J Agric Environ Ethics (2012) 25:909–925
DOI 10.1007/s10806-011-9351-1
ARTICLES
Bioenergy and Land Use: Framing the Ethical Debate
C. Gamborg • K. Millar • O. Shortall • P. Sandøe
Accepted: 21 September 2011 / Published online: 8 October 2011
Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011
Abstract Increasingly, ethical concerns are being raised regarding bioenergy
production. However, the ethical issues often do not stand out very clearly. The aim
of the present paper is to improve on this situation by analyzing the bioenergy
discussion from the perspective of land use. From this perspective, bioenergy
production may give rise to ethical problems because it competes with other forms
of land use. This may generate ethical problems mainly for two reasons. First,
bioenergy production may compete, directly or indirectly, with food production; and
as consequence the food security of poor people may be adversely affected (social
aspects arguments). Secondly, the production of bioenergy may directly or indirectly lead to deforestation and other changes of land use that have a negative effect
on greenhouse gas emissions (environmental arguments). So from this perspective
the main challenge raised by bioenergy production is to secure responsible land use.
The purpose of the paper is not to advocate, or promote, a specific ethical position
on bioenergy, but to structure the main arguments found. The paper falls in two
parts. One part addresses social aspects arguments for using agricultural land for
bioenergy—where food insecurity, malnourishment, and significant food poverty
are the main concerns. The second part scopes environmental implications—notably
greenhouse gas emissions impact, as affected by deforestation and other (indirect)
land-use changes. Alongside showing some of the current dilemmas presented by
wider land-use changes, arguments are analyzed from two ethical angels: a consequentialist and a deontological.
C. Gamborg (&) P. Sandøe
Danish Centre for Bioethics and Risk Assessment, University of Copenhagen, Rolighedsvej 25,
1958 Frederiksberg C, Denmark
e-mail: chg@life.ku.dk
K. Millar O. Shortall
Centre for Applied Bioethics, University of Nottingham, Sutton Bonington Campus Loughborough,
Nottingham, UK
123
910
C. Gamborg et al.
Keywords Biofuels Bioenergy Consequentialist Deontological
Environment Ethics Food security
Introduction
On the 13 April 2011 BBC News ran a story with the headline ‘‘Biofuels targets are
‘‘unethical,’’ says Nuffield report.’’ This report raises two key questions: In what
sense are the targets ‘‘unethical’’? Why would biofuels, in particular, be criticized as
unethical?1 To address these questions we need to examine the way in which
bioenergy is conceptualized and ask how the wider social and scientific debate is
currently framed.
It is valuable to firstly start by examining the emergence of this energy source
and the associated technologies. Early technical and political discussion of
biofuels—and more broadly bioenergy—focused on solutions to some of the key
energy challenges facing many developed countries, i.e., on ways to improve the
security of energy supply in an environmentally sound way. Thus, bioenergy was
considered as a promising option alongside other renewable energy sources, such as
solar, and wind energy and hydropower.2 The arguments presented for biofuels
highlighted the benefits of reducing dependence on fossil fuels and the countries
producing them; and therefore in this context the development and use of bioenergy,
as originally presented, appeared to have been viewed as an ethical necessity, an
inherently good practice. This can be seen in key policy documents of the time, such
as the 2009 EU Directive on Renewable Energy (hereafter the ‘‘RED Directive’’),3
with its target of 10% of transport fuels to be delivered by biofuels by 2020.
More recently, however, biofuel production has itself become one of the major
issues in an increasingly fierce debate over climate change and global food security.
The debate is somewhat akin to previous discussions of the industrialization of
agriculture (Thompson 2008) and the GMO debate of the late 1990s (Mol 2007),
both of which involved innovations held by some to be the solution to many foodrelated problems and by others as sources of new, intractable ones. Similarly,
biofuels are now being criticized on the grounds that they promote food shortages,
utilize much needed agricultural subsidies, offer little or no greenhouse gas (GHG)
mitigation, and drive deforestation in developing countries (Wenzel 2007).
One approach that may be used to examine the ethical issues raised by bioenergy
is to start by focusing on land use as a pivotal issue. Clearly, a key feature of current
ways of producing bioenergy is the reliance on land. Until the late 20th Century, in
an increasingly globalized world with more trade, land was considered to be less
1
www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-13056862.
2
There is a whole discussion to be had on deciding on which type of renewable is the most feasible and
desirable, taking into account conversion efficiency, availability, potential, cost, and many other factors,
see. e.g., the International Energy Agency (IDEA) http://www.iea.org/subjectqueries/index.asp.
3
DIRECTIVE 2009/28/EC OF THE EUROPEAN PARLIAMENT AND OF THE COUNCIL of 23
April 2009 on the promotion of the use of energy from renewable sources and amending and subsequently
repealing Directives 2001/77/EC and 2003/30/EC. http://eur-lex.europa.eu/LexUriServ/LexUriServ.
do?uri=OJ:L:2009:140:0016:0062:en:PDF.
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
911
and less of a limiting factor on production; it was considered a virtually limitless
resource. However, in recent years it has become apparent that it is a much scarce
resource, and it is now clear that its use in energy production may well compete with
food production, and indeed with so-called ‘‘ecosystem services’’. Hence, the
cultivation of biofuel crops may displace food crops. This could make access to
food problematic for some and distort food markets for others, which is most likely
to affect poor urban and rural communities. This aspect is still much debated and
more work needs to be done (and is being done) to determine how influential
different factors are on food prices. Turning to the environment, it was originally
asserted that, as biofuels displace fossil fuels, the carbon emitted when biofuels are
used would be counterbalanced by the original biomass production. However, in
recent years, a number of studies have shown that a more comprehensive and
detailed environmental assessment is needed: early expectations relied on simplistic
calculations for GHG emissions in which indirect land-use effects of biofuel
production were mainly overlooked.
In order to conduct an assessment of land use and bioenergy, it can be useful to
apply a simple yet workable distinction between social and environmental effects,
with each presenting unique challenges. A further set of issues revolves around the
nature of the ethical framework being applied to determine what may be acceptable
ways of producing these fuels. A key question here, for bioenergy, is whether the
ethical framework to be deployed should be consequentialist or should have
significant deontological elements; as examined below.
This paper firstly sets out the current policy context on bioenergy within the EU.
