Progress
and
Poverty
Henry George
Progress
and
Poverty
Why there are recessions
and poverty amid plenty
— and what to do about it!
Edited and abridged
for modern readers by Bob Drake
Robert Schalkenbach Foundation
Henry George
Progress and Poverty
Why there are recessions, and poverty amid plenty
— and what to do about it!
Edited and abridged for modern readers by Bob Drake
Book and cover design by Lindy Davies
ISBN
0-911312-98-6
Library of Congress Control Number: 2006928337
First Edition
Copyright © 2006 by the Robert Schalkenbach Foundation
149 Madison Avenue, Suite 601
New York NY 10016
Contents
Publisher’s Foreword by Cliff Cobb ............................... IX
Editor’s Preface by Bob Drake ....................................... XII
Author’s Preface to the Fourth Edition ....................... XV
Introduction: The Problem of Poverty Amid Progress .... 1
First Part: Wages and Capital
1. Why Traditional Theories of Wages are Wrong ........ 8
2. Defining Terms ........................................................ 17
3. Wages Are Produced By Labor, Not Drawn From
Capital ................................................................... 28
4. Workers Not Supported By Capital......................... 41
5. The True Functions of Capital ................................. 46
Second Part: Population and Subsistence
6. The Theory of Population According to Malthus ... 51
7. Malthus vs. Facts ...................................................... 57
8. Malthus vs. Analogies .............................................. 69
9. Malthusian Theory Disproved ................................. 75
Third Part: The Laws of Distribution
10. Necessary Relation of the Laws of Distribution ...... 83
11. The Law Of Rent .................................................. 89
12. The Cause of Interest ............................................. 95
13. False Interest ........................................................ 102
14. The Law Of Interest ............................................ 106
15. The Law Of Wages .............................................. 111
16. Correlating The Laws of Distribution ................. 120
17. The Problem Explained ....................................... 123
Fourth Part: The Effect of Material Progress
on the Distribution of Wealth
18. Dynamic Forces Not Yet Explored ...................... 126
19. Population Growth and Distribution of Wealth ... 128
20. Technology and the Distribution of Wealth ........ 137
21. Speculation ........................................................... 142
Fifth Part: The Problem Solved
22. The Root Cause of Recessions ............................. 145
23. The Persistence of Poverty
Despite Increasing Wealth .................................. 155
Sixth Part: The Remedy
24. Ineffective Remedies ............................................ 165
25. The True Remedy ................................................ 180
Seventh Part: Justice of the Remedy
26. The Injustice of Private Property In Land ........... 182
27. The Enslavement of Labor .................................. 192
28. Are Landowners Entitled to Compensation? ...... 198
29. History of Land as Private Property .................... 203
30. History of Property in Land in the US ................ 211
Eighth Part: Application of the Remedy
31. Private Property in Land is Inconsistent
with the Best Use of Land ................................... 219
32. Securing Equal Rights To Land .......................... 223
33. The Canons of Taxation ....................................... 226
34. Endorsements And Objections ............................ 236
Ninth Part: Effects of the Remedy
35. The Effect on Production .................................... 242
36. The Effect on The Distribution of Wealth .......... 246
37. The Effect on Individuals and Classes ................. 250
38. Changes in Society............................................... 254
Tenth Part: The Law of Human Progress
39. The Cause of Human Progress ............................ 263
40. Differences in Civilizations .................................. 270
41. The Law of Human Progress ............................... 275
42. How Modern Civilization May Decline ............. 287
43. The Central Truth ................................................ 295
44. Conclusion: The Individual Life .......................... 300
Afterword: Who Was Henry George?
by Agnes George de Mille ...................................... 304
Index .......................................................................... 311
Publisher’s Foreword
IX
Publisher’s Foreword
WE OWE Bob Drake a debt of gratitude for this meticulous condensation and modernization of Henry George’s
great work. The original version had an elegance that
evoked a passion for social justice among millions of readers in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. However, by the beginning of the twenty-first century, George’s
complex prose stood in the way of that intention for large
numbers of people. Now his ideas can once again be widely
accessible.
What were those ideas and why are they still important today? When Progress and Poverty was published in
1879, it was aimed in part at discrediting Social Darwinism, the idea that “survival of the fittest” should serve as a
social philosophy. That ideology, developed by Herbert
Spencer, William Graham Sumner, and others, provided
the intellectual basis for 1) American imperialism against
Mexico and the Philippines, 2) tax policies designed to
reduce burdens on the rich by shifting them onto the poor
and middle class, 3) the ascendancy of the concept of absolute property rights, unmitigated by any social claims
on property, 4) welfare programs that treat the poor as
failures and misfits, 5) racial segregation in education and
housing, and 6) eugenics programs to promote the “superior” race. The intellectual defense of racism is in abeyance, but the economic and political instruments of
domination have changed little. The renewed defense of
X
Progress and Poverty
taxing wages and consumer goods rather than property
holdings, expanded intellectual property rights, and vast
imperial ambitions are indications that Social Darwinism
is back in full force.
The revival of Social Darwinism continues to justify
social disparities on the basis of natural superiority or
fitness. Progress and Poverty, by contrast, reveals that those
disparities derive from special privileges. Many economists and politicians foster the illusion that great fortunes and poverty stem from the presence or absence of
individual skill and risk-taking. Henry George, by contrast, showed that the wealth gap occurs because a few
people are allowed to monopolize natural opportunities
and deny them to others. If we deprived social elites of
those monopolies, the whole facade of their greater “fitness” would come tumbling down. George did not advocate equality of income, the forcible redistribution of
wealth, or government management of the economy. He
simply believed that in a society not burdened by the
demands of a privileged elite, a full and satisfying life
would be attainable by everyone.
Henry George is best remembered as an advocate of
the “single tax” on location values. (I say “location” rather
than “land” to avoid the common confusion that George
was primarily interested in rural land. In fact his attention
was focused on the tens of trillions of dollars worth of
urban land that derives its value from location.) Yet, for
George, wise tax policy was merely a vehicle to break the
stranglehold of speculative ownership that effectively limits
the opportunity to earn an decent living and participate in
public life.
Perhaps the image that best captures George’s ultimate
intention is the final scene in a popular science fiction
Publisher’s Foreword
XI
film, when the hero is able to restore the oxygen supply
to the surface of a planet so that people will no longer be
enslaved by the man holding the oxygen monopoly. Freeing people from the oppression of monopoly power in
any form was Henry George’s great dream. Those who
have conceived of George as being concerned only with
tax policy should closely read the last third of Progress
and Poverty, which reveals his larger vision of justice and
genuine freedom.
Progress and Poverty stands the test of time. It contains profound economic analysis, penetrating social philosophy, and a practical guide to public policy. Those who
read it today will find in George’s work a great source of
vision and inspiration.
Cliff Cobb, Program Director
Robert Schalkenbach Foundation
XII
Progress and Poverty
Editor’s Preface
THOSE WHO FIRST pick up this book are likely to share
some concern about the problem of poverty; those who
finish it may also find some cause for hope. For the great
gift that Henry George gave the world was a systematic
explanation—logical and consistent—of why wealth is not
distributed fairly among those who produce it. But he did
not stop there—he also gave us a simple yet far-reaching
plan for a cure. It was, and still is, a plan for peace, prosperity, equality, and justice.
Progress and Poverty is an enduring classic. It has been
translated into dozens of languages; millions of copies have
been distributed worldwide.
Why, then, the need for a modern edition, and an
abridged one at that? Simply put, Henry George, like
many late-19th century authors, wrote in a style that
modern readers may find unduly complex. As editor, I
have endeavored to break long and intricate sentences
into shorter ones, creating what I call a “thought-bythought translation.”
Furthermore, references to history, mythology, and literature that do not advance the central argument have been
removed. Gender-balanced language has also been incorporated. However, I have not attempted to update financial statistics or technological examples.
I prepared this edition in two distinct stages: modernization and condensation. I have sought to ensure that
Editor’s Preface
XIII
nothing of substance was left out.
In modernizing the text, I reduced the average sentence length and increased the number of sentences. Sentences were shortened by about one-third. For example,
one passage showed a decline in average sentence length
from twenty-eight words to nineteen words. By comparison, the average sentence in Time magazine was fifteen
words in 1974, perhaps fewer today.
By simplifying language, I reduced the number of syllables per hundred words by about ten percent, to about
1.7 syllables per word. The number of sentences per hundred words was increased by fifty percent.
The combined effect of these changes transformed the
text from one comprehensible to only a small fraction of
the population to one that can be easily read by a highschool senior. An early test I performed showed that students were able to read the modernized text about
twenty-five percent faster than the original, even before
condensation. Although no formal testing for comprehension was done, anecdotal reports indicate that comprehension was greatly improved.
In the second stage, I condensed the modernized text
by rewriting sentences using simpler language, removing
multiple examples where one would suffice, and generally
editing for brevity. Although I occasionally rearranged sentences for clarity and continuity, keeping George’s original thesis intact was of utmost importance. In doing this,
I followed the exposition as Henry George presented it. I
endeavored to remove what is excessive and retain what is
essential. In the end, this edition is less than half the size
of the original.
This project has been a collective endeavor. Many
people contributed to the various drafts, starting with those
XIV
Progress and Poverty
teachers and students at the Henry George Schools in
Chicago, New York, and Philadelphia who provided suggestions and encouragement.
Many thanks to Terry Topczewski, Bob Jene, the late
Roy Corr, and Chuck Metalitz for their help and encouragement at various stages; Wyn Achenbaum, Herb Barry,
Cliff Cobb, George Collins, Josh Farley, Damon Gross,
Heather Remoff, and Tom Smith of the Robert
Schalkenbach Foundation board for their editorial reviews;
and George M. Menninger, Jr., John Kuchta, Scott Walton,
Sue Walton, Bruce Oatman, and Steve Zarlenga for their
moral support. Particular thanks to Lindy Davies and Mark
Sullivan for their assistance in the final stages of editing
and text preparation. Thanks also to the Robert
Schalkenbach Foundation and the Center for the Study of
Economics for institutional support.
Finally, special thanks must go to my wife (and great
jazz singer) Spider Saloff. Without her love and support,
none of the rest would have mattered.
Bob Drake, President,
Henry George School of Chicago
April 15, 2006
Author’s Preface
XV
Preface to the Fourth Edition
IN 1871, I FIRST PUBLISHED these ideas in a pamphlet entitled Our Land and Land Policy. Over time, I became
even more convinced of their truth. Seeing that many
misconceptions blocked their recognition, a fuller explanation seemed necessary. Still, it was impossible to answer all the questions as fully as they deserve. I have tried
to establish general principles, trusting readers to extend
their application.
While this book may be best appreciated by those familiar with economics, no previous study is needed to understand its argument or to judge its conclusions. I have
relied upon facts of common knowledge and common
observation, which readers can verify for themselves. They
can also decide whether the reasoning is valid.
I set out to discover why wages tend to a bare minimum despite increasing productive power. The current
theory of wages, I found, is based on a misconception
[namely, that wages are paid from capital]. In truth, wages
are produced by the labor for which they are paid. Therefore, other things being equal, wages should increase with
the number of laborers.
This immediately confronts the influential Malthusian doctrine that population tends to increase faster than
subsistence. Examination shows that this theory has no
real support. When brought to a decisive test, it is utterly
disproved.
XVI
Progress and Poverty
Since these theories cannot explain the connection
between progress and poverty, the solution must lie in the
three laws governing the distribution of wealth. These laws
should correlate with each other, yet economists fail to
show this. An examination of terminology reveals the confusion of thought that permits this discrepancy.
To work out these laws, I first take up the law of rent.
Although economists correctly understand this law, they
fail to appreciate its implications. For whatever determines
the part of production that goes to landowners must necessarily determine what is left over for labor and capital.
Nonetheless, I independently deduce the law of interest and the law of wages. Investigation shows that interest
and wages rise together when rent falls, and fall together
when rent rises. Therefore, rent, wages, and interest are all
determined by the margin of production, the point in production where rent begins. I also point out a source of
much confusion: mistaking the profits of monopoly for
the legitimate earnings of capital.
The laws of distribution are thus brought into harmony. The fact that rent always increases with material
progress explains why wages and interest do not.
The question is, what causes rent to increase? Population growth not only lowers the margin of production, it
also increases productivity. Both factors increase the proportion of income taken by rent, reducing the proportion
of wages and interest. Yet, technological and organizational
improvements lead to the same results. Even with a constant population, these alone would produce all the effects
Malthus attributes to population growth—as long as land
is held as private property.
Further, progress inevitably causes a continuous, speculative increase in land values if land is private property.
Author’s Preface
XVII
This drives rent up and wages down. It also produces periodic industrial depressions.
This analysis points to a remedy, although a radical
one. But is there any other? Examining other measures
advocated to raise wages merely proves our conclusion.
Nothing short of making land common property can permanently relieve poverty.
The question of justice naturally arises, so I next examine the nature and basis of property. There is a fundamental and irreconcilable difference between property in
the products of labor and property in land. One has a natural basis, the other none. Recognizing property in land
inherently denies the right to property produced by labor.
Landowners have no claim to compensation if society
chooses to resume its natural rights. Private property in
land always has led—and always must lead—to the enslavement of workers as development proceeds. In the
United States, we are already beginning to feel the effects
of accepting this erroneous and destructive principle.
As a practical matter, private ownership of land is not
necessary for its use or improvement. In fact, it entails
enormous waste. Recognizing the common right to land
does not require any shock or dispossession. It can be
reached by the simple and easy method of taxing only land
values. The principles of taxation show that this is the best
means of raising revenue.
What would be the effects of this proposed change? It
would enormously increase production. It would secure
justice in distribution. It would benefit all classes. And it
would make possible a higher and nobler civilization.
The inquiry now rises to a wider field. My conclusions assert certain laws. If these are really natural laws,
they must be apparent in universal history. As a final test,
XVIII
Progress and Poverty
therefore, I must work out the law of human progress.
Investigation reveals that differences in civilization are
not due to differences in individuals or races, but rather to
differences in social organization. Progress is always
kindled by association. And civilization always declines as
inequality develops.
Even now, in modern civilization, the causes that have
destroyed all previous civilizations are beginning to appear. Political democracy, without economic opportunity,
will devolve into anarchy and despotism.
But the law of social life agrees with the great moral
law of justice. This shows how decline may be prevented
and a grander advance begun.
If I have correctly solved the great problems I set out
to investigate, my conclusions completely change the character of political economy. They give it the coherence and
certainty of a true science. And they bring it into sympathy with the aspirations of humanity, from which it has
long been estranged.
What I have done in this book is to unite the truth
perceived by Smith and Ricardo with the truth perceived
by Proudhon and Lassalle.* I have shown that laissez
faire—in its full, true meaning—opens the way for us to
realize the noble dreams of socialism.
This work was written between August, 1877, and
March, 1879. Since its publication, events have shown these
views to be correct. The Irish land movement, especially,
shows the pressing nature of the problem.
* Adam Smith (1723-1790), David Ricardo (1772-1823), PierreJoseph Proudhon (1809-1865), and Ferdinand Lassalle (1825-1864).
The first two were classical economists; the latter two were socialist
reformers.
Author’s Preface
XIX
There has been nothing in the criticisms received to
induce me to change or modify these views. In fact, I have
yet to see an objection that was not already answered in
the book itself. Except for correcting some verbal errors
and adding this preface, this edition is the same as the
previous ones.*
Henry George
New York, November, 1880
Modernized and abridged, 2006
* George subsequently made one modification, regarding patents and
copyrights. See page 228.
XX
Progress and Poverty
Author’s Preface
XXI
To those who, seeing the vice
and misery that spring from the
unequal distribution of wealth
and privilege, feel the possibility of a higher social state and
would strive for its attainment.
San Francisco, March, 1879
XXII
Progress and Poverty
The Problem
1
Introduction
The Problem of Poverty Amid Progress
THE NINETEENTH CENTURY saw an enormous increase in
the ability to produce wealth. Steam and electricity, mechanization, specialization, and new business methods greatly
increased the power of labor.
Who could have foreseen the steamship, the railroad,
the tractor? Or factories weaving cloth faster than hundreds of weavers? Who could have heard the throb of
engines more powerful than all the beasts of burden combined? Or envisioned the immense effort saved by improvements in transportation, communication, and
commerce?
Surely, these new powers would elevate society from
its foundations, lifting the poorest above worry for the
material needs of life. Imagine these new machines relieving human toil, muscles of iron making the poorest worker’s
life a holiday, giving our nobler impulses room to grow.
Given such bountiful material conditions, surely we could
anticipate the golden age long dreamed of. How could there
be greed when everyone had enough? How could things
that arise from poverty—crime, ignorance, brutality—exist when poverty had vanished? Such were the dreams born
of this wonderful century of progress.
True, there were disappointments. Discovery upon
discovery, invention after invention still did not lessen
2
Progress and Poverty
the toil of those who most need relief or bring plenty to
the poor. But it seemed there were so many things that
could be blamed for this failure that our faith has hardly
weakened. Surely we would overcome these difficulties
in time.
Yet we must now face facts we cannot mistake. All
over the world, we hear complaints of industrial depression: labor condemned to involuntary idleness; capital going to waste; fear and hardship haunting workers. All this
dull, deadening pain, this keen, maddening anguish, is
summed up in the familiar phrase “hard times.”
This situation can hardly be accounted for by local
causes. It is common to communities with widely differing circumstances, political institutions, financial systems,
population densities, and social organization. There is
economic distress under tyrannies, but also where power
is in the hands of the people. Distress where protective
tariffs hamper trade, but also where trade is nearly free.
Distress in countries with paper money, and in countries
with gold and silver currencies.
Beneath all this, we can infer a common cause. It is
either what we call material progress, or something closely
connected with it. What we call an industrial depression
is merely an intensification of phenomena that always accompany material progress. They show themselves more
clearly and more strongly as progress goes on.
Where do we find the deepest poverty, the hardest
struggle for existence, the greatest enforced idleness? Why,
wherever material progress is most advanced. That is to
say, where population is densest, wealth greatest, and production and exchange most highly developed. In older
countries, destitution is found amid the greatest abundance.
The Problem
3
Conversely, workers emigrate to newer countries seeking higher wages. Capital also flows there seeking higher
interest. They go where material progress is still in earlier
stages. The older countries, where material progress has
reached its later stages, is where poverty occurs.
Go to a new community where the race of progress is
just beginning, where production and exchange are still
rude and inefficient. The best house may be only a log
cabin; the richest person must work every day. There is
not enough wealth to enable any class to live in ease and
luxury. No one makes an easy living, or even a very good
one—yet everyone can make a living. While you won’t
find wealth and all its effects, neither will you find beggars. No one willing and able to work lives in fear of want.
Though there is no luxury, there is no poverty.
But just when they start to achieve the conditions
civilized communities strive for, poverty takes a darker
turn. This occurs as savings in production and exchange
are made possible by denser settlement, closer connection with the rest of the world, and labor-saving machinery. It occurs just as wealth consequently increases.
(And wealth increases not only in the aggregate, but in
proportion to population.)
Now, some will find living better and easier—but others will find it hard to get a living at all. Beggars and prisons are the mark of progress as surely as elegant mansions,
bulging warehouses, and magnificent churches.
Unpleasant as it may be to admit, it is at last becoming
evident that progress has no tendency to reduce poverty.
The great fact is, poverty, with all its ills, appears whenever progress reaches a certain stage. Poverty is, in some
way, produced by progress itself.
4
Progress and Poverty
Progress simply widens the gulf between rich and
poor. It makes the struggle for existence more intense.
Wherever these forces are at work, large classes are maintained on charity.
Yes, in certain ways, the poorest now enjoy what the
richest could not a century ago. But this does not demonstrate an improvement—not so long as the ability to
obtain the necessities of life has not increased. A beggar
in the city may enjoy many things that a backwoods
farmer cannot. But the condition of the beggar is not
better than that of an independent farmer. What we call
progress does not improve the condition of the lowest
class in the essentials of healthy, happy human life. In
fact, it tends to depress their condition even more.
These new forces do not act on society from underneath. Rather, it is as though an immense wedge is being
driven through the middle. Those above it are elevated,
but those below are crushed.
Where the poor have long existed, this effect is no
longer obvious. When the lowest class can barely live, it is
impossible to get any lower: the next step is out of existence altogether. This has been the case for a long time in
many parts of Europe. But where new settlements advance
to the condition of older ones, we see that material progress
not only fails to relieve poverty, it actually produces it.
In the United States, it is obvious that squalor and
misery increase as villages grow into cities. Poverty is most
apparent in older and richer regions. If poverty is less deep
in San Francisco than New York, is it not because it lags
behind? Who can doubt that when it reaches the point
where New York is now, there will also be ragged children
in the streets?
The Problem
5
So long as the increased wealth that progress brings
goes to building great fortunes and increasing luxury,
progress is not real. When the contrast between the haves
and have-nots grows ever sharper, progress cannot be permanent. To educate people condemned to poverty only
makes them restless. To base a state with glaring social
inequalities on political institutions where people are supposed to be equal is to stand a pyramid on its head. Eventually, it will fall.
This relation of poverty to progress is the great question of our time. It is the riddle that the Sphinx* of
Fate puts to us. If we do not answer correctly, we will be
destroyed.
As important as this question is, we have no answer
that accounts for the facts or provides a cure.
Experts break into an anarchy of opinion, and people
accept misguided ideas. They are led to believe that there
is a necessary conflict between capital and labor; that machinery is an evil; that competition must be restrained; or
that it is the duty of government to provide capital or furnish work. Such ideas are fraught with danger, for they
allow charlatans and demagogues to control the masses.
But these ideas cannot be successfully challenged until
political economy gives some answer to the great question.
Political economy is not a set of dogmas. It is the explanation of a certain set of facts and their mutual relationships. Its deductions follow from premises we all
recognize. In fact, we base the reasoning and actions of
everyday life on them. These premises can be reduced to
* The Sphinx was a creature in Greek mythology who challenged travelers with a riddle. If they could not answer correctly, it devoured them.
6
Progress and Poverty
an expression as simple and basic as the physical law that
says: motion follows the line of least resistance.
Political economy proceeds from the following simple
axiom:
People seek to satisfy their desires with the least exertion.
The process then consists simply of identification and
separation. In this sense it is as exact a science as geometry. Its conclusions, when valid, should be just as apparent.
Now, in political economy we cannot test theories by
artificially producing combinations or conditions, as other
sciences can. Yet we can apply tests that are no less conclusive. This can be done by comparing societies in which
different conditions exist. Or, we can test various theories
in our imagination—by separating, combining, adding, or
eliminating forces or factors of known direction.
Properly done, such an investigation should yield a
conclusion that will correlate with every other truth. Every effect has a cause; every fact implies a preceding fact.
In the following pages, I will use these methods to
discover what law connects poverty with progress. I believe this law will also explain the recurring cycles of industrial and commercial depression, which now seem so
unexplainable.
Current political economy cannot explain why poverty persists in the midst of increasing wealth. It teaches
only unrelated and disjointed theories. It seems to me, this
is not due to any inability of the science. Rather, there
must be some false step in its premises, or some overlooked
factor in its estimates.
Such mistakes are generally concealed by respect paid
The Problem
7
to authority. Therefore, I will take nothing for granted.
Accepted theories will be tested; established facts will be
freshly questioned. I will not shrink from any conclusion,
but promise to follow the truth wherever it may lead.
What the outcome proves to be is not our affair. If the
conclusions we reach run counter to our prejudices, let us
not flinch. If they challenge institutions that have long
been regarded as wise and natural, let us not turn back.
8
Wages and Capital
First Part:
Wages and Capital
Chapter 1:
Why Traditional Theories of Wages
are Wrong
FIRST, LET’S CLEARLY DEFINE the problem we are investigating and review how currently accepted theories attempt
to explain it. We want to discover why poverty persists
despite increasing wealth. It is universally recognized that
wages tend toward a minimum level. Whatever causes this
must also cause the persistence of poverty. So let’s frame
our inquiry like this:
Why do wages tend to decrease to subsistence level, even as
productive power increases?
Current theory erroneously attempts to explains it
thus: (a) wages are set by the ratio between the number
of workers and the amount of capital available for labor;
(b) population is presumed to increase faster than the
increase in capital; (c) therefore, wages always move toward the lowest level workers will tolerate. That is, wages
are equal to capital divided by population. Increasing
population is held in check only by the limitations of
Traditional Theories of Wages
9
wages, so even if capital increases toward infinity, there
will be no improvement.
In plain English, current theory incorrectly claims
that wages cannot rise faster than the population among
which capital must be divided. Only low wages will slow
the population growth of workers.
This doctrine, though false, is virtually undisputed; it
is endorsed by noted economists and taught in great universities. It is popular among those not clever enough to
have theories of their own, as may be seen daily in newspaper columns and legislative debates. The general public
holds even cruder forms. Why—despite obvious inconsistencies and fallacies—do people cling to protectionist
views? They accept the mistaken belief that each community has only a fixed amount of wages available, and that
this would be further divided among “foreign competition.” This misconception is the basis of most other failed
attempts to increase the workers’ share, such as restricting
competition or abolishing interest.
Yet, despite being so widely held, this theory simply
does not fit the facts.
If wages are set by the ratio between labor and capital,
then the relative abundance of one must mean a lack of the
other. Now, if capital is not used for wages, it can be invested elsewhere. So the current interest rate is a relatively
good measure of whether capital is scarce or abundant.
According to this theory, then, high wages (scarce labor) must be accompanied by low interest (abundant capital). In the reverse case, low wages (abundant labor) must
be accompanied by high interest (scarce capital).
But we can see that, in fact, the opposite is true: Interest is high when wages are high. Interest is low when wages
10
Wages and Capital
are low. Wherever labor goes seeking higher wages, capital also flows seeking higher interest. Whenever there has
been a general rise or fall in wages, there has been a similar
rise or fall in interest at the same time.
Wages are usually higher in new countries (where capital is relatively scarce) than in old countries (where capital is
relatively abundant). Both wages and interest have been
higher in the United States than in England, and in the
Pacific rather than in the Atlantic States. In California, when
wages were higher than anywhere else in the world, interest
was also higher. Later, wages and interest in California went
down together.
Consider the economics of “good times” and “hard
times.” A brisk demand for labor (and good wages) is always accompanied by a brisk demand for capital (and high
interest rates). However, when jobs are scarce and wages
slump, there is always an accumulation of capital seeking
investment at low rates.
It is true that rates may be high during commercial
panics. However, this is not properly called a high rate of
interest. Rather, it is a rate of insurance against risk.
The present depression (1879) has seen unemployment
and lower wages. It has also seen the accumulation of unused capital in all the great cities, with nominal interest on
safe investments.
These are all well-known facts. They do point to a
relationship between wages and interest—but it is a relation of conjunction, not of opposition. There is no explanation of these conditions that is consistent with current
theory.
How, then, could such a theory arise? Why was it accepted by economists from Adam Smith to the present? If
Traditional Theories of Wages
11
we examine the reasoning supporting this theory, it becomes clear that it is not an induction from observed facts.
Rather, it is a deduction from a previously assumed theory.
Specifically, it has already been assumed that wages
are drawn from capital.
If capital is the source of wages, it logically follows
that total wages must be limited by the capital devoted to
wages. Hence, the amount individual laborers can receive
must be determined by the ratio between their number
and the amount of capital available.
This reasoning process is logically valid. However, as
we have seen, the conclusion drawn from it does not fit
the observed facts. Therefore, the problem must be in the
premise.
I am aware that the idea that wages are drawn from
capital is one of the most fundamental and widely accepted theorems of current political economy, accepted
as axiomatic by all the great economists. Nevertheless, I
think I can demonstrate that this is a fundamental error.
It forms the basis of a long series of errors that distort
the practical conclusions drawn from them.
The proposition I intend to prove is this:
Wages are not drawn from capital. On the contrary, wages
are drawn from the product of the labor for which they are paid.*
Now, while current theory says wages are drawn from
capital, it also says capital is reimbursed from production.
* For simplicity, George restricts his analysis here to the production of
physical wealth. Wages for services, the use of labor to satisfy desires
directly, are not advanced from capital, but from wealth devoted to
consumption (see page 33).
12
Wages and Capital
So at first glance this may appear to be a distinction without a difference. If this were merely a change in terminology, any discussion would only add to the meaningless petty
arguments that comprise so much of economics. But it
will become apparent that this is much more than a formal distinction. Indeed, all the current theories regarding
the relation between capital and labor are built on this
difference. Doctrines deduced from it are regarded as axiomatic; they limit and direct the ablest minds in discussing issues of momentous importance.
Among the beliefs based on the assumption that wages
are drawn directly from capital—not from the product of
labor—are the following: industry is limited by capital;
labor can only be employed as capital is accumulated; every increase of capital enables additional employment; conversion of circulating capital into fixed capital reduces the
fund available to labor; more laborers can be employed at
low wages than at high wages; profits are high when wages
are low; profits are low when wages are high.
In short, almost all the important theories of current
political economy are based on the erroneous assumption that labor is paid out of existing capital before any
product is produced. I maintain, on the contrary, that
wages are drawn directly from the product of labor. They
do not—even temporarily—come close to relying on existing capital.
If I can prove this, then all those other theories are left
without any support and must be discarded—including
all theories based on the belief that the supply of wages is
fixed. For such reasoning holds that as the number of workers increases, the share to each must diminish.
On this foundation, current economists have built a
Traditional Theories of Wages
13
vast superstructure of related theories. But in truth, this
foundation has merely been taken for granted. Not the
slightest attempt has been made to distinguish whether or
not it is based on fact.
It is inferred that wages are drawn from preexisting
capital because wages are generally paid in money. In
many cases, wages are paid before the product is fully
completed or useful. From this it is concluded that industry is limited by capital. That is, that labor cannot be
employed until capital has been accumulated; and then,
only to the extent of such capital.
Yet in the same books holding these theories, we find
the contradiction. First they claim, without reservation,
that capital limits labor. Then they state that capital is
stored up or accumulated labor. If we substitute this definition for the word capital, the proposition refutes itself.
That is, it says labor cannot be employed until the results
of labor have been accumulated. This is patently absurd.
But we cannot end the argument with this reductio ad
absurdum alone, for other explanations are likely to be
tried. Perhaps Divine Providence provided the capital that
allowed the first labor to begin? More likely, the proposition would be said to refer to more advanced societies
where complex production methods are used.
However, there is a fundamental truth in all economic
reasoning that we must firmly grasp and never let go of.
Modern society, though highly developed, is only an elaboration of the simplest society. Principles that are obvious
in simple relationships are not reversed or abolished in
more complex ones. The same principles are merely disguised by the use of sophisticated tools and the division of
labor.
14
Wages and Capital
The modern grist mill, with all its complicated machinery, is only a means of grinding corn. Factory workers
may run machines, print labels, or keep books. Yet, they
are really devoting their labor to the same task: preparing
food. The modern mill serves the same purpose as an ancient stone mortar unearthed by archeologists. Both the
ancient and modern workers are attempting to satisfy their
desires by exerting labor on natural resources.
Modern economy is a vast and intricate network of
production and exchange, with complex operations infinitely subdivided into specialized functions. Yet looking
at production as a whole, we see it is the cooperation of all
to satisfy the desires of each. Keeping this in mind, we see
clearly that the reward each obtains, though engaged in
diverse tasks, comes truly and directly from nature as the
result of that particular exertion. It is no different from
the efforts of the very first human.
Consider the example of a primitive fishing village.
Under the simplest conditions, they all catch their own
fish and dig their own bait. Soon, they realize the advantage of a division of labor. So now one person digs bait
while the others go out fishing. It is obvious at this point
that the one who digs bait is, in reality, doing as much
toward catching fish as those who actually take in the catch.
Next the advantages of canoes are discovered. Instead
of each person building a canoe, only one stays behind to
make and repair canoes for the others. In reality, the canoe-maker is devoting labor to catching fish as much as
those actually fishing. The fish eaten each night are as much
a product of the labor of the canoe-maker as they are of
the labor of those fishing. As the division of labor continues, we find that one group fishes, another hunts, a third
Traditional Theories of Wages
15
picks berries, a fourth gathers fruit, a fifth makes tools, a
sixth builds huts, and a seventh prepares clothing.
Division of labor, when fairly established, benefits all
by common pursuit. It is used instead of individuals attempting to satisfy all of their wants by directly resorting
to nature on their own. As they exchange with each other
the product of their labor for the products of others’ labor,
they are really applying their own labor to the production
of the things they use—just as if each person had made
each item alone. They are, in effect, satisfying their own
particular desires by the exertion of their own individual
powers. That is to say, they genuinely produce whatever
they receive.
These principles are obvious in simple society. If we
follow them through the complexities of what we call civilization, we can clearly see the same principles. In every
case where labor is exchanged for commodities, production actually precedes enjoyment. Such wages are not the
advance of capital.
Someone’s labor has contributed to the general stock
of wealth. He receives in return a draft against this general stock. He may use that draft in any particular form
that will best satisfy his desires. Though the money itself
may have been printed before his labor, it is really an exchange of the products of his labor for the products of
others’ labor. The important point is that neither the money,
nor the particular items he chooses to buy, are advances of
capital. On the contrary, money is merely a draft that represents the wealth his labor has already added to the general stock.
Keeping these principles in mind, we can see the same
truth in a variety of examples. An engineer cooped up in
16
Wages and Capital
some dingy office drawing plans for a great turbine is, in
reality, devoting her labor to the production of bread and
meat. She is doing so just as truly as if she were harvesting
grain in California or swinging a lariat on the pampas of
Argentina. She is as truly making her own clothes as if she
were shearing sheep in Australia or weaving cloth in a factory. She is effectively producing the wine for her dinner
just as though she had gathered the grapes in France.
A miner, digging silver ore thousands of feet underground, is, by virtue of a thousand exchanges, in effect
harvesting crops in the valley or fishing in the arctic; picking coffee in Honduras and cutting sugar in Hawaii; gathering cotton from Georgia and weaving it in Manchester;
or plucking fruit in the orchards of California.
The wages he receives for the week are merely certificates to show the world that he has done these things.
The money he receives in return for his labor is only the
first in a long series of exchanges. These transmute his
labor into those particular things for which he has really
been laboring.
All this is clear when we look at it this way. But the
fallacy remains firmly entrenched in many hiding places.
To reveal it, we must now change our investigation from
the deductive to the inductive. Our conclusions have been
obvious when we began with general principles and deduced specific examples. Let us now see if we arrive at the
same conclusions inductively—that is, by examining specific facts and tracing their relations into general principles.
Defining Terms
17
Chapter 2
Defining Terms
BEFORE PROCEEDING FURTHER, we must define our terms
so that each meaning remains consistent. Otherwise, our
reasoning will be vague and ambiguous. Many eminent
authors have stressed the importance of clear and precise
definitions. I cannot add to this, except to point out the
many examples of these same authors falling into the very
trap they warn against.
Certain words—such as wealth, capital, rent, and
wages—require a much more specific meaning in economic
reasoning than they do in everyday speech. Unfortunately,
even among economists, there is no agreement on the
meaning of these terms. Different writers give different
meanings to the same term. Even worse, one author will
use the same term in different senses. Nothing shows the
importance of precise language like the spectacle of the
brightest thinkers basing important conclusions on the
same word used in different senses.
I will strive to state clearly what I mean by any term of
importance—and to use it only in that sense. Further, I
will conform to common usage as much as possible, rather
than assign arbitrary meanings or coin new terms. The
reader should keep these definitions in mind, for otherwise I cannot be properly understood. My desire is to fix
the meaning plainly enough to express my thoughts clearly.
18
Wages and Capital
Now, we had been discussing whether wages are, in
fact, drawn from capital. So let’s start by defining wages
and capital. Economists have given a sufficiently definite meaning to wages. However, capital will require a
detailed explanation, since it has been used ambiguously
by many economists.
In common conversation, wages mean compensation
paid to someone hired to render services. The habit of applying it solely to compensation paid for manual labor further narrows its use. We do not speak of the wages of
professionals or managers, but of their fees, commissions,
or salaries. So, the common meaning of wages is compensation for manual labor.
But in political economy, the word wages has a much
wider meaning. Economists speak of three factors of production: land, labor, and capital. Labor includes all human
exertion in the production of wealth. Wages are the portion of production that goes to labor. Therefore, the term
wages includes all rewards for such exertion.
In the economic sense of the term, none of the distinctions of common speech apply. It does not matter what kind
of labor it is. Nor does it matter whether the reward for
labor is received from an employer or not. Wages, in the
economic sense, simply means the return for the exertion of
labor. It is distinguished from the return for the use of capital (interest), and from the return for the use of land (rent).
The wages of hunters are the game they kill; the wages
of fishermen, the fish they catch. Farmers get wages from
their crops. In addition, if they use their own capital and
their own land, part of the crop will be considered interest, part rent. Gold panned by self-employed prospectors
is as much their wages as money paid to hired miners.
Defining Terms
19
And, as Adam Smith noted, the high profits of retail storekeepers are in large part wages—that is, compensation for
their labor, not just for their capital.
In short, whatever is received as the result or reward of
exertion is wages. This is all we need to know for now, but
it is important to keep it in mind. In standard economics
texts, this term is used more or less clearly—at first. Sadly,
this clear definition is frequently ignored later on.
The idea of capital, on the other hand, is so beset with
ambiguities that it is difficult to determine a precise use of
the term. In general discourse, all sorts of things that have
a value, or will yield a return, are vaguely spoken of as
capital. Economists themselves use the term in so many
senses that it hardly has any fixed meaning.*
I could go on for pages citing contradictory—and selfcontradictory—definitions from other authors, but this
would only bore the reader. You can find further illustration
of the confusion among economists and learned professors
in any library, where their works are arranged side by side.
What name we call something is not the issue here.
The point is to use it to always mean the same thing—and
nothing else. Most people, in fact, understand what capital is well enough—until they begin to define it. Even
economists use the term in the same sense—in every case
except in their own definitions and the reasoning based
on them. They apply their particular definition to set up
the premise of their reasoning. But when conclusions are
drawn, capital is always used—or at least always understood—in one particular sense.
This commonly understood sense separates capital from
* Curious readers may find examples in the original text, pp. 33-36.
20
Wages and Capital
land and labor, the other factors of production. It also separates it from similar things used for gratification. The common meaning of capital is, simply put, wealth devoted to
producing more wealth. Adam Smith correctly expresses
this common idea when he says: “That part of a man’s stock
which be expects to afford him revenue is called his capital.” The capital of a community is therefore the sum of
such individual stocks. Said another way, it is the part of the
aggregate stock that is expected to procure more wealth.
Political and social writers are even more striking than
economic ones in their failure to use capital as an exact
term. Their difficulties arise from two facts. First, there
are certain things that—to an individual—are equivalent
to possessing capital. However, they are not part of the
capital of the community. Second, things of the same kind
may—or may not—be capital, depending on what they
are used for.
Keeping these points in mind, we can use the term
capital in a clear and constant manner, without any ambiguity or confusion. Our definition will enable us to say
what things are capital and what are not. The three factors of production are land, labor, and capital. The term
capital is used in contradistinction to land and labor.
Therefore, nothing properly included as either land or
labor can be called capital.
The term land does not simply mean the surface of
the earth as distinguished from air and water—it includes
all natural materials, forces, and opportunities. It is the
whole material universe outside of humans themselves.
Only by access to land, from which their very bodies are
drawn, can people use or come in contact with nature.
Therefore, nothing freely supplied by nature can be
Defining Terms
21
properly classed as capital.
Consider a fertile field, a rich vein of ore, or a falling
stream, which can supply power. These may give the owner
advantages that are equivalent to possessing capital. However, calling them capital would end the distinction between land and capital. It would make the terms
meaningless in relation to each other.
Similarly, the term labor includes all human exertion.
So human powers can never be properly classed as capital.
This, of course, applies whether they are natural or acquired powers. In common parlance, we often speak of
someone’s knowledge, skill, or industry as his or her capital. This language is obviously metaphorical. We cannot
use it in reasoning that requires exactness. Such qualities
may increase income, just as capital would. The community may increase its production by increases in knowledge, skill, or industry.
The effect may be the same as an increase of capital.
However, the increase in production is due to the increased
power of labor, not capital. Increased velocity may give the
impact of a cannon ball the same effect as increased weight.
Nevertheless, weight is one thing and velocity another.
Therefore, capital must exclude everything that may
be included as land or labor. This leaves only things that
are neither land nor labor. These things have resulted from
the union of the two original factors of production. In other
words, nothing can be capital that is not wealth.
Many of the ambiguities about capital derive from
ambiguities in the use of the inclusive term wealth. In
common use, wealth means anything having an exchange
value. When used as an economic term, however, it must
be limited to a much more definite meaning.
22
Wages and Capital
If we take into account the concept of collective or
general wealth, we see that many things we commonly call
wealth are not so at all. Instead, they represent the power
to obtain wealth in transactions between individuals (or
groups). That is, they have an exchange value. However,
their increase or decrease does not affect the sum of wealth
in the community. Therefore, they are not truly wealth.
Some examples are stocks, bonds, mortgages, promissory notes, or other certificates for transferring wealth. Neither can slaves be considered wealth. Their economic value
merely represents the power of one class to appropriate
the earnings of another. Lands or other natural opportunities obtain exchange value only from consent to an exclusive right to use them. This merely represents the power
given to landowners to demand a share of the wealth produced by those who use them.
Increase in the amount of bonds, mortgages, or notes
cannot increase the wealth of the community, since that
community includes those who pay as well as those who
receive. Slavery does not increase the wealth of a people,
for what the masters gain the enslaved lose. Rising land
values do not increase the common wealth, as whatever
landowners gain by higher prices, tenants or purchasers
lose in paying them.
All this relative wealth is undistinguished from actual wealth in legislation and law, as well as common
thought and speech. Yet with the destruction of nothing
more than a few drops of ink and a piece of paper, all this
“wealth” could be utterly annihilated. By an act of law,
debts may be canceled, slaves emancipated, land made
common property. Yet the aggregate wealth would not
be diminished at all—for what some would lose others
Defining Terms
23
would gain. Wealth was not created when Queen Elizabeth graced her favorite courtiers with profitable monopolies, nor when Boris Godunov declared Russian
peasants to be property.
The term wealth, when used in political economy, does
not include all things having an exchange value. It includes
only those things that increase the aggregate wealth when
produced or decrease it when destroyed. If we consider
what these things are and what their nature is, we will
have no difficulty defining wealth.
We speak of a community increasing its wealth. For
instance, we say that England increased its wealth under
Queen Victoria, or that California is wealthier than when
it belonged to Mexico. By saying this, we do not mean
there is more land or natural resources. We do not mean
some people owe more debts to others. Nor do we mean
there are more people. To express that idea, we speak of an
increase in population—not wealth.
What we really mean is there was an increase of certain tangible goods—things that have an actual, not merely
a relative, value. We mean buildings, cattle, tools, machinery, agricultural and mineral products, manufactured goods,
ships, wagons, furniture, and the like. More of such things
is an increase in wealth; less of them is a decrease in wealth.
We would say the community with the most of such things,
in proportion to its population, is the wealthiest.
What is the common characteristic of these things? They
all consist of natural substances that have been adapted by
human labor for human use. Wealth, then, may be defined
as natural products that have been secured, moved, combined, separated, or in other ways modified by human exertion to fit them for the gratification of human desires.
24
Wages and Capital
Their value depends on the amount of labor that, on average, would be required to produce things of like kind. In
other words, it is labor impressed upon matter so as to
store up the power of human labor to satisfy human desires, as the heat of the sun is stored in coal.
Wealth is not the sole object of labor, for labor is also
expended to directly satisfy human desires. Wealth is the
result of what we may call productive labor—that is,
labor that gives value to material things. Wealth does not
include anything nature supplies without human labor.
Yet the result of labor is not wealth unless it produces a
tangible product that satisfies human desires.
Capital is wealth devoted to a certain purpose. Therefore, nothing can be considered capital that does not fit
within the definition of wealth.
But though all capital is wealth, all wealth is not capital. Capital is only a particular part of wealth—that part
devoted to aid production. We must draw a line between
wealth that is capital and wealth that is not capital. If we
keep this in mind, we can eliminate misconceptions that
have led even gifted thinkers into a maze of contradiction.
The problem, it seems to me, is that the idea of what
capital is has been deduced from some preconceived idea
of what capital does. Logic would dictate first determining
what something is, then observing what it does. Instead,
the functions of capital have first been assumed. Then a
definition is fitted to include everything that does, or may
perform, those functions.
Let us adopt the natural order and ascertain what capital is before declaring what it does. The term in general is
well understood; we need only make the edges sharp and
clear. If actual articles of wealth were shown to a dozen
Defining Terms
25
intelligent people who had never read a line of economics,
it is doubtful that they would disagree at all about what
was capital or not.
No one would think of counting as capital someone’s
wig, or the cigar in the mouth of a smoker, or the toy a child
plays with. But we would count, without hesitation, a wig
for sale in a store, the stock of a tobacconist, or the goods in
the toy store. A coat made for sale would be accounted capital; but not the coat a tailor made to wear. Food used in a
restaurant would be capital; but not food in a pantry. Part of
a crop held for seed or sale, or given as wages, would be
capital; the part used by the farmer’s family would not.
I think we would agree with Adam Smith that capital
is “that part of a man’s stock which he expects to yield him
a revenue.” As examples, he lists:
machines and instruments of trade that aid or lessen
labor;
buildings used in trade, such as shops, farmhouses,
etc. (but not dwellings);
improvements of land for agricultural purposes;
goods for sale, from which producers and dealers
expect to derive a profit;
raw materials and partially manufactured articles still
in the hands of producers or dealers;
completed articles still in the hands of producers or
dealers.*
If we look for what distinguishes capital in this list, we
will not find it among the character or capabilities of the
*Smith’s original list included two items that do not fit under George’s
definition of capital. See original text, p. 47.
26
Wages and Capital
items (though vain attempts have been made to do so).
The key, it seems to me, is whether or not the item is in
the possession of the consumer. Wealth yet to be exchanged
is capital. Wealth in the hands of the consumer is not.
Hence, we can define capital as wealth in the course of
exchange. We must understand here that exchange does
not mean merely passing from hand to hand—it also includes the increase in wealth from the reproductive or
transformative forces of nature. Using this definition, we
can include all the things that capital properly includes,
and eliminate all it does not.
This definition includes all tools that are really capital. For what makes a tool capital is whether its uses or
services are to be exchanged or not. Thus, the lathe used
to make things for exchange is capital; one kept as a hobby
is not. Wealth used in the construction of a railroad, a theater, or a hotel is wealth in the course of exchange. The
exchange does not occur all at once, but little by little, with
an indefinite number of people—yet there is an exchange.
The consumers are not the owners, but rather the patrons
who use these facilities.
This definition is consistent with the idea that capital
is that part of wealth devoted to production of more wealth.
But to say production is merely “making things” is too narrow an understanding of the term. Production also includes
bringing things to the consumer. Storekeepers are as much
producers as farmers or manufacturers. The stock in a store
is capital, and it is as much devoted to production as the
capital of the others.
We are not yet concerned with the functions of
capital. That will be easier to determine later. Nor is the
definition itself important. I am not writing a textbook;
Defining Terms
27
I am trying to discover the laws governing a great social
problem. My purpose here has been to help the reader
form a clear idea of what things are meant when we speak
of capital.
In ending this chapter, let me note what is often forgotten. Terms like wealth, capital, and wages, as used in
political economy, are abstract terms. Nothing can be stated
or denied about them unless it applies to the whole class
of things they represent. The idea of wealth involves the
idea of exchangeability. To possess a given amount of wealth
is potentially to possess any or all types of wealth that would
be equivalent to it in exchange. Of course, the same is true
of capital.
The failure to bear this in mind has allowed fallacies,
which otherwise would be transparent lies, to pass for obvious truths.
28
Wages and Capital
Chapter 3
Wages Are Produced By Labor,
Not Drawn From Capital
THE IMPORTANCE of defining our terms can be seen at once
in this chapter. When people say wages are drawn from
capital, they are obviously using wages in the everyday
sense, forgetting the economic meaning.
When workers take their reward directly from the
product of their labor, their wages clearly are not drawn
from capital. If I go out and pick wild berries, the wages
for my labor are the berries. Surely no one will argue that
wages are drawn from capital in such a case—there is no
capital involved!
If I work a piece of leather into a pair of shoes, those
shoes are my wages, the result of my labor. They are not
drawn from capital, my own or anyone else’s. They are
brought into existence by my effort, and my capital is not
lessened at all—not even for a moment. At the start, my
capital consists of leather, thread, and so on. As I work,
value is steadily added. When the shoes are finished, I still
have my capital, plus the difference in value between the
original material and the shoes. This additional value becomes my wages.
Adam Smith recognized that wages are the product of
labor in such simple cases. His chapter on wages begins:
“The produce of labor constitutes the natural recompense
Wages Not Drawn from Capital
29
or wages of labor. In that original state of things which precedes both the appropriation of land and the accumulation
of stock, the whole produce of labor belongs to the laborer.
He has neither landlord nor master to share with him.”
If Smith had traced this obvious truth through more
complicated forms of production—recognizing wages as
the product of labor, with landlord and master merely
sharers—political economy would be very different today,
not a mess of contradictions and absurdities. Instead, he
recognized it only momentarily and abandoned it immediately—restarting his inquiry from the point of view of
the business owner providing wages from her capital.
