and Urban Governance: A State-Theoretical
Perspective’, Antipode, vol. 34, no. 3, pp. 452-72.
Jessop, B. 2006, ‘Spatial Fixes, Temporal Fixes, and Spatio-Temporal Fixes’, in N. Castree
and D. Gregory (eds), David Harvey: a Critical Reader, Blackwell Press: Oxford, pp. 146166.
Jones, C. 2009, 'hegemony', in I. McLean & A. McMillan (eds), The Concise Oxford
Dictionary of Politics (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press: Oxford.
Keen, S. 2001, Debunking Economics: The Naked Emperor Dethroned? (2nd edition), Zed
Books: London.
King, G. 2014, 'Restructuring the Social Sciences: Reflections from Harvard's Institute for
Quantitative Social Science', Political Science, vol. 47, no. 1, pp. 165-172.
Klein, N. 2007, The Shock Doctrine: The Rise of Disaster Capitalism, Picador: New York.
Konings, M. 2012, ‘Neoliberalism and the state’, in D. Cahill, L. Edwards, and F. Stilwell
(eds), Neoliberalism: Beyond the Free Market, Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, pp. 54-68.
Krugman, P. 2013, End This Depression Now!, W.W. Norton & Company: New York.
Kunkel, B. 2009 ‘On Your Marx’, n+1 Magazine, Issue 8, available
<https://nplusonemag.com/issue-8/the-intellectual-situation/on-your-marx/>.
76
at:
INTS402H
220086769
Kunkel, B. 2014, ‘Paupers and Richlings: Review of Capital in the 21st Century by Thomas
Piketty’, London Review of Books, vol. 36, no. 13.
Large, M. 2014, ‘The neoliberalism myth disempowers us’, The Guardian, 14 August 2014,
available at: <http://www.theguardian.com/business/2014/aug/13/neoliberalism-mythdisempowers-us>.
Laswell, H. 1936, Politics: Who Gets What, When, How, McGraw-Hill Book Company.
Lievesley, G. 2009, ‘Gramsci, Antonio (1891-1937), in I. McLean & A. McMillan (eds), The
Concise Oxford Dictionary of Politics (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press: Oxford
Lukes, S. 2004, Power: A Radical View (2nd ed.), Palgrave Macmillan: New York.
MacEwan, A. 1999, Neo-liberalism or Democracy? Economic Stratergy, Markets, and
Alternatives for the 21st Century, Pluto Press: Sydney.
Maddison, S. and Martin, G. 2010, ‘Introduction to ‘Surviving Neoliberalism: The Persistence
of Australian Social Movements’, Social Movement Studies: Journal of Social, Cultural
and Political Protest, vol. 9, no. 2, pp. 101-120.
Mankiw, N. 2014, Principles of Economics (7th ed.), Cengage Learning: Stanford.
Mansillo, L. 2014, ‘Six ways to fix Australia’s finances without cuts’, The Guardian, 9 May,
available at: <http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/may/09/six-ways-to-fixaustralias-finances-without-cuts>.
Marshall, A. 1920 [1890], Principles of Economics: An introductory volume (8th edition),
Macmillan and Co.: London.
McCarthy, T. 2013, ‘The Obamacare debate: the good, the bad – and the political’, The
Guardian, 24 October, available at:
<http://www.theguardian.com/world/2013/oct/23/obamacare-debate-the-good-the-bad-andthe-political>.
McLean, I. & McMillan, A. 2009, The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Politics (3rd ed.),
Oxford University Press: Oxford
Mirowski, P. 2013, Never Let A Serious Crisis Go To Waste: How Neoliberalism Survived
The Financial Meltdown, Verso: London.
Mirowski, P. and Plehwe, D. 2009, The Road From Mont Pelerin: The Making of the
Neoliberal Thought Collective, Harvard University Press: Harvard.
Monbiot, G. 2013, ‘Neo-liberals’ economic policy just a get-rich-quicker fraud’, The Sydney
Morning Herald, 21 January 2013, available at: < http://www.smh.com.au/federalpolitics/political-opinion/neoliberals-economic-policy-just-a-getrichquicker-fraud20130120-2d13e.html>.
