The Problem of Nature
in
Contemporary Social Theory
Paul Rutherford
June 2000
A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of
The Australian National University.
2
Declaration.
I hereby certify that the work contained in this thesis is my own
work, and that I have cited in the references all works and sources
consulted in the writing thereof.
Paul Rutherford
Political Science Program
Research School of Social Sciences
Australian National University, Canberra.
2000 Paul Rutherford
3
Acknowledgments
I wish to record my sincere thanks to Professor Barry Hindess, who both as a
friend and as chair of the supervisory panel for my doctoral program at the
Australian National University, provided not only enlightening and constructive
advice and but also genuine warmth and encouragement during the writing of this
thesis. I also extend my appreciation to the other members of my supervisory
panel, Dr Jim George and Dr David West for their encouragement and advice,
especially in the initial part of my candidature when I was working full-time at the
ANU.
Many colleagues have provided both encouragement and stimulating
intellectual comment during the period of time I spent at the ANU working on this
thesis. I am especially grateful for the support given to me by many colleagues
across both the Faculties and Institute of Advanced Studies at the ANU. In
particular I would like to mention Dr John Ballard while he was Head of the
Graduate Program in Political Science and International Relations and afterwards,
Professor John Warhurst during his time as Head of the Department of Political
Science in the Faculty of Arts, and Dr Frank Lewins. Of those colleagues outside
of the ANU, in particular I appreciated the generous encouragement and the
intellectual insights provided by Professor Nikolas Rose of the University of
London, and Associate Professor Paul Patton of the University of Sydney.
Through the support of many of the people I have mentioned here,
particularly Jim George, I was fortunate to receive an ANU PhD scholarship, and
I wish to thank the University for its support in that regard.
Finally, I must thank Penny and Skye for putting up with both the thesis and
myself for so long, and also for ensuring that I persevered to the end.
4
Abstract
This work examines the ways in which the relationship between society and
nature is problematic for social theory. The Frankfurt School’s notion of the
dialectic of enlightenment is considered, as are the attempts by Jurgen Habermas
to defend an ‘emancipatory’ theory of modernity against this. The marginalising
effect Habermas’ defence of reason has had on the place of nature in his critical
social theory is examined, as is the work of theorists such as Ulrich Beck and
Klaus Eder. For these latter authors, unlike Habermas, the social relation to nature
is at the centre of contemporary society, giving rise to new forms of
modernisation and politics.
Michel Foucault’s work on biopolitics and governmentality is examined
against the background of his philosophical debate with Habermas on power and
rationality. The growth of scientific ecology is shown to have both problematised
the social relation to nature and provided the political technology for new forms
of regulatory intervention in the management of the population and resources.
These new forms of intervention constitute a form of ecological governmentality
along the lines discussed by Foucault and others in relation to the human sciences.
However, Foucault’s work is not sufficiently critical of the relationship
between the natural sciences and power. Extending Foucault’s biopolitics to
environmental discourse is consistent with his general approach to power, but his
incomplete critique of political sovereignty meant that for him agency remained
tied to an idealised notion of the autonomy of the human subject. He therefore
made too strong a distinction between the human and natural sciences and
between power and the capacities of non-human entities, and continued to view
the natural sciences as separating themselves from power in a way that was not
possible in the human sciences.
A more general critique of epistemic sovereignty reveals that the natural
sciences (including ecology) are subject to disciplinary and normalising practices
similar to those of the human sciences. Foucault’s key inadequacy is that he
linked agency to human autonomy and sovereignty. The work of Bruno Latour
and other actor network theorists show that an unambiguous ontological
distinction between nature, material technologies and active human subjects is
highly problematic. In the place of a separate ‘society’ and ‘nature’, this thesis
argues that it is preferable to see these as a single socio-nature populated by the
hybrid products of translation networks.
By drawing together the insights of recent governmentality studies and the
approach of actor network theory to agency and translation, Foucault’s concept of
biopolitics can be adapted to provide a theoretical framework for understanding
the ecological programs of government that have emerged around the problem of
nature in second half of the twentieth century.
5
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Declaration. ...................................................................................................2
Acknowledgments...........................................................................................3
Abstract ..........................................................................................................4
TABLE OF CONTENTS.................................................................................5
Chapter 1
Introduction: the problem of nature............................................ 8
Structure of the thesis...................................................................................14
Chapter 2
Background: the negative dialectic of progress........................ 17
Introduction..................................................................................................17
Weber: the ‘iron cage’ of societal rationalisation.......................................18
The Frankfurt School: the Dialectic of Enlightenment................................20
The critique of instrumental reason .............................................................24
Habermas’ critique of the Dialectic of Enlightenment ................................31
Conclusion ...................................................................................................34
Chapter 3
The problem of nature in Habermas ......................................... 35
Introduction..................................................................................................35
The problem of nature in Habermas ............................................................36
Nature and cognitive interests .....................................................................39
Communicative action..................................................................................47
System and lifeworld ....................................................................................49
Nature in communicative action theory .......................................................52
Conclusion ...................................................................................................58
Chapter 4
The problem of nature in Eder and Beck.................................. 59
Introduction..................................................................................................59
(1) Eder: nature as a new field of social conflict.........................................59
Environmental movements as cultural models.............................................63
(2) Beck: ecological risk & reflexive modernisation ...................................68
Scientific expertise and the production of risks ...........................................71
Sub-politics: decline of the state as a political centre .................................80
(3) Luhmann: ecological communication & functional differentiation .......83
Conclusion ...................................................................................................86
6
Chapter 5
Foucault and critical theory: the debate on power................... 87
Introduction..................................................................................................87
Foucault: modern power and rationality.....................................................87
Foucault and Habermas: the debate on power............................................94
Foucault’s relationship to the German critical tradition ..........................101
Conclusion .................................................................................................109
Chapter 6
Biopolitics, governmentality and scientific expertise ............. 111
Introduction................................................................................................111
Discipline and biopolitics ..........................................................................111
Biopolitics and ecological risk...................................................................117
Governmental rationality...........................................................................121
Liberalism ..................................................................................................124
The modern discourse of scientific ecology ...............................................127
Expertise and governmentality...................................................................130
Ecology as regulatory science ...................................................................133
Environmental assessment & modelling as technologies of government ..137
Conclusion .................................................................................................143
Chapter 7
Foucault’s incomplete critique of the sovereignty.................. 146
Introduction................................................................................................146
Foucault’s characterisation of the natural sciences..................................147
Power and capacity: the subject revisited .................................................150
Foucault’s incomplete critique of sovereignty...........................................158
Rouse: the critique of epistemic sovereignty .............................................165
Conclusion .................................................................................................172
Chapter 8
Latour and actor network theory............................................. 174
Introduction................................................................................................174
Actor network theory..................................................................................175
Latour and Foucault: affinities and differences ........................................184
Actants and agency ....................................................................................187
Representation and the modern constitution .............................................192
Conclusion .................................................................................................197
7
Chapter 9
Conclusion: ecological modernisation or governmentality ? 200
Introduction................................................................................................200
Key themes .................................................................................................201
(1) The problem of nature for critical theory.............................................201
(2) The centrality of ecological problems in Eder and Beck .....................203
(3) Biopolitics and the problem of nature in Foucault ..............................206
(4) Foucault: the incomplete critique of sovereignty.................................208
(5) Latour: the critique of modern representation.....................................210
Ecological modernisation or ecological governmentality? .......................213
Bibliography............................................................................... 227
Total pages 245
8
Chapter 1
Introduction: the problem of nature
Most contemporary Western thinking about the natural environment is
characterised by an ecological view of nature, that is, by the belief that the
relationship between human society and nature must, at least to some degree, be
managed or guided by the principles and laws expounded by the science of
ecology. The research problem that underlies this thesis is how the natural
sciences, and ecology in particular, contribute to the governing of human conduct
through the representations of nature they provide. The thesis is a critical
reflection on how the representation of nature by scientific expertise acts as a
political resource which actively constitutes the objects of government and at the
same time provides the intellectual machinery or ‘political technology’ necessary
for such government.
More particularly, this thesis is about the problem of nature in contemporary
social theory. It examines the way in which two major theoretical perspectives - a
German tradition of critical theory drawing on the work of the Frankfurt School
and Jurgen Habermas, and a post-structuralist tradition deriving from the work of
French theorists Michel Foucault and Bruno Latour - engage with this problem.
Why study these two schools of thought? Both perspectives have something
significant to say about the relationship between society and nature, and I wanted
to explore the implications of the different approaches for how we understand key
concepts in political philosophy such as power and agency, and how these relate
to contemporary concerns over the natural environment.
The problem of nature as approached here is not primarily the problem as
framed by the rationalist and utilitarian traditions, of how to subject nature
through science and technology to human ends such as economic growth. Rather
the problem is one that results from the apparent success of such economic
development and scientific ‘domination’ of nature. The problem is most clearly
evident in the contemporary ecological notion that the exploitation of nature in
modern industrial society puts at risk not only human welfare but also the material
basis of life in general. The ‘problem of nature’ should be understood subject to
the qualification that in using this term I am referring specifically to the
contemporary theoretical formulation of the natural environment as an issue of
social concern and as a site of political conflict. By pointing to the theoretical
formulation of the social relation to nature as a problem, I wish to emphasise that
this process is an important discursive development not only within political and
social theory, but also within key areas of the natural sciences. Thus,
environmental risk is an issue that, in one form or another, has increasingly
9
occupied the social and biological sciences over the past four decades, and has
been the focus for an expanding domain of policy formulation and administrative
intervention by States, international institutions and social movements.
This work is firmly situated within the context of those contemporary
environmental debates and problems of ecological risk. Yet, I am not concerned
here with the scientific details of such issues in a substantive way. Neither am I
directly concerned with the evaluation of policies and regulatory instruments that
might be appropriate and efficacious for the management of environmental
problems. This is not to suggest that these tasks are unimportant, or that the
conclusions of this thesis have no relevance to the policy and practice of
environmental protection. 1
The German critical theory tradition – stretching from Weber via the
Frankfurt School to contemporary theorists of a new politics of ecological
modernisation such as Klaus Eder and Ulrich Beck – is intimately bound up with
the critique of the process of rationalisation. This tradition sees societal
rationalisation as the dynamic behind modernisation and takes seriously the
heteronomous effects of technocratic rationality on human freedom. German
critical theory has been one of the most outspoken critics of the effect of such
technocratic rationalisation on human autonomy. At the same time it has also
sought to preserve the notion that there is an underlying normative content of
reason which is essential to human freedom and social progress.
The Frankfurt School (particularly Horkheimer and Adorno) and recent
theorists such as Eder and Beck have taken as central in their work a close
connection between the scientific domination of ‘external’ nature and repression
of human ‘inner’ nature. In doing so they have anticipated from a social theory
perspective, themes taken up in environmental discourse over the past four
decades, and have done so with a degree of philosophical and sociological
sophistication that has generally been lacking in the moralistic and scientistic
efforts of much environmental dialogue. Nevertheless, this German tradition,
including contemporary theorists such as Beck, in the end fails to break with the
tendency to seek a ‘dialectical unification of processes of rationalisation’, and to
privilege the abstract and general over the substantive analysis of the multiple and
dispersed forms of practical and technical rationality which characterises the work
of the theoretical tradition deriving from Foucault. (Dean, 1998b)
1
In fact, I consider these to be important matters. Environmental policy and regulation are issues
with which I have been engaged for over 17 years of professional life - within non-government
environmental organisations, with State environment protection agencies, and in university
teaching.
10
The thesis is more sympathetic to work of the French theorists Foucault and
Latour. While the work of each has a different focus – Foucault is perhaps best
characterised a political philosopher, while Latour is a sociologist of science –
each can contribute to the development of a more satisfactory understanding of
the dynamics underlying contemporary ecological discourses and practices. In
particular both authors, albeit in different ways which I consider in some detail,
place particular importance on the relationship between expertise, scientific
knowledge, and government. Government is not simply (or in many instances,
even primarily) the activities of the State. Rather it is seen by both theorists as a
series of matrices or networks of power through which authorities of all sorts
(scientific, moral, economic, legal, technical, as well as ‘political’) attempt to
translate their plans, calculations, schemes and interests in ways which shape the
conduct and beliefs of others. Rose and Miller (1992 p.175) most succinctly sum
up this perspective when they say that
Knowledge is central to these activities of government and to the very
formation of its objects, for government is a domain of cognition,
calculation, experimentation and evaluation. And, we argue, government
is intrinsically linked to the activities of expertise, whose role is not one
of weaving an all-pervasive web of ‘social control’, but of enacting
assorted attempts at the calculated administration of diverse aspects of
conduct through countless, often competing, local tactics of education,
persuasion, inducement, management, incitement, motivation and
encouragement.
These comments direct our attention to one of the key elements that
distinguish this approach from the other main theoretical perspective considered
in this thesis, the critical theory of Jurgen Habermas and the Frankfurt School.
Both Foucault and Latour decline to understand the relationship between the
technical and the political as an opposition (although as I argue Foucault’s
approach has significant shortcomings). The technical is not something that
interferes with or frustrates the realisation of the potential for human freedom, but
rather is fundamental to the constitution of agency. Hence, the problem of nature
is examined here within a specific theoretical framework. That framework draws
on both the work of Foucault (and those scholars who have developed his work on
political philosophy and especially ‘governmentality’ over the past 15 years) 2 and
2
I am referring to the works of Nikolas Rose and Peter Miller in particular, but also important
work by Barry Hindess, Mitchell Dean, Paul Patton, Joseph Rose, Graham Burchell, and Colin
Gordon, among others. For the major contributions see Barry et al. (1996); Burchell et al.
(1991); Dean (1994); Gane and Johnson (1993); Gordon (1991); Hindess (1996); Miller
(1987); Moss (1998); Patton (1994); Rose (1999); Rose and Miller (1992); Rouse (1987).
11
the work of Bruno Latour and those associated with what is known as actor
network theory.3
Environmental issues and conflicts have generated a substantial literature in
political science (especially the policy studies area), philosophy (particularly in
ethics), sociology (social movement theory), law, economics, and geography.
Environmental conflicts make problematic the modes of conduct with which we
relate to the natural environment. What is at issue then, are the ways in which
specific social activities or technical practices affecting the natural environment
are turned into problems and challenged, giving rise to conflicts over how such
problems should be dealt with.4 Taking up the sort of analysis explored by
Foucault, the problem of the social relation to nature can be understood as
involving four different dimensions of ‘government’, each of which shapes the
ways in which we relate to and interact with the natural environment. These four
dimensions of government are forms of knowledge, relations of power, technical
rationalities, and practices of identity formation. Thus, as James Tully has
expressed it
Our ‘relation to nature’ in any organised form of practice, such as, say,
forestry, is a complex experience that conjoins four dimensions: (1) a
field of knowledge (including concepts, theories, economic, scientific,
and political disciplines, practical know-how and so on, often at odds
with each other), (2) ways of governing the individuals and groups
involved in this activity (employing techniques, rules, procedures,
relations of power, and so forth), (3) the practical rationalities in
accordance with which human aptitudes are exercised on nature through
various technologies, and (4) the practices of self-formation available in
our cultures by which individuals make themselves over as ethical agents
in relation to nature. (Tully, 1997 p.6)
Employing this general approach the thesis shows how Foucault’s notion of
biopower can be adapted to the understanding of environmental government.
Biopower is that aspect of modern power, according to Foucault, which is
simultaneously focused on disciplining of the body of the individual and
managing the population through the regulation of its biological processes.
Following from this, I advance three central propositions in this thesis. First, the
concern with environmental problems and ecological risk which has emerged to
prominence in the past four decades can be seen as a development of what
3
I include in this Latour’s early work with Woolgar (Woolgar and Latour, 1979) and the work of
Callon and Law. See Callon (1986); Callon and Latour (1981); Latour (1983); (1987); (1991);
(1993); Law (1986); (1991b); (1994).
4
Sometimes of course, the conflict is over whether or not there is a problem – this was
particularly evident in the earlier stages of the debates on both ozone depletion and global
warming.
12
Foucault called ‘the regulatory biopolitics of the population’. Second, this
relatively recent articulation of biopolitics gives rise to new techniques for
managing the environment and the population, which are dependent on the
institutionalisation of new areas of scientific expertise, which is itself based on a
bio-economic understanding of global systems ecology. Third, this aspect of
contemporary biopolitics is expressed as a distinctive mode of governmental
rationality that I describe as ecological governmentality.
As I have noted, examination of the work of the German scholars mentioned
above reveals a concern with the processes of social rationalisation that locates
the problem of nature as a consequence of modernisation. Discussion of how the
problem of nature relates to the wider concerns of a critical social theory leads
into the major debate between Habermas and Foucault on power and rationality.
While Foucault’s view of power is superior to that of Habermas and critical
theory, there is nevertheless a significant gap in his work as it applies to the
natural sciences. Indeed, it is argued that while the extension of Foucault’s notion
of biopolitics to environmental discourse and the natural sciences generally is in
many respects consistent with his theoretical approach, he appears reluctant to do
this in the way he did with the human sciences.
Foucault was unwilling to consistently extend his genealogical approach to
power and knowledge from the human to the natural sciences. The thesis
concludes that this is because, despite his critique of the traditional view of
political sovereignty (in which power is seen as a ‘possession’ centralised in the
State and largely equivalent with domination), Foucault does not take the critique
of sovereignty far enough. He retains a view of agency that is tied to human
autonomy, and which in some key respects idealises political sovereignty as the
absence of domination or even disciplinary power. He also appears to accept a
fairly conventional view of the natural sciences, affording them a special
epistemological status in which scientific knowledge is somehow able to detach
itself from the relations of power that he sees as inextricably tied the knowledge
and practices of the human science. In order to carry the critique of political
sovereignty further a more thorough critique of epistemic sovereignty is needed in
which all forms of scientific representation are subjected the same sorts of
rigorous examination given by Foucault to the human sciences.
A major finding of the thesis is that the problems of sovereignty which have
prevented Foucault and subsequent governmentality studies from consistently
applying the insights of this approach to the natural sciences can be overcome by
drawing on the work of Latour and actor network theory. Actor network theory is
broadly consistent with the approach developed by Foucault and has been
influential in providing some of the key concepts employed in governmentality
13
studies. 5 However, its most significant advantage is that it is able to deal with the
problem of agency in a more satisfactory and less anthropocentric manner than
does Foucault. This is achieved by rejecting any rigid ontological and
epistemological distinctions between subject/object and human/non-human, and
by showing that agency is not exclusively a property of the human subject. Rather
agency is a characteristic of networks composed of hybrid actants (rather than
actors). Actants are entities made up of a ‘socio-nature’ that collect together and
translate a diverse assemblage of capacities, powers, resources, technologies and
practices in the complex and multiple ways suggested by governmentality studies.
By recognising the centrality of material technologies (such as inscription
devices) in the scientific representation and mobilisation of ‘nature’, the actor
network approach permits genealogical analysis of the social relation to nature in
a way that more fully accounts for the complex inter-relationship between the
social and the technical. Power is not only the human capacity to act and shape
the conduct of other humans, but is a feature of any capacity to act, no matter
what the source of that action. Agency then is a property of a network, elements
of which will be non-human and may have a significant enough capacity to
initiate or direct action as to qualify as an ‘agent’.
The approach explored in this thesis is intended to contribute to two important
tasks in political philosophy and social theory. The first is to develop the
substantial insights of Foucault’s work on biopolitics and governmentality (and
subsequent studies on governmentality by others) and apply these to the analysis
of environmental politics and the role of the ecological sciences in the emergence
of new forms of governmental rationality. Until the recent publication of an edited
collection (Darier, 1999a) there had been no major attempt to bring Foucault’s
work to bear on environmental concerns. However, as I have argued in my
contribution to the Darier collection and elsewhere, 6 the biopolitical management
of the population is only possible if at the same time the natural environment on
which the population depends is itself subject to scientific and political
thematisation and problematisation. The second task is to open up a more robust
and focused dialogue between the substantial and important bodies of political
theory – particularly governmentality studies and actor network theory – that I
have drawn upon in this thesis. As I have shown each ‘school of thought’ is aware
of the other and each acknowledges the influence of the other on its own
approach, but this is something that tends to occur in the background.7 In the
governmentality writings, this is no doubt a reflection of the biases in Foucault’s
5
In particular the work of Nikolas Rose and Peter Miller. See Chapter 8 of this thesis.
6
See Rutherford (1993), (1994a), (1997a), (1999b).
7
Law (1994) and Kusch (1991) provide what are probably the most serious attempt to engage the
two schools of thought.
14
work against the natural sciences. Similarly, as actor network theory developed
out of the sociology of science and science studies, it has primarily been
interested in those areas – the natural sciences and material technologies –
neglected by Foucault (and those most influenced by his work).
Structure of the thesis
The remainder of the thesis, following this brief introduction, is divided into
two main parts. Chapters 2, 3 and 4 deal with the problem of nature in what can
be broadly described as the German critical theory tradition. Chapter 2 by way of
background considers the counter current to the Enlightenment view of
modernisation and progress which is evident in Weber and the Frankfurt School’s
appropriation of him and Nietzsche. This view, most evident in Horkheimer and
Adorno’s book Dialectic of Enlightenment, argues that the same processes of
societal rationalisation which were responsible for progress through the
domination of nature also reify and distort human inner nature. Horkheimer and
Adorno therefore rejected the Enlightenment’s philosophical separation of
subjectivity and nature, and argued instead for emancipation of both natures from
the violence of ‘identity thinking’ through an aesthetic reconciliation between the
two natures. This is a move that draws on Nietzsche’s critique of morality and
science, and which is attacked by Habermas as ‘reducing’ truth to power and
undermining the possibility of rational social critique, a charge he also makes
against Foucault’s work.
Chapter 3 examines Habermas’ attempt to develop critical social theory in a
direction that would overcome the Frankfurt School’s ‘one dimensional’ view of
rationality. The focus of the chapter is on how in his reconstruction of critical
theory, Habermas deals with the problem of the relationship between ‘inner’ and
‘outer’ nature as presented in Horkheimer and Adorno’s critique of instrumental
reason. This involves a detailed consideration of his early work in which the
natural history of the human species is seen as giving rise to a series of knowledge
constitutive interests. The chapter then goes on to examine the recasting of the
problem of nature in his later theory of communicative reason with its shift to
linguistic philosophy and systems theory. Both theoretical approaches, but
particularly the latter, are only able to overcome the problem of nature by
maintaining a radical separation between subjectivity and nature, and arguing the
only ‘theoretically fruitful’ attitude to nature is a strategic, instrumental one.
Some key criticisms of Habermas’ work are reviewed, focusing in particular on
the anthropocentric character of his rigid separation of nature and society, and his
dismissal of ecological movements as marginal and anti-modernist.
The critique of Habermas is developed further in Chapter 4 where the
contemporary work of the theorists Ulrich Beck and Klaus Eder is examined in
some detail. Unlike Habermas, both authors see the problem of nature as central
15
to contemporary social relations and the direction of further modernisation, and
regard ecological problems as providing the basis for new social divisions and
conflicts. Particular attention is given to the ways in which these authors argue
that the problem of nature in contemporary technological society is taken up by
ecological movements. Contrary to Habermas, for these theorists such movements
are not anti-modernist or irrational reactions to the complexity of social
rationalisation, but represent alternative, critical views of the course of
modernisation. Instead of being marginal, such movements can be seen as
significantly influencing the future direction of modernisation in technological
society.
Chapter 5 sets the ground for the transition to the second part of the thesis, by
introducing discussion of Foucault’s work, and more importantly by examining
the core differences between Habermas and Foucault over the nature of power and
rationality. This is important as Habermas’ criticisms of Horkheimer and Adorno
parallel those he directs at Foucault and other ‘post-structuralist’ theorists. My
argument in the second part of the thesis – that a more useful theoretical
framework for understanding ecological issues is found in Foucault’s concepts of
biopolitics and governmentality – is in part developed through this critique of the
shortcomings of Habermas’ view of power and its relationship to the natural
sciences. However, despite the differences, some common intellectual concerns
between the critical theory tradition and Foucault are evident, and these are
briefly considered in this chapter.
The second main part of the thesis consists of Chapters 6, 7 and 8, which deal
with the problem of nature as it arises in bodies of work influenced by two French
theorists of power, Foucault and Latour. Chapter 6 examines Foucault’s work on
biopolitics and governmentality in detail. The intersection of what Foucault calls
the emergence of the ‘population-riches’ problem and beginnings of the
environmental discourse are explored. It is argued that the extension of the notion
of biopolitics to the ecological relations of populations to their environment is
consistent with Foucault’s approach. This is demonstrated with a discussion of the
emergence of modes of governmental rationality that problematise and discipline
the social relation to the natural environment. Particular emphasis is placed on the
role of scientific expertise in this process, and the emergence of ecology as a
regulatory science, with functions not unlike those evident in the application of
biology to the human sciences.
Chapter 7 commences with a discussion of Foucault’s view of the relationship
between power and the natural sciences. It is shown that Foucault was far more
ambiguous about this than he was with the ‘dubious’ human sciences. In fact,
Foucault regarded the natural sciences as having attained a degree of
‘formalisation’ and ‘objectivity’ that allowed them to free themselves from power
in a way he regarded as impossible for the human sciences. The chapter identifies
the source of this approach in an underlying conception of subjectivity, evident in
16
his later works, which identifies agency and power with an idealised view of
human autonomy. It is argued that his critique of political sovereignty needs to be
carried further, to more thoroughly scrutinise the relationship between power,
domination and agency. It is also argued that this needs to be broadened to a
critique of epistemic sovereignty in general, so that the same sort of critical,
genealogical questions as are put to the human sciences are also asked of the
natural sciences.
Chapter 8 discusses the work of Bruno Latour and Michel Callon, and what is
known as actor network theory, and considers the intellectual affinities of this
with Foucault and some of the more recent work on governmentality. Following
the criticisms of Foucault’s approach to agency and the natural sciences in the
previous chapter, it is suggested that actor network theory can provide a way of
overcoming these shortcomings. Of particular importance is the use of what
Callon terms the principle of generalised symmetry. This is the methodological
cornerstone of actor network theory, and requires that irrespective of whether
human or non-human phenomena are studied, the same analytical framework
should be used. In line with actor network theory’s socio-technical approach, this
principle cautions against the assumption that agency is necessarily a human
characteristic. In making representational distinctions between ‘subject’ and
‘object’ problematic, this approach is able to follow through on the need identified
in the previous chapter to extend Foucault’s critique of political sovereignty to
that of a critique of epistemic sovereignty and all modes of scientific
representation. In doing so it thereby focuses attention on agency as an effect of
socio-technical networks rather than as an inherent property of the human subject.
Chapter 9 is the conclusion, and consists of two broad sections. The first
reviews the key themes and findings of the thesis, while the second briefly
considers some of the theoretical implications of these findings for political
philosophy and social theory, and the ways in which these disciplines deal with
the analysis of contemporary ecological problems.
17
Chapter 2
Background: the negative dialectic of progress
Introduction
This chapter examines some key social theorists who have been concerned in
varying ways with understanding modernity and who have questioned the
consequences of the rationalisation of society associated with modernisation. In
particular I focus on the Frankfurt School theorists Horkheimer and Adorno and
their diagnosis of the ‘dialectic of Enlightenment’, although in doing so I also
briefly discuss the influence of Weber, Nietzsche and Lukacs.
Modern Western political thought has portrayed human history as the struggle
to establish and maintain the material security of existence through the control of
nature. This discourse underlies a multitude of human endeavours - from battles to
subdue disease through medicine and public sanitation, to the drive for
development and industrialisation, to the rise of contemporary programs to deal
with the unintended contamination of the global environment by the unwanted byproducts and effects associated with the success of that same techno-industrial
development.
At their core, these notions presuppose biological embodiment as a
fundamental feature of human being. This claim, obvious in itself, has formed the
starting point for a broad range of problems in political philosophy and social
theory, from Hobbes, through Marx, Nietzsche and evident in contemporary
discourse about global ecological crisis. This concern with survival reflects an
understanding of human beings as simultaneously possessing a dual nature – a
species-being and a cultural-being. The tension between culture and nature is
manifested in numerous ways. It is crucial to the development of concepts of what
it is to be a person. What makes humans different from other living things, on this
account, is not any special relationship with the divine or mystical, but human
self-consciousness, our cultural, language dependent differentiation from the
merely biological. Additionally, and this is frequently taken as the distinguishing
characteristic of modern societies, some peoples have developed a capacity to,
and propensity for, the systematic scientific investigation of the world and the
technological manipulation of the human biophysical environment. This interplay
of culture and nature thus leads to those characteristics which define the modern
human subject - self-reflective agents pursuing a fundamental drive for selfpreservation through the rational manipulation of the non-human nature to
enhance the security and welfare of human beings. It is this relationship between
18
society and our environment that in recent decades has given rise to increased
consideration to the problems of ecological crisis.
Weber: the ‘iron cage’ of societal rationalisation
The work of Max Weber was centrally concerned with the processes of
modernisation, which he interpreted as involving the progressive rationalisation of
society. Rationalisation for Weber signified the spread of scientific specialisation
and technical differentiation peculiar to Western culture. (Smart, 1983 p.123)8 His
theory of rationalisation distinguished three aspects of rationality - purposive,
formal and discursive. Purposive rationality is that involved in the selection of the
most efficient means to achieve specific objectives and is directed towards an
instrumental manipulation of outcomes. It is particularly related to increasing the
efficiency of administrative and economic actions. Formal rationality, for Weber,
referred to a broader or more generalised systematisation aimed at imposing
coherence and order on the disorderly complexity of human experience, thought
and social actions. Weber identified this form of rationality with developments
such as the formalisation and ‘universalisation’ of law and the spread of
bureaucratic organisation within modern society, that is, with the means and
procedures for enhancing institutional calculability and control. Discursive
rationality for Weber related to notions of practical reason in a more traditional
Kantian sense, in that it involves adoption of coherent criteria for the substantive
evaluation of the actions of individuals. Weber saw this as related to the adoption
of the desacralized attitudes of modern science with its objectivity, freedom from
illusion and value neutrality. (Wellmer, 1985 p.40-1)
The growth of rationalisation and the rise of capitalism Weber attributed to
the development of Protestantism and its creation of a culture oriented towards the
mastery, through work and science, of the social and natural environment. (Smart,
1983 p.123; Turner, 1987 p.223-4) The Weberian attitude exhibits a certain
ambiguity towards rationalisation. Smart argues that the rationalisation process is
not understood by Weber as representing either the ‘progress of reason’ or
enlightenment. The focus of rationalisation is on the refinement of efficient means
of social organisation. Efficiency here is in terms of the realisation of particular
outcomes or objectives, so that increasing efficiency of administration and control
does not signal a move toward moral progress. This instrumental rationality of
efficient ends cannot provide the criteria for choosing between different values or
8
There are of course a variety of interpretations of Weber’s work. In this Chapter I do not attempt
to deal with the debates in the literature on how Weber should be read, but rather I present what
could be described as ‘the critical theory account’. A detailed consideration of Weber is beyond
the scope of this current thesis. My concern is to present Weber (by way of background) as
Horkheimer and Adorno read him for their work.
19
goals. Thus Weber rejected the ‘naive optimism in which science ... has been
celebrated as the way to happiness.’ (Smart, 1983)
The increase in societal rationalisation leads, through the dominance of
instrumental rationality and bureaucratic modes of administration, to an
undermining of the possibilities for autonomous individuality idealised by
Enlightenment thinking. Weber saw rationalisation as producing a paradox that
has become a central problem in critical social theory: that the rationalisation
process implies simultaneously both emancipation and reification or domination.
Wellmer (1985 p.41) argues that this paradox results from the conflation of
the descriptive-analytic features of Weber’s characterisation of modernity with a
particular Enlightenment derived normative connotation. At the analytic level,
rationalisation refers to an ‘internal systemic logic’ that tends towards increasing
formalisation and bureaucratisation of knowledge and social action, leading to the
conclusion that the modern individual must inevitably be bound by an ‘iron cage’
of instrumental reason and bureaucratic domination. (Smart, 1983 p.125)
However, Weber’s view of rationalisation is unable to escape from the normative
implications of a ‘more emphatic and comprehensive idea of reason’ arising from
the European intellectual tradition, in which ‘being rational signifies a basic
condition of human beings qua human beings.’ (Wellmer, 1985 p.41-2) Weber is
unable to disengage his descriptive sociology from this broader normative
assumption precisely because the rationalisation process is also a process of
enlightenment. The achievements of modern science and law, bound as they are to
the disenchantment of the world, represent the necessary conditions for modern
individual autonomy in the Western intellectual tradition. Disenchantment for
Weber represents the move from traditional authority, epitomised by religious
thinking, to a modern rational worldview, characterised by the differentiation of
knowledge into the domains of empirical fact and non-empirical value
judgements. Disenchantment then is the process of overcoming the illusion of
traditional societies that there can be any transcendental source of meaning and
validity in the natural or supernatural world, that is, outside of the ‘sphere of
symbolically mediated human praxis.’ (Wellmer, 1985 p.42) Not only is
disenchantment a necessary functional precondition for the development of
modern societies, in terms of facilitating instrumental rationality (in legal,
scientific and administrative action), it also is central to the emergence of the
modern idea of rationality (ie as reason in the comprehensive sense). This
broader, normative notion of rationality is, for Weber as it is for critical theorists
such as Habermas, a fundamental cognitive achievement that more than anything
else defines the modern consciousness, inasmuch as it signifies the emergence of
‘man’ as the sole source of intersubjective meaning and validity. (Wellmer, 1985
p.42-3)
Two key concepts raised by Weber’s theory of societal rationalisation, and
taken up later by later critical social theorists, should be noted at this point. The
20
first is the notion of differentiation of value spheres, which is central to
Habermas’ work. This notion plays a central part in Habermas’ defence of the
inherent emancipatory potential of reason against what he sees as the theoretical
confusion of the earlier Frankfurt School theorists, especially Horkheimer and
Adorno, and ‘conservatives’ such as Nietzsche and Foucault. Habermas’ defence
of reason proceeds via an elaboration of the theory of the differentiation of value
spheres and the proper relationship between different modes of rationality, and
aims to overcome what he sees as the unnecessarily ‘pessimistic’ attitude towards
modernity and rationalisation adopted by Weber and the early Frankfurt School.
Horkheimer and Adorno saw the differentiation accompanying rationalisation as
responsible for the rupture in modern Western thought between subjectivity and
nature. Their notion of the ‘dialectic of enlightenment’ in which the progress of
enlightenment and instrumental rationality undermines reason in the
comprehensive, emancipatory sense thus replays Weber’s paradoxical attitude
towards rationalisation.
The second important idea is that of disenchantment. Habermas’ approach to
critical theory is particularly reliant on the concept of enlightenment as a process
of disenchantment, as the cognitive overcoming of illusion and metaphysics. This
is crucial to his defence of what he characterises as the ‘unfinished’ project of
modernity, in that he values science and formal legal-political institutions as
positive achievements of modernity, achievements that are founded on the forms
of rationality made possible by the cognitive functions of disenchantment. The
result of this is to render all claims as to the validity of knowledge and moralpractical action susceptible to ‘intersubjective redemption’ through rational
argumentation. Habermas, although critical of the dangers of societal
rationalisation for the possibilities of emancipation, is thus concerned not to
accept the ‘pessimistic’ conclusions of Weber, and Horkheimer and Adorno,
regarding the role of reason as such. This view of the rational-critical attitude as
implicit to modernity plays a central role in Habermas’ formulation of the relation
between nature and humanity (which I will consider further below). It is also
central to his critique of the earlier Frankfurt School theorists’ view of the
inevitable complicity of ‘reason’ in the reifying separation of subjectivity and
nature.
The Frankfurt School: the Dialectic of Enlightenment
Weber’s sociology understood the process of rationalisation as directed
towards the administration and mastery of the social and natural environment, and
saw this as providing the conditions for the emergence of capitalism in Europe.
Unlike Marx, Weber did not believe that the ‘reification’ produced by modern
society would disappear if the ‘irrational’ market relations of capitalism were
replaced by ‘rational’ socialism. Indeed, he saw socialism as likely to lead to an
even greater growth in bureaucratisation and regulation of society. In this sense
21
Weber, rather than Marx, could be said to provide an important intellectual
impetus to the Frankfurt School’s notion of a ‘totally administered society’, but
also, through this, to the concept of ‘industrialism’ which has been influential in
both New Left and Green thinking. 9 By adapting from Weber the notion of a
‘negative dialectic’ of modernity, the Frankfurt School theorists (especially
Horkheimer, Adorno and Marcuse) rejected the Marxist belief in emancipation as
the immanent or logical consequence of the development of contradictions within
the mode of production. Instead critical theorists pointed to the link between the
ascendancy of an instrumental, scientific rationalism that increasingly expressed
itself in a technological manipulation of nature, and the expansion of the social
relations of the capitalist market. (Dallmayr, 1991 p.74-5) Of particular
importance in this regard is the strong link developed by critical theory between
the domination of nature and social domination. Two closely interrelated features
emerge from the work of Horkheimer and Adorno in particular and are important
for my purposes here. First, their further, explicit development of Weber’s
negative dialectic of progress, and second, their focus on the role of rational
thought and science (aimed at the mastery of nature) in producing a radical split
between subjectivity and nature in modern society.
Horkheimer and Adorno recognised in Weber’s idea of formal and
instrumental rationality an accurate depiction of the dominant features of modern
industrialised society. While rejecting the ‘objectivism’ of the Marxist belief in
the immanent and inevitable progress of social development towards a rational
and just society, they nonetheless sought to preserve the possibility that such a
‘liberated’ society could come about. Thus, in the place of a historical continuity
between capitalism and the classless, emancipated society, Horkheimer and
Adorno posed the need for a radical break with ‘the continuum of progress’. As
Wellmer indicates, their critical theory makes two key claims about the process of
societal rationalisation:
First, they claim that the realisation of the demands of reason has become
historically possible, given the technological development of modern
industrial societies - if only individuals would grasp this possibility; and
secondly they claim that the logic of development of modern societies - of
the rationalisation process in Weber’s sense - points in the opposite
direction and tends to lead to the establishment of a closed system of
instrumental reason, of reification and repression. (Wellmer, 1985 p.46)
9
Industrialism is seen by many New Left and Green critics as a particular mode of economictechnological organisation common to both capitalism and state socialism which is understood
as ‘resting upon the ideologies of growth and technological optimism’ and which aimed at the
technological domination of both nature and society. See Eckersley (1992) and Marcuse
(1968).
22
Weber identified the source of the rationalisation process as the rise of
Protestantism and the consequent (unintentional) creation of an ascetic culture
conducive to the development of markets, intellectual inquiry and world mastery
through science.10 Horkheimer and Adorno located the ultimate source of
rationalisation as belonging to the very nature of conceptual thinking itself.
(Alford, 1985b p.16) In their work they explored the increasing separation of
humanity and nature, and related this to the ascendancy of formalised and
instrumentalised reason in which the natural world, through science, came to be
understood in terms of the operation of quantitative, universal laws. Nature came
to be understood as disenchanted pure substance, ‘mere matter’, capable of
manipulation and control in the interests of human self-preservation. Critical
theory’s approach to rationalisation thus rests on a series of closely interconnected
arguments about the nature of rational thought and its relationship to nature.
Horkheimer, in his earlier writings had already rejected the MarxistLukacsian ‘objectivism’ that saw progress as linked to the idea of universal
history. Horkheimer nevertheless maintained a belief in progress as a real
historical possibility, where the concept of progress was understood primarily as
the material improvement of living standards through the development of the
productive capacity of society. Progress therefore was something to be pursued as
a practical task, and he rejected what he saw as Marxism’s attempt to invoke an
‘objective calculus of suffering and improvement’ which sought, through the
notion of ‘absolute progress’, to justify past and present suffering as a historically
necessary or ‘unavoidable cost’ of progress. (Grumley, 1989 p.160) Adorno,
under the influence of Walter Benjamin and Nietzsche, was even more suspicious
of the idea of progress. History was not the bearer of an immanent reality, indeed
the notion of progress served an ideological function of covering up and
reconciling the ‘disasters’ of capitalist development. See (Grumley, 1989 p.169;
Held, 1980 p.208-9)
Progress for Horkheimer and Adorno then, much as for Weber, could be
understood as the unceasing refinement and rational extension of the technical and
economic capacities of modern society, but it did not represent in any necessary
way either progress towards a morally superior state of existence nor the progress
of humanity towards ‘Reason’. (Wellmer, 1991 p.60) This critique of progress
was further developed, as a collaborative effort in their work Dialectic of
Enlightenment, (Adorno and Horkheimer, 1986) into a more radical critique of
instrumental reason. While this work was originally written during the latter part
of World War Two and first published in 1947 in German, it appears not to have
10
Turner argues that Weber saw more ancient cultural roots for Western rationality pre-dating the
rise of industrial capitalism, and claims that in fact ‘Weber appears to be committed to the idea
that rationalisation is a long term teleological and irreversible process in Western culture.’
(Turner, 1987 p.234)
23
had a significant impact until much later. Jay, in his history of the Frankfurt
School, notes that only through wide circulation as a ‘pirated’ edition in Germany
during the 1960s (where it ‘became an underground classic’) and its subsequent
‘official’ republication in 1970 did the book become influential. (Jay, 1973 p.255)
11
The Dialectic of Enlightenment, and Horkheimer’s (1985) The Eclipse of
Reason, reflected the further distancing of critical theory from the tradition of
orthodox Marxism, while at the same time confirming the continuing influence of
Weber and Nietzsche. (Held, 1980; Jay, 1973) Central to the move away from the
Marxist heritage was the abandonment of class struggle as the effective principle
of history, and its substitution by a broader, more all-encompassing conflict
between humanity and nature. The notion of Enlightenment in these works was no
longer understood simply as a cultural expression of the rise of capitalism, but as
the fundamental feature of Western thought and society in general. Tied to this
was the implicit critique of Marx as standing firmly within the Enlightenment
tradition, and the more explicit rejection of Marxism’s central emphasis on labour
as the mode of self-realisation of the human species. This emphasis on humanity
as an economic animal, according to Horkheimer and Adorno, resulted in
Marxism’s ‘reification of nature as a field for human exploitation’ which
continued a process that predated capitalism and appeared likely to persist, even
intensify, beyond capitalism. (Jay, 1973 p.256-8) In this respect, critical theory
echoes Weber’s tendency to see rationalisation as a long-term process inherent in
Western culture, transcending the specific historical development of capitalism.
(Turner, 1987 p.234) Thus the radical critique in Dialectic of Enlightenment is
directed at the Enlightenment tradition and Western thought itself, that is, at the
process of disenchantment described by Weber.
Weber has often been read as expressing resignation towards the rationalising
processes of modernity. (Jay, 1973 p.259; Smart, 1983 p.125) Smart argues that
while Weber identifies domination with the spread of rational discipline necessary
for modern bureaucratic modes of authority, his notion of charismatic authority,
through its capacity to disrupt the routinisation of everyday life, also retains a
metaphysical function. This ‘constitutes the sole locus of a possible, if temporary,
freedom for the individual from processes of social determination in general, and
rationalisation in particular’, even though this too is likely to succumb to
routinisation. (Smart, 1983 p.130) The work of the Frankfurt School displays a
similar ambivalence. As with Weber, it is unwilling, indeed persistently unable, to
break from an emphatic, positive notion of Reason. At the same time, a pessimism
11
The influence of Frankfurt School (especially Eric Fromm and Herbert Marcuse) on New Left
was significant, and via this there was an indirect influence on the left of the Green movement,
particularly in Germany but also in the USA. See Betz (1991) and Jamison and Eyerman
(1994).
24
and lack of clarity about the means of achieving a break with the dominance of
instrumental rationality and ‘identity thinking’ prevail. It is this tension that
critics, such as Habermas, see as forming the basis of a fundamental aporia in the
notion of dialectic of enlightenment. However, before considering these
criticisms, it is necessary to consider in more detail the Frankfurt School’s
critique of instrumental reason and the relationship of this to the perceived split
between the modern subject and nature.
The critique of instrumental reason
Horkheimer and Adorno saw the radical separation between subjectivity and
nature as the hallmark of modern society. This separation Horkheimer identified
with the rise of scientific thinking, and related to the growth of pervasive forms of
political domination. The Renaissance, through science, introduced a new view of
the natural world as an object to be manipulated and mastered for human
purposes. This new, objectifying attitude to nature was paralleled by the notion,
most clearly manifested by Machiavelli, that human beings too were objects of
domination and control.12 According to Horkheimer, Hobbes and later
Enlightenment theorists further carried this objectification of nature into the
objectification of subjectivity in political theory. (Jay, 1973 p.257)13 Thus,
Horkheimer made two claims, first that the separation of ‘man’ from nature is
undialectical, a artificial dichotomy, and second that having ‘split’ subject from
object, Enlightenment mechanistic thinking then further reduced the subject to an
object of instrumental calculation.
Against this separation, Horkheimer argued following Lukacs, that nature is
in fact a social category, that is, something conditioned by social practices. Hence
not only is nature dependent on human activity in that it is transformed by social
practices, but also in the way human concepts of what nature is are themselves
subject to change, and are therefore dependent on particular symbolic mediations
and cultural significances. (Grumley, 1989 p.156; Jay, 1973 p.257) However,
Horkheimer’s use of the concept of nature retained a recognition (as did Marx’s
1848 Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts (Marx, 1974 p.93-216)) of the
biological limits on human activity. Thus nature is not only socially constituted
but also provides the ‘permanent arena and irreducible pre-condition of human
activity.’ In other words, nature as a prediscursive thing-in-itself presents itself
‘both as potentiality and limit on the social meanings historically ascribed to it.’
12
Foucault suggests that this move to a concern with the disposition of things was not so much
attributable to Machiavelli as to his ‘police science’ critics. See (Foucault, 1991c). This is
discussed further in Chapter 5 of the current thesis.
13
As discussed in Chapter 8, Bruno Latour credits Hobbes, along with Boyle, as being
instrumental in the formulation and articulation of ‘the modern constitution’ which divides
nature from society.
25
(Grumley, 1989 p.156) In holding to this notion of a prediscursive nature
Horkheimer illustrated the complexity of this approach, for he insisted on the
dialectical interconnectedness of humans and nature while at the same time
rejecting an identity between these (ie between object and subject, nondiscursive
thing and discursive concept). This, of course, presents difficulties for any
explanation of how the alienation of humans from nature is to be overcome, for
central to the critical theory of Horkheimer and Adorno (and Marcuse) is the idea
of reconciliation with nature.
Adorno also attempted to utilise a notion of historicised nature, particularly in
building on the Lukacsian idea of a socially constructed ‘second nature’.14 Adorno
regarded both the concepts of nature and history as cognitive tools to be used in
the critique of the present, that is, he insisted on emphasising the dialectical
interrelationship and mutual determining of each as a means of destabilising any
attempt to assign either concept an ontological primacy. The task for Adorno was
thus as much to attack the myth of a ‘constant nature’, as it is to overcome the
myth of ‘progress’. (Buck-Morss, 1977 p.49) Not only are nature and history
mutually determining, but each element of this dialectical doublet also express a
dual character. On the one hand nature refers to embodied history, ‘the material
products of men’s labour as well as their own corporeal bodies’, while on the
other hand nature is ‘pre-given being’ standing outside of history, reason and
human mastery. (Buck-Morss, 1977 p.54) This division is reflected in Adorno’s
use of the idea of ‘first’ and ‘second nature’. First nature corresponds with the
sensuous, biological world, including the human body and those ‘human instincts
and passions repressed and displaced by civilisation’. (Benhabib, 1986 p.166)
Second nature refers to the reification of the historically produced social world in
which socially constituted conventions and practices are perceived as ‘natural’,
ahistorical givens. The consequence of this is that the status quo is fetishised. Just
as first nature is mythified in traditional societies, in modernity second nature
becomes myth. (Buck-Morss, 1977 p.55-6; Held, 1980 p.167-9) Adorno’s method
of critique was therefore to use ‘nature’ and ‘history’ as
cognitive concepts which demythify reality by means of reciprocal
critique. In other words, the concept of ‘nature’ exposes the non-identity
between the concept of historical progress and actual historical reality by
drawing attention to the material nature violated in the name of historical
‘progress’. Similarly, the concept of ‘history’ unmasks the ideology
which views existing social arrangements as ‘natural’, essential or true by
invoking their historical production. (Grumley, 1989 p.166)
14
Susan Buck-Morss points out that the concept of ‘second nature’ comes from Hegel, although
she also notes that Horkheimer claims the term dates from Democritus. See Buck-Morss (1977)
p.55 & footnote 94 p.228)
26
The denial of the interdependence of the subject and nature is traced in
Dialectic of Enlightenment to the spread of instrumental reason. The notion of
instrumental reason as used by Horkheimer and Adorno, drew on their earlier
critique of progress and a reinterpretation of Weber’s concept of rationalisation in
which the processes of societal and cultural rationalisation (which Weber sought
to differentiate) are merged into one.15 (Benhabib, 1986 p.162-3; Grumley, 1989
p.170) In Horkheimer and Adorno’s formulation, social rationalisation involved
the extension of the apparatus of administrative and political domination into all
areas of social life through the bureaucratisation of institutions such as the
economy, the military, education and the ‘culture industry’. Such rationalisation is
effected through the application of the procedures and techniques developed by
science and technology that derive their efficiency from the capacity to fragment
and formalise their objects in ways that enhance the controllability for specific
purposes. Thus the very processes of rationalisation (societal and cultural) that
Enlightenment saw as emancipatory, for Horkheimer and Adorno expressed a
relentless logic of domination, not only in shaping institutional practices, but also
in distorting the idea of Reason itself. The notion of a comprehensive, substantive
Reason is usurped by a narrow, bureaucratic-technical instrumental rationality.
Thus, the dialectic of Enlightenment is between these two forms of reason,
substantive or universal Reason, and reason as the rational manipulation of the
particular.
At the same time, the dialectic also concerns the way in which Enlightenment
itself reverts to myth. (Held, 1980 p.150-1) Horkheimer and Adorno saw myth
and Enlightenment as grounded in the same basic human need: self-preservation,
and it is this that connects nature and history. Science is a tool employed by the
human species for its self-preservation, for through the application of scientific
reason humans seek to control nature. This is also the function of myth. While
science objectifies nature and distances itself from its object, myth functions by
the ‘projection of the subjective onto nature’; both nevertheless seek to control
and understand nature. (Held, 1980 p.155)16 Therefore, while myth and
enlightenment are different, there is also a functional continuity between them.
15
For Weber, societal rationalisation referred both to institutional differentiation between the
economic and political spheres, and to the increasing formalisation of rationality within
economic, political and legal institutions. Cultural rationalisation referred to the
‘systematisation of worldviews’ and the consequent decline in the power of myth. See
Benhabib, (1986) p.379-80, footnote 19.
16
This is one of the problems with certain green perspectives, which seek the ‘re-subjectify’
nature, for example Mathews (1991) and Naess (1986). For critical discussion of this see
Bennett (1987); Luke (1988); Rutherford (1997c).
27
Thus Horkheimer and Adorno claimed that the unknown in nature (including
environmental uncertainty)17, is feared as a threat to self-preservation:
Man imagines himself free from fear when there is no longer anything
unknown. This determines the course of demthyologising ...
Enlightenment is mythic fear turned radical ... Nothing at all may remain
outside, because the mere idea of outsideness is the very source of fear.
(Adorno and Horkheimer, 1986)
At its very heart enlightenment, through science, thus aims at emancipation of
the human subject from the risks and uncertainty of its natural environment, but it
is a freedom sought through the domination of nature. It must be remembered
however that nature is not totally separate from humanity; history and nature exist
in a dialectical relation to each other. The control and mastery of ‘first nature’ by
the subject simultaneously constitutes ‘second nature’. The mastery of nature
therefore also involves processes that suppress and distort the spontaneous,
prediscursive instinctive drives of human beings. Horkheimer and Adorno see this
drive for self-preservation and the objectification of external nature as at the same
time a process of suppression of the self’s own inner nature. Indeed, the modern
unitary subject, the Cartesian cogito, is the product of this bifurcation of self and
nature. It is the price paid for the triumph of reason, but reason as ‘mythic fear
turned radical’, which becomes a systematising, totalising ‘instrumental
rationality’ that dominates not only external (first) nature, but also social relations
(second nature) and the inner, instinctive nature of the self. (Held, 1980 p.152-6;
Wellmer, 1991 p.59-61)
Following Nietzsche18, and conflating Weber’s differentiation of institutional
and cultural rationalisation, Frankfurt School critical theory understands the
totalising, systematising force of reason as inherent in the character of conceptual
thinking and language. Thus, in Wellmer’s words, in Dialectic of Enlightenment
At the heart of discursive thought we thus discovered an element of
violence, a subjugation of reality, a defence mechanism, a procedure for
excluding and controlling, a prearrangement of phenomena for the
purpose of controlling and manipulating them, and an implicit system of
delusion. This objectifying, systematising and instrumentalising reason
17
This is the problem of risk – see Chapter 4 for a discussion of the way this dealt with as a
central theme in the work of Beck. See Beck (1992b).