Let us pick up the clue where Adam Smith dropped
it. Proceeding step by step, we will see whether these relationships, obvious in simple examples, still hold true in
the most complex forms of production.
In the “original state of things,” as we have seen, the
entire product of labor belongs to the worker. Next in simplicity are cases where wages are paid in kind. That is to
say, workers’ wages come from the things produced by their
labor, even though they may be working for another or
using the capital of another. Clearly, these wages are drawn
from the product of the labor, not from capital. Let’s say I
hire workers to pick berries or make shoes. I then pay them
from the berries or shoes. There can be no question that
the source of their wages is the same labor for which they
are being paid.
Take the next step where wages are estimated in kind,
but paid in an equivalent value of something else. For instance, the custom on American whaling ships is to pay
each crew member a proportion of the catch. At the end
of a successful cruise, a ship carries the wages of her crew
30
Wages and Capital
in her hold, along with the owner’s profits and reimbursement for stores used during the voyage. The oil and bone
the crew have caught are their wages. Can anything be
clearer than that these have not been drawn from capital?
They are the product of their labor.
This fact is not changed or obscured in the least when
the crew is paid in cash. This is simply a matter of convenience: the value of each share is estimated at market
price, instead of dividing the actual oil and bone. Money
is just the equivalent of their real wages: the oil and bone.
In no way is there any advance of capital in such payment. The obligation to pay the whalers does not accrue
until the value of the catch, from which wages are to be
paid, is brought into port. When the owner takes money
from her capital to pay the crew, she adds the oil and
bone to her capital.
So far, there can be no dispute. Let us now take another step: the usual method of employing labor by paying wages. A company hires workers to stay on an island
gathering eggs, which are sent to San Francisco every few
days to be sold. At the end of the season, the workers are
paid a set wage in cash. Now, the owners could pay them a
portion of the eggs, as is done in other hatcheries. They
probably would, if there were uncertainty about the outcome. But since they know so many eggs will be gathered
by so much labor, it is more convenient to pay fixed wages.
This cash merely represents the eggs—for the sale of eggs
produces the cash to pay the wages. These wages are the
product of the labor for which they are paid—just as the
eggs would be to workers who gathered them for themselves without the intervention of an employer.
In these cases, we see that wages in money are the
Wages Not Drawn from Capital
31
same as wages in kind. Is this not true of all cases in which
wages are paid for productive labor? Isn’t the fund created
by labor really the fund from which wages are paid?
Now, the argument may be made that those working for themselves get nothing if some disaster spoils
the work; but those working for an employer get their
wages anyhow. This is not a real distinction, however.
Generally, any disaster that prevents an employer from
benefiting from labor also prevents the employer from
paying wages. On the whole, labor done for fixed wages
produces more than the amount of the wages. Otherwise, employers could not make any profit.
Production is the source of wages. Wages come from
the fruits of labor—not the advance of capital. Labor always precedes wages. This is true whether wages are received from an employer, or wages are taken directly from
the efforts of the workers. Wages paid by an employer imply
the previous rendering of labor by the employee for the
benefit of the employer. This is true whether paid by the
day, week, or month, or even by the piece.
Though it is obvious the way I have explained it, many
important deductions are based on the opposite position.
How can it be considered plausible that wages are drawn
from capital? It begins with the assertion that labor cannot operate unless capital supplies it with maintenance.
The unwary reader agrees that labor must have food and
clothing in order to work. Having been told that such
items are capital, the reader then accepts the conclusion
that capital is required before labor can be applied. From
this misdirection, it appears to be an obvious deduction
that industry is limited by capital. That is to say, that the
demand for labor depends on the supply of capital. Hence,
32
Wages and Capital
it appears to follow that wages are set by the ratio between the number of laborers looking for employment
and the amount of capital available to hire them.
A fallacy exists in this reasoning that has entangled
some of the brightest minds in a web of their own spinning. But I think our discussion in the previous chapter
will enable us to spot the error. It is the use of the term
capital in two different senses.
The primary proposition is that capital is required for
labor. Here “capital” is understood as including all food,
clothing, shelter, and so on. Whereas in the deductions
drawn from it, capital is used in its common and legitimate meaning. That is: wealth devoted to procuring more
wealth. This does not include wealth used for the immediate gratification of desire. It means wealth in the hands
of employers as distinguished from laborers.
So to say that workers cannot work without food and
clothing does not mean that only those who first receive
breakfast and clothes from an employer may work. The
fact is that laborers generally furnish their own breakfasts and their own clothes. Further, capitalists are never
compelled to make advances to labor before work begins
(though in exceptional cases they may choose to do so).
Of all the unemployed labor in the world today, there is
probably not a single one who could not be hired without paying wages in advance. Many would gladly wait
until the end of the month to be paid, many more until
the end of the week, as most workers usually do. The
precise time is immaterial. The essential point is that
wages are paid after the performance of labor.
Wages always imply the previous rendering of labor.
And what does “rendering of labor” imply? The production
Wages Not Drawn from Capital
33
of wealth. If this wealth is to be used in exchange or in
production, then it is capital. Therefore, the payment of capital in wages presupposes some production of capital—by
the very labor for which those wages are paid.
Since the employer generally makes a profit in this
transaction, paying wages is merely returning part of the
capital received from labor. The employee gets part of the
capital labor has produced.
How can it be said that wages are advanced by capital or drawn from preexisting capital? The value paid in
wages is an exchange for value created by labor. And the
employer always gets the capital created by labor before
paying out capital in wages. At what point, then, is capital lessened, even temporarily?
Note that I refer to labor as producing capital for
simplicity’s sake. Labor always produces either wealth
(which may or may not be capital) or services. Only in an
exceptional case of misadventure is nothing produced.
Now, sometimes labor is performed simply for the satisfaction of the employer. For example, getting one’s shoes
shined. Such wages are not paid from capital, but from
wealth devoted to consumption. Even if such funds were
once considered capital, they no longer are. By the very
act, they pass from the category of capital to that of wealth
used for gratification. It is the same as when a tobacconist takes cigars from the stock for sale and pockets them
for personal use.
Let’s test our reasoning against the facts. Consider a
manufacturer who produces finished products from raw
materials, say cloth from cotton. The company pays its
workers weekly, as is the custom. Before work begins on
Monday morning, we take an inventory of their capital. It
34
Wages and Capital
consists of buildings, machinery, raw materials, money on
hand, and finished products in stock. After work has ended
for the week and wages paid, we take a new inventory. For
the sake of simplicity, we will assume that nothing was
bought or sold during that week.
Let us look at their capital now. There will be less
money, since some was paid out in wages. There will be
less raw material, less coal, and so on. A deduction for
wear and tear must be made from the value of the buildings and machinery. But if the business is profitable, as
most are, the items of finished products will more than
compensate for these costs. There will be a net increase of
capital.
Obviously, then, wages were not drawn from capital.
They came from the value created by labor itself. There
was no more an advance of capital than if someone hired
workers to dig clams and paid them with the clams they
dug. Their wages were truly the product of their labor.
The same as, in Adam Smith’s words, “before the appropriation of land and the accumulation of stock.”
This situation is similar to that of bank depositors:
After they have put money in, they can take money out.
By withdrawing what they have previously put in, the bank
depositors do not lessen the capital of the bank. Likewise,
by receiving wages, the worker does not lessen, even temporarily, the capital of the employer. Nor does the worker
lessen the total capital of the community.
It is true workers generally are not paid in the same
kind of wealth they have created. Likewise, banks do not
give depositors the same bills or coins they deposited—
instead, they receive it in an equivalent form. We rightly
say the bank gives depositors the money they paid in. So
Wages Not Drawn from Capital
35
we are justified in saying workers receive in wages the
wealth they created with their labor.
This universal truth is often obscured because we confuse wealth with money, due to our habit of estimating capital
in terms of money. Money is a general medium of exchange,
the common flow through which wealth is transformed from
one form to another.
Difficulties in exchanging wealth generally show up on
the side of reducing wealth to money. Money may easily
be exchanged for any other form of wealth. Yet sometimes
it is more difficult to exchange a particular form of wealth
for money. The reason is simple: there are more who want
to make some exchange of wealth than there are those who
want to make a particular exchange.
Employers who pay wages in money sometimes find
it difficult to turn their products back into money quickly.
They are spoken of as “having exhausted” or “advanced”
their capital in wages. Yet the money paid out in wages
has, in fact, been exchanged for an increase in the value of
their products. (Only in exceptional cases is the value created by the labor less than wages paid.)
The capital they had before in money, they now have
in goods. It has been changed in form—but not lessened.
Now, in some cases production may require months or
years, during which no return is received. Meanwhile, wages
must be paid. Such cases—where wages are paid before the
desired results are completed—are always given as examples
of wages advanced from capital. Well, let us see.
In agriculture, for instance, harvesting must be preceded
by several months of plowing and sowing. Similarly, in the
construction of buildings, ships, railroads, and so on, owners cannot expect an immediate return. They must wait,
36
Wages and Capital
sometimes for many years. In these cases, it is easy to jump
to the conclusion that wages are advanced by capital—if
fundamental principles are forgotten. But if I have made
myself clear, the reader will not be fooled. A simple analysis
will show that such instances are no exception to the rule.
The fundamental principle is clear whether the product is
finished before or after wages are paid.
Let’s say I go to a broker to exchange silver for gold.
As I give them my silver, they hand me the equivalent in
gold (minus commission). Does the broker advance any
capital? Certainly not! What they had before in gold, they
now have in silver (plus profit!). Since they received the
silver before paying out the gold, they did not—even for
an instant—advance any capital.
The operation of the broker is exactly analogous to
the cases we are considering. Labor is rendered and value
is created before wages are paid. Creating value does not
depend on finishing the product—it takes place at every
stage of the process. It is the immediate result of the application of labor. No matter how long the process, labor
always adds capital before it takes it in wages. The owner
merely exchanges one form of capital for another.
Consider a blacksmith hired to make simple pickaxes.
Clearly, the smith adds picks to the employer’s capital before taking money from that capital in wages. But what
about a boilermaker working on a great ship? One may be
completed in a few minutes, the other not for years. Yet
both are items of wealth, articles of production. Each day’s
work produces wealth and adds capital. In the steamship
as in the pick, it is not the last blow (any more than the
first) that creates the value of the finished product. Value
is created continuously—it is the immediate result of the
Wages Not Drawn from Capital
37
exertion of labor.
We see this quite clearly when different parts of the
process are carried out by different producers. Here we
customarily estimate the value of labor in various preparatory stages. A moment’s reflection will show this to be the
case in the vast majority of products. Take a building, a
book, or a loaf of bread. The finished products were not
produced in one operation or by one set of producers. In
clearly defined steps, we can easily distinguish the different stages of creation and the value of materials. At each
step, we habitually estimate the creation of value and the
addition to capital.
The bread from the baker’s oven has a certain value.
But this is composed, in part, of the value of the flour
from which the dough was made. This, again, is composed
of the value of the wheat and the value given by milling.
And so on.
Production is not complete until the finished product
is in the hands of the consumer. Not, for example, when a
crop of cotton is gathered; nor when it is ginned; nor made
into yarn; nor even into cloth. The process is finished only
when the consumer receives the finished coat or shirt or
dress. Yet at each step, it is clear there is the creation of
value—an addition to capital.
It may take years to build a ship—but value is created day by day, hour by hour, from the very start. The
value of the finished ship is the sum of these increments.
No capital is advanced in paying wages during the building, because labor produces more capital than is paid back.
Clearly, if someone asked to buy a partially completed
ship, the owner would expect to make a profit at any stage
of construction. Likewise, a company’s stock does not
38
Wages and Capital
lose value as capital in one form (wages paid) is gradually changed into capital in another form (the ship). On
the contrary, on average its value probably increases as
work progresses.
This is obvious in agriculture also. Value is not created
all at once, but step by step during the whole process. A
plowed field will bring more than an unplowed one; a sown
field more than one merely plowed. The harvest is merely
the conclusion. Orchards and vineyards bring prices proportionate to their age, even though too new to bear fruit.
Likewise, horses and cattle increase in value as they mature. We do not always discern this increase in value, except at the usual points of exchange. Yet it most definitely
takes place every time labor is exerted.
Hence, whenever labor is rendered before wages are
paid, the advance of capital is really made by the worker—
not the owner. The advance is from the worker to the
employer—not from the employer to the employed.
Yet, you may protest, “Surely in the cases we have considered, capital is required!” Certainly. I do not dispute
that. But it is not needed to make advances to labor. It is
required for quite another purpose, as we shall see.
Suppose I hire workers to cut wood. If I pay in kind,
with a portion of the wood, it is clear no capital is required
to pay wages. But it is often easier and more profitable to
sell one large pile than several smaller ones. So for mutual
convenience, I pay wages in cash instead of wood. If I can
exchange the wood for money before wages are due, I still
do not need any capital.
It is only when I must wait to accumulate a particular
quantity of wood that any capital is required. Such quantity
might be needed before I can make any exchange; or merely
Wages Not Drawn from Capital
39
before I can get the terms I want. Even then, I will not need
capital if I can make a partial or tentative exchange by borrowing against the wood.
I will need capital only if I cannot—or choose to not—
sell the wood or borrow against it. In other words, I will
need capital only if I insist on accumulating a large stock
of wood. Clearly, I need this capital only to accumulate a
stock of product—not for paying wages.
Consider something more complicated, like cutting a
tunnel. If the workmen could be paid in pieces of tunnel,
no capital for wages would be required. Indeed, this could
be done easily by paying them in stock of the company. It
is only when the backers wish to accumulate capital in the
form of a completed tunnel that they need capital.
Let’s return to our initial example of a metals broker.
Surely they cannot carry on their business without capital.
But they do not need it to make any advance of capital to
me when they take my silver and hand me back gold. They
need it because the nature of their business requires keeping a certain amount of capital on hand, so they are prepared to make the type of exchange the customer desires.
We shall find it the same in every type of production.
Capital is required only when production is stored up. Producers never need capital to employ labor. When they need
capital, it is as merchants or speculators in the products of
labor. That is, in order to accumulate such products.
To recapitulate: People who work for themselves get
their wages in the things they produce, as they produce
them. They exchange this value into other forms whenever they sell these products.
The people who work for another and are paid in
money, work under a contract of exchange. They, too, cre-
40
Wages and Capital
ate their wages as they render their labor. But they only
collect them at stated times, in stated amounts, and in a
different form. In performing the labor, they are advancing on this exchange. When they get their wages, the exchange is completed. During the time they are earning
wages, the workers are advancing capital to their employer.
At no time (unless wages are paid before work is started)
is the employer advancing capital to them.
Whether the employer chooses to exchange the output immediately or to keep it for awhile in no way alters
the character of the transaction. It matters no more than
the final disposition of the product by the ultimate consumer, who may be somewhere on another continent at
the end of a long series, perhaps hundreds, of exchanges.
Workers Not Supported By Capital
41
Chapter 4
Workers Not Supported By Capital
BUT ONE DOUBT may linger. A farmer cannot eat a furrow;
nor can a half-built loom weave clothes. John Stuart Mill
asserted that people are maintained “not by the produce of
present labor, but of past.” Or, as another popular text put
it, many months elapse between sowing the seed and baking the bread.*
An assumption is made in these passages that appears
self-evident. Namely, that labor must subsist on capital
produced by prior labor. This thought runs through the
entire fabric of political economy. A related proposition is
regarded as equally axiomatic. That is, that “population
regulates itself by the funds which are to employ it, and,
therefore, always increases or diminishes with the increase
or diminution of capital.”** This assumption, in turn, further influences economic reasoning.
On reflection, however, we see these propositions
are not self-evident—they are absurd! They require the
assumption that labor cannot be exerted until the products of labor are saved. This puts the product before the
producer.
* Millicent Garrett Fawcett (1847-1929), Political Economy for Beginners, Chap. III, p. 25.
** David Ricardo (1772-1832), Principles of Political Economy, Chap.
11. The idea is common in many works.
42
Wages and Capital
To say a people eat breakfast before going to work is
not to say that they cannot go to work unless an employer
provides breakfast. People do not decide to eat or fast based
on whether or not they propose to engage in productive
labor. They eat because they are hungry.
The proposition that present labor must be maintained
by past production is true only in the sense that lunch provides the fuel for the afternoon’s work, or that before you
eat a rabbit, it must be caught and cooked. Clearly this is
not the sense in which the proposal is used in economic
reasoning. That sense is that a stock to support workers
must already exist before carrying out any effort that does
not immediately yield wealth available for subsistence. Let
us see if this is true.
Did Robinson Crusoe,* shipwrecked on an island, have
to accumulate a stock of food before he began to build his
canoe? Not at all. He needed only to spend part of his
time getting food, and part of his time building the canoe.
Suppose a hundred people landed in a new country.
Would they have to accumulate a season’s worth of provisions before they could begin to cultivate the soil? Obviously not. What is required is that part of the group find
enough fish, game, and berries to support them all. And
that, through mutual self-interest or common desire, those
gathering food in the present are willing to exchange it
with those whose efforts are directed toward the harvest
in the future.
What is true in these cases is true in all. Producing
things that cannot be used immediately does not require
* Hero of the novel published in 1719 by Daniel Defoe (1660-1731),
English writer.
Workers Not Supported By Capital
43
the previous production of wealth for maintaining workers during production. All that is necessary is, within the
circle of exchange, the contemporaneous production of
sufficient subsistence—assuming a willingness to trade one
for the other.
As a matter of fact, isn’t it true that, under normal
circumstances, consumption is supported by contemporaneous production? Imagine a wealthy idler who lives
on an inheritance and does no productive work at all.
Does he live on wealth accumulated in the past? On his
table are fresh eggs, butter, and milk; meat from the
butcher; vegetables from the garden. In short, hardly
anything has not recently left the hand of productive labor, except perhaps some old bottles of wine.
What this man inherited—and what he lives on—is
not actually wealth at all. It is only the power to command
wealth, as others produce it. His sustenance is clearly taken
from productive labor going on around him. (Remember
we must include transporters and distributors, as well as
those in the first stages of production.)
London contains more wealth than the same size space
almost anywhere else. Yet if productive labor in London
were to stop completely, within a few months hardly anyone would be left alive. It is the daily labor of the community that supplies its daily bread.
Workers engaged in long-term endeavors are supported by other workers producing sustenance. They engage in their respective work simultaneously. To build a
modern public project taking years to complete, the government does not appropriate wealth already produced. It
uses wealth yet to be produced—to be taken in taxes from
producers as the work progresses.
44
Wages and Capital
There may be a thousand intermediate exchanges in
the circle of exchange between two parties. A mechanic
wants food, clothing, and shelter for her family. How does
her work on an engine secure these items? Reduced to its
most basic terms, the transaction really amounts to an
exchange of labor between herself and the producers of
those items.
What causes a mechanic to work on an engine? Someone with the power to give her what she wants is willing to
exchange those things for an engine. In other words, there
exists a demand for an engine from those producing bread,
meat, and so on. Or, one step removed, there is a demand for
an engine from others who are producing still other things
that are wanted by those producing bread, meat, etc. Reversely,
the demand of the mechanic for bread and meat directs an
equivalent amount of labor toward the production of those
things. Thus, her labor produces, implicitly, the things she
spends her wage on. To put this in formal terms:
The demand for consumption determines the direction in
which labor will be expended in production.
All the complexities of our subject disappear in light
of this simple and obvious principle. We see the real objects and rewards of labor within the intricacies of modern
production. We reach the same conclusions we did from
observing the simpler forms of production and exchange
in primitive society. We see that now, as then, each laborer
is trying to obtain, by his or her work, the satisfaction of
his or her own desires.
The minute division of labor assigns each worker only
a small part—or perhaps nothing at all—of producing
the particular things he desires. Even so, in helping to
Workers Not Supported By Capital
45
produce what others want, he is directing their labor to
produce the things he wants. In effect, he is producing
them himself.
Thus we see that, no matter what is taken or consumed
by workers in return for their labor, there is no advance of
capital.
If I have made knives and bought wheat, I have simply exchanged one for the other. I have added knives to
the existing stock of wealth and taken wheat from it. It
cannot even be said that I have lessened the stock of wheat.
For by adding knives to the exchangeable stock of wealth
and taking out wheat, I have directed other labor—at the
end of a long series of exchanges—to produce more wheat.
Just the same as the wheat grower, by putting in wheat
and demanding knives, guided others to produce knives.
So farmers tend their fields, many months from harvest. Yet, by their exertion in plowing, they are producing
the food they eat and the wages they receive. For though
plowing is only part of producing a crop, it is as necessary
a part as the harvesting. By the assurance it gives of a future crop, it releases other items from the general stock,
which is constantly held. These then become the subsistence and wages of the plowman. This is not merely theoretically true. It is literally and practically true.
The series of exchanges that unite production and consumption may be likened to a curved pipe filled with water. If a quantity of water is poured in at one end, a like
quantity is released at the other. It is not the identical water, but is its equivalent.
And so those who do the work of production put in
what they take out. What they receive in subsistence and
wages is but the product of their labor.
46
Wages and Capital
Chapter 5
The True Functions of Capital
WE HAVE SEEN that capital is not required to pay wages or
support labor during production. What, then, are the true
functions of capital?
Capital, as we discovered, is wealth used to procure
more wealth. This we distinguish from wealth used to directly satisfy human desires. Therefore, capital may also
be defined as wealth in the course of exchange.
Capital increases the power of labor to produce wealth
in three ways:
(1) by applying labor in more effective ways (e. g.,
digging with a spade instead of by hand; or shipping by
steamship instead rowing a boat). (2) by taking advantage
of the reproductive forces of nature (e.g., growing more
crops by sowing or more animals by breeding). (3) by permitting the division of labor. (This increases human efficiency by utilizing unique capabilities, acquiring special
skills, and reducing waste. This allows people to produce
each form of wealth where it is most favorable, by taking
advantage of soil, climate, and location. )
The raw material that labor converts into wealth is
not capital. Rather, it is material supplied by nature. Therefore, capital does not limit industry. The only thing that
limits industry is access to natural materials.
It is clear, however, that capital may limit the form or
True Functions of Capital
47
the productiveness of industry—by limiting the tools and
the division of labor required for certain methods of production. Without the factory, there can be no factory
worker; without the plow, no plowman. Without the exchange of great capital, the many special forms of industry
concerned with exchanges would be impossible.
The tools available also limit productiveness. Does the
farmer have enough capital for a plow, or must she use a
spade? Must the mechanic use only a hammer, or the
weaver a hand loom? Capital for the best tools can multiply production by tenfold.
Advanced civilization requires the minute subdivision
of labor. The modern worker can exchange her labor with
that of those around her, or even around the world. To do
this, there must be stocks of goods in warehouses, stores,
and ships. By analogy, for a city dweller to draw a glass of
water, there must be millions of gallons stored in reservoirs and moving through miles of pipe.
But to say that capital may limit the form and productiveness of industry is a very different thing from saying
that capital does limit industry.
We can, of course, imagine a community in which
lack of capital would be the only obstacle to increased
productiveness of labor. But the only examples that occur to me are the wholesale destruction of capital by war,
fire, or natural disaster. Or possibly, the fresh settlement
of civilized people in a new land. Yet it has long been
known that capital is quickly replenished after war, and
that a new community swiftly makes needed capital.
Other than such rare and passing conditions, I am unable to think of any other cases where the productiveness of labor is really limited by lack of capital. There
48
Wages and Capital
may be individuals in a community who cannot apply
their labor as efficiently as they would like because they
lack capital. Yet, so long as there is sufficient capital in
the community at large, the real limitation is not capital,
but its proper distribution.
Indeed, even the limitation of form or productiveness
may be more theoretical than real. It is often said that poor
countries need capital for development. But behind this
“need”, can’t we perceive a greater want? One that includes—but is not the same as—lack of capital. Is it not
the abuses of government, the insecurity of property, and
the ignorance of the people that prevent the accumulation
and use of capital? Bad government may steal capital belonging to workers. It may seize wealth that producers
would use for improvements. The real limitation is misgovernment. The same with ignorance, custom, or other
conditions that hamper the use of capital. The real limitations are these things, not the lack of capital—which would
not be used even if placed there.
Giving a circular saw to a Terra del Fuegan or a locomotive to a Bedouin nomad would not add to their efficiency. The Apache and the Sioux are not kept from
farming by want of capital. If provided with seeds and tools,
they still would not use them productively—not until they
chose to stop their wandering lifestyle and learned to cultivate the soil. They have certain items they are accustomed
to using as their capital. Any wealth beyond these would
be either consumed or left to waste. If all the capital in
London were given to them in their present condition, it
would simply cease to be capital. They would use only an
infinitesimal part of it to assist them in the hunt.
Yet any capital they do desire, they manage to get,
True Functions of Capital
49
sometimes despite great difficulties. These wild tribes hunt
and fight with the best weapons that our factories produce, keeping up with all the latest improvements. It is
only as they adopt our civilization that they seek other
forms of capital. Otherwise, such things would not be of
any use to them.
In the reign of George IV, missionaries brought a New
Zealand chieftain, called Hongi, to England. His noble
appearance and beautiful tattooing attracted much attention. When he was to return to his people, he was presented with a considerable stock of tools, implements, and
seeds—thoughtful gifts from the monarch and some religious societies. The grateful chief did indeed use this capital
to produce food—but in a manner his English benefactors could scarcely imagine. Returning through Australia,
he exchanged his original capital for arms and ammunition. Once home, he waged war on another tribe with such
success that, after the first battle, three hundred prisoners
were cooked and eaten. Nowadays, Maoris have adopted
European habits and stopped their warfare. Many of them
have amassed considerable capital and put it to good use.
It would also be a mistake to attribute the simple
economies found in new communities solely to the need
for capital. These rude and inefficient modes of production and exchange require little capital. But when the conditions of such communities are considered, we find that
they are, in reality, the most effective.
A modern printing press could produce thousands
of pages, while a Franklin press might manage only a
hundred. Yet to print a small edition of a country newspaper, the old-fashioned press is by far the more efficient
machine. To occasionally carry two or three passengers,
50
Wages and Capital
a canoe is a better means than a steamboat. And putting
a great stock of goods into a backwoods store would be a
waste of capital.
Generally, it will be found that these methods result
not so much from lack of capital, as from inability to employ it profitably. No matter how much water you pour in
a bucket, it can never hold more than a bucketful.
These observations lead us irresistibly to some practical conclusions, which justify the great pains we have
taken to make sure of them. If wages come from labor,
and not capital, then the current theories are invalid.
We must disregard all remedies based on them, whether
they are proposed by workers or professors of economics. Poverty cannot be alleviated by increasing capital
or by restricting the number of workers. If each worker
creates his or her own wages, then wages cannot be diminished by more workers. On the contrary, labor’s efficiency clearly increases when there are more producers.
Other things being equal, the more labor, the higher
wages should be.
But the necessary proviso is “things being equal.” This
brings us to a question that must be disposed of before we
can proceed: Do the productive powers of nature decrease
as greater demands are made by a growing population?
Malthusian Theory
51
Second Part:
Population and Subsistence
Chapter 6
The Theory of Population
According to Malthus
IT IS SURPRISING that so many educated thinkers could have
accepted a theory of wages that our analysis has shown to
be utterly baseless. The explanation for this baffling fact
can be found in the general acceptance of another theory.
The theory of wages was never adequately examined because it seemed self-evident in the minds of economists
when backed by the Malthusian theory.
This theory—published in 1798 by Rev. Thomas
Malthus—postulates that population naturally tends to increase faster than nature can provide subsistence. The two
doctrines, fitted together, frame the answer to the problem of poverty given by current economic thought.
Both theories derive additional support from a principle in Ricardo’s theory of rent. Namely, that past a certain point, applying capital and labor to land yields a
diminishing return. Together, these ideas provide a likely
explanation for the phenomena of a highly organized, advanced society. This has prevented closer investigation.
52
Population and Subsistence
Malthus based his theory on the growth of the North
American colonies. This, he concluded, showed that
population naturally tended to double every twenty-five
years. Thus, population would increase at a geometrical
ratio. Meanwhile, subsistence from land, under the most
favorable circumstances, could not possibly increase faster
than in an arithmetical ratio. That is, to increase the same
amount every twenty-five years. In other words, population increases as 1, 2, 4, 8; while subsistence increases as
1, 2, 3, 4.
“The necessary effects of these two different rates of
increase, when brought together,” Mr. Malthus naively goes
on to say, “will be very striking.” He concludes that at the
end of only the first century, two thirds of the population
will be “totally unprovided for”; while in two thousand
years, “the difference would be almost incalculable.”
Such a result is, of course, prevented by the physical
fact that no more people can exist than can find food.
Hence, Malthus concludes that the tendency of population to indefinite increase may be held back by two means.
Population may be limited by “moral restraint” [i.e., sexual
abstinence]. Otherwise, various causes of increased mortality will do the job. He calls restraints on propagation
the “preventive check.” Increased mortality he names the
“positive check.”
This is the famous Malthusian doctrine, as promulgated by Malthus himself in his Essay on Population. The
fallacious reasoning in assuming geometrical and arithmetical rates of increase, is hardly worth discussing. It
merely provides a high-sounding formula that carries far
more weight with many people than the clearest reasoning. But this assumption is not essential. It is expressly
Malthusian Theory
53
repudiated by some who otherwise accept the doctrine.
Regardless, the essence of Malthusian theory is that
population tends to increase faster than the food supply.
Malthus claims that population constantly tends towards
increase. Unless restrained, it will ultimately press against
the limits of subsistence, although such limits are elastic,
not fixed. Nonetheless, it becomes increasingly difficult to
produce subsistence. Thus, whenever growth, over time, is
unchecked by conscious restraint, population will be kept
in check by a corresponding degree of deprivation.
Malthus unashamedly makes vice and suffering the
necessary result of natural instinct and affection. Despite
being silly and offensive, as well as repugnant to our sense
of a harmonious nature, it has withstood the refutations
and denunciations, the sarcasm, ridicule, and sentiment
directed against it. It demands recognition even from those
who do not believe it. Today it stands as an accepted truth
(though I will show it is false).
The reasons for its acceptance are not hard to find. It
appears to be backed by an indisputable mathematical
truth—that a continuously increasing population must
eventually exceed the capacity of the earth to furnish food,
or even standing room. It is supported by analogies in the
animal and vegetable kingdoms, where life beats wastefully against the barriers holding different species in check.
Many obvious facts seem to corroborate it. For instance,
the prevalence of poverty, vice, and misery amid dense
populations. In addition, the general effect of material
progress is to increase population without relieving poverty. It is pointed out that population grows rapidly in
newly settled counties. It slows in more densely settled
ones, apparently because of mortality among those con-
54
Population and Subsistence
demned to poverty.
Malthusian theory furnishes a general principle to
explain these facts. Moreover, it accounts for them in a
way that harmonizes with the doctrine that wages are
drawn from capital—and with all the principles deduced
from it. Current wage theory says that wages fall as more
workers compel a finer division of capital. Malthusian
theory claims poverty arises as increased population forces
further division of subsistence. It requires little to make
the two propositions as identical formally as they already
are substantially. Merely identify capital with subsistence,
and the number of workers with population. This identification is already made in current economic writing,
where the terms are often interchanged.
Ricardo furnished additional support a few years later,
by correcting the mistake Adam Smith had made regarding the nature and cause of rent. Ricardo showed that rent
increases as a growing population extends cultivation to
less and less productive land.
This formed a triple combination of interlocking theories. The previous doctrine of wages and the subsequent
doctrine of rent can be seen, in this view, as special examples of the general principle of the Malthusian theory
of population. Wages fall and rents rise with increasing
population. Both show the pressure of population against
subsistence.
To a factory worker, the obvious cause of low wages
and lack of work appears to be too much competition. And
in the squalid ghettos, what seems clearer than that there
are too many people? We may also note that, in our present
state of society, most workers appear to depend upon a
separate class of capitalists for employment. Under these
Malthusian Theory
55
conditions, we may pardon the masses—who rarely bother
to separate the real from the apparent.
But the real reason for the triumph of the theory is
that it does not threaten any vested right or antagonize
any powerful interest. Malthus was eminently reassuring
to the classes who wield the power of wealth and, thus,
largely dominate thought. The French Revolution had
aroused intense fear. At a time when old supports were
falling away, his theory came to the rescue. It saved the
special privileges by which only a few monopolize so much
of this world.
It proclaimed a natural cause for want and misery.
Malthus’ purpose was to justify existing inequality by
shifting the responsibility from human institutions to the
laws of the Creator. For if those things were attributed
to political institutions, they would condemn every government. Instead, he provided a philosophy to shield the
rich from the unpleasant image of the poor; to shelter
selfishness from question by interposing an inevitable
necessity. Poverty, want, and starvation are not the result
of greed or social maladjustment, it said. They are the
inevitable result of universal laws, as certain as gravity.
Even if the rich were to divide their wealth among the
poor, nothing would be gained. Population would increase
until it again pressed the limits of subsistence. Any equality that might result would be only common misery.
Thus, any reform that might interfere with the interests of any powerful class is discouraged as hopeless. Nothing can really be done, individually or socially, to reduce
poverty. This theory, while exploiting the erroneous
thoughts of the poor, justifies the greed of the rich and the
selfishness of the powerful. Such a theory will spread
56
Population and Subsistence
quickly and strike deep roots.Recently, this theory has received new support from Darwin’s theory on the origin of
species. Malthusian theory seems but the application to
human society of “survival of the fittest.” Only “the struggle
for existence,” cruel and remorseless, has differentiated humans from monkeys, and made our century succeed the
stone age.*
Thus seemingly proved, linked, and buttressed,
Malthusian theory is now generally accepted as an unquestionable truth: Poverty is due to the pressure of population against subsistence. Or in its other form, the
number of laborers will always increase until wages are
reduced to the minimum of survival.
All social phenomena are now to be explained in this
light—as for years the heavens were explained by supposing the earth was at the center of the universe. If authority
were the only consideration, argument would be futile. This
theory has received almost universal acceptance in the intellectual world, endorsed by economists and statesmen,
historians and scientists, psychologists and clergy, conservatives and radicals. It is held, and habitually reasoned from,
by many who have never even heard of Malthus, and
haven’t the slightest idea what his theory is.
Nevertheless, upon our investigation, the supporting
arguments for wage theory evaporated. So too, I believe,
will vanish the grounds for this doctrine, which is its twin.
*The debate between Darwin’s theory and “Social Darwinism” has
gone on into the 21st century.
Malthus vs. Facts
57
Chapter 7
Malthus vs. Facts
DESPITE ITS ENDORSEMENT by respected authorities, I believe we will find Malthusian theory utterly without support when we apply the test of straightforward analysis.
Facts marshaled in support do not prove it, and analogies
do not uphold it. Further, there are facts that conclusively
disprove it. There is no justification in experience or analogy for the assumption that there is any tendency for population to increase faster than the food supply.
The facts cited to support the Malthusian theory are
taken from new countries where population is sparse, or
among the poor classes in old countries where wealth is
distributed unequally. In these cases, human life is occupied with the physical necessities of existence. Reproduction under such conditions is at a high rate, which, if it
were to go unchecked, might eventually exceed subsistence.
But it is not legitimate to infer that reproduction would
continue at the same rate under conditions where population was sufficiently dense and wealth was distributed
evenly. These conditions would lift the whole community
above a mere struggle for existence. Nor can one assume
that such a community is impossible because population
growth would cause poverty. This is obviously circular reasoning, as it assumes the very point at issue. To prove that
overpopulation causes poverty, one would need to show
58
Population and Subsistence
that there are no other causes that could account for it.
With the present state of government, this is clearly impossible.
This is abundantly shown in Malthus’ Essay on Population itself. This famous book is spoken of more often
than read. The contrast between the merits of the book
itself and the effect it produced is one of the most remarkable in the history of literature. His other works, though
written after he became famous, had no influence. They
are treated with contempt, even by those who consider his
theory a great discovery.
Malthus begins with the assumption that population
increases in a geometrical ratio, while subsistence can increase in an arithmetical ratio at best. That is no more
valid than to assert than that, because a puppy doubled
the length of its tail while adding so many pounds of
weight, there is therefore a geometric progression of tail
length and an arithmetical progression of weight. We can
imagine Jonathan Swift, the great satirist, describing the
logical inference from such an assumption. He might have
the sages of a previously dogless island deducing from these
two ratios the “very striking consequence” that by the time
the dog grew to fifty pounds its tail would be over a mile
long! This, of course, this would be extremely difficult to
wag. Hence, they must recommend the “prudential check”
of a bandage as the only alternative to the “positive check”
of constant amputations.
After commencing with such an absurdity, the Rev.
Malthus continues to show the most ridiculous incapacity for logical thought. The main body of the book is
actually a refutation of the very theory it advances. His
review of what he calls positive checks simply shows that
Malthus vs. Facts
59
the effects he attributes to overpopulation actually arise
from other causes. He cites cases from around the world
where vice and misery restrain population by limiting
marriages or shortening life span. Not in a single case,
however, can this be traced to an actual increase in the
number of mouths over the power of the accompanying
hands to feed them. In every case, vice and misery spring
either from ignorance and greed, or from bad government, unjust laws, or war.
Nor has what Malthus failed to show been shown by
anyone since. We may search the globe and sift through
history in vain for any instance of a considerable country
in which poverty and want can be fairly attributed to the
pressure of an increasing population. Whatever dangers
may be possible in human increase, they have never yet
appeared. While this time may come, it never yet has afflicted mankind.
Historically, population has declined as often as increased. It has ebbed and flowed, while its centers have
changed. Regions once holding great populations are now
deserted, and their cultivated fields turned to jungle.
New nations have arisen and others declined. Sparse
regions have become populous and dense ones receded.
But as far back as we can go, without merely guessing,
there is nothing to show continuous increase. We are apt
to lose sight of this fact as we count our increasing millions. As yet, the principle of population has not been
strong enough to fully settle the world. Whether the aggregate population of the earth in 1879 is greater than at
any previous time, we can only guess. Compared with its
capacities to support human life, the earth as a whole is
still sparsely populated.
60
Population and Subsistence
Another broad, general fact is obvious. Malthus asserts
that the natural tendency of population to outrun subsistence is a universal law. If so, it should be as obvious as any
other natural law, and as universally recognized.
Why, then, do we find no injunction to limit population among the codes of the Jews, Egyptians, Hindus, or
Chinese? Nor among any people who have had dense
populations? On the contrary, the wisdom of the ages and
the religions of the world have always instilled the very
opposite idea: “Be fruitful and multiply.”
If the tendency to reproduce is as strong as Malthus
supposes, then how is it that family lines so often become
extinct? This occurs even in families where want is unknown. In an aristocracy such as England, hereditary titles
and possession offer every advantage. Yet the House of
Lords is kept up over the centuries only by the creation of
new titles.
To find the single example of a family that has survived any great lapse of time, we must go to immutable
China. There, descendants of Confucius still enjoy peculiar privileges and consideration. Taking the presumption that population tends to double every twenty-five
years, his lineage after 2,150 years should include
859,559,193,106,709,670,198,710,528 souls. Yet, instead
of any such unimaginable number, his descendants number about 22,000 total. This is quite a discrepancy!
Further, an increase of descendants does not mean an
increase of population. This would only happen if all the
breeding were in the same family. Mr. and Mrs. Smith
have a son and a daughter, who each marry someone else’s
child. Each has two children. Thus, Mr. and Mrs. Smith
have four grandchildren. Yet each generation is no larger
Malthus vs. Facts
61
than the other. While there are now four grandchildren,
each child would have four grandparents.
Supposing this process were to go on and on. The line
of descent might spread out to thousands, even millions.
But in each generation, there would be no more individuals
than in any previous generation. The web of generations is
like lattice-work or the diagonal threads in cloth. Commencing at any point at the top, the eye follows lines that
diverge widely at the bottom; but beginning at any point at
the bottom, the lines diverge in the same way to the top.
How many children a woman may have is variable. But that
she had two parents is certain! And that these also had two
parents each is also certain. Follow this geometrical progression through a few generations and see if it does not
lead to quite as “striking consequences” as Mr. Malthus’
peopling of the solar systems.
But let us now advance to specific cases. I assert that
examples commonly cited as instances of overpopulation
will not bear up under investigation. India, China, and
Ireland furnish the strongest of these. In each, great numbers have died of starvation, while entire classes were reduced to abject misery or compelled to emigrate. But is
this really due to overpopulation?
Comparing total population with total area, India and
China are far from being the most densely populated countries of the world. The population densities [in 1873] of
India and China were 132 and 119 per square mile, respectively. Compare this to England (442), Belgium (441),
Italy (234), and Japan (233). The total population of the
world was estimated to be just under 1.4 billion, for an
average of 26.64 per square mile.
Both India and China have large areas not fully used,
62
Population and Subsistence
or even unused. There is no doubt that they could support
a much greater population—and in greater comfort. Labor is crude and inefficient. Meanwhile, great natural resources go untapped. This does not arise from any innate
deficiency in their people. They devised the rudiments of
many modern inventions while our ancestors were still
wandering savages. The problem arises from the form
which social organization has taken in both countries. This
has shackled productive power and robbed industry of its
reward.
In India, from time immemorial, working classes have
been ground down by extortion and oppression into a condition of hopeless, and helpless, degradation. For ages,
peasants considered themselves happy if they could keep
enough to support life and save seed for the next crop. All
the wealth that could be wrung from the people was in the
possession of princes, who were little better than thieves.
Some they gave to their favorites; the rest they wasted in
useless luxury. Religion, reduced to an elaborate and terrible superstition, tyrannized their minds as physical force
did their bodies.
Capital could not be accumulated safely nor used to
assist production to any significant extent. Under these conditions, only arts that ministered to ostentation and luxury
could advance. Elephants of the rajah blazed with gold of
exquisite workmanship; umbrellas symbolizing his regal
power glittered with gems. But the plow of the ryot (peasant) was only a sharpened stick. Tools were of the poorest
and rudest description. Commerce could only be carried on
by stealth.
It is clear that this tyranny and insecurity produced
the want and starvation of India. Population did not pro-
Malthus vs. Facts
63
duce want, and want tyranny. As a chaplain with the East
India Company in 1796 noted:
“When we reflect upon the great fertility of Hindostan,
it is amazing to consider the frequency of famine. It is
evidently not owing to any sterility of soil or climate; the
evil must be traced to some political cause, and it requires
but little penetration to discover it in the avarice and extortion of the various governments. The great spur to industry, that of security, is taken away. Hence no man raises
more grain than is barely sufficient for himself, and the
first unfavorable season produces a famine.”
The good Reverend then goes on to describe the misery of the peasant in gloomy detail. The continuous violence produced a state under which “neither commerce nor
the arts could prosper, nor agriculture assume the appearance of a system.” This merciless rapacity would have produced want and famine even if the population were but
one to a square mile and the land a Garden of Eden.
British rule replaced this with a power even worse.
“They had been accustomed to live under tyranny, but never
tyranny like this,” the British historian Macaulay* explained. “It resembled the government of evil genii, rather
than the government of human tyrants.”
An enormous sum was drained away to England every year in various guises. The effect of English law was to
put a potent instrument of plunder in the hands of native
money lenders. Its rigid rules were mysterious proceedings to the natives. According to Florence Nightingale,
* Lord Thomas Macaulay (1800-1859), English historian, in his essay
on Lord Clive (1725-1774), the British general who led the conquest
of India.
64
Population and Subsistence
the famous humanitarian, terrible famines were caused by
taxation, which took the very means of cultivation from
farmers. They were reduced to actual slavery as “the consequences of our own [British] laws.” Even in faminestricken districts, food was exported to pay taxes.
In India now, as in times past, only the most superficial view can attribute starvation and want to the pressure
of population on the ability of land to produce subsistence.
Vast areas are still uncultivated, vast mineral resources untouched. If the farmers could keep some capital, industry
could revive and take on more productive forms, which
would undoubtedly support a much greater population.
The limit of the soil to furnish subsistence certainly has
not been reached.
It is clear that the true cause of poverty in India has
been, and continues to be, the greed of man—not the deficiency of nature.
What is true of India is true of China. As densely populated as China is in many parts, the extreme poverty of the
lower classes is not caused by overpopulation. Rather, it is
caused by factors similar to those at work in India.
Insecurity prevails, production faces great disadvantages, and trade is restricted. Government is a series of
extortions. Capital is safe only when someone has been
paid off. Goods are transported mainly on men’s shoulders. The Chinese junk must be constructed so it is unusable on the seas. And piracy is such a regular trade that
robbers often march in regiments.
Under these conditions, poverty would prevail and any
crop failure would result in famine, no matter how sparse
the population. China is obviously capable of supporting
a much greater population. All travelers testify to the great
Malthus vs. Facts
65
extent of uncultivated land, while immense mineral deposits exist untouched.
Neither in India nor China, therefore, can poverty
and starvation be charged to the pressure of population
against subsistence. Millions are not kept on the verge of
starvation (and occasionally pushed beyond it) by dense
population—but rather by causes that prevent the natural development of social organization and keep labor
from getting its full return.
Let me be clearly understood. I do not mean only that
India or China could maintain a greater population with a
more highly developed civilization. Malthusian doctrine
does not deny that increased production would permit a
greater population to find subsistence.
But the essence of that theory is that whatever the
capacity for production, the natural tendency of population is to press beyond it. This produces that degree of
vice and misery necessary to prevent further increase. So
as productive power increases, population will correspondingly increase. And in a little time, this will produce the
same results as before.
I assert that nowhere is there an example that will support this theory. Nowhere can poverty properly be attributed to population pressing against the power to procure
subsistence using the then-existing degree of human
knowledge. In every case, the vice and misery generally
attributed to overpopulation can be traced to warfare, tyranny, and oppression. These are the true causes that deny
security, which is essential to production, and prevent
knowledge from being properly utilized.
Later we will discover why population increase does
not produce want. For now, we are only concerned with
66
Population and Subsistence
the fact that it has not yet done so anywhere.
This fact is obvious with regard to India and China. It
also will be obvious wherever we track the true causes of
results that, on superficial view, are often assumed to come
from overpopulation.
Ireland, of all European countries, furnishes the great
stock example of alleged overpopulation. It is constantly
referred to as a demonstration of the Malthusian theory
worked out under the eyes of the civilized world. Proponents cite the extreme poverty of the peasantry, the low
wages, the Irish famine, and Irish emigration. I doubt if
we could find a more striking example of how a preaccepted theory has the power to blind people to the facts.
The truth is obvious. Ireland has never had a population it could not have maintained in ample comfort, given
the natural state of the country and the current state of
technological development. It is true, a large proportion
has barely existed, clothed in rags, with only potatoes for
food. When the potato blight came, they died by the thousands.
Did so many live in misery because of the inability of
the soil to support them? Is this why they starved on the
failure of a single crop?
On the contrary, it was the same remorseless greed
that robbed the Indian ryot of the fruits of his labor and
left him to starve where nature offered plenty. No merciless banditti plundered the land extorting taxes, as in Asia.
But the laborer was stripped just as effectively by a merciless horde of landlords. The soil had been divided among
them as their absolute possession, regardless of the rights
of those who lived upon it. Most farmers dared not make
improvements, even if the exorbitant rents left anything
Malthus vs. Facts
67
over. For to do so would only have led to a further increase
in rent. So labor was inefficient and wasteful. It was applied aimlessly, whereas had there been any security for its
fruits, it would have been applied continually.
Even under these conditions, it is a matter of fact that
Ireland did support eight million plus. For when her population was at its highest, Ireland was still a food exporting
country. Even during the famine, grain, meat, butter, and
cheese destined for export were carted past trenches piled
with the dead. So far as the people of Ireland were concerned, this food might as well have been burned or never
even produced. It went not as an exchange, but as a tribute.
The rent of absentee landlords was wrung from the producers by those who in no way contributed to production.
What if this food had been left to those who raised it?
What if they were able to keep and use the capital produced by their labor? What if security had stimulated industry and more economical production? There would have
been enough to support the largest population Ireland ever
had, and in bounteous comfort. The potato blight might
have come and gone without depriving even a single human being of a full meal.
It was not the imprudence of Irish peasants, as English economists coldly say, that made the potato the
staple of their food. Irish emigrants do not live upon the
potato when they can get other things. Certainly in the
United States, the prudence of the Irish character to save
something for a rainy day is remarkable. The Irish peasants lived on potatoes because rack rents stripped them
of everything else. The truth is that the poverty and misery of Ireland have never been fairly attributable to overpopulation.
68
Population and Subsistence
Writing this chapter, I have been looking over the literature of Irish misery. It is difficult to speak in civil terms
about the complacency with which Irish want and suffering is attributed to overpopulation. I know of nothing to
make the blood boil more than the grasping, grinding tyranny to which the Irish people have been subjected. It is
this, not any inability of the land to support its population, that caused Irish poverty and famine.
No matter how sparse the population or what the natural resources, poverty and starvation are inevitable consequences when the producers of wealth are forced to work
under conditions that deprive them of hope, self-respect,
energy, and thrift. They are inevitable when absentee landlords drain away, without return, at least a fourth of the
harvest. In addition, a starving industry must support resident landlords, with their horses and hounds, agents and
jobbers, middlemen and bailiffs, as well as an army of policemen and soldiers to hunt down any opposition to the
iniquitous system. Is it not blasphemy to blame this misery on natural law rather than on human greed?