Then it critically analyses the ethical framing of the debate. The analysis is divided
into two sections, one scoping the social issues raised by bioenergy and the other
focusing on environmental implications. In the analysis consequentialist and
deontological lines of thought are identified and discussed, with these corresponding
to utilitarian and Kantian approaches to the ethics of land use. An analysis of
bioenergy and land use policy adopting Kantian ethics would require consideration
of both the intention behind the policy and the principles that underlie this intention
(O’Neill 2000). This can be difficult to determine even when one is dealing with the
conduct of a single individual; it becomes even more challenging when policies
developed in a complex policy-making process are subjected to scrutiny.4
Within each of the two main sections of the paper, a brief overview of the debate,
as it has evolved, is presented. There follows an analysis of some of the prominent
arguments, in the course of which a range of controversial empirical assumptions
are highlighted. The purpose of this paper is not to advocate, or promote, a specific
ethical position on bioenergy. The aim is to map out the key issues raised by
bioenergy and land use and connect these with a prominent distinction in moral
philosophy, between consequentialist and deontological ethical positions. It is
4
Intention may be a simplistic concept when it comes to the investigation of the origins of a policy.
Palmer (2010) states that there was an ‘‘intricate interplay of variables’’ involved in the development of
the UK’s flagship biofuels policy, the Renewable Transport Fuels Obligation, involving ‘‘not just
scientific evidence and discursive argument but also political interests and institutional factors.’’ The
concept is arguably useful, however, for our purposes, as it allows us to subject the rationale for policies
to ethical analysis.
123
912
C. Gamborg et al.
intended that this will offer a better understanding of the debate and a more refined
appreciation of future policy needs.
Bioenergy and Land-Use Policy
Within the EU bioenergy has been promoted as an essential component of
sustainable energy-use. The Union’s ‘‘Europe 2020’’ strategy requires 20% of total
energy consumption to be based on renewables by the year 2020, a requirement set
out in the RED Directive. To reach this goal, binding national targets have been
imposed on Member States.5 Renewables include solid biomass, wind, solar energy,
and hydropower, as well as biofuels. Specifically, the RED Directive emphasizes
that only biofuels meeting the sustainability requirements of the EU—as evidenced
in Sustainable Biofuel Certificates, which confirm the protection of untouched
nature and sufficient GHG savings—can contribute to this EU policy target.6
Several definitions of the terms ‘‘biofuel’’ and ‘‘bioenergy’’ are currently used. In
this paper bioenergy refers broadly to renewable energy from biological sources
(biomass from wood and agriculture sources) which can be used for heat, electricity,
and transportation fuel, and associated co-products (see FAO 2008a, b). And
although there is noticeable inconsistency in the use of the terminology, biofuel
refers here to liquid fuels produced from the biological sources just mentioned. The
commercially established and most abundant sources of biofuel today are crops such
as soy, palm oil, sugar cane, or corn. These are often referred to as ‘‘firstgeneration’’ biofuels. ‘‘Second-generation’’ biofuels are produced from lignocellulosic biomass derived from non-food or food crop co-products (such as straw);
however, further technological and commercial development is still required in
order to make these viable (Connor and Hernandez 2009).
Bioenergy is unique in being the only form of renewable energy that can at the
same time be used for heating, electricity, and transport. Looking at transport, it is
estimated by the International Energy Agency (IEA 2008) that biofuels should be
able to reduce current fossil-fuel related carbon dioxide emissions from cars by
30–50%. Further reductions can be expected when biofuels are used in sea and air
transport. In Europe, the area cultivated with non-food rapeseed has grown rapidly
over the last decade with increased use of biodiesel. Bioethanol accounts for
approximately 20% of all biofuels within the EU, although it should be noted that
part of this production is also based on biomass imported from countries such as
Brazil.
The main drivers of biofuel production—as reflected in EU biofuel policy aims—
are energy security, a commitment to economic development, and the mitigation of
climate change. More specifically, the RED Directive and the Fuel Quality Directive
(hereafter the ‘‘FQD Directive’’), which were introduced in 2003 and revised in
2009, set out the following policy objectives: security of supply through reduced
5
http://eur-lex.europa.eu/LexUriServ/LexUriServ.do?uri=CELEX:32009L0028:EN:NOT.
6
http://ec.europa.eu/energy/renewables/biofuels/sustainability_criteria_en.htm.
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
913
dependency on crude oil and transport fuels; security of agricultural productivity
and quality of life in rural areas; and a reduction in GHG emissions through the use
of sustainably produced biofuels.
However, it has recently been pointed out that, while global biofuel production
offers opportunities, it also presents something of a food, energy, and the
environment trilemma (Tilman et al. 2009). Certainly, an increasing number of
studies are pointing to the potentially negative effects of land conversion for
biofuels. The role of biofuel production in slowing global warming has also been
questioned, with doubts being expressed about the ability of biofuels to deliver
lower GHG emissions (e.g., Searchinger et al. 2008; Fargione et al. 2008). It has
been claimed that, to the extent that the production of crop-based biofuels involves
deforestation or other types of land degradation, any carbon saving benefits will be
compromised. Hence, the issue of land use for biofuels—and more particularly
changes the production of those fuels necessitates—is becoming increasingly
controversial.
Bioenergy-related land-use change (LUC) can transform the forests and other
types of natural vegetation, and indeed organic soil matter, all of which are, in
effect, carbon stocks. Such change can take the form of deforestation and
conversion to arable land, or the replacement of grassland by arable land. Change
brought about by the annexation of land for crops (in this case, biofuel crops) in
these ways is direct LUC. When it occurs the existing stocks of carbon, embodied in
forest or grassland, are released, which then in turn alters the GHG emission
accounting value. When land that could otherwise be used for food or fodder crops
is used to grow biofuel crops, and the existing agricultural production shifts to new
land, creating a knock-on conversion of forest, grasslands, or other forms of natural
vegetation, indirect LUC takes place—the change being indirect in the sense that it
does not necessarily occur where the biofuel feedstock is produced, though of
course biofuel production is still the driver of the LUC. This can be mediated
through a pricing mechanism, with demand for biofuels impacting on food prices,
which in turn can create additional pressure to convert land. For example, if farmers
in the US switch production from soy to maize crops, soy imports may increase, and
this may in turn lead to ‘‘virgin’’ land being used to produce soy in Brazil. Hence,
indirect LUC and the displacement of food crops may result in higher food prices in
both regions. Of course, those rising prices might well impair food access, increase
food poverty, visit insecurity on rural and urban communities, and distort markets,
as well as affecting GHG emissions and biodiversity (Bouët et al. 2010; Cushion
et al. 2010).