18
Here I am referring to Nietzsche’s perspectivism, which at the considerable risk of
oversimplification, can said to ‘assert four distinguishable claims: (1) no accurate
representation of the world as it is in itself is possible; (2) there is nothing to which our theories
stand in the required correspondence relation to enable us to say that they are true or false; (3)
no method of understanding our world – sciences, logic, or moral theory – enjoys a privileged
status; (4) human needs always help to ‘constitute’ the world for us.’ (Magnus and Higgins,
1996 p.4)
28
has found its classical expression in the natural sciences; but as Foucault
has shown, the human sciences can also be viewed in the same
categories.19 (Wellmer, 1991 p.60)
Horkheimer and Adorno explicitly acknowledged the influence of Nietzsche
in their formulation of the dialectic of enlightenment. Their discussion of the way
in which rational thought serves a basic need to control nature reflects Nietzsche’s
view that the striving to master nature is a universal feature of reason, that is,
knowledge is fundamentally a tool of power. Nietzsche makes a clear connection
between self-preservation and knowledge as the object and purpose of the ‘will to
power’. The drive for self-preservation is thus the ‘motive’ behind the
development of knowledge. According to Nietzsche, ‘the desire for knowledge
depends upon the measure to which the will to power grows in a species: a species
grasps a certain amount of reality in order to become master of it, in order to press
it into service’ in the interest of self-preservation. (Held, 1980 p.156-7) Our desire
to know the world, not just as formalised scientific knowledge, but also in
everyday judgements about how the world is or what is ‘true’, involves a process
of abstraction and simplification that according to Nietzsche, is ‘directed not at
knowledge but at taking possession of things’. (Gemes, 1992 p.54) Nietzsche thus
not only rejected the notion of unconditional truth, he also links particular ideas of
what is ‘true’ to the pragmatic or instrumental exercise of power in the interests of
self-preservation. Horkheimer and Adorno’s characterisation of conceptual or
‘identity’ thought as that which imposes homogeneity and suppresses otherness is
therefore clearly dependent on Nietzsche.20
Unlike Nietzsche’s uncompromising critique of reason, or indeed Weber’s
ultimately fatalistic view of rationalisation, Horkheimer and Adorno attempt to
retain the possibilities of both a reconciliation with nature and a comprehensive
notion of emancipatory Reason. The critique of reason in Dialectic of
Enlightenment is still, as Buck-Morss notes, a critique ‘for the sake of the
Enlightenment and the rationality which it promised.’ Horkheimer and Adorno’s
work should thus be read as a ‘critical negation’ of the rationalist view of
historical progress which preserves as its aim the realisation of human
emancipation. (Buck-Morss, 1977 p.61) At its core, Horkheimer and Adorno’s
critique is a critique of instrumental reason precisely for the sake of reestablishing this form of ‘subjective reason’ as a subordinate component of a
comprehensive, ‘objective reason’. The pessimism of Dialectic of Enlightenment
to a large degree reflected Horkheimer and Adorno’s assessment of the realities of
the modern totally administered society and the recent experiences of fascism and
Stalinism. It also served, however, as a ‘negative construct’ intended to unmask
19
See Bennett (1987) for a discussion of this issue in terms of Foucault's work.
20
Heidegger is also an important figure in this mode of critique. See Benhabib (1984) p.106-11.
29
the totalitarian currents of instrumental reason and Enlightenment thinking that
threatened to destroy Reason and enlightenment in the broader, emancipatory
sense. (See Grumley, 1989 p.175-7; Held, 1980 p.156-7; Leiss, 1975 p.175-7;
Wellmer, 1991 p.60-63)
Central to this critique of instrumental reason was the notion of reconciliation
between the subject and nature, between inner and outer nature. Reconciliation is
seen as essential for emancipation because the history of the mastery of nature is
at the same time the history of the domination of humanity. Such domination will
continue unless humanity develops a critical understanding of the paradoxical
character of human reason, that is, of the ‘naturalness’ of the drive for selfpreservation and domination which at the same time is a trend that alienates
humanity from nature. The Dialectic of Enlightenment links the growth of
scientific knowledge and social progress with a retreat from the ‘unreflective
naturalism’ characteristic of modern disenchantment.21 However, Horkheimer and
Adorno do not believe that the process can be reversed through any sort of
simplistic ‘return to nature’ or through the invention of new nature mythologies
which equate Reason with nature. To do so would be to ignore the historical
realities of Enlightenment and technological progress that have brought the
modern subject into existence.22 (Dallmayr, 1991 p.76-7; Jay, 1973 p.270-2)
Moreover, the total identification of nature and subject, understood as complete
reconciliation would be a regression to yet another form of ‘identity thinking’ that
reduced subject to object, rather than a dialectical mediation of the interrelated
though non-identical. Reconciliation must be based not on assimilation of the
differences between humanity and the rest of nature, but through the ‘reflective
opposition between them.’23(Jay, 1973 p.267)
Consistent with the view of nature as a social category, reconciliation,
particularly as developed by Adorno’s appropriation of Benjamin’s idea of
‘mimesis’, is not intended to imply the possibility of unmediated access to nature.
21
‘Unreflective naturalism’ is also characteristic of much of contemporary environmental
thinking. See Bennett (1987).
22
Wellmer makes the point that Horkheimer and Adorno saw the decline of individuality in late
industrial society as a ‘regressive development’ despite the fact that they also saw the modern
cogito or unified self ‘not in terms of the autonomous subject which was destroyed by Freud,
but - rather more in the manner of Foucault - as the correlate or product of the 'discourse of
modernity', namely as a disciplined and disciplining form of organisation of humans as social
beings. It is violence that stands at the origin of this unified self, and not an act of autonomous
self-positing.’ Wellmer explains this apparent contradiction by suggesting that Horkheimer and
Adorno saw the modern ‘constellation of norms of rationality’ as a kind of ‘nodal point - like
bourgeois society for Marx - through which it is necessary to pass, but which is destined to be
sublated in a self-transcendence of reason.’ (Wellmer, 1991 p.62-3)
23
See Luke, (1988) and Rutherford (1993) for critiques of the deep ecology attempt at such an
assimilation of the differences between humanity and nature.
30
Rather it recognises that history and culture necessarily mediate the relationship
of humans to nature, and that any so-called ‘direct’ access to nature would in fact
be a fetishisation of nature. (Alford, 1985b p.158) Nevertheless, the notion of
mimetic reconciliation reflects the problem of characterising conceptual thinking
as directed at control and self-preservation. If the systematising, disciplining
character of language and rational thought always reifies and does violence to
nature and the subject, then it becomes improbable that any form of discursive
reason would be capable of breaking this circle. Indeed, Horkheimer and Adorno,
faced with the conclusion that all forms of linguistic and mathematical-scientific
expression are dominated by instrumental rationality, sought refuge for
emancipatory thought in a prediscursive, aesthetic ideal. In particular, the problem
is that formal rationality (‘identity thought’) becomes ‘philosophical imperialism’
in which truth is defined by the triumph of the universal and abstract over the
particular and the real, resulting in Enlightenment transforming itself into myth.
The only way to resist this is through the ‘radical self-reflection of thought’ to
make thought aware of its ‘complicity with power’ and to stimulate the
‘recollection of nature in the rational subject’. (Dallmayr, 1991 p.81)
Benhabib describes Adorno’s notion of mimetic reconciliation as the ability
of the subject to ‘forget oneself’ in the face of otherness, through ‘aesthetic
experience’ of the ‘naturally beautiful’. This idea of the ‘naturally beautiful’, as
an allegory for reconciliation in Adorno’s work does not represent an essentialist
category but the antithesis of modern society inasmuch as that society appears in a
fixed instrumental relation to nature. Mimesis is therefore the suggestion of the
possibility of a non-static mediation between nature and humans, rather than the
final realisation of some mystical condition beyond history. Benhabib sums this
up succinctly:
The utopia of a non-sacrificial non-identity of the subject is intimated in
that non-compulsory relation to otherness which forces the subject to
forget him- or her-self and to catch a glimpse of the moment of
reconciliation. What distinguishes this appeal to the aesthetic, it must be
emphasised, from a romantic theory of flight into nature is precisely the
ambivalence of the concept of nature. Nature, for Adorno, signifies not a
given entity, state, or medium, but ‘otherness’, the ‘otherness’ of society,
civilisation, and reason. The semantic content of this otherness changes
historically, and must be recreated again and again. (Benhabib, 1986
p.211-2)
Despite this, the characterisation by the Frankfurt School of all discursive
thought as linked to instrumental reason is seen by many critics, most notably
Habermas, as leading to serious theoretical problems for critical theory. In
particular these critics argue that such a move undermines the notion an
emancipatory moment to reason and deprives the project of rational critique of a
31
valid foundation. (See Habermas, 1982a p.13-30; Ingram, 1987 p.67-74 and
p.213-23; Wellmer, 1985 p.46-51)
Habermas’ critique of the Dialectic of Enlightenment
Habermas’ intellectual project can be understood as a response to the
pessimism of Dialectic of Enlightenment and as an attempt to redeem the positive
emancipatory potential of the Enlightenment tradition that, on his account,
remains as an unrealised practical task of the ‘project of modernity’. (Bernstein,
1985 p.31) Habermas’ philosophical criticism of Horkheimer and Adorno takes
on greater significance because the theoretical impasses he claims to find in
Dialectic of Enlightenment he also sees as repeated in the post-structuralist
revival of Nietzsche, especially in the works of Foucault, Deleuze, Derrida and
Lyotard. (Habermas, 1982a p.13) He sees what he regards as a clear continuity of
error in the works of Nietzsche, Adorno and Horkheimer and what he describes as
the ‘anti-modernism’ of the post-structuralist conservatism. (Habermas, 1981b
p.13; Ingram, 1987 p.75) This perspective is also reflected in his analysis of the
nature of new social movements. (Habermas, 1981c)
Adorno and Horkheimer had argued, said Habermas, that the separation of the
cultural spheres (science, morality and art), and the loss of reason in religion and
metaphysics had lead to the regression of reason in general into a ‘purposive
rationality at the service of a self-preservation gone wild. In cultural modernity
substantive reason is stripped of its validity claims and is assimilated to sheer
power.’ (Habermas, 1982a p.18) Habermas however rejects this as a one
dimensional, ‘flattened out’ view of modernity and reason, arguing instead that
there remains within each of the value spheres elements of rationality which are
not subsumed totally within purposive rationality. He cites such elements as those
within the sciences that transcend the production of instrumental knowledge; the
universalistic bases of law and morality embodied in the modern democratic and
constitutional state; and the emancipatory power of aesthetic experience.
(Habermas, 1982a p.18) Habermas differentiates rationality and action into
various spheres or types, placing particular importance on the distinction between
the communicative and instrumental forms. As a result of this differentiation of
reason, he claims that the universalistic claims of ‘bourgeois ideals’ in the realms
of morality and law represent, despite the distortions of modern capitalist society,
‘an irreversible collective learning process’. This is categorically distinguishable
from both the technical-developmental logic of the sciences and technology, and
from the formal and bureaucratic rationalisation of social institutions. (Habermas,
1982a p.18) Thus contrary to Adorno and Horkheimer, Habermas maintains a
strong belief in the potential for a democratic and emancipatory rational
organisation of society, a potential that is contained in his category of
communicative rationality, which for him is a fundamental feature of the modern
‘species-being’ of humanity.
32
Adorno and Horkheimer claimed that myth and enlightenment inevitably
reverted into each other, that ‘power and knowledge are synonymous’ (Adorno
and Horkheimer, 1986; Ingram, 1987 p.65) Habermas however argues that
‘demythologisation’ is necessary to distinguish between culture and nature,
between the objects of human manipulation and acting and speaking agents.
Enlightenment results in the ‘desocialisation of nature and ... the denaturalisation
of the social’ leading to a decentred worldview. (Habermas, 1982a p.19)
According to Habermas this decentred understanding makes possible the critique
of ideology, a form of critique which seeks to ‘demonstrate that the validity of a
theory ... has not freed itself sufficiently from the context of its genesis ... (and
that) hidden behind ... this theory is an inadmissible fusion of power and validity.’
(Habermas, 1982a p.20) Hence, ideology critique carries forward the process of
enlightenment by revealing categorical errors that arise from the conflation of
professed validity claims (that is, veracity or truthfulness) with concealed power
claims. Ideology critique becomes reflexive by carrying out its project on its own
theories. Adorno and Horkheimer however, claims Habermas, carry critique to a
second level of reflexivity in which the very method of ideology critique itself is
brought into question through the totalised critique of all thought as expressive of
power claims. With this Adorno and Horkheimer had abandoned hope in the
Marxist critique of ideology and the possibility of critical social science. Their
critique becomes a totalised attack on Reason as the very basis of critical analysis.
For Habermas, in the Dialectic of Enlightenment,
purposive-rationality, which had become total, eliminates the difference
between that which claims validity and that which only serves the
interests of self-preservation. By doing so instrumental reason breaks
down the barrier between truth and power and thereby annihilates the
fundamental differentiation which the modern decentred understanding of
the world thought it had gained definitively by overcoming myth. Reason,
once instrumentalised, has become assimilated to power and has thereby
given up its critical power. (Habermas, 1982a)
These criticisms of Adorno and Horkheimer are precisely those that
Habermas directs against Foucault’s theory of power/knowledge. It should be
noted here that in concentrating attention on those elements in Dialectic of
Enlightenment that draw on Nietzsche, Habermas brings clearly into focus the key
theoretical differences between himself and Foucault. I shall discuss the
philosophical debate between Habermas and Foucault on power in more detail in
Chapter 5.
Habermas identifies two fundamental areas in which Adorno and Horkheimer
agree with Nietzsche. First, each regarded thought as the mechanism through
which external nature is objectified and constituted as a resource for
manipulation. Thought is also for both associated with the repressive
internalisation of instincts and ‘natural drives’, that is, with the creation of ‘inner
33
nature’ or subjectivity. These modes of domination of internal and external nature
result in the ‘institutional domination of men over men’. (Habermas, 1982a p.24)
Second, Adorno and Horkheimer’s critique of instrumental reason parallels
Nietzsche’s critique of morality and scientific knowledge, in that for each behind
the ideals of universal morality, objectivity and truth, there lies the concealed
drive for self-preservation and domination, that is, the will to power. A
consequence of this, argues Habermas, is that for Nietzsche the will to power
destroys the possibility of any ‘claim to intersubjective validity’, as all judgement
is in the last resort based on aesthetic preference or ‘the judgement of taste’. For
Habermas this also destroys the possibility of critique, for without the foundations
of objectivity and universality attributed by modernist philosophy to truth and
validity claims, critique loses its meaning and reduces to no more than
‘difference’. (Habermas, 1982a p.25-6)
In order for Nietzsche to show why it is wrong to accept the domination of
life by science and morality, says Habermas, he must have resort to some criterion
on which to base such a value judgement. Habermas argues that Nietzsche’s
theory of power seeks to dissolve this problem by denying that value judgements
are validity claims but ‘mere expressions of claims to power’. (Habermas, 1982a
p.27) Horkheimer and Adorno find themselves confronted with this same problem
in that if they wish to retain their commitment to the practice of critique as an
‘ultimate unmasking’, they must also retain ‘at least one standard for their
explanation of the corruption of all reasonable standards.’ (Habermas, 1982a
p.28) It is Adorno and Horkheimer’s inability to do this that deprives their critique
of direction, according to Habermas. In fact, says Habermas, they simply abandon
the desire to overcome this aporia, not only leaving the contradiction unresolved,
but intensifying it. As a consequence Adorno and Horkheimer were unable
theoretically to avoid the negativity and pessimism of Dialectic of Enlightenment.
Habermas’ method of avoiding this ‘abyss’ is to execute an abstract categorical
differentiation within reason and thought, and by asserting the negative powers of
reason are the result of an inappropriate dominance of instrumental or technical
rationality over communicative rationality.
Nietzsche’s theory of power, argues Habermas, is thus confronted with the
problem that ‘critique surrenders the world ... to the irreconcilable struggle
between powers.’ (Habermas, 1982a p.28) This, says Habermas, is also the path
adopted by the post-structuralists such a Deleuze and Foucault. Although
Foucault’s concept of power allows for differentiation between specific discursive
formations, it still however denies any basis for universal or transcontextual
judgement of validity claims. It also fails, according to Habermas, to offer a
solution to the aporia of a critique that denies the validity of its own premises.
(Habermas, 1982a p.29)
34
Conclusion
The themes outlined in this chapter provide the background against which the
arguments of subsequent chapters will be developed. The notion of a negative
dialectic of progress is a concern that, in one form or another, influences the work
of the major theorists examined in this thesis. The main elements of this negative
dialectic include, first, the assertion that the key to the development of modern
society, and consequently to development of the modern subject, is to be found in
the processes of societal rationalisation. Second, these processes of
rationalisation, while they have made possible substantial social and economic
progress (through legal-political institutions and the power of science), have also
come to be seen as having a darker side in which reason and knowledge have
increasingly become forces of domination, discipline and control.
The way in which these themes are dealt with by social theory defines in a
significant sense what Habermas has called the ‘philosophical discourse on
modernity’. The themes covered in this chapter are essential to understanding
much of the social theoretical debate, over the last 30 years, and in particular the
philosophical discourse on power and subjectivity. Such a background is therefore
an indispensable starting point for a consideration of these issues in general and in
particular the disputes between critical theorists such as Habermas and theorists
such as Foucault.
Against this background, the chapters that follow consider the relevance of
these general social theoretical debates to the analysis of contemporary discourse
about ecological or environmental crisis. In this context, the current chapter has
pointed to what I described in Chapter 1 as the problem of nature in social theory.
It is against the background of the theoretical debates outlined in this chapter that
I now turn in the next two chapters to a detailed consideration of Habermas’
critical social theory, and the recent work of Ulrich Beck and Klaus Eder.
Following this I examine the work of Foucault and consider how it may be used to
understand ecological problems.
35
Chapter 3
The problem of nature in Habermas
Introduction
In the work of Horkheimer and Adorno the relationship between humanity
and nature is considered central to social theory, and it is this particular focus that
marks the later work of the Frankfurt School. The problem of the dialectical
relationship between ‘inner’ and ‘outer’ nature, is as we have seen in the previous
chapter, cast in a way that problematises the belief that technological and
scientific progress is necessary to the realisation of the goals of human
emancipation and moral progress. In calling into question this assumption,
Horkheimer and Adorno’s work anticipates themes common to the widespread
concern with environmental problems and ecological crisis that emerged in the
post-World War Two period in the industrialised Western societies.24 The
Frankfurt School and the broader discourse on the environment25 therefore have in
common a focus on what I described in the introduction to this thesis as the
problem of nature.
This and the next chapter consider the problem of nature as dealt with by
some contemporary critical theorists. I have not attempted a comprehensive
survey of the vast literature on social theory. Rather I present an examination of
selected theoretical approaches that can be considered as either central to the
24
This is not to claim that Horkheimer and Adorno's work directly inspired concern for such
ecological problems or the development of Green political theory. Eckersley comments that
while Frankfurt School Critical Theory takes up themes of fundamental significance to Green
theory, such as the critique of industrialism, technology and bureaucratic state administration, it
nonetheless failed to have as strong an impact on Green thought as such common concerns may
lead us to expect. Eckersley (1992) attributes this lack of greater influence by the Frankfurt
School largely to the direction imposed by Habermas’ work on the development of Critical
Theory since the 1960s (see p.97-99). It should however be noted that other Frankfurt School
theorists, especially Marcuse, were influential on the New Left in the 1960-70s. There is little
doubt that through this connection their ideas did have an impact on Green political theory,
particularly its anti-bureaucratic tendencies. Eckersley, (1992) p.10-11, mentions this. Betz
(1991) gives a detailed account of the influence of the New Left on the development of the
Green movement in Germany. See especially Chapters 1-3 of that work.
25
Here I am referring to the widespread growth of concern for the environment beginning in the
1960s and reflected in such works as Carson (1962); Commoner (1971); Ehlrich (1968); Hardin
(1968); Meadows et al. (1972)
36
framing of the debate (Habermas) or as significant recent attempts to develop a
more satisfactory social theoretical framework for analysis of ecological problems
(Eder, Beck).26 This present chapter further considers the way in which Habermas
deals with the problem of nature as it arises from Horkheimer and Adorno’s
treatment of the ‘dialectic of enlightenment’. In doing so I consider some of the
key elements of Habermas’ development of critical theory and some criticisms of
this. In particular I examine his notions of ‘system’ and ‘life-world’, and his
insistence that an objectifying and instrumental attitude to nature is an
unavoidable cost that must be borne if we are to preserve and extend what he
regards as the ‘cognitive gains’ of the ‘unfinished project of modernity’.
(Habermas, 1982b p.238-250) The following chapter goes on to consider some
recent theoretical works that give ecological problems a greater sociological
significance in advanced industrial society than does Habermas’ consideration of
these as conflicts.
The problem of nature in Habermas
As outlined in Chapter 2, Horkheimer and Adorno’s analysis in the end is
largely pessimistic about overcoming the historical impasse produced by
modernisation. In part this reflects a continued acceptance that a relatively high
level of material production, and therefore technological and economic progress,
as a necessary precondition for a free and humane society. However, in
Horkheimer and Adorno’s view, social domination is an inevitable consequence
of the domination of nature by science and technology. The only possible solution
to this lay in reconciliation with nature. The difficulty of this approach 27 is that
the domination of external nature required the control of inner nature, which is
achieved in the human subject only through imitating the rigidity and
despiritualisation of disenchanted nature within the self. According to this view,
the domination of external nature is therefore achieved only by distorting and
undermining the instinctual psychological structures that would provide the
subjective conditions for the realisation of an emancipated society. (Alford, 1985b
p.11; Whitebook, 1979 p.41) Thus after Dialectic of Enlightenment critical theory
faced the dilemma of explaining how reconciliation with nature could occur while
at the same time avoiding a significant undermining the productive capacity of
modern industrialised society.28 This latter question is a key focus in the
26
I have, for example, made only passing references to the work of Marcuse.
27
Apart from how such reconciliation was itself socially possible (as distinct from a private
intuitive or expressive reconciliation).
28
Marcuse, despite being critical of advanced science and technology, regarded them as essential
to the liberation of the instinctual nature of human beings. Advanced technology, and
particularly automation, offered the possibility of the freeing humanity from engaging in
necessary labour - and thus being able to enter into an instinctive, expressive reconciliation
37
environmental debate between ‘romantic’ or deep ecologists and the utilitarianism
implied by the notions of ecological modernisation and ‘sustainable
development’.29
Habermas declines to accept the notion of reconciliation with nature,
regarding it as regression into metaphysics. (Habermas, 1982a) Instead he
challenges the central argument of Dialectic of Enlightenment as expressing a
narrow ‘monistic’ notion of Reason as domination. While admitting the close
interrelationship between the domination of internal and external nature,
Habermas argues that these do not operate according to a single logic. He adopts a
differentiated concept of reason in which instrumental rationality as the logic of
domination of external nature necessarily ‘aims at reification’, while in the logic
of communicative rationality, which governs inner nature, reification is not the
aim but only a ‘possible pathological outcome’. For Habermas the reification of
external nature is necessary for the formulation of the objective technical rules
that allow science and technology to manipulate the natural world. By contrast, in
the development of inner or subjective nature, it is not a question of the creation
of formal rules of technical control, but rather one of the internalisation of
intersubjective norms. In other words, normative processes are aimed not at
reification but at ‘autonomy, individuation and socialisation’, and as such they
follow the logic of communicative rationality. (Whitebook, 1979 p.43)
By virtue of this differentiation of value spheres and their corresponding
modes of rationality, 30 Habermas unlike Horkheimer and Adorno is able to
maintain that the rationalisation of society is not inimical to moral progress and
emancipation. On the contrary, the basis for the development of a society
grounded in a free and democratic consensus is embodied in his notion of the
‘ideal speech situation’.31 The rational evolution of each aspect of the human self-
with nature. For a discussion of Marcuse's attitude to science, see Alford (1985b) especially
Chapter 4.
29
This distinction (which has been drawn by Klaus Eder among others) is discussed in Chapter 3
of the current thesis. See also Rutherford (1999a).
30
Parsons’ comments that ‘following Weber - and ultimately Kant - Habermas characterises
modernity as the differentiation of three spheres of 'value': science, morality and art. These
three spheres allow for the production of different forms of knowledge: scientific-technical,
moral-practical, and aesthetic-practical.’ (p.218) For a discussion of Habermas’ reliance on
Kant and Marx in his account of the relationship between human knowledge and nature, see
Parsons (1992) p.218-230. See also Bernstein (1985) p.24. For a more sympathetic but
nevertheless critical review of Habermas’ use of Kantian notions in this context. See McCarthy
(1978) p.110-125.
31
As McCarthy points out, for Habermas ‘the goal of critical theory – a form of life free from
unnecessary domination in all its forms – is inherent in the notion of truth’ and as truth,
according to Habermas, is fundamental to communication, truth is therefore ‘anticipated in
every act of communication.’ (McCarthy, 1978 p.7). West explains that for Habermas truth,
freedom and justice ‘are to be understood in terms of consensus theories of theoretical (factual
38
formative process (labour, communication and power), is immanent albeit in a
distorted form, in the legal and political institutions and humanist values of
modernity. Thus, moral progress is possible despite the over-importance of the
technical/instrumental mode of rationality. Rather than terminating in the dialectic
of enlightenment’s conflation of power and reason, modernity needs to be pushed
to completion, that is, social norms must be made fully rational, but in accordance
with the appropriate mode of rationality - moral-practical reason. (Habermas,
1982b p.240) 32
Habermas’ treatment of the problem of nature must be understood within the
context of his concern to rescue a rational basis for universal normative standards
against the ‘totalised critique’ of instrumental reason advanced, following in the
footsteps of Nietzsche and Weber, by Horkheimer and Adorno. (Habermas, 1982a
p.19-23) The rejection of this form of critique is central to his project, which aims
to maintain the critical role of social theory. In the hands of Horkheimer and
Adorno critical theory looses its earlier aspiration of developing a critical social
science directed towards fulfilling an explanatory-diagnostic role in furthering the
task of human emancipation from domination and repression. In the Frankfurt
School’s formulation of the dialectic of enlightenment the emancipatory power of
social science, itself an instance of ‘identity thinking’, is ensnared in the critique
of instrumental reason. It cannot guarantee a solution to problems of
rationalisation or modernity for it is part of the very mode of conceptual thought
responsible for these problems.33
Habermas however seeks to ground his emancipatory critical theory through
the reflexive use of social science. His re-formulation of critical theory is thus
directed towards ‘a non-positivist approach’ to theory in the social sciences, rather
than following Adorno’s negative dialectics, which Habermas characterises as ‘a
renunciation of the social sciences’. (Habermas, 1981a p.10) While positivism
denies the link between knowledge and interests (value), and therefore attempts to
deny any rational warrant to moral-practical thought, Horkheimer and Adorno’s
totalising critique of instrumental reason likewise undermines practical reason by
or scientific) and moral or practical truth (rightness). But a consensus is not valid if it is the
result of inadequate information or external pressure or compulsion. … Discourse is to be
measured against an ‘ideal speech situation’, which is free from relations of power or
domination, and which is undogmatically committed to the consideration of all available
evidence and even alternative conceptual schemes.’ An ideal speech situation is not possible
when ideology or power systematically distorts the rational force of ‘the better argument’. A
key task of critical theory is therefore to expose any such deviation from the ideal speech
situation. (West, 1996 p.75-6) I argue in Chapter 5 that Habermas’ view of the possibility of
power free communication is based on an inadequate conception of power.
32
See also Parsons (1992) p.218-9; Wellmer, (1985) p.50-2.
33
Foucault makes a similar point about the complicity of the human sciences in modern forms of
power. See for example Foucault (1980b) p.273-89.
39
assimilating value judgements to power. (Habermas, 1978 p.303; Habermas,
1982a p.22-3) Habermas’ concern in this respect is to avoid the relativism (or
perspectivalism) which he regards as inherent in Weber and the Frankfurt
School’s presentation of the processes of rationalisation. Instead he develops a
theory of modernity that acknowledges the ‘dialectic of social rationalisation’
(‘the main theme of the dialectic of enlightenment’). He also employs a theory of
communicative rationality (or ‘universal pragmatics’) that ‘possesses the
analytical selectivity’ needed to understand reification as a pathological
phenomena arising from the deformed or partial realisation of the rational
potential of modernity.
Habermas’ theoretical development of critical theory therefore has been
directed toward maintaining what he regards as this emancipatory potential of
modernity. While this, in his view, has required the rejection of Horkheimer and
Adorno’s monistic notion of reason, it has also lead to his reconceptualisation of
the idea of nature in accordance with this perspective. His treatment of nature has
varied as his ideas have developed, and this can broadly be grouped into two
phases, the first corresponding with his earlier formulation of the theory of
cognitive interests, the second with his development of a universal pragmatics. In
the first phase he relates different types of knowledge constitutive interests to the
natural history of the human species, while in the later period he views problems
of nature and ecology as expressions of the conflicts that arise at the interface of
‘system’ and ‘life-world’. I shall consider in turn each phase of his work.
Nature and cognitive interests
Habermas’ view of the relation between nature and society retains the
Frankfurt School’s understanding of nature as at the same time both the product of
human history and the ground for that history. (Habermas, 1978) 34 His theory of
cognitive interests appeals to a fundamental dialectical relationship between the
human subject and nature.35 He postulates a collective interest in utilising the
forces of nature for the purpose of the reproduction and self-preservation of
human society, and in doing so suggests a basic dependence on nature and at the
same time, through knowledge, a separation from it.36 This interest in self-
34
See also McCarthy (1978) p.113; Parsons (1992) p.222-5; Whitebook (1979) p.48.
35
In Habermas (1978) - see Chapter 2 and Appendix - Habermas understands the subject as
simultaneously possessing a human species-being and social-being, along the lines evident in
Marx. See Marx (1974).
36
‘Orientation toward technical control, toward mutual understanding in the conduct of life, and
toward emancipation from seemingly 'natural' constraint establish the specific viewpoints from
which we can apprehend reality ... By becoming aware of the impossibility of getting beyond
these transcendental limits, a part of nature acquires, through us, autonomy in nature. ... the
mind can become aware of its natural basis reflexively.’ (Habermas, 1978 p.311).
40
preservation is embedded in the natural history of the human species and gives
rise to particular ‘knowledge-constitutive interests’. The most significant point
about this claim is that knowledge is not separate from the wants and needs of
human beings, as traditional epistemology would have it, but is based in ‘the
metalogical necessity of interests that we neither prescribe nor represent, but with
which we must instead come to terms.’ (Habermas, 1978 p.312 - original
emphasis) Thus Habermas emphasises that what is taken as factual knowledge (or
‘objective knowledge’) reflects the success or failure of collective actions, lying
behind which is the interest in self-preservation giving rise to the interlocking of
knowledge and interests from the ‘life-world’. His view of knowledge therefore
exhibits the characteristics of philosophical pragmatism.
Following from his differentiation of reason and ‘value spheres’ as an
antidote to the Frankfurt School’s totalising notion of reason, Habermas posits
three types of knowledge-constitutive interests: the technical, the practical and the
emancipatory. (Habermas, 1978 p.308-310) According to this schema the
technical interest is that which governs human relations with nature, where the
interest is an instrumental interest in control and exploitability, of pragmatic
utility in securing the satisfaction of needs and wants brought forth in the natural
history of the human species. This natural history lies behind and is inseparable
from social and cultural processes. It gives rise to taken-for-granted (‘natural’ and
‘instinctual’) needs and motivations, but at the same time these are also
historically and socially shaped so that they transcend ‘mere self-preservation’.
That is, even the apparently natural interest in self-preservation is expressed
through the social system as the means of securing a ‘historical existence’ against
nature.37
The idea that interests are constitutive of knowledge means that humans can
only experience the world (‘reality’) as conditioned through these interests, and
additionally that knowledge would not be possible unless interests existed. This
means that interests have a cognitive function of constituting what it is possible to
have knowledge of, that is, they create ‘fundamental object domains’. (Habermas,
1978 p.369) 38 Interests therefore structure the possible viewpoints from which the
human species can apprehend reality. Habermas further argues that knowledgeconstitutive interests ‘take form in the medium of work, language and power’, that
37
‘the human interests that have emerged in man's natural history … derives both from nature and
from the cultural break with nature. ... What may appear as naked survival is always in its roots
a historical phenomenon. For it is subject to the criterion of what a society intends for itself as
the good life.’ (Habermas, 1978 p.312-3)
38
There is a similarity between this and the notion of ‘problematisation’ evident in the work of
Foucault and others on governmental rationality, and in the work of Latour and other actornetwork theorists. Both are discussed in detail in subsequent chapters.
41
is, each of these media shape interests in distinct ways and corresponds to the
different types of knowledge.39
Habermas reconstructs Marx’s differentiation of nature into three moments nature-in-itself, subjective nature and objective nature. Nature-in-itself is
conceived, following the early Marx, (Marx, 1974 p.329-30) 40 as that which
exists prior to the cultural world, as the basis of the natural evolution of the
human species in a biological sense. In addition to this naturalistic sense of extrahuman nature, Habermas also understands nature-in-itself as an epistemological
necessity, which presupposes nature as existing of itself, independently of human
history and experience41. This is nevertheless ‘an abstraction’, for nature must
always be encountered within the context of the socio-historical ‘self-formative
process’ of the human species. (Habermas, 1978 p.34)
In its anthropological aspects, Habermas further divides nature analytically
into ‘the subjective nature of man and the objective nature of his environment.’
‘Subjective bodily nature’ consists not only of the characteristics ‘of an organism
dependent on its environment (sensuous receptivity, need, emotionality,
vulnerability)’ but also the ‘adaptive modes of behaviour and active expressions
of life of an ‘active natural being.’ Central to the human self-formative process is
social labour, which is both a ‘natural’ process through which humans exchange
materials with their environment and at the same time a ‘transcendental’ act
through which the conditions for the constitution of objective knowledge of
external nature are brought into being. (Habermas, 1978 p.26-8) In the labour
process subjective nature is mediated with external environmental nature.
Habermas argues that humans are thus able to gain ‘access to nature’ only through
the ‘historical dimension disclosed by the labour processes’, that is, through
purposive-material interaction with the natural world. (Habermas, 1978 p.34)
39
The three ‘categories of possible knowledge’ are: that which ‘expands our power of technical
control’ (instrumental); that which ‘makes possible the orientation of action within common
traditions’ (practical); and that which ‘free consciousness from its dependence on hypostatised
powers’, ie social and psychic constraints (emancipatory). These types of knowledge ‘originate
in the interest structure of a species that is linked in its roots to definite means of social
organisation: work, language, and power. The human species secures its existence in systems of
social labour and self-assertion through violence, through tradition-bound social life in ordinary
language communication, and with the aid of ego identities that at every level of individuation
reconsolidate the consciousness of the individual in relation to the norms of the group.’
(Habermas, 1978 p.313)
40
There is clearly an attempt to combine Marx and Kant in Habermas’ account of nature, for
example see (Habermas, 1978 p.25-6, 35). For a detailed consideration of this aspect see
(Parsons, 1992).
41
This serves a similar function to Kant's thing-in-itself, as something which cannot be known as
such but which is postulated as lying behind the appearances confronted by the senses. See
Habermas (1982b) p.241-3; McCarthy (1978) p.110-25; Parsons (1992) p.221-6; Whitebook
(1979) p.48-9.
42
Hence objective nature is not identical to nature-in-itself but is constituted ‘only
in being mediated by the subjective nature of man through processes of social
labour’. (Habermas, 1978 p.28) 42
Habermas suggests that objective nature is not simply a creation of the
subject, but the synthetic product of the subject’s activity in attempting to
transform, control and utilise external nature (nature-in-itself). According to Marx
there is both a unity of humans and nature, and a struggle between the two, which
exists in the process of material production (social labour), and through which
both nature and the labouring subject are transformed. (Marx, 1976 p.283) 43
Following this approach, Habermas argues that the unity or synthesis between the
subject and nature is only brought about by the activity of the subject, and is
therefore necessarily something forced on to nature by the subject. Objective
nature however does not exist in isolation from nature-in-itself. While the activity
of the subject constitutes objective nature, it does not do so at will but encounters
resistance: there exists an ‘independence and externality’ to nature that resists the
subject. As a consequence, the unity of humans with nature ‘cannot eradicate the
autonomy of nature and the remainder of complete otherness that is lodged in its
facticity’, regardless of the scientific-technical power brought to bear. (Habermas,
1978 p.33) It is important to understand that in talking of objective (or objectified)
nature, Habermas is referring to the constitution of nature as an object of
instrumental action or scientific knowledge, that is, as an object of experience.
(Habermas, 1978 p.323 - translator's note 23) Objectified nature then, consists of
‘possible objects of experience’ and as such shares both the independence and
externality of nature and the ‘produced objectivity’ of a Lebenspraxis (worldconstituting life activity or social practice). (Habermas, 1978 p.27-28)
Habermas claims his use of the concept nature-in-itself is an ‘ironic’ reuse of
Kant’s thing-in-itself. He thus points to the pragmatic necessity of recognising the
contingency and resistance of an independent reality which we are forced to
construe as existing along the lines of nature-in-itself, even though this nature can
only be scientifically known to us ‘as objectivated.’ (Habermas, 1982b p.242)
Habermas’ twofold characterisation of natural objects as possessing the qualities
of both being-in-itself and humanly produced objectivity is captured in his
assertion that reality can only be known ‘in the perspective of possible technical
control.’ (Habermas, 1978 p.130) What he is saying is that reality or nature is both
disclosed and constituted. It is constituted to the extent that the meaning of
statements we make about nature and the properties we assign to nature, ‘must be
understood in relation to the structure of instrumental action.’ Nature is disclosed
42
Habermas takes labour to include science and technology. Both are ‘work’ in the Habermasian
sense.
43
For a discussion of the problem of nature and ecology in Marx see Grundmann (1991a) and
(1991b).
43
inasmuch that statements about nature must have a pragmatic utility, that is, they
must accommodate the resistance of nature to ‘false interpretations’. The facticity
ascribed to nature in statements must be construed as existing independently of
human action, as nature-in-itself. McCarthy argues that this approach allows
Habermas to avoid some of the difficulties of interpreting nature-in-itself as
strictly a Kantian thing-in-itself, for under Habermas’ re-formulation, nature-initself is no longer completely unknowable. Nature-in-itself is knowable to the
degree to which it can be subjected to instrumental action or technical
manipulation; that is, it is knowable ‘subject to the conditions of possible
objectivity’, to the degree to which nature is objectified. (McCarthy, 1978 p.117)
Habermas clearly understands subjective nature as including the fundamental
social life-structures, work and interaction. Here again there is a paradox, for if
nature can be known in the context of instrumental action then it follows that
‘subjective bodily nature’, inasmuch as it is known through instrumental means,
must also be understood as part of objectified nature.44 However, this same
subjective bodily nature would (in a consistently materialist ontology) need to
exist prior to constituted objectivity. The dilemma is then, that ‘either subjective
bodily nature is not a prior condition of possibility of cognition, or it is and we
cannot know it.’ (McCarthy, 1978 p.119) Habermas attempts to overcome this
problem by differentiating the conditions under which human knowledge of
objective and subjective nature is achieved. Thus while objective nature is
constituted in the context of instrumental action, subjective nature can only be
understood, according to Habermas, within the media of the ‘reproduction of
social life’ (work or social labour) and the ‘cultural conditions’ in which it takes
place (interaction). Unlike objective nature, subjective nature cannot be
understood within the same objectifying framework as biological reproduction
and preservation of the species. Work and interaction are elements of a selfformative process that includes ‘learning and arriving at mutual understanding.’
(Habermas, 1978 p.196) Subjective nature is therefore to be understood as bound
to these structures of social action (work and interaction) and the knowledge
constitutive interests that lie behind them. These are to be understood not as the
product of an objectifying process but of a reflexive or hermeneutic task, which
reflects on the conditions of objectivity:
In an epistemological context, then, subjective nature refers neither to an
unknowable nature-in-itself nor to an objectively constituted nature. It
refers to structures of human life that are grasped reflectively in an
attempt to elucidate the nature, conditions, and limitations of human
knowledge. (McCarthy, 1978 p.120)
44
There is some similarity here with Foucault’s approach to the human body. See Butler (1989).
44
One of the tasks of Habermas’ cognitive interest theory is to overcome what
he sees as Marx’s epistemological conflation of symbolic interaction and labour.
(Habermas, 1978) He attempts to do this by arguing that these separate domains
of action are based on different categories of knowledge that obey different logics
or rules of formation. (Habermas, 1978, Appendix; Habermas, 1982b) Labour, as
Parsons notes, is nevertheless defined by Habermas ‘in terms of dual character:
as both a category of human existence and an epistemological category.’ (Parsons,
1992 p.222) 45 Nature and labour therefore come together in a specific way in
Habermas - through science and technology. For him science and technology are
highly rationalised expressions of social labour. Indeed, Habermas makes a direct
link between the ‘old’ techniques of labour (techne) characteristic of artisan
production in the past and modern technology. He argues that the
function of the knowledge of modern science must therefore be
understood in connection with the system of social labour: it extends and
rationalises our power of technical control over the objects or - what
comes to the same thing - objectified processes of nature and society.
(Habermas, 1976 p.334)
Science and technology are therefore modern expressions of the same
cognitive interest as is labour, that is, the instrumental or technical interest in the
effective manipulation and control of nature and the social organisation of labour
necessary for this. Whereas Horkheimer and Adorno understood science and
technology as expressions of the objectifying tendency characteristic of all
conceptual reason, Habermas insists on a differentiation. The problem of nature
(insomuch as there is a problem) therefore does not arise from the ‘new function
of science as a technological force’, but rather from a failure to separate ‘practical
and technical power’. The difficulty is precisely that the different value spheres
and cognitive interests are not adequately distinguished, resulting in ‘the process
of scientification’ transgressing the proper limits of technical rationality and
intruding into areas of moral-practical reason, that is, politics. (Habermas, 1976
p.331-4) 46
One of the main strengths of Habermas’ interpretation of science is his
insistence that knowledge of nature cannot be separated from human interests and
their historical production. Thus contrary to the ahistorical orientation of
45
See Habermas (1978) p.28-35. It is not within the scope of this thesis to consider in detail the
bases from which Habermas draws his theory in this regard. For discussion and criticism of
Habermas’ attempt to synthesise Kant and Marx see Parsons (1992) p.218-30; McCarthy
(1978) p.110-25; Whitebook (1979) p.41-69.
46
This is an issue that is also taken up by Beck. See in particular (Beck, 1994 ) where he in effect
argues for a politicisation of decisions about technology - he asserts that the acceptability of
technological risks is a moral-practical one rather than a technical one. Beck’s work is
discussed in Chapter 4 of this thesis.
45
positivism and the totalising tendency of Horkheimer and Adorno, Habermas
attempts a historically based account of the relation between knowledge and
nature. However, his own tendency to seek a universal grounding for reason
undermines this. This is particularly the case with his argument that the technical
cognitive interest is a product of the natural history of the human species, and that
‘our’ technology as an expression of this must be conceived as a project of ‘the
human species as a whole.’ (Habermas, 1971 p.87) Such a homogenous view of
‘natural history’ and social evolution is as totalising in its own way as the
‘monistic’ notion of reason put forward in Horkheimer and Adorno’s Dialectic of
Enlightenment. The desire to secure a universal foundation, or more precisely,
universal criteria for assessing validity claims, is evident in key aspects of his
cognitive interest theory, and later in his theory of communicative action.
Habermas argues cognitive interests give rise to a universal or ‘quasitranscendental’ perspective, in that they are directed at satisfying universal
interests of the human species in self-preservation. These interests are however
historical in that they have evolved in the ‘natural history of the species’, but take
on an almost transcendental character in the way in which they provide a
universal and necessary horizon within which knowledge of the natural and social
world is possible. (Habermas, 1974 p.8, 21) As Alford comments, this ‘seems to
mean that each interest sets the conditions under which the possible objects of
experience can be known, but interests do not constitute the objects themselves.’
(Alford, 1985b p.80) Thus while on the one hand Habermas appears to want to
assert that knowledge is only possible within a historical context, he also seeks to
retain the notion of ‘objective’ knowledge of the natural world. This is very much
tied to his rejection of the Frankfurt School’s version of the critique of
instrumental reason. In emphasising the differentiation of reason, Habermas wants
to retain the claim of the pragmatic-technical usefulness of natural science while
at the same time quarantining politics and ethics from the objectifying logic of
those sciences. Unlike the natural sciences, the human sciences express the
cognitive interest in the development of intersubjective understanding that allows
agreement on moral-practical issues as a necessary means for orienting social
actions. The human sciences, in Habermas’ view, are fundamentally linked to
political and moral discourse, and involve interpretation and criticism directed
towards hermeneutic understanding of social interaction. Science and technology,
as forms of labour, are directed towards the technical mastery of external nature in
the interest of self-preservation of the species, while the human sciences are
directed towards understanding subjective nature and the realisation of human
emancipation and autonomy. (Habermas, 1971 p.87-93) Habermas thus asserts,
contrary to Horkheimer and Adorno, that the mastery of external nature need not
lead to the subjugation of ‘inner nature’, that is, there need be no necessary link
between an advanced science and technology and social domination.
46
Having made this separation between the natural and the social, Habermas
reinstates the notion of ‘objective’ or decontextualised knowledge of nature, for
while the cognitive interest in technical control of nature is the product of history,
it is the nevertheless the product of a common natural history of the entire
species. This suggests that while the technical interest in the control of nature is
the result of an evolutionary history, the species share a common interest in selfpreservation through mastery of nature. The ‘transcendental ego’ is naturalised in
the biological notion of species, and through this step Habermas attempts to
rescue the notion of the objectivity of the natural sciences, contrary to Horkheimer
and Adorno’s assimilation of knowledge to power.
As noted earlier, Habermas argues that we are forced to ‘construe nature as
something existing in itself, though it is scientifically accessible to us only as
objectivated.’ He also claims that nature, as ‘a contingently existing reality
independent of us’ resists ‘false interpretations’. (Habermas, 1982b p.242) It must
be asked, however, what is it that ‘resists’? It cannot be said that it is nature-initself for as Habermas insists, this cannot be known other than as objectified. The
‘independence’ of nature is therefore the resistance offered by objectified nature,
not external nature-in-itself, to which we have no access. It must be remembered
that objective nature in Habermas’ account is constituted through the process of
social labour, which includes scientific theorising. (Habermas, 1978 p.34) The
consequence of this is that what guarantees the objectivity of scientific knowledge
of nature is not the realities of nature-in-itself but the activity of objectification. In
other words, the independence and externality of nature, which Habermas says we
must construe as an ‘epistemological postulate’, cannot act as a measure of the
objectivity of technical-scientific knowledge. Instead objectivity is the ‘produced
objectivity’ of social practices. (Habermas, 1978 p.27-36) 47 In this circumstance
Habermas’ attempt to draw a rigid division between instrumental and practical
knowledge, between the natural and the human sciences must be questioned.48
47
This is not that far from the approach taken by actor-network accounts of how science
‘constructs’ nature. Actor network theory is discussed in Chapter 8 of this thesis. See also
Latour (1987 ).
48
Habermas does of course acknowledge that theory formation in the natural sciences is subject to
hermeneutic influences, as pointed to by 'post-empiricist' philosophy of science such as Popper,
Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend et al, [see (Habermas, 1984 p.107-11)] inasmuch as data and facts
cannot be described independently of theoretical languages and paradigms within which
observation statements are formulated and interpreted as meaningful. So, while the natural
sciences cannot be interest free or 'objective' in a positivist sense, they nevertheless do not obey
the same logic involved in communication. The natural sciences still obey an instrumentalobjectifying logic directed at manipulation and control of nature (expressed in labour) while the
human sciences are thoroughly communicative or ‘doubly hermeneutic’ [see (Habermas, 1984
p.110)] in that they are governed by a logic or practical interest in the reproduction of
intersubjective, mutual understanding that orientates social action. See Rouse, (1987), Chapter
6 for a detailed discussion and critique of Habermas’ under-estimation of the hermeneutic
character of natural scientific knowledge. I will return to a more extensive discussion of this
47
Communicative action
Habermas’ project, even in his early works aims to develop a systematic
theory of social rationalisation in a way that will explicate the ‘pathology of
modernity from the viewpoint of the realisation - the deformed realisation - of
reason in history.’ (Habermas, 1981a p.6-7) Habermas’ Knowledge and Human
Interests is an attempt to develop such a theory of rationality capable of giving a
rational basis for universal normative standards in the struggle for emancipation.
In this work Habermas derives an emancipatory interest from self-reflection on
the technical and practical cognitive interests. (Habermas, 1978, Appendix p.3145, and Postscript p.370-6) Here Habermas’ thrust is primarily epistemological in
that he is concerned with the ways in which critical self-reflection on the
connection between knowledge and interests can be grounded on an emancipatory
critical theory of society. For a variety of reasons Habermas came to see the
approach adopted in Knowledge and Human Interests as suffering from
shortcomings. (Habermas, 1978, Postscript) 49 Principal among these was the
failure of his cognitive interest theory to sufficiently extricate itself from the
epistemological orientation of the ‘philosophy of the subject’. Habermas argues
that in such a philosophical orientation the focus remains on the way in which
autonomous subjects relate to the objects in the world rather than on how subjects
are constituted and formed in social interactions based on communication.
(Habermas, 1985) 50
While Habermas moved away from use of ‘quasi-transcendental’ cognitive
interests he nonetheless retained some of the key distinctions embodied in his
earlier theory. The earlier distinction between technical interests and
argument in Chapter 6 of this thesis where I criticise Foucault for his tendency to assign a more
'objective' character to the natural sciences than he does to the human science, and thus separate
science from the critique of power. See also Latour’s criticism of Foucault (in Crawford, 1993)
on similar grounds – this is discussed in Chapter 8 below.
49
See Bernstein (1985) p.11-25 for an elaboration of these shortcomings.
50
Chapter 11 of that work in particular deals with these issues. Here Habermas claims that
‘Rationality refers in the first instance to the disposition of speaking and acting subjects to
acquire and use fallible knowledge. As long as the basic concepts of the philosophy of
consciousness lead us to understand knowledge exclusively as knowledge of something in the
objective world, rationality is assessed by how the isolated subject orients himself to
representational and propositional contents. Subject-centred reason finds its criteria in standards
of truth and success that govern the relationships of knowing and purposively acting subjects to
the world of possible objects or states of affairs. By contrast, as soon as we conceive of
knowledge as communicatively mediated, rationality is assessed in terms of the capacity of
responsible participants in interaction to orient themselves to validity claims geared to
intersubjective recognition.’ (p.314). From this it is clear why Habermas would consider his
cognitive interest theory fails to overcome the perspective of the philosophy of the subject - in
Knowledge and Human Interests the focus is still firmly on the relationship between knowledge
and purposive-instrumental reason.
48
practical/emancipatory interests is reformulated in its most systematic fashion in
Theory of Communicative Action. (Habermas, 1984; Habermas, 1987) In
particular, this later work retains a fundamental categorical distinction between
purposive-rational action and symbolic or communicative action. Whereas his
cognitive interest theory attempts to ground a universal emancipatory interest in
the natural history of the human species, his theory of communicative action (or
universal pragmatics) seeks a universal foundation for emancipatory critique in
the structure of the human speech act and communication in general. There is
therefore a ‘linguistic turn’ from natural history to language as the means of
grounding the rejection of various ‘forms of relativism’ and ‘irrationalism in
general’ that he sees as appearing ‘under the sign of a dubious revival of
Nietzsche’. (Habermas, 1981a p.12) 51 Thus Habermas now bases his theoretical
perspective on the notion of communicative action as a uniquely human form of
social action based in language and in his formulation, directed intrinsically
towards mutual understanding and consensus. However this new grounding for
emancipatory critique remains, as with his earlier theory, dependent on the
‘natural’ characteristics of the human species, in this case language.
Habermas’ theory of communicative action provides a perspective in which
the ‘cognitive-instrumental mastery of an objectivated nature (and society)’ is
understood as a process that derives from the separation of instrumental reason
from a ‘suppressed’ practical reason, that is, in its separation from the
‘communicative structures of the life-world’. For Habermas the notion of
communicative reason retains the comprehensive or emphatic concept of reason
(that Horkheimer and Adorno’s idea of instrumental reason undermines) by
postulating a rational potential inherent in speech acts which he regards as
possessing a discursive logic aimed at achieving a non-coercive, rational
consensus among participants. In Habermas’ later work the communicative
potential of reason becomes the effective principle behind the processes of social
modernisation, albeit a potential that is ‘simultaneously developed and distorted’
by modernity. (Habermas, 1987 p.315) While in one sense Habermas’ notion of
communicative reason has a ‘purely procedural character’ (and thus retains a
‘quasi-transcendental’ element), it is also understood by him as implicit to actual
social processes as these assume and necessitate mutual understanding and
consensus among social actors. Indeed, Habermas argues that the communicative
potential of reason derives from the everyday life-world with its taken for granted
cultural context providing the basis for processes of mutual understanding. The
rationalisation of the modern life-world, through the differentiation of spheres of
social action and the division of labour, is an inevitable (and positive) element of
modernisation. However this process, according to Habermas, is distorted by the
51
Habermas is no doubt referring here not only to Horkheimer and Adorno, but also to Heidegger,
Foucault, Derrida et al. See Habermas (1985) for elaboration of his critique of these theorists.