What is true in these three cases will be found true
in all cases—if we examine the facts. As far as our knowledge goes, we may safely say there has never been a case
in which the pressure of population against subsistence
has caused poverty—or even a decrease in the production of food per person.
Overpopulation is no more the cause of the famines
of India, China, and Ireland than it is of the famines of
sparsely populated Brazil. And the limitations of Nature
are no more to blame for poverty than they are for the
millions slain by Genghis Khan.
Malthus vs. Analogies
69
Chapter 8
Malthus vs. Analogies
ATTEMPTS TO SUPPORT the Malthusian theory with analogies are just as inconclusive as those which use facts.
The strength of the reproductive force in the animal
and vegetable kingdoms is constantly cited, from Malthus
to current textbooks. For instance, if protected from their
natural enemies, a single pair of salmon might fill the entire ocean, or a pair of rabbits overrun a continent. Many
plants scatter seeds by the hundreds, and some insects deposit eggs by the thousands. Each species constantly tends
to press against the limits of subsistence, and when not
limited by its enemies, apparently does so.
These examples attempt to prove that human population also tends to press against subsistence. Unless restrained
by other means, this must necessarily result in low wages
and poverty. And if that is not enough, then actual starvation will keep it within the limits of subsistence.
But is this analogy valid?
The human food supply is drawn from the animal and
vegetable kingdoms. The reproductive force in the vegetable and animal kingdoms is greater than among humans. Hence, this analogy simply proves the power of
subsistence to increase faster than population. All of the
things that furnish human subsistence have the power to
multiply many fold, sometimes a million fold. Meanwhile,
70
Population and Subsistence
humanity is merely doubling (even according to Malthus).
Doesn’t this show that even if human beings increase to
the full extent of their reproductive power, population can
never exceed subsistence?
There is one additional fact. The actual limit to each
species lies in the existence of other species: its rivals, its
enemies, or its food.
Humans, however, can extend the conditions that normally limit those species giving our sustenance. (In some
cases, our mere appearance will accomplish this.) The reproductive forces of these species then begin to work in
service of humans. This increase continues at a pace that
our own powers of increase cannot rival. If we shoot hawks,
birds will increase; if we trap foxes, rabbits will multiply.
This distinction between humans and all other forms
of life destroys the analogy. Of all living things, only humans can manipulate reproductive forces stronger than
their own to supply themselves with food. Bird, insect,
beast, and fish take only what they find. They increase at
the expense of their food. But the increase of humans will
increase their food. The population of the United States,
once small, is now forty-five million. Yet there is much
more food per capita.
It is not the increase of food that has caused the increase of humans—rather, the increase of humans has
brought about an increase of food. There is more food simply because there are more people. This is the difference:
Both humans and hawks eat chickens—but the more
hawks, the fewer chickens; while the more humans, the
more chickens.
Moreover, human subsistence in any particular place
is not bound by the physical limit of that place, but of the
Malthus vs. Analogies
71
globe. Fifty square miles, using present agricultural practices, will yield subsistence for only a few thousand people.
Yet over three million people reside in London—and their
subsistence increases as population increases. So far as the
limit of subsistence is concerned, London may grow to a
hundred million or five hundred million. For it draws upon
the whole globe for subsistence. Its limit is the limit of the
globe to furnish food for its inhabitants.
But another idea arises that gives Malthus great support: the diminishing productiveness of land. Beyond a
certain point, so the argument goes, land yields less and
less to additional labor and capital. Otherwise, a growing
population would not extend cultivation to additional land.
Acknowledging this appears to involve accepting the doctrine that a growing population increases the difficulty of
obtaining subsistence.
But if we analyze this proposition, we see that it depends on an implied qualification. It is true in a relative
context, but not when taken absolutely. Production and
consumption are only relative terms. Speaking absolutely,
people neither produce nor consume. They cannot exhaust or lessen the powers of nature. If the whole human
race were to work forever, they could not make the Earth
one atom heavier or lighter. Nor could they augment or
diminish the forces that produce all motion and sustain
all life.*
Water taken from the ocean must eventually return to
the ocean. So too, the food we take from nature is, from
* George was writing before Einstein showed that matter could be
converted into energy. Modern physics speaks of the conservation of
matter/energy, which still supports George’s point.
72
Population and Subsistence
the moment we take it, on its way back to those same reservoirs. What we draw from a limited extent of land may
temporarily reduce the productiveness of that land. But
the return will go to other land.
Life does not use up the forces that maintain life. We
come into the material universe bringing nothing; we take
nothing away when we depart. The human being, in physical terms, is just a transitory form of matter, a changing
mode of motion.
From this, it follows that the limit to population can
be only the limit of space—that the human race may not
increase its numbers beyond the possibility of finding elbow room. Remote and shadowy as it is, this possibility is
what makes Malthus’ theory appear self-evident.
But there is still another difference: Humans are the
only animals whose desires increase as they are fed—the
only animal that is never satisfied. The wants of every other
living thing are fixed. The ox of today aspires to no more
than the ox that humans first yoked. The only use they
can make of additional supplies, or additional opportunities, is to multiply.
But not so humans. No sooner are our animal wants
satisfied than new wants arise. The beast never goes further, but humans have just set their foot on the first step
of an infinite progression.
Once the demand for quantity is satisfied, we seek quality. As human power to gratify our wants increases, our
aspirations grow. At the lower levels of desire, we seek
merely to satisfy our senses. Moving to higher forms of
desire, humans awaken to other things. We brave the desert
and the polar sea, but not for food; we want to know how
the earth was formed and how life arose. We toil to satisfy
Malthus vs. Analogies
73
a hunger no animal has felt, a thirst no beast can know.
Given more food and better conditions, animals and
vegetables can only multiply—but humans will develop.
In the one case, the expansive force can only extend in
greater numbers. In the other, it will tend to extend existence into higher forms and wider powers.
None of this supports Malthus’ theory. Facts do not
uphold it, and analogy does not support it. It is a pure
figment of the imagination, like the preconceptions that
kept people from recognizing that the earth was round
and moved around the sun.
This theory of population is as unfounded as if we
made an assumption about the growth of a baby from the
rate of its early months. Say it weighed ten pounds at birth
and twenty pounds at eight months. From this, we might
calculate a result quite as striking as that of Mr. Malthus.
By this logic it would be the size of an elephant at twelve,
and at thirty would weigh over a billion tons.
The fact is, there is no more reason to worry about the
pressure of population upon subsistence than there is to
worry about the rapid growth of a baby. We are no more
justified in assuming that overpopulation produces poverty than we are in assuming that gravity must hurl the
moon to the earth and the earth into the sun.
Malthus asserted what he called positive and prudential checks. A third check comes into play with the
development of intellect and increased standards of living. This is indicated by many well-known facts. The birth
rate is lower among classes whose wealth has brought
leisure, comfort, and a fuller life. It is higher among the
poor who, though in the midst of wealth, are deprived of
its advantages, and thus are reduced to an animal exist-
74
Population and Subsistence
ence. It is also higher in new settlements.*
This shows the real law of population. The tendency
to increase is not uniform. It is strong where a larger population would allow greater progress. It is also strong where
dangerous conditions threaten the survival of the race. It
weakens as higher development becomes possible, and survival is assured. In other words, the law of population conforms with, and is subordinate to, the law of intellectual
development.
Any difficulty providing for an increasing population
arises not from the laws of nature, but from social maladjustments. These are what condemn people to want in the
midst of wealth.
In the last two chapters, we have supported a negative. That is, we have shown that Malthusian theory is not
proved by the reasoning set forth to defend it. The next
chapter will take the affirmative and show that it is actually disproved by the facts.
* This insight is referred to today as the “demographic shift,” and is
extensively documented. In addition to the correlation of improved
living standards with lower fertility, modern researchers have found
that better-educated women tend to have fewer children, even when
their incomes do not actually increase.
Malthusian Theory Disproved
75
Chapter 9
Malthusian Theory Disproved
FACTS are the supreme and final test. The wide acceptance
of Malthusian theory is a remarkable example of how easily we can ignore facts when blinded by a preaccepted
theory. The question is whether an increasing population
necessarily tends to reduce wages and cause poverty. This
is the same as asking whether it reduces the amount of
wealth a given amount of labor can produce.
The accepted theory says that greater demands upon
nature produce diminishing results. That is, less will be
produced proportional to additional effort. Doubling labor will not double output. Thus, a growing population
must reduce wages and deepen poverty. John Stuart Mill
claimed a large population can never be provided for as
well as a smaller one.
All this I deny. In fact, I assert that the very opposite
is true.
I assert that a larger population can collectively
produce more than a smaller one (in any given state of
development).
I assert that poverty is not caused by overpopulation.
It is caused by social injustice, not by any limitation of
nature.
I assert that in the natural order of things, a growing
population can produce more than is required to provide
76
Population and Subsistence
for the increased numbers.
I assert that, other things being equal, each individual
would receive greater comfort in a larger population—
under an equitable distribution of wealth.
I assert that in a state of equality, the natural increase
of population would constantly tend to make every individual richer instead of poorer.
Thus taking issue with this theory, I submit the question to the test of facts.
But I must first warn the reader not to confuse the
issue, as even writers of great reputation have done. For
the question of fact into which this issue resolves itself is
not, what size population produces the most subsistence?
Rather it is, what size population has the greatest power to
produce wealth?
Power to produce wealth in any form is the same as
power to produce subsistence. Likewise, consumption of
wealth in any form is equivalent to consumption of subsistence.
For instance, I may choose to buy food or cigars or
jewelry. By spending on any particular item, I thereby
direct labor to produce that item. We may say a set of diamonds has a value equal to so many barrels of flour. In
other words, it takes (on average) the same amount of labor to produce those diamonds as it would to produce so
much flour. So giving my wife diamonds is as much an
exertion of subsistence-producing power as if I loaded her
with so many barrels of flour as an extravagant display.
Similarly, a race horse requires care and labor enough
for many work horses. A regiment of soldiers diverts labor
that could otherwise produce subsistence for thousands of
people.
Malthusian Theory Disproved
77
Thus, the power of any population to produce the necessities of life is not to be measured only by the necessities actually produced. Rather, it is measured by the total
expenditure of power in all forms of production. Therefore we must ask, does the relative power of producing
wealth decrease with an increasing population?
There is no need for abstract reasoning; the question
is one of simple fact. And the facts are so obvious that it is
only necessary to call attention to them.
In modern times, we have seen many communities increase their population—and advance even more rapidly
in wealth. Compare any communities having similar people
in a similar stage of development. Isn’t the most densely
populated community also the richest? Aren’t the more
densely populated Eastern states richer in proportion to
population than the more sparsely populated Western or
Southern states? Isn’t England, where population is even
denser, also richer in proportion?
Where will you find wealth most lavishly devoted to
nonproductive uses, such as extravagant buildings, fine furniture, gardens, and yachts? It is where population is dense
rather than sparse. Where will you find the greatest proportion of those supported by the general production, without productive labor on their part? By this I mean the range
of gentlemen of leisure, thieves, policemen, servants, lawyers, people of letters, and the like. It is where population
is thick rather than thin. In which direction does capital
for investment flow? It flows from densely populated countries to sparse ones.
Undeniably, wealth is greatest where population is
densest. Therefore, the amount of wealth produced by a
given amount of labor increases as population increases.
78
Population and Subsistence
This is apparent wherever we look.
Let’s examine a particular case: California. At first
glance, this appears to be perhaps the best example supporting Malthus. While population has increased, wages
have decreased. In addition, its natural productivity has
obviously lessened.
The wave of immigration that poured into California
with the discovery of gold found a country where nature
was in the most generous mood. Primitive tools could easily
extract gold from rivers where glittering deposits had been
built up over thousands of years. The plains were alive with
countless herds of horses and cattle, and soil was being
tilled for the first time. Amid this abundance, wages and
interest were higher than anywhere else in the world.
This virgin profusion has been steadily eroding under
the demands of an increasing population. Mining now requires elaborate machinery and great skill. Cattle are
brought in by rail. Some land now in use would barely
yield a crop without irrigation. During this time, wages
and interest have steadily declined. People will now work
a week for what they once got per day.
But is this cause and effect? Are wages lower because
the reduced productiveness of nature means labor yields
less wealth? On the contrary!
The power of labor to produce wealth in California in
1879 is not less than in 1849—it is greater. During these
years, the efficiency of labor has increased in many ways—by
roads, harbors, steamboats, telegraphs, and machinery of all
kinds; by a closer connection with the rest of the world; and
by countless economies resulting from a larger population.
No one who considers this can doubt an increase in
productiveness. The return that labor receives from nature
Malthusian Theory Disproved
79
is, on the whole, much greater now than it was in the days
of unmined minerals and virgin soil. The increase in human power has more than compensated for the decline in
natural factors.
In fact, consumption of wealth, compared to the number of laborers, is much greater now than it was then. Back
then, population consisted almost exclusively of working
men. Now there are many women and children who must
also be supported. Others who do not produce wealth have
also increased in greater proportion. Luxury has grown far
more than wages have fallen. The best houses once were
shanties; now there are mansions. The richest then would
seem little better than paupers today.
In short, there is striking and conclusive evidence that
the production and consumption of wealth has increased
faster than population. If any class gets less, it is for one
reason only—because the distribution of wealth has become more
unequal.
The same thing is obvious wherever we look. The richest countries are not those where nature is most prolific, but
those where labor is most efficient. Not Mexico, but Massachusetts. Not Brazil, but Britain. Other things being equal,
countries with the densest population devote the largest proportion of production to luxury and the support of nonproducers. They are the countries where capital overflows.
In emergency, such as war, they can stand the greatest drain.
Though a much smaller proportion of the population is engaged in productive labor, a much larger surplus is available
for purposes other than supplying physical needs.
On the other hand, in a new country the whole available workforce is involved in production. There are no
paupers or beggars. Neither are there idle rich, nor whole
80
Population and Subsistence
classes whose labor is devoted to ministering to the convenience or caprice of the rich. There is no literary or scientific class, no criminal class, and no class maintained to
guard against them.
Yet, even with the whole community devoted to production, there is no consumption of wealth as in the old
country. The condition of the lower classes, however, is
better. Everyone can earn a living. Yet no one gets much
more. Few, if any, can live in anything that would be called
luxury (or even comfort). In the older country, consumption of wealth in proportion to population is greater. At
the same time, the proportion of labor devoted to the production of wealth is less. In other words, fewer laborers
produce more wealth.
Let us consider one last argument. Could the greater
wealth of older countries be due to the accumulation of
wealth, not greater productive power?
The truth is, wealth can be accumulated only to a small
degree. Wealth consists of the material universe transformed by labor into desirable forms. As such, it constantly
tends to revert back to its original state. Some wealth will
last only a few hours, others for days, months, or even a
few years. But there are really very few forms of wealth
that can be passed from one generation to another.
Take wealth in some of its most useful and seemingly
permanent forms: ships, houses, machinery. Unless labor is
constantly applied to preserve and repair them, they will
quickly become useless. If labor were to stop in any community, wealth would vanish. When labor starts again,
wealth will reappear almost immediately. It is like the jet of
a fountain that vanishes when the flow of water is shut off.
This is clear where war or disaster has swept away
Malthusian Theory Disproved
81
wealth—but left the population unimpaired. London has
no less wealth today because of The Great Fire (1666).
Nor Chicago because of its fire (1871). On those fireswept acres, magnificent buildings, overflowing with
goods, have arisen. A visitor, unaware of history, would
never dream these stately avenues lay black and bare a
few short years ago.
This same principle is obvious in every new city—
namely, that wealth is constantly re-created. No one who
has seen Melbourne or San Francisco can doubt that if
the population of England were transported to New
Zealand—leaving all accumulated wealth behind—it
would soon be as rich as England is now. Conversely, if
England were reduced to the sparseness of New Zealand,
they would soon be as poor—despite their accumulated
wealth. Wealth from generations past can no more account
for present consumption than last year’s dinners can give
strength today.
In sum, a growing population means an increase—not
a decrease—in the average production of wealth. The reason for this is obvious. It so vastly increases the power of
the human factor that it more than compensates for any
reduction in the natural factor. Twenty people working
together, even where nature is scant, can produce more
than twenty times the wealth one person can produce where
nature is bountiful. The denser the population, the finer
the division of labor, and the greater the economies of production and distribution.
Thus we see that the very reverse of Malthusian doctrine is true. In any given state of civilization, a greater
number of people can produce a larger proportionate
amount of wealth than can a smaller number.
82
Population and Subsistence
Can anything be clearer? The weakness of natural
forces is not the cause of poverty festering in the centers
of civilization. Consider those countries where poverty is
deepest. If their productive forces were fully employed,
they could clearly provide enough for all. They could not
merely provide comfort, but luxury. Industrial paralysis and
depression obviously do not arise from lack of productive
power. Whatever the trouble may be, it is clearly not a
lack of ability to produce wealth.
Poverty appears where productive power is greatest and
the production of wealth is largest. This is the enigma that
perplexes the civilized world, the puzzle we are trying to
unravel. It is obvious that Malthusian theory cannot explain it. That theory is utterly inconsistent with all the
facts. It gratuitously attributes to the laws of God results
that spring from the social maladjustments of humans. But
we have yet to find exactly what does produce poverty amid
advancing wealth.
Their Necessary Relation
83
Third Part:
The Laws of Distribution
Chapter 10
The Necessary Relation
of the Laws of Distribution
OUR PRECEDING EXAMINATION has shown that the current
explanation for the persistence of poverty despite increasing wealth is no explanation at all. But by demolishing it,
we have made the facts appear even more inexplicable. We
have, in short, proved that wages should be highest where
they are actually lowest.
At least we have discovered where it is useless to look.
The cause of poverty is not lack of capital. Nor is it the
limitation of nature. In short, it is not found in laws governing the production of wealth. Therefore, we must examine the laws governing its distribution.
First, let’s outline the distribution of wealth. Since
land, labor, and capital join to produce wealth, the output must then be divided among these three. To discover
the cause of poverty, we will have to find the law that
determines what part is distributed to labor (wages). Then
to make sure this law is correct, we must also find the
laws fixing what part goes to capital (interest) and what
84
Laws of Distribution
part to landowners (rent).
Producing is not simply making things—it also includes increasing their value by transporting or exchanging them. Wealth is produced by the commercial
community, just as it is by the agricultural or manufacturing community. In each case, some of it will go to the
owners of capital, some to laborers, and some to the owners of land.
Additionally, since capital is constantly consumed and
constantly replaced, a portion of the wealth produced goes
toward the replacement of capital. It is not necessary to
take this replacement of capital into account, however. It
is eliminated by considering capital as continuous. We
habitually do this, both in speaking and thinking of it.
The produce of the community is the general fund
that supports all consumption. The term refers to wealth
produced beyond what is required to replace any capital
consumed in the process. Therefore, interest means what
goes to capital after its replacement or maintenance.
Furthermore, some of the wealth produced is taken by
government in taxes (except in the most primitive communities). Again, for our purposes in determining the laws
of distribution, we may consider taxation either as not existing or as reducing output by that amount. Certain forms
of monopoly exercise powers analogous to taxation, and
may be treated likewise. (We will discuss these in Chapter
13.) After we have discovered the laws of distribution, we
can then see what effect taxation has upon the process.
Economists do not understand these laws correctly, as
we may see in any standard text. In all these works, we are
told that the three factors of production are land, labor,
and capital, and that the entire output is distributed to
Their Necessary Relation
85
their corresponding parts. Therefore, three terms are
needed. Each should clearly express one part to the exclusion of the others.
Rent is defined clearly enough as the part that goes to
owners of land. The term wages is also defined clearly
enough as the part that is the return to labor. The third
term, then, should express the return for the use of capital.
But here, we find a problem. In standard economics
books, there is a puzzling ambiguity and confusion. The
term that comes closest to exclusively expressing the idea
of return to capital is interest. Interest implies the return
for the use of capital, exclusive of any labor in its use or
management, and also exclusive of risk.
Note that the word profits simply means what is received in excess of what is expended. Such receipts may include rent and interest and wages, including compensation
for risk.* Therefore, profits cannot be used to signify the
share going to capital—as distinct from that going to labor
and to landowners. The term has no place in discussing the
distribution of wealth between the three factors of production, unless extreme violence is done to its meaning.
To speak of the distribution of wealth into “rent, wages,
and profits” is like dividing mankind into “men, women,
and human beings.” Yet, to the utter bewilderment of the
reader, this is what is done in all standard works. Undoubtedly, thousands have vainly puzzled over this confusion of
terms, and abandoned their efforts in despair. Believing
the fault could not be in such great thinkers, they assumed
* Today, some attribute risk-taking to a distinct factor, called “entrepreneurism”. George defined labor as all human exertion in production, whether mental or physical.
86
Laws of Distribution
it must be their own stupidity. Reading John Stuart Mill,
you can see this confusion exemplified by the most logical
of English economists—in a manner more striking than I
care to characterize.
No text, to my knowledge, brings these laws together
so the reader can recognize their relation to each other.
Instead, each is enveloped in a mass of reflections and dissertations. The reason is not far to seek: Bringing together
the three laws of distribution, as they are now taught, shows
at a glance that they lack necessary relation.
The laws of distribution are obviously laws of proportion. They must relate to each other so that given any two,
the third may be inferred. To say that one part of the whole
is increased is to say that one or both of the other parts
must be decreased (or vice versa).
Say Tom, Dick, and Harry are business partners. The
agreement setting the share of one also sets the shares of
the other two, either jointly or separately. If Tom gets thirty
percent, that leaves seventy percent to be divided between
Dick and Harry. If Tom gets thirty percent and Harry fifty
percent, that fixes Dick’s share at twenty percent.
But in standard economic texts, there is no such relation among the laws of distribution of wealth. If we fish
these laws out and bring them together, we find them stated
as follows:
Wages are determined by the ratio between capital
available for labor and the number seeking employment.
Rent is determined by the margin of production. That
is, rent equals the amount of produce in excess of what
could be produced from the poorest land in use with the
same amount of labor and capital.
Interest is determined by the demands of borrowers
Their Necessary Relation
87
and the supply of capital from lenders.
Or, if we take what is given as the law of profits, it is
determined by wages, falling as wages rise and rising as wages
fall. (What Mill calls “the cost of labor to the capitalist.”)
Bringing these together, we immediately see a problem: They lack relation to each other, which the true laws
of distribution must have. Since they do not correlate, at
least two of the three must be wrong.
We must then seek the true laws of distribution that
divide what is produced into wages, rent, and interest. The
proof that we have found them will be in their correlation.
To recapitulate what we have discovered in our investigation:
Land, labor, and capital are the factors of production.
Land includes all natural opportunities or forces. Labor
includes all human exertion. Capital includes all wealth
used to produce more wealth.
The output is distributed in returns to these three factors. Rent is that part that goes to owners of land as payment
for the use of natural opportunities. Wages are that part that
constitutes the reward for human exertion. Interest is that
part that constitutes the return for the use of capital.
These terms mutually exclude each other. The income
of any individual may be made up from any one, two, or all
three of these sources. But to discover the laws of distribution we must keep them separate.
I think the error of political economy has now been
abundantly revealed, and can be traced to an erroneous
viewpoint.
We live in a society where capitalists generally rent land
and hire labor. They thus seem to be the initiators or first
movers in production. Living and making observations in
88
Laws of Distribution
this state, the great developers of economic science were led
to look on capital as the prime factor in production. They
saw land as its instrument, and labor as its agent or tool.
This is apparent on every page. It is in the form and course
of their reasoning, in the character of their illustrations, and
even in their choice of terms. Everywhere capital is the starting point, and the capitalist the central figure.
This goes so far that both Smith and Ricardo use the
term “natural wages” to express the minimum on which
laborers can live.
On the contrary, unless injustice is natural, everything
a laborer produces should be his natural wages. This habit
of looking on capital as the employer of labor began when
Adam Smith, in his first book, left the viewpoint that “the
produce of labor constitutes the natural recompense or wages
of labor.” Instead, he adopted the view in which capital is
considered as employing labor and paying wages.
But when we consider the origin and natural sequence
of things, we see that this reverses the natural order of things.
Capital does not come first, it comes last. Capital is not the
employer of labor—it is, in reality, employed by labor.
The matter that labor converts into wealth comes only
from land. There must be land before labor can be exerted.
And labor must be exerted before capital can be produced.
Capital is a result of labor, a form of labor, a subdivision of
the general term. It is only stored-up labor, used by labor
to assist it in further production. Labor is the active and
initial force. Therefore, labor is the employer of capital,
not vice versa—and it is even possible for labor to produce
wealth without being aided by capital.
So the natural order is this: land, labor, capital.
Instead of using capital as our initial point, we should
start from land.
Law of Rent
89
Chapter 11
The Law Of Rent
RENT, IN THE ECONOMIC SENSE, is the part of the produce
that accrues to the owners of land (or other natural capabilities) by virtue of ownership.
This differs from the everyday meaning in several respects. Common speech mixes payments for use of improvements with payments for use of bare land. When we
speak of renting a house (or farm or factory), we combine
the price for using land with the price for using buildings,
machinery, fixtures, etc. But in the economic sense, rent
means only what is paid for using land. We must exclude
payments for the use of any product of human exertion.
Anything paid for buildings or other improvements is compensation for the use of capital. This is properly called
interest.
But the economic meaning is broader in a different
sense. In common speech, we speak of rent only when the
owner and the user are two different people. Yet in the
economic sense, there is rent even when the same person
is both. In this case, rent is what she might get if she rented
the land to someone else. Or, to look at it another way, the
return for her labor and capital (i.e., her wages and interest) is the part of her income equal to what she would
make if she had to rent the land, instead of owning it.
Rent is also expressed in the selling price of land. This
90
Laws of Distribution
price is payment for the right to perpetual use. In other
words, it is rent capitalized. If I buy land and hold it until
I can sell it for more, I will become rich—not from wages
for my labor nor interest for my capital—but merely by
rising rents.
Rent, in short, is the share of wealth given to landowners because they have an exclusive right to the use of
those natural capabilities.
Wherever land has an exchange value, there is rent
in the economic meaning of the term. If in use, there is
actual rent. If land is not in use but still has a value, there
is potential rent. It is this capacity of yielding rent that
gives land its value.
Until ownership confers some advantage, land has no
value. Therefore, land value does not arise from its productiveness or usefulness. No matter what its capabilities,
land has no value until some one is willing to pay for the
privilege of using it.
Rent does not, in any way, represent any aid or advantage to production. Rent is simply the power to take part
of the results of production.
Furthermore, the amount anyone will pay for land does
not depend on its capacity. Rather, it depends on its capacity compared to land that is available for free. Even very
good land has no value as long as other land, just as good,
is available without cost. But as soon as this other land is
appropriated—and the best land now available for nothing is inferior (either in fertility, location, or some other
quality)—then my land will have value and will begin to
yield rent. Now, suppose my land becomes less productive.
The rent I can get might still increase! Rent will increase
if the productiveness of land available without charge
Law of Rent
91
decreases even more.
Rent, in short, is the price of monopoly. It arises from
individual ownership of the natural elements—which human exertion can neither produce nor increase.
If one person owned all the land in a community, he
or she could demand any price desired for its use. As long
as that ownership was acknowledged, the others would
have no alternative (except death or emigration). This,
indeed, has been the case many times in the past.
In modern society, land is usually owned by too many
different people for the price to be fixed by whim. While
owners try to get all they can, there is a limit to what they
can obtain. This market price (or market rent) varies with
different lands and at different times.
The law of rent, then, will be the law or relation that
determines what rent or price an owner can get under free
competition. (To discover the principles of political
economy, we must always assume free competition among
all parties.)
Fortunately, economists agree on this point. It is an
accepted dictum of political economy, with the self-evident character of a geometric axiom. Of course, in all the
nonsense printed as economics in its present disjointed
condition, it would be hard to find anything that has not
been disputed. Yet all economic writers regarded as authorities endorse this law.
Often called Ricardo’s law of rent,* it has been exhaustively explained by all leading economists after him. It applies not only to farmland, but to land used for other
* David Ricardo (1772-1823) English economist. Although not the
first to state the law of rent, he brought it into prominence.
92
Laws of Distribution
purposes, and to all natural agencies, such as mines, fisheries, etc. It says:
The rent of land is determined by the excess of its production over that which the same application can secure from the
least productive land in use.
The effect of competition is to take the lowest reward
for which labor and capital will engage in production and
make that the highest they can claim. In other words, owners of more productive land are able to seize, in rent, everything above what labor and capital can obtain from the
least productive land in use.
We can say the same thing in a slightly different form:
Landowners can claim everything above what the same
application of labor and capital could secure in the least
productive occupation in which they can freely engage.
Since any occupation requires the use of land, this
amounts to precisely the same thing. Furthermore, all
things considered, lands will be used until the poorest
return equals the lowest compensation in other pursuits.
For instance, if farming paid more, clearly some labor
and capital engaged in other pursuits would turn to agriculture. This will continue until the yield to labor and capital in both pursuits reaches the same level, all things
considered. The process may be driven by extending cultivation to inferior land. Or the relative value of manufactured products may increase as production slows. In fact,
both processes may be at work. Regardless, the final point
at which manufacturing is still carried on will also be the
point to which cultivation is extended.
The law of rent is, in fact, a deduction from the law of
competition. In the final analysis, it rests on a principle as
Law of Rent
93
fundamental to political economy as the law of gravity is
to physics. Namely, that people seek to gratify their desires with the least exertion.
Ever since Ricardo, the basic law itself has been clearly
understood and recognized— but its corollaries have not.
Yet these are as plain as the simplest geometry. Wealth is
divided among rent, wages, and interest. Therefore, the
law of rent is necessarily the law of wages and interest
taken together.
In algebraic form:
Production = Rent + Wages + Interest.
Production – Rent = Wages + Interest.
Thus, wages and interest do not depend on what labor and capital produce—they depend on what is left
after rent is taken out. No matter how much they might
actually produce, they receive only what they could get
on land available without rent—on the least productive
land in use. Landowners take everything else. Hence, no
matter how much productive power increases, neither
wages nor interest can rise if the increase in rent keeps
pace with it.
Recognizing this simple relationship immediately illuminates what had seemed inexplicable. Increasing rent
is the key that explains why wages and interest fail to increase with greater productivity.
The wealth produced in every community is divided
into two parts by what may be called the rent line—that
is, by the return that labor and capital could obtain from
natural opportunities available without rent. Wages and
interest are paid from below this line. Everything above it
goes to rent.
94
Laws of Distribution
Thus, where land values are low, wages and interest
are high—even if relatively little wealth is produced. We
see this in new countries. In older countries, a larger amount
of wealth may be produced. Yet where the value of land is
high, wages and interest are low.
Productive power is increasing in all developing countries—but wages and interest do not follow. Rather, they
are controlled by how rent is affected. Wages and interest
can increase only when land values do not increase as
quickly as productivity.
All of this is demonstrated in actual fact.
Cause of Interest
95
Chapter 12
The Cause of Interest
WE HAVE DETERMINED the law of rent and its necessary
corollaries. Still, let’s seek each law separately and independently—without deduction from the law of rent. If we
discover them independently—and find they correlate—
then our conclusions will be certain. To start, let’s examine
the general subject of interest.
I have already warned of confusing profits with interest. Additionally, the economic meaning differs from common usage. Interest properly includes all returns for the
use of capital—not just payments from borrower to lender.
Further, the economic meaning excludes compensation for risk—which makes up a great part of what is commonly called interest. But compensation for risk is merely
an equalization of return between different uses of capital.
We want to discover what determines the general rate of
interest proper.
Rates also vary considerably in different countries and
at different times. Interest generally has been higher in the
United States than in England. Indeed, it has long been
well known that interest tends to sink as society progresses.
What can bind these variations together and reveal their
cause? It is obvious that current explanations run counter to
facts. It is easily proved that interest does not depend on productiveness, for interest is lowest where labor and capital are
96
Laws of Distribution
most productive. Nor does interest vary inversely with wages.
The fact is, interest is high when and where wages are high.
Likewise, low interest and low wages are found together.
So let us begin at the beginning. Even at the risk of
digressing, we must establish the cause of interest before
considering its law. In other words, why should borrowers
pay back more than they received from lenders? Why
should there be interest at all?
The standard texts all claim interest is a reward for
abstinence. But abstinence is a passive quality, not an active one. Abstinence in itself produces nothing. So why
should part of anything produced be given for it? If I bury
my money for a year, I have exercised as much abstinence
as if I had loaned it. Yet when loaned, I expect it to be
returned with an additional sum as interest.
Some may say I provide a service to the borrower by
lending my capital. But the borrower also does me a service by keeping it safely. Under some conditions, such a
service may be very valuable. Many forms of capital must
be constantly maintained, an onerous task if there is no
immediate use for them. The secure preservation, the maintenance, or the restoration of capital is an offset to its use.
So isn’t the debt discharged when the capital is returned?
Accumulation is the purpose of abstinence. It can do
no more. In fact, by itself, it can’t even do this. Think how
much wealth would disappear in just a few years if we simply abstained from using it!
Bastiat* and many others say the basis of interest is
* Frederic Bastiat (1801-1850), French economist, gave a well-known
illustration of interest involving the loan of a carpenter’s plane. George’s
analysis of the fallacies in this illustration is somewhat complex. It is
not necessary for our discussion here.
Cause of Interest
97
“the power which exists in tools to increase the productiveness of labor.” Clearly, however, this is not the basis in
justice or in fact. A fallacy allows it to pass as conclusive to
those who do not stop to analyze it. It is true that tools
increase labor’s productive power. The mistake lies in assuming that the loan transfers this power. This is really
not involved.
The essential thing loaned is not the increased power
that labor acquires. To suppose this, we would have to assume that such things were trade secrets or patent rights. In
such case, the illustration would become one of monopoly,
not capital. The essential thing loaned is this: the use of the
concrete results of the effort expended in producing the
tools—not the privilege of applying labor in a more effective way.
If interest were based on increased productiveness, the
rate of interest would increase with technology. This is
not so. Nor do I expect to pay more to borrow a fiftydollar sewing machine than to borrow fifty dollars’ worth
of needles. Nor if I borrow a steam engine rather than a
pile of bricks.
Capital, like wealth, is interchangeable. It is not one
particular thing—it is anything within the circle of exchange. Moreover, tools and machinery do not add to the
reproductive power of capital—they add to the productive power of labor.
Now, consider for a moment a world in which wealth
consisted only of inert matter, and production was only
working this inert matter into different shapes. Such things
have no reproductive power of their own. If I put away
hammers or barrels or money, they will not increase.
But suppose, instead, I put away wine. At the end
98
Laws of Distribution
of a year, the wine will have improved in quality and its
value will be greater. Or suppose I release a swarm of
bees. At the end of a year, I will have more bees, as well
as the honey they have made. Or suppose I put cattle
out on the range. At the end of the year, I will, on average, also have an increase.
What provides the increase in these cases is something
distinct and separate from labor. Though it generally requires labor to make use of it, we can readily distinguish it
from labor. It is the active power of nature—the principle
of growth, or reproduction, which characterizes all forms
of what we call life.
It seems to me that this is the true cause of interest—
that is, the increase of capital over and above that due to
labor. Certain powers in nature—with a force independent of our own efforts—help us turn matter into forms
we desire. In other words, they aid us in producing wealth.
Both types of things are included in the terms wealth
and capital—things that have no innate power of increase,
and things that yield over and above what can be attributed to labor. With inanimate things, labor alone is the
efficient cause. When labor stops, all production stops. But
in these other modes, time is an element. The seed grows
whether the farmer sleeps or works.
Furthermore, there are also variations in the powers of
nature and of people. Through exchange, these variations
can be used to obtain an increase in net output. This somewhat resembles the increase produced by the vital forces
of nature.
For instance, in one place a given amount of labor
will secure either what we may call 200 units of vegetable
food or 100 units of animal food. In another place, the
Cause of Interest
99
conditions are reversed: The same amount of labor will
produce 100 of vegetable or 200 of animal food. The relative value of animal to vegetable food will be two to one
in one location, but one to two in the other. If equal
amounts are required, the same amount of labor in either
place will secure 150 units of both. But suppose in one
place labor is used to procure vegetables, while in the
other to procure animal food. Then an exchange is made
in the quantity required. Thus, the people of each place—
with the same amount of labor—will acquire 200 of both
(less the losses and expenses of exchange). In each place,
the product that is exchanged brings back an increase.
Since wealth is interchangeable, it necessarily involves
an average between all types of wealth. So any special advantage that accrues from the possession of any one particular type must be averaged with all others. For no one
would keep capital in one form when it could be changed
into a more advantageous form.
So, in any circle of exchange, the power of increase
that nature gives to some forms of capital must be averaged with all forms of capital. Thereby, those who lend
money or bricks are not deprived of the power to obtain
an increase. They will get the same as if they had lent (or
used) an equivalent amount of capital in a form capable of
increase.
This general averaging—or “pooling” of advantages—
inevitably takes place wherever society carries on different
modes of production simultaneously. Thus, all types of
wealth maintain similar advantages. In the final analysis,
the advantage given by time comes from the generative
force of nature and from the varying powers of nature and
of people. If the quality and capacity of matter everywhere
100
Laws of Distribution
were uniform, and if productive power existed only in humans, then there would be no interest.
If I have a thousand dollars, I can certainly loan it out
at interest. But that does not arise because those without
funds would gladly pay me for the use of it. Rather, it comes
from the fact that capital, which my money represents,
has the power to yield an increase. The price something
will bring does not depend so much on what the buyer
would be willing to give rather than go without it—it depends on what the seller can get otherwise. Interest is not
a payment made for the use of capital—it is a return accruing from the increase of capital.
In short, then, when we analyze production, it falls
into three modes:
ADAPTING—Changing natural products, in form or
place, to fit them to satisfy human desire.
GROWING—Utilizing the vital forces of nature, as in
raising vegetables or animals.
EXCHANGING— Increasing the general sum of wealth
by exploiting local variations in the forces of nature, or variations among human forces due to situation, occupation, or character.
In adapting, capital gains its benefit in its use. In growing, the benefits arise not from use but from increase. In
exchanging, capital is exchanged rather than used. The benefit is in the increase, or greater value, of things received in
return. Essentially, benefits arising from use go to labor;
those from increase go to capital.
But the division of labor and the interchangeability of
wealth compel an averaging of benefits. For neither labor
nor capital will pursue any method of production while
Cause of Interest
101
another is available offering a greater return.
We can say this another way. In adapting, labor will
not get the whole return—but less enough to give capital
the increase it could have gotten in the other modes. Likewise, capital in the second and third modes will not get
the whole increase—but less enough to give labor the reward it could have gotten from the first mode.
Thus, interest springs from the power of increase given
to capital by the reproductive forces of nature, or by the
analogous capacity of exchange. This is not arbitrary, it is
natural. It is not the result of a particular social organization, but of laws of the universe.
102
Laws of Distribution
Chapter 13
False Interest
THE BELIEF that interest is a form of robbery is, I am persuaded, largely due to a failure to discriminate between
what is really capital and what is not. True interest is often
confused with revenue from sources other than use of capital. In common speech, we call anyone a “capitalist” who
makes money independent of labor. Further, anything received from any kind of investment is labeled interest. Before we decide whather labor and capital really are in
conflict we should clear up some misconceptions that
might cloud our judgment.
An enormous part of what is commonly called capital
is actually land value—it is not capital at all. Rent is not
the earnings of capital, and must be carefully separated from
interest.
Additionally, what are properly termed “wages of superintendence” are often confused with the earnings of
capital. This includes income derived from such personal
qualities as skill, tact, and organizational ability.
Stocks and bonds constitute another large part of what
is commonly called capital. These are not capital either—
they are simply evidence of indebtedness. Always remember that nothing can be capital that is not wealth. It must
consist of actual, tangible things that satisfy human desires. They can not be the spontaneous offerings of nature.
False Interest
103
And they must fulfill our desires by themselves, directly
or indirectly, but not by proxy.
Thus, a government bond is not capital—nor does it
even represent capital. Any capital once received for it has
been shot from cannons or used to keep men marching
and drilling. The bond cannot represent capital that has
been destroyed. It is simply a declaration that, some time
in the future, the government will take, by taxation, so
much wealth from the general stock then existing among
the people. This it will turn over to the bondholders when
the bond matures. Meanwhile, from time to time, it will
take, by taxation, a certain amount to give as interest. The
amount will be enough to make up whatever increase the
bondholders would have received if they had kept the original capital. Immense sums are taken from the production
of every modern country to pay interest on public debt.
These are not the earnings or increase of capital. They are
not even interest, in the strict sense of the term. They are
taxes levied on labor and capital—leaving less for wages
and less for true interest.
But suppose the bonds were issued for deepening a
river bed or erecting a lighthouse? Or, to modify the illustration, suppose they were issued by a railroad company?
These may be considered evidence of ownership of capital. But only so far as they represent real capital—existing
and applied to productive uses—and not bonds issued in
excess of actual capital used.
All too often, certificates are issued for two, three, or
even ten times the amount of actual capital used. The excess (over what is due as interest on the real capital invested) is regularly paid out as “interest” or dividends on
this fictitious amount. Large sums are also absorbed by
104
Laws of Distribution
management and never accounted for. All this is taken
from the aggregate production of the community—but not
for services rendered by capital.
There is another element contributing to the profits
we are speaking of here. That element is monopoly.
When the king granted his minion the exclusive privilege to make gold thread, the handsome income enjoyed
as a result did not arise from interest on capital invested in
manufacturing. Nor did it come from the talent and skill
of those who actually did the work. It came from an exclusive privilege. It was, in reality, the power to levy a tax
(for private enjoyment) on all users of such thread.
Much of the profits commonly confused with earnings of capital come from a similar source. Receipts from
patents granted to encourage invention are clearly attributable to this source. So are returns from monopolies created by protective tariffs under the pretense of encouraging
home industry.
But there is another form of monopoly, far more general and far more insidious. The accumulation of large
amounts of capital under consolidated control creates a
new kind of power—essentially different from the power
of increase. Increase is constructive in its nature. Power
from accumulation is destructive. It is often exercised with
reckless disregard, not only to industry but to the personal
rights of individuals.
A railroad approaches a small town as a robber approaches his victim.* “Agree to our terms or we will bypass
your town” is as effective a threat as “your money or your
* Nowadays, this could describe the way that “big-box” retail stores
approach communities.
False Interest
105
life.” As robbers unite to plunder and divide the spoils, the
trunk lines of railroads unite to raise rates and pool their
earnings. The public is then forced to pay the cost of the
whole maneuver, as the vanquished are forced to pay the
cost of their own enslavement by a conquering army.
Profits properly due to the elements of risk are also
frequently mislabeled interest. Some people acquire
wealth by taking chances in ventures where most suffer
losses. There are many such forms of speculation, especially that method of gambling known as the stock market. Nerve, judgment, and possession of capital give an
advantage. Also, those skills known as the arts of the confidence man. But, just as at a gaming table, whatever one
person gains someone else must lose.
Everyone knows the tyranny and greed with which
capital, when concentrated in large amounts, is frequently
wielded to corrupt, rob, and destroy. What I wish to call
the reader’s attention to here is this:
These profits should not be confused with the legitimate returns of capital as an agent of production. Any analysis will show that much of what is commonly confused with
interest is really the result of the power of concentrated capital. For the most part, this should be attributed to bad legislation, blind adherence to ancient customs, and
superstitious reverence for legal technicalities.
Examine the great fortunes said to exemplify the accumulative power of capital: the Rothschilds, the Vanderbilts,
the Astors. They have been built up, to a greater or lesser
degree, by the means we have been reviewing — not by
interest. When we find the general cause that tends to concentrate wealth, and thus power, in advancing communities, we will have the solution to our problem.
106
Laws of Distribution
Chapter 14
The Law Of Interest
WE MAY NOW SEEK the law of interest, recalling two things:
Capital does not employ labor; labor employs capital. Capital is not a fixed quantity; the amount can be increased or
decreased.
Capital is simply wealth applied in a certain way—
wealth being the larger category. Therefore, capital can be
increased (1) by applying more labor to its production; or
(2) by converting wealth into capital. Likewise, capital can
be decreased (1) by applying less labor; or (2) by converting capital back into wealth.
Under free conditions, the maximum that can be given
for the use of capital is the increase it will bring. Above this,
borrowing capital would involve a loss. The minimum is
the replacement of capital, or else capital could not be maintained. Interest will vary between these two points.
We must repeat: the maximum is not fixed—as some
writers carelessly state—by the increased efficiency capital gives to labor. Rather, the maximum is set by the average power of increase that belongs to capital in general.
The power of applying itself in advantageous forms is a
power of labor. Capital, as capital, cannot claim nor share in
this. Indians using only sticks and stones might kill one
buffalo a week. Yet with bows and arrows, they may kill one
every day. But the tribe’s weapon maker would not claim six
Law of Interest
107
out of seven buffaloes. Neither will capital invested in a
woolen factory entitle the owner to the difference between
the output of the factory and what could be made with a
spinning wheel. The march of knowledge has made these
advantages a common property and power of labor.
We established (in chapter 12) that the cause of interest is the vital forces of nature that give an advantage to
the element of time. And this should set the maximum
rate of interest. But the reproductive force of nature varies
enormously. For instance, if I raise rabbits and you raise
horses, my rabbits will multiply faster than your horses.
But my capital will not increase faster! The effect of the
varying rates will be to lower the value of rabbits compared to horses. Thus, differences are brought to a uniform level that determines the average increase of capital.
Whatever this point, it must be such that the reward
to capital and the reward to labor will be equal. That is to
say, the normal point of interest will give an equally attractive result for the exertion or sacrifice involved.
For labor and capital are merely different forms of
the same thing—human exertion. Capital is produced
by labor. It is labor impressed upon matter. This labor
has been stored up to be released as needed—as the heat
of the sun is stored in coal. Capital can be used only by
being consumed. In order for it to be maintained, labor
must produce it in proportion to its consumption in aiding labor. Therefore, capital used in production is simply
a mode of labor.
Under free competition, a principle operates to
maintain this equilibrium between wages and interest.
This principle is: People seek to gratify their desires with
the least exertion.
108
Laws of Distribution
The natural relation between interest and wages is an
equilibrium at which both will represent equal return for
equal exertion. Although this may be stated in a form that
suggests opposition, this is only in appearance. For each gets
only what they add to the common fund. Increasing the
portion of one does not decrease what the other receives.
We are, of course, speaking of the general rate of wages
and the general rate of interest. In a particular case or a
particular occupation, this equilibrium may be impeded.
But it will act quickly between the general rate of wages
and the general rate of interest. A particular situation may
have a clean line between labor and those who furnish
capital. Yet even in communities where this distinction is
the sharpest, the two shade off into each other by imperceptible gradations, until they meet in the same persons.
Here, the interaction that restores equilibrium goes on
without obstruction.
Furthermore, remember that capital is only a portion of wealth. It is distinguished from wealth only by
the purpose it is used for. Hence, the whole body of wealth
has an equalizing effect. This operates like a flywheel:
taking up capital when there is excess, and giving it out
again when there is lack. A jeweler may wear her diamonds while she is overstocked, but returns them to the
showcase when stock is low. If interest rises above the
equilibrium with wages, it produces two results: It will
direct labor to produce capital. It will also direct wealth
to be used as capital. Meanwhile, if wages rise above the
equilibrium, that will also produce two results: Labor will
turn away from producing capital. And the proportion
of wealth used as capital will be reduced, as some will
now be diverted to nonproductive uses.
Law of Interest
109
Thus, there is a certain relation between wages and
interest, which changes slowly, if at all. Hence, interest
must rise or fall with wages.
To illustrate: The price of flour is determined by the
price of wheat and cost of milling. Even over long intervals, the cost of milling hardly varies. But the price of wheat
varies greatly and frequently. Hence, we correctly say that
the price of flour is governed by the price of wheat.
To put this in the same form as the preceding discussion: The cost of milling fixes a certain relation between
the value of wheat and the value of flour. This ratio is constantly maintained by the interaction between the demand
for flour and the supply of wheat. Hence, the price of flour
must rise and fall with the price of wheat. We can leave
the connecting link, the price of wheat, to inference. We
would then say that the price of flour depends upon the
character of the seasons, wars, etc.
In the same way, we can put the law of interest in a
form that connects it directly with the law of rent. The
general rate of interest, then, will be determined by the
return to capital on the poorest land freely available. That
is to say, the return from the best land open to it without
the payment of rent. The law of interest, therefore, is shown
to be a corollary of the law of rent.
We can prove this conclusion another way. If we were
to eliminate wages, we could plainly see that interest must
decrease as rent increases. Of course, to do this we must
imagine a place where production occurs without labor.
Houses grow from seeds, and a jackknife thrown on the
ground bears a crop of assorted cutlery.*
* A modern reader might imagine a land of robots in the near future.
110
Laws of Distribution
Capitalists here would keep all the wealth produced
from their capital—but only as long as none of it was demanded in rent. When rent arose, it would come from
their interest. As rent increased, the return to the owners
of capital must necessarily decrease. If this place were an
island, interest would fall to just above its minimum (mere
replacement) as soon as capital reached the limit of the
island to support it. Landowners would receive almost the
entire output—for the only alternative would be for capitalists to throw their capital into the sea.
This, in sum, is the law of interest:
The relation between wages and interest is determined by
the average power of increase that attaches to capital from its
use in reproductive modes. As rent arises, interest will fall as
wages fall, or will be determined by the margin of production.