From a policy perspective it is important to determine the wide range of risks
associated with the EU biofuel policy, by which we mean the potentially adverse
results of direct and indirect LUC: increased competition for land, raised food and
feed supply and prices, and environmental costs (Croezen et al. 2010). However, it
is no easy task to determine these risks, and the boundaries of any assessment. Both
the data to be included and the framing of the assessment have been disputed
(Palmer 2010), and no official resolution of this matter (e.g., in terms of how EU
123
914
C. Gamborg et al.
envisages the calculation in its member states) has emerged to date (European
Commission 2010).7 A key area of dispute is whether, and to what extent, indirect
LUC should be included in biofuel assessment. Moreover, there is disagreement
over the way in which the impact of EU biofuel policy depends on the mix of
biofuels (how much is based on conventional food and feed crops and how much is
based on so-called residues, or non-edible crops). Nor have so-called ‘‘flanking
policies’’—i.e., trade policies, such as agreements between EU and non-EU states
on subsidies for fallow land or stimulation of growing feedstocks on marginal or
degraded land—been settled (European Commission 2010).
The connection between direct LUC and biofuel production is often readily traceable.
However, indirect changes are much harder to associate with a specific practice,
particularly as many other factors can come into play. Even where there is general
acknowledgement that a case of LUC is indirectly associated with biofuels, considerable
scientific controversy over how to calculate the associated GHG emissions remains—
and that is so even if we put the complexity associated with the wider impact assessment
to one side (Croezen et al. 2010). The implications of LUC for carbon neutrality have not
been fully considered by the EU; this much is clear from a recent report which discusses
possible policy changes (European Commission 2010).
At a time when the land-use issue is being disputed and policy development is
being discussed, the framing of the debate—in particular, its social aspects (e.g.,
concerns about food prices and food scarcity) and environmental aspects (concerns
about GHG emissions and biodiversity)—will undoubtedly play a notable role in
shaping the EU stance on biofuel. It is therefore important to look at the framing, in
its social and environmental aspects, in more detail.
Bioenergy Ethical Debate
Increasingly, biofuels are being subjected to forms of ethical analysis that focus
directly or indirectly on the land-use issue. A number of commentators have
highlighted important issues here. For example, Thompson (2008) places biofuels in
a broader agricultural ethics perspective; Mudge (2008) asks how we are to assess
whether biofuels are environmentally or ethically sound; Gamborg et al. (2009)
consider the acceptability of the use of food crops for energy; Gomiero et al. (2009)
discuss biofuels in relation to the appropriation of ecosystem services; Landeweerd
et al. (2009) reflect on the distribution of responsibilities; Mol (2010) focuses on the
role of environmental authorities; Sodano (2009) examines the human rights and
gender aspects of biofuels; and the Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2011) examine
whether there is a duty to produce biofuels if this can be done in an environmentally
and socially benign way through sustainability benchmarking.
Building on this literature, this paper will present an analysis of the ethical issues
that focuses on land use and draws a distinction between the social and
7
This point is also evident in the consultation undertaken by the Nuffield Council on Bioethics
(2011:92). In this consultation questions about land use changes, and how or whether to include them in
any assessment, elicited very polarized replies.
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
915
environmental aspects of land use. It should be noted that the term ‘‘aspect’’ instead
of ‘‘impact’’ is used here, as the latter may imply an exclusively consequentialist
approach to the issues, whereas in fact, non-consequentialist arguments will be
examined as well. The social aspects of the discussion are essentially ‘‘people and
community’’ issues: here we examine questions about livelihood and access to food,
about who benefits, who may bear the cost in relation to choice of technology, and
so forth. The principal environmental aspects to be considered are: reduction of
GHG emissions, biodiversity degradation, and loss of natural habitat.
Social Aspects
The arguments to be considered in this section focus on the way biofuel production
may compete with, or displace, food crops, and lead to food scarcity. These
arguments tend to concentrate on the commercial establishment of first-generation
biofuels— i.e., fuels derived from basic feedstock (such as seed or grain) that could
in theory enter the animal or human food chain. It has been alleged that biofuel
production of this sort is unwise, and some have claimed outright that it is morally
unacceptable: ‘‘10 years from now the rapid expansion of biofuel production may
look foolish, or worse—unethical, if it leads to environmental degradation, high
food prices, and increases the number of undernourished people’’ (Cassman and
Liska 2007: 22).
An argument of this kind can be found in the 2007 address made by Jean Zeigler,
the UN Special Rapporteur on the Right to Food (2000-2008): ‘‘It is a crime against
humanity to divert arable land to the production of crops which are then burned for
fuel.’’8 In a similar vein, referring to liquid biofuels, it has been argued that if ‘‘you
start to fuel cars with crops… you are instantly putting the world’s one billion
starving people in competition with the world’s one billion motorists.’’9
Runge and Senauer (2007) conducted a food and fuel balance calculation; they
state that ‘‘filling the 25-gallon tank of an SUV with pure ethanol requires over 450
pounds of corn—which contains enough calories to feed one person for a year.’’
Statements and calculations such as these (cf. Rice 2010) have sparked fierce
debate, and the points made by Zeigler and others have been countered. Matthews
(2008: 99), for example, points to the need for economic development in many
countries, arguing that ‘‘the real crime against humanity is to block Africa’s
potential, by blocking its exports and stunting its growth.’’ In essence it is claimed
that developing countries should be given the economic opportunity to ‘‘grow not
only food but also cash crops, and that the cash crop in greatest demand right now is
biofuels’’ (Matthews 2008: 99). However, according to the FAO (2008), it is exactly
this driver that has contributed to higher food prices, posing an immediate threat to
food security via a dramatic impact on the prices poorer food consumers have to pay
in urban and rural areas. This issue is complex, as exemplified by the studies from
the World Bank (Cushion et al. 2010) and The International Food Policy Research
8
http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/americas/7065061.stm) accessed 20 March 2010.
9
Quoting Ed Matthew, Friends of the Earth. http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/business/7026105.stm) accessed
20 March 2010.
123
916
C. Gamborg et al.
Institute IFPRI (Bouët et al. 2010). Thus there is notable disagreement about the
exact reasons for steep increases in worldwide food prices, such as that seen in the
food price spike between autumn 2007 and summer 2008, where a number of
commentators identified the use of corn for bioethanol (Bach 2009) as a causal, and
perhaps significant, contributory factor.
