Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2018, The Cambridge Kant Lexicon, ed J Wuerth, Cambridge University Press
…
4 pages
1 file
Lexicon article. Kant's 2nd thesis (1755) supplies the ontological ground for emergence.
The paper argues, against current views that see Kant as giving abstract descriptions of cognitive mechanisms (after the fashion of functionalism in cognitive science), that Kant sees mental phenomena as akin to emergent phenomena in a sense traditionally opposed to mechanism. After distinguishing several relevant notions of emergence, the paper distinguishes several of Kant’s basic emergentist theses, including his emergent materialism in chemistry and a species of mental emergence modelled on that chemical emergence. However, Kant’s doctrine of the epigenesis of pure Reason is argued to be Kant’s most fundamental emergentist thesis. The paper argues that Kant’s notion of mental emergence sheds light on some very puzzling aspects of his remarks about the unity of intuition and concept emphasized by Wilfrid Sellars. The paper sketches some of the problems in contemporary cognitive science and shows how a Sellarsian emergentism inspired by Kant addresses some of these problems and provides an interesting alternative to the kind of mechanistic positions that have tended to dominate the field. Finally, the paper locates the present emergentist reading with respect to the perspectivist reading of Kant.
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Later updates authored by Michael Thompson., 2003
Lexicon article. How Kant's philosophical journey started and what its first milestones were.
INVITED PAPERS 1 HEINRICH SCHEPERS, La monade costituente sé e il proprio mondo 11 MICHEL FICHANT, Les dualités de la dynamique leibnizienne ARTICLES 43 GIOVANNI DE SIMONE, Gli aspetti della cosmologia parmenidea in 28 B10 DK 65 FRANCESCA MASI, La definizione aristotelica di movimento e la critica ai predecessori. Aristot. Phys. III 2, 201b16-202a3 95 GRAZIANO RANOCCHIA, Diogene di Babilonia e Aristone nel PHerc. 1004 ([Filodemo], [Sulla retorica], Libro incerto). Parte prima 131 CARLA RITA PALMERINO, "Prima furon le cose e poi i nomi". Riflessioni intorno alla filosofia del linguaggio di Galileo 151 MATTIA BRANCATO, Leibniz, Weigel and the Birth of Binary Arithmetic
Journal of the History of Philosophy, 2002
A Companion to Kant, ed. Graham Bird (Oxford: Blackwell), 40-60, 2006
Chapter. Kant's metaphysical conjectures on the Big Bang that anticipated science.
Kantian Review, 2020
Review of Gualtiero Lorini's 2017 book, Fonti e lessico dell'ontologia kantiana: I corsi di metafisica (1762-1795)
This Element analyzes Kant’s metaphysics and epistemology of the exact science of nature. It explains his theory of true motion and ontology of matter. In addition, it reconstructs the patterns of evidential reasoning behind Kant’s foundational doctrines.
Penultimate Version. Published version in Justin E.H. Smith, ed., The Problem of Animal Generation in 17th and 18th C. Philosophy, Cambridge, CUP, 2005.
Wolff, German Metaphysics
prop. 2; 1:389.3-6/CETP70:7). Reality is structured by two first axioms ("bina sunt principia absolute prima," 1:389.3), and their propositional umbrella is contradiction.
In this sense-and only in this sense-is contradiction the "absolutely supreme" principle (prop. 3; 1:390.33/CETP70:9). Although Kant defers to the consensus that puts contradiction first, he does so with the caveat of there really being no "first".
Reality is complex, and its first cognitive principle is a derivative synthesis of affirmation and negation.
In section II, Kant examines the second ontological axiom, the law of causation. Determining reason governs natural processes in the guise of efficient causation.
Anything that exists is caused by something else, and nothing that exists has the ground of being in itself (prop 6, 1:394/CETP70:14). This also applies to God.
Contradicting Wolff's claim that God is above the causal structure of reality by having the ground of existence in Himself (cf. Philosophia prima sive Ontologia [1730] §309), Kant suggests that God should rather be defined as the "Being, the existence of which is prior to the very possibility both of itself and of all things" (prop. 7, 1:395/CETP70:15). God is "the absolutely necessary principle of all possibility" and also the only being "in which existence is prior to, or ... identical with possibility"
(1:395-396/CETP70:16-17). Traditionally (cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics 9.1-3), possibility is thought to precede existence and necessity. But in his ontological argument in prop. 7, Kant reverses this sequence and claims that necessity is prior to existence, and existence prior to possibility, an argument he will develop at length in OPA [1763] (2:79-83/CETP70:124-128).