In truth, the principal distribution of wealth is into
two—not three—parts. Capital is simply a form of labor.
Its distinction is a subdivision, like dividing labor into
skilled and unskilled. That is to say, wealth is divided between the possessors of two factors: (1) natural substances
and forces, and (2) human exertion. For all wealth is produced by the union of these two factors.
Law of Wages
111
Chapter 15
The Law Of Wages
THERE IS no common rate of wages in the same sense as the
common rate of interest, which is relatively specific at any
given time and place. Wages vary with individual abilities. As
society becomes more complex, there are also large variations
among occupations. Nevertheless, there is a certain general
relation between all wages. This concept—that wages are
higher or lower at one time or place than another—is quite
clear. So wages must rise and fall according to some law.
There is a law as basic to political economy as the law
of gravity is to physics. The fundamental principle of human action is this:
People seek to gratify their desires with the least exertion.
Clearly, this principle will tend, through competition,
to balance rewards for equal exertion under similar circumstances. When people work for themselves, this operates largely through price fluctuations. The same tendency
governs relationships between those who work for themselves and those who work for others. Given free conditions, no one would work for someone else if they could
make the same amount working for themselves.
But output does not depend only on the intensity or
quality of labor. Wealth is the product of two factors—
land and labor. A given amount of labor yields various re-
112
Laws of Distribution
sults, depending on the powers of the natural opportunities to which it is applied. This is easily seen in fundamental occupations, which still form the base of
production—even in the most highly developed societies.
People will not work at a lower point while a higher
one is available. So, the highest point of natural productiveness available will be same as the lowest point at which production continues. This is called the margin of production.
Wages will be set by the output at the most productive point open to labor. They will rise or fall as this point
rises or falls.
To illustrate, consider a simple society in which each
person is self-employed. Let’s say some hunt, some fish,
some farm. At first, all land being used yields a similar return for similar effort. Allowing for differences of ease, risk,
and so on, wages will be approximately equal in each. That
is, equal exertions will yield equal results for hunting, fishing, or farming. Wages will be the total production of labor.
(Remember, even though there are no employers yet, there
are still wages—that is, the return for labor. But no one
would work for someone else, at this stage, unless they received the full, average results of labor.)
Time passes. Cultivation now occurs on land of different quality. Wages will no longer be as before—the full,
average production of labor. Instead, wages will be the average at the margin of production—the point of lowest
return. Since people seek to satisfy their desires with the
least exertion, this point will yield a return to labor equivalent to the average return in hunting and fishing.
This equalization in return will be brought about by
prices. Labor no longer yields equal returns for equal exertion. Those working superior land get greater results,
Law of Wages
113
for the same exertion, than those on inferior land. Wages,
however, are still equal. The excess received from superior
land is, in reality, properly called rent. If land has been
subjected to individual ownership, this is what gives it value.
Circumstances have changed. To hire others, an employer need pay only what the labor yields at the lowest
point of cultivation. If the margin of production sinks lower,
wages will also drop. If it should rise, wages must also rise.
We have deduced the law of wages from an obvious
and universal principle—that people will seek to satisfy
their wants with the least exertion. Wages depend on the
margin of production. They will be greater or less depending on what labor can get from the best natural opportunities available to it.
We deduced this from simple states. If we examine
the complex phenomena of highly civilized societies, the
same law applies. Wages differ widely in these societies,
but they still bear a fairly definite and obvious relationship to each other.
Of course, this relation is not invariable. A well-known
entertainer may earn many times the wages of the best
mechanic, yet at some other time the same entertainer may
barely command the pay of a footman. Some jobs pay high
wages in big cities, while in a small town the pay is low.
We need not dwell on what causes wages to vary among
different jobs. This has been admirably explained by Adam
Smith and the economists who followed him.* They have
* Adam Smith has summarized these circumstances. They include: the
difficulty of the job itself; the difficulty and expense of training; the
constancy of employment; the degree of responsibility; and the probability of success. The last is analogous to the element of risk in profits
It accounts for the high wages of successful doctors, lawyers, actors, etc.
114
Laws of Distribution
worked out the details quite well—even if they failed to
comprehend the main law.
It is perfectly correct to say that wages of different
occupations vary according to supply and demand. Demand means the request that the community makes for
particular services. Supply is the relative amount of labor
available to perform those particular services.
However, when we hear (as we often do) that the general rate of wages is determined by supply and demand,
those words are meaningless. For supply and demand can
only be relative terms. Demand for labor can only mean
that some product of labor is offered in exchange for (other)
labor. Likewise, the supply of labor can only mean labor
offered in exchange for the products of labor.
Thus, supply is demand, and demand is supply. In the
whole community, they must be coextensive with each
other. Wages can never permanently exceed the production of labor.
The high wages of some occupations resemble lottery
prizes, where the great gain of one is taken from the losses
of many others. This accounts for the high wages of successful doctors, lawyers, actors, and the like. It is also largely
true of wages of superintendence in mercantile pursuits,
for over ninety percent of such firms ultimately fail.
Greater abilities or skill, whether natural or acquired,
command (on average) greater wages. These qualities are
essentially analogous to differences in strength or quickness in manual labor. Higher wages, paid to those who
can do more, are based on the wages of those who can
only do an average amount. So wages in occupations requiring superior abilities must depend on common wages
paid for ordinary abilities. In these occupations, the de-
Law of Wages
115
mand is more uniform and there is the greatest freedom
to engage in them.
These gradations of wages shade into each other by
imperceptible degrees. In each occupation, there are those
who combine it with others, or alternate between fields.
All mechanics could work as laborers, and many laborers
could easily become mechanics. Mechanics generally earn
more than laborers. Still, there are always some mechanics
who do not make as much as some laborers. The best paid
lawyers receive much higher wages than the best paid
clerks. Yet, the best paid clerks make more than some lawyers. In fact, the worst paid clerks make more than the
worst paid lawyers. Meanwhile, young people coming into
the ranks are drawn to the strongest incentive and least
obstruction.
Thus, the differences between occupations are so finely
balanced that the slightest change is enough to guide their
labor in one direction or another. Experience shows that
this equilibrium will be maintained even in the face of
artificial barriers. They may interfere with this interaction, but they cannot prevent it. They operate only as dams,
which pile up the water of a stream above its natural level,
but cannot prevent its overflow.
Thus, it is evident that wages in all strata must ultimately depend upon wages in the lowest and widest stratum. The general rate of wages will rise or fall as the lowest
wages rise or fall. The primary and fundamental occupations, on which all the others are built, are those that obtain wealth directly from nature. Hence the law of wages
applying to those occupations must be the general law of
wages. And wages in such occupations clearly depend upon
what labor can produce at the lowest point of natural pro-
116
Laws of Distribution
ductiveness to which it is regularly applied. Therefore:
Wages depend upon the margin of production. That is, wages
depend on the yield labor can obtain at the highest point of natural
productiveness open to it without the payment of rent.
Our demonstration is complete. The law just obtained
is identical to the one we deduced as a corollary of the law
of rent. It also harmonizes completely with the law of interest. It conforms with universal facts, and explains phenomena that seem unrelated and contradictory without it.
Specifically, it explains these four conditions: Where
land is free and labor works without capital, the entire
output will go to labor as wages. Where land is free and
labor is assisted by capital, wages will consist of the whole
produce less what is necessary to induce the storing up of
labor as capital. Where land is subject to ownership and
rent arises, wages will be fixed by what labor could secure
from the highest natural opportunities open to it without
paying rent (i.e., the margin of production). Where all
natural opportunities are monopolized, wages may be
forced by competition among laborers to the minimum at
which they will consent to reproduce. Clearly, the margin
cannot fall below the point of survival.
To recap: The law of wages is a corollary of Ricardo’s
law of rent. Like it, the law of wages contains its own proof,
and is self-evident as soon as it is stated. It is only the
application of the central truth that is the foundation of
economic reasoning—namely, that people seek to satisfy
their desires with the least exertion. All things considered,
the average person will not work for an employer for less
than can be earned in self-employment. Neither will a
person choose self-employment for less than could be
Law of Wages
117
earned working for an employer. Hence, the return labor
can get from free natural opportunities must set the wages
for labor in general. Said another way, the line of rent is
the necessary measure of the line of wages.
In fact, recognizing the law of rent depends upon accepting (often unconsciously) the law of wages. What
makes it clear that land of a particular quality will yield
rent equal to its surplus over the least productive land in
use? Because we know that owners of better land can get
others to work for them by paying what workers can get
on poorer land.
The law of wages is so obvious that it is often understood without being recognized. People who do not
trouble themselves about political economy grasp it in
its simpler forms, just as those unconcerned with the laws
of gravitation know that a heavy body falls to the earth.
It does not require a philosopher to see that the general
rate of wages would rise if natural opportunities were
available where workers could earn more than the lowest
wages. Even the most ignorant placer miners of early
California knew that as these mines gave out or were
monopolized, wages would fall.
It requires no finespun theory to explain why wages
are so high relative to production in new countries where
land is not yet monopolized. The cause is on the surface.
No one will work for another for less than can be earned
through self-employment—such as going nearby and independently operating a farm. It is only as land becomes
monopolized, and these natural opportunities are shut off,
that laborers are forced to compete with each other for
work. It then becomes possible for a farmer to hire hands
to do the work—while the farmer lives on the difference
118
Laws of Distribution
between what their labor produces and their wages.
Adam Smith himself saw the cause of high wages
where land was still open to settlement. Unfortunately, he
failed to appreciate the importance and the connection of
the fact. In the Causes of the Prosperity of New Colonies, he
reports:
Every colonist gets more land than he can possibly cultivate. He has no rent and scarce any taxes to pay. He is
eager, therefore, to collect laborers from every quarter and
to pay them the most liberal wages. But these liberal wages,
joined to the plenty and cheapness of land, soon make these
laborers leave him in order to become landlords themselves, and to reward with equal liberality other laborers
who soon leave them for the same reason they left their
first masters.*
It is impossible to read the works of Adam Smith
and other economists without seeing how, over and over
again, they stumble over the law of wages without recognizing it. If it were a dog, it would bite them! Indeed,
it is difficult to resist the notion that some of them actually saw it, but were afraid of its logical conclusions. To
an age that has rejected it, a great truth is not a word of
peace, but a sword!
Before closing this chapter, let me remind the reader
that I am not using the word wages in the sense of a
quantity, but in that of a proportion. When I say that wages
fall as rent rises, I do not mean that the quantity of wealth
laborers receive as wages is necessarily less. I mean that
the proportion it bears to the entire output is less. The
* Chap. VII, Book IV, Wealth of Nations.
Law of Wages
119
proportion may diminish while the quantity remains the
same, or even increases.
For example, suppose the margin of production declines. (We will say from 25 to 20.) As rents increase by
this difference, the proportion given in wages must decrease to the same extent. In the meantime, the productive power of labor has increased. Technology may have
advanced, or increasing population may make possible
greater economies of scale. The same effort at point 20
now produces as much wealth as point 25 used to. The
quantity of wages remains the same, though the proportion
has decreased.
This relative fall of wages will not be noticed in the
comforts of the laborers. It will be seen only in the increased
value of land—and in the greater income and extravagance
of the rent-receiving class.
120
Laws of Distribution
Chapter 16
Correlating The Laws of Distribution
THE CONCLUSIONS we have reached on the laws governing
the distribution of wealth recast a large and important part
of the science of political economy, as presently taught.
They overthrow some of its most elaborate theories, and
shed new light on some of its most important problems.
Yet in doing this, we have not advanced a single fundamental principle that is not already recognized.
True, we have substituted a new law of wages and a
new law of interest for those now taught. But these laws
are necessary deductions from the most fundamental law:
that people seek to gratify their desires with the least exertion. When viewed in relation to one of the factors of
production, this becomes the law of rent.
Ricardo’s statement of the law of rent has been accepted by every reputable economist since his day. Like
an axiom of geometry, it only needs to be understood to
be accepted. The laws of interest and of wages, as I have
stated them, are necessary deductions from the law of
rent. In recognizing the law of rent, they too must be
recognized. For discerning the law of rent clearly rests
on recognizing this fact: Competition prevents the return to labor and capital from being greater than what
could be produced on the poorest land in use. Once we
see this, we see what the owner of land will be able to
Laws of Distribution Correlated
121
claim as rent—everything that exceeds what an equal
amount of labor and capital could produce on the poorest land in use.
The laws of distribution, as we now understand, clearly
correlate with each other. This is in striking contrast to
the lack of harmony of those given by current political
economy. Let us state them side by side:
The Current Statement:
RENT depends on the margin of production, rising as
it falls and falling as it rises.
WAGES depend upon the ratio between the number of
laborers and the amount of capital devoted to their
employment.
INTEREST depends upon the equation between the supply of and demand for capital. (Or, as is stated of
profits, interest depends upon “the cost of labor”,
rising as wages fall and falling as wages rise.)
The True Statement:
RENT depends on the margin of production—rising
as it falls, and falling as it rises.
WAGES depend on the margin of production—falling
as it falls, and rising as it rises.
INTEREST depends on the margin of production—falling as it falls, and rising as it rises. (Its ratio with
wages being fixed by the net power of increase that
attaches to capital.)
In their current form, the laws of distribution have no
mutual relation and no common center. They are not correlating divisions of a whole. Rather, they are measures of
different qualities.
122
Laws of Distribution
In the statement we have given, all the laws spring
from a single point. They support and supplement each
other. Together they form correlating divisions of a complete whole.
The Problem Explained
123
Chapter 17
The Problem Explained
WE HAVE NOW obtained a clear, simple, and consistent
theory of the distribution of wealth. It accords with both
basic principles and existing facts. Once understood, it is
self-evident.
The old theory of wages had the support of the highest authorities, and was firmly rooted in common prejudices. Until it was proven groundless, it prevented any other
theory from even being considered. Similarly, the theory
that the earth was the center of the universe prevented
any consideration that the earth circled the sun.
There is, in fact, a striking resemblance between the
science of political economy, as currently taught, and astronomy prior to Copernicus. As they attempt to explain
social phenomena, economists employ devices that may
well be compared to the elaborate system of cycles and
epicycles constructed by the learned people of the past.
They tried to make celestial phenomena fit the dogmas of
authority and the primitive perceptions of the uneducated.
But as these elaborate theories could not explain observed
phenomena, a simpler theory finally supplanted them.
At this point the parallel ceases. The thought that our
solid earth is whirling through space is, at first, jarring to
our sensibilities. But the truth I wish to make clear is seen
naturally. It has been recognized early on by every society.
124
Laws of Distribution
It is obscured only by the complexities of civilization, the
distortions of selfish interests, and the false turns taken by
intellectual speculation. It is a theory that will give political economy the simplicity and harmony that Copernican
theory gave astronomy.
To recognize it, we need only return to first principles
and simple perceptions. Nothing can be clearer than that
wages fail to increase with increasing productive power,
and that this is due to rising rent.
Three things unite in production: land, labor, and capital. Three parties divide the output: landowner, laborer,
and capitalist. If the laborer and capitalist get no more
as production increases, it is a necessary inference that the
landowner takes the gain.
The facts agree with this inference. Neither wages nor
interest keep step with material progress. Yet rising rents
and land values invariably accompany advancement. Indeed, they are the mark of progress! Increasing rent explains why wages and interest do not increase. The same
cause that gives more to the land owner also denies it to
the laborer and capitalist.
Wages and interest are higher in new countries than
in old. The difference is not due to nature, but to the fact
that land is cheaper. Consequently, a smaller proportion is
taken by rent. Wages and interest are not determined by
total production, but by net production—after rent has
been taken out. Wages and interest are not set by the productiveness of labor, but by the value of land. Wherever
the value of land is relatively low, wages and interest are
relatively high. Where land is relatively high, wages and
interest are relatively low.
When society is in its earliest stages, all labor is applied
The Problem Explained
125
directly to the land. All wages are paid from its production.
It is obvious that if the landowner takes a larger share, the
worker gets a smaller one. But in modern production, labor
is applied after materials have been separated from the land,
and exchange plays a far greater role.
These complexities may disguise the facts, but they
do not alter them. All production is still the union of
land and labor. Rent cannot increase except at the expense of wages and interest. The rent on land in a manufacturing or commercial city lessens the amount available
to divide as wages and interest among those engaged in
the production and exchange of wealth in that place. To
see human beings in their most hopeless condition, do
not go to the unfenced prairies or the log cabins of the
backwoods where land is worth nothing. Go, instead, to
the great cities, where owning a little patch of ground is
worth a fortune.
It is a universal fact—seen everywhere—that the contrast between wealth and want grows as the value of land
increases. The greatest luxury and the most pathetic destitution exist side by side where land values are highest.
In short, the value of land depends entirely on the
power that ownership gives to appropriate the wealth created by labor. Land value always increases at the expense
of labor. The reason greater productive power does not
increase wages is because it increases the value of land.
Rent swallows up the whole gain.
That is why poverty accompanies progress.
126
Effect of Material Proigress
Fourth Part:
The Effect of Material Progress
on the Distribution of Wealth
Chapter 18
Dynamic Forces Not Yet Explored
WE HAVE REACHED a conclusion of great significance. We
have shown that rent—not labor—receives the increased
production of material progress. Further, we have seen that
labor and capital do not have opposing interests, as is popularly believed. In reality, the struggle is between labor and
capital, on one side, and landownership on the other.
But we have not fully solved the problem. We know
wages remain low because rent advances. Still, that is like
saying a steamboat moves because its wheels turn. The
further question is, what causes rent to advance? What is
the force or necessity that distributes an increasing proportion of production as rent?
Ricardo and others focused only on population
growth, which forces cultivation of poorer lands. But this
principle does not fully account for the increase of rent
as material progress goes on. Nor are all the conclusions
drawn from it valid. There are other causes that conspire
to raise rent. If we trace the effect of progress on the
distribution of wealth, we will see what these are and
Dynamics Yet to Explore
127
how they operate.
Three changes contribute to material progress: (1) increased population; (2) improvements in production and
exchange; and (3) improvements in knowledge, education,
government, police, and ethics (to the extent they increase
the power to produce wealth).
The latter two have essentially the same economic effect, so we can consider them together. But first, we will
consider the effects of increasing population by itself.
128
Effect of Material Progress
Chapter 19
Population Growth
and the Distribution of Wealth
HOW DOES A GROWING POPULATION increase rent? Current thought says a higher demand for subsistence forces
production to inferior land. For example, if the margin of
production is the place where the average laborer can produce 30, then on all lands where more than 30 is produced, there will be rent. A growing population requires
additional supplies, which cannot be obtained without extending cultivation. This causes lands that were formerly
free to bear rent. Say the margin is extended to 20. All
land between 20 and 30 will acquire value and yield rent.
All land over 30 will increase in value and bear higher
rent. As explained by Ricardo (and later economists), this
inability to procure more food except at a greater cost accounts for the increase in rent.
I will show, later, that rent would increase even if
population remained steady. But first, we must clear up
the misconception that using poorer land produces less
aggregate production, proportional to labor expended. For
increased population—of itself, and without any technological advances—makes possible an increase in the productive power of labor.
All things being equal, the labor of a hundred people
will produce much more than one hundred times the labor
Population Growth & Wealth Distribution
129
of one person. And the labor of a thousand, much more
than ten times the labor of a hundred. With every additional person, there is a more-than-proportionate addition
to the productive power of labor. As population increases,
naturally less productive land may be used—but without
any reduction in the average production of wealth per worker.
There will be no decrease even at the lowest point. If population doubles, land of only 20 (as per our earlier example)
may yield as much as land of 30 could before, given the
same amount of labor.
For it must not be forgotten (although it often is) that
the productiveness of either land or labor is not measured
by any one thing—but by all things we desire. A settler
may raise as much corn a hundred miles from the nearest
house as on land near a city. But in the city, one could
make as good a living, with the same effort, on much poorer
land (or on equal land after paying high rent). This is because labor becomes more effective in the midst of a large
population. Not, perhaps, in the production of corn, but
in the production of wealth. That is, in the ability to obtain the goods and services that are the real object of labor.
A growing population increases the effectiveness of
labor by permitting greater economies. More wealth can
be produced with the same effort. It increases productivity not only on the newer land, but on all the better land
already in use.
If productivity rose faster than the need for less productive land, the average production of wealth would increase. Thus, the minimum return to labor would increase,
although rent would still rise. In other words, wages would
rise as a quantity—but fall as a proportion.
If productivity just compensated for the diminishing
130
Effect of Material Progress
productiveness of additional land, average production
would still increase. Rent would increase (as the margin
fell), without reducing wages as a quantity.
Finally, as growth forced even poorer quality land into
use, the difference might be so great that even the increased
power of labor could not compensate for it. The minimum
return to labor would be reduced. Rents would rise, while
wages would fall, both as a proportion and a quantity.
But even here, average production will still increase
(unless the quality of land falls far more precipitously than
has ever happened). Remember, the increase of population, which compels the use of inferior land, increases the
effectiveness of labor at the same time. This increase affects all labor. Therefore, the gains on superior land will
more than compensate for diminished production on the
lowest quality.
In short, the aggregate production of wealth, compared
with the aggregate expenditure of labor, will be greater—
but its distribution will be more unequal. Rent will increase. Wages may or may not fall as a quantity. But
wages—as a proportion—will fall. Increasing population
seldom can—and probably never does—reduce the aggregate production of wealth compared to the aggregate expenditure of labor. On the contrary, a greater population
increases wealth—and frequently increases it greatly.
But it is a mistake to think that lowering the margin is
the only process that increases rent. Greater density raises
rent without reference to the natural qualities of land. The
enhanced powers of cooperation and exchange that come
with a larger population are equivalent to a greater capacity to produce wealth. Indeed, I think we can say without
metaphor that they actually increase the capacity of land.
Population Growth & Wealth Distribution
131
Improved tools or methods give greater results to the
same amount of labor. This is, in effect, equivalent to an
increase in the natural powers of land. But I do not mean
to say the power that comes with larger population is
merely like this. Rather, it brings out a greater power in
labor—and this power is localized on certain land. It does
not belong to labor in general, but only to labor exerted
on particular land. It resides in land as much as physical
qualities such as soil, climate, mineral deposits, or natural situation. Like these, this power passes with possession of the land.
Consider an improvement in cultivation (or tools or
machinery) that allows two crops a year instead of one.
Clearly, the effect is the same as if the fertility of that land
were doubled. But such improvements can be applied to
any land, while increased fertility affects only that land. In
large part, the increased productivity arising from population can be utilized only on certain land.
The Unbounded Savannah*
Imagine a vast, unbounded savanna, stretching off in
endless sameness till the traveler tires of the monotony.
The first family of settlers approaches and cannot tell where
to settle—every acre seems as good as any other. There is
no difference in location, fertility, or water. Perplexed by
this embarrassment of riches, they stop somewhere, anywhere, and make themselves a home.
The soil is virgin and rich, the game abundant, the
streams flash with trout. What they have would make them
*This famous narrative of a society’s development has often been excerpted. A savannah is a grassy plain.
132
Effect of Material Progress
rich—if only they were among others. Instead, they are
very poor. To say nothing of their mental cravings, which
would lead them to welcome the sorriest of strangers, they
labor under all the disadvantages of solitude. For any work
requiring a union of strength, they are limited to their own
family. Though they have cattle, they cannot often have
fresh meat—to get a steak, they must kill a whole steer.
They are their own blacksmith, carpenter, and cobbler; jacks
of all trades and masters of none.
Their children can have no schooling, unless they pay
the full salary of a teacher. Anything they cannot produce,
they must buy in quantity to keep on hand—or go without. For they cannot constantly leave work and make a
long journey to civilization. When forced to do so, getting
medicine or replacing a broken tool may cost their labor
and the use of their horses for several days.
Under such circumstances, though nature is prolific,
the family is poor. It is an easy matter to get enough to eat.
But beyond that, their labor can satisfy only the simplest
wants in the rudest way.
Soon, though, other immigrants arrive. Though every
acre is still as good as every other, there is no doubt where
to settle. The land may be the same, but one place is clearly
better than any other. And that is where there is already a
settler, and they may have a neighbor.
Conditions improve immediately for the earlier pioneers. Many things that were once impossible are now practical—for two families can help each other do things one
could never do. As others arrive, they are guided by the same
attraction, until there are a score of neighbors around our
first.
Labor now has an effectiveness that it could never ap-
Population Growth & Wealth Distribution
133
proach in the solitary state. If heavy work is to be done,
the community—working together—accomplish in a day
what would have required years alone. There is fresh meat
all the time. When one butchers a steer, the others share
in it, returning the favor in their turn. Together they hire a
schoolmaster. All their children are taught for a fraction
of what it would have cost the first settler. And it becomes
easy to send to the nearest town, for someone is always
going. But there is less need for such journeys.
A blacksmith and a wheelwright soon set up shop. Now
our settlers can have their tools repaired for a small part of
the labor it formerly cost. A store opens, and they can get
what they want, when they want it. A post office soon
gives regular communication with the rest of the world.
Occasionally, a passing lecturer opens up a glimpse of
the world of science, art, or literature. And finally comes
the circus, talked of for months before. Children, whose
horizon had been only the prairie, now visit the realms of
imagination: princes and princesses, lions and tigers, camels and elephants.
Go to our original settlers now and make this offer:
“You have planted so many acres, built a well, a barn, a
house. Your labor has added this much value to this farm.
But after farming for a few years, your land itself is not
quite as good. Still, I will give you the full value of all your
improvements—if you will go with your family into the
wilderness again.”
They would laugh at you. The land yields no more wheat
or potatoes than before—but it does yield far more of the
necessities and comforts of life. Labor brings no more crops
than before—yet it brings far more of all the other things
for which people work. The presence of others—the growth
134
Effect of Material Progress
of population—has raised the productiveness of labor in
these other things. This added productivity confers superiority over land of equal natural quality where there are no
settlers.
If, however, there is a continuous stretch of equal land
over which population is now spreading, it will not be necessary to go into the wilderness. A newcomer could settle
just beyond the others, and get the advantage of proximity
to them. The value or rent of land will then depend on the
advantage it has: the advantage of being at the center of
population over being at the edge.
As population continues to grow, so do the economies
its increase permits. In effect, these add to the productiveness of the land. Our first settler’s land is now the center
of population. The store, the blacksmith, the wheelwright
have set up nearby. A village arises, becoming the center
of exchange for the whole district.
This land has no greater agricultural productiveness
than it had at first. Yet it now begins to develop productiveness of a higher kind. Labor expended in raising crops
will yield no more of those than at first. But labor will
yield much greater returns in specialized branches of production—where proximity to others is required. The farmer
may go further on, and find land yielding as great a harvest. But what of the manufacturer, the storekeeper, the
professional? Their labor here, at the center of exchange,
gives a much greater return than labor expended even a
short distance away from it.
All this difference in productiveness, the landowner
can claim. Our pioneers can sell a few building lots at prices
they would not bring for farming, even if the fertility were
multiplied many times over. With the proceeds, they build
Population Growth & Wealth Distribution
135
fine houses and furnish them handsomely. Or to state the
transaction in its lowest terms: those who wish to use this
land will build and furnish the houses for them. They do
this on the condition that the landowners will allow the
workers to avail themselves of the superior productiveness
of this land—productiveness given solely by the increase
in population.
The town grows into a city: a St. Louis, a Chicago, a
San Francisco. Its population gives greater and greater utility to the land—and more and more wealth to its owners.
Production is performed on a grand scale, using the latest
machinery. The division of labor becomes extremely
minute, wonderfully multiplying efficiency. Exchanges are
of such volume and rapidity that they entail a minimum
of friction and loss. This land now offers enormous advantages for the application of labor. Instead of one person farming a few acres, thousands work in buildings with
floors stacked upon each other.
All these advantages attach to the land. On this land—
and no other—they can be utilized. For here is the center
of population: the focus of exchange, the marketplace, the
workshop of industry. Density of population has given this
land productive power equivalent to multiplying its original fertility a thousandfold.
Rent—which measures the difference between this
added productivity and that of the least productive land in
use—has increased accordingly.
Our settlers—or whoever has the rights to the land—
are now millionaires. Like Rip Van Winkle, they may have
lain down and slept. But they are still rich—not from anything they have done, but from the increase of population.
Nothing has changed in the land itself. It is the same
136
Effect of Material Progress
land that once, when our first settler came upon it, had no
value at all. The vast difference in productiveness, which
causes rents to rise, is not due to using inferior land. Rather,
it is more the result of the increased productiveness that
population gives to land already in use. This is how population acts to increase rent—as those living in an advancing country can see if they will just look around. The
process is going on before their eyes.
The most valuable lands on earth, those with the
highest rent, are not those with the highest natural fertility. Rather, they are lands given a greater usefulness by
population density.
We sail through space as if on a well-provisioned ship.*
If food above deck seems to grow scarce, we simply open a
hatch—and there is a new supply. And a very great command over others comes to those who, as the hatches are
opened, are permitted to say: “This is mine!”
* This may be the earliest mention of “Spaceship Earth”!
Labor-Saving Inventions
137
Chapter 20
Technology and the Distribution of Wealth
I INTEND TO SHOW that improved methods of production
and exchange will also increase rent, regardless of population. When this is established, we will have explained why
material progress lowers wages and produces poverty. No
theory of pressure against the means of subsistence is
needed, and Malthus’s theory—and all doctrines related
to it—will be completely disproved.
Inventions and increased productivity save labor. The
same results are produced with less labor—or greater results are produced with the same labor. If all material desires were satisfied, labor-saving improvements would
simply reduce the amount of labor expended. But such a
society cannot be found anywhere. A person is not an ox,
lying down to chew its cud when it has had its fill. A person is more like a leech—constantly asking for more.
Demand does not increase only when population does.
It grows—in each individual—with the power of obtaining the things desired, and with every opportunity for additional gratification. This being the case, the effect of
labor-saving improvements will be to increase the production of wealth.
Now, to produce wealth, two things are required: labor and land. Therefore, the effect of labor-saving
improvements will be to extend the demand for land.
138
Effect of Material Progress
So the primary effect of labor-saving improvements is to
increase the power of labor. But the secondary effect is to
extend the margin of production. And the end result is to
increase rent.
This shows that effects attributed to population are
really due to technological progress. It also explains the
otherwise perplexing fact that laborsaving machinery fails
to benefit workers.
Yet, to fully grasp this, it is necessary to keep one thing
in mind—the interchangeability of wealth. I mention this
again, because it is so persistently forgotten. The possession or production of any form of wealth is—in effect—
the possession or production of any other form of wealth
for which it can be exchanged. If you keep this clearly in
mind, you will see that all improvements tend to increase
rent. Not only improvements applied directly to land—
but all improvements that in any way save labor.
It is only because of the division of labor that any individual applies effort exclusively to the production of only
one form of wealth. An increase in the power of producing one thing adds to the power of obtaining others.
I cannot think of any form of wealth that would not
show an increased demand because of labor saved in the
production of other forms. Coffins are cited as examples
where demand is not likely to increase. But this is true
only in quantity. Increased power of supply leads to a demand for fancier coffins.
In economic reasoning it is frequently—but erroneously—assumed that the demand for food is limited. It is
fixed only in having a definite minimum; less than a certain amount will not keep a human being alive. But beyond this, the food a human being can use may be increased
Labor-Saving Inventions
139
almost infinitely.
Adam Smith and Ricardo have said the desire for food
is limited by the capacity of the human stomach. Clearly,
this is true only in the sense that when a person’s belly is
filled, hunger is satisfied. But demands for food have no
such limit. The stomach of a king can digest no more than
the stomach of a peasant. Yet a small plot of ground supports the peasant, while thousands of acres supply the demands of the king. Besides his own wasteful use of the
finest quality food, he requires immense supplies for his
servants, horses, and dogs.
And so every improvement or invention that gives labor the power to produce more wealth, no matter what it
may be, causes an increased demand for land and its products. Progress thus tends to force down the margin of production, the same as the demand of a larger population
would. This being the case, every labor-saving invention
has a tendency to increase rent. This is true whether it is a
tractor, a telegraph, or a sewing machine. There will be a
greater production of wealth—but landowners will get the
whole benefit.
I do not mean to say that the change in the margin
would always correspond exactly with the increase in production. Nor do I mean the process would have clearly defined steps. In any particular case, the margin may either
lag behind or exceed the increase in productivity. Nor is it
precisely true that all labor set free will seek employment.
Some will pass from the ranks of the productive to the unproductive, and become idlers. Observation shows that this
segment tends to increase with the progress of society.
All I wish to make clear is that even without any increase in population, the progress of invention constantly
140
Effect of Material Progress
tends to give a greater proportion of the production to
landowners. Therefore, a smaller and smaller share goes to
labor and capital. Since we can assign no limits to the
progress of invention, neither can we offer any limits to
the increase of rent—short of the entire output. If wealth
could be obtained without labor, there would be no use for
either labor or capital. Nor would there be any possible
way either could demand any share of the wealth produced.
If anybody but landowners continued to exist, it would be
at their whim or mercy—perhaps maintained for their
amusement, or as paupers by their charity.
This scenario may seem very remote, if not impossible
to attain. Yet it is a point towards which the march of invention is tending every day. In the great machine-worked
wheat fields of Dakota, one may ride for miles and miles
through waving grain without seeing a single dwelling.
The tractor and reaping machine are creating, in the modern world, Roman latifundia*—the great estates of ancient
Italy created by the influx of slaves from foreign wars. To
many a poor person forced out of a home, it may seem as
though these labor-saving inventions are a curse.
Of course, in the preceding, I have spoken about inventions and improvements when they are generally diffused. Sometimes an invention or improvement is used by
so few that they derive a special advantage from it. It is
hardly necessary to say that, to the extent it is a special
advantage, it does not affect the general distribution of
* Latifundia were large estates created when the wealthy displaced
smaller farmers. These once-independent farmers were then forced
to join the poor masses in Rome, or sell their lives for food in the
army.
Labor-Saving Inventions
141
wealth. The special profits arising from these situations
are often mistaken for the profits of capital—but they are
really the returns of monopoly.*
Improvements that directly expand productive power
are not the only ones that increase rent. Advances in government, manners, and morals that indirectly increase
productivity are also included. Considered as material
forces, the effect of all these is to increase productive
power. Like improvements in the productive arts, their
benefit is ultimately monopolized by landowners.
A notable instance of this is England’s abolition of
laws protecting certain trades. The resulting free trade has
enormously increased the wealth of Great Britain—but it
has not reduced poverty. It has simply increased rent. And
if the corrupt governments of our great American cities
were made into models of purity and thrift, it would not
raise wages or interest. It would simply increase the value
of land.
* As explained in Chapter 13.
142
Effect of Material Progress
Chapter 21
Speculation
THERE IS ANOTHER CAUSE, not yet mentioned, that must
be considered before we can fully explain the impact of
progress on the distribution of wealth. It is the confident
expectation that land values will increase in the future. The
steady increase of rent in all growing countries leads to
speculation—holding onto land for a higher price than it
would otherwise bring at that time.
We have thus far allowed an assumption that is generally made in explaining the theory of rent. That is, that
the actual margin of production always coincides with what
may be termed the necessary margin of production. We
have assumed that cultivation extends to less productive
points only as it becomes necessary to do so—and that
more productive points are fully utilized. This is probably
the case in stable or slowly developing communities. But
with rapid advancement, the swift and steady increase of
rent gives confidence to calculations of further increase. It
leads to land being withheld from use, as higher prices are
expected. Thus, the margin of production is forced out
farther than required by the necessities of production. As
landowners confidently expect rents to increase further,
they demand more rent than the land would provide under current conditions.
Settlers will take more land than they can use, if
Speculation
143
possible, in the belief that it will soon become valuable. As
they do, the margin is carried to even more remote points.
It is also well known that private mineral land is often
withheld from use, while poorer deposits are worked. In
new states, it is common to find individuals who are called
“land poor.” They persist in holding land they cannot use
themselves. They endure poverty, sometimes almost to deprivation, instead of selling their land. Or, they offer it at
prices where no one else could use it profitably.
The same thing may be seen in every rapidly growing
city. If superior land were always fully used before resorting to inferior land, no vacant lots would be left as a city
extended. Nor would we find miserable shanties in the
midst of costly buildings. Though some of these lots are
extremely valuable, they are withheld from their fullest
use, or any use at all. Instead, the owners prefer to wait for
a higher price than they could currently get from those
who are willing to improve them. They expect, of course,
that land values will increase.
The result of land being withheld is that the margin
of the city is pushed away so much farther from the center.
The actual margin of building is at the limits of the city.
This corresponds to the margin of production in agriculture. But we will not find land available at its value for
agricultural purposes, as we would if rent were determined
simply by present requirements. Instead, we find—for a
long distance beyond the city—that land bears a speculative value. This is based upon the belief that it will be required for urban purposes in the future. To reach the point
at which land can be purchased at a price not based upon
urban rent, we must go very far beyond the actual margin
of urban use.
144
Effect of Material Progress
We may conceive of speculation as extending the margin of production. Or, we can look at it as carrying the
rent line past the margin of production. However we view
it, the influence of speculation on increasing rent is an
important fact. It cannot be ignored in any complete theory
of the distribution of wealth in progressive countries.
Speculation is the force, arising from material progress,
that constantly tends to increase rent in a greater ratio than
progress increases production. As material progress goes
on and productive power increases, speculation thus constantly tends to reduce wages—not merely relatively, but
absolutely.
We see this process operating full force in land speculation manias, which mark the growth of new communities. These are abnormal and sporadic manifestations, yet
it is undeniable that the same cause operates steadily, with
greater or less intensity, in all progressive societies.
With commodities, rising prices will draw forth additional supplies. This cannot limit the speculative advance
in land values, however. Land is a fixed quantity, which
human action can neither increase nor decrease.
There is, nevertheless, a limit to the price of land. It is
set by the minimum that labor and capital require to engage in production. Hence, speculation cannot have the
same scope to advance rent in countries where wages and
interest are already near the minimum, as it does in countries where they are considerably above it.
Still, in all progressive countries, there is a constant
tendency for the speculative advance of rent to exceed the
limit at which production stops. This, I think, is shown by
recurring seasons of industrial paralysis (i.e., recessions)—
the matter to which we turn in the next chapter.
Root Cause of Recessions
145
Fifth Part:
The Problem Solved
Chapter 22
The Root Cause of Recessions
WE HAVE COMPLETED our long inquiry, and now we can
compile the results.
We will begin with depressions and recessions, which
affect every modern society. We have shown how land
speculation inflates land values, reduces wages and interest, and thereby checks production. There are other reasons as well, such as: the complexity and interdependence
of production; problems with money and credit; the artificial barriers of protective tariffs. Nonetheless, it is clear
that land speculation is the primary cause producing recessions. We can see this either by considering principles
or by observing phenomena.
As population grows and technology advances, land
values rise. This steady increase leads to speculation, as
future increases are anticipated. Land values are carried
beyond the point at which labor and capital would receive their customary returns. Production, therefore, begins to stop.
Production need not decrease absolutely—it may
146
The Problem Solved
simply fail to increase proportionately. In other words,
new labor and capital cannot find employment at the
usual rates.
Stopping production at some points must necessarily affect other points of the industrial network. Demand
is interrupted, checking production elsewhere. Paralysis
spreads through all the interlaced industry and commerce.
The same events can seem to show either overproduction
or overconsumption—depending on one’s point of view.
The period of depression will continue until: (1) the
speculative advance in rents is lost; or (2) the increased
efficiency of labor (due to population growth and/or improved technology) allows the normal rent line to overtake the speculative rent line; or (3) labor and capital are
willing to work for smaller returns. Most likely, all three
will cooperate to produce a new equilibrium*. Production
resumes in full. After rents begin to advance again, speculation returns; production is checked; and the same cycle
repeats itself.
Modern civilization is characterized by an elaborate
and complicated system of production. Moreover, there is
no such thing as a distinct and independent industrial community. We should not expect to see cause followed by
effect as clearly as we would in a simpler society. Nevertheless, the phenomena actually observed clearly correspond with what we have inferred. Deduction shows how
the actual phenomena result from the basic principle.
*It is also possible for these forces to move in different directions at
the same time. For example, in the 1990s, the speculative advance of
rents continued apace, but was offset by increased productivity due to
technological advancements.
Root Cause of Recessions
147
If we reverse the process, it is just as easy to use induction to follow the phenomena and arrive at the principle.
Depressions and recessions are always preceded by periods of activity and speculation. Some connection between
the two is generally acknowledged. Depression is seen as a
reaction to speculation, as this morning’s hangover is a reaction to last night’s debauch. There are two schools of
thought as to how this occurs.
The school of overproduction says production has exceeded the demand for consumption. They point out unsold goods, factories working half time, money lying idle,
and workers without jobs.
The school of overconsumption points to the very same
things as evidence that demand has stopped. This, they
say, is because people, made extravagant by fictitious prosperity, have lived beyond their means. The pinch was not
felt at the time, much as spendthrifts do not notice the
loss of their fortunes while squandering them. Now they
must retrench and consume less.
Each of these theories expresses one side, but fails to
comprehend the full truth. Each is equally preposterous
as an explanation of observed phenomena.
People want more wealth than they can get. The basis
of wealth is labor. How can there be overproduction as
long as people are willing to give their labor in return for
things? Likewise, when workers and machinery are forced
to stand idle, how can one claim overconsumption? The
desire to consume coexists with the willingness to produce. So industrial and commercial paralysis cannot be
attributed to either overproduction or overconsumption.
Clearly, the trouble is that production and consumption cannot meet and satisfy each other. This, it is
148
The Problem Solved
commonly agreed, arises from speculation. But speculation
in the products of labor simply tends to equalize supply and
demand. It steadies the interplay of production and consumption, much like a flywheel in a machine. This has been
well shown, and spares me the need to illustrate it.
Therefore, the problem must be speculation in things
that are not the product of labor. Yet it must be things
needed for production. And finally, it must be things of
fixed quantity.
The cause of recurring recessions must be speculation in land.
This process is obvious in the United States. During
each period of industrial activity, land values rose steadily,
culminating in speculation that drove them up in great
jumps. This was invariably followed by a partial cessation
of production, reducing effective demand as a correlative.
A commercial crash generally accompanied this. A period
of comparative stagnation followed, during which equilibrium was slowly reestablished. Then the same cycle began again.
In common parlance, we say “buyers have no money.”
But this ignores the fact that money is only a medium of
exchange. All trade is really the exchange of commodities
for other commodities. What would-be buyers really lack
is not money—it is commodities they can turn into money.
Sales may decline and manufacturing orders fall off, yet a
widespread desire for these things remains. This simply
shows that the supply of other things—which would be
exchanged for them in the course of trade—has declined.
Reduced consumer demand is just a result of decreased
production.
This is seen quite clearly in mill towns when workers
Root Cause of Recessions
149
are thrown out of work. Since workers have no means to
purchase what they desire, storekeepers are left with excess stock. They must then discharge some of their clerks.
The decreased demand leaves manufacturers with an overstock, and forces them to discharge their workers in the
same way. Somewhere—and it may be at the other end of
the world—a check in production has produced a check
in demand.
Demand is lessened without want being satisfied.
People want things as much as ever. But they do not have
as much to give for them. The obstruction then spreads
through the whole framework of industry and exchange.
Since the industrial pyramid clearly rests on land,
some obstacle must be preventing labor from expending
itself on land. That obstacle is the speculative advance in
land values. It is, in fact, a lockout of labor and capital by
landowners. Though habit has made us used to it, it is a
strange and unnatural thing that people, who are willing
to work to satisfy their wants, cannot find the opportunity to do so.
We speak of the supply of labor and the demand for
labor. Obviously, these are relative terms. Labor is what produces wealth. So the demand for labor always exists—for
people always want things that labor alone can provide.
We speak of a lack of jobs, but clearly it is not work
that is short. The supply of labor cannot be too great, nor
the demand for labor too small, when people still want
those things that labor produces. Trace this inactivity from
point to point, and you will find that unemployment in
one trade is caused by unemployment in another. This cannot arise from too large a supply of labor or too small a
demand for labor.
150
The Problem Solved
The real trouble must be that supply is somehow prevented from satisfying demand. Somewhere, there is an
obstacle keeping labor from producing the things that laborers want.
Put a few of the vast army of unemployed on an island
cut off from all the advantages of a civilized community,
without the cooperation and machinery that multiply productivity. Using only their own hands, they can feed themselves—but where productive power is at its highest, they
cannot. Is this not because they have access to nature in
one case, but are denied it in the other? The only thing
that can explain why people are forced to stand idle when
they would willingly work to supply their wants is that
labor is denied access to land.
When we speak of labor creating wealth, we speak
metaphorically. People create nothing. If the whole human race worked forever, it could not create the tiniest
speck of dust floating in a sunbeam. In producing wealth,
labor merely manipulates preexisting matter into desired
forms by using natural forces. Therefore, labor must have
access to this matter and to those forces to produce wealth.
That is to say, they must have access to land.
Land is the source of all wealth. It is the substance to
which labor gives form. When labor cannot satisfy its
wants, can there be any other cause than that labor is denied access to land?
The foundation of the industrial structure is land. Hat
makers, opticians, and craftsmen are not the pioneers of
new settlements. Miners did not go to California because
shoemakers, tailors, and printers were there. Rather, those
trades followed the miners. The storekeeper does not bring
the farmer, rather the farmer brings the storekeeper. It is
Root Cause of Recessions
151
not the growth of the city that develops the country, but
the development of the country that raises the city.
Therefore, when people of all trades cannot find opportunity to work, the difficulty must arise in the occupations that create demand for all other employment. It must
be because labor is shut out from land.
In great cities like Philadelphia or London or New
York, it may require a grasp of basic principles to see this.
But elsewhere, industrial development has not become so
elaborate—nor has the chain of exchange become so widely
separated. There, one has only to look at the obvious facts.
San Francisco ranks among the great cities of the world,
though barely thirty years old. Yet certain symptoms are
already beginning to appear. In older countries, these are
taken as evidence of overpopulation. But it is absurd to
talk of excess population in a state* with greater natural
resources than France, but less than a million people.
Still, unemployment has been growing for a number
of years. When the harvest season opens, the workers go
trooping out; when it is over, they come back again to the
city. Clearly, there are unemployed in the city because they
cannot find employment in the country.
It is not that all the land is in use. Within a few miles
of San Francisco is enough unused land to employ everyone who wants work. I do not mean that everyone could—
or should—become a farmer if given the chance. But
enough would do so to give employment to the rest.
What prevents labor from using this land? Simply that
land has been monopolized. It is held at speculative prices,
based not on present value, but on value that will come
* California in 1879
152
The Problem Solved
with future population growth. This speculative advance
is held with great tenacity in developing communities.
Owners hold on as long as they can, believing prices must
eventually rise.
Thus, the speculative advance in rent outran the normal advance. Production was checked, and demand decreased. Labor and capital were turned away from
occupations directly concerned with land. So they glutted
those where land is a less apparent element. This is how,
for instance, the rapid expansion of railroads was related
to the succeeding depression.
It may seem as if I have overlooked one thing in saying the primary cause of depressions is land speculation.
Such a cause should operate progressively; it should resemble a pressure, not a blow. Yet industrial depressions
seem to come on suddenly.
Let me offer an explanation for this. Exchange links
all forms of industry into one interdependent organization. For exchanges to be made between producers far removed by space and time, large stocks must be kept in
store and in transit. (This is the great function of capital,
in addition to supplying tools and seed.) These exchanges
are made largely on credit: the advance is made on one
side before the return is received on the other.
As a rule, these advances are made from more developed industries to fundamental ones. Natives who trade
coconuts for trinkets get their return immediately. Merchants, on the contrary, let out their goods a long while
before getting a return. Farmers sell their crops for cash as
soon as they are harvested. Manufacturers must keep large
stocks, ship goods long distances, and generally sell on
installments.
Root Cause of Recessions
153
Thus, advances and credits are generally from what
we may call secondary to primary industries. It follows
that any check to production that proceeds from the primary will not immediately manifest itself in the secondary. The system is, as it were, an elastic connection: it will
give considerably before breaking. But when it breaks, it
breaks with a snap.
Let me illustrate what I mean another way. A pyramid is composed of layers, with the bottom layer supporting the rest. If we could somehow make this bottom layer
gradually smaller, the upper part would retain its form for
some time. Eventually, gravity would overcome the adhesiveness of the material. At this point, it would not diminish gradually, but would break off suddenly, in large pieces.
The industrial organization may be likened to such a
pyramid. As each form of industry develops, through the
division of labor, it rises out of the others. Ultimately, everything rests upon land. For without land, labor is as powerless as a person would be in the void of space.
We have now explained the main cause and general
course of recurring paroxysms of industrial depression,
which are a conspicuous feature of modern life. Political
economy can only—and need only—deal with general tendencies. The exact character of the phenomena cannot be
predicted, because the actions and reactions are too diverse. We know that if a tree is cut, it will fall. But the
precise direction will be determined by the inclination of
the trunk, the spread of the branches, the impact of the
blows, the direction and force of the wind, and so on.
I have given a cause that clearly explains the main features of recessions. This is in striking contrast to the contradictory—and self-contradictory—attempts based on
154
The Problem Solved
current theories. It is clear that a speculative advance in
land values invariably precedes each recession. That these
are cause and effect is obvious to anyone who considers
the necessary relation between land and labor.