49
‘unfettered imperatives of (the) economic and administrative’ system, which
embodies a functional logic that suppresses questions of practical reason.
(Habermas, 1987 p.315-6) Thus the ‘natural’ life-world in which communicative
reason originates is ‘uncoupled’ from the economic and administrative system of
modern society. The functional or purposive logic of this system then comes to
dominate and distort the communicative-practical processes of society. It is in this
context that Habermas talks of the need to complete the ‘unfinished project’ of
modernity, that is, he argues that the full potential of communicative reason can
only be realised by re-establishing the proper relations between moral-practical
decisions and strategic-purposive ones within the economic and administrative
system.
System and lifeworld
In Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas’ response to what he regards
as the ‘dead end’ into which the Frankfurt School had taken critical social theory,
as well as to his own earlier inadequate attempts to overcome these, is twofold.
The first, as discussed above, is to further develop his earlier critique of
Horkheimer and Adorno’s one dimensional notion of reason through the use of a
linguistically based concept of communicative action linked to the notion, derived
from phenomenology and interpretative sociology, of the lifeworld. The second is
an attempt, developed in detail in volume two of Theory of Communicative
Action, to integrate this hermeneutic-phenomenological concept of the lifeworld
with the approach of systems theory derived from Talcott Parsons. (Habermas,
1987) An important feature of this reorientation is the shift of focus from the
differentiation of action spheres (instrumental, practical, emancipatory) to an
emphasis on the analysis of two distinct modes of action coordination. With this
change Habermas now gives a central role to communicative reason (at the
expense of cognitive interests) as providing both the ‘internal logic’ and
coordinating mechanism for the rational reproduction of the symbolic content of
the lifeworld. The material reproduction of society is now conceived as being
coordinated through the ‘system media’ of money and power within the social
‘sub-systems’ of the economy and the administrative state. (Habermas, 1987
p.250-77; Smith, 1993 p.107)
In the tradition of interpretative sociology (ie Schutz, Luckman) the notion of
the lifeworld refers to the pre-given stock (or horizon) of background knowledge
and values that individuals draw on as interpretative resources for the orientation
of action in social contexts. Habermas is critical of the ‘individualising’ and
‘culturalistic’ implications of this approach and instead argues that rather than
viewing action from the perspective of the individual actor it is necessary to
understand the existence of the lifeworld in collective terms. (McCarthy, 1984
p.xxiv-xxvi) In doing this, Habermas insists that the institutional order of society
must be considered an important structural element of the lifeworld. The argument
50
here is that the existence and reproduction of this institutional order (which
includes institutional production of norms) is essential to a stable lifeworld. The
existence of an institutional, norm producing, order is therefore vital in
‘coordinating, even constituting’ the everyday contexts within which social actors
pursue their activities. (Baxter, 1987 p.46-7) 52
Habermas argues that modernisation is the result of a process of social
differentiation and rationalisation that occurs on two levels simultaneously. He
combines hermeneutic and systems perspectives to view society simultaneously as
both as a lifeworld and a self-regulating system. In the former, solidarity or social
integration is based on the cultural coordination of the action orientations of
individuals through communicatively negotiated normative agreement and
legitimation. In the latter, functional integration is brought about via the
coordination of the action consequences in a way that contributes to the
maintenance of the institutional order or social system. (Habermas, 1987 p.117)
Habermas claims that social integration manifests itself as the symbolic
reproduction of the lifeworld, and is dependent on processes of socialisation and
cultural tradition. On the other hand, functional integration, according to
Habermas, is ‘equivalent to a material reproduction of the lifeworld that is
conceived as system maintenance’. Such functional integration or systemic
‘interdependency’, while requiring the social integration based on the symbolic
reproduction of the lifeworld through communicative reason, goes beyond the
‘communicative intermeshing of action orientations’, that is, ‘the system’ has a
degree of structural autonomy. By introducing this systems approach Habermas
thus emphasises that system integration is not the intended result of mutual
cooperation but must be understood as the unintentional expression of latent
systemic tendencies or functions. He argues that this systemic coordination of
actions is not comprehensible from a social actor’s ‘intuitive knowledge of
lifeworld contexts’. Rather ‘survival imperatives require a junctional integration
of the lifeworld, which reaches right through the symbolic structures of the
lifeworld and therefore cannot be grasped without further ado from the
perspective of participants.’ (Habermas, 1987 p.232-3) These survival imperatives
are those of the human species. The material reproduction of society requires
52
Habermas identifies three structural components of the lifeworld - culture, personality, and
society [or what Baxter and McCarthy call ‘the institutional order’; see Baxter (1987) p.47 and
McCarthy (1984) p.xxiv. Habermas explains that ‘By culture I mean the stock of knowledge
upon which participants in communication draw in order to provide themselves with
interpretations that will allow them to reach understanding ... By society I mean the legitimate
orders through which participants in communication regulate their membership in social
groups, and thereby secure solidarity. Under personality I understand the competences that
make subjects capable of speech and action, and thus enable them to participate in processes of
reaching understanding, and thereby assert their own identity.’ [Baxter (1987) p.47-8 quoted
from the German 1981 Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns, Band 2: Zur Kritik der
funktionalistischen Vernunft p.204-5].
51
system (functional) integration, and in this sense social reproduction is
‘fundamentally dependent upon the appropriation of natural resources’ needed to
maintain the material conditions of biological life. (Honneth, 1991 p.290-1)
It is against this methodological orientation that Habermas develops his view
of modernisation as a two-level process of rationalisation. At the first ‘level’, he
sees what he calls the uncoupling of the system from the lifeworld, in which the
means of functional integration (the sub-systems of economy and state) become
increasingly autonomous from those elements of the lifeworld responsible for
social integration. In other words, the institutional order is increasingly
differentiated from culture. At the second level Habermas sees a process of
growing differentiation and rationalisation within both the lifeworld and system
themselves. (Habermas, 1987 p.153-4) 53 Rationalisation of the lifeworld occurs
through the growth of modern society’s reliance on ‘discursive will formation’ in
which the values or normative statements that legitimate social practices become
dependent on formal, ‘rational’ procedures for their justification rather than the
authoritative invocation of cultural tradition.54 At the same time the means of
material reproduction of society become more complex, requiring a greater degree
of division and coordination of social labour. This process is driven by the
increasing complexity (and productive capacity) of economic exchange in
industrialised society and necessitates a corresponding expansion of the
administrative capacity and organisational power of the state directed toward the
purposive-rational efficiency of economic exchange and administrative actions.
(Habermas, 1987 p.153-197) 55
These processes of rationalisation however pull in two directions. On the one
hand they increase the potential for communicative rationality, while at the same
time the rationalisation and autonomisation of the mechanisms of functional
integration of the system tends to free (‘uncouple’) instrumental activity from the
normative restraints traditionally imposed by the cultural lifeworld. Thus against
the potential of modernisation to realise the communicative rationalisation of the
lifeworld, there is the tendency (realised in advanced industrial society) for the
functional elements of the institutional order (‘the system’) to replace normative
communication as the means of coordinating social actions. From the perspective
53
See also McCarthy (1984) p.xxviii; Baxter (1987) p.70-1.
54
Indeed, Habermas claims that even the reproduction of cultural tradition ‘becomes more
strongly dependent upon the capacity for critique and innovation’. It thus embodies a much
greater possibility of arriving through rational argumentation at mutual agreement on claims to
truth and normative validity which is reflected in the institutionalisation of scientific research,
modern legal practices and democratic political representation. Habermas translated by Baxter
(1987) p.49, from Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns II 1981, p.219-20. See also
Habermas (1984) p.70-1.
55
See also McCarthy (1984) p.xviii-xxiv).
52
of the sub-systems of the economy and the state, this gives rise to the situation in
which the ‘steering media’ of money and power develop into ‘formally organised
domains of action’. (Habermas, 1987 p.307) Rather than being embedded in the
appropriate lifeworld domain of communicative action, according to Habermas
these steering media represent a form of strategic action that not only uncouples
itself from the lifeworld, but also develops an ‘irresistible inner dynamic’ that
leads to the ‘colonisation of the lifeworld’. (Habermas, 1987 p.331 - emphasis in
original) In particular, Habermas points to the way in which such ‘norm free’
strategic action parallels in the social world the methods employed for dealing
with ‘scientifically objectivated nature’. Indeed, he argues that strategic or
purposive-instrumental action is freed of ‘normative restrictions to the extent that
it becomes linked to flows of information from the scientific system.’ (Habermas,
1987 p.196)
Nature in communicative action theory
In his earlier cognitive interest theory, while locating the generalised interests
of the human species in its natural history, Habermas nevertheless was concerned
to separate the social from non-human nature. As we have seen, he does this by
arguing that there are different types of cognitive interests, and that these reflect a
fundamental divergence between the different realms of human activity, that is,
between social labour and symbolic interaction. He also claims that these different
cognitive interests constitute distinct ‘object domains’ which each obey different
logics. (Habermas, 1978 p.369) These differences are in turn reflected in the
character of the methods of knowledge production, that is, between the
objectifying methods of the natural sciences and the hermeneutic methods of the
human sciences. In adopting this approach Habermas rejects Horkheimer and
Adorno’s call for reconciliation with nature, which he sees as regression into a
religious or metaphysical worldview that undermines the positive achievements of
modern scientific knowledge and politics. Nature, Habermas insists, can only
usefully be known as an object of control. (Habermas, 1982a; Habermas, 1982b)
Habermas’ attitude towards nature has not only been the subject of a
debate between Habermas and members of the Frankfurt School, 56 but has also
drawn criticism from a range of writers more directly concerned with ecological
problems. 57 Their key criticism is that Habermas’ theoretical differentiation of
56
This was an important issue of debate between Habermas and Marcuse, in which Habermas
(1971, p.85-6) attacked Marcuse's notion of a ‘new science’. See Alford (1985b) for a detailed
study of these differences.
57
In this respect the main works are Leiss (1975), DiNorcia (1974) Alford (1985a; 1985b),
Whitebook (1979), Ottmann (1982), Eckersley (1990; 1992), Parsons (1992). See McCarthy’s
comments (1978 p.112-125), and the response to much of the substance of these criticisms by
Habermas (1982b) especially Section III - Reason and Nature: reconciliation at the cost of reenchantment', p.238-250.
53
cognitive interests (and the corresponding differentiation of spheres of rationality)
is drawn with such rigidity that it denies the possibility of knowledge of, or
relations with, nature except insofar as this is mediated by an objectifying interest
in technical control. Habermas’ approach to nature is considered by most of these
critics as being too narrowly conceived to be capable of adequately dealing with
the ecological and ethical issues posed by the environmental problems facing
contemporary society. In particular, Habermas’ theory is attacked for being
‘thoroughly anthropocentric’ (Whitebook, 1979 p.52) in that it appears to exclude
the possibility of communicative interaction with nature, that is, it constructs the
distinction between technical and practical interests too rigidly. Ottmann, for
example, suggests that given the severity of modern ecological problems it may
be necessary to recognise that the human species has an interest in nature beyond
mere technical control. Indeed, a normative relationship to nature should be
considered an integral part of the human practical interest in ‘the good life’.
(Ottmann, 1982 p.89-92) Eckersley (1992) mounts a similar argument. 58
Habermas generally rejects these criticisms on the grounds that nature cannot
enter into the sorts of relations of mutual understanding and recognition that takes
place between subjects, and which he regards as characteristic of relations
founded on communicative reason. (Habermas, 1978 p.33) In other words, nature
is incapable of entering into discursive or dialogical relations as a ‘partner in
communication’ as are humans.59 He questions how any attitude other than the
‘objectivating attitude of the natural-scientific experimenting observer’ can be
‘theoretically fruitful’ in the sense of leading to a pragmatically successful
manipulation of natural resources required for the material reproduction of
society. He also rejects the idea that a ‘naturalistic ethic’ could be ‘adequately
grounded’ today without recourse to religious or metaphysical outlooks that
would undermine the ‘level of learning attained in the modern ie scientific
understanding of the world.’ (Habermas, 1982b p.242-3, 248) This is the crux of
Habermas’ defence - that useful knowledge of nature is only available through the
objectifying medium of social labour (particularly science and technology), and
that a ‘nature’ ethic would undermine the cognitive achievements that flow from
the disenchantment and rationalisation of society brought about by modernity.
Thus the real issue for Habermas’ in his debate with these critics is the question of
under what conditions can we know nature and which of these ways of knowing
58
See p.112-4.
59
While this is challenged on largely ethical grounds by the critics discussed here, Bruno Latour
argues against this assertion on somewhat different sociological, or more accurately, ‘actornetwork’ grounds. Latour questions whether the ‘modernity’ that Habermas seeks to defend has
ever really existed, that is, whether the separation of the human and non-human assumed by
Habermas is ontologically possible. (Latour, 1993 p.60-1) I argue that Latour and actornetwork theory provides some useful elements for a (largely sympathetic) critique of Foucault see Chapter 8 of this thesis.
54
nature are useful to human beings in a pragmatic sense? As we have seen, his
response to this is an emphatic insistence that functionally useful knowledge of
nature can only be acquired through the objectifying, ‘decentred attitude’ of
modern science. (Habermas, 1982b p.248) 60 The intricacies of this debate, and
especially the philosophical response of Green theorists, are outside of the scope
of the present discussion.61
However it is clear that the development of the theory of communicative
action does little to alter Habermas’ basic conceptualisation of the relation
between nature and society. If anything the move to the ‘paradigm of linguistic
philosophy’ (Habermas, 1987 p.390) strengthens his emphasis on the
intersubjective relations by privileging social over material reproduction. In
another sense however, the move to systems theory makes the relation to nature
less problematic. This arises out of Habermas’ criticism of Weber’s and the
Frankfurt School’s notion of reification (or the absolutising of purposiveinstrumental rationality in the interests of human self-preservation) as being
bound to the philosophy of the subject. (Habermas, 1987 p.399) Habermas claims
that the ‘problem of reification’ should be understood not so much as the
reification of consciousness as the result of an ‘unleashed functionalist reason of
system maintenance’ which overrides and distorts the fundamental
communicative processes of ‘sociation’ responsible for the symbolic structuring
of the lifeworld. (Habermas, 1987 p.392) He argues that the maintenance of
society is not simply dependent on technical mastery of external nature or on the
strategic relations between social groups. It also requires the coordination of
societal activities through communicative action, which can only be brought about
in accordance with the ‘conditions of rationality’ inherent in this. By introducing
60
From an epistemological perspective Habermas denies that it is possible to have direct,
unmediated access to nature-in-itself at the level of rationally reconstructive knowledge (ie as
theoretical knowledge). However, he does concede that some form of ‘private access’ to naturein-itself ‘guided by a pre-understanding of the lifeworld specific to humans’ may be possible.
But he insists that such a ‘performative attitude to external nature’ can only allow humans to
enter into communicative relations with nature via ‘aesthetic experience and feelings analogous
to morality’. (Habermas, 1982b p.242-4) Nevertheless, this is still not a genuinely
communicative relation in the sense of a linguistically shared intersubjectivity. This would
depend on the possibility of argumentatively challenging validity claims between linguistically
competent subjects (ie ‘the comprehensibility of the symbolic expression, the truth of the
propositional content, the truthfulness of the intentional expression, and the rightness of the
speech act with respect to existing norms and values.’ [Habermas quoted in Bernstein (1985,
p.19-20).] The extent to which a non-instrumental relation with nature is possible is in any case
limited by the specifically human pre-understandings of the lifeworld, which relies on human
communicative action. A similar line of argument is followed by Habermas with regard to
ethical theory where he maintains that ethics must be based on a discursive ‘norm-conformative
attitude’ in which ‘the principle egalitarian relation of reciprocity built into communicative
action ... cannot be carried over into relations between humans and nature.’ (Habermas, 1982b
p.248)
61
See Eckersley (1990) for a summary of the key arguments in the Green critique.
55
this ‘communications-theoretic turn’ (Habermas, 1987 p.392) as the keystone of
his later social theory, Habermas seeks to provide a universal and fundamental
grounding for emancipatory critique that the philosophy of the subject is unable to
defend from the reifying effects of social rationalisation. He thus claims to revive
the comprehensive notion of Reason that the Frankfurt School and Weber have
difficulty maintaining due to their dependence on the philosophy of the subject.
Habermas sees self-preservation, which the Dialectic of Enlightenment
identified as ultimately lying behind the triumph of instrumental rationality, as
underpinned by the logic of communicative action. The notion of selfpreservation in the hands of Habermas changes from ‘mere’ self-maintenance to
incorporate the broader concept of social reproduction which he regards as
dependent on communicative reason, through which the ‘utopian perspective’ of
emancipation is ‘built into the linguistic mechanism of the reproduction of the
species.’ (Habermas, 1987 p.398 - emphasis added) Thus while in his cognitive
interest theory the emancipatory interest is ‘derived’ from the natural history of
the human species, with communicative action theory emancipatory reason is
located as a quality intrinsic to the evolution of the species as language users.
Furthermore, the processes of self-preservation bound by communicative
rationality are also dependent on the ‘functional interconnection’ following from
the consequences of the activities of individuals and groups in society. In other
words, the social imperatives of self-preservation require mechanisms for both
social and functional integration, and these are constitutive of the modern subject.
62
In the shift to communicative action theory, social theory is thus no longer
tied to the view of the ‘subject that represents objects and toils against them’.
(Habermas, 1987 p.390) Instead Habermas uses this shift to locate the
instrumental as a moment of a more comprehensive rationality, thereby assigning
instrumental action to its ‘proper’, that is, subordinate place. In doing this
Habermas diminishes the importance of social labour, and therefore science and
technology, as problems in social theory. For Horkheimer and Adorno these are
problematic because they are the most powerful means for the rational domination
and suppression of nature. In shifting the focus of his social theory to the norms of
communicative interaction between social actors and away from the critique of
62
Habermas claims here that ‘A subjectivity that is characterised by communicative reason resists
the denaturing of the self for the sake of self-preservation. Unlike instrumental reason,
communicative reason cannot be subsumed without resistance under a blind self-preservation.
It refers neither to a subject that preserves itself in relating to objects via representation and
action, nor to a self-maintaining system that demarcates itself from an environment, but to a
symbolically structured lifeworld that is constituted in the interpretive accomplishments of its
members and only reproduced through communication. Thus communicative reason does not
simply encounter ready-made subjects and systems; rather it takes part in structuring what is to
be preserved.’ (Habermas, 1987 p.398)
56
instrumental rationality, Habermas does not substantially move away from his
earlier view of the need to adopt an objectifying attitude towards external nature.
Indeed, as Hayim suggests, in arguing for the foundational role of
communicative reason in structuring society, Habermas does not reduce the
importance of instrumental rationality for the economic reproduction of society.
Rather he emphasises its ‘unproblematic nature ... which appears as a selfmaintaining system tied to self-preservation’ in which the natural environment is
rigidly separated out from the symbolic structure of social life. (Hayim, 1992
p.190) In approaching science and technology as a value-neutral, instrumental
activity Habermas continues to stress the practical utility of science in fulfilling
the needs of material reproduction (system integration). This has the effect of
perpetuating his earlier characterisation of science as part of a human selfformative process, which expresses in a decontextualised, abstract manner
generalised human interests. As a consequence science is rendered as a
‘technically automatic and normatively unproblematic’ species enterprise.
(Hayim, 1992 p.194-5)
Honneth, who is in many aspects sympathetic to Habermas claims that
Habermas nonetheless adopts a ‘technocracy thesis’, in which the notion of
communicative action simultaneously fulfils two contradictory functions. On the
one hand communicative action is understood as something that stands outside the
relations of social labour and domination, and thus provides the basis for a critical
social theory. At the same time his theory conceptualises the relations of social
labour and domination in a fundamental sense as the product of communicative
action. (Honneth, 1991 p.247-8) The technocracy thesis posits the ‘irresistible
autonomisation of technology’ so that the evolution of social rationality occurs
largely as a means of providing technical solutions to the problems of social
reproduction. Habermas, according to Honneth, accepts science and technology
are dominant in advanced industrial society, while at the same time wishing to
cast this as a disturbance or pathology of the evolutionary development of the
human species. (Honneth, 1991 p.265) This is the theoretical motivation behind
Habermas’ separation of communicative and technical-purposive action, and
which underpins his diagnosis of a one-sided or distorted rationalisation of
society. However, in moving away from an emphasis on spheres of social action
(labour and symbolic communication) in favour of types of action coordination
(system and lifeworld), Habermas’ theory of society can be said to rely on Smith
(1993 p.197) describes as two key theoretical fictions – ‘norm-free organisation
of action’, and ‘power-free paths of communication.’ 63
63
See also Baxter (1987) p.66-80 and Honneth (1991) p.248-250, 264-266, for discussion of these
problems. Habermas’ dispute with Foucault on the nature of power revolved around precisely
these questions. This is discussed in Chapter 5 of this thesis.
57
The effect of these moves is apparent in Habermas’ treatment of the politics
of ecological problems and Green movements. Here his separation of system and
lifeworld leads to the argument that ecological movements are not concerned with
conflicts arising over the material reproduction of society as are the modernist
movements organised around distributive issues (eg the labour and socialist
movements). Habermas characterises ecological issues as primarily concerned
with ‘the grammar of forms of life’. He regards these as problems that arise within
the lifeworld (‘in areas of cultural reproduction, social integration, and
socialisation’) provoked by the ‘reification of communicative spheres of action’
brought about by the intrusion of the functional, system steering media of money
and power. (Habermas, 1981c p.33; Habermas, 1987 p.391-396) Habermas
suggests that ecological conflicts and environmental movements should be
understood as particularistic expressions of resistance to the pressures towards the
colonisation of the lifeworld, that is, these movements ‘seek to stem or block the
formal, organised spheres of action in favour of communicative structures’. He
identifies the critique of economic growth and the ‘self-destructive consequences
of the growth in (social) complexity’ as key unifying themes in the new social
movements. (Habermas, 1987 p.34-5)
While Habermas identifies ecological movements as particularistic reactions
to specific, tangible environmental problems, he argues that these specific
responses are dependent on the existence of an already highly rationalised
lifeworld. Furthermore and somewhat inconsistently, he suggests that ecological
problems are ‘largely abstract and require technical and economic solutions that
must, in turn, be planned globally and implemented by administrative means.’
(Habermas, 1987 p.35) Here Habermas also identifies ecological issues as
expressions of resistance to the problems generated by the ‘overcomplexity’ of the
system of functional integration. In this context, ecological problems arise as
systemic abstractions ‘forced upon the lifeworld’ which can only be properly dealt
with within the already highly rationalised modern lifeworld through
communicative action. At the same time however, these systemic ‘abstractions’
supersede or cut across the complex boundaries between the different modes of
action coordination in advanced industrial societies. In Habermas’ words,
ecological conflicts and problems therefore ‘arise at the seam between system and
lifeworld’. The implication of this approach is that ecological problems reflect an
inevitable tension between communicatively derived cultural norms specifying
the acceptable limits to the human appropriation of the natural environment 64 and
the functionally defined systemic imperatives of the material reproduction of
society.
64
Habermas describes these as ‘criteria of livability’ and ‘the limits to the deprivation of sensualaesthetic background needs’. (Habermas, 1987 p.35)
58
Conclusion
Habermas’ analysis of nature can be read in several ways, and indeed as we
have seen, his approach has changed over time. However, central to his analysis is
an attempt to separate human from non-human nature. This is not because he
adopts a simple realist view of an external ‘objective’ nature – he clearly does not
– but rather because he sees this as necessary if the notion of emancipatory reason
(and critique) is to be rescued from an ‘Nietzschean’ assimilation with power. By
making a categorical distinction between communicative and instrumental
rationality, Habermas argues that while treating nature as an object of
manipulation and control is necessary to human survival and progress, to do the
same to human beings themselves is to undermine the goal of such progress human autonomy.
Central to Habermas’ criticisms of Horkheimer and Adorno is the view that
power relations between human beings (that is, relations of control and
domination) are a pathological outcome resulting from the ‘colonisation’ and
distortion of social relations by technical or instrumental rationality, and not by
reason in general. As I shall discuss in Chapter 4, this leads to an idealised view
of human subjectivity based on communicative competence and a notion of
human emancipation that is premised on power free relations of communication.
Habermas is thus forced, by his desire to preserve the ideal of autonomous
rational human subject, to rigidly separate the relations between humans from the
relations of humans to nature. Such a move is, of course, very much a ‘modernist’
one.
A consequence of regarding contemporary ecological problems as
‘skirmishes’ at the interface between system and lifeworld is to cast these as
peripheral side effects of the rationalisation of society and the historical progress
of emancipation. Given his insistence that nature must be dealt with in an
objectifying, instrumental manner, Habermas therefore takes a particularly
pessimistic view of the ‘emancipatory’ potential of ecological politics and new
social movements. In contrast to Habermas’ approach, other contemporary
German social theorists see ecological problems and movements concerned with
environmental issues as expressions of the emerging social dynamics of late
modernity and as central to political debate. In the next chapter I consider the
approach adopted by some of these social theorists to the problem of nature and
ecological risk.
59
Chapter 4
The problem of nature in Eder and Beck
Introduction
In contrast to Habermas, other contemporary German theorists treat the
problem of nature as central to social theory. In this respect, these authors can be
regarded as reinstating the early Frankfurt School concern with the problem of the
relationship between nature and society. This chapter considers in some detail the
work of major contemporary social theorists Klaus Eder and Ulrich Beck, and
somewhat more briefly that of Niklas Luhmann. All come from the German
tradition of social theory in which Habermas has played such an important role.
These writers can be regarded as falling within the broad tradition of critical
social theory, inasmuch as they argue in their own ways for a critical defence of
‘modernity’, while at the same time seeking to develop a more relevant critique of
the contemporary expression of that modernity. In this context each can be
understood as engaging in an implicit critical debate with Habermas 65specifically
on the issue of the way in which his later work does not adequately deal with the
challenge posed to modernity by contemporary ecological problems.
(1) Eder: nature as a new field of social conflict
As I have indicated, Habermas tends to see ecological conflicts, and the social
movements concerned with these, as reactions to inherent tensions between the
communicative production of cultural norms in the lifeworld and the material
reproduction of society by the social system. Eder on the other hand seeks to
understand such conflicts as both reflecting a new phase in the evolution of
modern society, and following Touraine, as an important form of collective action
responsible for the historical production of society. 66 Eder sees the problem of
65
The debate with Habermas is also quite explicit and direct at times. In commenting on the
criticisms of Habermas (by Eder and others) on the question of 'new social movements',
Strydom suggests that ‘To the extent that they remain within Habermas' framework, they
constitute an immanent critique of his position.’ See Strydom (1990, p.156-164) and also the
comments by Scott Lash and Brian Wynne to this effect in their introduction to Beck (1992b).
Luhmann’s position is somewhat different, in that he is very much concerned to develop
systems theory. Nevertheless, in Theory of Communicative Action, Habermas explicitly seeks
to bring together systems theory and hermeneutics, and debates between Habermas and system
theorists including Luhmann have occurred.
66
For an elaboration of Eder's use of Touraine in this regard see Eder (1993) p.107-118.
[Originally published as Eder (1982) p.5-20].
60
nature, and the associated awareness of the worldwide ecological crisis, as the
central factor shaping contemporary discourse on modernity. According to Eder,
ecological crisis leads to the experience of a ‘deep ambivalence’ towards the ideas
of rationalisation and progress, in which rationalisation is increasingly seen as a
socially and environmentally negative process. He argues that notions of progress
and rationalisation become increasingly distinct from each other as the problem of
nature undermines the modern assumption of the separation of nature and culture.
One effect of this is a heightened sensitivity to what Eder regards as a basic
ambiguity towards the supposed rationality of modern Western culture, forcing a
re-evaluation of the ‘normative assumptions of modernity’, and a questioning of
progress as the inevitable product of modernity. (Eder, 1990a p.67; Eder, 1990b
p.40-2) The notion of a negative dialectic of progress, discussed in Chapter 2 of
this thesis, is clearly evident here. In particular new types of conflicts arise around
the problematisation of the social relation to nature. These call into question the
‘old’ idea, expressed by the bourgeois and labour movements, of progress through
technological development and the mastery of nature. However, unlike Habermas,
Eder argues that these new conflicts should be seen as disputes about the type of
modernisation and development that modern society should pursue, rather than an
expression of a neo-romantic anti-modernism. (Eder, 1990b p.40, 21; Eder, 1993
p.103-112)
The problematisation of nature and progress is related to fundamental changes
in social structure brought about by a global process of modernisation and
rationalisation involving an intensification of the exploitation of both labour and
nature. 67 For Eder, this is not simply the product of capitalist development, but
rather, capitalist development is only one element of a much broader social
process of modernisation. 68 He sees this process as tied to significant changes in
the class structure of advanced Western societies, in which the growth of new
middle class groups, associated with the service sector, are becoming a key
element of ‘the emerging post-industrial society.’ (Eder, 1990b p.22, 37-41) 69
The emergence of these post-industrial class conflicts challenges the prevailing
model of social development (what Eder calls industrialism) common to both
67
See Yoxen (1981) p.66-122 for a similar argument in relation to the growth of molecular
biology. Yoxen’s analysis draws on both Marxist and Foucauldian concepts.
68
Here Eder shares a view common to both Weber and Horkheimer and Adorno in Dialectic of
Enlightenment. Turner suggests that Weber's immediate analysis of the role of Protestantism in
the rise of capitalism is complemented by long-term view that understands Western rationality
(and the processes of rationalisation) as pre-dating capitalism, that is, as involving a ‘long-term
teleological and irreversible process in Western culture.’ See Turner (1987) p.222-41,
especially p.234.
69
A more detailed treatment is given in Eder (1993). There is a significant literature on the
notions of the ‘new class’ and its relation to post-industrial society. For discussion of this in
relation to the rise of environmentalism and Green movements, see Betz (1991) and Eckersley
(1989).
61
capitalist and socialist societies. According to Eder, the main features of this new
type of society are social conflicts ‘centred around the problem of the exploitation
of nature’, and the central role played by social and cultural movements in
‘determining the direction of further “modernisation”.’ (Eder, 1990b p.22)
Eder’s approach gives rise to a range of criticisms of Habermas’ treatment of
the problem of nature and his use of the system / lifeworld dichotomy in
connection with this. These criticism are important for they suggest how
Habermas’ tendency to marginalise environmental issues can be overcome
without abandoning the insights of a ‘macro’ or social systems approach to
ecological problems. In particular, Eder criticises what he describes as
modernism’s dominant cultural model of nature, which attempts to ignore the
impact of both cultural tradition and external nature on the context of thinking and
acting, leading to ethnocentrism and anthropocentricism. (Eder, 1990b p.26-27)
Marx’s notion of the human relation to nature is firmly within this modernist
model, conceiving nature as a mere object of human activity. As a consequence,
the Marxist heritage ‘naturalises’ the social relation to nature, and in doing so
posits a notion of rationality involving ‘a close relationship between progress and
the rationality built into the development of the forces of production.’ (Eder,
1990a p.68-9) Eder therefore argues that Marx’s productivist notion of rationality
defends the cultural model of nature responsible for the environmental crisis now
faced by the modern world. Much like Horkheimer and Adorno, Eder sees the
progress associated with the subjugation of nature as simultaneously representing
a regress in social relations with nature. Thus the legacy of Marx and Weber,
resting on this particular notion of rationality as inherent in modernity, has
become ‘equivalent to self-destruction’ in that it aggravates this crisis in the
relation between society and nature. (Eder, 1990a p.69; Eder, 1990b p.23, 36)
Eder also argues that Habermas’ critique of Marx is ‘insufficient’ because
Habermas
substitutes the social relations of men among themselves for the basic
relation of man to nature. This solution to the Marxian problem of nature
separates two spheres of human action and thus overlooks the internal
connections between both spheres of action. The problem of nature forces
us to give up the idea that nature is subject to instrumental and culture to
communicative action. (Eder, 1990a p.81 footnote 5)
Not only does Eder locate the social relation to nature as central to social
theory, as did Horkheimer and Adorno, he also argues that rather than excluding
nature from the realm of moral consideration (as does Habermas) it is possible
conceive of a practical reason ‘compatible with a re-enchanted nature.’ Such a
alternative form of rationality, says Eder, is in fact found in the new discourses on
nature expressed by the ecological counter-culture movements. (Eder, 1990a p.68)
Indeed, Eder’s analysis of the character, and social function, of ecological
movements represents a crucial difference with Habermas.
62
Habermas’ characterisation of new social movements draws a distinction
between those that tend to be universalistic and emancipatory (the women’s
movement and possibly anti-racist civil rights movements), and those that are
particularistic and defensive (all others, including the ecology movement). 70
While he distinguishes within the ‘resistance movements’ between those that seek
to defend ‘traditional and social property’ and those representing a ‘new conflict
potential’ based on ‘new forms of cooperation and community’, he nevertheless
regards all of these as reactions to the intrusion into the lifeworld of the forces of
money and power originating in the sub-systems of functional integration (the
economy and state administration). However, defenders of Habermas claim that,
in itself, this need not mean that movements such as the ecology movement
cannot contribute to the redressing of what he considers to be the pathologies and
distortions of one-sided, ‘unbalanced’ capitalist modernisation. White for
instance, argues that Habermas implies an ideal of ‘balanced’ development that is
consistent with his notion of the unrealised potential of modernity. Seen in this
context, says White, Habermas’ analysis need not marginalise new social
movements and ecological politics as an ‘unending border conflict’ at the
interface of system and lifeworld. (White, 1988 p.136-143) White suggests
Habermas’ theory in fact positions new social movements ‘as the best hope for a
more ‘balanced’ institutionalisation of the potential of modernity’. (White, 1988
p.126-7)
Such an interpretation however has its difficulties. As White concedes,
Habermas has not produced any detailed work dealing with the function and
significance of such social movements, (White, 1988 p.139) and what he has
written tends not to strengthen White’s interpretation. 71 Most commentators see
Habermas as adopting a pessimistic view regarding the emancipatory potential of
new social movements. 72 Indeed Habermas appears to regard any potential
rationality as subverted and obscured by the failure of both of ‘anti-modern’ and
post-modern ‘conservatism’ to distinguish between the different developmental
logics of lifeworld and system. (Habermas, 1981c p.36-7)
70
Habermas distinguishes the feminist movement from other new social movements on the
grounds that the ‘struggle against patriarchal oppression’ involves the potential realisation of an
emancipatory program based in the ‘acknowledged universalist foundations of morality and
legality (which) lends feminism the impetus of an offensive movement, whereas all other
movements are more defensive in character. The movements of resistance and retreat seek to
stem or block the formal, organised spheres of action in favour of communicative structures:
they do not seek to conquer new territory.’ (Habermas, 1981c p.34)
71
See in particular Habermas (1981c) p.36-7.
72
See for example Strydom (1990) p.156-164 and Cohen (1985) p.710-11.
63
Environmental movements as cultural models
Eder’s approach to modernity and the role of social movements rejects the
distinction that is pre-supposed in Habermas (and Weber), between traditionalism
and modernity, and which is expressed in Habermas’ view of new social
movements as at least potentially and often actually, anti-modernist. Instead Eder
identifies two competing cultural traditions or models of the relation to nature that
contribute to European modernity. (Eder, 1990b p.28-37) These two competing
traditions, or contradictory discourses, Eder labels the justice perspective and the
purity perspective.73 The justice perspective represents the dominant cultural
model of nature in Western society, and is expressed in the instrumentalistutilitarian tradition. The purity perspective embodies a non-utilitarian attitude to
nature, which rejects the reduction of nature to an object of theoretical reason.
(Eder, 1990b p.31) Eder argues that the ‘cultural code’ specific to modern
Western society consists of both of these contradictory discourses, so that
modernity, including the social relation to nature, must be understood as the
history of the inter-relationship between these two cultural models or discourses.
The counter tradition represented by the purity perspective is therefore not so
much irrational as the expression of a different rationality seeking to define an
alternative modernity. This is a significant theoretical move, which is congruent
with the actor network critique of modernist epistemology by theorists Bruno
Latour and Michel Callon, and which I discuss in Chapter 8 of this thesis.
These two competing notions of nature Eder typifies by a set of conceptual
oppositions which contrast different ways of apprehending nature (rationality vs
romanticism), of thematising the temporality of the relation of nature to culture
(evolution vs equilibrium), and conceptions of practical reason (utilitarian vs
73
Eder (1996) provides an explanation of this distinction between the purity and justice
perspectives. The notion of purity is derived from the work of Mary Douglas (1966, 1975). In
Eder’s usage, the purity perspective “codes the difference between nature and culture in a way
that is evident in the values attributed to the notion of purity: they are health (referring to bodily
and psychic integrity), empathy and life or the complimentary notions of sickness, suffering
and death.” These types of values are not susceptible to utilitarian calculation, but are “holistic
values” and as such are “indivisible goods”. In the justice perspective, the instrumentalist
tradition seeks to provide a rational legitimation of the social relation to nature. In this
perspective, the cultural perception of nature “remains on the level of validity claims”. Its
mobilises the relation to nature in terms of “the equal treatment of all beings as the premise of
human moral action, a premise characteristic of the utilitarian ethics” similar to those of Peter
Singer. Eder suggests that this perspective seeks to distribute in a rational way the costs of the
use of nature in production, without removing “man from his moral pedestal”. It seeks to
provide justice through minimising the costs to nature with the effect that the “relation of man
to nature becomes one of a private compensation for the economically instituted use of nature.”
(p.207-8)
64
communicative reason). (Eder, 1990a p.67) 74 Eder claims that two different but
equally modern cultural attitudes or models are expressed in this ‘double code’.
He argues that the rationalist and romanticist perspectives relate to ‘two
differentiated spheres of value: the cognitive and the aesthetic.’ Thus in the
cognitive-rational attitude to nature notions of efficiency are highly valued. In
scientific terms nature is something that is capable of being apprehended through
the theoretical reconstruction of sensory experience. In contrast to this, the
aesthetic-romantic attitude is based in a non-objectifying, expressive or intuitive
experience of nature, which Eder sees as best typified in modern art. (Eder, 1990a
p.74)
The different ways in which the temporal relation between nature and society
is conceptualised is another element of the double code of modernity. This
relationship can be cast as either a linear, progressive evolution or as a cyclical
equilibrium. In the evolutionary perspective nature is understood as an object
shaped by societal forces that lead inexorably to the domination of nature,
whereas the notion of an equilibrium between society and nature is characteristic
of romantic thinking in which nature is held to posses an intrinsic value. However,
Eder points out that the notion of equilibrium in this context still ‘presupposes an
interactive relationship between society and nature’. In other words, inasmuch as
the notion of equilibrium presupposes the cultural form that a society bestows on
its natural environment, it cannot avoid the ‘one-way relationship’ characteristic
of evolution in society’s mastery of nature. Even where the evolution and
equilibrium concepts are combined to understand society and nature as evolving
together, such co-evolution is still ‘a process mediated by culture.’ (Eder, 1990a
p.74-5) Eder’s third ‘double code’ refers to two competing interpretations or
underlying assumptions, regarding morality or practical reason as applied to
nature. Utilitarian reason, as the dominant ‘economic ideology’ of advanced
Western society, can be understood as strategic or substantive rationality in the
Weberian sense, which is aimed at ‘calculating the effects of the use of nature
upon nature’. This perspective tends to emphasise human rational self-interest in
isolation from ‘social and cultural restraints’. In contrast to this, the
communicative perspective on practical reason emphasises an interactive,
dialogical view of human nature. Attitudes based on this perspective are likely to
‘treat nature as a symbolic good and to restrict the uses of nature to what can be
justified on moral grounds.’ (Eder, 1990a p.75; Eder, 1990b p.34-6)
Habermas tends to focus on those aspects of new social movements that
reflect the purity perspective. Eder instead argues that both models of nature (each
employing different forms of moral reason) are expressed in contemporary
74
Eder (1990a) links these two attitudes to nature to differences in the Greek and Jewish cultural
traditions - see especially p.70-4. This argument is developed in much greater detail in Eder
(1996).
65
ecological movements and thus there is within such movements a much greater
potential for ambivalence than recognised by Habermas. Hence while ecology
movements often draw on the romantic, counter-cultural tradition, they also
employ the utilitarian perspective with its focus on efficiency. Indeed, as Eder
correctly suggests, contemporary ecological thinking can also be considered ‘the
most advanced version of the dominant utilitarian mind, a radicalisation of
modern economic ideology.’ (Eder, 1990a p.75)75 Habermas recognises ecological
problems as attacks on the ‘organic foundations of the life-world’ originating at
the level of functional integration, while regarding ecological movements as
manifestations of resistance to the effects of this within the cultural realm of the
lifeworld. His view of ecological movements as ‘unrealistic’ and essentially antimodern is reinforced by his argument that dealing with environmental problems
requires global technical-economic planning and administration. (Habermas,
1981c p.35-7) As discussed previously, although Habermas does not elaborate on
these questions. Nevertheless he suggests that while ecological movements are
reactions to the ‘colonisation’ of the lifeworld by system steering media, at root
environmental concerns must primarily be dealt with as problems of system
integration concerned with the material reproduction of society. Hence he claims
that the anti-modernism of new social movements stems from a failure to
distinguish between the positive potential of modernity that lies in the
rationalisation of the lifeworld and the increasing complexity of the social system.
(Habermas, 1981c p.37) This interpretation is consistent with his arguments
against the possibility of adopting a genuinely moral-practical (as distinct from
aesthetic-expressive) attitude to nature on the grounds that useful knowledge of
nature must be tied to the objectifying stance of the natural sciences. (Habermas,
1982b p.238-250)
Eder rejects what he sees as Habermas’ ‘false idealisation’ of the separation
between lifeworld and system. While recognising the validity of Habermas’
concern for relating the ‘two logics of social life’ (ie lifeworld and system), he
argues that practical reasoning can never be separated from the context of social
systemic factors (power and money) which it serves to reproduce. (Eder, 1988
p.937-940) However, Habermas’ analytical separation of system and lifeworld,
with its surrender of nature to the systemic realm of functional reason,
underestimates the interpenetration of morality and technology in shaping
75
Eder notes here that the ‘utilitarian justification of the relationship between man and nature, (is)
an idea that links Bentham to modern environmental economists and has spread - paradoxically
- with our greater awareness of the environmental crisis.’ This is an issue I will touch on in
Chapter 6 of this thesis, where I discuss Foucault's notion of biopolitics and the emergence of
contemporary discourses and practices which problematise the environment in terms of bioeconomic models of ecology. Here it is worth noting that several environmental historians have
also pointed to the connection between utilitarian concepts and ideas of nature. See for instance
Bramwell (1989) and Worster (1987a).
66
society.76 What is more, it obscures the fact that Western culture is the product of
the interaction of competing models of practical reason, of the two ‘indissolubly
tied’ notions of progress and modernity. (Eder, 1990a p.76)
The ecological crisis thus brings into question the core assumptions of the
received view of modernity, particularly the idea of progress through
technological development and the exploitation of nature. Overcoming the
separation of nature and culture has become an urgent problem for modern society
because the ecological crisis now threatens the material reproduction of society.
Eder argues that theorising on modernisation has traditionally focused on the
political and economic reproduction of society, but now the focus has shifted to
include problems of ecological reproduction. Thus Eder argues the problem of
nature is not primarily a technical problem of functionally integrating the material
needs of modern social system with its natural environment. It is a cultural
problem in that it questions the moral dimension of the notion of progress, which
has begun to threaten the conditions of life in general. (Eder, 1990b p.40-2) Eder
argues that the relation between society and nature is symbolically mediated, and
that this requires us to
reconstruct the theoretical idea of forces of production as a cultural
category, as a specifically defined cultural form for appropriating nature
... we can extend our notion of a social relation to nature and see the basic
forms of social life from production to consumption as being determined
by specific cultural definitions of that relation to nature. (Eder, 1990a
p.69)
This approach accomplishes what Habermas’ approach to new social
movements has difficulty in doing. Problems of material reproduction at the
system level can now be linked with the actions of ecological movements in a way
that understands this as more than the ‘overlap’ of communicatively derived
cultural norms and the functionally defined imperatives of the system
maintenance. Eder’s approach thus allows a more sophisticated understanding of
the ways in which discourse on ecological problems contributes to the historical
production of contemporary society.
Habermas draws an overly restrictive and simple contrast between
emancipatory social movements (bourgeois, labour and socialist etc) concerned
with material reproduction and problems of distribution, and new social
movements concerned with the ‘revitalisation’ of the possibilities for expression
and communication within the lifeworld. Eder on the other hand sees nature as a
field of collective action within which ecological movements engage in defining
76
This is a theme discussed in my examination of the work of theorists such as Nikolas Rose and
Bruno Latour in later chapters.
67
the future direction of social development and modernisation. This changes the
logic of social conflict by mobilising the way in which nature is symbolised as a
‘new cultural model’ for organising social action. (Eder, 1990b p.36-8) Thus
according to Eder it is necessary to distinguish within contemporary
environmentalism between social and cultural movements.77 Social movements in
this approach are understood as the carriers of notions of social progress. Within
the ecological movements this is expressed in the concern to establish a more
rational social relationship to the natural environment. This concern is essentially
a utilitarian one that carries forward, in a new form, the notion of the material
rationality characteristic of the ‘old’ social movements. It seeks to ‘optimise the
relation to nature, to establish a cybernetic state of nature in society.’ (Eder,
1990b p.39) 78
Environmentalism as a social movement in Eder’s sense then, is concerned
with what Weale (1992) calls a new politics of ecological modernisation, that is,
with a more rational and efficient management of the natural and social
environment. 79 According to Weale, the ideology of ecological modernisation is
characterised by the reconceptualisation of the relationship between economy and
environment. In particular, it is argued that avoiding the costs of environmental
protection in the present does not eliminate these costs, but merely transfers these
to future generations. Further, it is argued that environmental protection should
not be seen as an economic burden but a source of future economic value both in
terms of its capacity to contribute to economic growth in an increasingly
technological society and as a source of comparative advantage in a global
market. (Weale, 1992 p.75-9)
Cultural movements do not share this vision of rationalising the management
of nature. Rather these seek to establish a social relation with nature based on a
moral-practical rationality that questions ‘not only the social relations of
production, domination and consumption, but also the symbolic forms serving as
the medium of these social relations.’ (Eder, 1990a p.74; see also Eder, 1990b
p.39) It is in this sense that Eder talks of the counter-cultural aspects of the
ecology movements. Such cultural movements have accompanied social
movements throughout the course of societal modernisation, and as such they are
‘inextricably tied’ to contemporary ecological movements, although always in
potential opposition to the social movements. The ambivalent character of
77
It is perhaps necessary to say that elements of both can co-exist within ecological movements.
78
See also Eder (1990a, p.74; 1993, p.115-8). This is discussed further in Chapter 6 of the current
thesis. Worster (1987a) provides a comprehensive historical account of the utilitarian or bioeconomic aspects of modern ecological thought.
79
It is easy to see the appeal to utilitarian values in this. The appeal to notions of intergenerational equity is a clear example of Eder's justice perspective. I discuss the notion of
ecological modernisation further in Rutherford (1999a). See also Christoff (1996).
68
contemporary environmentalism is therefore a product of the tension between
these two types of movements. Such a distinction is very important for
understanding the contradictory character within environmentalism between
modernising, science-driven discourses and romantic, re-enchanting discourses.
These rival discourses co-exist and co-influence the political and cultural idioms
within which social relations with nature as thematised and expressed. 80
(2) Beck: ecological risk & reflexive modernisation
Whereas Eder is critical of Habermas’ ‘false idealisation’ of a ‘pure systemic
world in social life’ separate from the cultural processes of the lifeworld, (Eder,
1988 p.938) the approach taken by Ulrich Beck sees ecological crisis as the
structurally determined, systemic product of the modernisation process. For Beck
this process is one in which, by the late twentieth century, the expansion of
science and technology has produced a range of historically unprecedented global,
life threatening hazards and risks. Habermas argues that the ‘uncoupling’ of the
functional requirements of system integration, which are directed to the material
reproduction of society, from role of the cultural lifeworld in social integration, is
both the result of the increasing complexity and rationalisation of modern society.
He also this as necessary for the coordination of different types of social action
within such society. (Habermas, 1987 p.153-5, 183-5) Beck, however, claims that
this sort of differentiation reaches a point where the ‘latent side effects’ it
produces start to break-down the bases of both the material reproduction of
society and the separation of the social ‘subsystems of economy, politics, culture’
etc from nature. (Beck, 1992b p.81) As is Eder, Beck too is critical of the tradition
in Western thought that sees an antithesis between nature and society, arguing that
nature is utilised and ‘circulates’ within the social system including its cultural
‘sub-systems’. (Beck, 1992b p.80-2)
Beck nevertheless can be said to argue from within the broad perspectives of a
critical social theory concerned with modernisation and processes of societal
80
Melucci (1989) suggests a similar contrast between ‘technocracy’ and ‘naturalism’. However he
goes on to argue that ‘in highly developed societies the systems of control are being
restructured to integrate the alleged 'naturalness' of needs in support of new models of
conformity promoted, for example, by advertising campaigns based on the mythology of a
'pure' body and a 'natural' and 'healthy' environment. This trend can be resisted only by keeping
open the tension between 'natural' needs and the constraints of social existence. That in turn
requires the recognition that the 'nature' ... within us ... which expresses itself as a site of deeply
felt needs ... is in reality inseparable from the rules and rituals of social life.’ (p.121). However,
it should be noted that while in one sense the romantic or naturalist counter-cultural movements
embrace an expressive, intuitive attitude to nature, these intuitive norms, as Melucci (and
Habermas) implies, are derived from the symbolic resources of social life (the lifeworld) and in
contemporary Western society this includes science as a powerful source of 'cosmology'. This
point is recognised by recent works written from an ecocentric perspective - see in particular
Mathews (1991, p.48-50); Fox (1990, p.252-3); Eckersley (1992 p.114-6).
69
rationalisation. However, unlike Habermas, he is more inclined to see the ‘dark
dimension’ of these processes, and in particular the role performed by science and
knowledge in producing the negative and self-destructive side of progress. He
does however share with Habermas a view of modernity as a collective learning
process possessing an emancipatory potential realisable through the expansion of
the public sphere. As Scott Lash and Brian Wynne suggest in their introduction to
Beck’s Risk Society, the theory of reflexive modernisation developed by Beck can
be viewed as an immanent critique of Habermas. It seeks to take into account the
centrality of ecological problems for contemporary social theory, and does so in a
way that ‘can potentially provide the foundation for the rejection and recasting of
Habermas’ notion of modernisation as (an) Enlightenment project.’ Both Beck
and Eder thus share an appreciation of the existence of a negative dialectic of
progress, which has more in common with Horkheimer and Adorno than with
Habermas.
As with Eder, Beck understands the processes of global modernisation as
producing a new type of society, based on quite different social conflicts to those
of the earlier period of ‘primary industrialisation’ – that is, up to the 1970s. (Beck,
1992b p.20, 22) In common with Eder, it is this new ecological field of conflict
that Beck sees as fundamental to the analysis of contemporary society. This new
phase of modernity is seen by Beck in terms of a systemically induced shift from
problems of wealth distribution to those of risk distribution. According to this
analysis, classical industrial society is primarily organised around addressing
problems of material scarcity. Industrial society, through technological
productivity and the establishment of welfare state mechanisms, has to a
significant degree provided the capacity to meet real material needs. 81
However, the development of the same productive capacity that enables this,
at the very time gives rise to a whole new category of unintended and unforeseen
risks and hazards. According to Beck, in late modernity industrial societies are
less concerned with how to overcome scarcity than with how to limit and
distribute the effects of these systematically produced ‘latent side effects’. This
means that Weber’s notion of rationalisation, as strategic or purposive rationality,
no longer adequately characterises the current phase of the modernisation process,
for along with the expanding productive capacity of science and technology has
come the ‘incalculability of their consequences.’ Thus the unintended, destructive
consequences of technological development become ‘a dominant force in history
and society’, to the extent that the benefits of science and technology in utilising
the resources of nature begin to be overshadowed by the costs of political and
81
Note that Beck specifically identifies this as the situation in the advanced industrial states of the
West. The logic of wealth production and distribution, ie meeting ‘obvious material need’,
remains central to societal modernisation in the less industrialised countries of the ‘Third
World’. See Beck (1992b) p.20.