Since the principle of determining reason implies that nothing that exists "can be without a ground which determines its existence antecedently" (prop. 8; 1:396.8-9/CETP70:17), this raises the question of freedom. Freedom has the structure of spontaneous causation: a free action is the effect of a single, complete cause, and this cause is not caused by something else. So the intention or inclination of the will, which grounds free action, must be unconstrained. Instead of being determined by an open-ended chain of antecedent causes, the spontaneity of free action issues from an inner principle, the inclination (prop. 9, 1:402.12/CETP70:25).
But how can freedom, governed by spontaneous causation, occur in a world determined by chains of efficient causation? Efficient causation has the structure that each cause is the effect of a prior cause. Nothing comes out of nowhere; anything that exists is merely the most recent link of a chain. Kant addresses this difficulty in a dialogue (1:401.19-405.11/CETP70:24-30) between a proponent of determinism, Caius, and a defender of freedom, Titius. Kant/Titius suggests that the chain of efficient causes supplies motives (motiva) for intentions (1:403.14/CETP70:27), but the will is not compelled to act on them, for "we are eminently able to either focus our attention on them, or to suspend our attention, or to turn it in another direction"
(1:403.14-15/ibid.). There is a gap between the last link in the efficient chain, the motive, and the first link of spontaneous causation, the inclination. This allows the will to pivot. The will can turn to motives of its choice. This power rests on the inner principle of spontaneity. It lets the will incline to motives that are weaker than others (1:403.19-24/CETP70:27). Free action results from such pivots (1:402.3-13/CETP70:25).
By differentiating externally caused motives from spontaneously arising inclinations, Kant seeks to integrate lawful processes in the world with free actions of the mind.
Arguably, his compatibilist proposal only shifts the problem to a mind-internal gap between deterministic and free causes, which raises further questions. In CPrR
[1788], Kant would dismiss this notion of freedom as "no better than that of a turnspit, which when once wound up also carries out its motions of itself" (5:97/CEPP:218). Yet despite this later dismissal, the compatibilism of NE represents a metaphysical explanation. The problem of free will may not have a logical solution but can still be elucidated in dynamic terms. Minds exist in the world as monads that are wellsprings of power in interactive networks. Free are those minds that prevail over exterior impacts. Whether a mind is free is a matter of its relative strength in the network. Autonomy is the result of resistance produced by the "spontaneous power of self-determination" (semet ipsa sponte determinandi potestate; 1:404.8/CETP70:28).
In section 3, Kant proposes two further principles, which are "derivative" of determining reason (1:410.15/CETP70:37) and permit "deeper" metaphysical cognition (1:416.5-6/CETP70:45). The first of these principles is the principle of succession. It states that "no change can happen to substances except in so far as they are connected with other substances" (prop. 12;. This axiom of interconnectedness is the schema of physical processes. It accounts for change and time, and serves as the ontological platform for Newton's law of motions. The principle of succession in NE foreshadows Kant's later project in MNS [1786].
The second of these derivative causal laws is the principle of coexistence. It states that "finite substances do not, in virtue of their existence alone, stand in a relationship with each other, nor are they linked together by any interaction at all, except in so far as the common principle of their existence, namely the divine understanding, maintains them in a state of harmony in their reciprocal relations (prop. 13;. Coexistence complements succession.
Interaction, while essential for change, is not essential for the existence of substances.
The result is an integrative proposal. With the binary basis of contradiction developed in section 1, and the compatibilist proposal in section 2, NE supplies the ontological framework to the evolutionary philosophy of nature developed in TE
[1749] and UNH [1755]. In TE ( §1-10), Kant contends that nature stems from an energetic state whose forces are twofold, and in UNH (II.2 and II.7), he suggests that the interplay of attractive and repulsive forces creates a world of matter and minds.
With the derivative principles of succession and coexistence formulated in section 3, Kant hopes to arrive at a conciliatory conclusion that combines aspects of the theory of physical influx-advocated by early modern Neo-Aristotelians and more recently by Leonard Euler in Gedanken von den Elementen der Körper [1746] to account for action at a distance in Newtonian mechanics-with aspects of the theory of pre-established harmony advocated by Leibniz and his students.
(1500 words) Martin Schönfeld
IOSR Journals , 2019
Péninsule 80, 2020
Rev Espan Enferm Dig, 2006
ChemInform, 2009
International Journal of Thermal Sciences, 2010
Free Radical Biology and Medicine, 2008
$ Deep Work: Rules for Focused Success in a Distracted WorldDeep Work: Rules for Focused Success in a Distracted World *
Research Square (Research Square), 2023
American Speech, 2012
Protest in the Vietnam War Era, 2022
Denkmalpflege, 2004
Contaduría Universidad de Antioquia, 2008
Questions de communication, 2004
Archivos en Medicina Familiar, 2017
Ricerca didattica e formazione degli insegnanti. Modelli, approcci e metodologie, 2024