The recession runs its course and a new equilibrium is
established as the normal rent line and the speculative rent
line are being brought together by three factors: (1) The
fall of speculative land values, as shown by reduced rents
and shrinkage of real estate values in major cities. (2) The
increased efficiency of labor arising from population growth
and new technology. (3) The lowering of customary standards of wages and interest.
When equilibrium is reestablished, renewed activity
will set in. This will again result in a speculative advance
of land values. But wages and interest will not recover their
lost ground. The net result of all these disturbances is the
gradual forcing of wages and interest toward their minimum.
Persistence of Poverty
155
Chapter 23
The Persistence of Poverty
Despite Increasing Wealth
THE GREAT PROBLEM IS SOLVED. We are able to explain
social phenomena that have appalled philanthropists and
perplexed statesmen all over the civilized world. We have
found the reason why wages constantly tend to a minimum, giving but a bare living, despite increase in productive power:
As productive power increases, rent tends to increase even
more—constantly forcing down wages.
Advancing civilization tends to increase the power
of human labor to satisfy human desires. We should be
able to eliminate poverty. But workers cannot reap these
benefits because they are intercepted. Land is necessary
to labor. When it has been reduced to private ownership,
the increased productivity of labor only increases rent.
Thus, all the advantages of progress go to those who own
land. Wages do not increase—wages cannot increase. The
more labor produces, the more it must pay for the opportunity to make anything at all.
Mere laborers, therefore, have no more interest in
progress than Cuban slaves have in higher sugar prices.
Higher prices may spur their masters to drive them harder.
Likewise, a free laborer may be worse off with greater
156
The Problem Solved
productivity. Steadily rising rents generate speculation.
The effects of future improvements are discounted by
even higher rents. This tends to drive wages down to the
point of slavery, at which the worker can barely live. The
worker is robbed of all the benefits of increased productive power.
These improvements also cause a further subdivision
of labor. The efficiency of the whole body of laborers is
increased, but at the expense of the independence of its
constituents. Individual workers know only a tiny part of
the various processes required to supply even the commonest wants.
A primitive tribe may not produce much wealth, but
all members are capable of an independent life. Each shares
all the knowledge possessed by the tribe. They know the
habits of animals, birds, and fishes. They can make their
own shelter, clothing, and weapons. In short, they are all
capable of supplying their own wants. The independence
of all of the members makes them free contracting parties
in their relations with the community.
Compare this savage with workers in the lowest ranks
of civilized society. Their lives are spent in producing just
one thing or, more likely, the smallest part of one thing.
They cannot even make what is required for their work;
they use tools they can never hope to own. Compelled to
oppressive and constant labor, they get no more than the
savage: the bare necessaries of life. Yet they lose the independence the savage keeps.
Modern workers are mere links in an enormous chain
of producers and consumers. The very power of exerting
their labor to satisfy their needs passes from their control.
The worse their position in society, the more dependent
Persistence of Poverty
157
they are on society. Their power may be taken away by the
actions of others. Or even by general causes, over which
they have no more influence than they have over the motion of the stars.
Under such circumstances, people lose an essential
quality: the power of modifying and controlling their condition. They become slaves, machines, commodities. In
some respects, they are lower than animals.
I am no sentimental admirer of the savage state. I do
not get my ideas of nature from Rousseau. I am aware of
its material and mental lack, its low and narrow range. I
believe that civilization is the natural destiny of humanity,
the elevation and refinement of our powers.
Nevertheless, no one who faces the facts can avoid
the conclusion that—in the heart of our civilization—
there are large classes that even the sorriest savage would
not want to trade places with. Given the choice of being
born an Australian aborigine, an arctic Eskimo, or among
the lowest classes in a highly civilized country such as
Great Britain, one would make an infinitely better choice
in selecting the lot of the savage.
Those condemned to want in the midst of wealth
suffer all the hardships of savages, without the sense of
personal freedom. If their horizon is wider, it is only to
see the blessings they cannot enjoy. I challenge anyone
to produce an authentic account of primitive life citing
the degradation we find in official documents regarding
the condition of the working poor in highly civilized
countries.
I have outlined a simple theory that recognizes the
most obvious relations. It explains the conjunction of poverty with wealth; of low wages with high productivity; of
158
The Problem Solved
degradation amid enlightenment; of virtual slavery in political liberty. It flows from a general and unchanging law.
It shows the sequence and relation between phenomena
that are separate and contradictory without this theory.
It explains why interest and wages are higher in new
communities, even though the production is less. It explains why improvements that increase the productive
power of labor and capital do not increase the reward of
either. It shows that what is commonly called a conflict
between labor and capital is, in fact, a harmony of interests between them. It proves the fallacies of protectionism, while showing why free trade fails to benefit the
working class.
It explains why want increases with abundance, and
why wealth tends to greater and greater concentration. It
explains periodic recessions and depressions—and why
large numbers of potential producers stand idle, without
the absurd assumption that there is too little work to do or
too many hands to do it. It explains the negative impact of
machinery, without denying the natural advantages it gives.
It explains why vice and misery appear among dense
populations, without attributing to the laws of God those
defects arising only from the shortsighted and selfish decrees of humans.
This is an explanation in accordance with all the facts.
Look at the world today. The same conditions exist in different countries—regardless of the type of government,
industries, tariffs, or currency. But everywhere you find
poverty in the midst of wealth, you will find that land is
monopolized. Instead of being treated as the common
property of all the people, land is treated as the private
property of individuals. And before labor is allowed to use
Persistence of Poverty
159
it, large sums are extorted from the earnings of labor.
Compare different countries. You will see that it is not
the abundance of capital, nor the productiveness of labor,
that makes wages high or low. Rather, wages vary with the
extent to which those who monopolize land can levy tribute in the form of rent.
It is well-known, even among the most ignorant, that
new countries are always better for workers than rich countries. In new countries, although the total amount of wealth
is small, land is cheap. Whereas in rich countries, land is
costly. Wherever rent is relatively low, you will find wages
relatively high. Wherever rent is high, wages are low. As
land values increase, poverty deepens and beggars appear.
In the new settlements, where land is cheap, any inequalities in condition are very slight. In great cities, where land
is so valuable it is measured by the foot, you will find the
extremes of poverty and luxury.
The disparity between the two extremes of the social
scale may always be measured by the price of land. Land is
more valuable in New York than San Francisco; and in
New York, the squalor and misery would make the San
Franciscan stand aghast. Land is more valuable in London than in New York; and in London, the squalor and
destitution is worse than in New York.
The same relation is obvious if you compare the same
country in different times. The enormous increase in the
efficiency of labor has only added to rent. The rent of agricultural land in England is many times greater than it
was 500 years ago.* Yet wages, measured as a proportion
*Prof. James Rogers (1823-1900) estimated the increase in rent at fourteen times, if measured in wheat, or 120 times if measured in money.
160
The Problem Solved
of total production, have decreased everywhere.
The Black Death brought a great rise in wages in England in the fourteenth century. There can be no doubt
that such an awful decline in population decreased the effective power of labor. However, less competition for land
lowered rent to an even greater extent. This allowed wages
to rise so much that land holders enacted penal laws to
keep them down.
The reverse effect followed the monopolization of land
during the reign of Henry VIII. The commons were enclosed, and church lands divided among parasites who were
thus enabled to found noble families. The result was the
same as from a speculative increase in land values. According to none other than Malthus, a worker in the reign
of Henry VII would get half a bushel of wheat for about
one day’s common labor. By end of Elizabeth’s reign, it
would take three days of labor to purchase the same
amount. The rapid monopolization of land carried the
speculative rent line beyond the normal rent line, and produced tramps and paupers. We have lately seen similar
effects from similar causes in the United States.
We may as well cite historical illustrations of the attraction of gravity; the principle is just as universal and
just as obvious. Rent must reduce wages. This is as clear as
an equation: the larger the subtractor, the smaller the remainder.
The truth is self-evident. Put this question to anyone
capable of consecutive thought:
“Suppose some land should arise from the English
Channel. This land will remain unappropriated—like the
commons that once comprised a part of England. An
unlimited number of workers can have free access to it.
Persistence of Poverty
161
Here, a common laborer could make ten shillings a day.
What would be the effect upon wages in England?”
They would at once tell you that common wages
throughout England must soon rise to ten shillings a day.
Ask, “What would be the effect on rents?”
After a moment’s reflection, they would tell you, “Rents
must fall.”
If they thought out the next step, they would tell you
that all this would happen without much labor being diverted to the new natural opportunities. Nor would the
forms and direction of industry change much. The only
loss would be the kind of production that now yields, to
labor and landlord together, less than labor could secure
on the new opportunities.
The great rise in wages would be at the expense of rent.
Next take some hardheaded business owners who have
no theories, but know how to make money. Say to them:
“Here is a little village. In ten years, it will be a great city.
The railroad and the electric light are coming; it will soon
abound with all the machinery and improvements that
enormously multiply the effective power of labor.”
Now ask: “Will interest be any higher?”
“No!”
“Will the wages of common labor be any higher?”
“No,” they will tell you. “On the contrary, chances are
they will be lower. It will not be easier for a mere laborer
to make an independent living; chances are it will be
harder.”
“What, then, will be higher?” you ask.
“Rent, and the value of land!”
“Then what should I do?” you beg.
“Get yourself a piece of ground, and hold on to it.”
162
The Problem Solved
If you take their advice under these circumstances, you
need do nothing more. You may sit down and smoke your
pipe; you may lie around like an idler; you may go up in a
balloon, or down a hole in the ground. Yet without doing
one stroke of work, without adding one iota to the wealth
of the community—in ten years you will be rich!
In the new city you may have a luxurious mansion.
But among its public buildings, will be an almshouse.
In all our long investigation, we have been advancing
to this simple truth:
Land is required for the exertion of labor in the production of wealth. Therefore, to control the land is to command all
the fruits of labor, except only enough to enable labor to continue to exist.
We have been advancing as through enemy country,
in which every step must be secured, every position fortified, and every bypath explored. This simple truth, and its
application to social and political problems, is hidden from
the masses—hidden partly by its very simplicity. And in
greater part by widespread fallacies and erroneous habits
of thought. These lead us to look in every direction but
the right one for an explanation of the evils that oppress
and threaten the civilized world.
In back of these elaborate fallacies and misleading
theories is an active, energetic power. This is the power
that writes laws and molds thought. It operates in every
country, no matter what its political forms may be. It is
the power of a vast and dominant financial interest.
But this truth is so simple and clear, that to fully see it
once is to recognize it always. There are pictures that,
though looked at again and again, present only a confused
Persistence of Poverty
163
pattern of lines. Or, perhaps they seem to be only a landscape, trees, or something of the kind. Then, attention is
called to the fact that these things make up a face or a
figure. Once this relation is recognized, it is always clear.
It is so in this case.
In the light of this truth, all social facts group themselves in an orderly relation. The most diverse phenomena
are seen to spring from one great principle. It is not the
relations of capital and labor, not the pressure of population
against subsistence, that explains the unequal development
of society.
The great cause of inequality in the distribution of wealth
is inequality in the ownership of land.
Ownership of land is the great fundamental fact that
ultimately determines the social, the political, and consequently the intellectual and moral condition of a people.
And it must be so.
For land is the home of humans, the storehouse we
must draw upon for all our needs. Land is the material to
which we must apply our labor to supply all our desires.
Even the products of the sea cannot be taken, or the light
of the sun enjoyed, or any of the forces of nature utilized,
without the use of land or its products.
On land we are born, from it we live, to it we return
again. We are children of the soil as truly as a blade of
grass or the flower of the field. Take away from people all
that belongs to land, and they are but disembodied spirits.
Material progress cannot rid us of our dependence on land;
it can only add to our power to produce wealth from land.
Hence, when land is monopolized, progress might go
on to infinity without increasing wages or improving the
164
The Problem Solved
condition of those who have only their labor. It can only
add to the value of land and the power its possession gives.
Everywhere, in all times, among all peoples, possession of land is the base of aristocracy, the foundation of
great fortunes, the source of power. As the Brahmins said,
ages ago:
“To whomsoever the soil at any time belongs, to him
belong the fruits of it. White parasols and elephants mad
with pride are the flowers of a grant of land.”
Ineffective Remedies
165
Sixth Part:
The Remedy
Chapter 24
Ineffective Remedies
OUR CONCLUSIONS point to a solution. It is so radical that
it will not be considered if we believe less drastic measures
might work. Yet it is so simple that its effectiveness will be
discounted until more elaborate measures are evaluated.
Let us review current proposals to relieve social distress.
For convenience, we may group them into six categories:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
More efficient government
Better education and work habits
Unions or associations
Cooperation
Government regulation
Reistribution of land
1. More efficient government
Social distress is largely attributed to the immense burdens of government: huge debts, military establishments,
and general extravagance (which is especially characteristic of large cities). We must also include the robbery of
protective tariffs, which take a dollar or more out of the
166
The Remedy
pockets of consumers for every quarter they put in the
treasury.
The connection between these immense sums, taken
from the people, and the privations of the lower classes
seems obvious. From a superficial viewpoint, we might
naturally suppose that reducing this enormous burden
would make it easier for the poor to make a living. However, considering the economic principles we have identified, we can see that this would not be the effect.
Reducing taxes taken from production would be
equivalent to increasing productivity. It would, in effect,
add to the productive power of labor—just as increasing
population and technological improvements do. As it does
in those cases, any advantage would go to landlords in
higher rents. The great advances of power and machinery have not alleviated poverty—they have only increased
rent. And so would this.
I will not dispute that if these things could be done
suddenly, without the destruction of a revolution, there
might be a temporary improvement in the condition of
the lowest classes. Unfortunately, such reform is clearly
impossible. Yet even if it were possible, any temporary
improvement would ultimately be swallowed up by increased land values. Ultimately, the condition of those
who live by their labor would not be improved.
A dim consciousness of this is beginning to pervade
the masses, and it constitutes a grave political difficulty
closing in around the American republic. Those with
nothing but their labor care little about the extravagance
of government. Many—especially in the cities—are
disposed to look upon it as a good thing, “furnishing
employment ” and “putting money in circulation.”
Ineffective Remedies
167
“Boss Tweed”* robbed New York as a guerrilla chief might
a captured town. He was one of the new banditti grasping control of government in all our cities. His thievery
was notorious, his spoils blazoned in big diamonds and
lavish personal expenditure. Yet he was undoubtedly
popular with a majority of the voters.
Let me be clearly understood. I am not saying economy
in government is not desirable. I am simply saying that
reducing the cost of government will have no direct effect
on eliminating poverty or increasing wages—as long as land
is monopolized.
Nonetheless, every effort should be made to reduce
useless expenditures. The more complex and extravagant
government becomes, the more it becomes a power distinct from, and independent of, the people. We face momentous problems, yet the most important questions of
government are barely considered. The average American
voter has prejudices, party feelings, and general notions of
a certain kind. But he or she gives as much thought to the
fundamental questions of government as a streetcar horse
gives to the profits of the line. Were this not the case, so
many hoary abuses could not have survived, nor so many
new ones been added.
Anything that tends to make government simple and
inexpensive tends to put it under control of the people.
But no reduction in the expenses of government can, of
itself, cure or mitigate the evils arising from a constant
tendency toward unequal distribution of wealth.
* William Marcy Tweed (1823-1878), political leader of the infamous
Tammany Hall, an organization that stole millions from the citizens of
New York City. Tweed held several public offices, and died in prison.
168
The Remedy
2. Better education and work habits
Many believe that poverty is due to lack of industry,
frugality, and intelligence. This soothes any sense of responsibility and flatters by its suggestion of superiority.
They attribute their better circumstances to superior industry and superior intelligence—to say nothing of a superior lack of conscience, which is often the determining
quality of a millionaire.
Yet anyone who has grasped the laws determining the
distribution of wealth, which we discovered in previous
chapters, will see the mistake. It is true that any one of
several competitors may win a race, but it is impossible
that every one can.
This being the case, industry, skill, frugality, and intelligence can help the individual only in so far as they are
superior to the general level. Just as in a race, speed benefits a runner only if it exceeds that of the competitors. If
one person works harder or with superior skill or intelligence than ordinary people, that person will get ahead.
But if the average is brought up to this higher point, the
extra effort will bring only average wages. To get ahead,
one must then work harder still.
For once land acquires value, wages do not depend
upon the real earnings or product of labor—they depend
on what is left after rent is taken out. When all land is
monopolized, rent will drive wages down to the point at
which the poorest class will consent to live and reproduce.
Life might be more comfortable for many poor families if they were taught to prepare cheap dishes. But if
the working class generally came to live like that, wages
would ultimately fall proportionally. If American workers came down to the Chinese standard of living, they
Ineffective Remedies
169
would ultimately come down to the Chinese standard of
wages. The potato was introduced into Ireland to improve the condition of the poor by lowering their cost of
living. The actual result was to raise rents and lower wages.
When the potato blight came, the population had already reduced its standard of comfort so low that the
next step was starvation.
So if one individual works longer, that one may earn
more. But the wages of all cannot be increased this way. It
is well-known that occupations with longer hours do not
have higher wages. In fact, the longer the working day, the
more helpless the laborer generally becomes. Likewise, in
industries where it has become common for a wife and
children to supplement earnings, the wages of a whole family rarely exceed that of an individual in other occupations. Bohemian cigar makers of New York employ men,
women, and children in their tenements. They have thus
reduced wages to less than the Chinese were getting in
San Francisco.
These general facts are well known, and are fully recognized in standard economics texts. However, they are
explained away by the Malthusian theory of the supposed
tendency of population to multiply to the limit of subsistence. The true explanation, as I have sufficiently shown,
is in the tendency of rent to reduce wages.
As to the effects of education, it may be especially
worthwhile to say a few words, for there is a prevailing
tendency to attribute some magical influence to it. College graduates often think no better, and sometimes not as
well, as those who have never been to college. Be this as it
may, education can operate on wages only by increasing
the effective power of labor. (At least until it enables the
170
The Remedy
masses to discover and remove the true cause of unequal
distribution of wealth.)
Education, therefore, has the same effect as increased
skill or industry. It can raise the wages of an individual
only in so far as it renders one superior to others. When
reading and writing were rare accomplishments, a clerk
commanded high wages. Now that they are nearly universal, they give no advantage. The Chinese are virtually all
literate; yet wages in China are the lowest possible.
The diffusion of intelligence cannot raise wages generally, nor in any way improve the condition of the lowest
class. One senator called them the “mudsills” of society: those
who must rest on the soil, no matter how high the superstructure is built. The only hope of education is that it may
make people discontented with a state that condemns producers to a life of toil while non-producers loll in luxury.
No increase in the power of labor can increase general
wages—so long as rent swallows up all the gain. This is not
merely a deduction from principles; it is a fact proven by
experience. The growth of knowledge and the progress of
invention have multiplied the effective power of labor over
and over again without increasing wages.
It is true that greater prudence and higher intelligence
are associated with better material conditions. But this is
the effect, not the cause. Wherever conditions have improved, improvement in personal qualities has followed.
Wherever conditions have worsened, these qualities have
decayed. Yet, nowhere do we find that increased industry,
skill, prudence, or intelligence have improved conditions
among those condemned to toil for a bare living.
Qualities that raise people above animals are superimposed on those they share with animals. Only when we
Ineffective Remedies
171
are relieved from the wants of our animal nature can our
intellectual and moral nature grow. Condemn people to
drudgery for the necessities of an animal existence, and
they will do only what they are forced to do.
Improvements may not show immediately. Increased
wages may first be taken out in idleness and dissipation.
But ultimately they will bring industry, skill, intelligence,
and thrift. If we compare different countries, or different
classes in the same country, or different periods for the
same people, we find an invariable result: personal qualities appear as material conditions are improved.
To make people industrious, prudent, skillful, and intelligent, they must be relieved from want. If you would
have a slave show the virtues of a free person, you must
first make the slave free.
3. Unions or associations
The laws of distribution show that combinations of
workers actually can advance wages—and not at the expense of other workers, as is sometimes claimed; nor at
the expense of capital, as is generally believed. Ultimately,
it is at the expense of rent. The misconceptions arise from
the erroneous idea that wages are drawn from capital.
Unions have secured higher wages in particular trades
without lowering wages in other trades or reducing the
rate of profits. Wages affect an employer in comparison to
other employers. The first employer who succeeds in reducing wages gains an advantage; the first compelled to
pay more is put at a disadvantage. But the differential ends
when the competitors are also included in the change. Any
gain or loss is purely relative, and disappears when the
whole community is considered.
If the change in wages creates a change in relative
172
The Remedy
demand, then capital fixed in machinery, buildings, or
other things may become more (or less) profitable. But a
new equilibrium is soon reached. If there is too little capital in a certain form, the tendency to assume that form
soon brings it up to the required amount. If there is too
much, reduced production soon restores the level.
A change in wages in any particular occupation may
cause a change in the relative demand for labor—but it
cannot produce a change in total demand. Suppose a union
raises wages in a particular industry in one country. Meanwhile, wages go down in the same industry in another
country. If the change is great enough, part of the demand
in the first country will now be supplied by imports from
the second. Higher imports of one kind cause a corresponding decrease in imports of other kinds, or else a corresponding increase in exports. For one country can obtain
the products of another country only by exchanging the
products of its own labor and capital.
If all wages in any particular country were doubled,
that country would continue to export and import the same
things, and in the same proportions. Exchange is determined by the relative, not the absolute, cost of production.
If wages in some industries doubled while others increased
less, there would be a change in the proportion of the various things imported. Still, there would be no change in
the proportion between exports and imports.
Therefore, most of the objections to trade unions are
groundless. Their success cannot reduce other wages, nor
decrease the profits of capital, nor injure national prosperity. Nevertheless, the difficulties confronting effective combinations of workers are so great that the good they can
accomplish is limited. In addition, there are inherent dis-
Ineffective Remedies
173
advantages in the process. All any union has done is to
raise wages in a particular occupation. This is a task that
grows in difficulty. As wages of any particular kind rise
above the normal level of other wages, there is a strong
tendency to bring them back.
For instance, say a union can raise wages for typesetters by ten percent. Immediately, relative supply and demand are affected. On the one hand, there will be less
demand for typesetting. On the other, higher wages will
tend to increase the number of typesetters. This occurs in
ways even the strongest combination cannot prevent. If
the increase were twenty percent, these tendencies would
be stronger still.
As a practical matter, unions can do relatively little to
raise wages, even when supporting each other. They do
not affect the lower strata of unorganized laborers, who
need help the most. And those wages ultimately determine all above them. The effective approach would be by
a general combination including workers of all kinds.
Unfortunately, such a combination is practically impossible. The difficulties of combination are hard enough in
the smallest and most highly paid trades. They become
greater as we go down the industrial scale.
The only method unions have, the strike, is a struggle
of endurance. And do not forget who is really pitted against
whom. It is not labor against capital; it is labor on one
side, and landowners on the other. For wages cannot increase unless rent decreases. But landowners can sit and
wait. While landowners are inconvenienced, capital is destroyed, and laborers starve.
Land is absolutely necessary for production. It is
certain to increase in value in all growing countries. These
174
The Remedy
facts alone produce among landowners—without any formal alliance—the same effect that the most rigorous federation of workers or capitalists would. The struggle of
endurance involved in a strike is really what it has often
been compared to: war. Like all war, it reduces wealth. Like
war, the organization for a strike must be tyrannical. Those
who would fight for freedom give up their personal freedom on entering the army. They become a mere cog in a
great machine. So it must be with workers who organize
for a strike. Unions are, therefore, necessarily destructive
of the very things that workers seek to gain through them:
wealth and freedom.
4. Cooperation
It has become the fashion to preach cooperation as a
remedy for the grievances of the working class. Since these
evils do not arise from any conflict between labor and capital, cooperation cannot raise wages nor relieve poverty.
Two kinds of proposals have been made: cooperation
in supply and cooperation in production. Cooperation in
supply is simply a device to save labor and eliminate risk.
No matter how many middlemen it eliminates, it only reduces the cost of exchange. Its effect upon distribution is
the same as improvements and inventions. These have
wonderfully facilitated trade in modern times—yet the
effect is only to increase rent.
Cooperation in production is simply the substitution
of proportional wages for fixed wages. There are occasional
instances of this in almost all occupations. Sometimes
management is left to the workers, and the capitalist only
takes a fixed proportion of net production. All that is
claimed for cooperation in production is that it makes the
worker more active and industrious. In other words, it in-
Ineffective Remedies
175
creases the efficiency of labor. Its effect, therefore, is in the
same direction as other forms of material progress. It can
produce only the same result—higher rent.
It is striking proof of how basic principles are ignored
that cooperation is proposed as a means of raising wages
and relieving poverty. It can have no such general tendency. Imagine that cooperation of supply and cooperation of production replaced present methods. Cooperative
stores connect producer and consumer with a minimum
of expense. Cooperative factories, farms, and mines abolish capitalist employers who pay fixed wages.
All this greatly increases the efficiency of labor. What
of it? It becomes possible to produce the same amount of
wealth with less labor. Consequently, owners of land—the
source of all wealth—could command a greater amount
for the use of their land. This is not just theory; it is proven
by facts. Experience has shown that improvements in the
methods and machinery of production and exchange have
no tendency to improve the condition of the lowest class.
Wages are lower and poverty is deeper where trade goes
on at the least cost, and where production has the best
technology. The advantage only adds to rent.
But what if there were cooperation between producers and landowners? That would simply amount to the
payment of rent in kind. Call it cooperation, if you choose,
but the terms would still be fixed by the laws that determine rent. Wherever land is monopolized, any increase in
productive power simply gives landowners the power to
demand a larger share.
Nonetheless, in many instances where it has been
tried, it seems that cooperation has noticeably improved
the condition of those immediately engaged in it. This is
176
The Remedy
due to the fact that these cases are isolated. Industry or
skill may improve the condition of those who possess
them in superior degree. When these improvements become widespread, however, they cease to have the same
effect. Likewise, one may benefit from a special advantage in procuring supplies or a special efficiency given to
some labor. But these benefits would be lost as soon as
the improvements became so prevalent as to affect the
general relationships of distribution.
Increased productive power does not add to the reward of labor. This is not because of competition, but
because competition is one-sided. There can be no production without land—and land is monopolized. Producers must compete for its use, and this forces wages to a
minimum. It gives all the advantage of increasing productive power to landowners—in higher rents and increased
land values. Destroy this monopoly, and competition would
accomplish what cooperation attempts: giving everyone
what they fairly earn. Destroy this monopoly, and industry must become the cooperation of equals.
5. Government Regulation
Space will not permit a detailed examination of proposals to alleviate poverty by government regulation of
industry and accumulation. In their most comprehensive
forms, we generally call these methods socialism. Nor is
analysis necessary, for the same defects apply to all of them.
They substitute governmental control for the freedom of
individual action. They attempt to secure by restraint what
can better be secured by freedom. We should not resort to
them if we can achieve the same ends any other way.
For instance, a graduated income tax aims to mitigate
the immense concentration of wealth. The end is good;
Ineffective Remedies
177
but look at the means required. It employs a large number
of officials with inquisitorial powers. There are temptations to bribery, perjury, and all other means of evasion,
which beget a demoralization of opinion. It puts a premium upon unscrupulousness and a tax upon conscience.
Finally, in proportion to accomplishing its effect, it weakens the incentive to accumulate wealth, one of the driving
forces of industrial progress.
If these elaborate schemes for regulating everything and
finding a place for everybody could be carried out, we would
have a state of society resembling that of ancient Peru.
Modern society cannot successfully attempt socialism in
anything approaching such a form. The only force that has
ever proved effective for it, a strong religious faith, grows
fainter every day. We have passed out of the socialism of the
tribal state. We cannot enter it again, except by retrogression that would involve anarchy and perhaps barbarism.
The ideal of socialism is grand and noble. I am convinced it is possible to achieve. But such a state of society
cannot be manufactured—it must grow. Society is an organism, not a machine. It can live only by the individual
life of its parts. In the free and natural development of all
its parts, the harmony of the whole will be secured. All
that is necessary is “Land and Liberty.”*
6. Redistribution of Land
Many suspect that possession of land is somehow connected with our social problems. Most propositions look
toward a more general division of land. Some seek to
restrict the size of individual holdings. Grants to assist
in the settlement of public lands have even been sug* Motto of Russian revolutionaries, called Nihilists, in 1878.
178
The Remedy
gested. Such measures would merely allow ownership of
land to more quickly assume the form to which it tends.
Ownership in Great Britain and the United States has
been steadily concentrating. While statistical tables are
sometimes quoted to show a decrease in the average size
of holdings, ownership of land may still be concentrating.
As land passes to more intense use, the size of holdings tends to diminish. A stock range becomes a large farm,
a small farm becomes a vegetable garden, a patch of land
too small for even this makes a large property in the city.
Thus, growing population naturally reduces the size of
holdings by putting lands to higher or more intense uses.
This process is very conspicuous in new countries. Average holdings of one acre in a city may show a much greater
concentration of ownership than average holdings of 640
acres in a new township.
I refer to this to show the fallacy of assertions that
land monopoly is an evil that will cure itself. On the contrary, it is obvious that the proportion of landowners to
the whole population is constantly decreasing.
We clearly see a strong tendency toward concentration in agriculture. Small farms are being combined into
larger ones. Only a few years ago, 320 acres would have
made a large farm anywhere. In California there are now
farms up to sixty thousand acres, while Dakota farms embrace a hundred thousand acres.
The reason is obvious. The use of machinery causes a
general tendency towards large-scale production. Agriculture is beginning to exhibit the same trend that replaced
independent hand weavers with factories. Therefore, any
measure that merely allows a greater subdivision of land
would be ineffective. Further, any measure to force it would
Ineffective Remedies
179
reduce productivity. If land can be cultivated more cheaply
in large parcels, restricting ownership to small ones will
reduce the aggregate production of wealth.
Therefore, any effort to achieve a fairer division of
wealth by such restrictions is subject to the drawback that
it lessens the amount to be divided. It would be like the
story of the monkey dividing cheese between cats, who
equalized matters by taking a bite off the biggest piece. A
further and fatal objection is that restriction will not secure the only end worth aiming at: a fair division. It will
not reduce rent. Therefore it cannot increase wages. It may
make the comfortable classes larger, but it will not improve the condition of the lowest class. Thus, subdivision
of land does nothing to cure the evils of land monopoly. It
may even discourage adoption of more sweeping measures.
It strengthens the existing system by interesting a larger
number of people in its maintenance.
Let us abandon all attempts to eliminate land monopoly by restricting ownership. An equal distribution of
land is impossible. Yet anything short of that would be
only a relief, not a cure. Indeed, it would be a relief that
would prevent the adoption of a cure.
Nor is any remedy worth considering that does not
flow with the natural direction of social development.
There can be no mistaking that concentration is the order of development. The concentration of people in large
cities, of handicrafts in large factories, of transportation
by railroad and steamship lines, and of agricultural operations in large fields, all affirm this. To successfully resist this trend we would have to banish steam and
electricity from human service.
180
The Remedy
Chapter 25
The True Remedy
WE HAVE TRACED the unequal distribution of wealth, the
curse and menace of modern civilization, to the institution of private property in land. As long as this institution exists, no increase in production will permanently
benefit the masses. On the contrary, any improvements
must depress their condition further. We have examined
the remedies currently proposed to relieve poverty and
improve the distribution of wealth, and found them all
ineffective or impractical. Poverty deepens as wealth increases; wages fall while productivity grows. All because
land, the source of all wealth and the field of all labor, is
monopolized.
Deduction and induction have brought us to the same
truth: Unequal ownership of land causes unequal distribution of wealth. And because unequal ownership of land
is inseperable from the recognition of individual property in land, it necessarily follows that there is only one
remedy for the unjust distribution of wealth:
We must make land common property.*
*Many of George’s followers have sought to distance themselves from
the “communistic” tone of this statement. However, the idea of property clearly includes the use of something as an asset, to be sold, let,
or collateralized—and George held that it is unjust to put land
The True Remedy
181
But this is a truth that will arouse the most bitter
antagonism, given the present state of society. It must
fight its way, inch by inch. It will be necessary to meet
the objections of those who, even when forced to admit
this truth, will contend that it cannot be practically applied. In doing this we shall bring our previous reasoning to a new and crucial test. Just as we test addition by
subtraction and multiplication by division, so we can we
test our conclusions by the adequacy of our remedy. If it
is practical, it proves our conclusions are correct.
The laws of the universe are harmonious. If the remedy to which we have been led is the true one, it must be
consistent with justice; it must be practical in application;
it must accord with the tendencies of social development;
and it must harmonize with other reforms.
All this I propose to show.
The laws of the universe do not deny the natural aspirations of the human heart. The progress of society can be
toward equality, not inequality. Economic law will prove
the perceptions of Marcus Aurelius: “We are made for
cooperation—like feet, like hands, like eyelids, like the rows
of the upper and lower teeth.”
to such uses. Nowhere in any of his writings does he advocate the
seizure or nationalization of legitimate property in the products of
labor; on the contrary, George held that such wealth should not even
be taxed.
182
Justice of the Remedy
Seventh Part:
Justice of the Remedy
Chapter 26
The Injustice of Private Property In Land
JUSTICE IS FUNDAMENTAL to the human mind, though often warped by superstition, habit, and selfishness. When I
propose to abolish private property in land, the first question to be asked is that of justice. Only what is just can be
wise; only what is right will endure. I bow to this demand
and accept this test. If private property in land is just, then
what I propose is false. If private property in land is unjust, then my remedy is true.
What constitutes the rightful basis of property? What
allows someone to justly say, “This is mine!”? Is it not,
primarily, the right of a person to one’s own self? To the
use of one’s own powers? To enjoy the fruits of one’s own
labor? Each person is a definite, coherent, independent
whole. Each particular pair of hands obeys a particular
brain and is related to a particular body. And this alone
justifies individual ownership.
As each person belongs to himself or herself, so labor
belongs to the individual when put in concrete form. For
this reason, what someone makes or produces belongs to
Injustice of Private Property in Land
183
that person—even against the claim of the whole world.
It is that person’s property, to use or enjoy, give or exchange,
or even destroy. No one else can rightfully claim it. And
this right to the exclusive possession and enjoyment wrongs
no one else. Thus, there is a clear and indisputable title to
everything produced by human exertion. It descends from
the original producer, in whom it is vested by natural law.
The pen that I write with is justly mine. No other
human being can rightfully lay claim to it, for in me is the
title of the producers who made it. It has become mine
because it was transferred to me by the stationer, to whom
it was transferred by the importer, who obtained the exclusive right to it by transfer from the manufacturer. By
the same process of purchase, the manufacturer acquired
the vested rights of those who dug the material from the
ground and shaped it into a pen.
Thus, my exclusive right of ownership in the pen
springs from the natural right of individuals to the use of
their own faculties—the source from which all ideas of
exclusive ownership arise. It is not only the original source,
it is the only source.
Nature acknowledges no ownership or control existing in humans, except the results of labor. Is there any
other way to affect material things except by exerting the
power of one’s own faculties? All people exist in nature on
equal footing and have equal rights. Nature recognizes no
claim but labor—and without respect to who claims it.
When a pirate ship spreads its sails, wind fills them; as it
would those of a missionary. Fish will bite whether the
line leads to a good child who goes to Sunday school or a
bad one playing truant. The sun shines and the rain falls
on the just and unjust alike.
184
Justice of the Remedy
The laws of nature are the decrees of the Creator. They
recognize no right but labor. As nature gives only to labor,
the exertion of labor in production is the only title to exclusive possession.
This right of ownership springing from labor excludes
the possibility of any other right of ownership. A person
is rightfully entitled to the product of his or her labor (or
the labor of someone else from whom the right has been
received).
It is production that gives the producer the right to exclusive possession and enjoyment. If so, there can be no right
to exclusive possession of anything that is not the product
of labor. Therefore, private property in land is wrong.
The right to the product of labor cannot be enjoyed
without the right to free use of the opportunities offered
by nature. To admit a right to property in nature is to deny
the right of property as the product of labor. When nonproducers can claim a portion of the wealth created by
producers—as rent—then the right of producers to the
fruits of their labor is denied to that extent.
There is no escape from this position. To affirm that
someone can rightfully claim exclusive ownership of his
or her own labor—when embodied in material things—is
to deny that any one can rightfully claim exclusive ownership in land. Property in land is a claim having no justification in nature—it is a claim founded in the way societies
are organized.
What keeps us from recognizing the injustice of private property in land? By habit, we include all things made
subject to ownership in one category—which we call
“property.” The only distinctions are drawn by lawyers,
who distinguish only personal property from real estate—
Injustice of Private Property in Land
185
things movable from things immovable. The real and
natural distinction, however, is between the product of
labor and the free offerings of nature. In the terms of
political economy, between wealth and land. To class them
together is to confuse all thought regarding justice or
injustice, right or wrong.
A house and the lot on which it stands are classed
together by lawyers as real estate. Yet in nature and relations they differ widely. One is produced by human labor
(wealth). The other is a part of nature (land).
The essential characteristic of wealth is that it embodies labor. It is brought into being by human exertion.
Its existence or nonexistence, its increase or decrease, depends on humans. The essential characteristic of land is
that it does not embody labor. It exists irrespective of
human exertion, and irrespective of people. It is the field,
or environment, in which people find themselves; the
storehouse from which their needs must be supplied; the
raw material on which—and the forces with which—they
can act.
The moment this distinction is recognized, we see that
the sanction natural justice gives to one kind of property
is denied to the other. The rightfulness of property that is
the product of labor implies the wrongfulness of the individual ownership of land. The recognition of the former
places all people upon equal terms, and gives them the
due reward of their labor. Whereas the recognition of the
latter is to deny the equal rights of people. It allows those
who do not work to take the natural reward of those who
do. Whatever may be said for the institution of private
property in land, it clearly cannot be defended on the
grounds of justice.
186
Justice of the Remedy
The equal right of all people to the use of land is as
clear as their equal right to breathe the air—a right proclaimed by the very fact of their existence. We cannot suppose that some people have a right to be in this world and
others do not. If we are all here by permission of the Creator, we are all here with an equal title to the bounty of
nature.
This is a right that is natural and inalienable. It is a
right that vests in every human being who enters the world.
During each person’s stay in the world it can be limited
only by the equal rights of others. If all people living were
to unite to grant away their equal rights, they could not
grant away the rights of those who follow them. Have we
made the earth, that we should determine the rights of
those who come after us? No matter how long the claim,
nor how many pieces of paper are issued, there is no right
that natural justice recognizes to give one person possession of land that is not equally the right of all other people.
The smallest infant born in the most squalid room of the
most miserable tenement acquires, at the moment of birth,
a right to land equal to millionaires. And that child is
robbed if that right is denied.
Our previous conclusions were irresistible in and of
themselves. They now stand confirmed by the highest and
final test. Translated from economics into ethics, they show
that the source of increasing misery amid progress is a great
fundamental wrong: the appropriation of land as the exclusive property of some. For it is land on which—and
from which—all people must live. From this fundamental
injustice flow all the injustices that endanger modern development. They condemn the producer of wealth to
poverty, while pampering the non-producer in luxury.
Injustice of Private Property in Land
187
There is nothing strange or inexplicable in the phenomena now perplexing the world. It is not that material
progress is not in itself a good thing. It is not that nature
has produced children it has failed to provide for. It is not
that the Creator has left injustice in natural laws, such
that material progress should bring such bitter fruits. It is
not due to any lack of nature—but to human injustice.
Vice and misery, poverty and pauperism, are not the
legitimate results of growing population and industrial
development. They follow them only because land is
treated as private property. They are the direct and necessary result of violating the supreme law of justice—
giving to the exclusive possession of a few, what nature
has provided for all.
Since labor cannot produce wealth without using land,
denying equal right to use land is, necessarily, denying the
right of labor to its own product. If one person controls
the land on which others must labor, that person can appropriate the product of their labor as the price of permission to labor. This violates the fundamental law of nature:
that a person’s enjoyment of the fruits of nature requires
that person’s exertion.
The unjust distribution of wealth stemming from this
fundamental wrong is separating modern society into the
very rich and the very poor. The continuous increase of
rent is the price labor is forced to pay for the use of land. It
strips the many of wealth they justly earn, and heaps it in
the hands of a few who do nothing to earn it. The few
receive without producing, while others produce without
receiving. One is unjustly enriched—the others are robbed.
Why should those who suffer from this injustice hesitate for one moment to sweep it away? Why should land-
188
Justice of the Remedy
holders be permitted to reap what they have not sown?
Consider for a moment the utter absurdity by which
we gravely pass down titles giving the right to exclusive
possession of the earth, and thus absolute dominion over
others. In California, land titles go back to the government of Mexico, which took them from the Spanish King,
who took them from the Pope. The Pope, by a stroke of
the pen, divided lands—yet to be discovered!—between
Spain and Portugal.
In a word, ownership of land rests upon conquest.
Everywhere, there is not a right that binds, but a force
that compels. And when a title rests only on force, no complaint can be made when force annuls it. Whenever the
people, having the power, choose to annul those titles, no
objection can be made in the name of justice. People have
had the power to take or hold exclusive possession of portions of the earth’s surface. But when and where did there
ever exist the human being who had such a right?
The right to exclusive ownership of anything of human production is clear. No matter how many hands it
has passed through, at the beginning there was human
labor. Someone produced or procured it by exertion, thus
gaining clear title to it against all the rest of mankind.
That person could justly pass it from one to another by
sale or gift.
But at the end of what string of transfers or grants can
we find, or even suppose, a similar title to any part of the
material universe? To improvements, such an original title
can be shown. But this is a title only to the improvements,
and not to the land itself. If I clear a forest, drain a swamp,
or fill a bog, all I can justly claim is the value given by
these exertions. It gives me no right to the land itself. I
Injustice of Private Property in Land
189
have no claim other than my equal share with every other
member of the community toward the value added by the
growth of the community.
But it will be said: There are improvements that, in
time, become indistinguishable from the land itself. Very
well, then the title to the improvements becomes blended
with the title to the land. The individual right is lost in
the common right. It is the greater that swallows up the
less; not the less that swallows up the greater. Nature does
not proceed from humans, but humans from nature. And
it is into the bosom of nature that we and all our works
must return again.
Still, it will be said: Everyone has a right to the use
and enjoyment of nature. In order to gain the full benefit
of labor applied to land, a person must have the exclusive
right to its use. There is no difficulty, however, in determining where the individual right ends and the common
right begins. A delicate and exact test is supplied by value.
With its aid, there is no difficulty in determining and securing the exact rights of each, and the equal rights of all.
This can be determined, no matter how dense population
becomes.
The value of land, as we have seen, is the price of monopoly. It is the relative, not the absolute, capability of
land that determines its value. No matter what its intrinsic qualities may be, land that is no better than other land
that can be had for free can have no value. The value of
land always measures the difference between it and the
best land that may be had for free.
Thus, the value of land expresses, in exact and tangible
form, the right the community has in land held by an individual. And rent, therefore, expresses the exact amount an
190
Justice of the Remedy
individual should pay the community to satisfy the equal
rights of all other members.
We now have a method to reconcile the stability of
tenure, required for improvement, with a full and complete recognition of the equal rights of all to the use of
land. We can concede the undisturbed use of land to priority of possession—if we collect rent for the benefit of
the community.
What of the deduction of a complete and exclusive
individual right to land from priority of occupation? That
is, if possible, the most absurd ground on which land ownership can be defended. How can order of occupation give
exclusive and perpetual title to the surface of a globe on
which countless generations succeed each other! Did the
last generation have any better right to the use of this world
than we? Or those of a hundred years ago? Or of a thousand years ago?
Does the first person to arrive at a banquet acquire
the right to turn back all the chairs and claim that no
other guests can eat the food unless they agree to the
first person’s terms? Does the first person with a ticket at
the theater have the right to shut the doors and have the
performance go on for him or her alone? Does the first
passenger who enters a railroad car obtain the right to
scatter baggage over all the seats and force all subsequent
passengers to stand?
These cases are perfectly analogous. We arrive and we
depart. We are guests at a banquet continually spread, spectators and participants in an entertainment where there is
room for all who come. We are passengers on an orb whirling through space. Our rights to take and possess cannot
be exclusive. They must be bounded, everywhere, by the
Injustice of Private Property in Land
191
equal rights of others.
A passenger in a railroad car may spread baggage
around only until other passengers come in. So may settlers take and use as much land as they choose, until it is
needed by others. This fact is shown by land acquiring a
value when the initial right must be curtailed by the equal
rights of the others. But no priority of appropriation can
give a right that will bar the equal rights of others. If this
were not the case, then—by priority of appropriation—
one person could acquire the exclusive right to a whole
township, a whole state, a whole continent. If one could
concentrate the individual rights to the whole surface of
the globe, that person alone of all the teeming billions
would have the right to live, and could expel all the rest of
the inhabitants.
In point of fact, this absurd supposition actually does
occur, though on a smaller scale. I will refer to Britain
only because land ownership is more concentrated there,
and it affords a striking illustration of what private property in land necessarily involves. But it is true everywhere,
including the United States. The territorial lords of Great
Britain have, over and over again, expelled the native population from large areas. People, whose ancestors had lived
on the land from time immemorial, have been forced to
emigrate, become paupers, or starve. The vast body of the
British people and their subjects are forced to pay enormous sums to a few—for the privilege of being permitted
to live on the land they so fondly call their own.
192
Justice of the Remedy
Chapter 27
The Enslavement of Labor
AS CHATTEL SLAVERY, the owning of people, is unjust—so
private ownership of land is unjust. Ownership of land
always gives ownership of people. To what degree, is measured by the need for land. When starvation is the only
alternative, the ownership of people involved in the ownership of land becomes absolute. This is simply the law of
rent in different form.
Place one hundred people on an island from which
there is no escape. Make one of them the absolute owner
of the others—or the absolute owner of the soil. It will
make no difference—either to owner or to the others—
which one you choose. Either way, one individual will be
the absolute master of the other ninety-nine. Denying
permission to them to live on the island would force them
into the sea.
The same cause must operate, in the same way and to
the same end, even on a larger scale and through more complex relations. When people are compelled to live on—and
from—land treated as the exclusive property of others, the
ultimate result is the enslavement of workers. Though less
direct and less obvious, relations will tend to the same state
as on our hypothetical island. As population increases and
productivity improves, we move toward the same absolute
mastery of landlords and the same abject helplessness of
The Enslavement of Labor
193
labor. Rent will advance; wages will fall. Landowners continually increase their share of the total production, while
labor’s share constantly declines.
To the extent that moving to cheaper land becomes
difficult or impossible, workers will be reduced to a bare
living—no matter what they produce. Where land is monopolized, they will live as virtual slaves. Despite enormous increase in productive power, wages in the lower and
wider layers of industry tend—everywhere—to the wages
of slavery (i.e., just enough to maintain them in working
condition).
There is nothing strange in this fact. Owning the land
on which—and from which—people must live is virtually
the same as owning the people themselves. In accepting
the right of some individuals to the exclusive use and enjoyment of the earth, we condemn others to slavery. We
do this as fully and as completely as though we had formally made them chattel slaves.
In simple societies, production is largely the direct
application of labor to the soil. There, slavery is the obvious result of a few having an exclusive right to the soil
from which all must live. This is plainly seen in various
forms of serfdom. Chattel slavery originated in the capture of prisoners in war. Though it has existed to some
extent in every part of the globe, its effects have been trivial
compared to the slavery that originates in the appropriation of land.
Wherever society has reached a certain point of development, we see the general subjection of the many by
the few—the result of the appropriation of land as individual property. Ownership of land gives absolute power
over people who cannot live except by using it. Those
194
Justice of the Remedy
who possess the land are masters of the people who dwell
upon it.
The idea of individual ownership naturally and justly
attaches to things of human production. But when it is
extended to land, the rest is just a matter of time. The
strong and cunning easily acquire a superior share in this
species of property. For it is to be had, not by production,
but by appropriation. In becoming lords of the land, they
necessarily become lords of other people.
Ownership of land is the basis of aristocracy. It was
not nobility that gave land, but the possession of land that
gave nobility. All the enormous privileges of the nobility
of medieval Europe flowed from their position as the owners of the soil. This simple principle of ownership produced the lord on one side, and the vassal on the other.
One having all the rights, the other none.
The same cause has enslaved the masses of workers in
every age. It is still acting in the civilized world today. We
may say that personal liberty—freedom to move about—
is universally acknowledged. In the United States and most
civilized countries, political and legal inequality have been
abolished. Yet the greatest cause of inequality remains—
revealing itself in the unequal distribution of wealth.
The essence of slavery is that everything workers produce is taken from them, except enough to support a bare
existence. Under existing conditions, the lowest wages of
free labor invariably tend toward this same state. No matter how much productivity increases, rent steadily swallows up the whole gain (or even more). Thus, the condition
of the masses in every civilized country is tending toward
virtual slavery—under the forms of freedom.
Of all kinds of slavery, this is probably the most cruel
The Enslavement of Labor
195
and relentless. Laborers are robbed of their production and
forced to toil for mere subsistence. But their taskmasters
assume the form of inescapable demands. It does not seem
to be one human being who drives another, but “the inevitable laws of supply and demand.” And for this, no one in
particular is responsible. Even the selfish interest that
prompted the master to look after the well-being of his
slaves is lost.
Labor has become a commodity, and the worker a
machine. There are no masters and slaves, no owners and
owned—only buyers and sellers.