70
economic management of the risks generated by technology. (Beck, 1992b p.1922)
The potential for ‘self-endangerment’, rather than self-preservation, is
therefore a fundamental feature of this new phase of modern society which Beck
calls risk society. In late modernity ecological and technological risks are of a
completely different character to natural disasters or the risks and hazards of
wealth production in the era of primary industrialisation. These new ecological
‘mega-risks’ 82
induce systematic and often irreversible harm, generally remain invisible,
are based on causal interpretations, and thus initially only exist in terms
of the (scientific or anti-scientific) knowledge about them. They can thus
be changed, magnified, dramatised or minimised within knowledge, and
to that extent they are particularly open to social definition and
construction. Hence the mass media and the scientific and legal
professions in charge of defining risk become key social and political
positions. (Beck, 1992b p.22-3 – original emphasis)
Habermas claims that ecological problems are system-generated abstractions
‘forced upon the life-world’, which require system-based scientific, administrative
and economic solutions. Despite this, protest and resistance to environmental
problems is often a localised response to the ‘tangible destruction’ of the
environment, to the everyday experience of ‘developments that visibly attack the
organic foundations of the life-world’ such as poor urban planning, destruction of
the countryside and the health affects of pollution. (Habermas, 1981c p.35-6) The
problem with this is that Habermas fails to explain how these ‘abstract’,
generalised system-level problems are connected to the everyday perception of
‘specific’ problems in the lifeworld. His earlier treatment of nature in terms of
cognitive interest theory in fact would appear to offer some help in this regard. It
will be recalled that there Habermas characterised external (or objectified) nature
as consisting of ‘possible objects of experience’ which share both a certain
independence and externality, and the ‘produced objectivity’ of a ‘world-
82
The risks Beck refers to are ‘above all radioactivity, which completely evades human perceptive
abilities, but also toxins and pollutants in the air, the water and foodstuffs, together with their
accompanying short- and long-term effects on plants animals and people.’ (Beck, 1992b p.22)
Elsewhere these are defined as including nuclear power, (and) many types of chemical and biotechnological production as well as the continuing and threatening ecological destruction.’
These are described as ‘nuclear, chemical, genetic and ecological mega hazards.’ (Beck, 1992a
p.101-2). I generalise these various manifestations of technological risk as ecological risks.
Such a generalisation while useful for the sake of brevity, is also consistent with Beck's own
inclinations. This is attested to by his use terms such as ‘ecological enlightenment’ and
‘ecological democracy’ in his calls for the strengthening of the public sphere and the creation of
a ‘public science’, which he sees as a necessary political corrective to the potentially selfdestructive production of ‘mega-risks’. See Beck (1992a) p.118-9.
71
constituting’ social practice, or ‘Lebenspraxis’. (Habermas, 1978 p.25-42) 83
However, in moving away from his earlier notion of universalised speciesinterests and towards a concern for systems of action co-ordination, Habermas
also neglects any further elaboration of the thesis of a strong mediation between
‘nature’ and social production of scientific-technical knowledge contained in his
earlier work.
Scientific expertise and the production of risks
Beck places the mediation between nature and science at the centre of his
theory of modernisation. He demonstrates that what constitutes a risk, and the
way in which the consequent hazards are distributed, are discursively defined. The
sorts of global ecological hazards Beck is concerned with, such as depletion of the
stratospheric ozone layer and radiation contamination, are generally not visible or
perceptible in any unmediated way to the every-day experience of the lifeworld.
These sorts of ecological risks and hazards only come into existence through the
objectifying medium of expert judgement. They are not things of simple
experience but in a very strong sense ‘require the ‘sensory organs’ of science theories, experiments, measuring instruments - in order to become visible or
interpretable as hazards at all.’ (Beck, 1992b p.27) Unlike the problems of earlier
industrial society which involved material scarcity, those of late modernity cannot
be overcome by further development of the means of production and
redistributive social welfare. Previously exposure to risk was primarily
determined by class, whereas in late modernity risk is ‘somehow universal and
unspecific’ and no longer produces the sort of social solidarities associated with
class positions. ‘Risk positions’, argues Beck, are constitutive of new
dependencies in which the victims of technologically produced hazards are
rendered ‘incompetent in matters of their own affliction’ as increasingly the power
of judgement and definition is reserved by expert, ‘external knowledge
producers’. Thus on Beck’s analysis, both the substantive and theoretical
production of risks are structurally linked through the knowledge dependent
dynamic of modernisation, in which material conditions of life and the production
of knowledge are fastened tightly together.
Beck characterises risk society as involving the loss of ‘cognitive sovereignty’
by the individual when it comes to ecological hazards. Thus unlike ‘losses in
income and the like’, exposure to ecological threats involves ‘loss of sovereignty
over assessing the dangers, to which one is directly subjected. The whole
bureaucracy of knowledge opens up, with its long corridors, waiting benches,
responsible, semi-responsible, and incomprehensible shoulder-shruggers and
83
See also my discussion of this in the section 'Nature and cognitive interests' in Chapter 3 of this
thesis.
72
poseurs ... (that regulate) ... how one gets access to knowledge, (and) how it
should be done’. (Beck, 1992b p.53-5) This view, while undoubtedly pointing to
the way in which technocratic expertise is not politically accountable to citizens,
also suggests that the lack of such cognitive sovereignty and political
accountability seriously undermines the democratic role of the citizen in risk
society. I turn to a detailed consideration of the issue of sovereignty and related
issues in Chapters 7 to 9.
For Beck the production of risk is not simply a question of the factualmethodological substance of knowledge; rather defining hazards involves both
scientific-theoretical elements and moral-practical ones. 84 The moral component
arises from the statistical character of risk assessments. Risk determinations
combine mathematical probabilities of hazard with calculations of social interests.
Decisions dealing with risks thus not only deal with statements of probability but
are ‘at the same time also decisions defining who is afflicted, the extent and type
of hazard, the elements of the threat, the population concerned, delayed effects,
measures to be taken, those responsible, and claims for compensation.’ (Beck,
1992b p.54) The moral dimensions of risk determination are generally hidden by a
technocratic dynamic that reduces risks to questions of scientific and technical
manageability. Nevertheless, suggests Beck, risk society exaggerates the gap
between scientific and social rationality, while at the same time bringing into
focus the dependence between the two.85
While arguing that the social role of science and technology is central to the
development of risk society, Beck is highly critical of the way in which critics of
technocracy and ecological problems themselves tend to argue from a scientistic
position. He is thus critical of calls for a new ethical approach to science precisely
because this ignores the influence of the ‘logic of technocracy’, that is, the
‘autonomisation of technological development and its interconnections with
economic interests.’ (Beck, 1992a p.106) 86 Science is fundamental to the
production of technological risks while at the same time scientific expertise is
84
Beck claims that the experience of risks ‘presume a normative horizon of lost security ... Behind
all the objectifications, ... the question of acceptance arises and with it anew the old question:
how do we wish to live?’ That is, the issue is not simply the definition of the probability of
hazard, but also definition of degrees of acceptability and the social distribution of risk. See
Beck (1992b) p.27-30.
85
‘The scientific concern with risks of industrial development in fact relies on social expectations
and value judgement, just as the social discussion and perception of risks depends on scientific
arguments. Risk research follows ... in the footsteps of 'technophobia' which it was called up to
restrain, and from which, moreover, it has received an undreamed-of material support in recent
years.’ Beck (1992b) p.30.
86
Calls for an ‘ethical renewal of the sciences’, and towards nature in general, are common to
much Green political thinking. For a discussion of this see Eckersley (1992), especially Chapter
5.
73
given ‘binding authority’ ahead of law and politics, to define risks and specify
how they are to be managed. Thus while there is a monopolisation by scientists
and engineers in diagnosing hazards, the authority of science is constantly
undermined and called into question by its failure to contain or control these
ecological hazards.87 In fact Beck’s thesis is stronger than this, arguing that the
development of theoretical knowledge in the sciences systematically multiplies
analyses of risks while undermining the ‘original claims’ that scientific
management of risk is capable of providing physical security from hazard. (Beck,
1992a p.106-7)
At the same time Beck warns that the debate about ecological risk is largely
conducted in natural scientific terms, in which the problems are seen to be
chemical, biological, technological etc in origin. The debate thus tends to present
human beings ‘only as organic material’, turning into a ‘discussion of nature
without people’. His argument is that the critique of industry and technology
remains fundamentally locked into a naturalistic and technocratic perspective
characterised by a ‘loss of social thinking’. This perspective, Beck suggests, is
held by the political environment movements (in contrast to alternative life-style
movements) as well as by governments. 88 It is a perspective that renders modern
society in terms of the technical domination of nature while obscuring ‘the social,
87
See Yearley (1992) for a discussion of the way in which this creates particular problems for
environmental movements when they seek to use science to legitimate their political objectives.
88
Beck's reference to the ‘political’ environment movement suggests the distinction made by Eder
between the social utilitarian elements of the ecology movement (ie those based on the justice
perspective), and the cultural, ‘alternative lifestyle’ element based on the purity perspective.
However, even these cultural movements, such as ‘deep ecology’ emphasise ethical concern for
the intrinsic moral value of non-human life, but this is still very much based on a scientific
ontology which is taken as the source of its ‘ecocentrism’ (non-anthropocentricism), that is,
such cultural movements employ cultural values derived from a highly scientised lifeworld. The
appeal to science as the source of moral and epistemic authority is evident in the recent works
of ecocentric theorists such as Eckersley, Fox and Mathews. Ecocentric theory is critical of
what it sees as the instrumental, objectifying attitude toward nature adopted by the technocratic
dominant political culture, linking this to an anthropocentric worldview. However these writers
attempt to overcome this not by rejecting science per se, but by calling for a ‘new science’ that
is guided by an ecocentric interest in maintaining the integrity and health of the ecological
system. (Eckersley, 1992 p.114-6) Fox makes a distinction between the instrumental and
cosmological functions of science, suggesting that modern science provides a cosmology that
‘has had profound non-anthropological implications’, enabling green theory to understand ‘our
place in the larger scheme of things’. (Fox, 1990 p.252-3) Mathews, following Naess, argues
for a Spinozan monism as the basis for her theory of the ‘ecological self’ in which science,
stripped of ‘mechanistic assumptions, is a superlative tool for investigating the nature of the
physical world.’ While science cannot be taken as the sole basis of knowledge and truth, it
nevertheless is indispensable to a new ecological worldview. Thus Mathews argues that in
Western cultures environmentalism cannot posses legitimacy and credibility without ‘the
sanction of science’. (Mathews, 1991 p.48-50).
74
cultural and political risks of modernisation’. 89 In this respect Beck’s work can be
said to share with the Frankfurt School, Eder, and to a degree Habermas
(particularly his earlier work), an understanding of nature as historicised. An
important consequence of this view of nature as conditioned and symbolically
mediated by social practices, is the critique of the fetishising of both ‘progress’
and ‘nature’,90 and of the political function of scientific knowledge.
In light of advanced industrial society’s systematic production of ecological
‘mega-hazards’ which threaten the natural foundations of life, Beck argues that
the reappraisal of the relationship between society and nature has become a key
task for social theory. In particular he claims that it is no longer possible to cling
to the nineteenth century notion of an antithesis between nature and society,
which understands nature and society as outside of each other. (Beck, 1992b p.80)
At the end of the twentieth century nature must be understood as an historical
product, thoroughly integrated into and affected by the global system of industrial
production. Such a ‘societalisation’ of nature also means the ‘societalisation of
the destruction and threats to nature’. Under Beck’s approach, environmental
problems serve as the ‘conceptual arrangement’ in which the damage done to
nature through its social appropriation is re-employed as a resource in new types
of social and political conflict. 91 The consequence of this is that ‘in advanced
modernity, society with all its subsystems of the economy, politics, culture and
the family can no longer be understood as autonomous of nature.’ (Beck, 1992b
p.81) At the same time, Beck rejects the naive realism and scientism so evident in
much of the debate about protecting the natural environment. He is direct in his
characterisation of nature as a ‘highly synthetic product’, in that nowhere today is
‘nature’ untouched by human intervention. Similarly, science does not deal with
nature in a purely ‘objective’ manner, but within institutional contexts serving a
‘generalised social claim to the mastery of nature.’ According to Beck therefore,
what is treated there as ‘nature’ is the internal ‘second nature’ brought
into the cultural process, and thus burdened and overburdened with not
89
Beck comments that: ‘it is as if there had never been people such as a certain Max Weber, who
apparently wasted his time showing that without including structures of social power and
distribution, bureaucracies, prevailing norms and rationalities, such a debate is either
meaningless or absurd, and probably both.’ He further pointedly comments, ‘... this absence
seems to strike no one, not even sociologists themselves.’ (Beck, 1992b p.24-5)
90
See Buck-Morss (1977) p.49-56 and Chapter 2 of this thesis for discussion of this aspect of
Horkheimer and Adorno's work.
91
Thus Beck states ‘That means that 'modernisation risks' are the conceptual arrangement, the
categorical setting, in which injuries to and destruction of nature, as immanent in civilisation,
are seized upon socially. In this scenario of conflict, decisions are made as to the validity and
urgency of risks, and the way they will be repressed or dealt with is decided. Modernisation
risks are the scientised 'second morality' in which negotiations are conducted on the injuries of
the industrially exhausted ex-nature in a socially 'legitimate' way.’ (Beck, 1992b p.81)
75
very ‘natural’ system functions and meanings. ... In other words, because
it is a nature circulating and utilised within the system, nature has become
political, even at the objective hands of objective scientists. (Beck, 1992b
p.81-2)
Beck’s analysis of the relationship between nature and society with its
emphasis on the system and its sub-systems of action coordination, is clearly
influenced by the Habermasian framework. Similarly, Beck’s treatment of nature
has much in common with Habermas’ earlier view of objective nature, in which
nature is seen as that which is constituted as an object of human instrumental
action and the scientific knowledge that serves this. (Habermas, 1978) 92 In
particular, Beck’s analysis points to the systematic production of risks in late
modernity as originating in a narrowly economic, ‘techno-scientific rationality’
which he explicitly identifies in Habermasian terms as ‘a type of productivityraising knowledge interest.’93 Yet Beck’s work also enriches Habermas’ analysis.
by demonstrating the ways in which ecological problems, arising from what
appears in Habermas as the largely technical problems of the material
reproduction of society, interconnect with economic and political subsystems as
well as the cultural subsystems Habermas designates as belonging to the
lifeworld.
Much criticism of Habermas relates to the perceived rigidity or abstractness
of his notions of system and lifeworld, and the distinction between his different
categories of rationality. 94 Beck argues that nature cannot be considered
autonomous from society and its subsystems (economy, politics, culture and the
family). Also, as has been indicated above, ‘nature’ for Beck is societalised
nature, which is reproduced and utilised within the social system. In this regard,
Beck can be interpreted as joining the criticism of Habermas’ overly rigid, or in
Eder’s words, ‘false idealisation’, of the separation of system from lifeworld. In
any case, it is clear that Beck wants to show the multiple interconnections
between system and lifeworld, 95 and that in doing this he is far more critical of
92
See my discussion in that section of Chapter 2 of the current thesis headed 'Nature and cognitive
interests'.
93
‘This once again clarifies how a type of productivity-raising knowledge interest (to put it in
Habermas’ terms) prevails historically in scientifically directed technological development, an
interest which is related to the logic of wealth production and remains embedded in it.’ (Beck,
1992b p.60-1)
94
See for example Giddens (1982) p.82-116; Baxter (1987) p.39-86; Eder (1988) p.931-944;
Hayim (1992) p.187-209; Eckersley (1992) p.97-117; Ottmann (1982) p.79-97; Whitebook
(1979) p.41-69; Strydom (1990) p.156-164; Alford (1985b) p.139-177.
95
While it is beyond the scope of the present work to give a detailed account of all aspects of the
relationship of Beck's theory of reflexive modernisation and Habermas’ work, it should be
noted that Beck's work is concerned to explicate the ‘distributional logic of modernisation
risks’ and the impact this has on the various aspects of social structure in advanced industrial
76
the sciences than is Habermas. For example, Beck argues that the origin of the
critique of modern science and technology ‘lies not in the ‘irrationality’ of the
critics, but in the failure of techno-scientific rationality in the face of growing
risks and threats from civilisation.’ (Beck, 1992b p.59) Such a comment can be
interpreted as an implicit criticism of Habermas’ approach to the ecological
movements.
In his limited treatment of environmental problems, Habermas’ inclination is
to characterise ecological movements as part of a wider ‘neo-conservatism’ that
rejects modernity’s ‘reasonable content and its possibilities for the future’.
(Habermas, 1981b p.13-4; Habermas, 1981c p.33-7; Habermas, 1982b p.245-50) I
have suggested that the basis for this stand can be found in Habermas’ claim that
in modernity the differentiation of value spheres requires the application of
instrumental rather than practical reason to human relations with nature.96 He
conceptualises system and lifeworld as distinct domains of action coordination in
which ecological problems are primarily matters of material reproduction.97 In
contrast to this view of ecological movements as essentially anti-modern, Beck
understands them as the result of a growing awareness of the risks produced by
the latest phase of modernity. This awareness Beck attributes both to the
increasing scientisation of risk, and the expanding commerce in risks. (Beck,
1992b p.56) The scientisation of risk undermines a strict separation of system
from lifeworld inasmuch as risk is experienced in an already highly scientised
lifeworld, that is, the perception of modern ecological hazards depends on ‘a
theoretical and hence a scientised consciousness, even in the everyday
society, that is, its impact on social class, work, gender, individual biography, etc. In doing this
Beck 'fleshes out' the connection between 'lifeworld and system' in a way that Habermas only
does at a far more abstract level. Thus Beck comments, ‘Everything which appears separated in
the perspective of systems theory, becomes an integral component of the individual biography:
family and wage labour, education and employment, administration and the transportation
system, consumption, pedagogy, and so on. Subsystem boundaries apply to subsystems, not to
people in institutionally dependent individual situations. Or, expressing it in Habermasian
terms, individual situations lie across the distinction between system and lifeworld. The
subsystem boundaries pass through individual situations which are, so to speak, the
biographical side of that which is separated by system boundaries. Considered in this way, we
are concerned with the individualised institutional situations, whose connections and fractures
(neglected on the level of the system) continually produce frictions, disharmonies and
contradictions within and among individual biographies.’ (Beck, 1992b p.136-7)
96
Habermas claims that there is a ‘basic philosophical question’ of how a non-objectivising
attitude to nature could be ‘adequately grounded today without recourse to the substantial
reason of religious or metaphysical world-views, how it could be grounded at the level of
learning attained in the modern understanding of the world.’ (Habermas, 1982b p.248)
97
Habermas distinguishes problems of material reproduction from the ecological movement's
‘new politics’ concern with the ‘grammar of forms of life’, that is, the question of ‘how to
defend or reinstate endangered life styles, or how to put reformed life styles into practice.’
(Habermas, 1981c p.33).
77
consciousness of risks.’ (Beck, 1992b p.28) Because Beck sees the substantive
production of risks as closely tied to the development of expert scientific
knowledge, he is able to focus on the link between risk production and its
‘cognitive agents’. These cognitive agents comprise not only the those experts
who produce scientific knowledge and its technological applications, but also
those ‘counter-experts’ of the ecological movements etc, responsible for
producing critiques of environmental degradation and technology.
Advanced industrial society thus displays a ‘system immanent’ capacity to
endanger the ecological conditions of its own existence while at the same time
producing a self-referential, or reflexive, ‘questioning of itself through the
multiplication and the economic exploitation of hazards.’ (Beck, 1992b p.56-7) In
this perspective, ecological movements can be seen not so much as opposed to
modernity as an important force for ecological modernisation.98 In Beck’s view,
the influence of such movements derives in large measure from the existence of
systemic contradictions arising from the industrial production and political
administration of risks, which become an object of public concern through the
‘needling activities’ of ecology and citizens groups. In this way, according to
Beck, the counter experts of the ecological movements, in conjunction with mass
media, have taken the thematic initiative and placed the question of ‘the threat to
life’ on the social agenda. (Beck, 1992a p.115-6) 99
What is particularly interesting in Beck’s analysis is the way in which it
connects the concerns of ecological movements, primarily understood by
Habermas as the cultural expression of alternative ‘lifestyles’, with the broader
issues of global political economy, and the relationship between scientific
knowledge and power, in risk society. In so doing Beck provides a more
substantive consideration than does Habermas of the way in which what I have
referred to as the problem of nature gives rise to systemic (or functional)
pressures for ecological modernisation. 100 While this line of argument is not
logically incompatible with Habermas’ systems approach, it is unnecessarily
marginalised by his tendency to see ecological politics as largely isolated to
cultural-aesthetic questions. This a view, which as I have argued, is clearly the
98
This is not a term used by Beck, although he does talk of ‘ecological enlightenment’. See Beck,
(1995a). Beck speaks of ‘reflexive modernisation’.
99
The role of the media is important in Beck's argument: ‘the evening news ultimately exceeds
even the fantasies of countercultural dissent; daily newspaper reading becomes an exercise in
technology critique.’ (p.116) Beck stresses the dependence of such critique on the existence of
certain social conditions which prevail ‘in only a few countries’ (ie the West) such as
parliamentary democracy, material affluence and an independent press, ie it is a product of
liberal democracy.
100
Eder makes a similar point in his discussion of ecological thinking as ‘a radicalisation of
modern economic ideology.’ See Eder (1990a) p.75.
78
result of his attempts to isolate the critique of instrumental reason so as to save an
emancipatory role for reason.
As I have indicated earlier in this section, Beck argues that ecological risks
are characteristic of a new phase of modernisation which brings into being quite
different forms of social differentiation and conflict to those of the earlier period
of primary industrialisation. The conflicts that arise in relation to the ecological
risks of modernisation, while not in themselves conflicts of wealth distribution,
nevertheless are closely connected to the economic subsystem and to problems of
material reproduction. The emergence of ecological risks and conflicts challenge
key notions of industrial society such as ‘progress’, ‘scientific rationality’ and
‘economic growth’. Beck suggests therefore, as does Eder, that ecological
conflicts ‘take on the character of doctrinal struggles within civilisation over the
proper road for modernity’. (Beck, 1992b p.40) This is contrary to Habermas’
view of these movements as conservative and anti-modern per se. 101 Hence
debates that question industrial society’s exploitation of nature raise more than the
moral worth of nature, they also question the monopoly of autonomised and
concealed social change exercised by science and technology under the rhetoric of
progress.
This new ecological field of conflict creates new configurations of power
relations in the global economy in which, at least for the advanced industrial
nations, the elimination of scarcity increasingly tends to be replaced by the
elimination of risk as the rationale of the social system. There is thus a major
difference between the sorts of social antagonisms generated by wealth
production and those created by hazard production. The older antagonisms
between labour and capital, created by problems of scarcity and wealth
distribution, are undermined by the material success of industrialism. At the same
time the systemic technological production of hazards creates new antagonisms,
in which the ‘destruction of nature and destruction of markets coincide’:
‘Threats to nature’ are not only that; pointing them out also threatens
property, capital, jobs, trade union power, the economic foundation of
whole sectors and regions, and the structure of nation states and global
markets. ... (W)ealth production produced antagonisms between capital
and labour, while the systematic chemical, nuclear and genetic threats
bring about polarisation between capital and capital - and thus between
labour and labour - cutting across the social order. (Beck, 1992a p.11011) 102
101
See also Eder, (1990b) p.40, 21 and (1993) p.103-112.
102
Beck notes here that one of the consequences of this is that labour and labour power are no
longer simply understood as sources of wealth production but also as social forces of ‘threat
and destruction’. (p.113) This is reflected in the general critique of industrialism apparent in
79
The distribution and effect of risk does not fall equally. Some sectors of the
global economy and some regions suffer more than others from the destruction of
nature. Thus toxic accidents and pollution can transform particular commercial
interests into economic wastelands. 103 Events such as the Chernobyl nuclear
reactor accident and the Exxon Valdez oil spill are clear examples of such
ecological catastrophes, but more insidious processes, such as loss of fishing
grounds through ocean pollution or loss of agricultural and silvicultural
productivity through acid rain etc are also significant. Ecologically damaged
regions come into existence which transverse the borders of nation states and the
established ‘lines of conflict’ within societies. Global ecological problems,
especially those such as greenhouse gas induced climate change, have the
potential to undermine the economic basis of entire regions and states, leading to
waves of ‘eco-refugees and climatic asylum-seekers’. While global hazards cut
across traditional social class positions, they nevertheless still impact most on the
poorest within these newly defined ecological zones of conflict. (Beck, 1992a
p.110-11) At the same time however, technologically induced risks may also
represent market opportunities, both in terms of such things as pollution control
technology and expanded demand for professional expertise in the areas of
ecological management and environmental assessment and administration. 104
Beck argues that the new social antagonisms of risk society are expressed in a
complex set of ‘tensions between business and the elimination of risks, and
between the consumption and the production of risk definitions’ giving rise to
‘definitional struggles over the scale, degree and urgency of risks.’ (Beck, 1992b
p.46) On one level hazards are the creation of what appears as an autonomous
process resulting from a strictly instrumental use of technology in the production
of commodities. However, these hazards are defined and evaluated not at the level
of the private firm, but socially through a matrix of ‘quasi-governmental power
much Green social analysis. For example see Bahro (1986) p.12-13, 45-8 and Porritt (1894)
p.77-82.
103
Beck suggests that with such catastrophes ‘ ... 'blank spots' on the map arise again in the most
advanced stage of civilisation. ... suddenly discovered toxic waste dumps, transform housing
estates into toxic waste estates and turn farmland into wasteland.’ (Beck, 1992b p.39)
104
The direct cost of complying with the United States' pollution control regulations alone has
beenestimated to be in excess of US$100 billion per year. (Jasanoff, 1992 p.195) While this is a
cost to some sectors of the economy, the supply of equipment and expertise by other sectors
represents significant new market opportunities. For example, the US market for the
commercial treatment, storage and disposal of hazardous waste was valued at $3,000 million in
1997; in the same year environmental remediation and associated consulting cost $8,000
million. (HazNews, 1998 p.1) The European Commission explicitly recognises this: ‘the future
competitiveness of Community industry on world markets will depend heavily upon its ability
to offer goods and services causing no pollution and achieving standards at least as high as its
competitors. ... Technological innovation allied with a commitment to high supply standards
can open up new opportunities, by developing new markets and putting to work the
technologies of the future.’ (Commission of the European Communities, 1986 p.3)
80
positions’ encompassing the debate among scientific experts, in juridical
interpretation, and in the mass media. The transformation of the unintended
consequences of private economic activities into socially defined risks and
hazards is the result of ‘scientific battles’ fought out by ‘intellectual strategies in
intellectual milieux’ over the heads as it were, of the class positions of the
protagonists of the earlier industrial society. In this way the production and
distribution of knowledge is central to the functioning of risk society. (Beck,
1992a p.112-114) 105
Sub-politics: decline of the state as a political centre
However, this definition of risks, while the result of deliberate decisions (and
therefore social in character), is not political in the sense of being defined by
decisions taken in formal political institutions. The political system of industrial
society is premised on a differentiation of parliamentary politics from the ‘nonpolitics’ of the techno-economic pursuit of interests, which is expressed in private
investment decisions and scientific research agendas, and it is primarily in this
context that the decisions which produce ecological risks are made. It is in this
sense that Beck speaks of social change as the autonomised, latent side effect of
scientific and technological decisions in which social change is independent of the
intentions of the formal political institutions. (Beck, 1992b p.183-4) 106 This
process is not a distortion of modernity but rather the result of the success of
rationalisation and progress, and occurs in part, through the equation of social and
economic progress, assumed by modern Western culture. Risk society is thus
shaped by two contradictory processes - the institutionalisation of representative
democracy and the legitimation of the supposed intrinsic value of progress in
scientific and technical knowledge - which leads to far-reaching social changes
‘under the cloak of normality’. The effect of this is to give scientific and
economic development in late modernity the status of a ‘sub-politics’ which is not
subject to institutionalised political authorisation and legitimation. Nevertheless
these constantly produce and magnify the risks which increasingly become the
object of public discourse and over which government is called to act upon. 107
105
‘The social and economic importance of knowledge grows ... and with it the power over the
media to structure knowledge (science and research) and disseminate it (mass media). The risk
society is in this sense also the science, media and information society.’ (Beck, 1992b p.46).
106
While social decisions create ecological risks and hazards, what people do intentionally is
‘something quite different: they assert themselves in the market, use the rules of profit-making,
carry forth scientific and technical inquiry, and in so doing they turn over the conditions of
everyday life.’ (p.184)
107
‘Political institutions become the administrators of a development they neither have planned
for nor are able to structure, but must nevertheless somehow justify.’ (Beck, 1992b p.186-7)
See also Beck (1992a) p.114-5.
81
According to Beck this results in a fundamental transformation of the
character of politics in risk society, leading to three key developments. These are
first, the cultural consensus over the link between scientific-economic
development and progress begins to breakdown. Second the scientifically
generated awareness of ecological and technological risks gives rise to demands
for political control and accountability of processes that lie largely outside the
public sphere. Third, the breakdown of the notion of a political centre that is
capable of controlling the processes of scientific-economic development.
Alongside these there occurs (paradoxically) a simultaneous extension of the
monitoring activity by the state (and mass media and citizen groups) into ever
more intimate levels of plant management. These phenomena are manifestations
of a new phase of modernity Beck labels ‘reflexive modernisation’ in which
industrial society is forced to confront the effects of threats created by its own
technological ‘success’.108
The ‘sub-politics’ status of scientific-economic development undermines the
hitherto unquestioned belief in the inherent link between technological and social
progress. The consensus that technical progress is equivalent to social progress
Beck sees as based in the post-World War Two boom period, which in the
Western industrialised states involved an interlinking of the economic, technical
and social agendas of reconstruction. This consensus relied on the then obvious
fact that increases in productive capacity would lead to an improved material
standard of living. One aspect of this was to ensure that any adverse effects were
regarded as the social consequences of otherwise beneficial technological
development, which could be dealt with in isolation (and retrospectively) through
the political intervention of the welfare state, without interfering with the basic
non-political dynamics of technological development. 109 The post-war growth of
108
Beck defines reflexive modernisation in the following terms: By ‘virtue of its inherent
dynamism, modern society is undercutting its formations of class, stratum, occupation, sex
roles, nuclear family, plant, business sectors and also of course the prerequisites and
continuing forms of natural techno-economic progress. This new stage, in which progress can
turn into self-destruction, in which one kind of modernisation undercuts and changes another,
is what I call the stage of reflexive modernisation. … Reflexive modernisation … is supposed
to mean that a change of industrial society which occurs surreptitiously and unplanned in the
wake of normal, autonomised modernisation and with an unchanged, intact political and
economic order implies the following: a radicalisation of modernity, which breaks up the
premises and contours of industrial society and opens paths to another modernity. …This
concept does not imply (as the adjective ‘reflexive’ might suggest) reflection, but (first) selfconfrontation. … Let us call the autonomous, undesired and unseen, transition from industrial
to risk society reflexivity (to differentiate it from and contrast it with reflection). The ‘reflexive
modernisation’ means self-confrontation with the effects of risk society that cannot be dealt
with and assimilated in the system of industrial society – as measured by the latter’s
institutionalised standards.’ (Beck, 1994 p.2-6)
109
In this situation ‘technological development itself remains undisputed, is closed to (public)
decision-making and follows its own inherent objective logic.’ Beck also points to the role of
the consensus between organised labour and capital as ‘industrial bargaining parties’ in
82
risk-intensive large-scale technologies with their systemic production of global
ecological, nuclear and technological hazards and the ‘incalculability’ of their
consequences, leads increasingly to the situation where these ‘enter into a direct
mutual relationship to collective lifeworlds, outside the industrial arena’. (Beck,
1992b p.203)
This new, knowledge-dependent experience of risks, combined with the
success of the welfare state and formal democratic participation in the West leads
to a new political culture that demands public participation in decision-making in
areas previously outside the political system. In this regard social movements
such as those concerned with ecology can be understood not as the response to
some form of pathological distortion of the communicative and democratic
potential of the modern welfare state, but rather as the product of its success.
(Beck, 1992b p.185) This new political culture arises from the systemically
induced decentralisation of politics brought about by the multiplication of centres
of social and cultural sub-politics, which have the effect of disempowering the
traditional notion of politics with its assumptions of the sovereignty of the state,
parliament and the executive. 110 These centres of sub-politics, which Beck
characterises as including new social movements and citizen action groups, as
well as the mass media and the judiciary, thus broaden the ‘opportunities for
extra-parliamentary monitoring with and against the system.’ (Beck, 1992b p.194
- emphasis added) It is important to note that while this process opens up avenues
for resistance to scientific-economic development, it is still a process of
modernisation which at the same time both decentres and channels the scope of
formal political action. It also creates new opportunities for surveillance and
intervention through the modernisation of the scientific-economic system. (Beck,
1992b p.200)
Beck’s thesis is thus that the increased production and distribution of new
types of risk simultaneously drive the ‘self-politicisation’ of modernity, in which
economic growth and increasing productivity. The objects of dispute between these parties
were those of wealth distribution, which was always approached from a ‘common opposition
to 'hatred of technology', 'Luddism', or 'critique of civilisation'.’ (Beck, 1992b p.202)
110
Beck suggests that ‘the more successfully political rights were fought for, pushed through and
concretely realised in this century, the more emphatically the primacy of the political system
was called into question, and the more fictitious became the simultaneously claimed
concentration of decision-making at the top of the political and parliamentary system. ... Both
the formulation of ... program(s) and the decision-making process, as well as the enforcing of
those decisions, must rather be understood as a process of collective action. ... This implies,
however, that the official decision-making authority of political institutions is necessarily
decentralised. The political-administrative system then can no longer be the only or the central
locus of political events. In tandem with the democratisation, networks of agreement and
participation, negotiation, reinterpretation and possible resistance come into being across the
formal horizontal and vertical structure of authorisations and jurisdictions.’ (Beck, 1992b
p.191-2)
83
‘the concept, place and media of politics’ are altered fundamentally from those
that which prevailed in the earlier phase of industrial society. (Beck, 1992b p.183)
The implications of this for understanding the relation between the problem of
nature, ecological movements, and modernisation is quite different from those that
can be drawn from Habermas’ treatment of these issues. He assumes ecological
problems are largely a side effect of the material reproduction of society and are
amenable to technical solution through improved science and technology and
more efficient administration. Beck’s analysis on the other hand points both to an
integral link between the production of scientific knowledge per se and ecological
hazards, and to a diminution of the capacity of the political-administrative system
to control the production of these hazards. While Habermas sees ecological
movements as an anti-modern reaction to the complexity of the social system,
Beck emphasis is on such movements not only as a product of the latest phase of
modernity but also as a force for further modernisation. Equally important is
Beck’s view that reflexive modernisation undermines the notion of the relative
autonomy of the political-administrative system from the economic system, and of
both of these from social and cultural spheres. Habermas’ approach suggests that
the weakening of the formal institutions of parliamentary democracy and welfare
state, along with the rise of new social movements should be seen as elements of
what he calls the ‘new obscurity’. In contrast to this, Beck argues that the
processes of modernisation are already bypassing the modernity Habermas seeks
to ‘complete’.
(3) Luhmann: ecological communication & functional
differentiation
The theme of the lack of a political ‘centre’ to contemporary Western society,
evident in Beck’s work, also plays a key role in the work of Niklas Luhmann.111
However, whereas Beck suggests that this leads to a reflexive modernity with the
potential to reinvent politics through the ‘self-criticism of risk society’, (Beck,
1992b p.183-236; Beck, 1994 p.51-55) Luhmann is far more pessimistic about the
possibility of a rational coordination of societal responses to ecological problems.
Contrary to the approach of Beck and Eder, he argues that the various social
subsystems are largely functionally autonomous. (Sciulli, 1994 p.44)
As with Beck, Luhmann does not situate ecological problems in nature, but
within society. More specifically, he is concerned with developing a systemstheoretical understanding of the manner in which social systems become aware of,
and communicate, the differences between themselves and their environment.
Luhmann’s work is discussed only briefly here. While his work does touch on the
111
A version of the following section of this Chapter previously appeared in Rutherford (1999a)
p.106-109.
84
issues raised in this and previous chapters, his approach offer little of the insights
available from Eder, Beck or indeed Habermas. Nevertheless, Luhmann’s work,
and in particular his book Ecological Communication, (Luhmann, 1989)
represents a significant attempt to consider ecological issues within the context of
contemporary systems theory. As I argue in Chapter 6, systems theory has been
influential in ecological thinking over the past fifty years, and this influence does
spill over into attempts at linking social theory to environmental concerns.
The distinction between system and environment is one of two key concepts
in Luhmann’s system theory. Here the concept of environment is understood at a
very general level to refer to the context in which the ‘operationally closed’, selfreferential, functional subsystems of society (the scientific, legal, political and
economic systems, etc) operate as self-reproducing entities. Luhmann defines
these functional subsystems as autopoietic,112 to indicate ‘that the system is the
product of its own activity (work), and not simply self-sufficient activity as such’.
(Sciulli, 1994 p.14) The autopoietic nature of functional subsystems is therefore
determined, not by external environmental influences, but by the intrinsic primary
goal of all such self-reproducing systems – ‘the continuation of autopoeisis
without any concern for the environment’. (Luhmann, 1989 p.14 - emphasis
added) A second pivotal concept for Luhmann’s theory is the substitution of
‘communication’ for ‘action’ as the most basic operation of functional systems, in
which communication becomes the medium through which self-referentiality is
produced and sustained. Communication is the process whereby social systems
constitute themselves by observing themselves. Hence, the environment for
Luhmann is ‘anything which social communication can refer to.’ (Miller, 1994
p.104)
When Luhmann does specifically address problems of ecology, his concern is
to examine how modern societal subsystems react to these types of problems and
to explain why ‘society’ has difficulty in perceiving and managing them
appropriately. (Luhmann, 1989 p.33-5) His approach to these questions is shaped
by a view of modern society as an assemblage of highly differentiated functional
subsystems that lack of any central mechanism to control these subsystems, other
than the uncoordinated reactions or autopoietic adjustments (‘resonance’) of each
to the interference of the others. (Sciulli, 1994 p.47) This is so because each of the
subsystems is directed to performing a relatively limited social function; for
example, the subsystem of economy is narrowly concerned with prices and
payments, rather than with the broader environment.
Luhmann argues that subsystems operate with a set of binary codes, which
specify the ways in which reality becomes the subject of communication. Codes
specify values and counter-values (in law: legal/illegal, in science: true/false) and
112
This is a concept taken from the work of Maturana and Varela in theoretical biology.
85
operate so as to exclude other possible ways of ordering reality. (Luhmann, 1989
p.44-5) Subsystems react to their environments (which include the other
subsystems) only in the terms set out by these binary codes. It is only through
these codes that systems are able to self-referentially differentiate themselves
from their environment. Because the functional subsystems likewise can only
discern and respond to environmental disturbances in terms of their own internal
codes and meanings, the possibility of resonance between different subsystems is
restricted to what can be communicated across subsystems as meaningful. Thus,
‘each system has a different access to itself than to its environment which it can
only construct internally.’ (Luhmann, 1994 p14)
Several significant consequences flow from Luhmann’s approach. First, talk
of exposure to ecological risks is possible only where there is resonance, or
reaction, by a social subsystem to events in its environment, including the other
subsystems. Given that systems can respond only in accordance with their own
particular structures or codes, ecological risks can be perceived by society only as
exclusively internal phenomena. Physical and biological ‘objective facts’ have no
social effect (resonance) unless they are the subjects of communication. Luhmann
thus argues that society cannot communicate directly with its environment, but
instead can ‘only communicate about its environment’ within itself. (Luhmann,
1989 p.28-31) The key question that results from this, is how does society
structure the way it deals with environmental information? Here Luhmann points
to an apparently insoluble paradox. Modern society, as a highly differentiated set
of functional subsystems, structures communication about itself through binary
codes, so that resonance between society and its environment is always directed
through one of the functional subsystems and their associated programs (scientific
theories, legal rules, etc). The differentiation of society is a result of its increasing
complexity; yet the mechanisms for dealing with this complexity (functional
subsystems, coding, etc) operate by reducing information, that is, by
simplification. (Luhmann, 1989 p.18-9)
Here Luhmann is of course pointing to the reductive character of modern
expert knowledge systems. He rejects those (such as Husserl) who criticise
modernity on the basis of its tendency towards a one-dimensional
‘technicalisation (that) forgets the ‘lifeworld’.’ (Luhmann, 1994 p.17) Such
technicalisation is a fundamental characteristic of modern science, and in a move
similar to that adopted by Habermas, Luhmann dismisses the critique of science
and technology on this basis as a futile exercise. (Habermas, 1982b; Luhmann,
1994 p.18) In much the same way as Beck, Luhmann also rejects attempts to base
solutions to ecological problems on some new form of environmental ethics.
(Beck, 1992a; Luhmann, 1989 p.xvii) Neither is a solution to be found in science,
for, as a function subsystem, it cannot provide ‘meaningful’ solutions that would
be recognised within other subsystems (politics, law etc). Paradoxically, the
functional complexity of modern society relies on the ability of science (and other
86
subsystems) to reduce the epistemic complexity of the world through codification.
Science and technology thus construct simplifications that are then
‘experimentally’ reinserted into the world as a ‘simplification that works’, but
only within its own subsystem domain. (Luhmann, 1994 p.18) Why these should
‘work’ is of course a significant problem in itself. The way in which scientific
simplifications are translated from the laboratory into the broader society is a key
issue that shall I return to in Chapter 8, where I consider the work of Latour and
actor network theory.
Eder’s criticism of Habermas’ rigid separation of system and life-world
applies with even greater force to Luhmann’s systems theory. Similarly, the
aspect of Beck’s work which make it both potentially theoretically interesting and
useful - the elaboration of the connections between science and politics - is
systematically discounted by Luhmann. As a result of this, Luhmann appears to
effectively reject the ability of politics to offer any solution to ecological
problems. Luhmann carries Habermas’ relegation of ecological problems to the
status of skirmishes at the interface between system and life-world even further.
Indeed, it is possible to argue that for Luhmann ecological problems amount to
little more than system-generated ‘noise’, which is incapable of providing a
meaningful basis for coordinated action across subsystems and across an
increasingly complex environment. Beck (1994) is highly critical of Luhmann’s
argument regarding the self-referentiality of functional subsystems. He suggests
that the autonomy of subsystems in Luhmann’s systems theory elevates the notion
of self-referentiality ‘to the level of virtual autism’. (p.24-5)
Conclusion
In contrast to the limited scope for ecological ‘communication’ between the
political and scientific subsystems afforded by Luhmann’s work, both Eder and
Beck suggest that the processes of late modernity systematically multiply the
interactions between science, technology and politics. Both of these writers
suggest that the focus of politics has moved away from the formal politicaladministrative institutions of the state as the centre of political action and power.
Each in his different way points to an understanding of politics that acknowledges
the central role of the capacity to define and structure social actions through the
‘definition making power’ of expert knowledge and a range of sub-politics that
operate beyond the formal institutional structures of the political system. Such a
perspective of ‘government’ beyond the state is of course a central theme in the
work of Michel Foucault. Foucault’s view of modern power as ‘biopolitics’ and
his notion of governmentality are considered in detail the following chapters,
where I argue that such an approach is capable of providing significant theoretical
insights into the contemporary problematisation of the natural environment.
87
Chapter 5
Foucault and critical theory: the debate on power
Introduction
Previous chapters have sought to examine the links in contemporary social
theory between notions of societal rationalisation and modernisation, and
relationship of these to the problem of nature. The current chapter introduces
discussion of the work of Michel Foucault, in particular the pivotal debate
between Foucault and Habermas on power and rationality. Following an initial
examination of this important theoretical dispute, I consider, in a somewhat more
general sense, Foucault’s relationship to the broad tradition of critical thinking
that extends from Weber to Habermas, and which characterises modernity in
terms of processes of societal rationalisation. The aim of the current chapter is to
provide the theoretical setting for a detailed consideration, in subsequent chapters,
of Foucault’s notions of biopolitics and governmentality, and of whether these
provide the basis for reconceptualising the contemporary ecological
problematisation of nature in terms of such biopolitics.
Foucault: modern power and rationality
It can be argued that like both the Frankfurt School and Weber, Foucault’s
work also demonstrated a general concern with the processes of rationalisation in
society. (Grumley, 1989 p.183-227; Rabinow, 1984a p.13) However, unlike this
German social theory, Foucault’s work did not start with the threat posed by
instrumental rationality to the freedom and autonomy of the human subject.
Rather he was concerned with demonstrating how such technical rationalisation
and other objectifying processes produced the human subject in its modern form.
Thus from the outset Foucault’s project is not concerned with realising the
Enlightenment ideal of the emancipation of the subject,113 but rather with
explaining how the application of rationality in particular historical relations of
power and knowledge gave rise to the modern subject. His task was not the
realisation or completion of the ‘project of modernity’ but understanding the
facticity, or more accurately, the genealogy, of modernity itself. (Foucault, 1984b
p.38-50; Foucault, 1991c p.102-4)
113
I qualify this statement in later Chapters of this thesis, especially Chapter 7, where I argue that
Foucault fails to make as complete a break with the ideals of the autonomy of the subject as is
sometimes suggested.
88
Like Habermas, Foucault was also deeply occupied with the question of
‘communicative action’. Habermas’ concern is to articulate a largely transcontextual, and in some respects transcendental, theory of communicative reason,
whereas Foucault’s approach can be seen as concerned with analysing
communicative, or more accurately, discursive practices as inseparably linked to
relations of power. Thus while both share a concern with the question of language
and the conditions under which discourse occurs, they approached the problem
from different ontological assumptions. For Habermas the operation of power is
linked to the domination of instrumental or technical rationality over practical
reason. It is associated with the distortive effect of ideology in concealing the
ways in which human autonomy can assert itself. Foucault, on the other hand,
regarded power as the matrix in which social relations and social practices
become possible and function. Power is thus ‘coextensive and continuous with
life...(and)...is linked with a production of truth.’ (Foucault, 1982 p.214) Unlike
the ideologiekritik of critical social theory, which sees power as mystifying and
distortive of truth, Foucault’s understanding of power focused on the capacity of
power to effectively define ‘regimes of truth’, that is, as productive of ‘truth’ as
opposed to ‘falsity’. (Gordon, 1980a p.237; Hoy, 1986 p.123-147)
As a consequence of these differences, Foucault’s work may be characterised
by a series of closely interconnected concerns – understanding the historical
constitution of the subject, the problem of the relationship between power and
knowledge, and rationalities of government. In his essay ‘The Subject and
Power’, Foucault outlined three modes of objectification through which human
beings are constituted as subjects. The first of these was the objectifying of human
being through making it the object of various types of formalised, scientific
knowledge. Second, the objectifying of human being through ‘dividing practices’
whereby the subject is divided within itself and from others. Third, the processes
by which human beings ‘turn themselves’ into subjects. (Foucault, 1982 p.208)
These objectifying processes, in one form or another, lie at the core of Foucault’s
extensive work.
Foucault understood the disciplines of the human sciences as discursive
practices that define, in a more or less systematic manner, the objects within their
domain. Foucault argued that these scientific discourses, (covering the same
domains of ‘life, labour and language’ singled out by Habermas) 114 underwent
abrupt changes in the way statements were formulated and accepted as true,
contrary to a progressivist view of the growth of knowledge. His analysis of these
discourses indicates they displayed a certain internal coherence and autonomy
114
In The Order of Things Foucault examines the emergence of the what he calls the ‘modern
episteme’, linking this to the birth of the human sciences, through a detailed examination
which juxtaposes the analysis of grammar, natural history and economic thought in the
Classical and Modern periods. (Foucault, 1970)
89
while being firmly embedded in historically specific disciplinary practices and
institutional contexts. (Rabinow, 1984a p.8-9) In treating ‘discursive formations’
in this way, Foucault argued that the knowledges produced by the human sciences
cannot be regarded as true in a universal sense, but must be seen as socially
contingent and in some respects closer to ‘ideology’ than ‘fact’ in a realist sense.
115
In works such as Discipline and Punish and Madness and Civilisation,
Foucault dealt with the varied processes, particularly the expansion of the human
sciences, by which modern society progressively classified, controlled and
confined parts of the social world. Of particular interest to Foucault were the ways
in which the human body became the object of both these scientific discourse and
‘dividing practices’, ie practices of social objectification and categorisation.
Through a combination of the classificatory power of scientific discourse and
exclusory social practices, such as confinement, the social and personal identity of
the subject is structured.
The last of these modes of objectification identified by Foucault can be
described, following Rabinow (1984b), as ‘subjectification’. In the other two
modes of objectification, the subject is treated primarily as a docile body that is
defined, divided and confined by externally operating disciplinary and discursive
forces. (Foucault, 1979b p.135-169) Subjectification by contrast is essentially a
self-formative process, involving the active participation of the subject in its own
constitution, through a process of self-understanding that is frequently ‘mediated
by an external authority figure, be he confessor or psychoanalyst’. (Rabinow,
1984b p.11) Foucault’s notion of subjectification thus breaks with the traditional
subject-object ontology in that subjectivity is no longer privileged as the centre of
human autonomy. Technologies of power (the techniques of administration,
definition and control of the subject) both result from an active process of
subjectification of the self by the self, as well as from processes of objectification
of the self by others. This is significant because it means abandoning of the notion
that power distorts or represses an underlying, essential human subjectivity. It
indicates, in other words, that these objectifying and subjectifying processes do
not distort the ‘true’ nature of human beings, but in fact create the truth of the
subject. (Foucault, 1979b p.194)
Foucault’s work examined the historical emergence, since the seventeenth
century, of what he referred to as disciplinary practices or technologies of power.
This, he argued, was a modern form of power differing substantially from the
earlier sovereign power of the monarch. Sovereign power dealt with its subjects in
a singular and relatively uniform fashion. The everyday life of individuals was not
115
Foucault was nevertheless highly critical of the notion of ideology particularly as used in
Marxist theory. See Foucault (1980d) p.117-9 and Barrett (1991) p.123-156.
90
tightly regulated by the sovereign, and the assertion of power when it occurred
involved intervention, often in the form of violent spectacle, in order to
symbolically demonstrate that power. Disciplinary power on the other hand
represented a new technique, a new type of power:
This form of power applies itself to immediate everyday life which
categorises the individual, marks him by his own individuality, attaches
him to his own identity, imposes a law of truth on him which he must
recognise and which others have to recognise in him. It is a form of power
which makes individuals subjects. (Foucault, 1982 p.211-212)
Foucault identified three key elements to this new disciplinary power hierarchical observation, normalising judgement and the examination.
Hierarchical observation established a connection between visibility and power in
such a way that the ‘apparatus of surveillance’ produces the effect of power, and
through which the subjects of power are rendered ‘visible’ as the target of power.
The power of these hierarchical modes of observation is inherent to the apparatus
of continuous surveillance and the control of the spatial distribution of the bodies
of subjects. Foucault saw this sort of normalising judgement as an ‘extra- or infralegal penalty’ brought to bear over non-conforming behaviours, through which the
separation of normal from abnormal or deviant behaviour can be effected. The
effectiveness of this form of power does not come primarily from ‘repression’, but
rather through ‘gratification’ and reward for the adoption of ‘normal’ modes of
being and doing. Disciplinary power both specifies the range of key behaviours
that go towards constituting the individual and directs attention towards the
implementation of normalised (and normalising) behaviour. The other element of
modern power, the examination, brings together surveillance and judgement in
what Foucault referred to as the ‘normalising gaze’, a technique or practice
through which individuals are classified so as to constitute a population, against
the norms of which they are judged and regulated. (Foucault, 1979b p.189-90)
Central to Foucault’s concept of the examination is the creation of the individual
as a ‘case’ about which information is recorded and statistically incorporated into
data archives that are then used in programs of management for both the
individual and the larger population. Foucault made the point that this represented
the beginning of the ‘sciences of man’, and in the process increasingly brought
ordinary, everyday human existence into the descriptive domain of the formalised
discourses of the human sciences.
This modern form of power also refined the Christian practice of confession,
and incorporated it into that older technique of subjectification described by
Foucault as pastoral power. Characteristic of the Christian pastoral was its use of
individualisation aimed at spiritual salvation. Pastoral power sets up a situation of
constant self-examination, of opening up the individual’s inner-most being to the
scrutiny of conscience and through this the self-conscious submission to the will
and direction of a superior being (mediated through the confessor). This was not a
91
matter of self-examination as a means to self-mastery in the interests of the polity
as understood by the Greeks, but a question of overcoming illusions within the
self, of a constant examination of one’s own conscience and thoughts in order to
realise the pure Christian self. (Foucault, 1981c p.236-40) Thus according to
Foucault, the pastoral technique becomes a constitutive element in the formation
of the subject, by establishing a ‘link between total obedience, knowledge of
oneself, and confession to someone else’. (Foucault, 1981c p.239) For Foucault,
the modern state came to adopt a new, non-ecclesiastical form of this pastoral
power, a ‘matrix of individualisation’ in which spiritual salvation was
increasingly replaced by a civil salvation of physical well-being and social
security. With this appropriation of the techniques of pastoral power came an
expansion of the social field, resulting in a new configuration of individualising
power that focused on the development of knowledge of human beings on two
levels: ‘one, globalising and quantitative, concerning the population; the other,
analytical, concerning the individual.’ (Foucault, 1982 p.215)
In considering the specific nature of power, Foucault pointed out that power is
more than simply a relationship between agents. Relationships of communication
and relationships involving the technical capacities of bodies and instruments to
manipulate things, are not in themselves relations of power, although they may,
and often do, interact in a concerted way with relations of power so as to
constitute blocks of interaction that Foucault described as ‘disciplines’. (Foucault,
1982 p.217-219) Foucault’s view of power was strongly relational. Power
relations are fundamentally constituted in social interaction; they are not to be
understood as ‘superstructural’ or ideological. Power is not synonymous with
‘force’, ‘violence’ or ‘capacity’, all of which act directly upon bodies and
things.116 The defining feature of a relationship of power says Foucault, is that it is
a network of relationships, a ‘mode of action’:
which does not act directly and immediately on others ... It is a total
structure of actions brought to bear upon possible actions ... (It is) a way
of acting upon an acting subject or acting subjects by virtue of their acting
or being capable of acting. (Foucault, 1982 p.219-220)
In this approach subjects must therefore be free to act, and are able to do so as
long as the field of possibilities for action remains open. The relationship between
subjects, said Foucault, is a dynamic tension, an ‘agonism’. Furthermore, the
configuration of relations of power within any particular social context is a
historical product, and as such, specific relations of power are neither necessary
nor immutable, but rather open to transformation and change. Foucault’s concept
116
In Chapter 7 I discuss the distinction Foucault made between ‘power’ and ‘capacity’ and
criticise this as adopting an unnecessarily ‘positivist’ attitude towards the natural sciences
which is not consistent with his approach to the human science.