So in terms of food security, biofuels have been framed both as contributing
directly to worldwide hunger and as a mechanism to alleviate poverty through rural
economic empowerment, thereby reducing hunger.
From a consequentialist perspective, the questions we need to ask about the
relationship between food and fuel production, and whether this is developing in
distinctively new ways, are these: How much land is available? If land is not used to
grow fuels, will it be used to grow food? The main critical argument seems to rely
on assumptions that are all highly controversial: that the most important limiting
factor in efforts to address global malnutrition—which according to the World
Health Organization is the biggest contributor to child deaths, representing one third
of all child deaths (UNICEF et al. 2010)—is the availability of agricultural land;
that abstaining from growing bioenergy crops will ensure land is available for
increased food production; and that this in turn will lead to the alleviation of food
poverty (Pimentel et al. 2009).
The conversion of land to biofuel production within Europe and North America
may, as an indirect LUC, provide markets within which farmers outside Europe can
produce staple crops at better prices on the global market. It has been argued that in
the short term rising food prices threaten the food security of many people in
developing countries. However, over the medium to long-term, if farmers are given
the resources to respond, a reversal of the long-term trend of depressed agricultural
prices could allow them to increase production and revitalize many countries’
agriculture sectors (FAO 2008b). Similarly, the cultivation of biofuels as cash crops
in these countries may lead to increased investment in infrastructure that is needed
to support thriving or emergent agricultural markets (FAO 2008b). This observation
stems from the paradox that land for crop production is both considered a scarce
global resource and often under-utilized. For example, land is left fallow within the
EU because of CAP set-aside policies; outside the EU it is left fallow because it is
not economically viable. In a number of developing countries the quality of the land
or a lack of agricultural investment are significant limiting factors. However, with
greater resources and more investment in infrastructure, soil quality could be
improved, after which yields would increase. The criticism of biofuels illustrated by
the remarks of Zeigler (op cit) also seems to under-estimate the complexity of food
poverty. It is also, in effect, a criticism of most cash crops, not just first-generation
biofuels. A more comprehensive characterization of LUC is therefore needed if this
kind of criticism is to be substantiated.
Moreover, when it comes to second-generation biofuels that are not yet
commercially established the consequences for global food security are by no means
clear-cut. These biofuels may not present a simple and transparent solution to the
complex issues raised by first-generation biofuels. It was once claimed that there
would be no competition between second-generation fuels and food crops (AntizarLadislao and Turrion-Gomez 2008). Again, Doornsbosch and Steenblik (2007: 4)
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
917
have argued that ‘‘second-generation technologies could, in theory, make it possible
to avoid competing land-use claims by growing biomass feedstocks on marginal and
degraded land and using residual biomass materials.’’ However the social
implications of using marginal land (e.g., associated with willow production) or
agricultural co-products (e.g., straw) to produce second-generation biofuels have
been questioned. Franco et al. (2010) observe that individuals and communities
often depend on land categorized (but not by them) as ‘‘marginal.’’ Such land might
be relied upon in various ways: it can be used in subsistence agriculture or as a
source of community fuel (e.g., firewood). Some have also questioned, in principle,
the economic viability of an agricultural commodity that is produced on marginal
land when it is competing against a similar commodity produced on prime land
(Levidow and Paul 2008).
Much food produced on marginal land within the EU cannot compete with food
produced on prime land outside the EU, unless subsidized. The suspicion that the
same competitive advantage will apply to biofuels seems reasonable. It has been
shown that Jatropha planted on marginal land produces uneconomic, marginal yield
(Nuffield Council on Bioethics 2011). This raises important questions about the
production of second-generation biofuels on marginal land in Europe. One is
whether this production system will be unable to compete with cheaper biofuels
produced on prime land outside the EU. Another is: If marginal land is to be used
economically to produce biofuels, will this only be feasible, and acceptable, if a
policy stipulating that only marginal land can be used is in place? Such a policy
would seem unworkable in the current global commodity market. In addition, how
would policy-makers formally define ‘‘marginal’’ land? Would the adoption of a
strict definition affect other important uses of the supposedly ‘‘marginal’’ sites?
It has also been claimed that second-generation biofuels could provide more
energy output per unit of land than their first-generation predecessors, so that the
former involve a more efficient use of land (whether marginal or prime). This
implies that significant social advantages will arise from these biofuels in terms of
the energy security benefits; however, this needs further investigation. The FAO
(2008: 34) states that if second-generation fuel production were to use 25% of
agricultural land it would be able to replace 14% of transport fuels. Discussions of
second-generation biofuels often assume implicitly that such fuels will be able to
overcome the problems faced by first-generation biofuels if they are more energyefficient and ‘‘sustainable.’’ However, the utilization of 25% of currently available
agricultural land appears to be a very high price to pay for 14% of our current
transport fuel needs. Given that biofuel production will undoubtedly incur costs
connected with competition for resources and environmental damage, irrespective
of the technology used, a key question might be: What are the comparative benefits
of biofuel production in terms of economic development and energy security? The
consequences of second-generation biofuels, both positive and negative, need to be
evaluated not only in comparison with first-generation equivalents, but in relation to
other land uses across the board.
From a deontological perspective, the first claim—that biofuels compete with
food crops—could require an assessment of whether biofuels in fact constitute the
123
918
C. Gamborg et al.
most appropriate or right use of land. This requires us to explore further questions:
What is land for? What principles should we apply when seeking to determine the
levels of food energy produced on land and transport energy and electricity?
Estimations of efficiency of this kind are likely to depend on the outcome of a full
Life Cycle Assessment, and this assessment should be complemented by some form
of social impact assessment. Holistic assessment of this sort may reveal that other
forms of bioenergy are more efficient than biofuels, whether first-generation or
second-generation. For example, the cultivation of crops such as Miscanthus or
willow in short rotation coppice for non-liquid fuel production may turn out to be a
good use of the land. Such cultivation can be efficient—at least, as long as the crops
are used effectively in stationary facilities such as combined heat and power plants
(sometimes referred to as ‘‘CHPs’’) rather than used to produce biofuels (see Yuan
et al. 2008). Miscanthus and willow, which are regarded as high-yielding, yet lowinput, perennial crops with low, or zero, fertilizer requirements may deliver a
number of additional environmental benefits (Campbell et al. 2009; Rawlings 2007).