Monbiot, G. 2014, ‘Sick of this market-driven world? You should be’, The Guardian, 6
August 2014, available at:
<http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/aug/05/neoliberalism-mental-healthrich-poverty-economy>.
77
INTS402H
220086769
Nader, R. 2011, Cutting Corporate Welfare, Seven Stories Press, New York.
Norton, A. 2001, ‘Naming the Right: from the New Right to Economic Rationalism to
Neoliberalism’, Quadrant Magazine, vol. 45, no. 12, pp.62-65.
Nozick, R. 1977, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Basic Books: New York.
Overbeek, H. and van Apeldoorn, B. 2012, Neoliberalism in Crisis, Palgrave Macmillan
Publishers: Basingstoke
Oxfam, 2014a, Still The Lucky Country? The Growing Gap between Rich and Poor is a
Gaping Hole in the G20 Agenda, available at: <https://www.oxfam.org.au/wpcontent/uploads/2014/06/2014-66-g20-report_fa_web-2.pdf>.
Oxfam, 2014b, Working for the Few: Political capture and economic inequality, 178 Oxfam
Briefing Paper, available at: <http://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/bpworking-for-few-political-capture-economic-inequality-200114-summ-en.pdf>.
Peck, J. and Tickell, A. 2002, ‘Neoliberalizing Space’, Antipode, vol. 34, no. 3, pp. 380-404.
Peck, J., Theodore, N. and Brenner, N. 2012a, ‘Neoliberalism, interrupted’, in D. Cahill, L.
Edwards, and F. Stilwell (eds), Neoliberalism: Beyond the Free Market, Edward Elgar:
Cheltenham, UK, pp. 15-30.
Peck, J. Theodore, N. and Brenner, N. 2012b, ‘Neoliberalism Resurgent? Market Rule after
the Great Recession’, The South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 111, no. 2, pp. 265-288.
Phillips, B. 2014, ‘NATSEM independent modelling of 2014-15 Federal Budget’, National
Centre for Social and Economic Modelling, available at: < http://apo.org.au/node/39892>.
Piketty, T. 2014, Capital in the Twenty-First Century, TJ International: Padstow.
Porfilo, B. 2007, ‘Neoliberalism’, in G. Anderson and K. Heir (eds), Encyclopedia of Activism
and Social Justice, SAGE Publications Inc.: Washington DC.
Polanyi, K. 2001, The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our
Time (2nd edition), Beacon Press: Boston.
Quiggin, J. 1996, Great Expectations: Microeconomic Reform and Australia, Allen and
Ulwin: St. Leonards, NSW.
Quiggin, J. 2010, Zombie Economics: How Dead Ideas Still Walk Among Us, Princeton
University Press: Princeton.
Robbins, L. 1932, An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, Macmillan
and Co.: London.
Rudd, K. 2009, ‘The Global Financial Crisis’, The Monthly, February, no. 42, pp. 20-29.
Saez, E. and Zucman, G. 2014, Wealth Inequality in the United States since 1913: Evidence
from Capitalized Income Tax Data, NBER Working Paper, available at:
<http://eml.berkeley.edu/~saez/saez-zucmanNBER14wealth.pdf>.
Smith, A. 2010 [1776], The Wealth of Nations, Random House Publishing: New York.
78
INTS402H
220086769
Spies-Butcher, B. 2012, ‘Markets with equity? Lessons from Australia’s Third Way response
to neoliberalism’, in D. Cahill, L. Edwards, and F. Stilwell (eds), Neoliberalism: Beyond
the Free Market, Edward Elgar: Cheltenham, UK, pp. 204-230.
Steger, M. and Roy, R. 2010, Neoliberalism: A Very Short Introduction, Oxford University
Press: Oxford.
Stiglitz, J. 2013, The Price of Inequality, Penguin Publishing: London.
Stilwell, F. 2012, Political Economy: The Contest of Economic Ideas (3rd edition), Oxford
University Press: Oxford.