92
of power therefore consisted of far more than the negative power of domination
and repression. (Foucault, 1980e p.98)
Foucault did of course concede that power relations often result in relations of
domination and methods of subjugation, ‘even violent means of material
intervention’. (Foucault, 1980e p.96) Nevertheless, rather than conceiving of
relations of power as primarily repressive, he sought to understand the productive
modes of subjection as central to the formation of modern subjects and the
knowledge of them as embodied in the human sciences. He was therefore
concerned with the mechanisms of objectification and subjectification outlined
earlier this section. In these processes there can be recognised a ‘positive’ or
productive aspect of power relations that produces and transforms knowledge,
truth, discourse, and emotion. (Foucault, 1980d p.119) 117 Individuals (and groups)
are not merely the docile objects on which power operates, but also the result of
complex networks of social relations through which power is exercised and
articulated. Foucault’s genealogical approach to the constitution of power,
knowledge/discourse and subjectivity is thoroughly historical and social while
seeking to dispense with notion of the subject as founded on some
transcendentally given quality. 118 Foucault thus shared with Habermas a desire
not to rely on the philosophy of the subject or consciousness in understanding the
modern individual. As with Habermas, he too made use of a concept of
differentiated rationality, but again, rather than invoking a ‘categorical’ division
of rationality, 119 Foucault’s approach was a functional one in which the
significant forms of rationality were historically specific strategies, technologies
and programs of power. According to Colin Gordon, these three general forms of
rationality served as a means of
conceiving relations of power in terms of the differential and
differentiated interaction between distinct orders of historical events. In
order to understand these concepts, it is necessary to keep in mind a basic
distinction between three such general orders of events: that of certain
forms of explicit, rational, reflected discourse; that of non-discursive
social and institutional practices; and that of certain effects produced
within the social field. (Gordon, 1980a p.246)
117
Foucault asserts that ‘One of the prime effects of power (is) that certain bodies, certain
gestures, certain discourses, certain desires, come to be identified and constituted as
individuals.’ See also Foucault (1982) p.220-223. For discussion on this see Patton (1989)
p.260-276 and Krips (1990) p.170-182.
118
For possibly the clearest statement of the social nature of Foucault's notion of power see his
essay ‘The Subject and Power’ (Foucault, 1980d).
119
I refer here to Habermas’ Kantian differentiation of rationality into instrumental, practical and
critical categories.
93
Foucault was not suggesting that disciplinary power constituted a regime of
total domination. Rather it provided a tool for identifying the disjuncture between
the orders of discourse, practice and effects, and focused attention on the
significance such discrepancies might have for the development of specific
historical formations of power/knowledge. In effect said Foucault, there existed a
dynamic, reciprocal relationship between power and ‘strategies of struggle’, in
which there was always thus ‘a perpetual linking and a perpetual reversal.’
(Foucault, 1980d p.226) 120 Programs and technologies of power in Foucault's
work relate to the formation and reproduction of subjects and relations of power,
whereas strategy was the ‘instrumentalisation’ of the reality created by these
programs and technologies. (Gordon, 1980a p.250-251) Understood in this way
strategy signifies a non-discursive, ‘anonymous’ rationality in that while these
involve struggle or ‘agonism’ between subjects, there is no sovereign subject or
centre that can be said to consciously program or orchestrate the playing out of
this dynamic. Foucault thus argued that all power relations imply, at least
potentially, a ‘strategy of struggle’, and that a ‘strategy proper to power relations
(exists) insofar as they constitute modes of action upon possible action, the action
of others.’ (Gordon, 1980a p.225) Thus a strategy of power is the interplay of
programs and technologies of power, along with the ‘historical decipherment’ of
the potential for employment of the effects of these same programs and
technologies of power. (Foucault, 1982 p.225-6; Gordon, 1980a p.246-258)
The argument that power operates through anonymous, ‘centre-less’ strategies
has much in common with the approaches of theorists discussed in other chapters.
In particular it recalls the work of Ulrich Beck, who points to the ‘autonomised’
direction of social development by the interaction of technological and market
forces. Similarly, it resonates with the work of Bruno Latour and his colleagues,
who I discuss in later chapters, when they argue that agency should be understood
as a network-like property of the interaction of human actions and the capacities
of material technologies. In all of these bodies of work there can be found
attempts to account for the three ‘general orders of events’ referred to by Gordon
(ie explicit, rational discourses; non-discursive institutional practices; and the
effects these produce within the ‘social field’). It could be claimed that Habermas’
work also attempts to come to grips with these issues, but as I have argued the
abstractness of his theory defeats this.
120
In this work (ie 1980d) Foucault adds that ‘The consequence of this instability is the ability to
decipher the same events and the same transformations either from inside the history of
struggle or from the standpoint of the power relationships. The interpretations which result will
not consist of the same elements of meaning or the same links or the same types of
intelligibility, although they refer to the same historical fabric and each of the two analyses
must have reference to the other.’
94
In the next section I consider Habermas’ dispute with Foucault on the nature
of power. Habermas’ deficient view of power contributes substantially to his
overall inability to appreciate both the degree to which the problem of nature
reflects fundamental issues of the reproduction of the social system, and the
importance of ecological movements and discourses in shaping responses to these
issues.
Foucault and Habermas: the debate on power
At the end of Chapter 2, I dealt with Habermas’ response to Horkheimer and
Adorno’s treatment of the ‘dialectic of enlightenment’. Habermas argues that
Horkheimer and Adorno’s critique of instrumental reason parallels Nietzsche’s
critique of morality and scientific knowledge, in that both ultimately understand
morality and truth as expressions of the drive for self-preservation and
domination. This reduction of knowledge and morality to the Nietzschean will to
power, in Habermas’ view, undermines the basis for objective or universal claims
to intersubjective validity, and therefore the basis of meaningful critique itself.121 I
indicated that this criticism of Horkheimer and Adorno also highlights the key
theoretical differences between Habermas and Foucault. It is now necessary to
turn to a more specific consideration of the differences between Habermas and
Foucault, and to what I consider as the most significant deficiency of Habermas’
critical theory - his overly abstract and limited understanding of power. In
considering the ‘debate’ between Habermas and Foucault on this point, 122 I argue
that Foucault’s approach to the relationship between power and knowledge is far
more satisfactory than Habermas’. The usefulness of Foucault’s theoretical
approach, with specific reference to problem of nature and biopolitics, is a theme
that is then taken up more detail in Chapter 6 of this thesis.
Habermas’ critique of Foucault is most systematically developed in two
essays published in The Philosophical Discourse on Modernity. (Habermas, 1985
p.238-265, 266-293) Here, following the line of attack deployed against
Nietzsche, Horkheimer and Adorno in other essays in this collection, he criticises
Foucault on three methodological grounds: ‘presentism’, relativism and ‘cryptonormativism’, which he sees as leading to a lack of political commitment and
conservatism. (Habermas, 1985 p.276; Isenberg, 1991 p.301) By presentism
Habermas designates a methodological failure in Foucault’s approach that, while
seeking to ‘eliminate the hermeneutic problematic’ through adoption of a strictly
external, ‘structural’ standpoint for analysis of power relations, fails to achieve
‘objectivity’. Instead, argues Habermas, Foucault cannot escape the inevitable
hermeneutic pre-understandings that lies behind all historical analysis. By
121
122
See Chapter 2 of current thesis and Habermas (1982a).
Others of course largely carry on this ‘debate’.
95
refusing to confront this, claims Habermas, Foucault cannot admit that he
described the emergence of modern domination in terms of ‘the very biopolitics’
he seeks to explain, thus producing histories that are ‘narcissistically oriented’
toward the use of the study of the past ‘for the needs of the present’. (Habermas,
1985 p.277-8) Of course, far from seeing this as a criticism, Foucault in fact
explicitly saw it as one of the tasks of his work. 123
Habermas’ second charge is that Foucault’s historiography falls into
relativism. Foucault defined truth as internal to the discourses that produce it, with
the result that, in Habermas’ view, ‘the meaning of validity claims consists in the
power effects they have.’ (Habermas, 1985 p.279) Historical analysis therefore
can only reveal a functional ‘self-maintenance’ of discursive practices. As a
consequence of this concealed self-referentiality, Foucault’s attempts to create a
counter-knowledge to the human sciences, which would give voice to subjugated
local forms of knowledge, is self-defeating for the reason that ‘every
counterpower’ is itself an expression of power. Hence argues Habermas, the
overthrowing of existing hierarchies of knowledge by subjugated ones merely
establishes a new hierarchy that cannot lay claim to a validity or truth content that
would ‘transcend local argument’. (Habermas, 1985 p.281) As Janicaud indicates,
in this second prong of his attack on Foucault’s relativism, Habermas shifts his
criticism from the empirical to the transcendental by attempting to ‘unmask a
second-degree relativism which is the inverse of self-justification (ie his first
criticism): a self-reference which is self-defeating.’ (Janicaud, 1992 p.288)
The third of Habermas’ criticisms is that of ‘crypto-normativism’. Here he
claims that Foucault suffered from the same problem of which he accuses the
human sciences. Thus he argued that while Foucault’s genealogy sought to
bracket itself off from value judgement and adopt a purely descriptive attitude,
Foucault nevertheless clearly adopted particular normative positions but refuses to
engage in any serious theoretical discussion as to their justification. Instead
Foucault appeared to present engagement in terms of strategic resistance and the
mobilisation of local counterpower. Habermas argues that despite Foucault’s
refusal to engage in the ‘counter-discourse’ within modernity, he surreptitiously
locates the justification for resistance in a vitalistic ‘Lebensphilosophie’ based in
‘the body’s experience of itself’ as subjected to disciplinary force of biopower, a
position that he nevertheless rejected in his writings. (Habermas, 1985 p.285)
Habermas’ three criticisms are in fact the same charge expressed from the various
standpoints of signification, truth and value. (Janicaud, 1992 p.291) All three
criticisms focus on the alleged inability of Foucault’s theory in providing a secure,
123
Thus in discussing his work on psychiatric hospitals, Foucault insists ‘My work was
undertaken only as a function of those conflicts. The problem and the stake there was the
possibility of a discourse which would be both true and strategically effective, the possibility
of a historical truth which could have a political effect.’ (Foucault, 1980c p.64)
96
universalisable grounding for claims to truth and validity which Habermas’
regards as fundamental to the possibility of critique.
Habermas sees these methodological problems as deriving for a ‘systematic
ambiguity’ running through Foucault’s notion of power. He argues that Foucault’s
genealogy served both an empirical function of analysing the historical formation
of technologies of power, and a metatheoretical role that sought to explain the
transcendental conditions under which any scientific knowledge is possible.
(Habermas, 1985 p.274) Habermas sees these two tasks as separate and
irreconcilable, claiming that Foucault’s unacknowledged reliance on a
transcendental and ‘unsociological’ Nietzschean notion of power underpins the
‘empirical shortcomings’ of his work. Habermas is perhaps correct to point to the
metaphysical-transcendental element of Foucault’s concept of power, inasmuch as
it is based on the notion of a will to truth, although Foucault’s position on this is
ambiguous. Foucault argued that the form of power he was concerned with is a
modern development that arises at a particular historical juncture. He also insisted
that his studies ‘always analyse quite precise and localised phenomena: for
example, the formation of disciplinary systems in eighteenth-century Europe.’
(Foucault, 1991b p.167) However, having established that the form of disciplinary
power he is concerned with has a historical genesis, he did often tend to speak of
it as a ‘modality of intervention’, that is, as a generalised type of political
technology, as a ‘diagram’ or ‘schema’, as ‘panopticism’.124 However, Habermas’
criticism is somewhat weakened by his own reliance on equally metaphysical
assumptions about the ontological primacy of communicative reason, which he
(similar to Foucault) identifies as the product of a particular set of historical
conditions (modernity) but which once in existence take on a universal, ‘quasi’
transcendental function.
As I have indicated, the crux of Habermas’ criticism is the charge that
Foucault’s theory of power undermines the possibility of an emancipatory critique
of power. The source of the problem is that he sees Foucault’s use of power as
‘reversing’ the relationship between truth and power, so that truth becomes
dependent on power. (Habermas, 1985 p.274) This is problematic for Habermas’
theory precisely because he remains bound to a traditional view of power as
domination, as repressive, a view enunciated not only in Habermas’ own works,
but also spelt out in detail by critics such as Taylor and Fraser. 125 Habermas
criticises Foucault for failing to differentiate between the will to power and the
will to knowledge. (Janicaud, 1992 p.290, 300) Of course, Habermas does not
entertain the notion of completely disinterested knowledge. However, even
124
For a useful discussion of the ‘ambiguous’ use of the idea of biopower by Foucault, see
Donnelly (1992) p.199-203. See also Barret-Kriegal (1992).
125
For discussion of this see Fraser (1989); Connolly (1985); Taylor (1984), (1985); Patton
(1989), (1994); Bove, (1988).
97
though human interests shape knowledge, these are the generalised interests of the
species. Although he moved away form the use of the notion of cognitive interests
per se because of its link to the philosophy of the subject, even at the time of
Knowledge and Human Interests he tied the interest in emancipation from power
to the production and acquisition of knowledge. (Habermas, 1978 p.286-7)
Already at that point, Habermas understood emancipation as predicated on the
communicative logic inherent in human language, which by its very nature
‘expresses unequivocally the intention of universal and unconstrained consensus.’
(Habermas, 1978 p.314) This view is preserved in the shift to the theory of
communicative action. Indeed his criticism of Foucault’s treatment of truth as the
product of power is that it makes power ‘subjectless’ and therefore no longer
bound to ‘the competencies of acting and judging subjects’ that enable the
formation of a rational consensus between subjects which is central to his own
theory. (Habermas, 1985 p.274)
In another commentary on Foucault Habermas argues that power subverts the
‘normative standards of the analytic of the true’. (Habermas, 1989 p.178-9) This
is not to suggest that Habermas necessarily believes that power can be fully
overcome at the level of the individual. Indeed his attempt to incorporate systems
theory in his Theory of Communicative Action is based in part on a recognition of
the heteronomous forces within the economic and administrative ‘subsystems’ of
the society that condition social actors. Nevertheless he retains the philosophical
commitment of his Frankfurt School predecessors to the ideal of the person as an
autonomous agent. 126 As Hindess (1996) indicates, for this sort of critical theory
the ‘impact of power is identified in terms of a difference between the real and the
postulated ideal.’ Thus for Habermas power is posited primarily as a largely
abstract counterfactual to the ideal of a power-less, autonomous, rational process
of intersubjective consensus formation, rather than in the more empirical sense
adopted by Foucault in which its role is to describe the ‘effects of identifiable
conditions and processes’.
The difference between these two approaches to power is linked to
differences in the way the notion of reason is understood. Hoy has characterised
this succinctly in the following terms: ‘Whereas Foucault is ... interested in the
historicity of reason, Habermas is interested in the theory of reason.’ (Hoy, 1994)
Despite Habermas’ critique of Horkheimer and Adorno’s ‘one dimensional’ view
of reason, his own differentiation of reason remains largely ahistorical and
abstracted from specific social contexts. In conjunction with his commitment to a
universalised communicative rationality, this leads him to see theories or social
126
Without also retaining what Foucault saw as their refusal of the Enlightenment ‘blackmail’
implicit to Habermas’ critique of Horkheimer and Adorno, (and Foucault); that is, the view
that ‘operates as though a rational critique of rationality were impossible.’ (Foucault, 1983
p.201; 1984b p.44-5)
98
forces that challenge his particular conception of reason as a challenge to
rationality per se, as well as to ‘modernity’ as the generalised bearer (at least
potentially) of the evolution of reason and hence human autonomy. As indicated
in Chapter 3, this results in Habermas interpreting many new social movements,
and particularly ecological movements, as essentially anti-modernist and therefore
potentially irrational. A similar move is apparent in his characterisation of the
early Frankfurt School and French theorists such as Foucault as anti-modernist
and ‘neo-conservative’. In this instance, Habermas sees Foucault’s work as an
attack on the resources of modernity. In effect, Habermas regards Foucault’s (and
Horkheimer and Adorno’s) understanding of truth and knowledge as determined
by power relations as representing a ‘repudiation of enunciative discourse
altogether’. (Margolis, 1993 p.46)
However, as Margolis has argued, Habermas’ project lacks the degree of
grounding and universality it claims for itself. Habermas admits that the
rationality of argumentation (‘the unforced force of the better argument’) is an
‘idealisation’, something that ‘discourse participants always have to suppose’.
(Habermas, 1985 p.130) He in fact conflates empirical and transcendental
(metatheoretical) arguments as to the character of communicative reason, the very
criticism he levels at Foucault’s use of power. First, he claims that it is implicit to
everyday social processes, that is, the communicative potential of reason derives
from actual cultural processes for achieving mutual understanding within the lifeworld. At the same time he claims that communicative reason has a ‘purely
procedural character’ and as such is ‘quasi-transcendental’. (Habermas, 1987
p.314-6) Thus communicative action is a cultural achievement in the evolution of
society and simultaneously an ontological condition necessary for any form of
social existence. However, in terms of empirical adequacy, Habermas fails to
provide any evidence as to when such ‘uncoerced consensus’ actually occurs, in
contrast to Foucault’s provision of considerable historical detail in support of his
claims about the emergence of modern forms of discipline. Indeed Habermas also
fails to explain how it would even be possible to know whether any instance of
consensus escapes the more subtle forms of coercion and deception present in
social interactions. (Margolis, 1993 p.49)
Introducing this ‘systematic ambiguity’ at the heart of his own critical theory
does not help Habermas avoid explaining how discursive inquiry can posses a
universal validity while at the same time being ‘inseparable from whatever
unreason ... lies embedded in the practices of actual life.’ (Margolis, 1993 p.4950) The consensus of Habermas’ ideal speech situation, even if posed in its
weakest form as an ideal to be striven for, assumes a neutrality and transparency
in discourse that is not simply utopian but also seriously flawed sociologically.
Apart from the mere assertion that there are ‘unavoidable communication
presuppositions of augmentative discourse’ (Habermas, 1985 p.130) Habermas is
unable to provide any compelling justification for accepting that communicative
99
reason is capable of providing a secure grounding for universal (or even
potentially universalisable) truth or normative standards. As Margolis insists,
there ‘is no reason in the world why “the unforced force of the better argument” is
anything more than a purely local appraisal.’ (Margolis, 1993 p.50-1) Thus
Habermas’ criticisms of Foucault regarding the lack of empirical adequacy and
the conflation of empirical and metatheoretical tasks are equally applicable to his
own arguments. It appears that Habermas’ own theory is as guilty of being
‘narcissistically oriented’ as is Foucault’s. This does not necessarily strengthen
Foucault’s position, but does weaken the grounds upon which Habermas can
claim a theoretical superiority for his own.
Habermas’ mischaracterisation of Foucault’s notion of power represents a
more substantial problem for his critique. In this context, Kelly has argued that a
central issue in the dispute between the two theorists has been Habermas’
misunderstanding of the relationship between juridical and disciplinary power in
Foucault’s writings.127 Kelly suggests this is the result of Habermas’ tendency, in
The Philosophical Discourse on Modernity, to base his criticisms on a one-sided
reading of Foucault’s notion of power in Discipline and Punish. (Kelly, 1994b
p.366-7) From this Habermas extracts a view of Foucault’s project as describing
the ‘victory of regulatory reason’ which is seen as a process of continuous and
generalised augmentation of discipline and domination in modernity. (Habermas,
1985 p.245) Here Habermas’ reading of Foucault closely follows that of Honneth.
(Honneth, 1991) Both interpret Foucault as suggesting power in modern society
operates on the model of the total institution, that is, as a totalising and all
pervasive repressive discipline. Neither demonstrates a broad awareness of
Foucault’s discussions of power beyond his main books, and even this awareness
goes little beyond Discipline and Punish, and occasionally the first volume of
History of Sexuality. 128 Not only is this reading of Foucault deficient, as a
comparison with the general discussion of his notion of power in the first section
127
‘Juridical’ power refers to the sovereign view of power discussed earlier in this chapter, in
which power is traditionally understood as the possession of a centralised political authority
(such as the State) or social class, the ‘exercise’ of which is conceived in terms of prohibition
or repression.
128
In particular, neither author substantially engages Foucault's more specific comments on the
nature of power contained in numerous articles and interviews, nor his work on governmental
rationalities and liberalism. Habermas refers approvingly to Honneth's work on Foucault in
The Philosophical Discourse on Modernity (Habermas, 1985 p.255, 268) and generally follows
a similar approach, although with much less detail or rigour. Honneth's work (the parts on
Foucault) was submitted as a dissertation in 1983 and first published in German in 1985, the
same year as the German edition of Habermas’ The Philosophical Discourse on Modernity,
although Habermas was clearly familiar with this in preparing his own work. Both Honneth
and Habermas cite some passages from interviews in the Power/Knowledge collection, but
neither appears familiar with important works of Foucault such as 'The Subject and Power'
(1982), his lectures delivered at the College du France between 1970 and 1984, nor his
'Governmentality' essay, which first appeared in English in 1979.
100
of this chapter would indicate, but both Honneth and Habermas also attribute to
Foucault a view of societal rationalisation as an all-embracing phenomenon.
However, to employ Hoy’s (1994) characterisation referred to earlier in this
chapter, Foucault is not concerned with a theory of rationality that discerns the
general principles of Reason, but rather with the history of particular rationalities.
Thus Foucault’s genealogies emphasise the ‘local and contingent aspects’ of
specific rationalisation processes ‘without assuming any necessary coherence
overall’ as do both the early Frankfurt School and Habermas. Of course, as
Hindess emphasises, the significance of this difference between Foucault and the
Frankfurt tradition, while real should not be overstated. (Hindess, 1996) The
move from the universal to the singular in Foucault involves shifting the focus of
the Kantian critique rather than an abandonment of it, as I argue in Chapter 7.
Kelly’s analysis demonstrates that Habermas’ reading of Foucault fails to
understand the local and contingent character of the power relations described by
Foucault. Hence Habermas (1985) wrongly attributes to Foucault the view that the
disciplinary power (ie panopticism) ‘found in modern punishment is characteristic
for the structure of societal modernisation as a whole.’ (p.288-9 - emphasis
added) Not only did Foucault explicitly deny that modern society is a disciplinary
society ‘in all its aspects’, 129 his analysis of panopticism in Discipline and Punish
did not, as Habermas appears to suggest, claim that modern discipline was
dispersed into society in general from the prison. (Foucault, 1979b p.138, 224;
Kelly, 1994b p.366-371) Kelly also argues that by construing Foucault’s notion of
disciplinary power in largely traditional terms, Habermas fails to appreciate the
distinction between it and juridical power. Contrary to the inference drawn by
Habermas’ commentary in The Philosophical Discourse on Modernity, Foucault
did not argue that juridical modes of power are no longer important. The claim
was rather that the preoccupation of political theory (on both the Right and the
Left) with a ‘juridical schematism’ that unfailingly characterises the nature of
power as repressive and negative had stood in the way of critical-empirical
investigation of the actual operation of power in historically specific contexts.
(Foucault, 1980d p.115-6, 118-127) Thus Foucault argued that it is necessary to
understand modern power in terms that encompass not only the legal-juridical
functions of the State, but also those myriad ‘micro-level’ practices and
techniques that ‘necessarily extend beyond the limits of the State’. (Foucault,
1980d p.122) He did not claim that the State is unimportant, or that juridical
power has disappeared, 130 but rather that the State can only operate by virtue of
129
See particularly Foucault's rebuttal of the charge that he fails to distinguish between democratic
and totalitarian regimes, in Foucault (1991b) p.166-70.
130
Habermas argues that ‘As soon as Foucault takes up the threads of the biopolitical
establishment of disciplinary power, he lets drop the threads of the legal organisation of the
exercise of power and the legitimation of the order of domination.’ (Habermas, 1985 p.290)
101
already existing relations of positive disciplinary power at the micro-level of
society. Power then for Foucault is not reducible to these negative and prohibitive
juridical-administrative functions of the State; in fact he argued that this
disciplinary biopower had come to be necessary to the continued existence and
operation of these juridical functions. (Foucault, 1980d p.122) 131 As Kelly
suggests then, while the disciplinary and juridical modes of power frequently
conflict and compete, they are also correlative. (Kelly, 1994b p.375-6) In the next
chapter I discuss Foucault's notions of biopolitics and governmentality in detail.
Foucault’s relationship to the German critical tradition
Before doing this I first turn to a more general consideration of Foucault’s
work in relation to the largely German tradition of critical thought on
modernisation discussed briefly in earlier chapters. This is useful because
Habermas’ attacks on Foucault may suggest a greater degree of difference
between the two than is perhaps warranted. This is a question I shall return to in
Chapters 7 and 8 in my discussion of Foucault’s incomplete break with the
notions of human sovereignty and autonomy so cherished by both the Frankfurt
School and Habermas (and one might add, Nietzsche). Perhaps of equal
importance, however, it is important to recognise that despite the differences
between the two on the question of power, both arguably share common
intellectual roots in what are branches of a European critical tradition.
The significance of Nietzsche’s influence on Foucault has been widely
discussed. 132 In several interviews Foucault pointed to the significance of
Nietzsche for his own thinking, describing his reading of Nietzsche as providing
‘a point of rupture’ and a ‘revelation’ in his intellectual development. (Foucault,
1983 p.198-9; 1988c p.13) Foucault indicates that his motivation for drawing on
elements of Nietzsche’s work was a concern with ‘the possibility of elaborating a
history of rationality’ (and of knowledge) that is not based on the ‘founding act of
the rationalist subject’. He notes that the leading French historian of science,
Georges Canguilhem, who was influential in his early studies, also shared an
interest in Nietzsche and was ‘thoroughly receptive’ to the own to write such a
history of knowledge and reason. 133 Foucault identifies two camps in post-World
Habermas’ comments here clearly reveal his lack of familiarity with Foucault’s work on
governmentality, security and liberalism.
131
Elsewhere Foucault characterised this as the ‘governmentalisation of the State’. Foucault,
(1991c) p.103.
132
See from example Dreyfus and Rabinow (1982) p.104-117; Lash (1984) p.1-17; Habermas
(1985) p.238-265; Deleuze (1988). Foucault gave his most detailed consideration of Nietzsche
in a 1971 essay published as Foucault (1984a) - see p.79-100.
133
Canguilhem, whose main area of expertise was the history of biology and medicine, was one of
Foucault's examiners for his second attempt for the agregation de philosophe at the Ecole
102
War Two French philosophy - a philosophy of the subject expressed in
phenomenology, and a philosophy of ‘the concept’, of knowledge and rationality,
represented by Bachelard’s and Canguilhem’s history of science. He locates his
own concerns as firmly aligned with those of the second camp’s ‘historical
critique of reason’.134 Significantly, Foucault noted that in Germany the ‘Frankfurt
School and Lukacs, by way of Feuerbach, Marx, Nietzsche, and Max Weber’
represented this line of critique. (Gutting, 1989 p.9-12) 135 Hence while rejecting
many of the Statist assumptions of power inherited from Marxism, Foucault
nevertheless saw his own project as having much in common with the tradition of
social critique.136
Three key elements of Nietzsche’s philosophy in particular were important to
Foucault’s project of doing a history of ‘the concept’. First, Nietzsche relied on
the notion of becoming in his understanding of the world, and as a consequence he
argued that knowledge of the world is always perspectival. As the world (‘being’)
is in a constant state of flux, a positivist conception of ‘objective’ or ‘true’
knowledge is rejected. What we ‘know’ is not reality (‘being’) but appearances
that acquire a veneer of solidity in the history of cultural practices, through the
imposition on the world of interpretations which have proven themselves useful.
137
A second consequence of the dependence of knowledge on historical-cultural
Normale Superieure in 1951. (In his unsuccessful 1950 attempt at the agregration, one of
Foucault's papers was on the theme of ‘man's position in nature’). Canguilhem later became
Foucault's 'supervisor' when he submitted Folie et deraison Historie de la folie a l'age classique
(Madness and Civilisation) as his principal thesis for the doctorat es lettres in 1961, and
reported in very approving terms on the topic and quality of the thesis. Foucault's
‘complimentary thesis’ was a translation and discussion of Kant's essay Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View. The conclusion of the complimentary thesis ends its discussion of
Kant with a reference to Nietzsche's philosophy as ‘finally putting an end to questions about
man.’ Thus while Foucault's 1971 article systematically appropriates Nietzschean themes,
already in 1961 it is evident that Foucault had come to see Nietzsche as a resource in his
attempt to come to grips with the 'history of reason'. For above bibliographic details see Macey
(1994) p.45, 88-90, 103-6 and Bernauer (1988) p.120, 161.
134
See Foucault’s (1991d) discussion of the influence of Canguilhem and Nietzsche on his work.
135
Gutting is here quoting from Foucault’s essay 'La vie: l'experience et la science', in Revue de
metaphysique et de morale 70 (1985), an earlier version of which appeared as the introduction
to the English translation of Canguilhem's 1978, On the Normal and the Pathological. See also
Foucault (1983).
136
See Foucault (1991a) for Foucault’s criticism of the Frankfurt School, and Foucault (1991d)
for comments on Althusser.
137
Nietzsche argues that the world, as that which is in a ‘state of becoming’ cannot ‘in a strict
sense be 'comprehended' or 'known'; only in so far as the 'comprehending' and 'knowing'
intellect discovers a crude ready-made world put together out of nothing but appearances, but
appearances which, to the extent to which they are the kind that have preserved life, have
become firm - only to this extent is there anything like 'knowledge', ie a measuring of earlier
and later errors by one another.’ Nietzsche, Will to Power, section 520, quoted in Turner,
(1984) p.242.
103
practices is that language plays a powerful role in moulding the ways in which it
is possible to think about the world. In other words, language functions as the
medium through which experience is systematised, in which order and ‘stability’
are imposed on a world of constant ‘becoming’. 138 The third significant element
of Nietzsche’s epistemology is that he regards interests as a necessary condition
of knowledge. On the one hand his perspectivalism insists that knowledge is
relative to such things as time, location, culture and language, and as such cannot
be isolated from the context and relations of its constitution. However, he also
understands knowledge (and subjectivity) as more generally serving the interest of
the human species in securing the means for the preservation of its own life. Thus
Nietzsche argues
Consciousness does not really belong to man’s individual existence but
rather to his social or herd nature ... We simply lack any organ for
knowledge, for ‘truth’: we ‘know’ (or believe or imagine) just as much as
may be useful in the interests of the human herd, the species. (Turner,
1984 p.242) 139
This suggests a view in which knowledge serves a functional role in the
evolutionary development or natural history of the human species, which while
ultimately based in the biological attributes, is also linked to the ‘necessary
features’ of social communication. (Turner, 1984 p.242-3) 140 The similarity of
this view to Habermas’ notion of a human technical interest in the mastery of
nature and a practical interest in communication is readily apparent, 141 as is the
similarity to Horkheimer and Adorno’s radicalisation of the link between ‘identity
thinking’, instrumental reason and the domination of nature. In Foucault’s case,
138
Nietzsche thus argues that the structure of language is in fact what is responsible for notions of
causality and subjectivity: ‘Where there exists a language affinity it is quite impossible, thanks
to the common philosophy of grammar - I mean thanks to unconscious domination and
directing by similar grammatical functions - to avoid everything being prepared in advance for
a similar evolution and succession of philosophical systems; just as the road seems to be barred
to certain other possibilities of world interpretation.’ Nietzsche (1989), section 20 p.50; also
Turner (1984) p.242.
139
Nietzsche, The Gay Science, section 354, quoted in Turner (1984) p.242.
140
Warren points out that ‘the conditions of possibility’ for knowledge are in part seen by
Nietzsche as ‘interests relating to human agency’, that is, as involving interests in ‘the material,
social and cultural worlds as means to and conditions of power organised as subjectivity.’
Knowledge cannot be extricated from the interest the self has in increasing its ‘feeling of
power’ or will to power. See Warren (1988) p.90-2.
141
Warren points to Habermas’ treatment of interests (as a positive condition of knowledge) as ‘a
contemporary equivalent’ of Nietzsche's approach, ‘notwithstanding Habermas' own
interpretation of Nietzsche.’ (Warren, 1988 p.269 footnote 35). Warren argues that Habermas’
interpretation of Nietzsche's theory of power ‘misses the mark’ due to over-reliance on works
such as Untimely Considerations and The Gay Science in which Nietzsche's views on truth and
knowledge were not fully developed. See Warren (1988) p.270 footnote 46.
104
the influence of Nietzsche can clearly be seen in his insistence that the idea of a
necessary correlation between the order of discourse and the order of things is a
metaphysical assumption of Western philosophy. (Foucault, 1970; 1981d)
Similarly some parallels and overlap between the concern of Weber and
Foucault can be discerned.142 Indeed, Dreyfus and Rabinow suggest that Foucault
inherited from Weber ‘a concern with rationalisation and objectification as the
essential trend ... and most important problem’ of modern society. (Dreyfus and
Rabinow, 1982 p.166) 143 Smart sees some areas of common concern, such as
rationalisation, power and discipline, but also points to important differences
between the two. Thus while Weber’s notion of rationalisation took the form of a
global, all-encompassing process, Foucault’s work was concerned with rationality
in much more specific and relative sense, and is developed in a way that denied
any ‘absolute form of rationality against which specific forms might be compared
or evaluated.’ In contrast to the ‘monolithic dimensions’ of Weber’s thesis,
Foucault explicitly rejected understanding rationalisation in terms of any
totalising notion of modern society or culture. As a consequence Foucault’s
analysis, according to Smart, held open the possibility of resistance whereas
Weber succumbed to the fatalistic vision of the ‘iron cage’ of bureaucratic
domination and instrumental reason. (Smart, 1983 p.126) 144
A further area of commonality between Weber and Foucault is that both were
also concerned with forms of domination and discipline. However, Weber tended
to conceptualise power in terms that emphasised the importance of the state and
the intentionality of subjects, and which saw power in a juridical sense as negative
and prohibitive. (O'Neill, 1987 p.54-5; Smart, 1983 p.126 p.129) By contrast,
Foucault treated power as a far more positive and relational phenomenon, which
not only constrains individuals but also is productive of different modes of
subjectivity and the social relations possible in any particular historical milieu.
(Foucault, 1982 p.219-20) Nevertheless, both placed emphasis on an
understanding of rationalisation as the disciplining of the body, the origins of
142
Some attempts to deal with this connection include Turner (1984) p.157-176, 226-251; (1987)
p.222-241; Gordon (1987) p.293-316; Smart (1983) p.123-137; Lash (1987) p.355-377;
O’Neill (1987) p.43-60; Hindess (1987) p.137-153; Clegg (1994); Owen (1994).
143
As indicated above, Foucault clearly locates his work within the same broad problem as
Weber, but is quite insistent that French philosophical thought ‘knew absolutely nothing - or
only vaguely, only very indirectly - about the current of Weberian thought.’ See Foucault
(1983) p.200.
144
Gordon however argues that ‘Weber is as innocent as Foucault of the so-called Weberianism
that adopts a uniform, monolithic conception of historical phenomena of rationalisation.’ See
Gordon (1987) p.293-4. Turner suggests that while Smart's characterisation of Weber is
justified, it is important to note that Weber did argue against postulating ‘general laws of social
development’, and to that extent Weber's work ‘lacked internal consistency’. See Turner
(1987) p.232-3.
105
which are traced to the institutional practices of the monastery and army in
medieval Europe. 145 The rational disciplining of the body was characterised by
Weber as a process in which the ‘natural rhythm’ of human beings as biological
organisms was brought into ‘line with the demands of the work procedure, (and
were) attuned to a new rhythm through the functional specialisation of muscles
and through the creation of an optimal economy of physical effort.’ (Smart, 1983
p.130-1) 146 Such comments bear a striking resemblance to Foucault’s description
of what he terms biopower or the ‘anatomo-politics of the human body’. This new
form of power which began to emerge in the seventeenth century, is ‘centred on
the body as a machine’, and involves the disciplining of the body through ‘the
optimisation of its capacities’ so as to produce a ‘parallel increase of its
usefulness and its docility, its integration into systems of efficient and economic
controls.’ As with Weber then, Foucault saw this new form of discipline as
indispensable to the development of capitalism, which required the ‘controlled
insertion of bodies into the machinery of production and the adjustment of the
phenomena of population to economic processes.’ (Foucault, 1990 p. 139-41)147
Gordon has suggested a further link in Foucault’s later work on
governmentality and neo-liberalism with a growing interest in the significance of
Weber’s influence on recent intellectual history. (Gordon, 1986 p.79; Gordon,
1987 p.295-6) In particular Foucault credited Weber with providing a counterfocus to Marxism. In doing so he directed the attention of social theory to the
problem of the ‘irrational rationality of capitalist society’, that is, to the historical
understanding of the present in terms of processes of rationalisation which are
‘multiple, specific and potentially discordant.’148 In particular, Foucault pointed to
145
Turner argues that while Weber's main focus is on the changes in knowledge and
consciousness brought about by rationalisation and the development of capitalism, this
perspective also incorporates a ‘general process whereby the body ceases to be a feature of
religious culture and is incorporated via medicalisation into a topic within scientific discourse’,
that is, there is a shift to ‘regulation of the body and of populations.’ (Turner, 1987 p.224-6)
See also Smart (1983) p.129-31; Miller (1987) p.5-9.
146
See Weber (1968) p.1156.
147
I discuss the aspect of Foucault's work in relation to the development of modern ecological
discourse in Chapter 6. See O’Neill (1987) for a discussion of the rise of industrial discipline
and its treatment in the work of Weber, Foucault and Marx. O'Neill argues that industrial
discipline tends to ‘naturalise bureaucratic controls which are embedded in the social
organisation or power structure of the firm’, and that the ‘bureaucracies of state and economy’
seek to depoliticise their power by subordinating this within ‘the neutral image of disciplined
technology and expertise.’ (p.55-7). See also Turner (1984) especially Chapters 7 & 10 and
(1987). For a Foucauldian examination of the bureaucratic regulation of industrial bargaining
under US labour law, see Moore 1993 p.165-189.
148
Dews argues that Foucault's characterisation of power as productive of objects and rituals of
truth is ‘acceptable’ when understood within the Weberian tradition's focus on the historical
specificity of the transition from traditional to modern society. Thus Dews claims that
Foucault's account of power describes ‘the productivity and efficiency of those purposive-
106
a common Weberian heritage in both the Frankfurt School and the neo-liberalism
of the Ordoliberalen or Freiburg School (Gordon, 1986 p.79-81) 149 which, while
politically opposed, nevertheless also share an emphasis on anti-naturalism, the
historical contingency of social forms and a specific concern with the problems of
the ethical conduct of life in modern Western society.150
Nietzsche and Weber have likewise also been key theoretical influences on
Frankfurt School critical theory. Horkheimer and Adorno explicitly acknowledge
their debt to Nietzsche in their treatment of the ‘dialectic of enlightenment’,
claiming it was he who first recognised the existence of a nihilistic ‘anti-life
force’ inherent within enlightenment. 151 Their discussion of the domination of
nature as a universal feature of ‘identity thinking’ and instrumental reason draws
heavily on Nietzsche’s theme that knowledge operates as a tool of the ‘will to
power’, in which the drive to predict and master nature serves the interests of selfpreservation. (Held, 1980 p.156-7) Similarly, key aspects of Weber’s concept of
societal rationalisation were appropriated by Horkheimer and Adorno in their
analyses of the domination of reason by instrumental rationality and the rise of a
bureaucratised, ‘totally administered society.’ (Held, 1980 p.65-68)
Habermas too bases central elements of his understanding of societal
rationalisation and modernisation on a critical reading of Weber, arguing that
Weber’s analysis fails to appreciate the ‘selectivity’, or differentiation, exhibited
in the processes of rationalisation. According to Habermas, Weber cannot
adequately explain the way in which under conditions of capitalist modernisation,
instrumental rationality ‘surges beyond the bounds’ of the material reproduction
of economy and state, distorting the communicative reason necessary to the
‘symbolic reproduction of the life-world.’ Hence, he argues that it is possible to
overcome Weberian pessimism (the ‘iron cage’) once critical theory understands
that the ‘colonisation’ of life-world by instrumental reason is a pathological
distortion of the rationalisation process rather than its inevitable outcome. For
Habermas, the progressive potential of modernity can be realised provided critical
rational forms of organisation which Weber detected in modern bureaucracies and in the
capitalist organisation of the labour process. Similarly, Foucault's repeated denial's that power
can be considered as a possession of groups or individuals becomes comprehensible in the
light of Weber's account of the transition from 'charismatic' and 'traditional' to 'legal-rational'
forms of domination.’ (Dews, 1987 p.150-52)
149
Here Gordon draws on then unpublished recordings and transcripts of Foucault's lectures on
the history of liberalism and neo-liberalism delivered in March-April 1979. See also Gordon
(1987) p.314-5.
150
Thus, according to Gordon, Foucault points in his 1979 lectures to a ‘double destiny of
Weberianism in Germany’ which ‘ends with the street battles of 1968 in which the last
disciples of the Frankfurt School confront the police of a government inspired by the teachings
of the Freiburg School.’ (Gordon, 1986 p.80)
151
For a review of the influence of Nietzsche on critical theory, see Putz (1981) p.103-114.
107
theory appreciates the different analytical approaches appropriate to action within
the separate social environments of system and life-world. 152 The significance of
Nietzsche in Habermas’ reconstruction of critical theory is less positive yet
arguably still central. In Nietzsche lies the main intellectual impetus behind both
the Frankfurt School and Foucault’s descent into what Habermas regards as the
conservative dead-end of the ‘dialectic of enlightenment’. By ‘conflating’
knowledge with power, Nietzsche provides what Habermas sees as ‘the real
challenge for the discourse on modernity’. (Habermas, 1985 p.74) 153 On this point
rest most of the substantial theoretical differences between Habermas and
Foucault discussed in the first part of this chapter.154
Since Foucault’s death there have been a number of attempts to come to grips
not only with the differences between Habermas and Foucault, but also their
commonalties. 155 Similarities have also been drawn between the work of the early
Frankfurt School and Foucault. Honneth for example, points to several key
features of critique common to Adorno and Foucault, although emphasising the
divergent philosophical grounds on which these are based. According to Honneth,
both Adorno and Foucault understand modernity as a process of technical or
instrumental rationalisation that, under the cloak of moral emancipation and
progress, violently disciplines a ‘pre-rational’ dimension of the human body to
produce the ‘modern, forcefully unified individual’. (Honneth, 1986 p.53-4) Each
finds the root of modernity in the intellectual and political changes initiated by the
European Enlightenment; each works on the view that knowledge assures
domination behind the ‘generalisation of theoretical and moral validity claims’
and the growth of legal and constitutional structures. In this view, both Adorno
and Foucault understand instrumental rationality as expressing a tendency towards
the totalitarian control of social life. Modernity, in other words, is characterised
by the regulative capacity to ‘intervene like total institutions in the life context of
every single individual in order to make him a conforming member of society
through discipline and control, manipulation and drilling’. This is a view I have
argued is not accurate as far as Foucault is concerned. However, in agreement
152
The first requires a systems theory while the latter demands a hermeneutic or ‘action-theoretic’
approach. See Habermas (1981a) p.5-31; (1984) Chapter II, and (1987) Chapter VIII,
especially p.303-331.
153
For Habermas’ critique of Nietzsche, see Habermas (1985). For a concise and critical
consideration of the significance of Nietzsche in work of Foucault and other post-structuralist
writers such as Derrida, Lyotard and Lacan, see Dews (1987).
154
The connection between knowledge and power is central to the examination of contemporary
ecological discourse and programs of environmental regulation discussed in Chapter 6 of this
thesis.
155
Some significant examples of this include Kelly (1994); Miller (1987); Honneth (1991); Dews
(1987); Habermas (1985). See also, for example McCarthy (1990) p.437-469; Richters (1988)
p.611-643.
108
with Habermas, Honneth sees Foucault as succumbing to a totalising critique
similar to that which deprives Adorno and Horkheimer of a rational basis for their
own arguments for a critical social theory. He points to the quite different
conceptions of subjectivity that lead to these similarities, while claiming that
Foucault’s social theory in the end is a ‘version of the Dialectic of Enlightenment
reduced to systems theory.’ (Honneth, 1986 p.56-58) 156
McCarthy has also drawn out some of the broad affinities, as well as
differences, between Foucault and the Frankfurt School, including Habermas. For
my purposes, some of these similarities are particularly significant. McCarthy
argues that both Foucault and the Frankfurt School assert the ‘primacy of the
practical over the theoretical’ by treating knowledge production as social practice,
and requiring that epistemic practices be understood within their broader practical
context. Foucault concludes from this the impossibility of knowledge or truth (at
least in the human sciences) that is outside of relations of power and hence
capable of grounding a theory of the social totality. This is in contrast to the
Frankfurt School, which did not give up the attempt to find some form of
universalising truth-function for reason in the realisation of social emancipation.
(McCarthy, 1990 p.441-2) 157 Following from this Foucault sees a pervasive
complicity of human science expertise in modern forms of domination and
discipline. McCarthy argues that the Frankfurt School theorists, and in particular
Habermas, while critical of the role played by the social sciences and social
scientific expertise in societal rationalisation, nevertheless still sought to
distinguish between different forms of social inquiry in a way that did not regard
them all as extensions of an instrumental rationality directed towards ‘ever more
effective forms of domination.’ (McCarthy, 1990 p.439-40, 442) 158 Despite the
differences between the two approaches to social theory, a key feature of each is
the use of ‘functional accounts of how and why purportedly rational practices
came to be taken for granted’. Such accounts are central to critique inasmuch as
they problematise and destabilise the apparently natural and necessary character
156
Elsewhere Honneth argues the usefulness of Habermas’ differentiation of spheres of social
action (symbolic and material) in undermined by the move in Theory of Communicative
Action to a systems theory approach dominated by a technocratically conceived understanding
of two fundamentally different modes of action-coordination. Thus Honneth claims, despite
criticism of Horkheimer and Adorno, Habermas fails to extricate his own theoretical project
from the technocratic diagnosis of modernity laid out in Dialectic of Enlightenment. See
Honneth (1991); Smith (1993).
157
I argue in the Chapter 7 of the current thesis that Foucault makes a dubious distinction between
the human and natural sciences when he suggests that the latter has been able to detach itself
from the social contexts of power in which it originated.
158
McCarthy is not suggesting that Foucault lacked a notion of social critique. See McCarthy's
(1990) discussion of this (p.451-2). As I discuss in Chapter 7, the basis on which Foucault
could argue that any form of scientific knowledge is not implicated in power raises significant
theoretical questions.
109
of social and epistemic practices by demonstrating how these are in fact the
product of ‘contingent relations of force and an arbitrary closing off of
alternatives’. (McCarthy, 1990 p.439-40)
However much these common concerns with the role of rationalisation as a
fundamental characteristic of modernity provide Habermas and Foucault with a
similar object of inquiry, there remain significant differences between the two. A
detailed exploration of these differences is an important philosophical task that is
both beyond the scope of this current work and is undertaken elsewhere by
others.159 Here, my focus has been on the differences between the two as it is most
directly relevant to the problem of nature.
Conclusion
The debate between Foucault and Habermas on rationality and power, and
their relation to knowledge, is the key area of disagreement between the two. It is
in any case the point on which I have focused as this debate leads directly into
Foucault’s notions of biopower and governmentality. It is these concepts which I
argue provide a particularly useful antidote to Habermas’ unsatisfactory
theoretical approach to understanding ecological problems in particular, and more
generally to his adherence to what Smith (1993, p.107) has described as the
‘theoretical fictions’ of norm-free organisation of action and power-free paths of
communication. Appreciation of the reciprocal relation between juridical power
and biopower, discussed in the early part of this chapter, is indispensable to any
analysis of the regulatory biopolitics of the population, and particularly for
understanding the growth of ecological regulation with its dependence on
scientific knowledge.
Habermas’ system-lifeworld scheme, despite hints of potential usefulness (ie
its focus on questions of social reproduction), obscures the need for historicalempirical investigation by its very generality and abstractness. His formulation
leads to a rigid separation of power and discourse, a problem directly linked to a
juridical schematism in his understanding of power. He arbitrarily restricts the
domain of power to the social ‘system’ (administration and economy),
recognising the operation of power within the ‘lifeworld’ only as a pathological
state resulting from ‘colonisation’ by the system. This is a theoretical
consequence of his conceptualisation of the lifeworld as the power-free realm of
communicative action, which he sees as furnishing the ontological and
transcendental preconditions for all sociality and rationality. By persisting with
the theoretical fiction of power free discourse, Habermas falls into an empty
159
See in particular Miller (1987), Honneth (1991), Hindess (1996).
110
proceduralism and fails in his self appointed task of establishing the possibility of
a universal grounding for validity and truth claims.
In the next chapter I turn specifically to a consideration of Foucault's work on
biopolitics and governmentality. In particular I consider the potential of these
concepts to provide a useful theoretical framework from which to understand the
development of scientific ecology as an important element of contemporary
attempts to regulate the behaviour of the human population.
111
Chapter 6
Biopolitics, governmentality and scientific
expertise
Introduction
This chapter considers in more detail aspects of Foucault’s work on
biopolitics and government.160 It starts by tracing the development of the theme of
disciplinary power through to biopolitics in Foucault's work and his shift from a
focus on the individual and the ‘micro-physics of power’, to a more global
concern with the management of populations. The link between the development
of this notion of biopolitics and the work on governmental rationality is explored.
The chapter considers the work of authors such as Nikolas Rose and Peter Miller,
who tie governmentality to an analysis of the role of expertise in advanced liberal
societies. This discussion prepares the way for a critical consideration in Chapters
7 and 8 of Foucault’s treatment of the natural sciences, and subsequently, an
evaluation of the notions of ecological modernisation and risk society in the final
chapter.
Discipline and biopolitics
The previous chapter argued that Habermas’ criticisms of Foucault failed to
adequately appreciate the interrelationship between juridical power and
disciplinary power. That chapter concluded with the suggestion that an
understanding of this is indispensable to an analysis of the biopolitics of
populations and the growth in ecological regulation. It is now necessary to trace
the connection between discipline and biopolitics as a precursor to examining
Foucault’s notion of governmental rationality (or governmentality).
In Discipline and Punish, Foucault examined in detail the emergence of a new
form of power, a disciplinary ‘technology’ that directly acts upon the body of the
individual. Disciplinary power does not completely displace other forms of
power, but instead ‘invests’ these with a new capacity to penetrate the most
minute, everyday activities of individuals. This disciplinary power has the effect
of producing docile bodies ‘that may be subjected, used, transformed and
improved.’ (Foucault, 1979b p.136) The emergence of disciplinary power,
according to Foucault, was directly related to the growth of capitalism in Europe:
160
A version of this chapter has previously appeared as Rutherford (1999b)
112
it is largely as a force of production that the body is invested with
relations of power and domination; but, on the other hand, its constitution
as labour power is possible only if it is caught up in a system of
subjection ... the body becomes a useful force only if it is both a
productive body and a subjected body. (Foucault, 1979b p.25-6)
The development of capitalism, the economic modernisation of Europe, was
reciprocally tied to the emergence of disciplinary power. Indeed Foucault
suggested that the spread of these new disciplinary techniques preceded the
growth of capitalism. The investing of social relations with these new ‘micro’
relations of power while not a cause of capitalist modernisation were very much
‘the prerequisite for its success’. (Foucault, 1990 p.140-1; Rabinow, 1984b p.18)
161
The focus of Discipline and Punish was on understanding disciplinary
technologies as based on a form of power that operates in the ‘minute, capillary
relations of domination’ that form the ongoing substratum for the institutions and
structures of the state. (Gordon, 1980a p.255) This ‘microphysics of power’
suggested that the actual operation of power relations could only be grasped
through analysis of the disciplinary techniques that produced docile bodies within
specific institutional contexts, such as the prison, the school or the workplace. A
key criticism that arose regarding Foucault’s work of this period was that
emphasis on such local relations of power ignored the ‘macro’ issue of the
relationships between particular institutions (‘society’) and the state. Foucault’s
work on governmental rationality provided a direct and important response to this
type of criticism.162 By 1976 Foucault had turned his attention to a consideration
of the connection between the operation of power at the micro level of the
individual within particular institutional situations, and the problem of the
regulation at a global or macro level of entire populations by the state. (Foucault,
1990) 163
The context in which Foucault developed this connection was his description
of the emergence, in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, of a new form of
political power concerned with the ‘task of administering life’ (Foucault, 1990
p.139). This modern form of power, which he called biopower, focused on the
fostering of life and the care of populations. He described biopower as developing
161
This argument is not dissimilar to that of Weber.