Given this alternative approach, it could be argued that it is ethically problematic to
use land to produce biofuels for transport if we have a global scarcity of viable land,
particularly if the fundamental targeted purpose of biofuel production is to increase
energy supply.
One cannot properly address the question whether biofuels lead to food scarcity
or displacement without considering possible inefficiencies and inequalities of
current food production systems. Livestock production is widely felt to be a very
inefficient way to produce food because it uses grains as animal feed that can be
directly consumed by humans (Steinfield et al. 2006). Hence depending on how we
value land across several land use options—i.e., for meat production, staple food
production, or energy production—it might well be suggested lower levels of animal
production are a better option than reducing, or altogether avoiding, the cultivation
of crops for first-generation biofuel production. In other words, it is important to
place the bioenergy debate in a wider agricultural context. Our reasons for valuing
food energy (and other forms of energy) need to be made explicit if we are to
structure land use priorities around specific values. Indeed it is helpful to
differentiate two kinds of arguments: those supporting the use of land for bioenergy
with the primary intention of providing benefits to communities in developing
countries, on the one hand, and those supporting policies that do not have this
explicit intention, but that point to this as an additional beneficial consequence, on
the other.
The main aim of developing bioenergy could be to provide a greater volume of
safe, reliable energy to communities in developing countries (UNEP 2009).
European biofuels policy could have the beneficial, secondary consequence of
strengthening agricultural sectors in developing countries, as claimed above.
Although raised prices might stimulate supply, significant challenges to equitable
market access may remain for farmers in developing regions wanting to produce
food and/or biofuel crops. Again, bioenergy production needs to be assessed in
terms of market opportunities, specifically to determine whether the farmers
involved will obtain fair returns, or whether, instead, they will face unique
challenges when attempting to access an equitable market.
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
919
A study by German et al. (2011) focusing on biofuel production in six developing
countries found that the potential environmental and rural-development benefits
have largely not materialized. This study can be used to support the idea that the
beneficial outcomes of bioenergy production depend not just on the form of land
use, but also on the policies that affect trade and equitable market access. Hence the
market values implicit within the prevailing economic ‘‘arrangements’’ must be
addressed in tandem with those applied through bioenergy policy. If the stimulation
of agricultural markets is not the intended consequence of bioenergy policy, and if it
is claimed merely that this may come about despite certain obstacles, the skepticism
of some commentators about the likelihood of an equitable market emerging is
understandable. It could therefore be argued, in deontological terms, that bioenergy
policy should not be justified on the basis of this possible, secondary positive
consequence.
These observations serve to highlight the fact that there is a genuine ethical
debate to be had about the relationship between the production of bioenergy and
global food security. In taking a position on this issue, one needs to be aware of a
number of its controversial empirical aspects: principally, the consequences for food
security in the short-term and the long-term, and the land-use effects of different
forms of bioenergy. In addition there are various ways of characterizing the ethical
concerns involved—regarding both the balancing of effects on different communities over time and the nature of the intentions connected with different bioenergy
policies.
Environmental Aspects
We turn now to environmental aspects of biofuels and land use. It is often assumed
that when biofuels are based on co-products (sometimes referred to as ‘‘waste
products’’), or are produced through the cultivation of marginal land, no, or very
few, detrimental land-use practices are involved and negative environmental
impacts are reduced. Thus it is often argued that these forms of bioenergy—whose
prospects have been contemplated for more than 30 years (Pimentel et al. 1981)—
would require minimal resources in terms of water and land, reduce GHG
emissions, and avoid degradation of habitats and biodiversity (Nuffield Council on
Bioethics 2011). Lignocellulosic biofuels, i.e.,. second-generation biofuels that use
indigestible co-products from food or fodder crops or other biomass sources such as
Miscanthus, have been promoted as environment-friendly, and hence ethically
attractive, bioenergy solutions.
This assumption, or set of assumptions, has been challenged, however. Some
observers allege that the production of biomass for second-generation biofuels in
fact presents a number of threats to environmental conservation and biodiversity,
and therefore is not sustainable. Specifically, it is claimed that the use of biomass
from crop and forest residues could disrupt local carbon cycles and the fertility of
agricultural soil; and that applications of artificial fertilizer to compensate for the
disruption may well result in eutrophication and the loss, in effect, of any potential
savings in GHG emissions (Doornsbosch and Steenblik 2008).
123
920
C. Gamborg et al.
Assessments of the benefits of second-generation biofuels must take into account
the impacts of indirect LUC. Yet, as stated above, this aspect of assessment is
controversial (Searchinger et al. 2008). It would be possible in principle,
presumably, to manage the sequelae of indirect LUC by ensuring that imported
biomass is not sourced from converted areas that were previously forest, or naturally
carbon-rich in some other way, or such as to support high levels of biodiversity. If
feedstocks could be sourced from abandoned or underutilized arable land (Croezen
et al. 2010), and if yields could be increased in way which does not require high
levels of fertilizer input (with associated emissions), the EU’s current sustainability
criteria could be met.
Thus although second-generation biofuel production is claimed to deliver greater
savings in GHG emissions than first-generation biofuel production (Delshad et al.
2010), these savings could be absorbed, or lost, in an indirect LUC, if production of
the necessary biomass simply results in the displacement of cropland on to land that
presently acts as a carbon sink, such as forest and pasture (Melillo et al. 2009).
It is no easy matter evaluating the empirical evidence used to determine the
sustainability credentials of second-generation biofuels, and establishing both the
direct and indirect environmental impacts over a longer time horizon is particularly
difficult. The currently dominant Life Cycle Assessment approach to the development of policy instruments like environmental certification and labeling may
adequately address only the vertical dimension of environmental impact: that is, the
direct effects of production of a particular product (UNEP 2009). It has been
claimed that current approaches are less able to cope with the horizontal dimension:
indirect and cumulative environmental impacts such as eutrophication and GHG
emissions from indirect land-use change (UNEP 2009).
From the consequentialist perspective, the two questions introduced earlier
become pertinent once again in connection with environmental aspects: What is
‘‘marginal’’ (or, as it is sometimes stated, ‘‘abandoned’’ land)? What are ‘‘byproducts’’ or ‘‘waste’’ material?
On the first of these questions, even from an agrarian perspective, of course there
is always an alternative use for a piece of land. Moreover, if the land in question is
converted to production, the net carbon sequestering through natural re-growth and
the wider impacts on biodiversity will need to be calculated. And, as has been
pointed out by Bindraban et al. (2009), the exploitation of this land will often
require high inputs of nutrients and water, which in turn has a production cost and
impacts upon GHG savings.