When Southern slaveholders saw the condition of the
free poor in civilized countries, it is no wonder they easily
persuaded themselves to accept slavery. There can be no
doubt that Southern field hands were (as a class) better
fed, better lodged, and better clothed than agricultural laborers in England. In the South during slavery, it would
have been scandalous for masters to force their slaves to
live and work under conditions that large classes of free
white men and women did in Northern cities. If public
opinion had not restrained them, their own selfish interest in maintaining the health and strength of their slaves
would have.
Is it any wonder that demands to abolish slavery
seemed hypocritical to slaveholders? And now that slavery has been abolished, the planters find they have sustained no loss. Ownership of the land—on which the freed
slaves must live—gives them almost as much control of
labor as before. Yet they are relieved of some very expensive responsibilities.
As population increases and land becomes more valuable, the planters will get a greater share (proportionately)
196
Justice of the Remedy
of the earnings of their laborers than they did under slavery. Of course, labor will get a smaller share. At least slaves
got enough to keep them in good physical health. But in
countries such as England, there are large classes of laborers who do not get even that.
These modifying influences are lost in the complicated
processes of modern production, where serfdom assumes
a less obvious form. Those whose labor is appropriated
and those who appropriate it are widely separated through
many intermediate gradations. This makes relations between members of the two classes indirect and general,
while before they were direct and particular.
That such conditions are not more common here is
due to the great extent of fertile land available on this continent. This has not only provided an escape valve for the
older sections of the Union, it has greatly relieved the pressure in Europe. But this avenue of relief cannot last forever. It is already closing up fast. As it closes, the pressure
must become greater.
The working class is being driven into this helpless,
hopeless poverty by a force like a resistless and unpitying
machine. It drives people to acts barbarians would refuse.
The Boston collar manufacturer who pays his workers two
cents an hour may sympathize with their condition. But,
like them, he is governed by the law of competition. His
business cannot survive if he pays more. And so it goes,
through all the intermediate gradations. It seems to be the
inexorable laws of supply and demand that forces the lower
classes into the slavery of poverty. And an individual can
no more dispute this power than the winds and tides.
But in reality, it is the same cause that always has, and
always must, result in slavery:
The Enslavement of Labor
197
The monopolization by some of what nature meant for all.
As long as we recognize private property in land, our
boasted freedom will inevitably involve slavery. Until it is
abolished, Declarations of Independence and Acts of
Emancipation are in vain. So long as one person can claim
exclusive ownership of land—from which other people
must live—slavery will exist. Indeed, as material progress
grows, it must grow and deepen.
198
Justice of the Remedy
Chapter 28
Are Landowners Entitled
to Compensation?
THERE CAN BE NO ESCAPE from this truth: There can be no
honest title to exclusive possession of the earth. Private
property in land is a bold, bare, enormous wrong—like
chattel slavery. The majority of people do not recognize
this, simply because the majority of people do not think.
To them, whatever is, is right. It continues to appear so
until its injustice has been pointed out repeatedly. In general, they are ready to crucify whoever first attempts this.
Yet it is impossible to think at all about the production and distribution of wealth, without seeing that property in land is a fundamentally different thing from
property in objects of human production. Furthermore,
our examination has also shown that private property in
land cannot be justified on the grounds of utility. On the
contrary, it is the great cause of poverty and misery. Expediency, therefore, joins justice in demanding that we abolish it.
This institution has no stronger ground than a mere
municipal regulation. So what reason can there be for hesitation?
One worry—even among those who clearly see that
land, by right, is common property—is this: Restoring
common rights to land appears to be an injustice to those
Compensation for Landowners?
199
who have purchased it with their rightful wealth. Land
being treated as private property for so long, they have
based their calculations upon its permanence. So, it is
said, justice requires that we compensate the owners if
we abolish it.
The essential defect in this lies in the impossibility of
bridging the radical difference between right and wrong.
For the interests of landholders to be conserved, the interests and rights of others must be disregarded. If landholders lose nothing of their special privileges, the people at
large can gain nothing.
Buying individual property rights would only give
landholders a claim of the same kind and amount that
their possession of land now gives them, only in another
form. Through taxation, it would give them the same proportion of the earnings of labor and capital that they now
appropriate in rent. The unjust advantage of landowners
would be preserved, while the unjust disadvantage of others would be continued.
Yet even this discussion is a hopeful sign. Cries for justice are timid and humble when first protesting a time-honored wrong. We have been educated to look upon the “vested
rights” of landowners with all the superstitious reverence
that ancient Egyptians looked upon the crocodile.
But ideas grow when times are ripe, even though their
first appearances are insignificant. The antislavery movement in the United States began with talk of compensating owners. But when four million slaves were emancipated,
the owners got no compensation. Nor did they clamor for
any. One day, the people of England or the United States
will be sufficiently aroused to the injustice and disadvantages of individual ownership of land to reclaim it. And
200
Justice of the Remedy
they will not trouble themselves about compensating landowners.
Nor should there be any concern. How absurd! If the
land of any country belongs to the people of that country,
what right—in morality or justice—do landowners have
to compensation? If the land belongs to the people, why
should they pay its value for their own land?
Herbert Spencer once wrote,* “Had we to deal with
the parties who originally robbed the human race of its
heritage, we might make short work of the matter.” Why
not make short work of it anyhow?
For this robbery is not like the robbery of a horse or
some money. That theft ceases with the act. This is a continuous robbery that goes on every hour of every day. It is
a toll levied upon labor constantly and continuously. It is
not merely a robbery in the past—it is a robbery in the
present. And a robbery that deprives the newborn of their
birthright. Why should we hesitate to make short work of
such a system?
Just because I was robbed yesterday and the day before and the day before that, must I allow myself to be
robbed today and tomorrow as well? Is there any reason to
conclude that the robber has acquired a vested right to rob
me? If land belongs to the people, why continue to permit
landowners to take rent? And why compensate them in
* Herbert Spencer (1820-1903), English philosopher, Social Statics,
page 142. This reference is from the edition published—with his consent—from 1864 to 1892. Thereafter, he repudiated it, and issued a
new edition that eliminated all references declaring property in land
to be unjust. Henry George addressed Spencer’s reversal in a later
book, A Perplexed Philosopher.
Compensation for Landowners?
201
any manner for their “loss” of rent?
Consider what rent really is. It represents a value created by the whole community. It does not arise spontaneously from the land. Nor is it due to anything that
landowners have done.
Let landowners have, if you please, everything land
would give them—in the absence of the rest of the community. But rent is the creation of the whole community.
So it necessarily belongs to the whole community.
Suppose we were to try the case using common law—
which has been built by and for landowners. What does
the law allow someone who innocently buys land later
judged to belong to another? Nothing at all.
That fact that one purchased in good faith gives no
right or claim whatsoever. The law simply says: “The land
belongs to A, let the sheriff put him in possession!” It gives
no claim to the innocent purchaser of a wrongful title, and
allows no compensation.
Not only this, but it takes all improvements made in
good faith. The buyers may have paid a high price, making every effort to see that the title is good. They may
have held undisturbed possession for years, without hint
of an adverse claimant. They may have even erected buildings more valuable than the land itself.
Yet clever lawyers may find a technical flaw in the papers. Or they may hunt up some forgotten heir who never
dreamed of such rights. Then, not only the land, but all
the improvements may be taken away.
And there is even more! According to common law,
after surrendering the land and giving up the improvements,
the buyers may be called upon to account for all the profits
derived from use of the land during the time of possession.
202
Justice of the Remedy
These dictates of justice have been formulated into
law by landowners themselves. They are applied every day
in American and English courts. If we were to apply them
to the case of “The People vs. The Landowners,” we would
not think of giving landholders any compensation. Indeed,
we would take all the improvements and whatever else
they may have as well.
But I do not propose to go that far. It is sufficient if
the people resume ownership of the land. Let the landowners retain their improvements and personal property
in secure possession.
By this measure of justice, there would be no oppression and no injury to any class. The great cause of the
unequal distribution of wealth would be swept away. And
with it, the suffering, degradation, and waste that it entails. All would share in the general prosperity. The gain
of small landholders would be enormous; that of large landholders would still be real.
For in welcoming justice, peace and plenty will follow—bringing good not just to some, but to all. For justice itself is the highest and truest expediency. How true
this is, we shall shortly see.
History of Land as Private Property
203
Chapter 29
History of Land as Private Property
ANY CUSTOM that has existed for a long time seems natural and necessary to us. This is merely habit. Nonetheless,
this, more than anything else, keeps us from realizing the
basic injustice of private property in land—and prevents
us from considering any proposal to abolish it. We are so
used to treating land as individual property that the vast
majority of people never think of questioning it. It is thoroughly recognized in our laws, manners, and customs.
Most people even think it is required for the use of
land. They are unable to conceive of society as possible
without reducing land to private possession. The first step
in improving land is to find an owner. A person’s land is
looked on as property to sell, lease, give, or bequeath—the
same as houses, cattle, goods, or furniture. The “sacredness of property” has been preached so constantly—especially by the “conservators of ancient barbarism,” as Voltaire
called lawyers—that most people view private ownership
of land as the very foundation of civilization. They fancy
returning land to common ownership as some wild fantasy—or an attempt to return society to barbarism.
Even if it were true—which it is not—that land had
always been treated as private property, this would not
prove the justice or necessity of continuing to treat it as
such. The universal existence of slavery was once affirmed.
204
Justice of the Remedy
Yet that did not prove it just or necessary. Not long ago,
monarchy seemed all but universal. Not only kings, but
the majority of their subjects, really believed that no country could survive without a king. Yet France, to say nothing of America, gets along quite well without a king. And
the Queen of England has as much power to govern the
realm as the wooden figurehead of a ship has to determine
its course.
But the assumption that land had always been treated
as private property is not true. On the contrary, the common right to land has always been recognized as the primary right. Private ownership has appeared only as the
result of usurpation—that is, being seized by force.
The primary and persistent perception of mankind is
that everyone has an equal right to land. The opinion that
private property in land is necessary to society is a comparatively modern idea, as artificial and as baseless as the
divine right of kings. It is only the result of an ignorance
that cannot look beyond its immediate surroundings. History, research, and the observations of travelers prove that
wherever human society has formed, the common right of
people to use the earth has been recognized. Unrestricted
individual ownership has never been freely adopted. It has
always been born in war and conquest—and in the selfish
use the cunning have made of law and superstition.
Wherever we can trace the early history of society—
in Europe, Asia, Africa, America, and Polynesia—land was
once considered common property. All members of the
community had equal rights to the use and enjoyment of
the land of the community.
This recognition of the common right to land did not
prevent the full recognition of the exclusive right to the
History of Land as Private Property
205
products of labor. Nor was it abandoned when the development of agriculture imposed the necessity of recognizing exclusive possession of land—to secure the results of
labor expended in cultivating it.
How, then, has private ownership of land become so
widespread? Why was the original idea of equal rights
supplanted by the idea of exclusive and unequal rights?
The causes are the same ones that led to the establishment of privileged classes. We can summarize them briefly:
(1) The concentration of power in the hands of chieftains
and the military. (2) Conquest that reduces the conquered
to slavery and divides their lands, with a disproportionate
share going to the chiefs. (3) The differentiation and influence of a priestly class. (4) The differentiation and influence of a class of professional lawyers.
The interests of priests and lawyers were served by the
substitution of exclusive property in place of common land.
In Europe lawyers have been especially effective in destroying all vestiges of the ancient tenure by substituting
Roman law—exclusive ownership.
Unfortunately, inequality, once produced, always tends
toward greater inequality. This struggle—between equal
rights to the soil and the tendency to monopolize it in
individual possession—caused the internal conflicts of
ancient Greece and Rome. But the final triumph of the
tendency toward ownership eventually destroyed both.
By the power with which the great attracts the less,
small family estates became part of the great estates—the
latifundia—of enormously rich patricians. The former
owners were forced into slave gangs, or became virtual serfs.
Others fled to the cities, swelling the ranks of the proletariat, who had nothing to sell but their votes. As a result,
206
Justice of the Remedy
population declined, art sank, the intellect weakened, and
once splendid civilizations became empty shells.
The hardy virtues born of personal independence died
out, while exhaustive agriculture impoverished the soil.
At length the barbarians broke through; a civilization once
proud was left in ruins. During Rome’s grandeur, such a
fate would have seemed as impossible as it seems to us
now that the Comanches could conquer the United States
or Laplanders desolate Europe.
The fundamental cause was tenure of land. On the
one hand, denial of the common right to land resulted in
decay; on the other, equality gave strength. Every family
in the German villages was entitled to an equal share of
common land. This impressed a remarkable character on
the individual, which explains how small bands of barbarians overran a great empire. Rome perished from “the failure of the crop of men.”
After the Roman Empire fell, the idea of common
rights was blended with the idea of exclusive property. The
feudal system was the result.
But side by side and underneath the feudal system, a
more primitive organization revived. Based on the common rights of cultivators, it has left traces all over Europe,
and still survives in many places.
Feudalism clearly recognized—in theory at least—that
land belongs to society at large, not to the individual. A
fief (a feudal estate) was essentially a trust to which certain obligations attached. The sovereign was, theoretically,
the representative of the collective power and rights of the
whole people. Though land was granted to individual possession, specific duties were required. Through these, some
equivalent to the benefits received from the common right
History of Land as Private Property
207
was rendered back to the commonwealth.
Under the feudal scheme, crown lands supported public
expenditures. Church lands defrayed the cost of public
worship and instruction, as well as care for the sick and
destitute. The military tenant was under obligation to raise
a certain force when needed.
These duties were a rude and inefficient recognition—
but unquestionably still a recognition—of a fact obvious
to the natural perceptions of all men: Land is not individual property, but common property.
Amid the feudal system there were communities who
tilled the soil as common property, though subject to feudal dues. Of course the lords, if they had the power, claimed
pretty much all they thought worth claiming. Yet the idea
of common right was strong enough to attach itself, by
custom, to a considerable part of the land.
The commons must have been a very large proportion
of most European countries in those times. After centuries of appropriation by the aristocracy, France still retains
almost ten million acres of communal land. In England,
while over eight million acres have been enclosed since
1710, some two million acres still remain as commons,
though mostly worthless soil.
But these are not the only things that prove the universality and persistence of a common right to the soil.
There are also the very institutions under which modern
civilization has developed. Certain things persist in our
legal systems that point to this common right, though they
have lost their original meaning. For instance, the doctrine of eminent domain arises from nothing but the recognition of the sovereign or government as representing
the collective rights of the people. Legal terminology also
208
Justice of the Remedy
distinguishes between real and personal property. This very
difference is the survival of a primitive distinction between
what was originally looked on as common property and
what, from its nature, was always considered the exclusive
property of the individual.
The general course of development of modern civilization since the feudal period has subverted the natural
and primary ideas of collective ownership of the soil. Paradoxical as it may appear, the emergence of liberty from
feudal bonds has been accompanied by a tendency toward
a form of land ownership that enslaves the working class.
This is being felt all over the civilized world. Political
economists mistake it for the pressure of natural laws, while
workers mistake it for the oppression of capital.
It is clear that in Great Britain today, the right of the
people as a whole to the soil of their native country is much
less fully acknowledged than it was in feudal times. The
commons, once so extensive, largely contributed to the
independence and support of the lower classes. Today, all
but a small remnant of worthless land has been appropriated for individual ownership and enclosed. Most crown
lands have passed into private possession. Now the British
workingman must pay to support the royal family and all
the petty princelings who marry into it.
A smaller proportion of the people now own the land.
And their ownership is much more absolute. Thirty thousand people have legal power to expel the whole population from five-sixths of the British Islands. The vast
majority of the British people have no right whatsoever to
their native land, except to walk the streets.
The reason, I take it, that the idea of private property
in land has grown alongside the idea of personal freedom
History of Land as Private Property
209
is this:
In the progress of civilization, the grosser forms of
supremacy connected with land ownership were dropped,
or abolished, or became less obvious. Parliamentary government gradually stripped the great lords of individual
importance and repressed their most striking abuses. As
this happened, attention was diverted from the more insidious—but really more potent—forms of domination.
Meanwhile, there was a steady progression of legal
ideas drawn from Roman law, the great storehouse of
modern jurisprudence. This tended to level the natural
distinction between property in land and property in other
things. Landowners were then able to put property in land
on the same basis as other property.
Moreover, the political power of land barons was not
broken by the revolt of those classes who could clearly feel
the injustice of land ownership. What broke their power
was the growth of the artisan and trading classes. But the
relation between their wages and rent is not as obvious.
These classes developed under a system of guilds and
corporations. As I explained previously, trade unions and
monopolies enabled them to somewhat fence themselves
off from the general law of wages. But those were more
easily maintained then than now, when population is
steadily becoming more mobile due to improved transportation, education, and access to current news.
These classes did not see—and still do not see—that
land tenure is the fundamental fact that ultimately determines the conditions of industrial, social, and political life.
And so the tendency has been to assimilate the idea of
property in land with that of property in things of human
production.
210
Justice of the Remedy
The original landholders of England got their land on
terms that required them to provide military defense and
meet other conditions, which amounted to a considerable
part of their rent. Had the form of feudal dues simply been
changed into ones better adapted to the changed times,
English wars need never have incurred a single pound of
debt. English labor and capital need not have been taxed a
single farthing. All this would have come from rent. But
since that time, landholders have appropriated it to themselves.
What if landholders had been kept to this contract?
What if any land enclosed required similar terms? There
would be no need for customs duties, excise, license, or
income taxes. The income accruing to the nation from these
landowners would meet all present expenditures and, in
addition, leave a large surplus. This could be used for any
purpose aiding the comfort or well-being of the people as
a whole.
Looking back, wherever there is light to guide us, we
see that people recognized the common ownership in land
in their earliest perceptions. Private property in land is a
usurpation, a creation of force and fraud.
Property in Land in the US
211
Chapter 30
History of Property in Land
in the United States
IN EARLIER STAGES of civilization, land was always regarded as common property. Turning from the dim past
to our own times, we see that people still instinctively
recognize equal rights to the bounty of nature—if placed
under circumstances where the influence of education
and habit are weakened.
The discovery of gold in California brought diverse
people together in a new country. Probably not one in a
thousand had ever dreamed of any distinction between
land and wealth. They had long been used to thinking
of land as individual property. Things might have been
different had the land been agricultural or grazing or
forest land; or had its value come from its location for
commercial purposes. Then, they would have applied
the land system they had been used to, and reduced it
to private ownership in large tracts.
But here was land where gold could be had simply
by washing it out. This novelty broke through their
habitual ideas, and they were thrown back upon first
principles. By common consent, it was declared that
gold-bearing land should remain common property. No
one could take more than could reasonably be mined,
nor hold it for longer than it was being used. Title to
212
Justice of the Remedy
the land remained with the government. No individual
could acquire more than a possessory claim.
Miners in each district established the size of an
individual claim, plus the amount of work required to
constitute use. If this work were not done, any one could
relocate on the ground. The essential idea was to prevent monopoly. No one was allowed to play “dog in the
manger,” and hinder, forestall, or lock up natural resources. Labor was acknowledged as the creator of
wealth, and its reward was secured.
As placer mining declined, the familiar idea of private property finally prevailed. A law was passed to permit the ownership of mineral lands. The only effect was
to lock up opportunities. It gave owners the power to
say that no one else may use what they do not use themselves. In many cases mining land was withheld from
use for speculative purposes—just as valuable building
lots and agricultural land are.
If the first English settlers in North America had
found circumstances that called their attention anew to
the question of land ownership, they no doubt would
have reverted to first principles. For they reverted to
first principles in matters of government. Just as aristocracy and monarchy were rejected, so too, individual
ownership of land would have been rejected. But in the
country from which they came, this system had not yet
fully developed itself. Nor had its effects been fully felt.
In the new country, an immense continent invited
settlement. The question of the justice in private property in land did not arise. At first, no harm seemed done
by treating land as property. In a new country, equality
seemed sufficiently assured if no one took land to the
Property in Land in the US
213
exclusion of the rest. And there was plenty of land left
for others. The problems stemming from individual
ownership of land had not yet appeared.
In the South, where settlement had an aristocratic
character, land was carved into large estates. The natural complement of this was the introduction of slavery.
But in New England, the first settlers divided the land
as their ancestors had divided Britain twelve centuries
before. The head of each family was given his town lot
and his seed lot. Beyond these lay the free commons.
English kings attempted to create great proprietors by
huge land grants. Settlers saw the injustice of this attempted monopoly, and no one got much from these
grants. However, because land was so abundant, attention was not called to the injustice in individual ownership of land. But even when tracts are small, this must
involve monopoly when land becomes scarce.
So it came to pass that the great republic of the modern world adopted an institution that destroyed the republics of antiquity. They proclaimed the inalienable
right of all people to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness. Yet they accepted without question a principle
that ultimately denies the equal right to life and liberty—by denying equal and inalienable right to the soil.
At the cost of a bloody war, they abolished chattel slavery. Yet they allowed a more widespread and dangerous form of slavery to take root.
The continent seemed so wide, so vast. The unsettled
land prevented the full effect of private appropriation
from being felt, even in older sections. Besides, why
shouldn’t some take more land than they could use—
even if this forced those who needed it later to pay them
214
Justice of the Remedy
for the privilege of using it? Why should it seem unjust, when others in their turn might do the same thing
by going farther on?
But worse, the fortunes resulting from appropriation of land were heralded as prizes of labor—when, in
reality, they have been drawn from levies upon the wages
of labor. Our landed aristocracy is in its first generation
in the newer states, and to a considerable degree, even
in the older states. Those who profit by the increase in
land values have been largely people who began life
without a cent. Their great fortunes seem, to them and
to many others, the best proof that existing social conditions reward prudence, foresight, industry, and thrift.
Whereas the truth is, these fortunes are only the
gains of monopoly. They are necessarily made at the
expense of labor. The fact that those thus enriched
started as laborers hides this. Every ticket-holder in a
lottery delights in the imagination at the magnitude of
the prizes. This same feeling has prevented even the
poor from quarreling with a system that has made many
poor people rich.
In short, the American people have failed to see the
essential injustice of private property in land, because
they have not yet felt its full effects. We are insulated
by the vast extent of land not yet reduced to private
possession, the enormous common to which the energetic always turned.
This great public domain is the key fact that has
formed our national character and colored our thought.
It is not that we have rejected a titled aristocracy; nor
that we elect our officials; nor that our laws are in the
name of the people instead of a prince; nor that our
Property in Land in the US
215
judges do not wear wigs. None of these are why we have
avoided the ills of the effete despotism of the Old
World.
Whence comes our general intelligence, our comfort, our active invention, and our power of adaptation
and assimilation? And further, our free, independent
spirit, the energy and hopefulness that have marked our
people? They are not causes—they are results. They have
sprung from unfenced land.
Our vast public domain has been the force that
transforms unambitious European peasants into selfreliant Western farmers. Even those dwelling in crowded
cities gain a consciousness of freedom from it. It is a
wellspring of hope even to those who never take refuge
in it. As children grow to adulthood in Europe, they
find all the best seats at the banquet of life marked
“taken.” They must struggle with each other for the
crumbs that fall, without one chance in a thousand of
finding a seat. In America, whatever their condition,
there has always been the consciousness that the public
domain lay before them.
The knowledge of this fact has penetrated our whole
national life, both in acting and reacting. It gives us generosity and independence, elasticity and ambition. All
that we are proud of in the American character, all that
makes our conditions and institutions better than those
of older countries, may be traced to this fact:
Land has always been cheap in the United States,
because new soil has been open to the settler.
But now our advance has reached the Pacific. The
public domain is almost gone. Its influence is already
rapidly failing; its influence will soon end. The republic
216
Justice of the Remedy
has entered upon a new era—in which the monopoly of
land will show itself with accelerating effect.
I do not mean to say that there will be no public
domain. For a long time to come, there will be millions
of acres of public lands carried on the books. But what
remains are the great mountain ranges, sterile deserts,
and high plains fit only for grazing. California appears,
on paper, to have the most land available. Yet much of
this is covered by railroad grants. Some is held, but not
yet reported by survey. Much is monopolized by locations that control the water. As a matter of fact, it is
difficult to point to any part of the state where settlers
can take up a farm. Weary of the quest, they end up
buying land or renting it on shares. There is no scarcity
of land in California—but appropriation has gotten
ahead of the settlers, and manages to keep ahead.
There is no question the United States can support
a population of hundreds of millions. But in view of
such an increase, what becomes of the public domain?
In a very short time, all useful land will have an owner.
We are making the land of a whole people the exclusive property of some. The evil effects of this process will not wait until the final appropriation of the
public domain to show themselves. It is not necessary
to contemplate them in the future; we may see them
in the present. They have grown with our growth, and
are still increasing.
We plow new fields and build new cities. We cross
the land with railroads and lace the air with telegraph
wires. We build schools and colleges, and add invention after invention.
Yet it becomes no easier for the masses to make a
Property in Land in the US
217
living—on the contrary, it is becoming harder. The
wealthy become wealthier; the poor become more dependent. The gulf between boss and worker grows
wider. Social contrasts become sharper and beggars are
common.
We call ourselves the most progressive people on
earth. But what is the goal of our progress, if these are
its fruits?
These are the results of private property in land.
They are the effects of a principle that must act with
ever increasing force. It is not that laborers have increased faster than capital. It is not that population is
pressing against subsistence. It is not that machinery
has made work scarce. Nor is there is any real antagonism between labor and capital.
It is simply that land is becoming more valuable.
And the terms on which labor can obtain access to natural opportunities—which alone enable it to produce—
are becoming harder and harder.
The public domain is receding and narrowing, while
property in land is concentrating. The proportion of
people with no legal right to the land on which they
live grows steadily larger. The scale of cultivation recalls the latifundia that destroyed Rome. In California,
a large proportion of farmland is rented—at rates from
one-fourth to even one-half the crop.
Lower wages, hard times, increasing poverty are simply the results of the natural laws we have traced—laws
as universal and as irresistible as gravitation.
We did not establish a republic when we set forth
inalienable human rights. We shall never establish a republic until we carry out that declaration—by giving
218
Justice of the Remedy
the poorest child born among us an equal right to the
soil!
We did not abolish slavery with the Fourteenth
Amendment. To abolish slavery we must abolish exclusive ownership of land!
Unless we come back to first principles, unless we
recognize our natural perceptions of justice, unless we
acknowledge the equal right of all to land—our free institutions will be in vain. And all our discoveries and
inventions will only add to the force that presses the
masses down.
Private Property in Land is Inefficient
219
Eighth Part:
Application of the Remedy
Chapter 31
Private Property in Land is Inconsistent
with the Best Use of Land
WHEN WE CONFUSE the accidental with the essential, the
result is a delusion. It is a delusion that land must be private property to be used effectively. It is a further delusion
that making land common property—as it once was in
the past—would destroy civilization and reduce us to barbarism. Lawmakers have done their best to expand this
delusion, while economists have generally consented to it.
A story* tells how the Chinese accidentally discovered
roast pork, after a hut caught fire. For a long time, the
story goes, they thought you must burn down a house to
cook a pig. Finally, a sage arose to show the people this
was not necessary.
But it does not take a sage to see that absolute ownership of land is not required to make improvements—only
security for those improvements.
This is obvious to anyone who looks. Private property
* By Charles Lamb (1775-1834), English author.
220
Applying the Remedy
in land is as crude, wasteful, and uncertain a device for
securing improvement, as burning down a house is for
roasting a pig. But we do not have the excuse Lamb’s characters had, for they had never heard of a pig being roasted
except when a house burned.
To us, however, it is quite common for land to be improved by those who do not own it. Most of London is
built on leased ground. Tenant farmers cultivate the bulk
of land in Great Britain. In the United States, the same
system is prevalent.
If rent were collected by the government, wouldn’t land
be used to the same extent as now—when rent goes to
private individuals? Wouldn’t land be improved as well and
as securely as now? Of course! Treating land as common
property in no way interferes with its proper use.
What is necessary is not private ownership, but security of improvements. It is only necessary to tell someone
“whatever your labor or capital produces on this land is
yours” —not “this land is yours.” People sow only to reap;
they build to live in houses. These are the natural rewards
of their labor. Owning land has nothing to do with it.
It was for security that landholders surrendered ownership to feudal lords. When a landlord pledged not to claim
rent for twenty years, Irish peasants turned a barren mountain into lush gardens. On the mere promise of a fixed ground
rent for a term of years, the most costly buildings in London and New York are erected on leased ground.* If those
who make such improvements are guaranteed security, we
may safely abolish private property in land.
* For instance, Rockefeller Center, The Empire State Building, and
The World Trade Center were built on leased land.
Private Property in Land is Inefficient
221
The complete recognition of common rights to land
need not interfere, in any way, with the complete recognition of individual rights to improvements or production.
Two people may own a ship without sawing it in half. A
railway may have thousands of shareholders, yet run as
well as under a single owner.
Everything could go on exactly as it does now—and
still recognize the common right to land—simply by appropriating rent for the common benefit.
In the center of San Francisco there is a lot in which
the common rights of the people are still legally recognized. It is not cut up into tiny pieces; nor is it unused. It
is covered with fine buildings, which are the property of
private individuals. They stand there in perfect security.
The only difference between this lot and those around it
is this: Its rent goes to the common school fund—while
the other rent goes into private pockets. What is to prevent the land of the whole country being held by the people
in the same manner?
Consider those conditions commonly thought to demand private ownership. It would be difficult to find a
place where these exist in higher degree than certain islands in the Aleutian Archipelago of Alaska, which are
the breeding grounds of the fur seal. To prevent their utter
destruction, the harvest of furs must be carefully managed.
For without this resource, the islands are of no use.
If such a fishery were open to anyone, it would be in
the interest of each party to kill as many as they could at
once, without reference to the future. In a few seasons it
would be utterly destroyed, as fisheries in other oceans
have been.
But despite this danger, it is not necessary to make
222
Applying the Remedy
these islands private property. Instead, the islands have been
leased out and have already added over two million dollars
to the national treasury—without diminishing their value.
Under the careful management of the Alaska Fur Company, the seals have increased, not decreased.
These islands are still the common property of the
people of the United States. Yet for far less convincing
reasons, the great public domain of the American people
has been made into private property as fast as anybody
could take it.
Far from private property being necessary for the
proper use of land, the contrary is true. Treating land as
private property, in actual fact, stands in the way of its proper
use.
If land were treated as public property, it would be
used and improved as soon as there was need. But as private property, an individual owner is allowed to prevent
others from using what the owner cannot—or will not—
use. Large tracts are kept idle at the caprice of the owner,
held out of use waiting for higher prices. Meanwhile, others are forced to use places where their labor will be far
less productive. In every city, valuable lots may be seen
vacant for this reason. This means of using land is as wasteful, unnecessary, and uncertain as burning down houses to
roast pigs.
If the best use of land is the test, then private property
in land is condemned—as it is condemned by every other
consideration.
Securing Equal Rights to Land
223
Chapter 32
Securing Equal Rights To Land
WE HAVE WEIGHED every objection and found nothing—
in either justice or efficiency—to deter us from making
land common property by confiscating rent. But the question of method remains: How shall we do it?
We could simply abolish private titles and declare all
land public property. Then, lease lots to the highest bidders, under conditions guaranteeing the right to improvements. This would give a complex society the same equality
of rights achieved in simpler communities through equal
shares of land. And by leasing land to whoever could obtain the most from it, we would secure the greatest production.
But such a plan, though perfectly feasible, is not the
best option. Rather, I propose to accomplish the same results in a simpler, easier, and quieter way.
To formally confiscate all land would involve a needless shock, and would require a needless extension of government. Both can be avoided. Great changes are best
brought about under old forms. When nature makes a
higher form, it takes a lower one and develops it. This,
too, is the law of social growth. Let us work with it.
I do not propose to purchase or confiscate private property in land. Let those who now hold land retain possession, if they want. They may buy and sell or bequeath it.
224
Applying the Remedy
Let them even continue to call it “their” land. We may
safely leave them the shell, if we take the kernel.
It is not necessary to confiscate land—only to confiscate rent.
Taking rent for public use does not require that the
state lease land; that would risk favoritism, collusion, and
corruption. No new government agency need be created;
the machinery already exists. Instead of extending it, all
we have to do is to simplify and reduce it.
Government already takes some rent in taxation. With
a few changes in our tax laws, we could take almost all.
Letting owners keep a small percentage would cost much
less than renting through a state agency. Using the existing machinery of government, we may assert the common
right to land without any shock.
Therefore, I propose that we appropriate land rent for
public use, through taxation.
This simple yet effective solution will raise wages, increase the earnings of capital, eliminate poverty, reduce
crime, and provide full employment. It will unleash human power and elevate society. In its form, ownership of
land would remain just as it is now. No owner need be
dispossessed. No restriction need be placed upon the
amount of land any one could hold.
If rent were taken by the state in taxes, then land would
really be common property—no matter in whose name or
in what parcels it was held. Every member of the community would participate in the advantages of its ownership.
Land values increase as population grows and progress
advances. In any civilized country, this is enough to bear
all government expenses. In better developed countries, it
is much more than enough. In fact, when rent exceeds
Securing Equal Rights to Land
225
current government revenues, it will be necessary to actually increase the land tax to absorb excess rent. Taxation of
rent would increase as we abolish other taxes. So, we may
put our proposition into practical form by proposing:
To abolish all taxes—except on land values.
This is the first step in the practical struggle. Experience has taught me that wherever this idea is considered,
it makes headway. But few who would benefit most from
it see its full significance and power. It is difficult for workingmen to give up the notion that there is some basic antagonism between capital and labor. It is difficult for small
farmers and homesteaders to get over the idea that this
plan would unduly tax them. It is difficult for both classes
to let go of the idea that exempting capital from taxation
would benefit only the rich.
A great wrong always dies hard. These erroneous ideas
spring from confused thought. But behind ignorance and
prejudice, there is a powerful interest—one that has dominated literature, education, and public opinion. The great
wrong that condemns millions to poverty will not die without a bitter struggle.
226
Applying the Remedy
Chapter 33
The Canons of Taxation
THE BEST MEANS of raising public revenues will be one
that meets these conditions:
1. It should bear as lightly as possible on production—
least impeding the growth of the general fund, from which
taxes must be paid and the community maintained.
2. It should be easily and cheaply collected, and it
should fall as directly as possible on the ultimate payers—
taking as little as possible from the people beyond what it
yields the government.
3. It should be certain—offering the least opportunity for abuse and corruption, and the least temptation
for evasion.
4. It should bear equally—giving no one an advantage, nor putting another at a disadvantage.
Let us consider what form of taxation best fits these
conditions.
1. The Effect of Taxes on Production
It is obvious that all taxes come from the product of
land and labor. There is no source of wealth other than the
union of human exertion with the materials and forces of
nature. But equal taxes may have very different effects on
production, depending on how they are imposed.
Canons of Taxation
227
Taxes that reduce the rewards of producers lessen the
incentive to produce. Taxes based on the use of any of the
three factors of production—land, labor, or capital—inevitably discourage production. Such taxes introduce artificial obstacles to the creation of wealth.
The method of taxation is, in fact, just as important as
the amount. A small burden poorly placed may hinder a
horse that could easily carry a much larger load properly
adjusted. Similarly, taxes may impoverish people and destroy their power to produce wealth. Yet the same amount
of taxes, if levied another way, could be borne with ease. A
tax on date trees caused Egyptian farmers to cut down
their trees; but twice the tax, imposed on land, had no
such result.
Now, taxes on labor as it is exerted, on wealth as it is
used as capital, or on land as it is developed will clearly
discourage production—much more than taxes levied on
laborers whether they work or play, on wealth whether
used productively or fruitlessly, or on land whether cultivated or left idle.
To a greater or lesser degree, impediments to production are characteristic of most taxes modern governments
use to raise revenue. Many kinds of production and exchange are seriously crippled by taxes that divert industry
from more productive to less productive forms. These include all taxes on manufacturing, all taxes on commerce,
all taxes on capital, and all taxes on improvements. All
such taxes tend to reduce the production of wealth. Their
tendency is the same as the Egyptian tax on date trees,
though their effect may not be seen as clearly. They should
never be used when it is possible to use means that do not
check production.
228
Applying the Remedy
The great class of taxes that do not interfere with
production are taxes on monopolies. The profit of monopoly is in itself a tax on production. Taxing it would
simply divert into public coffers what producers must pay
anyway.
There are various sorts of monopolies. Some businesses
are, in their nature, monopolies. These are generally the
proper function of government. Delivering the mail, for
example. For the same reason, railroads should belong to
the public, as roads do.
Patent and copyright laws create temporary monopolies. Though the two are often confused, they are not
alike.* Indeed, they are essentially different. Copyright
does not prevent others from using facts, ideas, knowledge, laws, or combinations for similar productions. It
only prohibits using the identical form. That is, it protects the actual labor expended in producing the work. It
does not interfere with the similar right of anyone else to
do likewise. It rests, therefore, upon our natural, moral
right to enjoy the products of our own exertion—and it
would be unjust and unwise to tax them.
The patent, on the other hand, prohibits anyone from
doing a similar thing. Therefore, it is an interference with
the equal liberty on which the right of ownership rests.
Everyone has a moral right to think what I think, or to
perceive what I perceive, or to do what I do. It does not
matter whether someone gets the hint from me or independently of me.
Discovery can give no right of ownership. Whatever
* George said that he fell into this error himself in the first edition of
this book. He subsequently acknowledged and corrected it.
Canons of Taxation
229
is discovered must have already been there to be discovered. If someone makes a wheelbarrow, a book or a picture, the inventor has a moral right to that particular
product, but no right to prevent others from making similar things. Though such a prohibition is intended to stimulate discovery and invention, in the long run it actually
discourages them.
Finally, there are also onerous monopolies resulting
from the aggregation of capital in certain businesses.
(See Chapter 20.) It would be much better to abolish
such monopolies than to try to tax the returns of their
monopoly.
But all these other monopolies are trivial compared
with the monopoly of land. The value of land expresses a
monopoly, pure and simple. The value of a railroad or a
telegraph line, or the price of gas or a patent medicine
may partly express the cost of monopoly. But it also expresses the effort of labor and capital. On the other hand,
the value of land does not include labor or capital at all. It
expresses nothing but the advantage of appropriation. It
is, in every respect, tailored for taxation.
A tax on land (unless it exceeds actual rent) cannot
check production in the slightest degree—unlike taxes
on commodities, or exchange, or capital, or any of the
tools or processes of production. The value of land does
not express the reward of production. It is not like the
value of cattle, crops, buildings, or any of the things called
personal property and improvements.
Land value expresses the exchange value of monopoly.
It is not in any way the creation of the individual who owns
the land. It is created by the growth of the community.
Hence, the community can take it all without reducing
230
Applying the Remedy
the incentive to improvement, and without decreasing the
production of wealth. Taking the entire rent in taxes will
not reduce the wages of labor or the reward of capital one
iota. Nor will it increase the price of a single commodity. It
will not make production more difficult in any way.
But there is more than this. Taxes on land actually tend
to increase production—by destroying speculative rent,
which impedes production when valuable land is withheld
from use. Industrial depressions originate in speculative land
values. They then propagate themselves over the whole civilized world, paralyzing industry.
Taking rent for public use through taxation would
prevent all this. If land were taxed near its rental value,
no one could afford to hold unused land. This land would
be made available to those who would use it. Consequently, labor and capital could produce much more with
the same exertion.
With regard to production, a tax on land value is the
best tax that can be imposed. Tax manufacturing, and you
inhibit manufacturing. Tax improvements, and you lessen
improvement. Tax commerce, and you prevent exchange.
Tax capital, and you drive it away. But take the whole value
of land in taxation, and the only effect will be to stimulate
industry, open new opportunities, and increase the production of wealth.
2. Ease and Cost of Collection
Of all taxes, a tax on land is the easiest and cheapest to
collect. Land cannot be hidden or carried off. Its value can
be easily determined. Once the assessment is made, nothing but a receiver is required for collection.
The machinery for that purpose already exists. Part of
Canons of Taxation
231
public revenue currently comes from taxes on land. We could
just as easily collect all the rent as a part of it. Substituting
this single tax for all other taxes would save the entire cost
of collecting them. What an enormous saving this might be
can be inferred by observing the horde of officials now engaged in this endeavor. This saving would greatly reduce
the difference between what taxation now costs the people
and the revenue it yields to the government.
But a land tax would reduce this difference in an even
more important way. A tax on land is paid directly by those
on whom it falls. It does not add to prices. In contrast, taxes
on things of variable quantity are shifted from seller to buyer
in the course of exchange, and they increase as they go.
A tax on money loaned has often been attempted. In
this case, the lender will simply charge the tax to the borrower. The borrower must pay the increase or not get the
loan. If the borrower uses it in business, the tax must be
regained from customers. Otherwise the business becomes
unprofitable.
If we tax buildings, the tenants must finally pay it.
Construction will stop until rents rise enough to pay the
regular profit and the tax besides.
If we tax goods, manufacturers or importers will charge
higher prices to wholesalers, wholesalers to retailers, and
retailers to consumers. The tax ultimately falls on consumers, who pay not only the tax itself—but a profit on it
at each step of the process.
Each dealer requires profit on capital advanced to pay
taxes, as much as profit on capital advanced to pay for goods.
For instance, an importer in San Francisco sells Manila cigars to wholesalers for $70 a thousand. The cigars
cost $14, while the customs duty adds $56. Dealers must
232
Applying the Remedy
make a profit not just on $14 (the real cost of the cigars),
but on the $70 they must shell out (cost plus duty). In this
way all taxes that add to prices are shifted from hand to
hand. They increase as they go, until they ultimately rest
on the consumer—who ends up paying much more than
what is received by the government.
Taxes raise prices by increasing the cost of production.
This, in turn, reduces supply. But land is not something
made by human production. Taxes on rent, therefore, cannot check supply.
Though taxing land makes landowners pay more, it
gives them no power to obtain more. For there is no way
this can reduce the supply of land. On the contrary, it forces
those who hold land on speculation to sell or rent for what
they can get. A land tax increases competition among
owners. This lowers the price of land.
Thus, in all respects, a tax on land values is the cheapest way by which a large revenue can be raised. It gives
government the largest net revenue in proportion to the
amount taken from the people.
3. Certainty of Collection
Certainty is an important element in taxation. Collection provides opportunities for corruption on one side,
and evasion or fraud on the other. The bulk of our revenues are collected by methods to be condemned on this
ground, if on no other.
In earlier days, coasts were lined with one army of
people trying to prevent smuggling, and another engaged
in evading them. Clearly, the maintenance of both groups
had to come from the production of labor and capital. The
expenses and profits of smugglers, as well as the pay and
Canons of Taxation
233
bribes of custom officers, constituted a tax upon the industry of the nation. And this was in addition to what was
received by the government!
We can also include all inducements to assessors, and
moneys expended electing pliable officials to procure favorable acts or decisions. And do not forget all the expenses of legal proceedings and punishments, not only to
the government but to those prosecuted. These evasions
take so much from the general fund of wealth, without
adding to revenue.
Yet this is the least part of the cost. Taxes that lack the
element of certainty have the most terrible effect upon
public morals. Our revenue laws might as well be entitled,
“Acts to promote the corruption of public officials, to suppress honesty and encourage fraud, to promote perjury,
and to divorce law from justice.” This is their true character, and they succeed admirably.
But we need not resort to arbitrary assessments. A tax
on land values is the least arbitrary of taxes, and possesses
the highest degree of certainty. It may be assessed and collected with precision because of the immovable and
unconcealable nature of land itself.
Taxes on land may be collected to the last cent.
Though assessment of land is now often unequal, assessment of personal property is far more uneven. Inequalities arise mostly from taxing improvements along
with land. If all taxes were placed on land values, regardless of improvements, the design of taxation would
be simple and clear. It would be open to public observation. Assessment could be made with the certainty of
a real estate agent determining the price a seller can get
for a lot.
234
Applying the Remedy
4. Equality
The common idea that our system of taxing everything vainly attempts to carry out is this: Citizens should
pay taxes in proportion to their means, or in proportion to
their incomes. But even ignoring all the insurmountable
practical difficulties of taxation according to means, it is
clear that justice cannot be attained through this.
Let us turn to Nature and read the mandates of justice in its laws. Nature gives to labor, and to labor alone.
Even in a Garden of Eden, people would starve without
exertion. Now, take two people of equal incomes. One gets
income from labor; the other, from the rent of land. Is it
just that they should contribute equally to the expenses of
the state? Certainly not.
The worker’s income represents wealth created and
added to the general wealth of the state. The landowner’s
income represents only wealth taken from the general stock,
with nothing given in return. The worker’s right to income comes from the justification of Nature, which returns wealth to labor. The landowner’s claim is a mere
fictitious right, created by municipal regulation. It is unknown and unrecognized by Nature. It is a monopoly of
natural opportunities—gifts that Nature offers impartially
to all, and in which all have an equal birthright.
Value created and maintained by the community can
justly be called upon to meet community expenses. What
kinds of value are these? Only the value of land. This value
does not arise until a community is formed; it grows as the
community grows. It exists only as the community exists.
Scatter the largest community, and land, once so valuable,
would have no value at all. With every increase of population, the value of land rises; with every decrease, it falls.
Canons of Taxation
235
A tax upon land values is, therefore, the most just and
equal of all taxes. It falls only on those who receive a unique
and valuable benefit from society. And it falls on them in
proportion to the benefit they receive. It is taking by the
community, for the use of the community, from the value
that is the creation of the community. It is the application
of the common property to common uses.
When all rent is taken by taxation for the needs of the
community, equality will be attained. No citizen will have
an advantage over any other, except through personal industry, skill, and intelligence. People will gain what they
fairly earn. Only then, and not until then, will labor get its
full reward, and capital its natural return.
236
Applying the Remedy
Chapter 34
Endorsements And Objections
EVER SINCE the nature of rent and law of rent were first
determined, every credible economist has acknowledged,
expressly or tacitly, the grounds by which we have concluded that a tax on land values is the best method of raising public revenues.*
David Ricardo says a tax on rent would fall wholly on
landlords, and could not be shifted to consumers. Rent
would not be altered by such a tax, and it would not discourage the cultivation of land at the margin.
John McCulloch objects to a land tax. However, he
bases this solely on the assumption that we cannot distinguish the value of land from improvements. But supposing we could? He agrees we could then tax the entire
amount paid to landlords for permission to use the natural powers of the soil. He also agrees they could not pass
this on to anyone else, and that it would not affect prices.
John Stuart Mill not only admits all this, but expressly
declares the expediency and justice of a tax on rent. He
asks what right landlords have to accept riches that come
* We have paraphrased quotations found in the original text. These
writers, all British, include: David Ricardo (1772-1823). John Ramsey
McCulloch (1789-1864). John Stuart Mill (1806-1873). Millicent
Garrett Fawcett (1847-1929).
Endorsements and Objections
237
to them from the general progress of society—without any
work, risk, or thrift on their part? He proposes to take all
future increase, since they belong to society by natural right.
Millicent Fawcett says that land tax is in the nature of
a rent paid by the landowner to the state. The “economic
perfection” of this system is obvious, she notes.
In fact, the accepted doctrine of rent involves the idea
that rent should be the particular subject of taxation, both
on grounds of practicality and justice. It may be found, in
embryonic form, in the works of all economists who have
accepted Ricardo’s law of rent.
Why didn’t they take these principles to their inevitable conclusion, as we have done? Apparently, there was
an unwillingness to offend the enormous interests involved
in private ownership of land. In addition, false theories
about the causes of poverty have dominated economic
thought.
But there has been one school of economists who perceived what is clear to man’s natural perception when not
influenced by habit. Revenues from common property—
land—should be appropriated for common purposes. The
French Economistes or Physiocrats* of the eighteenth century proposed what I have—to abolish all taxes except those
on the value of land. Regrettably, the French Revolution
overwhelmed their ideas just as they were gaining strength
among the thinking classes.
Without knowing anything of their doctrines, I have
reached the same conclusion, on grounds that cannot be
questioned. The only objection found in standard econom* The Physiocrats were led by Francois Quesnay (1694-1774), and his
student, Robert Jacques Turgot (1727-1781).
238
Applying the Remedy
ics texts actually concedes its advantages. That is, the difficulty of separating land from improvements might cause
us to tax something else besides rent.
Macaulay* once remarked that if the law of gravity
were unfavorable to any substantial financial interest, there
would soon be no lack of arguments against it. Here is an
illustration of this truth!
Assume that it is impossible to perfectly separate the
value of land from improvements. Is the fear of accidentally taxing some improvements any reason to continue taxing all improvements? To tax values that labor and capital
have intimately combined with land might discourage production. How much greater discouragement must come
from taxing not only these, but all values that labor and
capital create?
But, as a matter of fact, the value of land can always be
readily distinguished from the value of improvements. In
countries like the United States much valuable land has
never been improved. In many states, assessors regularly
estimate the value of land and the value of improvements
separately. Only afterward are they reunited under the term
“real estate.”
Where land has been occupied from time immemorial, there is still no difficulty determining the value of
bare land. Frequently, land is owned by one person and
buildings by another. When a fire destroys improvements,
a clear and definite value remains in the land. In the oldest
country in the world, no difficulty whatever can attend
the separation. We need only separate the value of clearly
distinguishable improvements, made within a reasonable
* Thomas Macaulay (1800-1859), English historian.