162
Gordon notes that Foucault introduced his governmentality lectures at the College du France as
being, in part, an answer to this criticism. See Gordon (1991) p.4.
163
See also Dean (1994) p.175-6 and Gordon (1991) p.4-5. This is also a key issue addressed by
actor network theory, which I discuss in detail in Chapter 8. For a particularly insightful and
useful discussion of the relationship between micro-relations of power and macro-social
structure, see Callon and Latour (1981).
113
in two distinct yet related forms. The first of these, constituting ‘an anatomopolitics of the human body’, focuses on disciplining the body of the individual to
increase its utility and manageability through its ‘integration into systems of
efficient and economic controls’. This element of biopower is generally
equivalent to the notion of disciplinary power developed by Foucault in Discipline
and Punish. The second, and more recent form of biopower, focuses on the
supervision of what Foucault called ‘the species body’, that is, ‘the body imbued
with the mechanics of life and serving as the basis of the biological processes’.
Management of the species body occurs through a range of ‘interventions and
regulatory controls’ Foucault characterised as ‘a biopolitics of the population.’
(Foucault, 1990 p.139)
Foucault identified a range of empirical investigations, particularly in
demography and geography, which were closely connected to the rise of these
regulatory interventions. In general he argued that the social sciences developed
to meet particular demands of the administration of human populations, resources
and the economic relations between them. (Foucault, 1980b p.171-2; 1991c p.93)
In these developments, population emerged as an economic and political problem
in which the central concern is the proper balance between population growth and
available resources. (Foucault, 1990 p.25) While Foucault does not do so
explicitly, it is worth noting that in this process, not only does the idea of a
measurable and manageable population come into existence, so also does the
notion of the environment as the sum of the physical resources on which the
population depends. According to Foucault, in the eighteenth century population
and environment come to be seen as constituting ‘perfect living interrelation’,
with the task of the state involving the supervision of the ‘living interrelations
between those two types of living beings’ (population and environment).
(Foucault, 1988b p.160) 164 The elaboration of this ‘population-riches problem’
occurred within a network of new types of knowledge and techniques of
government, having as their primary concern programs for the statistical
description and the efficient management and disposition of all elements of the
population and its resources. (Foucault, 1991c p.93; 1981a p.238; 1988b p.104)
Through this problematisation of the population, the term economy came in
the eighteenth century to signify an entirely new reality and a field of
governmental intervention. (Foucault, 1991c p.92) Foucault suggested that
population constituted a new realm of intervention in three respects. First, the
emergence of the population as a distinct and measurable reality was connected to
an understanding that ‘population has specific economic effects: statistics, by
164
Here Foucault is referring to the work of police theorists, particularly von Justi, who
appropriated to political-administrative thought the new demographic knowledge. Here, as
elsewhere, Foucault appears to refer to the ‘environment’ as the totality of natural resources
and physical living conditions of human populations.
114
making it possible to quantify these specific phenomena of population, also shows
that this specificity is irreducible to the dimension of the family.’ These specific
phenomena included such things as ‘epidemics, endemic levels of mortality,
ascending spirals of labour and wealth’ etc. Second, in the 18th century the
welfare of the population, that is, improving living conditions, health, longevity,
increasing wealth, etc, increasingly came to be regarded as an ultimate end of
government. In the process, the idea of the population itself as the subject of
needs and interests came to the fore. Population thus became ‘an object in the
hands of government’, acted upon and manipulated through a range of new
governmental programs and techniques aimed at managing those demographic
factors relevant to welfare and security. Third, population became the focus for
political economy, the ‘new science of government’ which was inextricably
related to ‘a knowledge of all the processes related to population in its larger
sense: ... what we now call the economy.’ Thus government at this time
increasingly came to be based on a model of the ‘continuous and multiple
relations between population, territory and wealth’. This required new modes of
intervention in the domains of population and economy, and was aimed at
protecting and enhancing the interests of the population, and through this the
state. (Foucault, 1991c p.99-101)
As noted above, Foucault regarded biopower as ‘indispensable’ to the
development of capitalism. He pointed to the parallel growth of the institutions of
state power alongside the techniques of biopower (both disciplinary anatomopolitics and biopolitics) within the economy and population. It is through the
operation of biopower ‘at every level of the social body’, across a diverse range of
social locations (including schools, clinics, the family, the military and
administration) that the modern capitalist economy became possible and was
sustained. The techniques of biopower also played a pivotal role in processes of
social segregation and hierarchisation. These not only guaranteed that the political
relations of domination and hegemony of the modern state were efficiently
perpetuated, but also ensured a congruence between the ‘accumulation of men to
that of capital, the joining of the growth of human groups to the expansion of
productive forces.’ (Foucault, 1990 p.140-1)
Foucault identified several other key factors as arising from the formation of
this new domain of political action focused on human beings as living entities.
One was what he described as the eighteenth century ‘rupture’ in the way in
which scientific discourse dealt with the ‘twofold problematic of life and man’.
By this Foucault meant the emergence of the modern view of human beings,
which was based on a new view of the relationship between history and life.
Human life was seen as having a ‘dual position’ that is simultaneously ‘outside
history, in its biological environment, and inside human historicity, penetrated by
115
the latter’s techniques of knowledge and power.’ 165 (Foucault, 1990 p.143) This
dual problematic itself can be understood, in large part, as arising from the
fundamental shift that occurred towards the end of the eighteenth century, in the
way in which life in general was conceptualised. The transformation was
associated, according to Foucault’s account, with a general discontinuity between
the ‘classical’ and the ‘modern’ era, and in particular with the development of
modern biology. Unlike classical natural history, modern biology saw life as
dependent for its existence on the way in which organisms are functionally linked
to their external surroundings, that is on the way in which they exchange
resources with their environment. The classical view of a timeless continuity of
nature was replaced by a concept of life in which species were understood as
discontinuous entities shaped by the evolutionary influence of environment, and
therefore ‘tied to the time in which these forces and their effects exist.’ (Gutting,
1989 p.192) 166
Another key outcome of the growth of modern biopower was the increasing
importance of what Foucault described as the ‘action of the norm’, at the expense
of sovereign power and the law. (Foucault, 1990 p.144) There are several key
elements to this argument. As outlined in Chapter 5, there was a decline in the
absolute power of the sovereign over his subjects, and a shift to reliance on a
series of expert knowledges that endowed the subject with a multiplicity of
properties denoting such things as sexuality, criminality, states of physical, mental
and moral health etc. In concert with this, there developed a series of specific
disciplinary technologies that operated corporeally to train the body, increasing its
economic utility and political docility. (Foucault, 1979b p.128-44) The experts
involved in the production of these new discourses also acted as the technicians
and ‘normative judges’ responsible for the application of such disciplinary and
corrective programs. Affecting such detailed, individualised supervision was
beyond the blunt, prohibitive capacities of the judicial system. Rather Foucault
argued that what had come into existence was a subtle, individualising mode of
power that was able to ‘take charge of life’ and distribute the living, biological
subject as efficiently as possible within the social and economic field. Such a task
required ‘continuous regulatory and corrective mechanisms’ with the power to
‘quantify, measure, appraise and hierachise’ so as to effect a distribution about the
norm. (Foucault, 1990 p.144)
165
I argue in Chapter 7 that while Foucault's treatment of power takes the significant step of
identifying this ‘dual position’, it also unfortunately tends to perpetuates this in some respects
by failing to rigorously subject the biological environment itself to scrutiny. The ‘biological
environment’ is itself an historical product and not a mere ‘substrate of life’ that lies outside the
relations of power, especially those of the natural sciences which Foucault tended to neglect.
166
See Foucault (1970) p.125-62, 263-79, and (1979a) p.125-30.
116
As I emphasised in the previous chapter, Foucault did not see biopower as
replacing juridical power but rather saw it functioning in conjunction with it, so
that the law increasingly tended to function as a norm rather than as a rigid
prohibition. The legal system was more and more ‘incorporated into a continuum
of apparatuses (medical, administrative, and so on) whose functions are for the
most part regulatory’. (Foucault, 1990 p.144) It was this displacement of
sovereign power and the incorporation of the juridical as a correlative to the
effectivity of the norm that distinguished biopower. (Hewitt, 1983 p.69) It was the
conjunction of the modern biological understanding of ‘life’ and the proliferation
of medical and social scientific knowledge as normalising disciplines that brought
forth a qualitatively different and distinctively modern biopolitics. For Foucault,
the rise of biopower, from the eighteenth century onwards, represented quite
literally the ‘entry of life into history’. (Foucault, 1990 p.141) In saying this
Foucault was not denying that the age-old problem of the biological struggle for
existence, as manifested in the threat of famine and epidemic, could exert a
political effect on history. Such influences were clearly not new. Rather he was
arguing that with economic development and increased productivity during the
eighteenth century it became possible to gain some control over the threat of death
at this basic biological-demographic level.
Foucault’s comments on why this occurred were in most regards quite in line
with traditional accounts of modernisation. He argued that increases in
agricultural productivity and availability of resources in eighteenth century
Europe encouraged rapid demographic growth and accompanied greater security
from starvation and disease. Essential to this was the development of new areas of
knowledge, particularly in biology, agriculture, and public health. (Foucault,
1980b p.168-72; Foucault, 1990 p.142) It is against the background of these
transformations that Foucault identified the emergence of the discourses on
population and security. He was able to claim that life entered history precisely
because these new technical and normative disciplines provided a relative control
over the actual conditions of life. In doing so they took upon themselves
responsibility for the control and modification of ‘the life processes’. In the
modern West, knowledge of the biological conditions of life and their relationship
to individual and collective welfare thus came to be reflected upon as political
concerns, and no longer as ‘an inaccessible substrate’ that only emerged
periodically against the randomness of fate and death. (Foucault, 1990 p.142)
Political power was no longer primarily sovereign power exercised over legal
subjects (over whom the ultimate authority was death) but was concerned with the
management of living beings and their relations with all the factors that shaped
security and welfare. The influence biopower exercised over living beings was
necessarily ‘applied at the level of life itself’, and in so operating, biopower
simultaneously gained influence over the individual both politically and as a
biological entity. The corporeal nature of the body of the subject was brought
directly into the explicit calculations of power and was thereby transformed into a
117
subjected body. The body (individually and collectively) became both the raw
material of power and at the same time that which produces and transforms itself
as a living being. (Foucault, 1990 p.142-3; Hewitt, 1983 p.69)
Foucault explicitly discounted the suggestion that biopower resulted in the
total integration of all aspects of life into the techniques that administer it, 167
indeed, he asserted that life ‘constantly escapes them’. (Foucault, 1990 p.143) 168
Nevertheless, with the increasing penetration of biopower’s normalising reach
into new areas of life activity, and hence the emergence of life as a political
object, a new conception of rights developed. However, according to Foucault,
this was a form of rights radically different from the traditional right of
sovereignty and was incomprehensible from within the framework of the classical
juridical system. It was in fact a notion of ‘rights’ that, while couched in the
traditional terminology of rights and law, was ‘turned back’ against that
traditional system. Thus the politicisation of life, directed as it was at the
satisfaction of essentially biological needs (including the psychological) gave rise
to a recognisably modern interpretation of rights. Foucault described this as ‘the
“right” to life, to one’s body, to health, to happiness, to the satisfaction of needs,
and beyond all the oppressions or “alienations”, the “right” to discover what one
is and all that one can be’. (Foucault, 1990 p.145) It is within this context that the
‘right to life’ of the modern subject came into being and within which its actions
must be understood.
Biopolitics and ecological risk
Some of Foucault’s remarks suggest continuity between this modern right to
life and the contemporary concern about risks to the environment. He claimed that
the ‘biological risks’ confronting the human species now ‘are perhaps greater and
certainly more serious, than before the birth of microbiology.’ (Foucault, 1990
p.143) He further suggested that the economic and social conditions that from the
eighteenth century allowed the West a measure of relief from the struggle against
famine etc do not necessarily apply ‘outside the Western world’. He then went on
to link the notion of modernity directly to biopower and the conditions under
which it emerged.
But what might be called a society’s ‘threshold of modernity’ has been
reached when the life of the species is wagered on its own political
strategies. For millennia, man remained what he was for Aristotle: a
living animal with the additional capacity for a political existence;
167
This is an argument mounted against Foucault by Habermas and Honneth. See Chapter 5 of the
current thesis.
168
See also Butler (1989) on this.
118
modern man is an animal whose politics places his existence as a living
being in question. (Foucault, 1990 p.143 - emphasis added) 169
These comments suggest that Foucault’s work on biopolitics is capable of
addressing the notion of ecological risk and the problem of the social relation to
nature, which have emerged as central problems for contemporary social theory.
As discussed in Chapter 4, Ulrich Beck and Klaus Eder both regard ecological
threats as the systemic result of global processes of modernisation and
rationalisation, which have created new ecological fields of conflict within
contemporary society. Foucault's understanding of modernity as involving the
emergence of biology as an object of political calculation and control indicates
that the sorts of biological concerns he dealt with are not fundamentally dissimilar
from those more specifically ecological ones focused on by Beck and Eder.
Beck for example draws a clear link between the success of economic growth
and the consolidation of welfare state mechanisms in providing an unprecedented
level of security for life. The development of such productive capacities is, at the
same time, seen as creating an entirely new class of technologically induced risks
which have the potential for the ecological ‘self-endangerment’ of human society
and life in general. This is tied to what Beck describes as the sub-politics of risk
society, in which power operates largely outside the formal institutions of
government, resulting in a breakdown of the notion of a political centre capable of
controlling the processes of scientific-economic development. At the same time,
and despite this lack of a political centre, there has been a proliferation in
knowledge-based programs of risk creation, monitoring and intervention in the
most detailed levels of industrial management, by both state and non-state actors.
170
Beck’s work suggests that these processes are a defining feature of late
modernity and are quite different from the traditional distributional conflicts
characteristic of the era of primary industrialisation, which he places as coming to
a close by the early 1970s. (Beck, 1992b p.20-22)
There is a clear similarity in this line of argument with the distinction
Foucault drew between the ‘old’ environmental risks such as famine, and those
‘modern’ ones that result when the life of the human species is wagered ‘on its
own political strategies’. However, Foucault’s account of the emergence of
biopower in the eighteenth century casts doubt on Beck’s insistence that the ‘risk
society’ is a fundamentally new type of society or even a very recent
development. It may be that the sorts of social processes Beck focuses on,
particularly the relationship between technical capacity, expert knowledge and the
distribution of risks (and power) are not so much a fundamentally new
169
Foucault’s use of the term ‘modernity’ in other works is somewhat different. See Foucault,
(1991e).
170
See the discussion of Beck and Eder in Chapter 4 of this thesis.
119
phenomenon but simply a recent articulation of the biopolitics Foucault described
in another context. I give further consideration to the relationship between
Foucault and the work of Beck and Eder in the final chapter. For the present let us
return to the consideration of Foucault’s notion of biopower, before examining its
connection to his work on governmental rationality.
One useful way of understanding Foucault’s notion of biopower is to follow
Bryan Turner (1984 p.159), who argues that, notwithstanding his apparent
hostility to systematic theorising, Foucault’s work implicitly embraces a particular
causal explanation of the modern world. Turner identifies the ‘unifying theme’ of
Foucault’s work as a dual focus on the ‘rationalisation of the body and the
rationalisation of populations by new combinations of power and knowledge’. He
argues that these rationalisations are the effect of increasing population densities,
which in the nineteenth century came to threaten ‘the political order of society’.
(Turner, 1984 p.163- emphasis added) Turner rightly emphasises the role
population pressures played in Foucault’s analysis of the development of
biopower, 171 pointing out that
it is this factor which stands behind the expansion and development of
new regimes and regimens of control - a profusion of taxonomies, tables,
examinations, drills, dressage, chrestomathies, surveys, samples and
censuses. The pressure of men in urban space necessitates a new
institutional order of prisons, asylums, clinics, factories and schools in
which accumulated bodies can be made serviceable and safe. Just as the
space of knowledge experiences accumulations of new discourses, so the
social space is littered with bodies and the institutions which are designed
to control them. (Turner, 1984 p.160-1)
If this view is developed, not only is knowledge pivotal to practices of power,
but it is also central to the very constitution of the objects of upon which biopower
operates, that is, to the ‘making-up’ of both people and things. Biopolitics
therefore is inherently linked to the development and elaboration of specific forms
of expertise. This is a theme I consider in more detail later in this chapter. For the
present, it sufficient to emphasise that the definition and administration of
populations simultaneously requires the constitution and management of the
environment in which those populations exist and upon which they depend. Such a
conclusion is implicit in Foucault’s approach although not developed. As a
consequence Foucault does not adequately deal with the way in which the
political and economic problematisation of populations also gave rise, at a more
recent time, to a similar problematisation of nature and the environment.
Notwithstanding my suggestion above that Foucault hints at continuity between
171
Direct confirmation that this is Foucault’s approach can be seen in Foucault (1990) p.142 and
Foucault (1980b) p.171-2.
120
biopower and ecological risk, I develop a critique of Foucault's approach to the
natural sciences in Chapters 7 and 8. 172 Nevertheless, it is clear from Foucault’s
discussions of the biopolitical regulation of populations that this assumes not only
the disciplining of individuals and populations, but also, necessarily, a concern
with the administration of ‘all the conditions of life’ as represented by the
environment.
For Foucault, biopolitics as the task of administering life at the level of the
‘species body’, comes into existence at the multiple points of application to the
body (both individually and collectively) of disciplines such as public health,
medicine, demography, education, social welfare, etc. (Barret-Kriegal, 1992
p.194) Ecology and environmental management can also be regarded as
expressions of biopolitics, as these originate in, and operate upon, the same basic
concerns for managing the ‘continuous and multiple relations’ between the
population, its resources and the environment. Contemporary ecological
discourse, in other words, is an articulation of what Foucault calls the ‘populationriches problem’. This suggests a specifically ecological or environmental
dimension to biopolitics, which makes more complex the way in which we
understand the ‘body’ as the target and site of power. Not only are we forced to
deal with the individual ‘anatomical’ body and the social body, and the relations
between these, but we must also take into account an ecological relationship in
which the focus is on the relationship between the social body and the biological
species body. 173 This is not to suggest that there will not be new forms of
discipline and normality directed at the body at the individual level (indeed these
would appear to be a necessary component in ecological governmentality) 174.
172
See also Rouse (1993) p.137-62; (1987) Chapter 7; and Rutherford (1994a)
173
The term 'social body' can be regarded as a metaphor for ‘the collective embodiment of the
targets of power, the body as 'species', whether in the form of an entire population or a specific
group of prisoners, school children, the insane and so forth, who are subject to specific types
of administration and regulation.’ (Hewitt, 1983 p.71) Foucault however says that the term is
not simply a metaphor: it refers to a materiality. The police ‘take charge of the physical
element of the social body’; the object of the police is first and foremost the complete
regulation or ‘whole management’ of the ‘complex and multiple materiality’ of the social
body, the species body. The police is both an ‘institutional grouping’, that is, a specific set of
social apparatuses and administrative structures, and a ‘modality of intervention’, [Foucault et
al, quoted in Barret-Kriegal (1992)] that is, a generalised type of political technology, a
‘diagram’ or ‘schema’, ‘panopticism’. For a discussion of Foucault's ‘ambiguous’ use of these
two aspects of his notion of biopower, see Donnelly (1992) p.199-203.
174
For a discussion of how environmental education and environmental drills are combined, in the
case of the Canadian Green Plan, to instil new ecological disciplinary practices in the daily
lives of individuals, see Darier (1995) and also Bowerbank (1999). An anecdotal tale from the
author’s own experience can perhaps succinctly demonstrate such environmental disciplinary
practices. In the early 1990s certain state government jurisdictions in Australia became
concerned by the cancer risks of increased exposure of young school children to ultra violet
radiation resulting from atmospheric ozone depletion in the Southern Hemisphere. The school
authorities introduced rules requiring children to where sun hats outside during play breaks.
121
However, as with areas of social policy such as public health, the ecological is
primarily biopolitical in nature, that is, it is manifested in specific regulatory
controls aimed at the population, albeit from a somewhat different perspective.
Governmental rationality
Foucault’s work on biopolitics, especially the first volume of The History of
Sexuality represented a development that went beyond his earlier writings on the
relation between knowledge and power. As Mitchell Dean argues, the last chapter
of The History of Sexuality (Vol 1) in particular foreshadowed a new concern
with the problem of government and the role of the state that Foucault took up
during the period 1978-84. This was the main work in which Foucault considered
in some detail the relation between the ‘institutionalised micro-forms of work
upon the self ... and the global strategies of the government of the state.’ (Dean,
1994 p.175) Whereas Foucault’s earlier work had focused on power in terms of a
local microphysics of power, this later work recasts the problem of power at a
much broader, macro-level of analysis. This is not to suggest that Foucault
abandoned his strong emphasis on the importance of the micro-level origin and
application of power. Rather that the problem was reformulated in a more
complex and sophisticated manner, in which the analysis of the state, and
government in its broader sense, was not reliant on a juxtaposition of the micro
and macro levels of power.
Despite the change in focus that occurs in the writings on biopolitics, and
more fully in those on governmental rationality, these later works nevertheless
maintain two key concerns developed in his earlier writings. These are, first,
continuity between the earlier concern to elaborate a microphysics of power (the
disciplinary technologies of the body) and the sorts of biopolitical problems raised
by the regulation of entire populations and societies. Second, there is continuity
between both of these concerns and the practice of ethics as a form of
‘government of the self’. (Dean, 1994 p.176) Foucault’s work on government thus
takes as its object of analysis, to use Dean’s phrase, the ‘triple domain’ of
government. That is, its is concerned with understanding the multiple means by
which human conduct is governed through various practices of individual self-
Children who forgot their hats were restricted to areas of the school grounds where tree cover
provided shading. Here we have a very specific (and simple) regulation of the spatial
distribution of human individuals as biological entities based on a series of quite ‘abstract’
scientific knowledges and risk assessments, which included (1) radiation exposure dose
predictions based on the chemistry of CFC derived chlorine in the stratosphere and its
relationship to increased penetration into the lower atmosphere of several wavelengths of ultra
violet radiation; (2) epidemiological projections of the likely rate of melanoma cancers in the
population in 20 to 40 years later resulting from childhood exposure to sunburn; and (3) the
unknown level of risk to specific individuals given the statistical nature of hazard probabilities
at the population level.
122
government, the government of others, and the government of the state.
Foucault’s characterisation of government as ‘the conduct of conduct’ (Burchell,
1996 p.19; Foucault, 1982 p.220-1) delineates the field of government in a very
broad sense. It is a ‘massive domain’ that extends from the minutiae of individual
self-reflection to the depersonalised, anonymous rationalities concerned with the
political regulation of states, populations and societies. (Dean, 1994 p.176-7)
Foucault’s development of this notion of government was based on a
reconstruction of the principle forms, or ‘economies’ of power in the West that
contributed to the formation of the ‘governmental’ state. Key to this was the
development of new political relations (at the end of the sixteenth and during the
first half of the seventeenth centuries) that arose out of a discourse concerning the
art, or technique, of governing. This political discourse specifically centred on the
state as being its own end and having its own logic and nature, expressed in the
theory of raison d’etat. According to Foucault reason of state formed out of two
political technologies that lead to the formation of the modern nation-state. These
were the diplomatic-military practices that developed the external capacities of
states through the system of military alliances (leading to the Treaty of
Westphalia), and a political technology internal to the state known as the police,
which attended to the development of all ‘the means necessary to increase the
forces of the state from within’. These two political technologies came together in
the system of mercantilism or cameralism to give rise to the formation of the
modern state. (Foucault, 1988b p.103-4)
It was particularly in the development of the police that we see the beginnings
of the modern political rationality that enables the formation of biopower. Gordon
suggests that the term ‘police ‘ (‘the science of police’ or Polizeiwissenschaften)
as used by Foucault is most closely rendered in English as policy. (Gordon, 1991
p.10-11) It is particularly in the German and French development of the notion of
‘the police’ (or policy science) that Foucault says we see the beginnings of the
modern political and governmental rationalities that his notion of biopower aims
to analyse.175 This new ‘police state’ (or policy state), unlike previous forms of
rule, did not operate primarily on the basis of the juridical principles of
sovereignty and territory. Until the end of the sixteenth century the juridical
foundation of sovereignty and the state was territory and the subjects that
inhabited it, so that, said Foucault, sovereignty was ‘not exercised on things’.
Police theorists however replaced the emphasis on maintaining the principality
(territory) with a concern for the science of police, or art of government. Central
to this new perspective was a definition of government that no longer focused
primarily on the governing of territory but rather on the governing of things. In
Foucault’s words, for the exponents of police science
175
See Rabinow (1984b) p.16 and Foucault (1991c; 1988b)
123
what government has to do with is not territory but rather a complex
composed of men and things. The things with which this sense of
government is concerned are in fact men, but men in their relations, their
links, their imbrications with those other things which are wealth,
resources, means of subsistence, the territory with its specific qualities,
climate, irrigation, fertility, etc; men in their relations to that other kind of
things, customs, habits, ways of acting and thinking etc; lastly, men in
their relations to that other kind of things, accidents and misfortunes such
as famine, epidemics, death, etc. (Foucault, 1991c p.93)
There was thus a movement away from emphasis on the negative tasks of
politics, understood as force, as the task of resisting external opponents and
enforcing internal law and order which was characteristic of the sovereign form of
power. Instead the principal concern of the state increasingly became the
productive tasks of the police, involving a continuous and remarkably specific
series of ‘positive interventions in the behaviour of individuals’ and groups.
(Foucault, 1991c p.93) These new police doctrines of government represented a
radical shift from the largely negative emphasis on the ‘holding out’ of sovereign
power within a territory, to the emphasis on the positive, detailed management of
the entire social body, and, to ensuring the abundance and prosperity of the
population.
Similarly, the doctrine of reason of state, in holding that the principles of
government were inherent to the state rather than deriving from natural or divine
law, posed the problem of determining the needs or interests of the state and
acquiring the knowledge and information necessary to realise those interests. The
task of administration rested above all else on the detailed knowledge of the
‘complex and multiple materiality’ of all those things upon which the state’s
strength and wealth depended. Thus the task of administration, of the police, rests
above all on the gathering of detailed information on all matters relating to the
resources and needs of the state. The term statistics, noted Foucault, meant
precisely ‘the science of the state’, involving detailed and precise empirical
‘knowledge of the state in all its elements’ and particularly as these dealt with
such things as geography, demography, natural resources, agriculture, climate etc.
In this was to be found the main feature of the conduct of reason of state and the
science of police, or policy. In order to efficiently arrange things in the best
interests of the state (that is, for ‘convenient ends’), it was necessary to aspire
towards an ever more detailed knowledge of the resources of the state, including
all the characteristics of its population. (Foucault, 1991c p.93-6)
What emerges most clearly in Foucault’s analysis of police science as a
specifically modern form of governmental reason is the dependence of
government, in all its forms (ethical and political) on a detailed, pragmatic
knowledge of that ‘complex composed of men and things’. That is, knowledge of
populations, resources and those factors which affect their productivity. The
124
strength of the state, in police theory, was directly linked to the well being of the
population. The power of the state is increased inasmuch as the physical (and
social) condition of the population is secured, made productive and improved.
Foucault identified in his examination of the work of the French and German
police theorists (particularly von Justi), the clearest definition of the aim of the
modern art of government. That aim was ‘to develop those elements constitutive
of individuals’ lives in such a way that their development also fosters that of the
strength of the state.’ Hence, the police state’s concern to acquire the most
exhaustively detailed knowledge of, and on the basis of that to intervene in, the
activities of each of its citizens assumes a pastoral, even totalitarian, dimension.
(Foucault, 1981c p. 245-8, 252) At the same time, and because of this, the police
state is also the ‘state of prosperity’. (Gordon, 1991 p.10) This should not be seen
as support for those, such as Habermas and Honneth, who see in such a statement
evidence of Foucault’s alleged view of modernity as a totally administered
society. What is missed by such an assertion is the genealogical lineage pointed to
by Foucault’s analysis. Reason of state and police are elements that, while they
contribute to the modern governmental rationality, do not fully define it. The
police quest for ‘total’ knowledge was to prove unrealisable in practice. Indeed, if
we are to fully understand Foucault’s account of how disciplinary biopower and
modern state rationality (exemplified in reason of state and police) are brought
into play it is also necessary to take into account the influence of liberalism.
Liberalism
Foucault’s analysis suggested the modern art of government is derived from
two distinct yet related sources - first, the Cameralist/police science influence
with its emphasis on a pragmatic knowledge of the state’s capacity and resources,
and second, liberalism. As I have suggested, police science harboured within it an
aspiration to a perfect or total knowledge of the workings of all the state’s
resources and population. Such knowledge, it was thought, was necessary if the
development of the state was to be regulated so as to maximise the realisation of
its own ends (security, prosperity etc) in the most efficient manner. Thus police
science, as a governmental rationality premised upon the principle of reason of
state, always operated on the presumption of their being ‘too little government’.
(Foucault, 1981b p.354)
Liberalism on the other hand emerges as a critique of state reason. (Gordon,
1991 p.15) Liberalism is frequently understood primarily as a political (and
economic) theory or ideology concerned with the defence of individual liberty
from encroachment by the state. However Foucault’s approach was to view
liberalism as a specific practice of government that embodies a continuous
reflection on not only the limits of government but also its necessity. (Foucault,
1981b p.354-6) Where liberalism differs from reason of state is that the state is no
125
longer considered as its own end, and neither is government considered to be
synonymous with the state. Thus Foucault argued
Liberalism, then, is to be analysed as a principle and method of
rationalising the exercise of government ... the liberal rationalisation finds
its point of departure in the idea that government would not be considered
its own end. Here, government is not to be understood as an institution
but, rather, as an activity which consists in directing human conduct
within the setting and with the instruments of state. ... Phrased differently,
this latter question asked what makes it necessary for there to be a
government and what objectives ought it to pursue with regard to society
in order to justify its existence. (Foucault, 1981b p.354-5: emphasis
added)
As with police science and reason of state, the concern of liberalism was (and
is) how to achieve maximal efficiency of rule, but of a different sort. The interests
of the population can no longer be understood as necessarily coextensive with
those of the state. Liberalism is still concerned with governing, that is, with how
human conduct can be directed to appropriate ends. Where liberalism differs, as a
mode of governmental rationality, is that it specifically considers what
governmental tasks can be efficiently (and legitimately) conducted by the state
and what ambitions must of necessity be regarded as outside of state competence
in order to efficiently achieve what does lie within its power. (Foucault, 1981b
p.356; Gordon, 1991 p.15)
As a critique of state reason, liberalism called into question the immediate
unity of knowledge and government assumed by police science. The liberal
critique, developed by theorists such as Adam Smith and Adam Ferguson, pointed
to the impossibility, in the economic sphere, of possessing knowledge of the
interests and preferences of individuals such that government could direct and
regulate private economic activities for the public good. Foucault noted that this
should also to be seen as a problem posed by liberalism for government in
general. The state, according to liberal theorists, cannot in fact posses the sorts of
totalising knowledge upon which police science sought to base state action. The
opacity, the unknowability, of economic processes precluded the possibility of an
economic sovereignty assumed by reason of state. Thus the familiar liberal
assertion that the state’s ability to act (beneficially) is restricted by the inherently
fallible and limited scope of its knowledge. 176
One result of the influence of liberal thought was to initiate a new relation
between knowledge and government in which political economy assumed a
greater autonomy and distance from pragmatic state needs than its Cameralist
176
For discussion of Foucault's analysis of liberalism see Burchell (1991) and Gordon (1991).
126
forms. Political economy was seen as a form of knowledge that was central to
state functioning, but it could not deliver the sorts of detailed state planning
envisaged by police science (or the later Leninist appropriation of this same
dream). Political economy therefore assumed, said Foucault, ‘the role of a
knowledge which is ‘lateral to’ or ‘in tete-a-tete with’ the art of governing: it
cannot however, in itself constitute that art.’ (Gordon, 1991 p.16) 177 Liberalism
did not dismiss the need for government, but rather, and this is what Foucault saw
as distinctive about liberal governmental rationality, it dissolved the immediate
unity between knowledge and government, and consequently the equation of
maximising governmental effectiveness with maximising governmental
regulation. (Burchell, 1991 p.138-9) 178 In doing so liberalism brought into being a
new relationship between knowledge and government, involving what Colin
Gordon has succinctly described as ‘a new mode of objectification of governed
reality’, that resituates ‘governmental reason within a newly complicated, open
and unstable politico-epistemic configuration.’ (Gordon, 1991 p.16) Foucault
called this new configuration of knowledge and techniques of rule
governmentality. He described this as the
ensemble formed by the institutions, procedures, analyses and reflections,
the calculations and tactics that allow the exercise of this very specific
albeit complex form of power, which has as its target population, as its
principal form of knowledge political economy and its essential technical
means apparatuses of security. ... this type of power which may be termed
government, (results) on the one hand, in the formation of a whole series
of specific governmental apparatuses, and on the other, in the
development of a whole complex of savoirs [knowledges]. (Foucault,
1991c p.102-3: emphasis added)
This relationship between particular, more or less formalised bodies of
knowledge and specific administrative mechanisms has become a crucial feature
of government in advanced liberal societies. Increasingly in such complex
societies government, the conduct of conduct, necessarily relied on the role of
professional expertise. As Donzelot has demonstrated, throughout the nineteenth
century there was a proliferation of alliances between private and professional
agents that led to the formation of a series of welfare programs directed at
governing perceived problems within the social body. (Donzelot, 1993; 1979)
Over time these welfare programs became linked with the functions and
institutions of the state, however, the adoption of these welfare programs by the
state did not lead to the rise of an all-powerful, interventionist state. Instead it
resulted in the bringing together of a diverse network of arguments, projects, and
mechanisms through which various political forces sought to pursue a multitude
177
Gordon cites Foucault’s lecture at College du France, 28 March, 1978.
178
Burchell cites Foucault’s ‘Naissance de la biopolitique’, in Resumes des Course.
127
of social and political objectives. Thus welfare did not represent a coherent, state
plan for social regulation and normalisation, but rather was composed of a series
of networks assembled from diverse, often antagonistic elements. Modern social
welfare did not originate as centrally directed projects of state action but was ‘a
composition of fragile and mobile relationships’ between non-state professionals,
intellectuals and social movements, and state agencies. (Rose and Miller, 1992
p.192-3) Hence, the development of social welfare and subsequently the welfare
state involved forging and maintaining alliances and networks between diverse
experts and political forces, of which the state was only one. In a similar way the
development of programs of environmental security can be understood as drawing
on an equally complex, open and unstable ‘politico-epistemic configuration’.
Such a perspective suggests that while the aspirations for an ecological ‘police
science’ may well exist, the issues raised by the liberal critique of government
mitigate against the success of straightforward technocratic solutions to ecological
problems.
The modern discourse of scientific ecology
Consistent with Foucault’s analysis of the rise of biopolitics, the
problematisation of the relationship between population and the environment can
be linked to three major social developments in the eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries. These were the emergence of modern biology as the science of life, the
rapid increase in the population of Europe leading to a series of mass migrations
to other continents, (Foucault, 1991c p.98; Worster, 1987b p.92-5) and the
development of an international capitalist market. (Dreyfus and Rabinow, 1982
p.135; Rabinow, 1984b p.17-8; Worster, 1987b p.92-5) Work by environmental
historians has emphasised the importance of the interaction between European
population growth, migration and the development of international markets in the
same period pointed to in Foucault’s work on the emergence of biopolitics.
Foucault was interested in ‘the deep historical link’ between the emergence of
biopolitics and the population-resources problem, which he describes as ‘the
process which isolates the economy as a specific sector of reality and political
economy as the science and technique of intervention of government in that field
of reality.’ (Foucault, 1991c p.102) The environmental historian David Worster
has argued that the ‘two great global forces’ of population growth and world
markets drove social changes in the nineteenth century resulting in an
‘environmental upheaval’ that was to ‘remake nature with geological
effectiveness.’ (Worster, 1987b p.95-7) 179 Richard Grove has argued that new
forms of management of colonial environments in the period 1670 to the mid1950s, such as forestry, irrigation and soil conservation, had a more profound
179
See also Crosby (1986).
128
‘political’ impact than many of the other more ‘conspicuous and dramatic aspects
of colonial rule.’ (Grove, 1990 p.17)
Foucault saw the emergence of biopolitics in the eighteenth century as linked
to an expanding series of population discourses focusing on health, criminality,
education, sexuality, etc. Interestingly, at this same time we also find evidence in
the historical scholarship of the beginnings of another new discourse that had as
its object what today we would call the environment. Worster, for example, placed
the first systematic documentation of concern about this new problem with the
publication in 1864 of Man and Nature by George Perkins Marsh, a work that
sought to demonstrate the danger to humanity and the rest of nature posed by
rapid change in the global environment. (Worster, 1987b p.91-2) 180 Clarence
Glacken also identified Marsh’s work as marking the arrival of a recognisably
modern perspective on the relationship of humans to nature. The nineteenth
century thus saw, in Glacken’s words, the advent of ‘an entirely different order,
influenced by the theory of evolution, specialisation in the attainment of
knowledge, (and) acceleration in the transformation of nature.’ (Glacken, 1967
p.704-5) Anna Bramwell in her history of environmentalism similarly points to
modern ecological concepts as deriving from ‘a set of biological, physical science
and geographical ideas that arose separately around the mid-nineteenth century.’
(Bramwell, 1989 p.15) 181 Malthus’s ideas on population, published in An Essay
on the Principle of Population at the close of the eighteenth century, along with
Darwin’s The Origin of Species published in 1859, were seen as providing key
themes discernible in the modern ecological analysis of environmental problems.
(Pepper, 1984 p.91-103; Worster, 1987a) 182
The population-resources problem, the central theme of the nineteenth century
discourses pointed to by both Foucault and environmental historians, remains
central to the contemporary discourses of ecological crisis. A range of works
influential in the environmental debate of the last four decades had as their key
focus the notion of the carrying capacity of the Earth, which was seen as a
biological law with a profound influence for contemporary environmental and
population-resources problems. While the emphasis and political implications
drawn from this idea vary, most saw population growth as a fundamental factor in
ecological crisis. Well-known examples of this approach include Hardin (1968),
180
In Britain the establishment of the first national environmental group was in 1865 (the
Commons, Open Spaces and Footpaths Preservation Society). The US Sierra Club was formed
in 1892. See Pepper (1984) p.14. There was also a proliferation of colonial geographic and
conservation societies during this period. See Schneider (1990) and Grove (1990).
181
See also Lowe and Goyder (1983) p.16.
182
Worster notes that the bio-economic approach of post-World War Two systems ecology
displays a diminished reliance on earlier Darwinian evolutionary influences. ( p.331) See also
Grove (1992)
129
Ehlrich (1968), Meadows et al., (1972) and The Club of Rome, Goldsmith (1972)
and The Ecologist, and governmental reports such as that of the U.S. Council on
Environmental Quality (1981). Other influential works on ecological crisis placed
less emphasis on absolute population levels as the cause of environmental
degradation. Instead these often focused on the problem of global pollution, and
the mode and intensity of resource exploitation, which was in turn seen as related
to population levels, and industrialism (and consumerism) as a system of
production. Here the central concern was the impact of new forms of technology
which have proliferated in the post-World War Two period, 183 and which are
characterised by the extensive manufacture and use of synthetic, toxic chemicals.
Carson (1962), Commoner (1971), and Bookchin (1962) were important examples
of this work.
These and numerous similar works have several important features in
common. Each problematised the environment as the previously taken for granted
biological basis for human life and constituted it politically as a ‘topic of social
concern and potential conflict.’ (Cramer et al., 1989 p.96) Each sought to locate
their claims to authority within the framework of a global ecosystems approach to
ecology,184 whether it be Hardin’s and Ehlrich’s biological law of carrying
capacity, Commoner’s four laws of ecology,185 or The Club of Rome’s complex
computer modelling of the limits to growth186. Central to each was the view that
human populations are constrained by the operation of ecological laws that were
biological and therefore both natural and non-anthropocentric. These ecological
laws were understood as having significant economic and political consequences,
and were frequently expressed in the economic form of externalities impacting on
ecologically defined public goods.187 The concern of this contemporary discourse
was (and is) how to manage populations and resources in relation to their natural
environments. This focus remains central to current environmental discourses; it
is, for example, a clear theme in the Brundtland report to the United Nations
(Brundtland, 1987) and the ongoing international debate on sustainable
development since the publication of that report. This continues to be evident in
the 1992 United Nations Earth Summit (Brown et al., 1990; MacNeill et al.,
183
It is these sort of developments and their effects that Beck (1992b) focuses on as the key
distinguishing feature of ‘risk society’.
184
I discuss the significance of global ecosystem modelling for a biopolitics of the environment
later in this Chapter, and also in Rutherford (1997a).
185
Commoner's laws: 1. Everything is connected to everything else; 2. Everything must go
somewhere; 3. Nature knows best; and, 4. There is no such thing as a free lunch. (Commoner,
1971 p.33-46)
186
These limits are presented as the interaction between world population, industrialisation,
pollution, food production, and resource depletion. See Meadows et al, (1972) p.29.
187
Public goods in this case are often defined in terms that include a broader, non-anthropocentric
biotic community, as well as human beings.
130
1991) and the establishment of the UN Sustainable Development Commission and
the 1994 UN Population Conference.
Expertise and governmentality
Before looking specifically at the development of these programs of
environmental security and governance, it is necessary to consider in more detail
the connection between expert knowledge and governmentality. In doing this I
draw in particular on the work by Nikolas Rose and Peter Miller on
governmentality. This work emphasises that the exercise of political power in
advanced liberal societies depends to a significant degree on the way in which the
intellectual resources, technical activities and social authority of expertise are
mobilised to govern the conduct of individuals and populations. (Rose, 1993;
Rose and Miller, 1992)
A major consequence of Foucault’s approach to the problem of government is
that it calls into question the straightforward equation of political power with the
actions of the state. Thus Foucault’s critique of sovereignty argued that political
thinking had attached ‘excessive value’ to the role of the state in government. For
Foucault, and later governmentality theorists such as Rose and Miller, the
problem of government is not confined to the state. Following from Foucault's
analysis of liberalism, ‘government’ should be understood as encompassing a
much broader range of forces which, in a variety of ways, have sought to manage
and regulate the behaviour of the population, both in its biopolitical ‘aggregate
effects’ and in its disciplinary ‘depths and details’. (Foucault, 1991c p.102)
Foucault therefore argued that it is a mistake to attribute the state with the degree
of coherence or ‘rigorous functionality’ that Western political thinking has
traditionally done. Rather than the state being a calculating political subject or
centre from which power emanates, it is in fact a historical sedimentation made up
of a multitude of techniques for governing conduct, to which the state has
attached itself in various ways. Indeed Foucault suggests that the
governmentalisation of the state is ... what has permitted the state to
survive, and ... if the state is what it is today, this is so precisely thanks to
this governmentality, which is at once internal and external to the state,
since it is the tactics of government which make possible the continual
definition and redefinition of what is within the competence of the state
and what is not, the public versus the private, and so on; thus the state can
only be understood in its survival and its limits on the basis of the general
tactics of governmentality. (Foucault, 1991c p.103)
In effect then, the modern state must be seen not as that which gives rise to
government, but as one important, yet nonetheless historically contingent form
that government has taken. Such an approach to understanding government
emphasises the multiplicity of the practical knowledges and techniques brought to
131
bear on the general domain of the population in order to render it amenable to
intervention and regulation. (Miller and Rose, 1993 p.77-8) According to
Foucault, a central feature of Western modernity, from the eighteenth century
onwards, is thus not the ‘etatisation of society’ but ‘the ‘governmentalisation’ of
the state’. (Foucault, 1991c p.103) As indicated earlier in this chapter, this
governmentalisation developed around biopower with its problematisation of
human beings as living, biological beings and which Foucault saw as marking the
point at which Western society could be said to have crossed the ‘threshold of
modernity’. (Foucault, 1990).
Developing his earlier notion of power/knowledge, Foucault’s work on
governmentality emphasised the centrality of knowledge to the practice of
government. This is a theme that has been further developed by Rose and Miller,
who stress that governmentality has a distinctively discursive character. In
particular they argue that language must be understood as performative, so that
the way in which language is employed in political rationalities is not simply
contemplative or even descriptive. Rather it is the means through which the
specific domains of governmental concern are constituted and made amenable to
intervention and regulation. (Miller and Rose, 1993 p.78-81; Rose, 1993 p.288-9;
Rose and Miller, 1992 p.177) Pivotal to this is the production and mobilisation of
systematic bodies of knowledge relating to the particular social domain in
question. Rose argues that throughout the late nineteenth and first half of the
twentieth centuries, the authority of social science expertise became intimately
connected with the apparatus of formal political rule, culminating in ‘welfarism’
or the welfare state. The key point however, is that while this professional
expertise provided a social means of governing behaviour, it also enabled this for
the most part to be done in a way that was removed from detailed and
comprehensive political direction by the state. This liberal welfarism facilitated
both the formulation of social norms and consequently the social evaluation of
individual conduct against these, while maintaining a considerable degree of
separation between the normative, truth-producing activities of professional
authorities and the exercise of the coercive capacities of the state. Keeping much
of the knowledge producing activities of the social sciences removed from
centralised political control thus continued what Foucault described (in relation to
political economy) as the ‘lateral’ role played by knowledge in the liberal art of
governance. (Gordon, 1991 p.16) As Nikolas Rose points out, for liberal
welfarism
The truth claims of expertise were highly significant ... through the
powers of truth, distant events and persons could be governed ‘at arms
length’: political rule would not itself set out the norms of individual
conduct, but would install and empower a variety of ‘professionals’ who
would, investing them with authority to act as experts in the devices of
social rule. (Rose, 1993 p.285)
132
Rose goes on to argue that over the past fifty years, such welfarist ‘strategies
of rule’ have undergone fundamental changes. This has been due in part to the
neo-liberal critique of the supposed failures of the welfare state, but also because
welfarism itself laid the basis for new techniques of rule, which he regards as
fundamental to constituting advanced liberalism as a distinctive mode of
government. 188 Advanced liberalism establishes a different relationship between
government and expertise - unlike welfarism, the emphasis is not on social rule
but rather it seeks to govern through ‘the regulated choices’ of the individual. At
the same time it attempts to affect a further separation of professional expertise
from the state through marketisation and the subsequent subjection of expert
knowledge production to ‘the rationalities of competition, accountability and
consumer demand.’ (Rose, 1993 p.291-2)
Rose’s argument is directed particularly at the social sciences and economics,
and as he suggests, the discontinuity between welfarist and advanced liberal
strategies of rule should be understood as different problematisations of rule
rather than as a strict periodisation. (Rose, 1993 p.285) The degree to which
ecological governmentality can be characterised in this way is a matter that I will
return to in the final chapter. Here I will note that the problematisation of the
environment as an object of government would appear, at least in northern
Europe, to give credence to the notion of an ecological version of the welfare
state. However, it is certainly the case that since the late 1980s there has been
considerable debate about ‘state failure’ with respect to environmental protection
and increasing attention to the role of market-based instruments in regulating
environmental behaviour.189
Rose and Miller (1992 p.178-9) suggest that governmental (or political)
rationalities characteristically possess moral, epistemological, and idiomatic
elements. 190 It is the epistemological character that is perhaps most important in
environmental discourse, for it is in this domain that governmental rationalities
are articulated in terms of a specifically ecological knowledge of the objects and
problems to be addressed. In this case the epistemology originates in scientific
ecology: it is this that provides the authoritative accounts of the sorts of entities
which environmental government must be concerned with managing ecosystems, global climate and atmospheric processes, habitat and species
diversity, population and carrying capacity, etc.
188
There is a parallel here with theorists such as Beck, who argues that ‘risk society’ comes into
being partially as a result of the success of welfarism and economic growth. See Chapter 4 of
this thesis.
189
See Eckersley (1995), and also my discussion of notions of ‘ecological modernisation’ in
Rutherford (1999a).
190
In particular, environmental concerns have produced a vast outpouring of discourse on ethical
and normative questions.
133
Ecology as regulatory science
Hence, consistent with Rose and Miller’s characterisation of governmental
rationalities, scientific expertise can be said to be fundamental to the both the
political and epistemic definition of contemporary environmental problems.191 In
its modern form ecology emerged in the 1940s and 1950s, based on an ‘energyeconomic model’ of the environment in which the essential feature was the flow
of energy through ecosystems. (Jamison, 1993 p.189; Worster, 1987a p.311, 339)
This bio-economic paradigm, or systems ecology, is a product of twentieth
century science, a distinctly transnational enterprise drawing upon European and
US national scientific traditions, but appearing in its contemporary form in the US
in the period since World War Two. Despite the popularising of nature in holistic,
and sometimes organicist terms, the bio-economic model can be said to express an
‘agronomic attitude toward nature’ which has sought to provide the analytic tools
needed to ‘intensively farm’ the Earth’s resources. (Jamison, 1993 p.193)
The language of modern systems ecology reflects this, abounding with
agronomic and economic terms such as producers, consumers, total energy
income, yield, crop, gross and net productivity, nutrient capital, competitive
exclusion, energy budget, efficiency, etc. Modern scientific ecology from the
1940s came to see itself as ‘the science of natural economics’ in which nature
became a ‘a modernised economic system, ... a corporate state, a chain of
factories, and assembly line’. Not surprisingly conflict is often seen as having
‘little place in such a well-regulated economy.’ (Worster, 1987a p.311-13) By the
mid to late 1980s, this science-based model of the social relation to nature was
increasingly incorporated into a set of governmental programs based on a political
rationality that Albert Weale has labelled ecological modernisation. This
perspective challenges the view of an inherent conflict between environmental
protection and economic growth per se and instead sees the maintenance of a
healthy environment as an essential precondition for long-term economic
development. (Weale, 1992 p.31) 192 This view shaped the emergence of a
complex raft of ‘sustainable development’ policies that by the early 1990s had
gained widespread influence with national governments and international
191
This is particularly evident when one considers the importance of complex mathematical
modelling of the global environment (popularised by The Limits to Growth). The current
approach to global warming is a far more sophisticated, and more politically influential,
response involving more complex computer modelling of global phenomena than that of The
Limits to Growth three decades ago. See Buttel and Taylor (1992) p.218, 221-2, and
Rutherford (1997a).
192
The claim that economic development and environmental quality are mutually exclusive is
associated with the counter-cultural aspects of environmentalism (eg ‘deep ecology’) – or what
Eder describes as the purity model of nature. See Chapter 4 of this thesis. See also (Eder,
1996)
134
institutions through the United Nations Conference on Environment and
Development process.193 Ecology can thus be seen as developing from the 1950s
and extending into the 1990s, as the rationale behind a new, and increasingly
influential, form of political economy.
The rise of the systems approach to ecology occurred in a very specific
historical and cultural context. In a general sense systems ecology appears as the
product of the industrialisation of science. The emergence of ‘big science’ during
and after World War Two saw the organisation of scientific research in the US
along large-scale, capital-intensive, corporate lines, where research output
increasingly became an important contributor to economic growth and national
power. Applied systems ecology in this period gained significant impetus from
work conducted by the US Atomic Energy Commission, originating in the
Manhattan Project, into the problems of nuclear waste and radiation ecology.
(Kwa, 1993) Jamison points to three ways in which the post-war development of
modern systems ecology was shaped by the US institutional and cultural context
in which it emerged. First the industrialisation of science and the influence this
new industrial setting had on generating the view of ecology as ‘a powerful
technique of social engineering ... (which could potentially) ... regulate and
control the flows of pollutants and other human interventions through large scale
ecosystems.’ (Jamison, 1993 p.197-8) Second, the availability and popularity in
the US of powerful computer technology that allowed the unparalleled application
of mathematical models to natural processes. This was a direct extension of the
conceptualisation of ecological interactions as cybernetic, ‘self-regulating,
feedback systems’ that had emerged originally from the use of computers in the
Manhattan Project for the development of weapons guidance systems. Third, an
American tradition combining the influence of a utilitarian Progressive-era
conservation philosophy with the legacy of pragmatic regional planning programs
of the 1930s facilitated the development of an approach to ecology that lent itself
to large-scale environmental control and management. (Jamison, 1993 p.194-8;
Worster, 1987a p.312)
While the industrialisation of science, including ecology, became evident in
the US towards the end of World War Two and grew during the 1950s,
environmental concerns throughout the 1950s and early 1960s tended to reflect
the professional interests of scientists. (Cramer et al., 1989 p.96-7) These
professional research interests played a significant role in the development of a
coherent, science-based environmentalism through the International Geophysical
Year (1957-8) and the International Biological Program (1964-74). The IBP in
particular was a massive transnational enterprise involving research in 97
193
The UNCED report, Our Common Future (Brundtland, 1987) provides a particularly clear
statement of how this new political rationality is deeply embedded in the discourse on
sustainable development.