Stilwell, F. 2014, ‘The Australian Federal Budget: 63 economists say the foundation is
unsound’, Progress in Political Economy, 9 October, available at:
<http://ppesydney.net/economists-statement-on-commonwealth-budgetary-and-economicpriorities>.
Stilwell, F. and Jordan, K. 2007, Who Gets What? Analysing Economic Inequality in
Australia, Cambridge University Press: Cambridge.
Streeck, W. 2014, ‘How Will Capitalism End’, New Left Review, vol. 87, no. 2, pp. 35-64.
Stretton, H. 1969, The Political Sciences: General principles of selection in social science
and history, Routledge & Kegan Paul: London.
Stretton, H. 1993, ‘Whodunnit to social democracy’, Overland, vol. 132, pp. 50-64.
Summers, L. 1998, ‘Treasury Deputy Lawrence H. Summers Testimony Before the Senate
Committee on Agriculture, Nutrition, and Forestry on the CFTC Concept Release’, Press
Release, available at:
<http://www.treasury.gov/press-center/pressreleases/Pages/rr2616.aspx>.
Swan, W. 2014, ‘The ideology driving the Abbott government’s first budget’, The Saturday
Paper, 17 May, available at:
<http://www.thesaturdaypaper.com.au/topic/politics/2014/05/17/the-ideology-driving-theabbott-governments-first-budget/1400248800#.VE7pnfmUd8E>.
Sydney Morning Herald, 2014, ‘Federal budget 2014: Winners and losers’, The Sydney
Morning Herald, 13 May, available at: <http://www.smh.com.au/business/federalbudget/federal-budget-2014-winners-and-losers-20140513-38802.html>.
Taylor, K. 2009, ‘utopianism’, in I. McLean and A. McMillan (eds), The Concise Oxford
Dictionary of Politics (3rd ed.), Oxford University Press, Oxford.
The Australia Institute, 2014a, ‘Stop Helping Joe’, The Australia Institute Infrographic,
available at: <http://www.tai.org.au/content/stop-helping-joe>.
The Australia Institute, 2014b, ‘Economists’ Statement on Commonwealth Budgetary and
Economic Priorities’, The Australia Institute, available at:
<http://www.tai.org.au/content/economists%E2%80%99-statement-commonwealthbudgetary-and-economic-priorities>.
Trans-National Institute, 2014, State of Power 2014: Report, The Tran-National Institute,
available at: < http://www.tni.org/briefing/state-power-2014>.
79
INTS402H
220086769
van Apeldoorn, B. 2009, ‘The contradictions of “embedded neoliberalism” and Europe’s
multi-level legitimacy crisis: the European Project and its limits’, in B. van Apeldoorn, J.
Drahokoupil and L. Horn (eds), Contradictions and limits of Neoliberal European
Governance: From Lisbon to Lisbon, Palgrave Macmillan: New York, pp. 21-43.
van Apeldoorn, B., Drahokoupil J. and Horn, L. 2009, Contradictions and limits of Neoliberal
European Governance: From Lisbon to Lisbon, Palgrave Macmillan: New York
van Apeldoorn, B. and Overbeek, H. 2012, ‘Introduction: The Life Course of the Neoliberal
Project and the Global Crisis’, in H. Overbeek and B. van Apeldoorn (eds), Neoliberalism
in Crisis, Palgrave Macmillan Publishers: Basingstoke.
van Dyke, L. 2003, ‘Milking the System: How corporate welfare fleeces the taxpayer,
destroys the environment and corrupts public policy’, Overland, vol. 110, pp. 110-116.
Zafarullah, H. & Huque, A. 2012, Managing Development in a Globalized World: Concepts,
Processes, Institutions, CRC Press, Taylor & Francis Group: New York.
Wilson, S. and Turnbull, N. 2001, ‘Wedge politics and welfare reform in Australia’,
Australian Journal of Politics and History, vol. 47, no. 3, pp. 384-402.
Woodley, N. and Henderson, A. 2014, ‘Backbencher backs calls for dole waiting period after
report argues proposal will breach human rights’, ABC News, 30 September, available at:
<http://www.abc.net.au/news/2014-09-30/dole-wait-will-breach-human-rights-bipartisanreport-finds/5777882>.
80