On the second question, though second-generation biofuels use co-products that
are sometimes accurately characterized as surplus to current agricultural need,
rather than referred to as waste, indirect LUC may be problematic if, for example, it
is not included in emissions accounting. According to Howarth and Bringezu (2008:
68) ‘‘indirect land use will be responsible for substantially more carbon loss (up to
twice as much) than direct land use; however, because of predicted increases in
fertilizer use, nitrous oxide emissions will be more important than carbon losses
themselves in terms of warming potential.’’ If this view is substantiated by empirical
evidence, it will be hard to resist the conclusion that second-generation biofuels
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
921
could lead to higher GHG emissions than their fossil fuel counterparts and as such
result in substantially greater carbon loss (up to twice as much) than direct land use.
In addition, the availability of some ‘‘co-products,’’ like straw and other coproducts of crop production, may not be as unlimited as originally hoped. Use of
residual co-produced material such as straw as a feedstock on a large scale may, in
practice, be unfeasible. Assumed to be an ‘‘available resource,’’ such co-products
may turn out to be very limited feedstocks: it is important to acknowledge that straw
is still part of the crop, and that therefore there is a natural limit to how much is
available. The quantity of a co-product like straw available depends on factors such
as crop rotation, field management practice, and climate (Pahkala and Kontturi
2009). More importantly, straw is useful as a farm resource in number of ways—for
example, it is used as bedding for livestock, and it can be used (when dug back) to
improve soil fertility, control erosion, and maintain soil carbon (Gomiero et al.
2009). In short, the casual description of some co-products as ‘‘waste material’’
conceals various ‘‘uses,’’ greater exploration of value is needed.
It can be seen, then, that the specific ‘‘details’’ of production, and the differences
between different kinds of production, affect assessments of bioenergy and land use.
In turn, if we apply a consequentialist approach, this affects the assessment of
acceptability. For example, diverting land currently used to produce the animal feed
used in highly (energy) inefficient meat production systems to first-generation
biofuel production may be a more acceptable and sustainable practice (under the
assumption of a drop in the consumption of the relevant kinds of meat).
From a deontological perspective, a key task in the discussion of the potential
environmental benefits of producing biofuels from co-products, is that of reframing
the (predominantly consequentialist) argument. Questions to be addressed here
include: Are the co-products used to mitigate climate change or for other reasons? Is
land being treated merely as a means or as an end itself?
Clearly, one of the most important goals of biofuel and bioenergy policy is to
mitigate climate change: the intention behind the policies is to limit global warming.
One of the reasons that biofuels have faced such harsh criticism from environmental
NGOs is the view that there is a gross mismatch between intention and reality in this
respect. At first glance, it may seem inappropriate to examine the environmental
dimension of land use in Kantian terms, since at the micro-level the relevant
decisions are made, not so much with the intention of bringing about, or avoiding,
particular environmental outcomes, but rather with market conditions and resource
constraints in mind: that is, people do not intend to release carbon dioxide into the
atmosphere, or to destroy ecosystems, when they cut down a forest to grow palm oil
for biodiesel, but they do so because it is profitable and/or is deemed to support
development. Indirect LUC is also very problematic because it is by definition an
unintended consequence of biofuel production. As in the case of the social
dimensions of biofuels production, this raises questions about the prioritization of
the intention to mitigate climate change by using biofuels and shows that a realistic
appraisal of the work needed to align intention and reality is required.
It is possible to examine the market conditions and resource constraints under
which biofuels are produced and traded within a Kantian framework. One might
conclude that, in the biofuels commodity market, land is viewed as private property,
123
922
C. Gamborg et al.
and that this is tantamount to treating land merely as a means and not as an end in
itself (O’Neill 2000).
Some take a rather different view of land and land use. Jasanoff (2010) states that
greater awareness of current environmental problems is leading to deeper reflection
on questions about who and what has standing in our ethical reasoning. She points
out that India and Ecuador have included ‘‘rights of the environment’’ within their
constitutions. Similarly, it was recently reported that Bolivia has granted nature
equal rights to those of humans in a Law of Mother Earth.10 Does this constitute
treating land as an end, not a means? Certainly, it raises questions about the
interpretation of nature’s ‘‘ends’’: nature is not one homogeneous entity and it
cannot be said to have plans or guiding principles.
The argument under consideration here also raises questions about the way we
deal with situations where people’s rights conflict with notions of the ethical
standing of nature. Debate in environmental ethics has often returned to the
contentious issue of whether the environment should be valued for its own sake or
instrumentally, because of the pleasure or benefits it provides for us (Jamieson
2008). In the case of carbon sequestration, this could be seen as something of a false
dichotomy, as the existence of trees benefits us. It shows that our relationship with
the land is not always a one-way relationship of exploitation: humans actively use
passive land as a resource, and depend on its activities. If the rights of nature are
interpreted as the right to exist without interference from humans, one might be
tempted to discern here a moral and legal imperative to bring to a halt the
deforestation caused by biofuels, though this in turn may cause many problems of
interpretation and conflict-management.
Other win–win outcomes for people and the environment have been predicted for
biofuels: as well as being useful to us, they are ‘‘natural’’ products that sequester
carbon as they grow. However, industrial agricultural methods and land grabbing
have created disillusionment with this claim, as discussed above. This suggests that
when we treat natural resources like land as means to our own ends, as we are
obliged to do in producing biofuels, we must investigate the conditions in which
these means are used. How should we change our model of resource use when we
switch from fossil fuels (regarded by many as essentially a ‘‘free’’ gift from nature)
to biofuels (a costly technology to produce involving many difficult resource tradeoffs)? Would this involve changing the end use of the resource or the nature of the
markets through which it is sold?
Moreover, when we address the question of how to value trade-offs between the
non-environmental benefits of bioenergy production (income and energy) and
environmental benefits from the same piece of land, we need according to the line of
moral thinking in play here to consider the relative prioritization of the intentions
behind bioenergy policy when they conflict, as many maintain they do. We must
ask: What does a given policy implicitly assume to be the most important use of
land?
10
Guardian, 10 April 2011 (http://www.guardian.co.uk/environment/2011/apr/10/bolivia-enshrinesnatural-worlds-rights).
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
923
Conclusions
The biofuel debate has moved beyond discussion of energy security, less reliance on
fossil fuels and the production of more environmentally responsible energy sources.