135
countries directed towards the understanding of the biological basis of
productivity and human welfare. The work of the IBP emphasised areas of
research which were ‘calculated to benefit from international collaboration, and
were urgent because of the rapid rate of changes taking place in all environments
throughout the world.’ The focus of the IBP was distinctively ecological in
character, being directed towards understanding ‘organic production ... and the
potentialities and uses of new and existing natural resources, ... (as well as) human
adaptability to change.’ (Worthington, 1983 p.165) 194
The sorts of extensive, transnational research programs on ecological issues
mentioned above came throughout the 1960s and 1970s increasingly to
characterise scientific and political discourse on the environment. From the end of
the 1960s, through the establishment of a wide range of environmental legislation
and enforcement agencies, the advanced industrialised countries experienced a
rapid growth of state intervention directed at environmental regulation and
planning. Ecological and environmental research in the 1970s thus laid the
foundation for public policies of significant economic and political impact,
particularly in terms of the regulatory intervention in the activities of industry. In
financial terms alone these are significant,195 however of more general importance
is that the period since the early 1970s has seen the significant institutionalisation
of what could be described as forms of ecological governmentality. Two
important aspects of this have been the growth of what has been described as
regulatory science, and the international spread of procedures for environmental
impact assessment (EIA).
Sheila Jasanoff has used the notion of regulatory science to characterise the
widespread reliance of the advanced industrial state on extensive networks of
expert scientific advisory bodies. The increasing integration of science and policy
making has become a central feature of environmental (and health) regulation in
such states (Beck, 1992a; Hart and Victor, 1993; Jasanoff, 1990) as well as in
international institutions and processes. (Hass, 1990) 196 Adapting the
194
For discussion of the importance of the IBP for the growth and institutionalisation of modern
scientific ecology, see Kwa (1987); Bocking (1995); Caldwell (1991) p.261; Egerton (1983)
p.268-71; Golley (1993) p.109-166; McIntosh (1985) p.213-41.
195
For example, the direct cost of complying with US pollution control regulations is estimated to
be in excess of US$100 billion per year (Jasanoff, 1992 p.195). The US commercial market for
the transport, storage and disposal of hazardous wastes alone was $US 3,000 million per year
in 1997, while environmental remediation and consulting services was around $US 8,000
million in the same year. (HazNews, 1998 p.1)
196
Hass uses the term ‘epistemic communities’ to refer to the role played by scientists in bringing
specialised knowledge into the policy-making process on environmental issues at the
transnational level. While Hass and his supporters are cautious about the applicability of this
approach beyond the specific cases studied, the work of Jasanoff (1990), Jamison (1993) and
others clearly suggests that a rigid separation between ‘science’ and ‘policy’ and the
136
‘governmentality’ approach to encompass the phenomenon of regulatory science
focuses attention on the key political role such expert advisory groups play as loci
of epistemological legitimation and policing. By framing the definition of
ecological risks and by certifying what is to count as scientifically acceptable
knowledge of the natural world, regulatory science and the extended ‘epistemic
communities’ of policy makers with which such science is integrated, provides
what Rose and Miller (1992) term ‘the intellectual machinery of government’.
While attempts to define environment-society relationships in terms of systems
ecology produce a high level of technical uncertainty and thus the potential for
social conflict, regulatory science can be understood as an example of how liberal
governmentality disassociates the ‘substantive authority of expertise from the
apparatuses of political rule’. (Rose, 1993 p.285) This is a theme that also
emerges in the work of Beck, although with somewhat less sophistication than is
evident in that of the ‘governmentality’ approach.
The rapid expansion of social regulation associated with the growth of
discourse on ecological problems from the 1970s produced a largely new domain
for the biopolitical administration of life. The population became the target for a
new form of ecological security and welfare in which environmental agencies and
the professional disciplines required by them set about the task of protecting the
public from hazardous and environmentally damaging technologies. Such
programs of government demanded ‘ever more complex predictive analyses of the
risks and benefits of regulation.’ (Jasanoff, 1990 p.3) As Brian Wynne has noted,
the regulatory ‘turn to science’, as an attempt to provide greater stability and
legitimacy in environmental policy, ‘also in important respects ... defined society,
by tacitly defining the scope and nature of social intervention in public policy risk
decisions.’ (Wynne, 1992 p.746-8) The increasing importance of ecology as a
regulatory science is therefore a particularly significant articulation of the
biopolitics that Foucault saw as characteristic of modern governmental
rationalities. The emergence of ecology as a regulatory science is clearly linked to
the growth of ‘big science’, despite the anti-corporatist orientation of many
environmental movements. Indeed a notable feature of regulatory science is the
central role state agencies and industrial interests (especially transnational
corporations) play in the normative constitution of ecological knowledge, that is,
in the manufacture, negotiation and certification of knowledge. (Wynne, 1992
p.754) Regulatory ecological science does not so much describe the environment
as both actively constitute it as an object of knowledge and, through various
modes of positive intervention, manage and police it.
These biopolitical strategies for the regulation of the ecological life of entire
populations could be regarded as illiberal, inasmuch as their focus is less on the
‘domestic’ and ‘international’ manifestations of the science-policy interrelationship is open to
question.
137
interests of the individual than on the population and the broader ‘ecosystem’.
However in some regards the environment can be understood in much the same
way as the economy; for liberal government the task would thus be how to take
proper account of this other natural realm, particularly given the close
interdependence between the two. Posed in this way, the problem of nature is
subject to the same sorts of questions regarding the methods of rule as are applied
to the economy. The ecological injunction that everything is connected to
everything else reproduces in the environmental sphere a problem similar to that
of the opacity of economic processes, and suggests also the impossibility of a
comprehensive environmental sovereignty. One the one hand, environmental
problems are subject to natural laws, and must therefore be dealt with by technical
means based on expert knowledge. On the other hand, governmental authorities
(both state and non-state) must also take into account the effect that these natural
processes have on the wealth and welfare of citizens, both collectively at the level
of the population and as individuals and hence their effect on ‘the economy’. This
raises the problem of the legitimacy of such authorities. (Rose, 1993 p.292)
The resort to scientific expertise, particularly in the institutional form
provided by regulatory science, is in this respect consistent with the liberal
response to the dilemma of too little government versus too much. As was seen in
previous discussion of Beck, the lack of a political centre capable of subjecting
the ‘mega’ risks generated by economic and technological development to any
effective form of public accountability or authorisation is a chronic problem for
ecological discourse. If as I have argued, environmental problems are yet another
side of what Foucault called the ‘population-riches problem’, it will be impossible
in practice to separate ecological issues from the sorts questions that arise for
liberalism in relation to governing the economy. This is not to suggest that the
responses will be identical, but simply that the problem of governing the
environment will be subject to a similar set of constraints, as governing
environmental performance means intervening in the economic activities of
individuals and companies. 197
Environmental assessment & modelling as technologies of
government
Foucault suggested that it is often in the mundane and humble procedures of
examination and assessment at the micro-level that we can discern the operation
of biopower. In this context the technique of environmental impact assessment
(EIA) provides a useful illustration of one aspect of ecological governmentality.
As noted above, a major element in the response to environmental problems from
197
One need only look at the burgeoning of environmental economics as a significant discipline in
the past twenty years to appreciate this point.
138
the 1960s onwards has involved substantive legislation aimed at regulating
particular pollutants. However, the 1969 introduction of the US National
Environment Policy Act (NEPA) marked an important departure from this
traditional legal-juridical path. The NEPA adopted a procedural approach to
environment protection requiring the preparation of detailed environmental
impact statements for major development projects that had the potential to
significantly affect the environment. By the 1980s the US EIA process had been
adapted and implemented in one form or another in many other industrialised
countries. EIA sets out statutory criteria for ecological assessment requiring
government agencies to take account of these criteria in their decision making.
However, EIA goes beyond legislating for a science-based, ‘rationalcomprehensive’ assessment and decision-making process. While studies do point
to the capacity of EIA to improve the effectiveness, coordination and legitimacy
of environmental planning decisions, others suggest that these legal-formal
mechanisms also utilise a range of what Wandesforde-Smith has described as
‘powerful, informal incentives’ within government to ‘produce agencies that
continuously and progressively think about environmental values.’ (Bartlett, 1990
p.90) EIA can be understood as operating in a highly flexible, self-regulating
manner involving continuous mediation between the internal formation of
environmental programs and objectives within organisations (not just state
agencies but also non-governmental organisations and private corporations), and
the external political and economic context within which these operate. This
suggests that EIA processes have the ability to implement environmental
management not simply by juridical ‘command and control’ methods. Rather,
through a set of ecological norms and administrative procedures, it is capable of
channelling problem solving in particular directions that stimulate State agencies,
private companies and other social actors to be both innovative and effective in
the implementation of ecological goals. (Bartlett, 1990)
Bartlett argues that where EIA is successful, that is, where it substantively
influences the direction and outcome of environmental planning and economic
activity, it does so ‘by changing, formally and informally, the premises and rules
for arriving at legitimate decisions.’ (Bartlett, 1990 p.91) Thus he argues that EIA
creates an ‘insidious’ mechanism for imbedding ecological modes of thought and
environmental values into the actions of organisations and individuals.
By establishing, continuously reaffirming and progressively legitimating
environmental values and ecological criteria as standards by which
individual actions are to be structured, chosen, and evaluated, EIA
institutionalises substantive ecological rationality. ... It changes patterns
of relationships among organisations and among individuals inside and
outside organisations. It creates powerful incentives, formal and informal,
that thereafter force a great deal of learning and self-regulation upon
individual and organisational actors. And it provides opportunities for
139
individuals to develop and affirm environmental values and to press for
innovative adaptation of structures and processes to a changing political
world. (Bartlett, 1990 p.91-2)
The particular strength of EIA, and that which separates it from the simple
legislative imposition of controls (such as permissible discharge levels for
pollutants), is that it structures the institutional and normative fields in which
actions and governmental programs take place without specifying final outcomes.
It establishes a governmental technology, which simultaneously guides and
problematises actions in relation to the environment in which juridical techniques
are subsumed under the effectivity of the norm. These sorts of techniques also
incorporate what Foucault described as a ‘pastoral’ attitude, where government is
understood in terms of the metaphor of ‘the shepherd and his flock’. Such a view
sees the goal of government as the promotion of ‘the well-being of its subjects’ by
means of an intimate and continuous regulation of behaviour, 198 and is thus more
concerned with the welfare or security of subjects than is the liberal concern with
autonomy. This is a basic normative perspective, which is deeply embedded in
almost all schools of environmental thought - the notion of wise stewardship as
fundamental to the management of all-encompassing ecological relationships.
The EIA process (including the conduct of scientific environmental impact
studies) is often criticised because these are generally conducted by the
development proponents themselves, and as a consequence frequently suffer from
‘technical flaws’, ‘incomplete presentation of information’ and therefore cannot
be regarded as a substitute for ‘overall planning’. (Walker, 1989 p.33) Such an
argument may miss the point, 199 for it is precisely by incorporating the developer
and other non-environmental state agencies into the process of problem definition
that EIA internalises and normalises ecological analysis and behaviour within
individual and organisational actors. This of course is not to suggest that such
techniques cannot become co-opted to immediate, short-term political
manoeuvring by politicians and governments - clearly, they can be and are from
time to time. 200 Nor is it to suggest that the proponents of developments do not
pursue commercial self-interest – the question is, under what political rationality
198
Foucault saw the practice of police science as clear example of this pastoral attitude. See
Foucault (1981c) and also Hindess (1996) p.118-23.
199
See also Rutherford 1994b.
200
It is perhaps the case that EIA ‘works’ best as a technology of government the more distant it is
from the political interventions of executive government. This is because a development that is
a political issue for politicians is one that has by definition already mobilised powerful
competing interests, and these interests have brought the issues into the arena of executive
government as part of a strategy aimed at protecting those interests. Anyone with practical
experience in environmental regulation will know that the number of development projects that
become political issues in this way is a relatively small proportion. In most cases, it is simply
much easier and far quicker to do what is necessary under the EIA process.
140
are such interests pursued, and what effect does this have on the way actions are
governed? That these questions will almost always be overlaid with other
particular economic and political effects needs to be considered.
Nevertheless, at the broader strategic level of political rationalities, EIA can
be described as a means of institutionalising ecological rationality in
governmental and social choice mechanisms. (Bartlett, 1990 p.88-9) EIA is of
course in part a regulatory mechanism in the legal-juridical sense, but it is more
than this. It attempts to enhance the effectiveness of government (in the
Foucauldian sense) in regulating the complex and multiple materiality of the
species body, both by institutionalising a scientised form of administrative
apparatus, and more importantly perhaps, by opening up the species body
(population) in a new way to that generalised ‘modality of intervention’
characterised by Foucault as panopticism. Hence, a fundamental feature of EIA is
that it also functions as a normalising strategy, that is, it does not mandate specific
outcomes from the centre, but sets up a framework for rationalising behaviour in
particular ways. In other words, EIA brings into being new relations of power
through an interpenetrating cluster of positive norms of internal self-control and
external regulation that effect a policing of specific practices of the population,
both at a general institutional level and through what Foucault describes as a
‘positive intervention in the behaviour of individuals.’ (Foucault, 1988b p.159)
Using Mitchell Dean’s (1998b) terminology, Environmental Impact Assessment
can be described as a technology of performance, as it functions ‘to monitor,
compare, and evaluate the performance of those whose agency is thereby
activated.’ Such technologies of performance are ‘utilised from above, as indirect
means of regulating agencies, at transforming professionals into “calculating
individuals” within “calculable spaces”, subject to particular “calculative
regimes”, to use Miller’s language (1992).’ (Dean 1998b, p.36)
Another illustration of these relations of biopolitics in the natural sciences can
be found by examining the role played by computer modelling in the construction
of knowledge of global environmental change, or the ‘greenhouse effect’.201 The
discourse on global environmental change has many of the characteristics
previously discussed. Within the institutional context of a highly technical,
transnational science, the extension of scientific knowledge to the world beyond
the laboratory involves the interpretation of outputs of complex computer models
of the global atmosphere and oceans, 202 along with the techniques of monitoring
and standardisation in which such knowledge is embodied. As I shall discuss
further in subsequent chapters, the extension of this type of apparently esoteric
scientific knowledge outside the laboratory necessarily involves an adjustment of
201
The example used here previously appeared in Rutherford (1997a) p554-6.
202
Known as ‘general circulation models’.
141
‘non-scientific practices and situations’ outside of the laboratory so as to make
these ‘amenable to the employment of scientific materials and practices’. (Rouse,
1987 p.211) Extending scientific knowledge and techniques outside of the
laboratory brings about a strategic realignment of power relations by disciplining
and structuring the social and physical environment in which non-scientific agents
act.
The specific consequences of this are illustrated by Taylor and Buttel, who
argue that the largely uncritical acceptance by social scientists and environmental
movements of the unproblematic ‘reality’ of the knowledge-constructs of the
natural sciences is instrumental in the production of a complex set of hierarchical
political and economic alignments. (Buttel and Taylor, 1992) These alignments
are shaped by the theories, techniques, and instruments of highly formalised
physical sciences and of systems ecology, which privilege ‘global constructions of
ecological knowledge’ in ways that allow programs of environmental
management to be grafted onto a set of dominant ‘geo-political institutions’.
(Buttel and Taylor, 1992 p.226) In particular, the privileged status accorded to
theories and models drawn from the physical sciences has facilitated the
development of a strategic ‘coincidence of interests’ between environmental
groups, scientists, and institutions such as the World Bank and international
development agencies, which seek to discipline future development in the less
developed States. (Taylor and Buttel, 1992 p.412)
The scientific construction of knowledge of the global environmental risks
aggregates population and resources in ways that obscure the differential impact
of environmental problems and policies on regional and local populations and
groups within those populations, or as Beck argues, that cut across traditional
interest alignments. Thus, Taylor and Buttel argue that such technical knowledge
constructions function simultaneously as a scientific concept and as an ‘ideology’
that helps structure sociopolitical relationships in particular ways ‘to erect a new
global regulatory order’. (Buttel and Taylor, 1992 p.222) This regulatory order
reflects the way in which the government of environmental risk produces ‘a
division between active citizens (capable of managing their own risk) and targeted
populations (disadvantaged groups, the ‘at risk’, the high-risk etc) who require
intervention in the management of risks. (Dean, 1998b p.35) As Dean notes such a
division involves the deployment of quite different types of governmental
technologies, and is characteristic of neo-liberal ‘prudentialism’ which relies on
the enhanced role of professional expertise, especially that associated with the
prediction, quantification and prevention of risk factors. 203 Environmental Impact
Assessment discussed above is an example of a type of governmental technology
203
The issue of ecological risk, as I have argued in Chapter 4, is a central concern in Beck’s work.
Dean (1998b) provides a highly perceptive critique of Beck’s somewhat simplistic treatment of
risk, by drawing on the work of Foucault and governmentality studies.
142
applied to active citizens – it is primarily directed at professionally educated
engineers, business people and government officials capable of ‘regulated
autonomy’ to use Rose and Miller’s (1992) terminology. It differs from the
governmental technologies applied to targeted populations such as school children
whose exposure to high levels of ultraviolet radiation in the summer months is
regulated through the disciplining of dress codes and spatial distribution (in the
school ground) of the ‘at risk’ population.204
Central to global climate science is a reliance on complex computer
modelling of the global environment that incorporates the systems approach to
ecology referred to earlier in this chapter. Since the 1970s there have been two
major elements in such global modelling. The first involved the use of the
concepts of system dynamics to make predictions about the impact of future
population growth, resource use and pollution output on the world economy and
environment. This resulted in The Limits to Growth report which used these
computer simulations to argue that continued population growth would lead to the
depletion of the world’s stocks of non-renewable natural resources and precipitate
a global economic collapse, unless coordinated policies for a no-growth, ‘steadystate’ economy were implemented world-wide. (Meadows et al., 1972) The
Limits to Growth was both widely criticised and defended, but regardless of the
merits of the forecasts made in the report, it had a major influence in constructing
the contemporary ecological representation of the world. The core of this
representation is the concept of a single global system and the problematisation of
the relationships between population, resources and the natural environment. The
report thus provided a coherent, popularised articulation of the themes of systems
ecology that was embraced by environmental movements in the industrialised
countries, and which helped shape political support for new forms of
environmental regulation. (Taylor and Buttel, 1992 p.409-10)
The second element of global climate modelling, in the form of general
circulation models of the atmosphere, came to prominence in the 1980s. These
models were initially designed to predict the future course and impact of human
induced changes to atmospheric chemistry, most notably increases in carbon
dioxide levels. In the late 1980s, the modelling was further extended to develop
scenarios of the impact of climate change on global agriculture and biodiversity,
as well as economic and security consequences. Unlike The Limits to Growth,
climate modelling has been able to command substantial scientific and
institutional influence and resources, both within the national science-policy
communities of the advanced industrial states and within international and
transnational bodies such as the United Nations and the OECD. In particular
climate modelling provided both the scientific rationale and technical tools for the
204
See note 174 above.
143
work of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change carried out under the
auspices of the World Meteorological Organisation. It was this work which led to
the establishment of a framework convention on climate change at the UN
Conference on Environment and Development (the ‘Earth Summit’) in 1992. 205
Conclusion
Systems ecology, and the highly mathematised natural sciences (such as
atmospheric chemistry and physics) involved in global ecosystem modelling exert
a powerful influence across a wide range of environmental policy and social
planning areas. The ecological sciences are fundamental to key aspects of
contemporary biopolitics - ecological discourse both problematises numerous
areas of life while at the same time elaborating programs of environmental
intervention aimed at normalising the social relation to nature in specific,
ecologically benign ways. The contemporary notion of the environment is
constituted as inherently problematic by the development of specialised scientific
(as well as legal and moral) discourse on ecology. This specialised discourse
provides what Rose and Miller (1992) have described as ‘the intellectual
machinery of government’, through which social relations with nature are
thematised and brought into the domain of ‘conscious political calculation’
through the formation of programs of government. Such programs
presuppose that the real is programmable, that it is a domain subject to
certain determinants, rules, norms and processes that can be acted upon
and improved by authorities. They make the objects of government
thinkable in such a way that their ills appear susceptible to diagnosis,
prescription and cure by calculating and normalising intervention. (Rose
and Miller, 1992 p.182)
Central to these activities is the production and use of knowledge by experts.
The formation of ecological programs of government occurs to a significant
degree within the institutional context of regulatory science, in which
environmental experts simultaneously provide scientifically authoritative
technical judgments and politically legitimised policies. Programs of government
therefore embody knowledgeable accounts of what are considered legitimate
problems, and the goals and objectives to be pursued in addressing them.
However, programs must be capable of being deployed on the population, brought
to bear on the ‘species body’ through a range of interventions and regulatory
instruments. The means of making programs operable can be considered the
technologies of government. (Rose and Miller, 1992 p.175) I have suggested that
the technique of environmental impact assessment can be thought of as an
205
For a detailed historical study of the role of scientific elites in mediating between science and
policy in the early years of climate change research see Hart and Victor (1993).
144
example of such a technology of government which expresses most clearly the
sorts of productive relations of power Foucault calls biopolitics. In a similar vein
Eric Darier’s (Darier, 1995) study of Canada’s Green Plan provides an
illuminating example, in the ecological domain, of what Rose and Miller describe
as a program of government. 206
It is important to emphasise that what is being argued here is not that
ecological governmentality is part of some simple, unidirectional and generalised
extension of state domination of society, much less an expression of Adorno’s
totally administered society. Rather, the developments described here reflect what
Foucault referred to as ‘the ‘governmentalisation’ of the state’. (Foucault, 1991c)
Government, understood as the attempt to implement all those more or less
formally articulated plans, projects and practices that seek to systematically shape
the conduct of individuals, groups and populations, is not the exclusive domain of
the state. Indeed, the complexity of modern society appears to engender an
increasing reliance on liberal techniques of government, which depend on
governing at a distance, ‘seeking to create locales, entities and persons able to
operate a regulated autonomy.’ (Rose and Miller, 1992 p.173) Thus, as suggested
in this chapter, non-state actors, particularly professionals, academics and social
movements contribute to the governmentalisation of life by entering into complex
and potentially unstable relations with state agencies, other institutions and
political forces.
This chapter has suggested that Foucault’s work on biopolitics holds promise
for a more sophisticated understanding of contemporary environmental concerns.
No consideration of ecological problems can ignore the biological problem posed
by the impact of populations on the available stock of natural resources. As I have
shown, this is precisely the problem Foucault situates as fundamental to
biopolitics. Thus there is an overlap, although not developed by Foucault himself,
in which the ‘entry of life into history’ is both a biopolitical and ecological (or
eco-political) phenomenon. Life in the modern biological sense, enters history
precisely because the mechanisms of biological life become the objects of both
‘reason of state’ and ‘government’ in the broader sense described by Foucault. In
this respect, biological life becomes simultaneously an object of scientific
knowledge, state strategic calculation, market capitalisation and ethical discourse,
206
Darier argues that the notion of governmentality is directly relevant to understanding the
application of environmental policy. His study of the Canadian Green Plan emphasises that it
is best understood as ‘a clear attempt to discipline the population by “instilling” new norms of
environmental conduct and, thus, (it) constructs a new subjectivity based on “environmental
citizenship”.’ Darier also notes that the Green Plan should also be seen as ‘an example of
resistance against other prevalent kinds of subjectification – such as the “market” – and could
constitute one of the conditions for the emergence of a subsequent green “self” with all the
dangers that this entails.’ (Darier, 1995)
145
and in so doing, also becomes the subject of articulated, explicit governmental
rationalities.
146
Chapter 7
Foucault’s incomplete critique of the sovereignty
Introduction
In the preceding chapter it was suggested that because Foucault restricted his
attention to the role of the human sciences in the development of biopower, he did
not consider the way in which the political and economic problematisation of
population give rise to a similar problematisation of the natural environment.
Nevertheless, it was argued that his approach to biopolitics and governmentality
could be extended to help understand the growth of environmental discourse and
ecopolitical programs of government.
The current chapter turns to a consideration of Foucault’s approach to the
relationship between power and natural scientific knowledge. More particularly,
this chapter examines the way in which his treatment of agency and the subject
influenced his apparent lack of interest in the relationship between the ‘hard’
natural sciences and social power. This relationship is an issue on which Foucault
was considerably more ambiguous than in his studies of the human sciences. As
the preceding chapter has indicated, environmental discourses draw heavily on
knowledge from the natural sciences. If the Foucauldian analysis of the relation
between expertise, knowledge and the government of conduct is to be useful in
those instances where knowledge is primarily drawn from the sciences of nature
rather than of society, then it is necessary to ask whether the natural sciences are
in any decisive sense less embroiled in relations of power than the human
sciences?
These are the issues examined in this and the following chapter. Here my
focus is on the apparent inconsistency between Foucault’s approach to the natural
and human sciences. I argue that this inconsistency can be explained by
Foucault’s failure to break with the notion of sovereignty as fully as has been
claimed, both by Foucault himself and by many of those commenting on his work.
One consequence of this is that while Foucault understands the subject as the
product of historically contingent relations of power, discipline and scientific
objectification, he nonetheless still insists on a fundamental distinction between
actions on human agents and actions on non-human things.
147
Foucault’s characterisation of the natural sciences
One problem in attempting to determine the status of the natural sciences in
Foucault’s work is that he does not deal with these in a comprehensive manner,
and if anything, the attention they receive diminishes as his work developed over
time. Thus, the most systematic consideration of the natural sciences is to be
found in his earlier archaeological works (particularly The Archaeology of
Knowledge and The Order of Things), in which, as Rabinow says, discourse tends
to be ‘bracketed off from the social practices and institutions in which it is
embedded’, (Rabinow, 1984a p.9-10) with the consequence that the nondiscursive and institutional elements of scientific practice are not dealt with in a
substantial way.
A second problem is that any attempt to apply the insights of Foucault’s
analyses of the human sciences to the natural sciences must confront the apparent
distinction he made between the two, including the way in which he allowed a
less epistemologically problematic status to certain natural sciences (eg
mathematics, chemistry) than the human sciences. As with his analysis of the
emergence of the human sciences, Foucault saw the earlier development of the
natural sciences as having their origins in techniques of discipline and social
regulation. In particular, he suggested that the investigatory practices of Church in
the twelfth and thirteenth centuries, and particularly The Inquisition, provided
both an ‘operating model’ and the ‘technical matrix’ for the nascent natural
sciences.
It is worth recalling the connection Foucault (1979b) claimed exists here. The
investigatory or inquisitorial practices arose in conjunction with the
reorganisation of the Church and proliferation of the monarchical states in
Europe. Its origin then was political, linked to the ‘birth of the states and of
monarchical sovereignty’, but apart from serving this explicitly political-juridical
function it also contributed, as a cluster of ‘regulated techniques’, to the formation
of knowledge. ‘In fact’, said Foucault, ‘the investigation has been the no doubt
crude, but fundamental element in the constitution of the empirical sciences.’ The
‘terrible power’ of the practices of investigation enabled the proliferation of the
‘great empirical knowledge that covered the things of the world and transcribed
them into the ordering of an infinite discourse that observes, describes and
establishes the ‘facts’ (at a time when the western world was beginning the
economic and political conquest of this same world)’. Significantly however,
Foucault claims that ‘although it is true that, in becoming a technique for the
empirical sciences, the investigation has detached itself from the inquisitorial
procedure, in which it was historically rooted, the examination has remained
extremely close to the disciplinary power that shaped it.’ (Foucault, 1979b p.2246 emphasis added) In other words, both the natural and human sciences share a
148
common historical origin in disciplinary technology. Whereas the natural sciences
have somehow succeeded in detaching themselves from the inquisitorial model,
the human sciences with their reliance on the practices of ‘the examination’, have
remained enmeshed in disciplinary power. (Foucault, 1979b p.227) Foucault did
not elaborate in Discipline and Punish or in subsequent writings, how and why
this divergence should occur.
Some explanation of this may be found in his earlier works. In The
Archaeology of Knowledge, Foucault distinguished four ‘thresholds’ or stages in
the emergence of discursive formations. 207 Perhaps most significant in
considering the development of the natural sciences as largely autonomous bodies
of knowledge removed from direct implication in disciplinary power, is what
Foucault called the ‘threshold of scientificity’. This is when the basic
archaeological rules governing statements within a discursive formation are
further supplemented by more specific laws or rules governing the construction of
propositions in accordance with the accepted norms of a scientific methodology.
(Foucault, 1972 p.186-7; Gutting, 1989 p.252-3) This indicates that the difference
between the thresholds of epistemologisation and scientificity is largely, perhaps
even exclusively, one of the degree of precision, rigour and formalisation.
(Grumley, 1989 p.252) Certainly Foucault states that it is primarily a matter of the
extent to which the statements and propositions that constitute a discursive
formation obey formal criteria.208 Elsewhere he suggests that in order to be
definable as a science, an ‘epistemological configuration’ must possess the
characteristics of ‘objectivity’ and ‘systemacity’. (Foucault, 1970 p.365)
As pointed out in Chapter 5, Foucault’s work was not a critique of rationality
in general. Gutting’s detailed analysis of the relation of Foucault’s archaeology to
the history of science of Bachelard and Canguilhem, demonstrates that neither
was it a critique of scientific rationality nor of the natural sciences per se.
(Gutting, 1989 p.255) The focus was not on the systematic or rigorous natural
sciences, but on the human sciences, those ‘dubious’ disciplines that have not yet
crossed and may never cross, this threshold of scientificity to detach themselves
from relations of power. Foucault’s critique, therefore, was primarily directed at
specific applications of biology to human beings (via medicine, psychiatry, etc)
and to the human sciences in general, that is, it was directed at particular historical
applications of knowledge dealing with the ways in which human beings, as
distinct from non-human nature, are constituted as subjects by, and of, power.
207
These four thresholds are those of positivity, epistemologisation, scientificity, and
formalisation. See Foucault (1972) p.186-189.
208
That is, when the statements of a discursive formation ‘comply not only with archaeological
rules of formation, but also with certain laws for the construction of propositions.’ (Foucault,
1972 p.187)
149
In one sense Foucault appeared to regard the natural sciences as less
problematic, from the point of view of their connection to social power, because
these have become bodies of knowledge that have crossed the threshold of
scientificity to obey formal criteria in a way that gives rise to ‘relatively stable
practices and objects’ in a manner somewhat similar to Kuhn’s conception of
normal science. (Dreyfus and Rabinow, 1982 p.116). In another sense, the natural
sciences were treated by Foucault as too problematic because the relationship
between sciences such as theoretical physics, organic chemistry or mathematics,
and relations of social power involve what he suggested are ‘excessively
complicated’ questions in which the ‘threshold of possible explanations (is)
impossibly high’. (Foucault, 1980d p.109-10) Foucault thus seemed to say that the
interconnection between this type of scientific knowledge and the effects of power
are extremely attenuated and not readily amenable to social analysis in a way that
he found politically interesting or important. 209 His focus was thus on the human
sciences, those ‘dubious’ disciplines such as medicine and psychiatry that are
‘profoundly enmeshed in social structures’. What makes the human sciences both
significant and interesting on this account is precisely the role these play in
defining the historical conditions of emergence of particular modes of human
subjectivity and the ways in which awareness of this historicity opens up
possibilities for transforming these subjectivities.
Could Foucault’s claim that the natural sciences were able to detach
themselves from power relations reflect an acceptance that there is a fundamental
difference between the objects of human and natural sciences? While Foucault’s
approach to the natural sciences is by no means that of simple realism,210 he
nevertheless did not adequately provide any strong arguments for accepting that
the natural sciences, as discursive constructs, should be regarded as anything
209
210
For an interesting Foucault-influenced analysis of the ‘capitalising’ of molecular biology and
the transformation of life into a productive force, see Yoxen (1981). While Yoxen deals with an
area of biology which has become closely linked to medicine, he nevertheless shows how very
clearly how ‘hard sciences’ of molecular biology (ie the genetics and biochemistry of
recombinant DNA) have became embroiled in disciplinary practices. The relevance of Yoxen’s
work has substantially increased in recent years with subsequent advances in the technology of
gene manipulation, particularly gene therapy in medicine and use of patented, genetically
modified organisms in agriculture. Yoxen’s article is also of interest in that it demonstrates the
active competition between scientific interests (molecular biology and ecology) in the
governmentalisation of the U.S. state.
In particular see Foucault's treatment of the development of modern biology provided in The
Order of Things. An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. (Foucault, 1970) This is definitely not a
simple realist account, but, as Gutting demonstrates, is very much influenced by the work of
French historians of science Bachelard and Canguilhem. Bachelard and Canguilhem introduced
themes such as the theory dependence of observation, discontinuity and incommensurability in
science, that 'preceded by two or three decades similar discussions by Anglo-American historians
and philosophers of science such as Kuhn and Feyerabend' (Gutting, 1989 p.16, 33). See also
Dreyfus and Rabinow (1982) p.116-7.
150
other than deeply implicated in the same knowledge/power matrix as the human
sciences. Greater rigour and systemacity, or even predicability, of their own, are
not sufficient grounds for a fundamental difference in the relationship of the
natural sciences to power.
Power and capacity: the subject revisited
Foucault’s work unquestionably developed very significant critical insights
into the ways that subjects are constituted in relations of power, but it nevertheless
confined power to relations between active human subjects. This is most evident
in the distinction he drew between power and ‘capacities’. Power is a mode of
action upon the action of others, while the technical capacities of bodies and
instruments to manipulate things do not in themselves entail relations of power.
(Foucault, 1982 p.219-22) Thus Foucault differentiates capacity from power in
the following terms:
As far as this power is concerned, it is first necessary to distinguish that
which is exerted over things and gives the ability to modify, use,
consume, or destroy them - a power which stems from aptitudes directly
inherent in the body or relayed by external instruments. Let us say that
here it is a question of ‘capacity’. On the other hand, what characterises
the power we are analysing is that it brings into play relations between
individuals (or between groups). (Foucault, 1982 p.217 - emphasis added)
What was Foucault suggesting here? Why insist on the difference between
actions on things and relations of power? The obvious response is that most of
modern Western political thought takes as fundamental the differences between
the human and non-human, between culture and nature etc. However, given
Foucault’s strong critique of humanism and his insistence that human beings are
historically produced by power, that is, through processes of subjectification and
discipline, it becomes necessary to examine this question further. More
specifically, it is important to consider this as it relates to the way in which
Foucault dealt with the natural sciences. As suggested in the previous chapter,
such sciences must be seen as playing a key role in the contemporary
problematisation of the natural environment, and in the biopolitical (or
ecopolitical) regulation of human populations that follows from this. In sketching
Foucault’s approach to power in Chapter 5, I pointed to his emphasis on this
productive aspect of power, in contrast to the generally negative characterisation
of power as domination by Habermas. It is therefore necessary to look more
closely at the distinction Foucault made between power and domination.
This distinction can be illuminated by contrasting it with the approach
adopted by Charles Taylor, whose criticisms of Foucault in many respects parallel
those raised by Habermas. Taylor maintained that not only did power and
domination necessarily imply an imposition on the significant interests or
151
purposes of the individual, but that it also implies the potential for liberation from
this imposition. From this perspective the concept of power is therefore
incoherent unless it is linked to the possibility of emancipation from power.
(Taylor, 1984 p.172-4) According to critics such as Taylor and Habermas,
Foucault’s position does not allow this, and is thus ultimately incapable of
providing a coherent normative basis for the critique of power. (Habermas, 1985
p.276) In contrast to this identification of power with domination, Foucault
characterised power as a mode of action upon the action of others, that is, a
relationship that involves actors who are free insomuch as the field of possible
action and response is not fully pre-determined or closed. (Foucault, 1982 p.21922) A state of domination exists when the relations of power are ‘firmly set and
congealed’, instead of being variable and fluid. Hence, for Foucault domination
was a specific outcome of power relations in which stable and relatively durable
mechanisms of power replace the dynamic ‘agonism’ of the strategic
manoeuvring between agents. (Foucault, 1982 p.222-26; Foucault, 1988a p.3)
In Taylor’s approach the exercise of power, seen as imposition contrary to the
will or interests of a pre-constituted subject, inevitably appears as a loss of
freedom, as a diminution of the subject’s capacity for autonomy and selfrealisation. In this context, the claim that to talk of power without the correlative
concept of emancipation from power is incoherent appears to make sense. Of
course, such an approach confuses the issue of what sort of subject is involved.
For Taylor (and Habermas) the subject that is imposed upon by power was the
modern individual defined in terms of both personal autonomy and capacity for
collective self-rule. (Taylor, 1984 p.178) For Foucault, the subject with its various
capacities, was precisely that which must be explained in terms of the historical
deployment of power and discourse. As a consequence, the relationship between
power and autonomy must be understood differently. If the subject is not a preconstituted entity that power undermines, but rather is the result of power
relations, then autonomy cannot be understood simply as the absence of
imposition or repression.
In this regard Paul Patton argues that even domination cannot be explained by
a simple account of imposition as Taylor attempted to do. Instead domination is
the product of a relatively stable system of extractive power resulting from an
ongoing asymmetry of power relations. (Patton, 1989) 211 In other words, even in
the case of domination, the relationship still relies on the ‘capture’ of the
capacities of others,212 and is not purely an instance of direct imposition on, or
power over, a subject. What distinguishes domination then, is the establishment of
211
Here Patton employs Macpherson's concept of extractive power, that is, the ability ‘to make
use of and derive benefit from the capacities of others’.
212
Patton is not using the term ‘capacities’ in the more narrow sense employed by Foucault in the
earlier quoted passage, but rather more broadly as ‘capacity to act’ (upon the actions of others).
152
asymmetrical relations of power that have congealed, in which the ‘possibility of
reversal’ no longer applies.
Patton distinguishes between negative and positive freedom - the absence of
imposition or power over (a subject) is freedom in the negative sense, while an
agent’s capacity to act for its own ends constitutes power to, or positive freedom.
Patton argues that by making such a distinction between negative and positive
freedom, Foucault’s approach to power relations becomes clearer - power relies
primarily upon power to, that is, power as capacity to act upon the actions of
others. The relationship between power and freedom in Foucault also becomes
clearer - power is exercised over free agents and freedom is a precondition for the
exercise of power. (Foucault, 1982 p.221) Power and freedom are thus intimately
tied together - as primary capacity (or ‘power to’) power presupposes positive
freedom to act. Similarly a power relation proper (as distinct from a state of
domination) is a dynamic relationship between agents in which there is always the
potential for a reversal of the strategic position of each party. Hence freedom
cannot be reduced to an attribute of the subject, but must be understood as an
essential element in relations of power. (Connolly, 1985 p.371)
Taylor’s approach to the relationship between freedom and power can
therefore be seen to have relied on the sort of privileging of the subject
characteristic of most modern Western political thinking, with its idealisation of
autonomy. In contrast to this approach, Foucault’s understanding of power is
generally understood as rejecting any ‘founding subject’ whose essential nature
power represses or distorts. Although in this chapter I argue that Foucault’s break
with the subject is not as complete as has often been claimed, he nonetheless did
not conceive of power as a wholly negative force undermining the pre-constituted
autonomous subject. Rather power was seen by him as productive, as giving rise
to the historical relations and discursive practices through which subjects are
formed. As with Habermas, Taylor’s criticism of Foucault can therefore said to
have been based on a misrepresentation of Foucault’s approach to power.213 This
rebuttal of the one dimensional conception of power attributed to Foucault by
critics such as Habermas and Taylor, however, still leaves us with the task of
understanding why Foucault appeared to regard the connection between power
and knowledge in the human sciences differently from that which applied in the
natural sciences?
A clue to this is provided by further consideration, in the light of the
foregoing discussion about the connection between power and freedom, of
Foucault’s distinction between power and capacity. Patton rightly indicates that
for Foucault what distinguished the forces or capacities that act directly on bodies
213
For a discussion of Habermas and Honneth misunderstanding of Foucault’ approach to power,
see Chapter 5 of the current thesis.
153
and instruments from relations of power is that the latter treat human beings as
acting subjects rather than merely docile bodies or things. (Patton, 1989 p.271)
Thus Foucault could be seen at least in his later works, as having understood
freedom (in the sense discussed above) as the ‘ontological precondition of politics
and ethics’. In doing so he assumed a particular conception of ‘the human
material upon which power is exercised’. In this Foucault appeared to preserve the
modern philosophical acceptance of basic differences in the relations involving
the instrumental manipulation of things and the actions of agents or subjects
(although he does see these as forming ‘blocks’ which can ‘constitute regulated
and concerted systems’ or disciplines). (Foucault, 1982 p.218-9) Patton elaborates
on this in the following terms:
This human material is active; it is an entity composed of forces or
endowed with certain capacities. It is a subject of power, where this term
is understood in its primary sense of capacity to do or become certain
things. This conception of the human material may therefore be supposed
to amount to a ‘thin’ conception of the subject of thought and action:
whatever else it may be, the human subject is a being endowed with
capacities. It is the subject of power, but this power is only realised in and
through the diversity of human bodily capacities and forms of
subjectivity. (Patton, 1994 p.61)
One of Habermas’ principal criticisms of Foucault, that of ‘cryptonormativism’, focuses on just this ‘thin’ conception of subjectivity. Habermas
attacked Foucault for failing to acknowledge that his writings in effect locate the
justification for resistance to power in a form of vitalism based on ‘the body’s
experience of itself’ as subjected to the disciplinary force of biopower.
(Habermas, 1985 p.285) Similar arguments have been made by feminist writers
such as Judith Butler, who comments that in Foucault power becomes the focal
point of a ‘displaced vitalism’, in which ‘power, conceived as productive, is the
form life takes when it no longer needs to guard itself against death.’ (Butler,
1993 p.88) While Foucault’s argument concerning the body as constructed by
power is complex, it is also in some respects ambiguous. On the one hand he
insisted that the body had no ontological independence outside of discourse and
power, (Foucault, 1984a p.83, 87-8; Foucault, 1990) yet as Bulter argues, his
Nietzschean genealogy posited the body both as a surface or site inscribed by
power, and as a set of prediscursive subterranean ‘forces’ that are ‘repressed and
transmuted’ by such inscription, and which provide the basis of resistance to
power. (Butler, 1989 p.601-7) Butler claims that while Foucault criticised
Nietzsche’s presumption of a life-affirming ‘prediscursive instinctuality’ (for
example, in Discipline and Punish), he nevertheless fell back into employing such
a notion in other works (as in ‘Nietzsche, Genealogy and History’), sometimes
even expressing this as ‘the essential and transhistorical precondition of
“history”.’ (Butler, 1989 p.606-7) Similarly, Bryan Turner argues that despite the
apparent anti-foundationalism of Foucault’s epistemology, his work is
154
underscored by a ‘romanticism ... in which the primitive body, existing before
signification, represents a world of innocent enjoyment.’214 (Turner, 1992 p.53-55)
Other commentators, such as Ladelle McWhorter, deny that Foucault saw the
body as a natural object standing in opposition to culture - rather it stood in
opposition to the philosophical discourse ‘that gives us nature/culture dualism’
and its associated disputes. McWhorter also points to the influence of Nietzsche’s
use of the term body, but insists that both Foucault and Nietzsche use this to deny
the possibility of any ‘sure and singular source of the truth of man’, even in the
natural body.215 (McWhorter, 1989 p.608-14)
Patton explains the link between Foucault and Nietzsche in a slightly different
manner. He argues that Foucault’s thin conception of the subject was developed
into a ‘more robust conception of human being’ in later works, especially The Use
of Pleasure. (Patton, 1994 p.69) There he points to the discussion of practices of
self-regulation (over one’s body and sexual relations with others) as evidence of
Foucault’s acceptance of the notion of autonomy, not only of the individual self,
but also in terms of forms of sociality or community.216 (Patton, 1994 p.65, 67)
Autonomy in this sense thus stands in equivalence to power as the ‘self-directed
use and development of human capacities.’ (Patton, 1994 p.68) These capacities
derive from a variety of sources - some are dependent on the physical properties
of the body as a biological entity, while others are the products of social and
institutional interactions. Patton goes further to distinguish a third, interpretative
dimension to capacity associated with the Nietzschean notion of will to power. He
argues that in Nietzsche the will to power is an affective state involving a
‘feedback loop’ between the capacity for action itself and a self-conscious
experience of successful action as power - involving what Warren describes as the
‘self reflective goal of experiencing the self as agent’. (Patton, 1994 p.70; Warren,
1988 p.138)
Drawing on Nietzsche in this way, Patton directs our attention to Foucault’s
insistence on the way in which structures of domination in contemporary society
are characteristically accompanied by acts of resistance. Patton suggests that
while this may provide evidence of some minimal capacity for autonomous action
by subjects, in order for Foucault to be able to explain why individuals and groups
actually experience particular relations of power as domination, he must extend
his ‘thin’ conception of human being (as a subject endowed with the capacity for
action) to presuppose a ‘fuller’ or more ‘robust’ conception of subjectivity that
214
See also Turner (1984) p.157-76
215
See also Bennett (1987)
216
Patton comments ‘there is no reason to expect that such degrees of autonomy will be developed
by individuals acting alone rather than in the context of movements for change in certain
aspects of social life.’
155
encompasses a sense of agency, that is, as involving the experience of feelings of
power/powerlessness along the lines suggested by Nietzsche. (Patton, 1994 p.701)
In drawing this connection between Foucault’s later work and the
Nietzschean notion of will-to-power, Patton is able to respond to those such as
Habermas and Taylor who criticise Foucault for his failure to provide a universal
normative basis for evaluating different regimes of power, and hence his inability
to explain why it is morally justified to resist domination. As noted previously,
one response is the non-normative observation that such power is in fact resisted,
that is, to say that resistance ‘follows from the nature of particular human beings.’
(Patton, 1994 p.69) However, Foucault’s argument went further by basing the fact
of resistance on ontological assumptions regarding the sorts of human capacities
that give rise to action, including resistance. Patton’s analysis demonstrates not
only that autonomy is the ‘ontological precondition’ for power, but also that an
important element in forming the capacity of human beings for such action is the
self-reflexive experience of agency.
Thus as Patton claims, effective moral values (and presumably other forms of
normative evaluation such as what constitutes legitimate knowledge in a
particular scientific domain) are therefore reliant on the circumstances and
manner in which the self-experience of agency takes place, that is, ‘values are
internal to types of individual and social being, not independent of them.’ (Patton,
1994 p.71) It is in this context that Foucault’s references to the need for a ‘new
economy of power relations’ and a ‘practice of freedom’ must be understood that is, Foucault was proposing a form of ethics that by definition is incapable of
providing the sort of universality demanded by critics such as Habermas. Such an
ethic, says Patton, would nevertheless justify resistance to specific instances of
domination precisely because the practices of liberty that it invokes would be
‘internal’ to particular forms of subjectivity, and would therefore be dependent on
the ways in which individuals and groups experienced agency. (Foucault, 1982;
1988a)
This perhaps could be regarded as a partially effective response to the
criticisms of Habermas and Taylor, and indeed, acceptance of such an
interpretation is necessary to fully capture the subtlety of Foucault’s later work.217
(Foucault, 1983 p.198-201; 1988c p.13) Nevertheless it could be claimed that
Foucault only achieved this by moving away from his earlier goal of writing a
history of rationalities not based on the founding act of the subject. In pointing to
the Nietzschean foundations of Foucault’s notion of agency, Patton’s work
highlights why Foucault has been vulnerable to the charge of harbouring a
vitalism of the primitive body and with making this the transhistorical
217
This is something that I have argued critics such as Habermas fail to do. See Chapter 5.
156
precondition of history. Patton’s argument implies that the conception of freedom
employed in Foucault’s later work is fundamentally perspectival, and as such
dependent on the ways in which different individuals experience agency and
subjectivity. He argues that Foucault clearly saw freedom as ‘the ontological
precondition of politics and ethics’, but goes on to stress that
this is an historical rather than a transcendental ontology. Freedom here is
not the transcendental condition of moral action, as it is for Kant, but
rather the contingent historical condition for action upon the actions of
others (politics) and action upon the self (ethics). Just as for Foucault
political power exists only in the concrete forms of government of
conduct, so freedom exists only in the concrete capacities to act of
particular agents. (Patton, 1994 p.68)
While it may be conceded the forms of subjectivity invoked by Foucault
appeared to lack a singular transcendental quality, given that they are formed by
historically contingent regimes of power, Patton’s argument does not fully
extricate Foucault from the allegation of vitalism. For what lies behind
Nietzsche’s will to power, and consequently the body as possessing a series of
capacities for action which aim at enhancing the experience of agency, is the
argument that language and knowledge function as useful tools for survival
inasmuch as they allow a practical imposition of order on the chaotic flux of the
world.
For Nietzsche consciousness and self-consciousness, and thus the capacity to
experience agency, have their origin in the evolutionary development of the
human species.218 In a direct sense then Nietzsche saw agency (and the experience
of it - ‘the feeling of power’) as linked to the vital biological interest of the human
species in self-preservation. (Held, 1980 p.156-7; Warren, 1988 p.90-2) At the
same time he claimed that the will-to-power is not confined to human beings, but
is an essential quality of all life. Nor is life simply a striving for self-preservation:
‘Nature is a struggle not to exist but to overcome, to prevail and to triumph, even
in defeat ... Nature is ... will-to-power.’219 (Platt, 1988 p.148-9) Nature for
Nietzsche consists of the chaotic ‘flux and multiplicity of raw experience’ - it is
not particularly predisposed to any anthropocentric form of secure cognitive and
cultural representation. Nevertheless, the human species inscribes nature with its
218
On this see Turner (1984) p.242-4. For an attempt to link Nietzsche's view of the will-topower, as a general biological feature of life, to the modern ecological perspective, see
Hallman (1991). There is an interesting parallel here to the use of Spinoza's notion of conatus
by ‘deep ecology’ theorists such as Naess, who argues that conatus (or ‘striving to persevere in
oneself or one's being’) is more than the urge to survive, but is a striving for an increased
power of self-creation and self-development, and as such is an ‘urge towards higher levels of
freedom (libertas).’ See Naess (1985) and (1977).
219
For Nietzsche, of course, ‘man’ is the ‘crown of nature’.
157
cultural practices, and in so doing attempts more or less successfully to confer
familiarity and continuity to the world. (Warren, 1988 p.47-8) Thus culture
(which includes values and knowledge) as a way of constituting and disciplining
relations with nature is always historical and perspectival. Warren points out that
for Nietzsche ‘the conditions of possibility’ for such knowledge (and values) are
in part ‘interests relating to human agency’, that is, as involving interests in ‘the
material, social and cultural worlds as means to and conditions of power
organised as subjectivity.’ Knowledge and values therefore cannot be extricated
from the interest the self has in increasing its ‘feeling of power’. (Warren, 1988
p.90-2)
There are notable parallels in the role that these sorts of interests play in the
work of Nietzsche and Habermas. Although Habermas criticises Foucault for his
Nietzschean inspired ‘crypto-normativism’, Warren suggests that Habermas’
treatment of interests as a positive condition of knowledge, is a ‘contemporary
equivalent’ of Nietzsche’s approach (‘notwithstanding Habermas’ own
interpretation of Nietzsche’).220 (Warren, 1988 p.268, note 35) What is clear is
that both Nietzsche and Habermas conceive of interests as having their basis in
the natural history of the human species, and that these interests are inseparable
from human embodiment and sensuous needs. In the early Habermas, these
species’ interests, which give rise to knowledge, language and values (understood
as the achievements of the transcendental subject) are tied to the vital, biological
need for self-preservation.221 (Habermas, 1978, Appendix) A similar argument is
developed by Turner when he claims that for Nietzsche ‘the nature and functions
of knowledge are thus located in the evolutionary development and needs of the
species, especially in the necessary features of social communication. Language is
a requirement of human survival and is rooted ultimately in the physiological
basis of human existence.’ (Turner, 1984 p.242-3) Here again, there is a parallel
between Nietzsche and Habermas’ view of communicative action as a
fundamental attribute of the human species.
If as Patton cogently argues, Foucault is to be understood as basing his notion
of agency on Nietzsche, then Foucault could be said to base not only his ‘thin’
conception of subjectivity, but also the later and ‘fuller’ development of this, on
those vital capacities attached to the primitive body that forms the site of
signification and cultural inscription. Such a view is consistent, following my
220
Habermas' criticisms of Nietzsche (and Horkheimer and Adorno’s appropriation of Nietzsche)
are discussed at the end of Chapter 1 of the current thesis. See also Turner (1984) for
discussion of Nietzsche and Foucault.