Endorsements and Objections
239
period of time, from the value of the land, should the improvements be destroyed. This, manifestly, is all that justice or policy requires.
Absolute accuracy is impossible under any system.
Attempting to separate everything the human race has
done from what nature originally provided would be both
absurd and impractical. In ancient times, the Romans may
have drained a swamp or terraced a hill. These are now as
much a part of the natural advantage of the British Isles as
though the work had been done by an earthquake or a
glacier. After a certain lapse of time, the value of such permanent improvements would be considered as having
lapsed into that of the land. Accordingly, they would be
taxed as land.
But this could have no deterrent effect on such improvements. Such works are frequently undertaken on land
leased for a certain number of years. The fact is, each generation builds and improves for itself, not for the remote
future. Furthermore, each generation is heir not only to
the natural powers of the earth, but to all that remains of
the work of past generations.
Another objection may be that taxation and representation cannot safely be divorced. It may be desirable to
combine political power with the consciousness of public
burdens, but the present system certainly does not secure
it. Indirect taxes are mostly raised from those who pay
little or nothing consciously. In our large cities, elections
are decided by things similar to what influenced the Roman masses, who cared about nothing but bread and circuses.
Substituting a single land tax for numerous others
would hardly lessen the number of conscious taxpayers.
240
Applying the Remedy
Instead, the division of land now held on speculation would
greatly increase the number. It would equalize the distribution of wealth. Even the poorest would be raised above
abject poverty, while overgrown fortunes would be cut
down.
The dangerous classes politically are the very rich and
very poor. A person gains interest in government from feeling part of the community and its prosperity.
But if the tax on land values is so beneficial, why does
government resort to so many different ones? The answer
is obvious! A tax on land values is the only tax that does
not distribute itself—that is, it cannot be passed on to others. It falls only on landowners. There is no way they can
shift the burden to anyone else. Hence, a large and powerful interest is opposed to taxing land values.
Businesses do not oppose taxes they can easily shift
from their own shoulders. In fact, they frequently try to
maintain them. So do other powerful interests who might
profit from the higher prices such taxes bring about. A
multitude of taxes have been imposed with a view toward
private advantage, rather than raising revenue.
The ingenuity of politicians has been applied to devising taxes that drain the wages of labor and the earnings
of capital like a vampire sucking the blood of its victim.
Nearly all of these taxes are ultimately paid by that indefinable being, “the consumer.” They come in such small
amounts, and in such insidious ways, that we do not notice them.
The Civil War was the golden opportunity of these
special interests. Taxes were piled on every possible thing—
not so much to raise revenue as to enable particular classes
to participate in the advantages of tax-gathering and tax-
Endorsements and Objections
241
pocketing.
For this reason, those taxes costing people the least
have been easier to abolish than those costing the most.
License taxes are generally favored by those on whom they
are imposed. They tend to keep others from entering the
business. Large manufacturers are frequently grateful for
taxes on goods for similar reasons. This was seen in the
opposition of distillers to the reduction of the whisky tax.
Duties on imports tend to give certain producers special
advantages.
In all such cases, special interests capable of concerted
action favor those taxes. But a solid and powerful interest
bitterly opposes taxing land values. Nonetheless, once the
truth I am trying to make clear is understood by the masses,
a union of political forces strong enough to carry it into
practice will become possible.
242
Effects of the Remedy
Ninth Part:
Effects of the Remedy
Chapter 35
The Effect on Production
THE ADVANTAGES OF A SINGLE TAX on land become increasingly clear the more they are considered. Abolishing other
taxes would be like removing an immense weight from a
powerful spring. These taxes now hamper every type of
exchange and every form of industry. Remove these burdens and production would proceed at an unimaginable
pace. This, in its turn, would further increase land values,
and create an even bigger surplus for common purposes.
The present method of taxation acts like artificial
mountains and deserts. It costs more to get goods through
a custom house than it does to carry them around the world.
It penalizes industry and skill.
Suppose I work hard to build a good house, while you
are content to live in a hovel. The taxman makes me pay a
penalty every year for my effort by taxing me more. If I
save while you squander, I am taxed while you are exempt.
If I build something useful, I must pay for my industry as
if I had done an injury to the state. If I offer a service to
the public, I am taxed as though it were a public nuisance.
On Production
243
We say we want capital, but if I accumulate it I am charged
as though it were a privilege.
The full burden of these taxes on production is realized only by those who have attempted to follow our system of taxation through its ramifications. As I noted, the
heaviest part of taxation falls in increased prices. Abolishing these taxes would lift the whole enormous weight of
taxation from productive industry. All would be free to
make or save, to buy or sell, without being fined by taxes.
The state currently tells producers: “The more you add
to the general wealth, the more you will be taxed.” Instead, the state should say: “Be as industrious, thrifty, and
enterprising as you choose. Keep your full reward. You
won’t be fined for adding to the community’s wealth.”
The whole community will gain by this—for there is
a natural reward to the community as well. We cannot
keep the good we do, any more than the harm. Every productive enterprise yields collateral advantages, in addition
to what it returns to those who undertake it. Building a
house, factory, ship, or railroad benefits others besides those
who get the direct profits.
Let the individual producer keep all the direct benefits of exertion. Let the worker have the full reward of
labor. Give the capitalist the full return on capital. The
more labor and capital produce, the larger the common
wealth in which all share.
This general gain is expressed in a definite and concrete form through the value of land, or its rent. The state
may take from this fund, while leaving labor and capital
their full reward. And with increased production, this fund
would increase commensurately.
Shifting the burden of taxation, from production and
244
Effects of the Remedy
exchange to land value (or rent), would not merely give
new stimulus to the production of wealth—it would open
new opportunities. Under this system, no one would hold
land without using it. So land now withheld from use
would be thrown open to improvement.
The selling price of land would fall, and land speculation would receive its death blow. Land monopolization
would no longer pay. Millions of acres, where others are
now shut out by high prices, would be abandoned or sold
at trivial prices.
This is true not only on the frontier, but in cities as
well. The simple device of placing all taxes on the value of
land would, in effect, put land up for auction to whoever
would pay the highest rent to the state. The demand for
land determines its value. If taxes took almost all that value,
anyone holding land without using it would have to pay
nearly what it would be worth to anyone else who wanted
to use it.
This would apply not just to agricultural land, but to
all land. Mineral land would be thrown open, too. In the
heart of the city, no one could afford to keep land from its
most profitable use. On the outskirts, no one could demand more for land than what its current potential use
would warrant.
Everywhere land had attained a value, taxation would
drive improvement. It would not act as a fine upon improvement, as it does now. Whoever planted an orchard,
sowed a field, built a house, or erected a factory—no matter how costly—would pay no more in taxes than if the
land were kept idle. The owner of a vacant city lot would
pay for the privilege of keeping other people off. It would
cost as much to keep a row of tumble-down shanties as a
On Production
245
grand hotel or great warehouse.
Currently, everywhere labor is most productive, a bonus must be paid before labor can be exerted. This would
be eliminated. Farmers would not have to mortgage their
labor for years to obtain land to cultivate. City homeowners
would not have to lay out as much for small lots as for the
houses built on them. A company building a factory would
not have to spend a great part of its capital for a site. Plus,
all the other taxes now levied on machinery and improvements would be removed.
Consider the effect of such a change on the labor market. Competition would no longer be one-sided. Workers
now compete with each other, cutting wages down to bare
subsistence. Instead, employers would have to compete for
labor. Wages would rise to the fair earnings of labor.
The greatest of all competitors would have entered
into the labor market—one whose demand cannot be
satisfied until all desire is satisfied: the demand of labor
itself. Employers would have to bid not only against other
employers—all feeling the stimulus of greater trade and
increased profits—but against the ability of laborers to become their own employers. For natural opportunities would
now be opened to them by a tax preventing monopolization.
Natural opportunities would be free to labor. Capital
and improvements would be exempt from tax. Exchange
would be unhampered. Recurring depressions would cease.
Every wheel of production would be set in motion. Demand would keep pace with supply, and supply with demand. Trade would grow in every direction, and wealth
increase on every hand.
246
Effects of the Remedy
Chapter 36
The Effect on The Distribution of Wealth
THE ADVANTAGES of a tax on land values—great as they
already appear—cannot be fully appreciated until we consider the effect on the distribution of wealth.
All civilized countries have an unequal distribution of
wealth that grows steadily worse. The cause, we have found,
is that ownership of land provides greater and greater power
to appropriate the wealth produced by labor and capital as
material progress goes on. We can counteract this tendency
by removing all taxes on labor and capital—and putting
them on rent. If we went so far as to take all the rent in
taxes, the cause of inequality would be totally destroyed.
Wealth produced in every community would be divided into two parts. One part would be distributed to
individual producers—as wages and interest—according
to what each had contributed to production. The other
part—land rent collected as taxes—would go to the community as a whole. It would be distributed as public benefits to all members of that community. And justly so.
Wages and interest represent the result of individual effort. Land rent represents the increased power that the
community, as a whole, provides to the individual.
Rent, under this system, would promote equality, instead of causing inequality as it does now. To fully understand this effect, let’s review some principles we have
On Distribution
247
already determined.
Wages and interest are set by the margin of production—what can be made on land with no rent. Labor and
capital keep only what is left after rent and taxes. Collecting rent through taxes would virtually abolish private ownership in land, because it would destroy speculative
monopolization and reduce the price of land. This would
increase wages and interest, by opening opportunities that
are now monopolized. A new equilibrium would be established, with wages and interest much higher.
Productivity increases with population, with
laborsaving invention, with improved methods of exchange. These benefits could no longer be monopolized.
Any increase in rent arising from these advances would
benefit the whole community. All would be richer, not just
one class.
Further, if it were possible to calculate the full cost of
poverty, it would be appalling. New York City alone spends
over seven million dollars a year on charity. Yet spending
by government, private charities, and individuals combined
is merely the smallest item in the account. Consider the
following items: the lost earnings of wasted labor; the social cost of reckless and idle habits; the appalling statistics
on mortality, especially infant mortality, among the poor;
the proliferation of liquor stores and bars as poverty deepens; the thieves, prostitutes, beggars, and tramps bred by
poverty; and the cost of guarding society against them.
These are just part of the full burden that unjust distribution of wealth places on the aggregate society. The ignorance and vice produced by inequality show themselves in
the stupidity and corruption of government, and the waste
of public funds.
248
Effects of the Remedy
Appropriating rent for public purposes would not
merely stop waste and relieve society of these enormous
losses. Wages would rise and new avenues of employment
would appear. Furthermore, it is well-known that labor is
most productive where wages are highest. Higher wages
increase self-respect, hope, and energy. This is true the
world over. Mind, not muscle, is the greatest agent of production. The physical power evolved in the human frame
is one of the weakest forces of nature. With human intelligence, matter becomes plastic to human will.
Who can say what level the wealth-producing capacity of labor might reach, if producers receive their fair share
of its advantages? American invention and the American
aptitude for laborsaving processes are the result of higher
wages. Had our producers been condemned to the low
reward of the Egyptian fellah or Chinese coolie, we would
be drawing water by hand and transporting goods on our
shoulders.
Increasing the reward of labor and capital would stimulate invention even further. The harmful effects of laborsaving machinery on workers would disappear. Currently,
many people regard automation as a curse, not a blessing.
By removing these defects, every new power would improve the condition of all.
The simple plan of taxation I propose would equalize
the distribution of wealth, preventing waste and increasing productivity.
I shall not deny this may lessen the intensity with which
wealth is pursued. It seems to me that in a society where
no one fears poverty, no one would struggle and strain for
great wealth, as people do now. Certainly the spectacle of
people slaving away for the sake of dying rich is unnatural
On Distribution
249
and absurd. In a society where fear of want had been removed, we would view those who acquire more than they
can use as we now look on someone who wears a dozen
hats.
Though we may lose this incentive, we can surely spare
it. Whatever its function may have been in an earlier stage
of development, it is not needed now. The dangers threatening our civilization do not come from weakness in production. They come from the unequal distribution of
wealth.
250
Effects of the Remedy
Chapter 37
The Effect on Individuals and Classes
WE WOULD CONFISCATE RENT by placing taxes only on land.
On first hearing this, landholders are likely to be alarmed;
small farmers and homeowners will be told this would rob
them of their hard-earned property. But a moment’s reflection will show something different.
Everyone whose interest as worker and/or capitalist
exceeds their interest as landowner will gain. Even large
landholders ultimately will benefit, for production will
increase much more than the loss to private land ownership. The whole community will share in these gains and
in a healthier social condition.
It is obvious that those who live by wages, of head or
hand, will benefit greatly: laborers, clerks, mechanics, and
professionals. So will those who live partly by wages and
partly by earnings of capital: merchants, manufacturers,
and traders; from the peddler to the steamship owner. Furthermore, we may include all those whose income comes
from investments other than land.
Consider a merchant or professional with a house
and lot. She will not be harmed by our change, but will
gain. The selling price of the lot will diminish*—but its
* The rent of land is capitalized into a selling price. As the community
approaches collecting 100% of the rent, the selling price of land will
approach zero.
On Individuals and Classes
251
usefulness will not. It will serve her purposes as well as
ever. The value of other lots diminish in the same ratio,
so she retains the same security of having a lot as she had
before. If she needs a larger lot, or if her children need
lots, she will reap the advantage. She is no more a loser
than if she bought a pair of boots that later sell for less.
The boots are just as useful, and the next pair will be
cheaper.
Furthermore, though taxes on land will be higher, she
will be free from taxes on the house and improvements,
on furniture and personal property, and on all she and her
family eat, drink, and wear. Meanwhile her earnings will
increase greatly because of higher wages, constant employment, and greater trade. Her only loss would be if she wants
to sell her lot without getting another. This is a small loss
compared with a great gain.
The same is true of the farmer. I am not speaking of
“farmers” who never touch a plow; I mean working farmers.
Of everyone above mere laborers, they have the most to
gain from placing all taxes on land values. This may seem
contradictory until we fully understand the proposition.
Farmers generally sense they don’t get as good a living as their hard work ought to earn them. However,
they may not be able to trace the cause. The fact is, taxation, as now levied, falls on them with exceptional severity. All their improvements are taxed: houses, barns,
fences, crops, and stock. Their personal property cannot
be concealed or undervalued as easily as the more valuable kinds concentrated in cities. Not only are they taxed
on personal property and improvements, which the owners of unused land escape; even worse, their land is generally taxed at a higher rate than land held on
252
Effects of the Remedy
speculation—simply because it is improved.
A single tax on land values would fall hardest not on
agricultural districts, where land is comparatively cheap,
but on towns and cities, where prices are high. Taxes, being levied on the value of bare land, would fall as heavily
on unimproved as improved land. Acre for acre, the improved and cultivated farm—with its buildings, fences,
orchards, crops, and stock—would be taxed no more than
unused land of equal quality. Thus, speculation would be
reduced.
Destroying speculative land values would tend to diffuse population where it is too dense, and concentrate it
where it is too sparse. City tenements would give way to
homes with gardens. People in the country would share
more of the economies and social life of the city.
Working farmers are not just landowners—they are
laborers and capitalists, as well. They earn their living by
their labor and their capital. To varying degrees, this is
true of all landholders. While some may not be laborers, it
would be hard to find one who is not a capitalist. Indeed,
the general rule is: the larger the landowner, the greater
the capitalist. This is so true that the two are often confused in common thought. Putting all taxes on land would
largely reduce all great fortunes, but it would hardly leave
the rich penniless.
Not only would wealth increase enormously—it would
be equally distributed. This does not mean each individual
would get the same amount. That would not be equal distribution, since different individuals have different powers and different desires. Rather, wealth would be
distributed in accordance to how much each contributed.
This would vary with the industry, skill, knowledge, or
On Individuals and Classes
253
prudence of each individual.
Wealth would no longer concentrate in those who do
not produce, taken from those who do. The idle rich would
no longer lounge in luxury, while those who actually produce settle for the barest necessities. Any inequalities that
continued to exist would be of natural causes. They would
not be artificial inequalities, produced by denial of natural
law. The great cause of inequality—monopoly of land—
would be gone.
254
Effects of the Remedy
Chapter 38
Changes in Society
WE PROPOSE to readjust the very foundation of society.
Space does not permit an elaborate discussion of all the
changes this would bring about. Once general principles
are applied, the details will be easily adjusted. Still, some
of the main features merit mention.
Most notably, government could be vastly simplified.
We could eliminate an immense and complicated network
of governmental machinery needed to collect taxes, prevent and punish evasion, and check revenue from many
different sources.
A similar saving would occur in the administration of
justice. Much of the business of civil courts arises from
disputes over ownership of land. If all occupants were, essentially, rent-paying tenants of the state, such cases would
cease. With poverty ended, morality would grow stronger,
reducing other business of these courts.
Wages would rise and everyone would be able to make
an easy and comfortable living. This would immediately
reduce, and soon eliminate, thieves, swindlers, and other
criminals who arise from the unequal distribution of
wealth. This would lighten the administration of criminal
law, with all its paraphernalia of police, prisons, and penitentiaries. We should eliminate not only many judges, bailiffs, clerks, and jailers, but also the great host of lawyers
On Society
255
now maintained at the expense of those who actually produce wealth. They would cease to be a drain on the vital
force and attention of society. Talent now wasted in legal
subtleties would be turned to higher pursuits.
The legislative, judicial, and executive functions of
government would be vastly simplified. Public debts and
standing armies historically were products of the change
from feudal to allodial (i.e., private) land tenures. Once
we revert to the idea that land is the common right of the
people of a country, I do not think these would remain for
long. Public debts could readily be paid off by a tax that
would not lessen the wages of labor nor check production.
As intelligence and independence grow among the masses,
standing armies would soon disappear.
Society would approach the ideal of Jeffersonian democracy; repressive government would be abolished. Yet,
at the same time and in the same degree, it would become
possible to realize the goals of socialism without coercion.
With many of its present operations simplified or eliminated, government could assume other functions that now
demand recognition. Surplus revenue from land taxation
would grow as material progress increased its speed, tending to increase rent. Government would change its character and become the administrator of a great cooperative
society. It would merely be the agency by which common
property was administered for common benefit.
Does this seem impracticable? Consider the vast
changes in social life if labor kept its full reward. It would
banish want and the fear of want. Everyone would have
freedom to develop in natural harmony.
We are apt to assume that greed is the strongest human motive and that fear of punishment is required to
256
Effects of the Remedy
keep people honest. It seems selfish interests are always
stronger than common interests. Nothing could be further from the truth.
Don’t these behaviors arise because of want? Poverty
is the relentless hell waiting beneath civilized society. Poverty is not just deprivation; it is shame and degradation. It
is only natural that people should make every effort to
escape from this hell. People often do mean, greedy, grasping things in the effort to save their families, their children, from want.
In this struggle, one of the strongest motives of human action—the desire for approval—is sometimes distorted into the most abnormal forms. The hunger for the
respect, admiration, or sympathy of our fellows is instinctive and universal. It is seen everywhere. It is as powerful
among the most primitive savages as it is among the most
highly cultivated members of polished society. It triumphs
over comfort, over pain, even over fear of death. It dictates
both the most trivial and the most important actions.
People admire what they desire. The sting of want—
or fear of want—makes people admire riches above all else.
To become wealthy is to become respected, admired, and
influential.
Get money! Honestly, if you can—but at any rate get
money. This is the lesson society daily and hourly exhorts.
People instinctively admire virtue and truth. But poverty
makes them admire riches even more. It is well to be honest and just, but those who get a million dollars by fraud
and injustice have more admiration and influence than
those who refuse it. They are on the list of “substantial
citizens,” sought and flattered by men and women. They
may be patrons of arts, friends of the refined. Their alms
On Society
257
may feed the poor, help the struggling, and brighten desolate places. Noble institutions commemorate their names.
Long after they have accumulated enough wealth to
satisfy every desire, they go on working, scheming, and
striving to add more riches. They are driven by the desire
“to be something.” This is not from tyrannical habit, but
from the subtler satisfactions riches give: power and influence, being looked up to and respected. Their wealth not
only raises them above want, but makes them people of
distinction in the community. This is what makes the rich
so afraid to part with money, and so anxious to get more.
The change I have proposed would destroy the conditions that distort these impulses. It would transmute forces
that now disintegrate society into forces to unite it. Give
labor its full earnings and expanded opportunity. Take, for
the benefit of the whole community, that which the growth
of the community creates. Then poverty would vanish.
Production would be set free. People would worry
about finding employment no more than they worry about
finding air to breathe. The enormous increase of wealth
would give even the poorest ample comfort. The march of
science and invention would benefit all.
With fear of poverty gone, the admiration of riches
would decay. People would seek the respect and approval
of their fellows in ways other than the acquisition and display of wealth. The skill, attention, and integrity now used
for private gain would be brought to the management of
public affairs and the administration of common funds.
The prize of the ancient Olympic games was a simple
wreath of wild olive. Yet it called forth the most strenuous
effort. For a simple bit of ribbon, people have performed
services no money could buy.
258
Effects of the Remedy
Any philosophy based on selfishness as the master
motive of human action is shortsighted. It is blind to the
facts. If you want to move people to action, to what do you
appeal? Not to their pockets, but to their patriotism; not
to selfishness, but to sympathy. We will all give everything
to preserve our lives. That is self-interest. But to higher
impulses, people will give even their lives.
Call it religion, patriotism, sympathy, love of humanity, or love of God. Call it what you will. There is a force
that overcomes selfishness and drives it out. It is a force
beside which all others are weak. Anywhere people have
ever lived, it has shown its power. Today, as ever, the world
is filled with it. The person who has never seen or never
felt it is to be pitied.
This force of forces now goes to waste, or it assumes
perverted forms. We may use it, if we but choose. All we
have to do is give it freedom and scope. We are made for
cooperation, like rows of upper and lower teeth. One thing
alone prevents harmonious social development: the wrong
that produces inequality.
Some suppose that only impracticable dreamers
could envision a society where greed is banished, prisons stand empty, individual interest is subordinated to
general interest, and no one would seek to rob or to
oppress neighbors. Practical, levelheaded people, who
pride themselves on seeing facts as they are, have a hearty
contempt for such dreamers. But those practical people,
though they write books and hold chairs at universities, do not think.
Among the company of well-bred men and women
dining together there is no struggle for food, no attempt
to get more than one’s neighbor, no attempt to gorge or
On Society
259
steal. On the contrary, each is anxious to help a neighbor
before helping himself or herself, offering the best to others. Should anyone show the slightest inclination to act
the pig or pilferer, the hoarder would face a swift and heavy
penalty of social contempt and ostracism.
All this is so familiar that it seems the natural state of
things. Yet it is no more natural to be greedy for wealth
than to be greedy for food. People are greedy for food when
they are not assured there will be a fair and equitable distribution, which would give each enough. When these
conditions are assured, they stop being greedy.
In society as presently constituted, people are greedy
for wealth because the conditions of distribution are so
unjust. Instead of each being sure of enough, many are
condemned to poverty. This is what causes the rat race
and the scramble for wealth. An equitable distribution of
wealth would exempt everyone from this fear. It would
destroy greed for wealth, as greed for food is destroyed in
polite society.
On crowded steamers, manners often differed between cabin and steerage, illustrating this principle of
human nature. Both had enough food. However, steerage had no regulations to insure efficient service, so meals
became a scramble. In cabin, on the contrary, each was
assigned a place, and there was no fear of not getting
enough to eat. There was no scrambling and no waste.
The difference was not in the character of the people,
but simply in the arrangements. A cabin passenger transferred to steerage would participate in the greedy rush; a
steerage passenger transferred to cabin would become
respectful and polite.
The same would occur in society in general if the
260
Effects of the Remedy
present unjust system were replaced with a fair distribution of wealth. In cultivated and refined society, coarser
passions are not held in check by force or law, but by common opinion and mutual desire. If this is possible for part
of a community, it is possible for a whole community.
Some say there would be no incentive to work without fear of poverty; people would simply become idlers.
This is the old slaveholders’ argument that labor must be
driven with the lash. Nothing is further from the truth.
Want might be banished, but desire would remain. Humans are more than animals: we are the unsatisfied animal. Each step we take kindles new desires.
Work itself is not repugnant to humans, only work
that shows no results. To toil day after day and barely get
the necessities of life, this is hard indeed. But released from
this prison, people would work harder and better. Were
the lives of great people, like Benjamin Franklin or
Michelangelo, idle ones? The fact is, work that improves
the condition of humanity is not done to earn a living. In
a society where poverty was eliminated, such work would
increase enormously.
The waste of mental power is the greatest of all the
enormous wastes resulting from the present organization
of society. How infinitesimal are the forces that contribute to the advancement of civilization compared to the
forces that lie dormant! Considering the great mass of
people, how few are thinkers, discoverers, inventors, organizers. Yet many such people are born—it is conditions
that permit so few to develop. What would their talents
have mattered, had Columbus gone into the clergy instead of going to sea, or Shakespeare been apprenticed to
a chimney sweep, or Isaac Newton become a farmer?
On Society
261
But, it will be said, others would have risen instead.
And this is true. It shows how prolific human nature is.
The common worker is transformed into the queen bee
when needed. When circumstances are favorable, a common person rises to the status of hero or leader, sage or
saint. But for every one who attains full stature, how many
are stunted and denied?
How little does heredity count compared with conditions. Place an English infant in the heart of China, and it
will grow up the same as those who are native. The person
would use the same speech, think the same thoughts, show
the same tastes. Switch a countess with an infant in the
slums. Would the blood of a hundred earls give you a refined and cultured woman?
To remove the fear of want, to give to all classes comfort and independence and opportunities for development—this would be like giving water to a desert. Consider
the possibilities if society gave opportunity to all. Factory
workers are now turned into machines; children grow up
in squalor, vice, and ignorance. They need but the opportunity to bring forth powers of the highest order. Talents
now hidden, virtues unsuspected, would come forth to
make human life richer, fuller, happier.
In our present state, even the fortunate few at the top
of the social pyramid must suffer from the want, ignorance, and degradation underneath. The change I propose
would benefit everyone, even the largest landholder.
Wouldn’t the rich person’s children be safer penniless in
such a society, than with the largest fortune in this one? If
such a society existed, it would be a bargain to gain entrance by giving up all possessions.
I have now traced our social weakness and disease to
262
Effects of the Remedy
their source. I have shown the remedy. I have covered every point, and met every objection. But the problems we
have been considering, great as they are, pass into problems greater still. They go to the grandest problems with
which the human mind can grapple. I am about to ask the
reader to go with me further still, into higher fields.
What Causes Human Progress?
263
Tenth Part:
The Law of Human Progress
Chapter 39
The Cause of Human Progress
IF OUR CONCLUSIONS ARE CORRECT, they will fall under a
larger generalization. We may rephrase our question, then,
from a broader perspective:
What is the law of human progress?
Whether humans gradually developed from animals
is not the question here. Inference cannot proceed from
the unknown to the known. However humans may have
originated, we can know our species only as we find it now.
There is no trace of humans in any lower state than that of
primitive people still found today. No vestige remains of
what bridged the chasm between humans and animals.
Between the lowest savage and the highest animal, there
is an irreconcilable difference. It is not a difference of degree, but of kind. Many of the characteristics, actions, and
emotions of humans are seen in lower animals. But no matter how low on the scale of humanity, no person has ever
been found without the one characteristic of which animals
show not the slightest trace. It is something clearly
264
The Law of Human Progress
recognizable, yet almost undefinable. Something that gives
humans the power of improvement—that makes us the progressive animal.
The beaver builds a dam, the bird a nest—but always
on the same models. Human dwellings pass from rude huts
to magnificent mansions. A dog can, to a certain extent,
connect cause and effect, and learn some tricks. But this
capacity has not increased in all the ages it has been domesticated. Today’s dog is no smarter than the dogs of
ancient savages.
We know of no animal that uses clothes, cooks food,
makes tools or weapons, breeds other animals to eat, or
has an articulate language. Humans lacking these skills
have never been found. In fact, human physical ability is
so inferior that there is virtually no place we could exist
without those skills. Humans everywhere, and at all times
we know of, have exhibited this faculty—to supplement
what nature has done for us by what we do for ourselves.
But the degree varies greatly. Between the steamship
and a canoe, there is an enormous difference. These variations cannot be attributed to differences in original capacity. The most advanced today were savages within historic
times. We also see wide differences between peoples of the
same stock. Neither can they be accounted for by differences in physical environment. In many cases, the cradles of
learning are now occupied by barbarians. Yet great cities
rise in a few years over the hunting grounds of wild tribes.
These differences are evidently connected with social
development. Beyond perhaps the simplest rudiments, it
becomes possible for humans to improve only as we live
with other people. We improve as we learn to cooperate in
society. All these improvements in human powers and con-
What Causes Human Progress?
265
ditions we summarize in the term “civilization.”
But what is the law of this improvement? Which social arrangements favor it and which do not? Different
communities have arrived at different stages of civilization. Can some common principle explain this?
The prevailing belief is that civilizations progress by
development or evolution. That is, by the survival of the
fittest and hereditary transmission of acquired qualities.
This explanation of progress is, I think, very much like
the view naturally taken by the wealthy regarding the unequal distribution of wealth. There is plenty of money to
be made by those who have the will and ability, they say;
ignorance, idleness, or wastefulness creates the difference
between rich and poor.
So the common explanation of differences among civilizations is one of differences in capacity. The more civilized races are superior races. Common Englishmen felt
they had a naturally superiority over frog-eating Frenchmen. American opinion attributed their country’s success
in invention and material comfort to “Yankee ingenuity.”
In the beginning of this inquiry, we examined—and
disproved—certain economic theories that supported common opinion. This view saw capitalists as paying wages,
while competition reduced wages. Just as Malthusian
theory supported existing prejudices, seeing progress as
gradual race improvement harmonizes with common opinion. It gives coherence and a scientific formula to opinions already prevailing. Its phenomenal spread since
Darwin* has not been so much conquest as assimilation.
* Charles Darwin (1809-1882), British naturalist. He published The
Origin of Species in 1859.
266
The Law of Human Progress
So this view now dominates thought: The struggle for
existence, in proportion to its intensity, spurs people to
new efforts and inventions. The capacity for improvement
is established by hereditary transmission, and spread as
the most improved (i.e., best adapted) individuals survive
to propagate. Similarly, the best adapted tribe, nation, or
race survives in the struggle between social groups. This
theory is now used to explain the differences in the relative progress of societies, as well as the differences between
humans and animals. These phenomena are now explained
as confidently and as widely by this theory as, a short while
ago, they were explained by special creation and divine
intervention.
The practical effect of this theory is a sort of hopeful
fatalism: progress is the result of slow, steady, remorseless forces. War, slavery, tyranny, superstition, famine, and
poverty are the impelling causes that drive humans on.
They work by eliminating poor types and extending the
higher. Advances are fixed by hereditary transmission.
The current individual is the result of changes perpetuated through a long series of past individuals. Social organization then takes its form from the individuals of
which it is composed. Philosophers may teach that this
does not lessen the duty of trying to reform abuses. But
as generally understood, the result is fatalism. Why
bother, since change can only occur through slow development of man’s nature?
Yet we have reached a point where progress seems to
be natural to us. We look forward confidently to greater
achievements. Some even believe people may someday
travel to distant planets. This theory of progression seems
so natural to us amid an advancing civilization.
What Causes Human Progress?
267
But, without soaring to the stars, if we simply look
around the world, we are confronted with an undeniable
fact—stagnant civilizations.
The majority of the human race today has no idea of
progress. They look to the past as the time of human perfection. We may explain the difference between savage and
civilized, saying savages are still so poorly developed that
their progress is hardly apparent. But how shall we account for civilizations that progressed so far—and then
stopped?
Today’s Western civilization is not more advanced than
India and China due to a longer period of development.
We are not, as it were, adults of nature while they are children. They were civilized when we were savages. They had
great cities, powerful governments, art, literature, and commerce when Europeans were living in huts and skin tents.
Yet while we progressed from this savage state to modern civilization, they stood still. If progress is the result of
inevitable laws that propel people forward, how shall we
account for this? These arrested civilizations stopped when
they were superior in many respects to sixteenth century
Europe. Moreover, both received the infusion of new ideas
from conquering races with different customs and thought.
But it is not simply that current theory fails to account for these arrested civilizations. It is not merely that
people have gone so far on the path of progress and then
stopped. It is that people have gone so far—and then gone
back. It is not merely an isolated case that thus confronts
the theory — it is the universal rule.
Every civilization the world has ever seen has had its
period of vigorous growth; of arrest and stagnation; then,
decline and fall. True, our own civilization is more ad-
268
The Law of Human Progress
vanced and moves quicker than any preceding civilization.
But so was Roman civilization in its day. That proves nothing about its permanence unless it is better in whatever
caused the ultimate failure of its predecessors.
In truth, nothing could be further from explaining the
facts of universal history than this theory that civilization
is the result of natural selection. It is inconsistent with the
fact that civilization has arisen at different times, and in
different places, and has progressed at different rates. If
improvements were fixed in man’s nature, there might be
occasional interruption, but in general, progress would be
continuous. Advance would lead to advance, and civilization would develop into higher civilization. It is not merely
the general rule, but the universal rule, that the reverse is
true. The earth is the tomb of the dead empires.
In every case, the more advanced civilization, supposedly modified by heredity, has been succeeded by a fresh
race coming from a lower level. The barbarians of one epoch have been the civilized people of the next. It has always been the case that, under the influences of civilization,
people at first improve—and later degenerate. Every civilization that has been overwhelmed by barbarians has really perished from internal decay.
The moment this universal fact is recognized, it eliminates the theory of progress by hereditary transmission.
Looking over the history of the world, advance does not
coincide with heredity for any length of time. In any particular line, regression always seems to follow advance.
Can we say there is a national or race life, as there is an
individual life? Does every social group have, as it were, a
certain amount of energy to expend before it decays?
Analogies are the most dangerous mode of thought. They
What Causes Human Progress?
269
may connect similarities, yet disguise or cover up the truth.
The aggregate force of a group is the sum of its individual
components. A community cannot lose vital power unless
the vital powers of its components are lessened. As long as
members are constantly reproduced with all the fresh vigor
of childhood, a community cannot grow old by loss of its
powers as a person does.
Yet within this analogy lurks an obvious truth. The
obstacles that finally bring progress to a halt are actually
raised by the course of progress itself. The conditions that
have destroyed all previous civilizations have been conditions produced by the growth of civilization itself.
270
The Law of Human Progress
Chapter 40
Differences in Civilizations
TO DISCOVER the law of human progress, we must first
determine the essential nature of the differences between
civilizations. Such great disparities cannot be explained
by innate differences in the individuals who compose these
communities. True, there are natural differences and hereditary transmission of particular traits. But these are
nothing compared to social influences.
What is more ingrained than language? Nothing persists longer, nor shows nationality quicker. It is our medium of thought. Yet we are not born with a predisposition
to any language. Although our ancestors have spoken one
language for generations, children hearing a different
tongue from birth will learn that just as easily.
Manners and customs of nation or class are also matters of education and habit, not hereditary transmission.
White infants captured and raised by Indians demonstrate
this: They become thorough Indians. That the reverse is
not as true of Indians brought up by whites is due to the
fact that they are never treated precisely the same as white
children.
I once heard a highly intelligent Negro gentleman,
Bishop Hillery, remark: “Our children, when they are
young, are fully as bright as white children, and learn as
readily. But as soon as they get old enough to appreciate
Differences in Civilizations
271
their status—to realize that they are looked upon as belonging to an inferior race, and can never hope to be anything more than cooks, waiters, or something of that
sort—they lose their ambition and cease to keep up.”
Conditions and surroundings profoundly modify human character. Paupers will raise paupers, even if the children are not their own. Frequent contact with criminals
may make criminals out of the children of virtuous parents. Those who learn to rely on charity inevitably lose the
self-respect and independence necessary for self-reliance
when the struggle is hard. Thus it is well known that charity
often increases the demand for more charity.
In any large community, diverse classes and groups
show the same kind of differences as we see between different civilizations: differences in knowledge, belief, customs, tastes, and speech. But these differences are certainly
not innate. No baby is born a Methodist or Catholic, nor
with a particular dialect or accent. These differences are
derived from association in these groups.
This body of traditions, beliefs, customs, laws, habits
and associations arises in every community and surrounds
every individual. This, not hereditary transmission, makes
the English different from the French, the American from
the Chinese, and the civilized from the primitive. Heredity may develop or alter qualities—but much more so the
physical than the mental characteristics.
Even in our wildest state, human life is infinitely more
complex than animal life, for we are affected by an infinitely
greater number of influences. Amid these, the relative influence of heredity diminishes. The physical differences
between races are hardly greater than between black
and white horses. If this is true of our physical structure,
272
The Law of Human Progress
it must be reflected even more in our mental constitution.
All our physical parts we bring with us into the world, but
the mind develops afterward. We cannot tell whether the
mind of a newborn infant is to be English or Chinese, or
even the mind of a civilized person or the mind of a savage.
That depends entirely on the social environment in which
it is placed.
Suppose infants of highly civilized parents were taken
to an uninhabited country and somehow kept alive until
adulthood. They would be the most helpless savages imaginable. They would need to discover fire, to invent the simplest tools, and to construct a language. Just as children
learn to walk, they would have to stumble their way to the
simplest knowledge the lowest culture now possesses.
No doubt, they could do all these things in time. These
possibilities are latent in the human mind, as the power of
walking is latent in the human frame. But I do not believe
they would do them better or worse, or quicker or slower,
than children of barbarians under the same conditions.
What could mankind attain if each generation were separated from the next by an interval of time, like seventeenyear locusts? Only one such interval would see the decline
of mankind—not simply to savagery, but to a condition
compared with which savagery, as we know it, would seem
civilized. Conversely, if savage infants were placed in civilized homes, can we suppose that they would show any
difference growing up? (We must assume in this experiment that they would be raised the same as other children.) The great lesson thus learned is that “human nature
is human nature all the world over.”
There is a people, found in all parts of the world, who
illustrate which traits are transmitted by heredity and which
Differences in Civilizations
273
are transmitted by association. The Jews have maintained
the purity of their blood more scrupulously, and for a far
longer time, than any European race. Yet the only characteristic that can be attributed to this is physical appearance. (And this is far less than conventionally supposed, as
anyone who takes the trouble can see.) Although they have
constantly married among themselves, the Jews have everywhere been modified by their surroundings. English,
Russian, Polish, German, and Oriental Jews differ from
each other, in many respects, as much as do the other people
of those countries.
Yet they have much in common and have preserved
their character no matter where they are. The reason is
clear. The Hebrew religion has always preserved the distinctiveness of the Hebrew race. Certainly religion is not
transmitted by heredity, but by association.
The Chinese have a very set character. Yet in California they easily adopt American methods of working, trading, and using machinery. They have no lack of flexibility
or natural capacity. That they do not change in other respects is due to the Chinese environment that still persists
and surrounds them. Coming from China, they plan to
return. While here, they live in a little China of their own,
as the English in India maintain a little England. We naturally seek to associate with those who share our peculiarities. Thus language, religion and custom tend to persist
anywhere individuals are not absolutely isolated.
Modern civilization stands far above those who have
preceded us, and far above our less advanced contemporaries. But not because we are any taller. We stand atop a pyramid. The centuries have built a structure to support us.
Let me repeat: I do not mean that all people possess the
274
The Law of Human Progress
same mental capacity, any more than I mean they are physically alike. I do not deny the influence of heredity in transmitting mental characteristics in the same way, and possibly
to the same degree, as physical attributes. But the differences between communities in different places and at different times—what we call differences in civilizations—are
not differences that reside in individuals, but differences that
belong to their societies. That is, they result from the conditions individuals are exposed to in society.
Each society, small or great, weaves itself a web of knowledge, beliefs, customs, language, tastes, institutions, and laws.
(More precisely, we should say webs. For each community
is made up of smaller societies, which overlap and intertwine each other.) Into this, the individual is received at
birth and continues till death. This is the matrix in which
mind unfolds, and from which it takes its stamp. This is
how customs, religions, prejudices, tastes, and languages
develop and are perpetuated. This is how skill is transmitted and knowledge is stored. The discoveries of one time
are made the common stock and stepping stone of the next.
Though this is often an obstacle to progress, it is also
what makes progress possible. It enables a schoolboy in
our time to learn more about the universe in a few hours
than the ancient astronomers knew after a lifetime. It places
an ordinary scientist today far above the level reached by
the giant mind of Aristotle. This is to a civilization what
memory is to an individual. Our wonderful arts, our farreaching science, our marvelous inventions—they have
come about through this.
Human progress goes on as the advances of one generation become the common property of the next—and
the starting point for new ones.
The Law of Human Progress
275
Chapter 41
The Law of Human Progress
WHAT, THEN, IS THE LAW OF HUMAN PROGRESS? This law
not only describes how civilization advances—it must also
account for arrested, decayed, and destroyed civilizations.
Since mankind presumably started with the same capacities at the same time, it must explain the great disparity in
social development that now exists. It must account for
regression, as well as progression; for different rates of
progress; and for the bursts and starts and halts. In short,
it must tell us what the essential conditions of progress
are—and which social arrangements advance it and which
retard it.
It is not difficult to discover such a law. If we simply
look, we can see it. I do not pretend to give it scientific
precision, but merely to point it out.
Desires inherent in human nature are the incentives
to progress: to satisfy our physical, intellectual, and emotional wants. Short of infinity, they can never be satisfied—
for they grow as they are fed.
Mind is the instrument by which humanity advances.
Through it, each advance is retained and made higher
ground for further advances. The narrow span of human
life allows each individual to go only a short distance. Each
generation does little by itself. Yet succeeding generations
add to the gains of their ancestors, and gradually elevate
276
The Law of Human Progress
humanity.
Mental power is, therefore, the motor of progress. Civilizations advance in proportion to the mental power expended in progression—that is, mental power devoted to
the extension of knowledge, the improvement of methods, and the betterment of social conditions. There is a
limit to the amount of work that can be done with the
mind, just as there a limit to the work that can be done
with the body. Therefore, the mental power that can be
devoted to progress is only what is left over after what is
required for other, non-progressive purposes.
These non-progressive purposes, which consume mental power, can be classified in two categories: maintenance
and conflict. Maintenance includes not only supporting
existence, but also keeping up social conditions and holding advances already gained. Conflict includes not only
war or preparation for war; it encompasses all mental power
expended seeking gratification at the expense of others,
and resisting such aggression.
If we compare society to a boat, we see its progress is
not based on the total exertion of the crew. Rather, it depends only on exertion devoted to propelling it. The total
is reduced by any force expended on bailing, or fighting
among themselves, or pulling in different directions.
A person living alone would need all of his or her powers just to maintain existence. Mental power is set free for
higher uses only when human beings associate in communities. Improvement becomes possible when people come
together in peaceful association. This permits the division
of labor—and all the economies that come from cooperation. The wider and the closer the association, the greater
the possibilities of improvement. Therefore, association is
The Law of Human Progress
277
the first essential of progress.
Mental power is wasted in conflict to the extent moral
law is ignored—for moral law gives each person equality
of rights. The terms equality or justice signify the same
thing here: the recognition of moral law. So equality, or
justice, is the second essential of progress.
Association frees mental power for improvement.
Equality keeps this power from dissipating in fruitless
struggles. We thus arrive at our law:
Association in equality is the law of human progress.
Here, at last, is the law that can explain all diversities,
all advances, all halts, and all retrogressions. People progress
by cooperating with each other to increase the mental
power that may be devoted to improvement. However, as
conflict is provoked, or as inequality (of power or condition) develops, this tendency is lessened, checked, and finally reversed. The rate of development will depend on
the resistance it meets. Obstacles may be external and internal. In earlier stages of civilization, external forces tend
to be greater. Internal obstacles grow more important in
later stages.
Humans are social animals. We do not need to be
caught and tamed to persuade us to live with others. A
family relationship is necessary due to our utter helplessness at birth and our long period of immaturity. We observe that the family is wider, and in its extensions stronger,
among simpler peoples. The first societies are families.
They expand into tribes, still holding a mutual blood relationship. Even when they have become great nations, they
claim a common descent.
The first limit, or resistance, to association comes from
278
The Law of Human Progress
conditions of physical nature. These vary greatly with location, and must produce corresponding differences in
social progress. Climate, soil, and physical features will
largely determine population growth and the cohesion of
society in the early stages. Association brings only minor
improvement at first, especially under difficult conditions,
or where mountains, deserts, or sea isolate people. On the
rich plains of warm climates, people can exist with much
less effort. More mental power can be devoted to improvement. Hence, civilization naturally first arose in the great
valleys and table lands where we find its earliest monuments.
Diversity in natural conditions produces diversity in
social development. Differences arise in language, custom,
tradition, religion. Prejudice and animosity arise. Warfare
becomes a chronic and seemingly natural relation of societies to each other. Power is depleted in attack or defense,
in mutual slaughter and destruction of wealth, or in warlike preparations. Protective tariffs and standing armies
among the civilized world today bear witness to how long
these hostilities persist.
When small, separated communities exist in a state of
chronic warfare, a conquering tribe or nation may unite
these smaller communities into a larger one, in which internal peace is preserved. So conquest can promote association, by liberating mental power from the demands of
constant war.
But conquest is not the only civilizing force. While
diversities of climate, soil, and geography at first separate
mankind, they also act to encourage exchange. Commerce
also promotes civilization. It is in itself a form of association or cooperation. It not only operates directly—it also
The Law of Human Progress
279
builds up interests opposed to war. It dispels ignorance,
which is the fertile mother of prejudice and hate.
And likewise religion. Though it has sometimes divided people and led to war, at other times it has promoted association. Common worship has often furnished
the basis of union. Modern European civilization arose
from the triumph of Christianity over the barbarians. If
the Church had not existed when the Roman Empire fell,
Europe would have lacked any bond of association, and
might have fallen to a primitive condition.
Looking over history, we see civilization springing up
wherever people are brought into association—and disappearing as this association is broken up. As people have
been brought into closer and closer association and cooperation, progress has gone on with greater and greater force.
But we shall never understand the course of civilization, and its varied phenomena, without considering the
internal resistances or counter forces that arise in the very
heart of advancing society. Only they can explain how a
civilization, once adequately started, could be destroyed
by barbarians—or stop by itself.
Mental power, the motor of social progress, is set free
by association—or perhaps “integration” may be a more
accurate term. In this process, society becomes more complex. Individuals become more dependent upon each other.
Occupations and functions are specialized.
Instead of each person attempting to supply all wants
in isolation, the various trades and industries are separated.
One person acquires skill in one thing, and another in something else. The body of knowledge becomes larger than
any one person can grasp. So it is separated into different
parts, which different individuals pursue. Government
280
The Law of Human Progress
acquires special functions for preserving order, administering justice, and waging war. Even religious ceremonies pass
to people specially devoted to that purpose. Each member
is then vitally dependent on the others.
This process of integration, and the specialization of
functions and powers, is vulnerable to inequality. I do not
mean that inequality is a necessary result of social growth.
Rather, it is the constant tendency of social growth—if it
is not accompanied by certain changes in social organization. These changes must secure equality under the new
conditions that growth produces.
To put it plainly, the force that halts progress evolves
along with progress. How does this operate? Let us recall
two qualities of human nature: One is the power of habit;
the other is the possibility of mental and moral decay. Because of our tendency to continue doing things the same
way, customs, laws, and methods persist long after they
have lost their original usefulness. Decay allows the growth
of institutions and ways of thinking from which people’s
normal judgments would instinctively revolt.
The growth and development of society makes each
person more dependent on the whole. It lessens the influence of individuals, even over their own conditions, compared with the influence of society. But even further,
association gives rise to a collective power. This power is
different than the sum of individual powers. Groups exhibit actions and impulses that individuals would not under
the same circumstances. By analogy, as simple animals
become complex, a power of the integrated whole arises
above that of the parts.
We observed the same phenomenon in our inquiry
into the nature and growth of rent. Where population is
The Law of Human Progress
281
sparse, land has no value. To the degree that people congregate, land value land appears and rises. This is something clearly distinguishable from value produced by
individual effort. It is a value that springs from association. It increases as association grows greater, and disappears as association is broken up.
The same thing is true of power. As society grows,
habit tends to continue previous social arrangements. Collective power, as it arises, lodges in the hands of a portion
of the community. This unequal distribution of wealth and
power, which grows as society advances, tends to produce
greater inequality. Then the idea of justice is blurred by
habitual toleration of injustice.
The war chief of a band of savages is merely one of
their number; they only follow him as their bravest. When
large bodies act together, personal selection becomes more
difficult. A blinder obedience is necessary and can be enforced. As collective power grows, the ruler’s power to reward or punish increases. From the necessities of war on a
large scale, absolute power arises. The masses are then mere
slaves of the king’s caprice.
And so of the specialization of function. When society has grown to a certain point, a regular military force
can be specialized. It is no longer necessary to summon
every producer away from work in case of attack. This produces a manifest gain in productive power. But this inevitably leads to the concentration of power in the hands of a
military class or their chiefs.
Similarly, the preservation of internal order, the administration of justice, the construction and care of public
works, and, notably, the practice of religion, all tend to
pass to special classes. And it is their nature to magnify
282
The Law of Human Progress
their function and extend their power.
But the greatest cause of inequality is the natural monopoly given by possession of land. The initial understanding of people always seems to be that land is common
property. This is recognized at first by simple methods,
such as cultivating land in common or dividing it annually. These approaches are only compatible with low stages
of development.