It is now a much broader debate, and within that debate the central questions are
about what is deemed to be responsible land use.
An important observation is that talk about a debate is misleading, because the
assessment of bioenergy compresses many debates—debates that are highly
complex and challenging to unpack in a structured and accessible way. Secondly,
it is important to understand that these debates are not only about empirical
uncertainties but also involve the clarification and relative weighting of potentially
conflicting values. These values are very much up for discussion.
One of the most important issues in the bioenergy debate turns on questions about
land-use: What direct and indirect consequences are at stake here? What is the right,
or the best, use of land? How should utilization priorities be set? This paper has
explored the conceptualization, or framing, of biofuel production in light of these
questions in order to throw a more nuanced light on the basis of judgments about the
acceptability of bioenergy, and specifically biofuels.
The burden of the paper has been to bring a range of questions to the foreground:
What underlying assumptions or perspectives are being applied (who matters, where)?
What impacts or effects are being considered? Should things other than impacts matter
in judgments of acceptability? How are the risks being framed? What kinds of benefit
are being taken into account? How should different concerns be balanced?
Attempts to analyze this complex ethical issue will rely, more or less implicitly, on a
conceptualization that involves various assumptions. Some of these assumptions will
concern the data to be included in each level of assessment (e.g., social or environmental
assessments), and which aspects are to be emphasized or prioritized. Others, perhaps less
obviously, will be evidence of a broadly consequentialist or deontological ethical
perspective. And of course the various framings will result in actors, including policymakers, potentially taking different positions on the ethical acceptability of bioenergy
and biofuels in terms of the land-use issue. One practical message of the analysis
presented in this paper is, we suggest, that deeper ethical engagement in the debate about
the future role of bioenergy is needed. Such engagement can only complement and
fruitfully extend the current technical and economic approaches.
Acknowledgments We would like to thank two anonymous referees for helpful comments. Special
thanks are also due to Paul Robinson. Financial support through the Subproject ‘‘International and
national governance of bioenergy: trade, environment and integration of energy systems’’ under the
Research Alliance ‘‘Enabling and Governing Transitions to a Low Carbon Society’’ funded by the Danish
Council for Strategic Research (Grant no. 09-067275/DSF) and the UK project LACE and the BBSRC
Sustainable BioEnergy Centre (BSBEC) is gratefully acknowledged.
References
Antizar-Ladislao, B., & Turrion-Gomez, J. L. (2008). Second-generation biofuels and local bioenergy
systems. Biofuels, Bioproducts & Biorefining, 2, 455–469.
123
924
C. Gamborg et al.
Bach, F. B. (2009). Biofuels: Hunger, subsidies and lack of effect on CO2 emission. In M. Gjerris C.
Gamborg J. E. Olesen & J. Wolf (Eds.), Earth on fire (pp. 169–174) Copenhagen: The Institute of Food
and Resource Economics, The Faculty of Life Sciences, University of Copenhagen. Available at:
\http://curis.ku.dk/portal-life/files/14971824/Earth_on_Fire_forbedret.pdf http://curis.ku.dk/portallife/files/14971824/Earth_on_Fire_forbedret.pdf. Accessed 2 March 2011.
Bindraban, P. S., Bulte, E. H., & Conijn, S. G. (2009). Can large-scale biofuels production be sustainable
by 2020? Agricultural Systems, 101, 197–199.
Bouët, A., Dimaranan, B. V., & Valin, H. (2010). Modeling the global trade and environmental impacts
of biofuel policies. IFPRI discussion paper 01018. The International Food Policy Research Institute
(IFPRI). Available at http://www.ifpri.org/publication/modeling-global-trade-and-environmentalimpacts-biofuel-policies. Accessed 7 August 2011.
Campbell, J. E., Lobell, D. B., & Field, C. B. (2009). Greater transportation energy and GHG offsets from
bioelectricity than ethanol. Science, 324, 1055–1057.
Cassman, K. G., & Liska, A. J. (2007). Food and fuel for all: Realistic or foolish? Biofuels, Bioproducts
and Biorefining, 1, 18–23.
Connor, D. J., & Hernandez, C. G. (2009). Crops for biofuels: Current status and prospects for the future.
In R.W. Howarth & S. Bringezu (Eds.), Biofuels: Environmental consequences and interactions with
changing land use (pp. 65–80). Available at http://cip.cornell.edu/biofuels/. Accessed 2 March 2011.
Croezen, H. J., Bergsma, G. C., Otten, M. B. J., & van Valkengoed, M. P. J. (2010). Biofuels: Indirect
land use change and climate impact. Delflt: CE Delft.
Cushion, E., Whiteman, A., & Dieterle, G. (2010). Bioenergy development: Issues and impacts for
poverty and natural resource management. Washington, DC: The International Bank for
Reconstruction and Development/The World Bank. Available at http://www-wds.worldbank.org/.
Accessed 7 August 2011.
Delshad, A. B., Raymond, L., Sawicki, V., & Wegener, D. T. (2010). Public attitudes towards political
and technological options for biofuels. Energy Policy, 38, 3415–3425.
Doornsbosch, R., & Steenblik, R. (2007). Biofuels: Is the cure worse than the disease? OECD Roundtable
on Sustainable Development. Available at http://media.ft.com/cms/fb8b5078-5fdb-11dc-b0fe-0000
779fd2ac.pdf. Accessed 2 March 2011.
European Commission. (2010). Report from the commission on indirect land-use change related to
biofuels and bioliquids. Available at: http://ec.europa/energy/renewables/biofuels/doc/land-usechange/com_2010_811_report.en.pdfhhtp:.
FAO. (2008a). The state of food and agriculture. Biofuels: Prospects risks and opportunities.
Rome: FAO.
FAO. (2008b). Bioenergy, food security and sustainability—towards an international framework. FAO.
Available at: http://www.fao.org/fileadmin/user_upload/foodclimate/HLCdocs/HLC08-inf-3-E.pdf.
Accessed 2 March 2011.
Fargione, J., Hill, J., Tilman, D., Polasky, S., & Hawthorne, S. (2008). Land clearing and the biofuel
carbon debt. Science, 319, 1235–1238.
Franco, J., Levidow, L., Fig, D., Goldfrab, L., Honicke, M., & Mendonca, M. L. (2010). Assumptions in
the European union biofuels policy: Frictions with experiences in Germany, Brazil and
Mozambique. Journal of Peasant Studies, 37(4), 661–698.
Gamborg, C., Madsen, K. H., & Sandøe, P. (2009). Keeping warm in an ethical way is it acceptable to use
food crops as fuel? In K. Millar, P. Hobson-West, & B. Nerlich (Eds.), Ethical futures: Bioscience
and food horizons. Nottingham: Wageningen Academic Publishers.
German, L., Schoneveld, G., Skutch, M., Andriani, R., Obidzinski, K., Pacheco, P., Komarudin, H.,
Andrianto, A., Lima, M., & Dayang Norwana, A. A. B. (2011). The local social and environmental
impacts of biofuel feedstock expansion: A synthesis of case studies from Asia, Africa and Latin
America. [online] available at: http://www.cifor.cgiar.org/publications/pdf_files/infobrief/3295infobrief.pdf. Accessed June 2011.
Gomiero, T., Paoletti, M. G., & Pimentel, D. (2009). Biofuels: Efficiency, ethics, and limits to human
appropriation of ecosystem services. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. doi:
10.1007/s10806-009-9218-x.
Howarth, R. W., & Bringezu, S. (2008). Biofuels: Environmental consequences and interactions with
changing land use. Available at http://cip.cornell.edu/biofuels/. Accessed 2 March 2011.
IEA. (2008). From 1st to 2nd-generation biofuels technologies. http://www.iea.org/papers/2008/2nd_
Biofuel_Gen.pdf Accessed 20 March 2011.
123
Bioenergy and Land Use
925
Jamieson, D. (2008). Ethics and the environment: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Jasanoff, S. (2010). A new climate for society. Theory, Culture and Society, 27(2–3), 233–253.
Landeweerd, L., Osseweijer, P., & Kinderlerer, J. (2009). Distributing responsibility in the debate about
sustainable biofuels. Science Engineering Ethics, 15, 531–543.
Levidow, L., & Paul, H. (2008). Land-use bioenergy and agro-biotechnology. Berlin: WBGU.
Mathews, J. A. (2008). Opinion: Is growing biofuel crops a crime against humanity? Biofuels,
Bioproducts and Biorefining, 2, 97–99.
Melillo, J. M., Reilly, J. M., Kicklighter, D. W., Gurgel, A. C., Cronin, T. C., Paltsev, S., et al. (2009).
Indirect emissions from biofuels: How important? Science, 326, 1397–1399.
Mol, A. P. J. (2007). Boundless biofuels? Between environmental sustainability and vulnerability.
Sociologica Ruralis, 47(4), 297–315.
Mudge, S. M. (2008). Is the use of biofuels environmentally sound or ethical? Journal of Environmental
Monitoring, 10, 701–702.
Nuffield Council on Bioethics. (2011). Biofuels: Ethical issues. London: Nuffield Council on Bioethics.
O’Neill, O. (2000). A simplified account of Kantian ethics. In J. E. White (Ed.), Contemporary Moral
Problems. Belmont CA: Wadsworth.
Pahkala, K., & Kontturi, M. (2009). Potential of straw as bio-energy raw material in northern European
countries. NJF Report, 5(3), 56.
Palmer, J. (2010). Stopping the unstoppable? A discursive-institutionalist analysis of renewable transport
fuel policy. Environment and Planning C: Government and Policy, 28(6), 992–1010.
Pimentel, D., Moran, M. A., Fast, S., Weber, G., Bukantis, R., & Balliett, L. (1981). Biomass energy from
crop and forest residues. Science, 212, 1110–1115.
Pimentel, D., Marklein, A., Toth, M. A., Karpoff, M. N., Paul, G. S., & McCormack, R. (2009). Food
versus biofuels: Environmental and economic costs. Human Ecology, 37, 1–12.
Rawlings, A. (2007). An expanding liquid biofuel market: Investigating the likely impacts on welfare and
environment. Environmental Ethics, 1, 26–37.
Rice, T. (2010). Meals per gallon. The impact of industrial biofuels on people and global hunger.
London: ActionAid UK. Available at http://www.europolitics.info/pdf/gratuit_en/266253-en.pdf.
Accessed 19 March 2011.
Runge, F., Senauer, B. (2007). How biofuels could starve the poor. Foreign Affairs, 41–53.
Searchinger, T., Heimlich, R., Houghton, R. A., Dong, F., Elobeid, A., Fabiosa, J., et al. (2008). Use of
US croplands for biofuels increases greenhouse gases through emissions from land-use change.
Science, 319, 1238–1240.
Sodano, V. (2009). Food security, human rights and gender equality. In K. Millar, P. Hobson-West, & B.
Nerlich (Eds.), Ethical futures: Bioscience and food horizons. Nottingham: Wageningen Academic
Publishers.
Steinfeld, H., Gerber, P., Wassenaar, T., Castel, V., Rosales, M., & de Haan, C. (2006). Livestock’s long
shadow—environmental issues and options. FAO report. http://www.fao.org/docrep/010/
a0701e/a0701e00.HTM. Accessed 7 June 2011.
Thompson, P. A. (2008). The agricultural ethics of biofuels: A first look. Journal of Agricultural and
Environmental Ethics, 21(2), 183–198.
Tilman, T., Socolow, R., Foley, J. A., Hill, J., Larson, E., & Lynd, L. (2009). Beneficial biofuels–the food,
energy, and environment trilemma. Science, 325, 270–271.
UNEP. (2009). Towards sustainable production and use and of resources: Assessing biofuels. [online]
available at: http://www.biomassenergycentre.org.uk/pls/portal/docs/PAGE/RESOURCES/REF_
LIB_RES/PUBLICATIONS/UKBIOMASSSTRATEGY.PDF. Accessed February 2011.
UNICEF, WHO, UNESCO, UNFPA, UNDP, UNAIDS, WFP, The World Bank. (2010). Facts for life.
(4th ed.). New York: United Nations Children’s Fund. Availble at http://www.factsforlifeglobal.org/
resources/factsforlife-en-full.pdf. Accessed 8 August 2011.
Wenzel, H. (2007). Bio-ethanol: Is the world on the wrong track? Analysis of energy issues. In H. Gani &
K. Dam-Johansen (Eds.), ECCE6 Book of Abstracts, 1. Lyngby: Department of Chemical
Engineering, Technical University of Denmark.
Yuan, J. S., Tiller, K. H., Al-Ahmad, H., Stewart, N. R., & Stewart, C. N. (2008). Plants to power:
Bioenergy to fuel the future. Trends in Plant Science, 13(8), 421–429.
123