The idea of property arises naturally regarding things
of human production. This idea is easily transferred to land.
When population is sparse, ownership of land merely ensures that the due reward of labor goes to the one who
uses and improves it. As population becomes dense, rent
appears. This institution ultimately operates to strip the
producer of wages earned.
War and conquest tend to concentrate political power
and lead to the institution of slavery. They also naturally
result in the appropriation of land. A dominant class, who
concentrate power in their own hands, will soon concentrate ownership of land. They take large portions of conquered land, while the former inhabitants are forced to farm
it as tenants or serfs. Some public domain or common lands
remain for awhile in the natural course of development. But
these are readily acquired by the powerful, as we see by
modern examples. Once inequality is established, ownership of land tends to concentrate as development goes on.
We can now explain all the phenomena of petrifaction
and retrogression from the fact that inequality of wealth
and power develops as social development occurs. This finally counteracts the force by which improvements are
made and society advances. I will simply set forth this general fact here, because the particular sequence of events
The Law of Human Progress
283
will vary under different conditions.
These two principles—association and equality—can
be seen at work in the rise and spread, and then the decline and fall, of the Roman Empire. Rome arose from the
association of independent farmers and free citizens of Italy.
It gained fresh strength from conquests, which brought
hostile nations into common relations. Yet the tendency
to inequality hindered progress from the start, and it only
increased with conquest. Inequality dried up the strength
and destroyed the vigor of the Roman world. Rome rotted, declined, and fell. Long before Vandal or Goth broke
through the legions, Rome was dead at the heart.
Great estates—“latifundia”—ruined Italy. The barbarism that overwhelmed Rome came not from without, but
from within. It was the inevitable product of a system that
carved the provinces into estates for senatorial families.
Serfs and slaves replaced independent farmers. Government became dictatorship, patriotism became subservience.
Vices were openly displayed, literature sank, learning was
forgotten. Fertile districts became wastelands, even without the ravages of war. Everywhere inequality produced
decay: political, mental, moral, and material.
Modern civilization owes its superiority to the growth
of equality along with association. Two great causes contributed to this. First, power was split into numerous
smaller centers. The second factor was the influence of
Christianity.
Europe saw the association of peoples who had acquired, through separation, distinctive social characteristics. This smaller organization prevented concentration of
power and wealth in one center. Petty chiefs and feudal
lords grasped local sovereignty and held each other in
284
The Law of Human Progress
check. Teutonic ideas of equality were a transforming influence, as they worked their way through the fabric of
disconnected societies. Although Europe was split into
countless separated fragments, the idea of closer association existed in the recollections of a universal empire and
in the claims of a universal church. It is true Christianity
was distorted by percolating through a rotting civilization.
Yet the essential idea of equality was never wholly destroyed.
In addition, two things of utmost importance to the
budding civilization occurred—the first was the establishment of the papacy; the second was the celibacy of the
clergy. The papacy prevented spiritual power from concentrating in the same lines as temporal power. Celibacy
prevented the establishment of a priestly caste, during a
time when power tended to hereditary form.
In spite of everything, the Church still promoted association and was a witness for the natural human equality. In common hands, the Church placed a sign before
which the proudest knelt. Bishops became peers of the
highest nobles. Church edicts ran across political boundaries. The Pope arbitrated between nations and was honored by kings.
The rise of European civilization is too vast a subject
to give proper perspective in a few paragraphs. But all its
main features, and all its details, illustrate one truth:
Progress occurs to the extent that society tends toward
closer association and greater equality. Civilization is cooperation. Union and liberty are its factors.
Modern civilization has gone so much higher than any
before due to the great extension of association—not just
in larger and denser communities, but in the increase of
The Law of Human Progress
285
commerce, and the numerous exchanges knitting each
community together, and linking them with others far
apart; and also in the growth of international and municipal law, advances in security of property and person, strides
in individual liberty, and movement towards democratic
government. In short, our civilization has gone farther in
recognizing equal rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness.
The spirit of fatalism pervading current literature finds
it fashionable to speak of war and slavery as means of human progress. But war is the opposite of association. It
can aid progress only when it prevents further war, or
breaks down antisocial barriers.
As for slavery, I cannot see how it could ever have aided
progress. Freedom is the synonym of equality, the stimulus and condition of progress. Slavery never did, and never
could, aid improvement. Slavery necessarily involves a
waste of human power. This is true whether the community consists of a single master and a single slave, or thousands of masters and millions of slaves. Slave labor is less
productive than free labor. Masters waste power holding
and watching their slaves. From first to last, slavery has
hampered and prevented progress—as has every denial of
equality.
Slavery was universal in the classical world. This is
undoubtedly why mental activity there polished literature
and refined art, but never hit on any of the great discoveries and inventions of modem civilization. Robbing workers of the fruits of their labor stifles the spirit of invention.
It discourages the use of improvements, even when made.
No slaveholding people were ever an inventive people.
Their upper classes may become luxurious and polished,
286
The Law of Human Progress
but never inventive.
The law of human progress, what is it but moral law?
Political economy and social science can teach only the
same simple truths that underlie every religion that has
striven to formulate the spiritual yearnings of man. Civilizations advance as their social arrangements promote justice. They advance as they acknowledge equality of human
rights. They advance as they insure liberty to each person,
bounded only by the equal liberty of every other person.
As they fail in these, advancing civilizations come to a halt
and recede.
How Modern Civilization May Decline
287
Chapter 42
How Modern Civilization May Decline
OUR CONCLUSIONS about the law of human progress agree
completely with our previous conclusions about the laws
of political economy. They also show that making land
common property—by taxing its value—would give an
enormous boost to civilization. Furthermore, unless we do
so, we will regress.
Every previous civilization has been destroyed by the
unequal distribution of wealth and power. I have traced
this tendency to its cause—and provided a simple way to
remove it. I will now show how, if this is not done, modern civilization will decline to barbarism, as all previous
civilizations have.
History clearly shows these periods of decline, though
they were not recognized at their start. When the first
Emperor was changing Rome from brick to marble and
extending the frontier, who would have said Rome was
entering its decline? Yet such was the case.
Our civilization appears to be advancing faster than
ever. Yet anyone who looks will see the same cause that
doomed Rome is operating today—with increasing force.
The more advanced the community, the greater the intensity. Wages and interest fall, while rents rise. The rich get
richer, the poor grow helpless, the middle class is swept
away.
288
The Law of Human Progress
It is worthwhile to explain the process, since many
people cannot see how progress could turn into retreat.
They think such a thing is impossible. Many scoff at any
implication that we are not progressing in all respects.
The conditions of social progress, we have found, are association and equality. The general tendency of modern
development has indeed been toward political and legal
equality. We have abolished slavery, revoked hereditary
privileges, instituted representative government, and recognized religious freedom. High and low, weak and strong
have more equal security in their person and property.
There is freedom of movement and occupation, of speech
and of the press.
The initial effect of political equality is a more equal
distribution of wealth and power. While population is
sparse, unequal distribution of wealth is due mainly to inequality of personal rights. The inequality resulting from
private ownership of land shows itself only as material
progress advances. Political equality does not, in itself, prevent inequality arising from private ownership of land.
Furthermore, political equality—when coexisting with an
increasing tendency toward unequal distribution of
wealth—will ultimately beget either tyranny or anarchy.
A representative government may become a dictatorship without formally changing its constitution or abandoning popular elections. Forms are nothing when
substance has gone. And the forms of popular government
are those from which the substance of freedom may go
most easily. For there despotism advances in the name of
the people. Once that single source of power is secured,
everything is secured. An aristocracy of wealth will never
struggle while it can bribe a tyrant.
How Modern Civilization May Decline
289
When the disparity of condition increases, democratic
elections make it easy to seize the source of power. Many
feel no connection with the conduct of government. Embittered by poverty, they are ready to sell their votes to the
highest bidder or follow the most blatant demagogue. One
class has become too rich to be stripped of its luxuries, no
matter how public affairs are administered. Another class
is so poor that promises of a few dollars will outweigh
abstract considerations on election day. A few roll in wealth,
while the many seethe with discontent at things they don’t
know how to remedy.
Where there is anything close to equal distribution of
wealth, the more democratic government is, the better it
will be. Where there is gross inequality in the distribution
of wealth, the opposite is true. The more democratic government is, the worse it will be. To give the vote to people
who must beg or steal or starve, to whom the chance to
work is a favor—this is to invoke destruction. To put political power in hands embittered and degraded by poverty is to wreak havoc.
Hereditary succession (or even selection by lot) may,
by accident, occasionally place the wise and just in power.
But in a corrupt democracy, the tendency is always to give
power to the worst. Honesty and patriotism are a handicap, while dishonesty brings success. The best sink to the
bottom, the worst float to the top. The vile are ousted only
by the viler.
National character gradually absorbs the qualities that
win power. In the long panorama of history, we see over
and over that this transforms free people into slaves. A
corrupt democratic government must finally corrupt the
people. And when the people become corrupt, there is no
290
The Law of Human Progress
resurrection. Life is gone, only the carcass remains. It is
left but for the plowshares of fate to bury it out of sight.
Unequal distribution of wealth inevitably transforms
popular government into despotism. This is not a thing of
the far future. It has already begun in the United States,
and is proceeding rapidly before our very eyes. Men of the
highest ability and character avoid politics. The technique
of handlers and hacks counts more than the reputations of
statesmen. The power of money is increasing, while voting is done recklessly. Political differences are no longer
differences of principle. Political parties are passing into
the control of what might be considered oligarchies and
dictatorships.
Modern growth is typified by the great city. Here we
find the greatest wealth and the deepest poverty. And here
popular government has most clearly broken down. In all
the great American cities of today, a ruling class is defined
as clearly as in the most aristocratic countries. Its members have whole wards in their pockets, select slates for
nominating conventions, and distribute offices as they
bargain together. “They toil not, neither do they spin,”*
yet they wear the finest of raiment and spend money lavishly. They are men of power, whose favor the ambitious
must court, and whose vengeance they must avoid.
Who are these men? The wise, the learned, the good?
No. They are gamblers, fighters, or worse. Men who have
made a trade of controlling votes, and buying and selling
offices and legislation. Through these men, rich corporations and powerful financial interests pack the Senate
and the courts with their lackeys. In many places today, a
* Matthew 6:28
How Modern Civilization May Decline
291
Washington, a Franklin, or a Jefferson could not even
get into the state legislature. Their very character would
be an insurmountable disqualification.
In theory we are intense democrats. Yet growing among
us is a class who have all the power of the aristocracy—
without any of their virtues. A few men control thousands
of miles of railroad, millions of acres of land, and the livelihood of thousands. They name the governors as they
name clerks, and choose senators as they choose attorneys.
Their will with legislatures is as supreme as a French king’s.
The development of industry and commerce—acting
in a social organization where land is privately owned—
threatens to force every worker to seek a master. ( Just as
the collapse of the Roman Empire compelled every freeman to seek a feudal lord.) Industry takes on a form where
one is master, while many serve. If a person steals enough,
the punishment will only amount to losing part of the theft.
And if a thief steals a fortune, colleagues will greet the
embezzler like a Viking returning from pillage.
The most ominous political sign in the United States
today is the growing complacency with corruption. Many
believe there is no honest person in public office; or worse,
that if there were one, he or she would be a fool not to
seize the opportunities. The people themselves are becoming corrupted. Our democratic government is running the
course it must inevitably follow under conditions producing unequal distribution of wealth.
Where this will lead is clear. Contempt for law develops, and reform becomes hopeless. Volcanic forces festering among the masses will explode when some accident
gives them vent. Where will the new barbarians come
from? Go through the squalid ghettos of great cities and
292
The Law of Human Progress
you can already see them gathering.*
Hinting that our civilization may be in decline seems
like wild pessimism. A fundamental belief in progress remains. But this will always be the case when advance gradually passes into retrogression. In social development, as in
everything else, motion tends to continue in a straight line.
Where there has been previous advance, it is extremely
difficult to recognize decline—even after it has begun.
Civilizations do not decline along the same paths they
came up. Government will not take us back from democracy to monarchy and to feudalism. It will take us to dictatorship or anarchy. Religion will not go back to the faiths
of our forefathers, but into new forms of superstition.
The regression of civilization, after a period of advance,
may be so gradual that it attracts no attention at the time.
Indeed, many mistake such a decline for advancement. As
the arts decline, the change may be accompanied by—or
rather caused by—a change of taste. Artists who quickly
adopted the new styles are regarded—in their day—as superior. As art and literature become more lifeless, foolish,
and stilted—conforming to changing taste—the new fashion would regard its increasing weakness as increasing
strength and beauty. Really good writers would not find
* The British historian Thomas Macaulay (1800-1859) predicted that
after all the decent land had been claimed in the United States, poverty would reach the levels it did in England. The nation would then
destroy itself through its own democratic institutions. “The Huns and
Vandals who ravaged the Roman empire came from without; your
Huns and Vandals will have been engendered within your own country by your own institutions [because]… There is nothing to stop you.
Your constitution is all sail and no anchor.” (Letter to Henry S. Randall,
biographer of Thomas Jefferson.)
How Modern Civilization May Decline
293
readers; they would be regarded as dull. The prevailing
taste becomes that of a less cultured class who regard what
they like as the best of its kind.
Whether current trends in taste and opinion indicate
regression is not the point. Many other things beyond dispute indicate our civilization has reached a critical point—
unless a new start is made toward equality. Inequality is
the necessary result of material progress wherever land is
monopolized. Inequality cannot go much further without
carrying us into a downward spiral so easy to start and so
hard to stop.
Industrial depressions, which cause as much waste and
suffering as war or famine, are like twinges and shocks preceding paralysis. The struggle to survive is increasing in intensity. We must strain every nerve to keep from being
trodden underfoot in the scramble for wealth. This saps the
energy to gain and maintain improvements. Diseases from
related causes proliferate. In every civilized country, poverty, crime, insanity, and suicide are increasing.
When the tide turns, it does not happen all at once.
When the sun passes noon, the heat of the day continues
to increase. One can tell only by the way the shadows fall.
But as sure as the tide must turn, as sure as the setting sun
brings darkness, so sure is it that our civilization has begun to wane. Invention marches on, our cities expand. Yet
civilization has begun to wane when, in proportion to
population, we have more prisons, more welfare, more
mental illness. Society does not die from top to bottom; it
dies from bottom to top.
But the decline of civilization looms far more palpable than any statistics. There is a vague but general
disappointment, an increased bitterness, a widespread
294
The Law of Human Progress
feeling of unrest and brooding revolution. If this were
accompanied by some definite idea of how to obtain relief, it might be a hopeful sign. But it is not. Though we
have been searching a long, long time, our power of connecting cause to effect seems not a whit improved.
A vast change in religious ideas is sweeping the world
that may have a momentous effect, which only the future can tell. This is not a change in the form of religion—it is the negation and destruction of the ideas from
which religion springs. Christianity is not simply shedding superstitions; it is dying at the root. And nothing
arises to take its place.
The fundamental ideas of an intelligent creator and
an afterlife are quickly weakening in the general mind.
Whether or not this may be an advance in itself is not the
point. The important part religion has played in history
shows the significance of the change now going on. Unless human nature has suddenly changed its deepest characteristics, as shown by the universal history of the human
race, the mightiest actions and reactions are thus being
prepared.
Previously, such stages of thought have always marked
periods of transition. To a lesser degree, a similar state preceded the French Revolution. But the closest parallel to
the wreck of religious ideas now going on is when ancient
civilization began to pass from splendor to decline.
What change may come, no mortal can tell. But that
some great change must come, thoughtful people are beginning to feel. The civilized world is trembling on the
verge of a great movement. Either it must be a leap upward, to advances yet undreamed of—or it will be a plunge
downward, carrying us back toward barbarism.
The Central Truth
295
Chapter 43
The Central Truth
OUR ECONOMIC INQUIRY led us to a certain truth. The same
truth explains the rise and fall of civilizations. Furthermore, it agrees with our deep-seated perceptions of relation and sequence, which we call moral perceptions.
The evils arising from the unequal and unjust distribution of wealth become more and more apparent as modern civilization goes on. They are not signs of progress,
but tendencies that will bring progress to a halt. They will
not cure themselves. Unless their cause is removed, they
will expand until they sweep us back into barbarism—the
path every previous civilization has taken.
But this truth also shows that these evils are not imposed by natural laws. They arise solely from social maladjustments that ignore natural laws. Poverty, with all
the evils that flow from it, springs from a denial of justice. By allowing a few to monopolize opportunities nature freely offers to all, we have ignored the fundamental
law of justice.
By sweeping away this injustice—and asserting the
rights of all people to natural opportunities—we shall conform ourselves to this law. We shall remove the great cause
of unnatural inequality in the distribution of wealth and
power. We shall abolish poverty; tame the ruthless passions of greed; and dry up the springs of vice and misery.
296
The Law of Human Progress
We shall light the lamp of knowledge in dark places; give
new vigor to invention and a fresh impulse to discovery;
substitute political strength for political weakness; and
make tyranny and anarchy impossible.
The reform I have proposed will make all other reforms easier. It agrees with all that is desirable—politically, socially, or morally. It is simply carrying out, in letter
and spirit, the self-evident truths set forth in the Declaration of Independence: that all people are created equal;
that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable rights; that among these are life, liberty, and the
pursuit of happiness.
These rights are denied when the equal right to land
is denied—for people can only live by using land. Equal
political rights will not compensate for denying equal rights
to the gifts of nature. Without equal rights to land, political liberty is merely the right to compete for employment
at starvation wages.
We honor liberty in name and form. We set up statues and sound her praises. But we have not fully trusted
her. And as we grow, her demands grow. She will have
no half service. For liberty means justice, and justice is
the natural law.
Some think liberty’s mission is accomplished when she
has abolished hereditary privileges and given the vote. They
think she has no further relation to the everyday affairs of
life. They have not seen her real grandeur. To them, her
poets seem dreamers, her martyrs but fools. Yet it is not
for an abstraction that people have toiled and died. In every age, the witnesses of liberty have stood forth.
We speak as if liberty were one thing, and virtue,
wealth, knowledge, invention, and independence were oth-
The Central Truth
297
ers. But liberty is the source, the mother, the necessary
condition, of all these. She is to virtue what light is to
color; to wealth what sunshine is to grain; to knowledge
what eyes are to sight.
In the history of every nation we may read the same
truth. It is the universal law, the lesson of the centuries. Our
primary social organization is a denial of justice. Allowing
one person to own the land—on which and from which
others must live—makes them slaves. The degree, or proportion, of slavery increases as material progress goes on.
This subtle alchemy is extracting the fruits of their
labor from the masses in every civilized country, in ways
they do not realize. It institutes a harder and more hopeless slavery in place of the one that has been destroyed. It
brings tyranny out of political freedom, and must soon
transform democratic institutions into anarchy. This is what
turns the blessings of material progress into a curse, what
crowds human beings into squalid tenement houses, and
fills the prisons and brothels. This is what plagues people
with want and consumes them with greed.
Civilization so based cannot continue. The eternal laws
of the universe forbid it. The ruins of dead empires so
testify. Justice herself demands that we right this wrong.
It is blasphemy to attribute the suffering and brutality
that comes from poverty to the inscrutable decrees of Providence. It is not the Almighty, but we who are responsible
for the vice and misery that fester amid our civilization.
The Creator showers us with gifts — more than enough
for all. But like swine scrambling for food, we tread them
in the mire while we tear each other apart.
Suppose at God’s command, for every blade of grass
that now grows, two should spring up. And crops increase
298
The Law of Human Progress
a hundred-fold. Would poverty be reduced? No—any benefit that would accrue would be temporary. The miraculous new powers could be utilized only through land. And
while land is private property, the classes that currently
monopolize the bounty of the Creator would monopolize
all the new bounty.
Landowners alone would benefit. Rents would increase, but wages would still tend to the starvation point.
This is not merely a deduction of political economy—
it is a fact of experience. We have seen it with our own
eyes, in our own times.
The effect of invention and improvement on the production of wealth has been precisely the same as an increase in the fertility of nature.
What has been the result? Simply that landowners took
all the gain. The wonderful discoveries and inventions of
our century have neither increased wages nor lightened
toil. The effect has simply been to make the few richer—
and the many more helpless!
Can the gifts of the Creator be misappropriated with
impunity? Can labor be robbed of its earnings, while greed
rolls in wealth? Is it right that many should want, while a
few are glutted? Turn to history! On every page we read
that such wrongs never go unpunished. The nemesis that
follows injustice never falters nor sleeps.
Look around today. Can this continue? The pillars
of state tremble, and the foundations of society shudder
from forces pent-up beneath. Great new powers, born of
progress, have entered the world. They will compel us to
a higher plane, or else they will overwhelm us.
The world is pulsing with unrest. There is an irreconcilable conflict between democratic ideas and the
The Central Truth
299
aristocratic organization of society. We cannot permit
people to vote, then force them to beg. We cannot go on
educating them, then refusing them the right to earn a
living. We cannot go on chattering about inalienable human rights, then deny the inalienable right to the bounty
of the Creator.
While there is still time, we may turn to justice. If we
do, the dangers that threaten us will disappear. With want
destroyed and greed transformed, equality will take the
place of jealousy and fear. Think of the powers now wasted,
the fields of knowledge yet to be explored, the possibilities that the wondrous inventions of this century only hint
at. Who can presume the heights to which our civilization
may soar?
300
The Law of Human Progress
Chapter 44
Conclusion: The Individual Life
MY TASK IS DONE. Yet behind the problems of social life
lies the problem of individual life. This thought brought
me cheer while writing this book, and it may be of cheer
to those who, in their heart of hearts, take up the struggle.
The truth I have tried to show will not find easy acceptance. If that were possible, it would have been accepted
long ago, and never obscured. But it will find friends who
will suffer and toil for it; and if need be, die for it. This is
the power of truth. Ultimately, it will prevail. But in our
own times or even when any memory of us remains, who
shall say?
Want and misery, ignorance and brutality are caused
by unjust social institutions. Those who try to right them
find bitterness and disappointment. So it has been in the
past; so is it now. The most bitter thought is that the effort
is hopeless, the sacrifice futile. This fear sometimes comes
to even the best and bravest. How few of those who sow
the seed will see it grow.
The standard of truth and justice has been raised many
times. Over and over, it has been trampled down, often in
blood. If the forces opposed to truth were weak, why would
error so long prevail?
But for those who see the truth and would follow it,
success is not the only thing. Lies and injustice often
Conclusion: The Individual Life
301
provide that! Must not truth and justice have something
to give that is their own, by proper right?
When I set out on this inquiry, I had no theory to
support, no conclusions to prove. Simply seeing the squalor and misery of a great city appalled and tormented me
so that it would not let me rest. I constantly wondered
what caused it and how it could be cured. Out of this,
something came to me that I did not expect to find; a faith
that was dead has been revived.
If we analyze the ideas that have destroyed the hope
of an afterlife, we shall not find their source in physical
science. Rather, they stem from certain teachings of political and social science that have permeated thought in
all directions. These have their root in three doctrines: First,
that population is larger than we can provide for. Second,
that poverty, vice, and misery are the result of natural laws—
and are actually the means by which civilization advances.
Third, that human progress occurs through slow genetic
changes.
These doctrines, which have generally been accepted
as truth, reduce the individual to insignificance. They
destroy the idea that there can be any regard for individual existence in the ordering of the universe. Or that
there can be any recognition of what we would call moral
qualities.
It is difficult to reconcile the concept of human immortality with the idea that nature constantly wastes people by
bringing them into being where there is no room for them.
It is impossible to reconcile the idea of an intelligent and
beneficent Creator with the belief that wretchedness and
degradation, which are the lot of such a large proportion
of humankind, result from divine decrees. Finally, the idea
302
The Law of Human Progress
that the human species is the result of slow modifications
perpetuated by heredity irresistibly suggests the idea that
the object of human existence is the life of the species, not
the individual.
Our investigation has shown that these doctrines are
false. Population does not tend to outrun subsistence. Poverty and human suffering do not spring from natural laws;
they come from the ignorance and selfishness of people.
Human progress does not come from changes in the nature of mankind. On the contrary, human nature, generally speaking, has always been the same.
Political economy has been called the dismal science.
As currently taught, it is indeed hopeless and despairing.
Yet, in its proper symmetry, political economy is radiant
with hope.
When understood correctly, the laws governing the
production and distribution of wealth demonstrate that
poverty and injustice are not inevitable. On the contrary, a
social state is possible in which poverty would be unknown.
Then, the higher qualities of human nature would have
an opportunity for full development.
Social development is not governed by divine providence nor merciless fate, but by natural law. Human will is
the great determining factor. In the aggregate, the human
condition is what we make of it. Economic law and moral
law are essentially the same. The intellect grasps this truth
after toilsome effort—but the moral sense reaches it quickly
by intuition.
Science shows us the universality of law. The same law
operates in the smallest divisions and in the immeasurable
distances of space. An astronomer follows a moving body
until it disappears from the range of the telescope. But
Conclusion: The Individual Life
303
this is merely the visible part of its orbit. Beyond sight, the
law still holds. Centuries later, the astronomer’s calculations are proven correct.
If we trace the laws that govern life in human society,
we find they are the same in the largest community as in
the smallest. We find that what seem to be, at first sight,
divergences and exceptions are merely manifestations of
the same principles. And we find that everywhere we can
trace it, social law runs into and conforms with moral law.
In the life of a community, justice infallibly brings its reward, injustice its punishment. But we cannot see this in
individual life.
Human progress is not the improvement of human
nature. The advances of civilization are not accumulated
in the constitution of individuals, but in the constitution
of society. They are not fixed and permanent, but may be
lost at any time.
What then is the meaning of life inevitably bounded
by death? To me, it seems intelligible only as an avenue to
another life. Its facts can be explained only by a theory
that must be expressed in myth and symbol. The Prince of
Light still battles the Powers of Darkness.
To anyone who will hear it, the clarions of battle call.
Strong souls and high endeavor, the world needs them
now. Though truth and right seem often overwhelmed,
we may not see it all. Shall we say that what passes from
our sight passes into oblivion? Even animals have senses
we do not. Far, far beyond our grasp, eternal laws must
hold their sway.
304
Afterword
Afterword
Who Was Henry George?
By Agnes George de Mille
A HUNDRED YEARS AGO a young unknown printer in San
Francisco wrote a book he called Progress and Poverty. He
wrote after his daily working hours, in the only leisure
open to him for writing. He had no real training in political economy. Indeed he had stopped schooling in the seventh grade in his native Philadelphia, and shipped before
the mast as a cabin boy, making a complete voyage around
the world. Three years later, he was halfway through a second voyage as able seaman when he left the ship in San
Francisco and went to work as a journeyman printer. After that he took whatever honest job came to hand. All he
knew of economics were the basic rules of Adam Smith,
David Ricardo, and other economists, and the new philosophies of Herbert Spencer and John Stuart Mill, much
of which he gleaned from reading in public libraries and
from his own painstakingly amassed library. Marx was yet
to be translated into English.
George was endowed for his job. He was curious and
he was alertly attentive to all that went on around him.
He had that rarest of all attributes in the scholar and historian—that gift without which all education is useless.
He had mother wit. He read what he needed to read, and
he understood what he read. And he was fortunate; he
Who Was Henry George?
305
lived and worked in a rapidly developing society. George
had the unique opportunity of studying the formation of
a civilization—the change of an encampment into a thriving metropolis. He saw a city of tents and mud change
into a fine town of paved streets and decent housing, with
tramways and buses. And as he saw the beginning of
wealth, he noted the first appearance of pauperism. He
saw degradation forming as he saw the advent of leisure
and affluence, and he felt compelled to discover why they
arose concurrently.
The result of his inquiry, Progress and Poverty, is written simply, but so beautifully that it has been compared to
the very greatest works of the English language. But
George was totally unknown, and so no one would print
his book. He and his friends, also printers, set the type
themselves and ran off an author’s edition which eventually found its way into the hands of a New York publisher,
D. Appleton & Co. An English edition soon followed
which aroused enormous interest. Alfred Russel Wallace,
the English scientist and writer, pronounced it “the most
remarkable and important book of the present century.” It
was not long before George was known internationally.
During his lifetime, he became the third most famous
man in the United States, only surpassed in public acclaim
by Thomas Edison and Mark Twain. George was translated into almost every language that knew print, and some
of the greatest, most influential thinkers of his time paid
tribute. Leo Tolstoy’s appreciation stressed the logic of
George’s exposition: “The chief weapon against the teaching of Henry George was that which is always used against
irrefutable and self-evident truths. This method, which is
still being applied in relation to George, was that of hush-
306
Afterword
ing up .... People do not argue with the teaching of George,
they simply do not know it.” John Dewey fervently stressed
the originality of George’s work, stating that, “Henry
George is one of a small number of definitely original social philosophers that the world has produced,” and “It
would require less than the fingers of the two hands to
enumerate those who, from Plato down, rank with Henry
George among the world’s social philosophers.” And Bernard Shaw, in a letter to my mother, Anna George, years
later wrote, “Your father found me a literary dilettante and
militant rationalist in religion, and a barren rascal at that.
By turning my mind to economics he made a man of me....”
Inevitably he was reviled as well as idolized. The men
who believed in what he advocated called themselves disciples, and they were in fact nothing less: working to the
death, proclaiming, advocating, haranguing, and proselytizing the idea. But it was not implemented by blood, as
was communism, and so was not forced on people’s attention. Shortly after George’s death, it dropped out of the
political field. Once a badge of honor, the title, “Single
Taxer,” came into general disuse. Except in Australia and
New Zealand, Taiwan and Hong Kong and scattered cities around the world, his plan of social action has been
neglected while those of Marx, Keynes, Galbraith and
Friedman have won great attention, and Marx’s has been
given partial implementation, for a time, at least, in large
areas of the globe.
But nothing that has been tried satisfies. We, the
people, are locked in a death grapple and nothing our leaders offer, or are willing to offer, mitigates our troubles.
George said, “The people must think because the people
alone can act.”
Who Was Henry George?
307
We have reached the deplorable circumstance where
in large measure a very powerful few are in possession of
the earth’s resources, the land and its riches and all the
franchises and other privileges that yield a return. These
positions are maintained virtually without taxation; they
are immune to the demands made on others. The very
poor, who have nothing, are the object of compulsory
charity. And the rest—the workers, the middle-class, the
backbone of the country—are made to support the lot by
their labor.
We are taxed at every point of our lives, on everything
we earn, on everything we save, on much that we inherit,
on much that we buy at every stage of the manufacture
and on the final purchase. The taxes are punishing, crippling, demoralizing. Also they are, to a great extent, unnecessary.
But our system, in which state and federal taxes are
interlocked, is deeply entrenched and hard to correct.
Moreover, it survives because it is based on bewilderment;
it is maintained in a manner so bizarre and intricate that it
is impossible for the ordinary citizen to know what he owes
his government except with highly paid help. We support
a large section of our government (the Internal Revenue
Service) to prove that we are breaking our own laws. And
we support a large profession (tax lawyers) to protect us
from our own employees. College courses are given to explain the tax forms which would otherwise be quite unintelligible.
All this is galling and destructive, but it is still, in a
measure, superficial. The great sinister fact, the one that
we must live with, is that we are yielding up sovereignty.
The nation is no longer comprised of the thirteen original
308
Afterword
states, nor of the thirty-seven younger sister states, but of
the real powers: the cartels, the corporations. Owning the
bulk of our productive resources, they are the issue of that
concentration of ownership that George saw evolving, and
warned against.
These multinationals are not American any more.
Transcending nations, they serve not their country’s interests, but their own. They manipulate our tax policies to
help themselves. They determine our statecraft. They are
autonomous. They do not need to coin money or raise
armies. They use ours.
And in opposition rise up the great labor unions. In
the meantime, the bureaucracy, both federal and local, supported by the deadly opposing factions, legislate themselves mounting power never originally intended for our
government and exert a ubiquitous influence which can
be, and often is, corrupt.
I do not wish to be misunderstood as falling into the
trap of the socialists and communists who condemn all
privately owned business, all factories, all machinery and
organizations for producing wealth. There is nothing
wrong with private corporations owning the means of producing wealth. Georgists believe in private enterprise, and
in its virtues and incentives to produce at maximum efficiency. It is the insidious linking together of special privilege, the unjust outright private ownership of natural or
public resources, monopolies, franchises, that produce unfair domination and autocracy.
The means of producing wealth differ at the root: some
is thieved from the people and some is honestly earned.
George differentiated; Marx did not. The consequences
of our failure to discern lie at the heart of our trouble.
Who Was Henry George?
309
This clown civilization is ours. We chose this of our
own free will, in our own free democracy, with all the means
to legislate intelligently readily at hand. We chose this
because it suited a few people to have us do so. They
counted on our mental indolence and we freely and obediently conformed. We chose not to think.
Henry George was a lucid voice, direct and bold, that
pointed out basic truths, that cut through the confusion
which developed like rot. Each age has known such diseases and each age has gone down for lack of understanding. It is not valid to say that our times are more complex
than ages past and therefore the solution must be more
complex. The problems are, on the whole, the same. The
fact that we now have electricity and computers does not
in any way controvert the fact that we can succumb to the
injustices that toppled Rome.
To avert such a calamity, to eliminate involuntary poverty and unemployment, and to enable each individual to
attain his maximum potential, George wrote his extraordinary treatise a hundred years ago. His ideas stand: he
who makes should have; he who saves should enjoy; what
the community produces belongs to the community for
communal uses; and God’s earth, all of it, is the right of
the people who inhabit the earth. In the words of Thomas
Jefferson, “The earth belongs in usufruct to the living.”
This is simple and this is unanswerable. The ramifications may not be simple but they do not alter the fundamental logic.
There never has been a time in our history when we
have needed so sorely to hear good sense, to learn to define terms exactly, to draw reasonable conclusions. As
George said, “The truth that I have tried to make clear
310
Afterword
will not find easy acceptance. If that could be, it would
have been accepted long ago. If that could be, it would
never have been obscured.”
We are on the brink. It is possible to have another
Dark Ages. But in George there is a voice of hope.
Agnes George de Mille was the granddaughter of Henry George.
Famous in her own right as a choreographer and the founder of the
Agnes de Mille Heritage Dance Theater, she received the Handel
Medallion, New York’s highest award for achievement in the arts.
She was the author of thirteen books. This essay was published as the
preface to the centenary edition of Progress and Poverty in 1979.
Index
311
Index
A
abstinence, not the cause of
interest 96
Alaska fur seal, example of
sustainable resource
management 221
association
barriers to 278
first essential of human
progress 276
B
Black Death, increased wages
in Europe 160
bond, government
not capital 103
bonds, represent capital when
not issued in excess of
actual production 103
“Boss Tweed” 167
Brazil, endured famine, yet
sparsely populated 68
bread, as example of multistage production 37
C
California
decline of wages in 78
gold rush in 211
high wages in 10
land speculation in 151
origin of land titles in 188
placer mines in 117
they upheld land as common property 212
capital
a portion of wealth 108
aids labor in three distinct
ways 46
concentrations of 105
distinct from land & labor 21
how it is increased or
decreased 106
inconsistent definitions of 19
interchangeability of 97
need for in poor countries 48
reproductive modes of 98
stored-up labor 88
subset of wealth 24
true functions of 46
Chicago, fire in 1871 81
China
alleged overpopulation in 61
poverty in 64
Chinese
immigrants, maintain
familiar environment 273
workers, highly literate 170
Christianity
decline of 294
its role in advance of
European civilization 284
civilization
decline of, not inevitable 295
development of 265
differences in, not due to
heredity 271
perishes from internal decay
268
regression of, not noticed at
first 292
312
Index
common property in land,
natural perception of early
civilizations 282
commons, enclosures of 207
confiscation of land, not
necessary 223
consumption
and production, relative
terms 71
demand for, determines
production 44
cooperation, temporary
benefits of 176
Copernicus 123
Crusoe, Robinson 42
E
D
F
Darwin, Charles 56, 265
de Mille, Agnes George 310
definitions, must be clear and
precise 17
demand, increases as production increases 139
democracy, Jeffersonian ideal
of 255
democratic government,
intensifies existing
inequalities 289
depression of 1879 10
depressions. See recessions
Dewey, John 306
dining table, example of behavior in a just society 258
distribution of wealth See laws
of distribution
division of labor
earliest beginnings of 14
dynamics, of wealth distribution 126
factors of production 87
famine, in Ireland not caused
by overpopulation 67
farms, size of tends to increase
178
Fawcett, Millicent Garrett 41
fertility, high among poor
people 57
feudalism, and common right
to land 206
Fourteenth Amendment 218
fur seal. See Alaska fur seal
economic terms, different in
everyday speech 17
Edison, Thomas 305
education, no effect on general
level of wages 169
England
land ownership in 208
land rent in 159
landowners originally called
to pay for military 210
equality. See justice
Essay on Population, by
Malthus 52, 58
G
government, more efficiency in
165
greed, not strongest human
motivator 256
guilds and unons, development
of 209
Index
H
Henry VIII 160
human beings
increase their own food
supply 70
the only never-satisfied
animal 72, 260
human desires
are unlimited 72, 139, 275
human progress. See also law
of human progress
creates interdependence 279
distinguished from biological evolution 263
I
imagination, tool for testing
economic theories 6
improvements
permanent, value of 189
secure possession of must be
assured 202
security of 219
compatible with common
property in land 220
separating their value from
that of land 238
income tax, weaknesses of 177
India
alleged overpopulation in 61
poverty in 62
wealth drained by British
empire 63
industry, not limited by lack of
capital 47
interest
cause of 95
313
does not include compensation for risk 95
economic vs. commonspeech meanings of 85
equilibrium with wages 108
law of 110
maximum and minimum
points 106
natural, not arbitrary 101
not caused by increased
productiveness 97, 106
rises and falls with wages
9, 109
Internal Revenue Service 307
Ireland
alleged overpopulation in 61
exported food during
famine 67
famine in, claimed as
evidence for Malthusian
theory 66
J
Jefferson, Thomas 309
Jews, adopt customs of the
various countries where
they live 273
justice, second essential of
human progress 277
L
labor
commodification of 195
division of 138
employs capital 88
more productive where
wages are higher 248
314
labor (cont.)
not maintained by capital 41
social costs of its going to
waste 247
supply and demand of 149
labor unions. See also guilds
gains of, at the expense of
rent 171
gains tend to erode over
time 173
pitted against land, not
capital 173
Labor-Saving Inventions
enable greater production 137
increase rent 140
Lamb, Charles 219
land
exclusive tenure not the same
as private property 189
limit of rise in speculative
price 144
must be made common
property 180
must not be classed with
wealth as property 185
natural right to 186
public purchase of is unjust
199
redistribution of, not
practical 177-79
separating value from that
of improvements 238
utterly necessary to life 163
“Land and Liberty,” motto of
Russian “Nihilists” 177
land ownership. See private
property in land
“land poor,” as speculators 143
land rent 224. See also public
collection of land rent
Index
land speculation 142
distinguished from speculation in commodities 144
effect of farmland near cities
143
in California 151
lockout of labor and capital
149
often involves partial use of
land 143
prematurely extends margin
144
returns when recessions end
146
land value
created by the community
234
easily distinguished from
that of improvements 238
equal rights of all quantified
in 189
land value tax See public
collection of land rent
landowners, question of
compensation for 199
Lassalle, Ferdinand XVIII
latifundia 140, 217
law of human progress 277
must account for advance as
well as decline 275
must account for diffeences
in civilizations 270
laws of distribution
their necessary relation 83, 86
correlation of 120
liberty
means justice 296
real grandeur of 296
London, great fire in 1666 81
Index
M
Macaulay, Lord Thomas 63
predicted decline of U.S. 292
Malthus, Rev. Thomas R. 51
on wages during reign of
Henry VIII 160
Malthusian theory 52
appears supported by facts
& analogies 53
disproved 75
doesn’t threaten vested
interests 54
essence of 65
Irish famine claimed as
evidence for 66
supported by wages-fund
theory 54
Maoris 49
margin of production
and law of interest 110
defined 112, 116
key to laws of distribution
121
prematurely extended by
land speculation 144
Marx, Karl, how he differed
from George 308
material progress, three
elements of 127
McCulloch, John, on public
collection of land rent 236
mental power
greatest waste in unjust
society 260
maintenance and conflict
are its non-productive
uses 276
315
Mill, John Stuart 41, 304
on public collection of land
rent 236
modern civilization, its
probable decline 287
modern society, elaboration of
simple society 13
money, confused with capital 35
monopoly. See also natural
monopoly
taxation of does not check
production 229
moral law, universality of 303
N
natural monopolies 228
should be operated by
government 229
natural wages 88
new community 3
New York 4
land values in 159
O
Our Land and Land Policy by
Henry George XV
overconsumption 146, 147
overproduction 146
impossible while excess
capacity exists 147
P
permanent improvements,
value eventually lapses into
land value 239
Philadelphia, George’s
birthplace 304
316
Physiocrats 237
placer mines. See California,
placer mines in
political economy, fundamental
axiom of 6, 93, 107, 111,
116, 120
political equality, insufficient
to prevent society’s
decline 288
population
density correlated with
greater wealth 77, 79
density of in 1879 61
increase of
effect on production 129
enables greater cooperation and exchange 130
of animals & plants, presses
limits of subsistence 69
poverty
abolishing would strengthen
morality, reduce crime 254
cannot be attributed to
increasing population 59
cause of 83
fear of, leads to struggle for
wealth 248
in many different kinds of
society 2
makes people admire riches
256
social costs of 247
Principles of Political Economy,
by Ricardo 41
private property in land
as wrong as chattel slavery
198
basis of aristocracy 194
Index
causes slavery 192
causes vice & misery 187
continuous robbery 200
denies equal rights 184
forces behind its adoption
by society 205
injustice of 182
is inefficient 219
relatively recent phenomenon 204
source of is conquest 188
production
effect of taxes on 226
manipulation, not creation,
of matter 150
modern, contrasted with
primitive 157
relative to consumption 71
source of wages 31
three modes of 100
when it is completed 37
profits
due to risk, not part of
interest 105
not part of wealth distribution 85
property
real vs. personal 208
rightful basis of 182
protectionism
obvious fallacies of 9
inhibits association 278
Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph XVIII
public collection of land rent
benefits to landowners 250
cannot be passed on 240
could easily settle public
debts 255
Index
does not add to prices 231
effect on distribution 246
great benefits for farmers 251
increases production 230
its full significance hard to
grasp 225
makes land common
property 224
makes other reforms easier
296
most certain revenue source
233
obviates need to mortgage
land 245
opens natural opportunities
to labor 245
opposed by powerful
interests 241
secures equal rights to land
224
wealth would be distributed
according to productive
contributions 252
will not reduce wages of
interest 230
would end land speculation
244
would vastly simplify
government 254
pyramid, of industrial organization 153
Q
Quesnay, Francois 237
R
real estate, includes both land
and wealth 185, 238
317
recessions
in the United States 148
ineffective remedies 165
root cause of 145, 148
sudden onset of 152
three factors contributing to
the end of 146, 154
remedy See also public
collection of land rent
necessary tests of 181
rent 85
created by entire community
201
defined 90
economic vs. commonspeech meaning 89
grows with social progress
281
law of 89, 92
rent increased by
better education and work
habits 168
cooperation 174
education 170
more efficient government
166
Ricardo, David XVIII, 41, 304
his law of rent 51, 91, 120
his rent theory used to support Malthusian theory 54
on public collection of land
rent 236
on the desire for food 139
on wages 88
risk
a function of labor 85
not part of distribution of
wealth 85
318
Roman Empire, decline & fall
of 206, 283
S
savannah, story of 131
San Francisco 4
commonly-owned lot in 221
land values in 159
selfishness, not strongest
human motivator 258
services, wages for, not from
capital 33
Shaw, George Bernard 306
simple truth 162
single tax X, 242. See also
public collection of land
rent
slavery 192
chattel, insignificant compared to wage slavery 193
essence of 194
grows & deepens with
material progress 197
its abolition caused no loss
to Southern planters 195
waste of human power 285
slaves, are not wealth 22
Smith, Adam XVIII, 19, 20, 34,
304
“Causes of the Prosperity of
New Colonies” 118
on the desire for food 139
on variation in wages 113
on wages 28, 88
social darwinism X, 56
Social Statics, by Spencer 200
socialism
Index
and government regulation
176
ideal of 177
in tribal state 177
realizing its goals without
coercion 255
society
differences in, not due to differences in individuals 274
maintained by ongoing
production 81
“Spaceship Earth” 136
Spencer, Herbert IX, 200, 304
stocks and bonds
not capital 102
not wealth 22
Storekeepers, as producers 26
Sumner, William Graham XI
supply and demand, their
interrelation 114
Swift, Jonathan 58
T
Tammany Hall 167
taxation
ability-to-pay principle 234
benefits-received principle
235
“broad-based” 240
canons of 226
corrupting influence of 233
effect on production 226
falls heavily on farmers 251
method of implementing
remedy 224
not part of primary distribution 84
Index
penalizes industry and thrift
242
question of certainty 232
taxes, sales
favored by large companies
241
passed on to consumer 231
profits on 232
tenure, stability of 190
Tolstoy, Leo 305
Turgot, Robert Jacques 237
Twain, Mark 305
U
unemployment 158
unions. See labor unions
United States
abundance of land is
key fact of history 214
closing of frontier 215
great fortunes due to land
monopoly 214
increasing corruption in
291
land speculation in 148
recessions in 148
V
value, added at each stage of
production 38
Voltaire, on lawyers 203
W
wage-slavery See also slavery
not abolished by 14th
Amendment 218
319
wages 85
always preceded by labor 31
at all levels depend on
lowest, widest level 115
equilibrium with interest 108
general rate of 108, 114, 115
gradations of 115
in long-term enterprise, not
advanced from capital 35
law of 116
refers to wages as proportion of total wealth 118
not drawn from capital 11
not paid in advance 32
paid in kind 30
return for labor of all kinds 18
rise and fall with interest
9, 109
variations in 111
wages of superintendence, not
part of interest 102
Wallace, Alfred Russell
on Progress and Poverty 305
wealth
defined 23–24
exchangeability of 27, 76
interchangeability of
99, 138
tendency to deteriorate 80
Winkle, Rip Van 135
workers
alienation of 156
general combination of, not
practical 173
personal qualities improve
as wages increase 170
320
Index
The Robert Schalkenbach Foundation (RSF) was
founded in 1925 to promote and develop the ideas of
Henry George and to keep them in the public dialogue. George offered a response to the ideological
polarization between collectivism and individualism,
by presenting a social philosophy that reconciles the
opposing features of capitalism and socialism.
RSF carries out its mission in several ways: 1) by publishing the works of Henry George and distributing
the works of related authors, 2) by funding research
to extend the ideas of Henry George in new contexts,
and 3) by funding advocacy projects that apply his
principles to specific situations.
RSF encourages those who are familiar with Henry
George’s ideas to approach the foundation through a
one-page query letter about potential projects that
might be of mutual interest. Please check our website
for the most recent indication of the kinds of projects
the foundation funds.
Robert Schalkenbach Foundation
149 Madison Avenue, Suite 601
New York NY 10016
Tel: 212-683-6424
Toll-free: 800-269-9555
Fax: 212-683-6454
www.schalkenbach.org
Index
321
Books by Henry George
Published by the Robert Schalkenbach Foundation
Progress and Poverty — An Inquiry Into the Cause of
Industrial Depressions and the Increase of Want with
the Increase of Wealth... The Remedy
Unabridged, 1992 (orig. 1879), 616 pp
Protection or Free Trade — An Examination of the Tariff
Question, with Especial Regard to the Interests of
Labor
1980 (orig. 1886), 335 pp
Social Problems
1996 (orig. 1883), 310 pp
The Land Question — Viewpoint and Counterviewpoint on the Need for Land Reform
1982 (orig. 1884), 348 pp
A Perplexed Philosopher — An Examination of Herbert
Spencer’s Utterances on the Land Question
1988 (orig. 1892), 276 pp
The Science of Political Economy
Unabridged, 1992 (orig. 1898), 545 pp.
Abridged, 2004, 284 pp.
Other works by Henry George and related authors are also
available from the the Foundation. Free catalogue available on request, and online.
800-269-9555
www.schalkenbach.org
322
Index
For Further Exploration
Tuiton-free courses on the economics and social philosophy of Henry George are offered by:
Henry George School of Social Science, 121 East 30th
Street, New York NY 10016. 212-889-8020
www.henrygeorgeschool.org
Henry George School of Philadelphia, 413 South 10th
Street; Philadelphia, PA 19147. 215-922-4278
www.geocities.com/henrygeorgeschool
Henry George School of Chicago, 28 East Jackson
#1004, Chicago IL 60604. 312-362-9302
www.hgchicago.org
Henry George School of Los Angeles, P.O.Box 55,
Tujunga CA 94105. 818-352-4141
henrygeorgeschool@comcast.net
Henry George School of Northern California, 55 New
Montgomery Street; San Francisco, CA 94105.
415-543-4294
www.henrygeorgesf.org
Correspondence courses (Internet or regular mail)
based on the works of Henry George are offered by
the Henry George Institute, 121 East 30th Street,
New York, NY 10016
www.henrygeorge.org
A world-wide list of all Georgist organizations, with
contact information, is available from the Council of
Georgist Organizations, P. O. Box 57, Evanston IL
60204
www.progress.org/cgo