221
See Chapter 3 of the current thesis for discussion of the ‘early’ Habermas’ approach to
knowledge constitutive interests. Of course, Habermas insists that while human interests
emerged from the human species' natural history, knowledge constitutive interests ‘derive both
from nature and from the cultural break with nature.’ (Habermas, 1978 p.312)
158
suggestion in the previous chapter, with the way in which Foucault takes the body
as the both the target of modern government and the source biopower. Turner is
thus correct to emphasise that Foucault’s intellectual endeavour is primarily
focused on the institutionalisation of the body through ‘the demographic (a theory
of the population) and the physiological (a theory of the body).’ (Turner, 1984
p.159-163) However, need the acceptance of such a reliance on the vitalism of the
body be problematic for Foucault’s analysis? In itself, probably not, for the most
valuable contributions of Foucault’s work are not substantially undermined by
admitting that the processes of human objectification and subjectification must
necessarily operate on some sort of substrate. However, it does lead us to inquire
further into the assumptions that underpin Foucault’s later approach to power, in
order to understand his different treatment of the human and natural sciences.
Foucault’s incomplete critique of sovereignty
In the context of the argument developed by Patton and as Foucault (1988a)
suggested, the effects of domination need not always be seen as morally
objectionable. 222 It merely suggests that individuals have a capacity for
autonomous action, and that when this freedom to act is significantly curtailed,
this is or at least may be, experienced as loss of autonomy, as domination. Neither
the fact that any particular individual’s capacity to act has been reduced to a
minimum, nor the subsequent experience of this as a loss of freedom by the
individual in question means that domination as such is morally wrong unless a
further step is taken in the argument to claim that, as a general principle, the
autonomy of others should not be significantly limited. This, of course, is a key
element in much modern political thought, with its dual emphasis on individual
autonomy and legitimate political sovereignty. This is precisely the point made by
Taylor when he argued that power (he uses this in the sense of power over) or
domination involves an imposition on the significant interests or purposes of an
individual.
Barry Hindess has questioned some of the philosophical assumptions behind
Foucault’s later attempts to distinguish between power, government and
domination. (Hindess, 1996) Hindess argues that from Hobbes and Locke
onwards, political reflection on power has been dominated by two distinct
conceptions of power - power as simple quantitative capacity to act, and power as
legitimate capacity or right, which is dependent on the notion of consent by the
subjects over whom such power is exercised. Confusion between these two ideas
has been endemic to modern political thought, even among would-be radical
critics of power, such as Habermas and Steven Lukes, (Lukes, 1974) who argue
222
Foucault uses the example of the asymmetry of power relations involved in education as an
example.
159
for the emancipation of the individual from power. (Hindess, 1996 p.1-22) Critical
theory carries forward the ‘confusion’ between these two concepts of power,
which are based on two substantially different models of the human subject. Thus
despite Habermas’ criticisms of earlier critical theorists, he effectively retains
their key underlying assumptions such as the ideal of the autonomous, rational
individual and the possibility of some form of political community free from the
distorting effects of power. (Hindess, 1996 p.94) In this regard suggests Hindess,
there is a clear continuity between contemporary critical theory and Locke, in
whose work is evident two views of the subject. One emphasises the autonomous,
rational individual whose consent is necessary for the legitimate exercise of
political power, while the other treats the individual as a considerably more
malleable entity whose attitudes and hence standards of moral judgment are
moulded by processes of social interaction. (Hindess, 1996 p.18, 58-63, 94-5)
It is not necessary to revisit in detail the discussion in earlier chapters of
critical theory, other than to acknowledge Hindess’ persuasive argument that
critical theory, in its purportedly radical treatment of power, fails to break with
the preoccupation with sovereignty and right, which Foucault identified as the
central problem of modern political theory. Of significance for the discussion here
is that in clarifying the shortcomings of critical theory’s critique of power,
Hindess brings into focus Foucault’s own continuing attachment to an underlying
vision of individual autonomy. In this context it is useful to cite Hindess’
summation of how this notion of autonomy underpins the entire critical theory
project. Hindess argues that contemporary critical theorists such as Lukes,
Marcuse and Habermas
base a significant part of their analyses of power on: (1) a model of the
individual as a creature of social conditions; (2) an image of the
autonomous individual which provides an ideal against which the present
can be measured; (3) the claim that such an ideal could be realised in a
realm of social existence that is not structured by the illegitimate effects
of power. This last presents us with the utopian vision of an idealised civil
society whose inhabitants would be precisely the autonomous, rational
persons required by the Lockean account of political power. In their
different ways ...[these theorists] ... acknowledge the reality of
heteronomy - the fact that the attributes and capacities of persons are
crucially dependent on social conditions - while retaining the Lockean
ideal of the autonomous, rational person. (Hindess, 1996 p.95)
Hindess recognises the radical nature of Foucault’s break with the
‘Hobbesian’ model of sovereign power in that it rejects the standard
preoccupation with sovereignty and legitimacy. Yet at the same time, he points to
elements in Foucault’s work that continued to cling to the ‘enduring fictions’ of
Western political thought. In particular Hindess questions the distinction Foucault
made in his later writings between power and domination. If power is co-
160
extensive with all social relations, and therefore unavoidable, then the normative
ideal of a general emancipation from power relations is simply untenable. Of
course, as Hindess and Patton note, this did not mean Foucault rejected the notion
of a limited ‘emancipation’ from specific systems of power or from the effects of
particular techniques of power. (Hindess, 1996 p.152; Patton, 1989 p.274-6)
In general Foucault expressed a deep distrust of notions of universal
emancipation or ‘liberation’, an attitude linked to his rejection of humanism, and
to his concern to understand history as the history of multiple, specific and
therefore potentially conflicting rationalities of government. (Foucault, 1984b)
Paradoxically, from the perspective of traditional political philosophy, the core of
these concerns in Foucault's work was the desire not to close off the possibilities
of human action and therefore autonomy and freedom. (Foucault, 1988c p.15) In
his later work Foucault conceded that ‘liberation’ could be the necessary
precondition for the practice of liberty, but he defined the applicability of these
terms in a restricted manner. First, he suggested ‘liberation’ may be necessary
where a state of domination exists, that is, where the relations of power have
become fixed and ‘congealed’. Second, the ‘liberation’ must be understood as
limited to those specific factors that have become the object of such domination.
In other words for Foucault ‘liberation’ involved freeing up existing (or creating
new) relationships of power, not dissolving them per se. This was the freeing up
of the capacity of particular agents to act (power to), and hence involves the
transformation of rigidified relations (states of domination) towards the dynamic
‘agonism’ that exists between autonomous agents in relations of power (and
resistance) proper.223
Foucault rejected the sorts of universal emancipation espoused by humanists
such as Taylor and the critical theorists, because rather than removing restrictions
on the free play of relations of power, their view of liberation was based on a
foundational human subject which had become suppressed or alienated.
Liberation in this context referred to the restoration of this repressed subject to its
genuine form. (Foucault, 1988a p.2-3) By contrast, Foucault’s critique of
humanism was based on the argument that it was through historically contingent
discursive and disciplinary practices that this very ‘idea or model of humanity was
developed, and now this idea of man has become normative, self-evident and is
supposed to be universal.’ The representation of certain modes of subjectivity as
universal or transcendental had to be rejected precisely because it ‘presents a
certain form of our ethics as a universal model for any kind of freedom’, and in
doing so forecloses other possibilities for freedom. (Foucault, 1988c p.15)
223
‘Liberation opens up new relationships of power, which have to be controlled by practices of
liberty.’ (Foucault, 1988a p.4)
161
Given Foucault’s rejection of the notion of freedom as involving the
liberation of an essential subjectivity from the distortions imposed by power, in
what alternative sense can freedom be understood? Ian Hacking points to what he
describes as Foucault’s ‘extreme nominalism’, which denies any pre-conceptual
mode of being and insists that all aspects of the social, including subjectivity
itself, must be seen as historically contingent. (Hacking, 1986a p.29, 37)
Elsewhere he develops this further to describe how a theory of ‘dynamic
nominalism’ relates to the notion of the individual person. Intentional action, says
Hacking, is action ‘under a description’, that is, deliberate human action is
dependent on the ways in which we describe those actions. Consequently, new
modes of description create new modes of being and new possibilities for
intentional action. Hacking suggests that each category of personhood has its own
history, which can be understood as resulting from two ‘vectors of labelling’ - one
from above, imposed by the discourse of scientific disciplines and dividing
practices, the other from below, defining the autonomous behaviour of
individuals. (Hacking, 1986b p.231-5)
Two possibilities for freedom arise from this. Firstly, the potential for
different types of subjectivity is in a basic ontological sense indeterminate and
open, although actual forms will be the product of historically derived relations of
power relations that are open to change. Secondly, while the power relations and
‘regimes of truth’ will tend, through various objectifying processes, towards
normalisation of the individual, the thrust from below of what Foucault called
anonymous, subjugated knowledge provides a resistance to normalisation and
disciplinary practices. (Foucault, 1980e p.81-84) As Patton comments, this
‘spectrum of existing forms of individuality’ defines the possibilities for
subjectivity at any particular historical juncture. Thus Foucault’s genealogical
method inevitably finds itself in a certain dynamic tension. A tension that on the
one hand presents a form of historical a priori of what is possible within a
particular historical space, while at the same time opening up games of truth to
radical questioning, exposing received forms of subjectivity as historically
contingent ‘straightjackets of identity’ that are not immutable or inevitable, but
imposed and arbitrary. (Patton, 1989) It is this tension that Foucault is referring to
in his later work when he talks of the ethos of the ‘care of the self’ as a practice of
liberty and directs his attention to ‘the problem of the relationships between
subject and games of truth’. In so doing he drew a contrast with his earlier work
on power,224 and acknowledged this involved a shift of emphasis from a concern
with the relationship between knowledge and these coercive or objectifying
practices towards the ‘practices of self-formation of the subject’. (Foucault, 1988a
p.2) In Hacking’s terms this could be seen as a shift between the ‘two vectors of
224
Where the emphasis was on ‘coercive practices’ such as psychiatry and the penal system, and
‘theoretical or scientific games’, such as ‘the analysis of language and of the living being’
(Foucault, 1988a p.2)
162
labelling’ to an emphasis on the one ‘from below’ which is concerned with
reflexively defining the autonomous behaviour of the individual.
The difficulty Hindess points to in this shift is that Foucault appeared to
suggest ‘not simply that domination will in fact be resisted, but also that it should
be kept to a minimum’ (Hindess, 1996 p.154). In other words, Foucault appeared
to shift from the recognition of resistance as an effect of certain types of power
relations, to advancing what appeared to be a universalised normative injunction.
Thus while at a methodological level Foucault seemed to reject notions of
generalised emancipation and universal ethical standards, Hindess suggests that in
his later remarks on both the critical function of philosophy and on the nature of
freedom, he could be regarded as resurrecting some of the central concerns of
critical theory, particularly the idealisation of autonomy. Hindess illustrates this
by contrasting Foucault’s earlier (1971) Nietzschean account of history as ‘the
endlessly repeated play of dominations (in which) humanity installs each of its
violences in a system of rules and thus proceeds from domination to domination’,
(Foucault, 1984a p.85) with the view put forward in his last interview in 1984,
where the critical function of philosophy is identified as ‘the challenging of all
phenomena of domination at whatever level or under whatever form they present
themselves’. (Foucault, 1988a)
Foucault linked this critical role for philosophy to the ‘Socratic imperative’
for the individual to ‘ground yourself in liberty, through the mastery of the self.’
(Foucault, 1988a p.20) This is so because it is free individuals who are engaged in
relations of power (or ‘strategic games of liberty’) with each other, which
Foucault contrasts with states of domination (‘which are what we ordinarily call
power’) and political power (‘understood of course, as a state of domination’).
(Foucault, 1988a p.19-20) Thus less than six months before his death, Foucault
outlined his project in terms that very clearly placed the notion of the freedom and
autonomy of the subject at the centre of his work:
I do not think that the only point of possible resistance to political power understood of course, as a state of domination - lies in the relationship of
self to self. I say that governmentality implies the relationship of self to
self, which means exactly that, in the idea of governmentality, I am
aiming at the totality of practices, by which one can constitute, define,
organise, instrumentalise the strategies which individuals in their liberty
can have in regard to each other. It is free individuals who try to control,
to determine, to delimit the liberty of others and, in order to do that, they
dispose of certain instruments to govern others. That rests indeed on
freedom, on the relationship of self to self and the relationship to the
other. (Foucault, 1988a p.20)
This move, which allows Foucault to distinguish between domination and
‘strategic games of power between liberties’, is seen by Hindess as invoking an
163
idealised conception of community in which domination is kept to a minimum,
and thus as promoting yet another ‘version of the utopian critique of power’ that
Foucault’s own work in other respects had served to undermine. (Hindess, 1996
p.156) Hindess suggests that if we accept Foucault’s view (and he clearly thinks
we should) that the human subject is constituted by the effects of power, then
there are no grounds for a normative condemnation of domination in general.
How can we accept the productivity of power in the formation of human
capacities and at the same time condemn the role subjectification and domination
play in this process? In particular Hindess draws on the argument developed by
Nietzsche concerning the source of ‘responsibility’ or autonomy in the modern
individual. Nietzsche examined how the ‘sovereign individual’ (‘the man who has
his own independence, protracted will and the right to make promises’) comes
into being historically. (Nietzsche, 1989) What Nietzsche deals with is precisely
the genealogy of the modern subject of power, the ‘free individual’ that Foucault
invokes as engaging in practices of liberty.225
Nietzsche’s claim was that the very condition of autonomy, expressed through
the capacity to take sovereign responsibility for one’s actions (‘the right to make
promises’) is the result of a long history of moral discipline and social
regimentation in which human beings are made ‘to a certain degree necessary,
uniform, like among like, regular, and consequently calculable’ (Nietzsche, 1989
p.58-9) - the very point Foucault himself made time and again. Thus, as a crucial
component of the historical processes responsible for the formation of modern
subjectivity, domination must be understood as ‘an indispensable condition of
liberty - or at least the kinds of liberty that both we and Nietzsche have learned to
desire. (Hindess, 1996 p.155)
Hindess suggests that to be consistent, Foucault’s analysis of the productivity
of power relations must also recognise that some degree of domination and
subjectification are necessary for the existence of organised social structures and
institutions. Consequently, as both Nietzsche and Hobbes argued, these are also
necessary for the forms of liberty made possible by ‘organised social existence’.
(Hindess, 1996 p.157) A consistent application of Foucault’s own analysis would
therefore require that while it would be a sociological fact that particular instances
of domination would be resisted, there could be no transcendental normative
grounds on which to condemn domination in general. That Foucault in his later
works appeared to repeatedly to do just this indicates he neglected his own
methodological prescription that criticism should not be practiced as a ‘search for
formal structures with universal value’, but rather as specific historical
225
In rebuffing Habermas’ utopian notion of power free communication, Foucault suggested that
it was necessary to ‘ground oneself in liberty’, that is, ‘to give one's self the rules of law, the
techniques of management, ... and the ethos, the practice of self that would allow ... games of
power to be played with a minimum of domination.’ (Foucault, 1988a p.8)
164
investigations into the events and processes responsible for producing the modern
subject in its various forms. This demanded that philosophical analysis must
eschew ‘all projects that claim to be global or radical’. (Foucault, 1991e p.45-6)
According to Hindess, the basis of Foucault’s apparent inconsistency on this
question lies in his incomplete critique of sovereignty. He failed to fully
disengage his analysis from that pervasive ‘modern obsession with the idea of the
person as autonomous agent, and consequently, with the idea that a community of
such persons can, and should, be governed by consent of its members.’ (Hindess,
1996 p.157) This was implicit in Foucault’s treatment of domination as something
that should be avoided or minimised as far as possible because it undermines the
liberty of the individual and leads to ‘congealed’ or rigid relations of power. Here
Foucault returned to a theme familiar in modern political philosophy when he
expressed a concern not only for the repressive effect on the liberty of those
subjected to domination, but also the view that domination in some way corrupts
those exercising power (domination). This is made clear when he suggested that
‘if you care for yourself correctly ... then you cannot abuse your power over
others.’ (Foucault, 1988a p.18)
While Foucault (and others) have focused on elaborating the genealogy of the
modern individual, much less has been done to understand the ways in which
power and domination constitute the community within which such individuals
are formed. (Hindess, 1996 p.158) Thus while the differentiation of domination
from power can serve useful analytical or descriptive purposes, Foucault’s reasons
for privileging the freedom associated with power relations proper must be called
into question if his own arguments about the productive nature of the disciplinary
processes are to be taken seriously. In his analysis Hindess concludes that
Foucault’s criticism of political sovereignty did not go far enough. Not only do
we need, as Foucault insisted, a political philosophy that is not built around the
problem of sovereignty, we also need to free ourselves from that other constitutive
fiction of modern political thought - that of political community. A full
consideration of this problem is beyond the scope of the present thesis.
Nevertheless, Hindess’ analysis does suggest an answer to the question of why
Foucault made a distinction between capacities exerted over things and relations
of power among acting human subjects, and why the natural sciences, which take
as their object the study of non-human things, were seen by him as capable of
detaching themselves from relations of power.
My argument here is that Foucault’s ‘privileging’ of the natural sciences
should be seen as linked directly to his underlying philosophical concern with
autonomy as a fundamental feature of human nature. As suggested earlier in this
chapter, Foucault’s analysis appears to have rested on a vitalism of human bodily
capacities (what Patton terms a thin conception of the subject of thought and
action), but more significantly it ontologically characterised human nature as the
capacity for agency, a move which was tied to a particular idealisation of
165
individual autonomy. Thomas Wartenberg has argued that Foucault ‘attributes to
power the structure of human agency - that is, the capability of performing actions
with strategic intent’ and that this amounts to posing power ‘as a quasi-subject’, a
move which obscures the actual processes involved in power relationships.
According to Wartenberg, despite his insights into the mechanisms of social
domination, Foucault thus effectively relied on a metaphysical positing of a
‘supra-human subject ... as necessary for explaining the nature of human social
development.’ (Wartenberg, 1990 p.137-9) While Wartenberg over-states the
degree to which Foucault was guilty of hypostasising power, there was clearly in
Foucault's later work an underlying Nietzschean notion of human nature that lent
itself to an idealisation or affirmation of individual autonomy.
Rouse: the critique of epistemic sovereignty
The argument that Foucault’s critique of sovereignty does not go far enough
has been raised in a different way by Joseph Rouse. 226 His analysis is important in
the context of the present chapter because he is one of the few scholars to
specifically consider how Foucault’s work applies to the natural sciences. 227
Rouse (1987; 1991; 1993; 1994) claims that a critique of sovereignty analogous to
that put forward by Foucault in relation to political theory can be developed in
epistemology and philosophy of the natural sciences.
A key element of Foucault’s criticism of the concept of political sovereignty
was that it obscured the ways in which power actually operates in modern
societies. Theories of sovereignty rely one-sidedly on the politico-juridical model
of power as repressive and prohibitive, and neglect the dispersed sources of power
(its ‘microphysics’) and its deployment outside the frameworks of the state.228 In
this regard Rouse points to Foucault’s claim that the principle of sovereignty in
political theory was increasingly separated from ‘any real political location’ and
instead was turned into an ‘analytic’ or ‘theoretical’ construct against which
political practice is assessed. (Rouse, 1993 p.145; 1994 p.101) Foucault’s concern
then was that political criticism based on the concepts of sovereignty and right
misrepresented how power operates, but also that it ‘dangerously misunderstands
its own positioning’ by failing to recognise the fictitious nature of the rational
consent that purportedly formed the ultimate foundation of political sovereignty.
That is, the modern institutions and practices of sovereignty are not the source of
power but rather were constituted by the sorts of disciplinary practices that lay
226
A version of this section of the Chapter was previously published in Rutherford (1994a).
227
Other major works to consider this include Kusch (1991) and Gutting (1989).
228
See Chapters 5 and 6 respectively of the current thesis for detailed discussion of these points.
Foucault most clearly develops his critique of sovereignty in his lectures published in the Colin
Gordon (1980b) collection and Foucault (1990)
166
outside of the political realm of law and right. In rejecting political criticism based
on rights, Foucault was objecting to any attempt to endow historically specific
political positions (and in particular, French intellectual Marxism) with the
standpoint of a generalised or transcendental epistemic sovereignty. 229 (Rouse,
1993 p.144-9; 1994 p.101-4) While Foucault does not use this term, Rouse argues
that it is not difficult to discern a fairly clear parallel within epistemology to the
concern with sovereignty evident in political thought.
All of the central issues of political sovereignty are reproduced in
epistemology: the constitution of a unitary regime, based upon legitimacy
through law, established from an impartial standpoint above particular
conflicts, and enforced through discontinuous interventions that aim to
suppress illegitimacy. The problematic of epistemic sovereignty is
fundamentally located in the standard contrast between knowledge and
belief or assertion. ... Knowledge is a unified (or constitently unifiable)
network of statements that can be extracted from the welter of confused
and conflicting contenders and legitimated in accord with rules of rational
method, the epistemic surrogate of law. Here is where the figure of the
epistemic sovereign is theoretically important. Sovereignty need not be
located in any actual sovereign knower, any more than political
sovereignty requires a monarch. But just as the sovereign power must be
one that could consistently be embodied in a single will, sovereign
knowledge must be consistently representable in a single coherent
propositional system. (Rouse, 1993 p.147)
The objections Foucault raised with political sovereignty can be seen to apply
to epistemic sovereignty as a view of knowledge that tends to ignore the local and
multiple ‘micropractices’ that produce knowledge and its objects. Foucault’s work
makes it clear that relations of power and knowledge constitute both the ‘knowing
subject and the truths known’. (Rouse, 1994 p.103) Just as Foucault’s critique of
sovereignty sought to overcome the theoretical privileging of sovereignty and law
in the analysis of power, his genealogical investigations were an ‘attempt to
emancipate historical knowledges (from) the coercion of a theoretical, unitary,
formal, and scientific discourse’ which ‘aims to inscribe knowledges in the
hierarchical order of power associated with science’. (Foucault, 1980e p.85) Given
this, it is reasonable to suggest that while Foucault did not develop a critique of
the natural sciences in the same way as he did for the human sciences, it is
nevertheless possible to find a strong parallel between the ways in which natural
scientific knowledge is produced and the sorts of disciplinary practices Foucault
identified in the production of power/knowledge in the human sciences.
229
On Foucault's criticism of Marxism, see Foucault (1980e) p.84-8.
167
Rouse argues that despite Foucault’s own apparent reluctance to apply his
approach to the established natural sciences, his genealogies, by problematising
the notion of an essential human subjectivity, also challenge the traditional
concepts of representation and action that ground the distinction between the
natural and human sciences. (Rouse, 1993 p.138-9) Rouse aptly points out that
any
strong epistemic or political distinction between nature and society would
clearly be subject to the central motivating question of Foucault’s work:
‘in what is given to us as universal, necessary, obligatory, what place is
occupied by whatever is singular, contingent, and the product of arbitrary
constraints?’ (Rouse, 1993 p.138-9)
He therefore suggests the need to broaden Foucault’s notion of power beyond
interaction conceived simply as relations between human agents, to one that
encompasses the ways in which the configuration of technical practices and
material technologies help structure specific alignments of power. (Rouse, 1991
p.660) As with the human sciences, scientific knowledge of new phenomena in
the natural world (including ecological processes and entities such as global
warming) alters the strategic alignments of power relations within society. Both
the natural and human sciences rely on developing historically new practices of
surveillance which serve to describe, partition, measure, classify and refine the
behaviour and properties of their objects of study. New domains of scientific
expertise come into existence through postulating new objects of knowledge and
by developing new techniques for measuring, manipulating and monitoring these
new entities. The extension of knowledge and its associated material technologies
acts to discipline and control the action-environment of social agents. On this
account natural scientific knowledge cannot be separated from power, for
knowledge is embodied in the skills, techniques and machines which are integral
to scientific activity. (Rouse, 1987; 1991) Conceptual skills and material
techniques, which arise from specific alignments of capacities and power at the
local or micro-level of the laboratory and within particular technical discourses
(such as computer models) are extended outside the laboratory and mediate the
way in which the world is produced, reproduced and structured. That is, ‘power
relations require not only keeping other human agents in line, but also a reliable
alignment of the physical environment.’ (Rouse, 1991 p.659) Foucault suggested
something similar when he discussed the ‘paradox’ of relations of capacity and
power. In that context he said that ‘control over things is mediated by relations
with others’ but he maintained the importance of analytically separating three
axes or ‘practical systems’ of critique: those of knowledge, power and ethics.
(Foucault, 1984b p.48-9)
Some of the key features that Foucault identified with power relations in the
social field can be found in the exercise of capacities over things. In particular the
notion of surveillance with its practices of examination, recording and
168
normalising classification was central to Foucault’s understanding of biopower
(both as anatomo-politics and as biopolitics), and this finds an obvious parallel in
the objectifying practices of the natural sciences. Indeed, as mentioned above,
Foucault points to the common origin of the human and natural sciences in the
‘terrible power’ of the investigatory technique. (Foucault, 1979b p.224-6) In
Foucault’s work this disciplinary impetus, in which people are treated as docile
bodies, was supplemented with an emphasis on the productive character of power.
This productive dimension was connected by Foucault, via the technique of the
confession, to the self-constituting activities of speaking subjects compelled ‘to
speak the truth’ of the self. (Foucault, 1982 p.208) 230 The production of the truth
of the self depends on the ‘decipherment of what is said’ by the expert as
confessor. Confession is primarily a procedure in which particular sorts of signs
are elicited from the subject and interpreted by experts, and it is only through such
a process of interpretation that truth is ‘scientifically validated’.
In his discussion of the formation of modern sexuality Foucault thus pointed
to the interdependence between procedures of confession and ‘scientific
discursivity’, and argued that in making the truths of the human sciences
(particularly those of sexuality) into signs dependent on the ‘hermeneutic
function’ of the expert, it became possible for the procedures of confession to
become part of ‘the regular formation of scientific discourse.’ (Foucault, 1990
p.64-7) Here Foucault restricted his comments to the human sciences. Rouse
however argues that it is not just the speaking human subject that is ‘constrained
to produce signs’. The natural sciences too abound with countless ways in which
things are also forced to speak, that is, emit signs - as in the human sciences, the
objects of investigation in natural sciences do not remain silent and docile.
(Rouse, 1987 p.220) Indeed, most if not all of the entities of the natural sciences
are only accessible through signs produced by various techniques, equipment,
methods and models, the ‘disclosures’ of which are taken as genuine or real only
within the ‘authoritative interpretative constraints that distinguish data from
artefacts or noise.’ (Rouse, 1993 p.141) 231 What Rouse has argued then is that the
signs extracted from things may be as important in producing political effects as
those elicited from speaking subjects. (Rouse, 1987 p.220)
230
See also Rouse (1987) p.218 and (1993) p.140.
231
Rouse cites as examples of techniques used to incite the production of signs such procedures
as 'radioactive labelling, cloud and bubble chambers, x-ray crystallography, and various forms
of chromatography, spectroscopy, microscopy, and telescopy'. To this could be added the
techniques of the environmental sciences, such as general circulation models of the global
atmosphere, and even concepts such as 'ecosystem' and 'biodiversity' as these are dependent on
forces and entities such as trophic levels and genes which are themselves only accessible
through the signs emitted by similar sorts of instruments and techniques referred to by Rouse. I
have elaborated on this elsewhere. See Rutherford, (1994a; 1997a).
169
When this argument is considered in the context of the production of
scientific truths in ecological discourse its strength is readily apparent. For
example, some parallels can be drawn here with Beck’s analysis of the role of
contemporary science in the systemic production of ecological ‘mega-hazards’.
As discussed in Chapter 4, Beck demonstrates that what constitutes an ecological
risk, and the way in which the consequent environmental and health hazards are
distributed, are discursively defined. The sorts of global ecological hazards Beck
is concerned with, such as radiation contamination and depletion of the
stratospheric ozone layer, are not readily visible or perceptible in unmediated
every-day experience. Rather, ecological risks only come into existence through
the objectifying medium of expert judgment, that is, these sorts of hazards are not
things of simple experience but require the interpretation of scientific theories and
intervention of measuring instruments ‘in order to become visible or interpretable
as hazards at all.’ (Beck, 1992b p.27) 232 Beck suggests that contemporary
ecological and technological hazards are characterised by their invisibility to nonexpert experience. Such risks
are based on causal interpretations, and thus initially only exist in terms
of the knowledge about them. They can thus be changed, magnified,
dramatised or minimised within knowledge, and to that extent they are
particularly open to social definition and construction. (Beck, 1992b
p.22-3)
One consequence of this is that the victims of technologically produced hazards
are rendered ‘incompetent in matters of their own affliction’, with the power to
define hazards and judge exposure to risks increasingly restricted to expert
‘external knowledge producers’. (Beck, 1992a p.97-123; 1992b p.53-5)
Rouse argues that while knowledge, in this case that produced by the natural
sciences, is not equivalent to power, nevertheless it cannot be considered in
isolation from the social field in which it exists. Knowledge includes not only
propositional statements (in Foucault’s usage connaissances) but also objects,
instruments, skills, and various social networks. In themselves none of these
constitute the discursive field of knowledge (what Foucault termed savior).
Scientific statements only count as knowledge by virtue of their actual use, that is,
in terms of their practical deployment or alignment with other heterogeneous
elements; to conceive of scientific knowledge as a stable and ‘distinct object
domain’ overlooks the dynamic interconnection between knowledge and other
social and material resources. (Rouse, 1994 p.110-1) 233 This of course is
232
There is a clear parallel here with Habermas’ treatment of ‘objective nature’ as that which can
only be made available as an object of possible knowledge through the objectifying processes
of modern science. See Chapter 3 of present thesis for discussion of Habermas on this.
233
Hence Rouse takes ‘the “field” within which scientific claims acquire significance and
justification to include more than a web of belief: skills and techniques, instruments and
170
consistent with Foucault’s approach to knowledge in the human sciences.
(Foucault, 1990 p.93-4) As with Foucault’s view of the human sciences, a crucial
element of Rouse’s analysis of natural science is his emphasis on the diverse
sources of these localised, heterogeneous elements. In line with Rouse’s argument
against the possibility of epistemic sovereignty, scientific knowledge production
must be understood as a series of historical practices the subtlety and detail of
which cannot be captured by generalisations about ‘scientific reason’. Nor can
this be captured by generalisations about the degree of formalisation, as Foucault
tended to suggest in his early archaeological work. (Foucault, 1972)
Similarly, the sorts of authoritative interpretation referred to by Foucault as
central to the human sciences is also exercised in the natural sciences. As with the
human sciences, this also occurs in quite specific socio-historical circumstances
with numerous, highly localised origins - what Rouse terms laboratory
‘microworlds’. Accordingly, scientific concepts and theories, such as genes,
retroviruses and global climate change ‘only become possible objects of
knowledge or discourse within ... a complex practical field, shaped by the
availability of equipment, and subtle technical and theoretical skills.’ (Rouse,
1991 p.660) In other words, science depends as much on creating and mobilising
technical capacities, associated with instruments, machines, tests, protocols etc, as
it does on theory construction.234 Indeed, this approach implies that the
investigatory practices carried out in the laboratory (and its analogues in field
studies) are far more crucial than is generally suggested by philosophical studies
of science, which treat science primarily as a theoretical-discursive activity.
This is a criticism that can also be said to apply to Foucault’s treatment of the
natural sciences. 235 Drawing on the work of Bruno Latour236, Rouse emphasises
that a key feature of natural science is the ability to construct new phenomena
within the laboratory or other experimental situation. 237 What makes science
material systems (including networks of manufacture and supply), resource availability (money
and facilities, but also staff, information, an audience, etc), institutional structures, relevance to
other social practices and political concerns and much more.’ (Rouse, 1991 p.662-3)
234
Rose and Miller (1992) develop a substantially similar approach. However their focus is on
the role of the expertise of the social sciences. See Chapter 6 in the current thesis for a more
detailed discussion of this.
235
At least in works such as Foucault (1970; 1972).
236
The work of Latour is discussed in the next chapter. Rose and Miller also draw on Latour,
particularly for the notion of ‘action at a distance’ which they employ to explain the modes of
liberal and neo-liberal governmentality which rely heavily on various forms of professional
expertise for the shaping of conduct outside of the formal institutions of state rule. See Rose
and Miller (1992); Rose (1993).
237
Here Rouse draws on Ian Hacking’s definition of phenomenon: ‘By ‘phenomenon’ Hacking
means a manifest regularity in the natural world. It is not a private sensation but a public event
171
powerful is precisely its capacity to structure the world outside the laboratory. Yet
this capacity is not simply the ability to transfer the phenomena from the
constructed world of the laboratory to the outside world. More fundamentally it is
the ability to transfer the laboratory conditions themselves into the outside world,
a task which characteristically necessitates extending the materials and techniques
that ‘made possible the disclosure and tracking of laboratory phenomena’ in the
first place. (Rouse, 1987 p.101; 1993 p.139-43)
The principal achievement of science is its capacity to create new phenomena.
Science is more than simply a theoretical-discursive activity, but it is also more
than the simple discovery of facts through empirical observation. Rouse points to
the inherent opportunism of the natural sciences - science is a highly practical
activity in which the direction of research (and hence the type of knowledge
produced) is to a considerable degree shaped by the techniques and
instrumentation available. The capacity of scientists to manipulate instruments
and experimental apparatus is as much a practical art as theoretical
representation. Thus experimentation involves much more than the testing of the
adequacy of prior theorising against observed facts. Rather it
opens new domains for investigation, refines them to make them suitable
for theoretical reflection and provides a practical grasp of that domain as
a resource. The creation of new phenomena, and scientists’ practical
understanding of the instrumental context of the laboratory within which
this creation occurs, cannot be easily subordinated to a theory-dominant
picture of how science develops. (Rouse, 1987 p. 100-1) 238
This approach brings into focus the importance of the non-discursive
practices as well as those discursive-theoretical elements that are generally taken
to characterise the natural sciences. It forces us to pay attention to the ways in
that commands our attention. What distinguishes a phenomenon are its clarity and reliability.
Phenomena are clearly discernible, and the circumstances of their occurrence (although not
always their causes or their most adequate description) must be well understood. The clarity of
phenomena is to be contrasted to the complexity, the confused muddle, of most events in the
world. In the language of information theory, phenomena have a high signal-to-noise ratio. But
in this sense of the word there are comparatively few phenomena in nature. Hacking cites the
pre-eminence of astronomy as a source of manifest regularity... A few chemical reactions and
changes of state might also be cited ... But generally nature presents us with a blooming,
buzzing confusion ... An empirical science dependent upon evident regularities in nature will
very quickly encounter irreducible local idiosyncrasies. The objects of such a science would be
far too complex for any systematic investigation stemming from observation, however careful.
We tend to say too many factors are involved for any of them to be clearly seen, although, as
Hacking notes, this can be said only in retrospect, when those ‘factors’ have been
distinguished, isolated and analysed. Before that there is just complexity, and the ‘factors’
from which it supposedly results do not exist.' (Rouse, 1987 p.99; Hacking, 1983)
238
For more detailed illustrations of this see Rouse (1987) p.69-126; also Mulkay (1979) p.63-95
and Woolgar and Latour (1979).
172
which technical resources (instruments and techniques) are employed in the
construction of phenomena in the experimental settings (laboratory microworlds).
It also requires that we further consider the ways in which these phenomena are
mobilised and deployed beyond their initial local settings and transferred into the
wider society. Central to this approach is the understanding that laboratory
microworlds are analogues in the natural sciences of the disciplinary and
normalising locales (prisons, clinics, etc) dealt with in Foucault’s consideration of
the human sciences.
Conclusion
The arguments for regarding the natural sciences in this way are considered
further in the next chapter, where I discuss the work of Bruno Latour and actor
network theory. However, it can be seen that it is possible to develop a detailed
and highly plausible application of Foucault’s approach to understand how the
natural sciences are enmeshed in strategies of power and knowledge. (Rouse,
1987 p.209-47) The claim that Foucault’s critique of political sovereignty can be
broadened out in a theoretically consistent manner to a critique of epistemic
sovereignty in general and the natural sciences in particular, amounts to an
immanent critique of Foucault on this count. If it were simply a case of
acknowledging Foucault did not develop his ideas in relation to the natural
sciences because his primary intellectual (and political) interests lay elsewhere,
then the sorts of comments made here could be seen as an extension of Foucault’s
work rather than as a critique. However, when these arguments regarding
epistemic sovereignty are taken against the background of Hindess’ comments
regarding Foucault’s incomplete critique of political sovereignty, their broader
critical nature becomes apparent.
To reiterate, Foucault’s preparedness to treat the natural sciences in a manner
different from the human sciences - by maintaining that the former are able to
detach or distance themselves from relations of social power - accepts that there
are basic differences between the objects of these different sciences. Hence his
distinction between capacities over things and relations of power between active
subjects. As I have argued, this distinction, which is perfectly consistent with the
main currents of Western philosophical thinking, can be traced to a philosophical
commitment to autonomy and the capacity for agency as the defining
characteristic of the human subject.
Rouse’s approach to this issue draws on the work of the French sociologist of
science Bruno Latour in significant ways.239 Latour’s criticism of the ‘modern
239
I have already noted in Chapter 6 that Rose and Miller’s work on neo-liberal modes of
governmentality draws on Latour’s notion of ‘action at a distance’. See Rose and Miller
(1992).
173
constitution’ of political philosophy and sociology argues that these critical
enterprises are based on the failed attempt to rigidly separate nature and society.
Latour is also critical of Foucault, particularly of his acceptance of the ‘the
solidity of the natural sciences’. The argument that the sources of power cut
across the subject/nature divide is taken up in more detail the next chapter.
174
Chapter 8
Latour and actor network theory.
Introduction
The preceding chapter examined the connection between Foucault’s
willingness to see the natural sciences as able to detach themselves from relations
of power and knowledge, something that he regarded as impossible in the human
sciences. This attitude was considered in the context of what I described as
Foucault’s incomplete critique of sovereignty. That chapter concluded by
suggesting that to be consistent with the tasks he set for his own project,
Foucault’s criticism of political sovereignty needed to be carried further into a
rejection of all forms of epistemic sovereignty.
The argument that Foucault’s notion of power can be developed to deal with
the natural sciences is pursued further in current chapter. In doing this I draw on
the work of the French sociologist of science, Bruno Latour. In particular, I
consider how the distinction between the ‘social’ and the ‘natural’ is called into
question by a broader critique of epistemic sovereignty. Building on this, I
explore the compatibility of the work of Latour and actor network theory with that
of Foucault. I suggest that the actor network theory approach can provide an
understanding of power and representation in the natural sciences that in key
respects is not inconsistent with Foucault’s general approach to such questions.
Foucault’s approach to the separation of power in the social and natural
sciences is problematic and open to challenge. As I noted in the previous chapter,
Rouse’s work draws on that of Bruno Latour, and it is to the work of Latour,
Michel Callon and others associated with ‘actor network theory’ that I now turn.
As suggested in the preceding discussion, if power is to be considered as a
relationship (or set of relationships) which is not purely a property of the human
subject or agent, then the importance of non-human material entities, including
technical resources in understanding power in modern society must be considered
in a different light. Actor network theory, and in particular the work of Latour and
Callon, promises to help in providing the conceptual approach to overcome the
sorts of difficulties identified in the preceding chapter. Indeed, several
commentators have alluded to areas of similarity between the general approach to
175
power adopted by Foucault and that found in actor network theory.240 In the first
part of this chapter I set out some of the key elements of actor network theory,
noting in the process the points of similarity with Foucault, before considering in
the subsequent parts the points of divergence between the two.
Actor network theory
Actor network theory originated in attempts by sociologists of science to
explain, contrary to the prevailing approaches in philosophy of science, how
science was ‘really done’, and to understand how science and technology
interacted to impact on society outside the narrow confines of the laboratory. It
thus emerged as a critique of other theories or models of science, and in dialogue
with other sociologically informed approaches to the relationship between
scientific work and the broader society. 241 As such, its early development appears
to have occurred largely separate from the central philosophical and sociological
debates on power and social theory in which, in recent decades, the work of
Foucault has been enmeshed. 242 This is not to suggest that the predominantly
European members of the actor network theory ‘school’ were unaware of the
potential intersection of their work with the problems and approaches found in
Foucault’s work. 243 In fact there is evidence that this link is recognised, albeit
often only as a background commentary in the footnotes.
An interesting footnote to an article by Latour (1986) provides a clear
example of this is. In that article, Latour criticises sociological theory for the
reifying use of notions such as ‘society’ and ‘power’ to explain the apparent
stability of social relationships. He argues instead for an approach that
understands the ‘stability’ of macro-social structures in terms of the performative
nature of micro-relations of power. His analysis parallels that of Foucault in
emphasising that macro social structures are the product of the sorts of constant
‘agonistic’ relations of power at the micro or local level that Foucault discussed in
works such as The Subject and Power and Power/Knowledge.244
240
See for example Law (1991a) p.169 and (1997) p.3; Kusch (1991) p.190-191; Ward (1994)
p.91; Dean (1998a) p.191, 197
241
Most notably the Edinburgh School of science studies represented in the work of such
researchers as Barry Barnes and David Bloor.
242
While this development was separate from these debates, it was not in ignorance of them - in
particular see Barry Barnes (1988) substantial work on power.
243
Bruno Latour and Michel Callon, arguably the most influential actor network theorists, are of
course both French.
244
See in particular Foucault, (1982), (1980d) and (1980e).
176
Latour however added a significant dimension to his analysis that was not
adequately dealt with by Foucault, by arguing that stable social institutions245
always necessarily involve the mobilisation of heterogeneous ‘extrasomatic
resources’ in order to impose and enforce the definitions of particular actors.
Furthermore says Latour, the only way to understand such social stability is
through examining how power is exerted locally, but that this must also include
understanding how non-human and technological resources have been mobilised
by actors at the micro-level in conjunction with social elements. (Latour, 1986
p.277) Latour’s reference to Foucault occurs against the background of his
explanation of this argument, as the final footnote to his paper. It reads in full:
This is in effect the same result obtained by Michel Foucault 246 when he
dissolved the notion of power held by the powerful in favour of
micropowers diffused through the many technologies to discipline and
keep in line. It is simply an expansion of Foucault’s notion to the many
techniques employed in machines and the hard sciences. (Latour, 1986
p.279 emphasis added)
Considered in the context of my discussion of Rouse in the previous chapter there
are good reasons to accept Latour’s claim that his approach is a logical
development of Foucault’s analysis. However, before evaluating the similarities
and differences between Foucault and actor network theory in more detail, it is
first necessary to examine the key propositions that underpin actor network
theory.
According to Callon’s explanation of the ‘translation model’ of science
adopted by actor network theory, the prime objective of science is to produce
statements, which he qualifies by stressing the importance of both the process by
which such statements are made, and the role of non-propositional elements in
their production. Statements in turn make up translation chains in that all
scientific statements refer to other statements, objects and other ‘time spaces’,
which are condensed and thus made available. Translation chains ‘combine
heterogeneous elements of which the most important are statements, technical
devices and tacit skills that can rightly be called embodied skills.’ (Callon, 1995
p.50) Relationships between these heterogeneous elements are built through what
Latour called inscriptions - written traces produced in reports, laboratory notes,
graphic displays, data tables etc. The important point here is that contrary to those
models of science which assume a fundamental division between experimental
instruments and observational statements, the translation model sees simply a
245
Foucault argued that such stable institutions, resulted from what he called states of domination
‘when stable mechanisms replace the free play of antagonistic reactions’. (Foucault, 1982
p.225-6).
246
The reference here is to Discipline and Punish.
177
range of inscriptions which vary in their degree of sophistication and organising
capacity.247
Callon explicitly draws a parallel between the approach of Foucault and
Latour, this time when he argues that ‘Writing devices are important in all
scientific fields and beyond. For example, Foucault ... analyses the hospital as a
device that places the individual in a “network of writing”.’ (Callon, 1995 p.51)
Developing this analysis further, Callon emphasises that, for actor network
theory:
Science is a vast enterprise of writing, but to move from an inscription to
a statement, and from one statement to another, requires embodied skills
and/or technical devices ... it is the constant interaction between
inscriptions, technical devices, and embodied skills that leads to the
development of statements. (Callon, 1995 p.51)
Nevertheless, scientific activity does not simply produce statements; often it seeks
to move statements out of the laboratory. Here Latour’s approach can be seen as a
challenge to the conventional distinction drawn by much philosophy of science
between the content of knowledge and the context of its production - a key point
also raised by Rouse in his argument regarding the problems of epistemic
sovereignty. Callon suggests that Latour’s notion of inscription, contrary to
conventional rationalist approaches to science, allows us to understand how the
content and context of knowledge ‘are simultaneously reconfigured’. Translation
thus leads to the ‘identification and shaping of allies and seeking their support.’
This involves establishing some form of coincidence of interest between the
statements (and devices) produced in the laboratory (or in field studies in ecology)
and other, external non-scientific actors, to establish translation networks
concerned with the development and extension of the translations of a particular
set of statements or research results. 248
Callon identifies two basic forms of these translation networks. First there are
those which principally circulate their products within the specialised
communities and spaces of science - as statements within the scientific literature
and instruments within the laboratory. Second, there are those which ‘stabilise
some of these entities’ (ie statements and instruments) ‘and mobilise them to
multiply connections with non-specialists’ outside the laboratory. In each of these
cases however, it is the scientific activity that establishes the translation network.
247
The similarity between Rouse’s approach and that of Latour and Callon on these points is
clear. See also Latour (1987), especially Chapter 6.
248
Callon says that the notion of a translation network ‘refers to a compound reality in which
inscriptions (and in particular, statements), technical devices, and human actors (including
researchers, technicians, industrialists, firms, charitable organisations, and politicians) are
brought together and interact with each other.’ (Callon, 1995 p.52)
178
Callon argues that when networks of the second type are established they extend
and grow because scientists, by virtue of the defining role they play in the
manufacture of statements and instruments, are able to speak ‘on behalf of’ the
scientific entities produced (eg DNA, electrons, and I would argue, entities such
endangered species, environmental hazards etc). 249
However, what is important about this second type of translation is that in
extending the network beyond the scientific journals and laboratories, scientists
translate scientific entities for non-scientific interests (companies, governments,
interests groups). In doing so they thus are also potentially in a position to speak
on behalf of substantial numbers of other actors external to science who have
developed an interest in a particular scientific entity or who may see these as of
benefit to their own interests in some way.250 Scientists play a unique role here in
that they are engaged in a double translation or representation. This occurs, first
in translating the statements that manufacture the content of scientific knowledge
(producing the entities to which their statements refer), and second, in shaping the
context in which such knowledge (and entities) are relevant to, and interact with,
other interests and networks. This is of particular significance because
representation in science cannot be separated into statements and the objects to
which these refer or correspond in some external ‘real’ world. The entire process
is rather a chain of translations in which any single statement can be understood
as a series of translations, which refer to a multitude of other inscriptions,
embodied skills and technical devices.
Callon further suggests two important consequences of such an approach.
First, because statements do not refer to an ‘outside reality’ but are simply
‘location points’ in a teeming network of such statements etc, it is not possible to
speak of a single ‘reference’ but only of ‘an entanglement of micro references’.
What we take as a reference to the ‘out-thereness’ of entities in the world is only a
focus on the ‘final’ statement in a chain of translations.251 Hence, reference is
much like power for Foucault, ‘nothing more than an effect of a translation chain’
the robustness of which ‘depends entirely upon the latter.’ (Callon, 1995 p.53)
The second consequence of the translation network approach is that it explains
that particular strength of science which allows the scientist to ‘re-present’ in their
translation of statements and techniques the interests of other actors attracted to
that particular area of scientific work. They are able, that is, to ‘re-present’
249
Callon describes a third type of translation network - which is in effect a more dynamic version
of the second type - in which networks are ‘active on both fronts and enter into a dynamic
expansion, where each translation within the laboratory leads the network outside to be
lengthened.’ (Callon, 1995 p.52)
250
See Callon (1986) and Latour (1983) for detailed case studies of how this occurs.
251
There is a parallel here with Hacking’s notion of ‘phenomena’ as used by Rouse. See Chapter
6 of this thesis.
179
themselves as the ‘spokesperson of both nature and society.’ (Callon, 1995 p.53)
252
A key claim of actor network theory, therefore, is that the ‘facts’ of the
natural sciences are, like those of the social sciences, constructed. They are
established through the production of strong associational networks - the stronger
and more extensive a network becomes, the more solid the scientific facts
become.
The scientist, by successfully recruiting allies, both human and nonhuman, appealing to authority, referring to former texts and procedures,
compiling data, creating computer files, utilising laboratories and
equipment, etc, is able to create an encompassing network, the
sponsorship of a sustaining audience, and ultimately a community of
truth. It is through this network-building that the scientist is able to go
from soft rhetoric to hard knowledge ... What becomes a scientific fact
and an accepted truth is a direct outcome of the strength of the ties, or in
[Latour’s] words ‘metrological chains’, 253 which a scientist or group of
scientists is able to construct and enforce. If the scientist has been
successful, reality has been defined. (Ward, 1994 p.83)
This approach goes directly to the problem of the relationship between the highly
formalised natural sciences and relations of power in society, which as we saw in
an earlier chapter, is precisely the issue Foucault dismissed as an ‘excessively
complicated’ question in which the ‘threshold of explanation is impossibly high’.
(Foucault, 1980d p.109-110) However the general approach of actor network
theory to knowledge and power is similar to that adopted by Foucault. It is also
able demonstrate that the difference between the ‘inside’ and ‘outside’ of the
laboratory is in effect the same sort of relationship Foucault pointed to in his
analyses of the social sciences which pointed to the continuity between the
‘micro’ and ‘macro’ levels of social structure.
At the same time actor network theory allows us to explain the special
character attributed to natural science - which Foucault regarded as connected to
‘the centralising powers’ and functions of institutionalised scientific discourse in
Western societies. 254 The actor network approach argues that in modern societies
252
In fact this is, as I argue below, one way of accounting for the particular effects, repeatedly
commented on in Foucault’s works, of the ‘power which the West since Medieval times has
attributed to science and has reserved for those engaged in scientific discourse.’ (Foucault,
1980e p.85)
253
A metrological chain is another term used by Latour for a translation chain. See Latour (1987)
p.179.
254
Foucault refers to the ‘effects of the centralising powers which are linked to the institution and
functioning of an organised scientific discourse with a society such as ours’ and which are
180
the most dynamic and important sources of power come from science, and ‘not
from the classical political process’. 255 Indeed Latour suggests that the very
techno-scientific processes that political science and sociology have ‘deemed
uninteresting or too technical to be analysed’ 256 are in fact more influential than
many social processes. (Latour, 1983 p.168)
As indicated in my discussion of Rouse in Chapter 7, what makes science so
important (and indeed, ‘special’) is its ability to shape the world outside of the
laboratory by translating the disciplinary conditions of the laboratory into broader
social, economic and technological arenas. Latour explains that this performative
characteristic of science resides in its ability to enrol and enlist the interests of
‘outside’ actors in its translation networks. He uses the example of Pasteur’s
research into anthrax to illustrate this argument. What was crucial in making the
science of microbiology a powerful force in both agriculture and medicine (with
profound social and economic consequences), was the work of Pasteur’s team in
convincing agricultural interests that the anthrax disease could be controlled
through the scientific knowledge developed in his laboratory. This was only
possible however if farm practices were reorganised in ways which translated into
the field those laboratory conditions and practices which allowed the anthrax
bacillus to be manipulated and rendered docile.
What made this possible was the scientific success in manipulating
translations of scale. The artificial, highly disciplined micro environments of the
laboratory allowed manipulations of the bacillus in ways that were just not
possible on the pre-scientific farm. The laboratory application of the techniques of
sterility, isolation, vaccine testing, etc provided a regime of simplification and
discipline needed to study how the anthrax disease worked. That is, it enabled a
disciplining of the entire anthrax disease, which the unruly ‘outside’ world of the
farm would not. There are two elements to Latour’s argument here. First, the
laboratory techniques which permit the systematic analysis of the disease
behaviour must be perfected in the highly artificial, constructed environments of
the laboratory. However, and this is Latour’s crucial second point, for the
knowledge and techniques accumulated on the micro scale to be successfully
translated into the macro world of the farm and commercial agriculture, a very
important precondition must be present. That is, in order to extend the success rate
endowed with a special ability to invest particular discourses ‘and those who uphold them with
the effects of a power which the West since Medieval times has attributed to science and has
reserved for those engaged in scientific discourse.’ (Foucault, 1980e p.84-5).
255
The similarity of this to Beck’s analysis of science and technology in risk society should be
noted although there are important differences. See Chapter 3; I consider this further in the
Conclusion of this thesis. See also Rutherford (1999a).
256
These, of course, are the two reasons I suggested in the previous chapter for Foucault’s relative
lack attention to the natural sciences.
181
of the vaccine in the laboratory to the farm, it is also necessary to extend the
disciplinary regime of the laboratory onto the farm. Pasteur’s vaccine will only
work on the condition that the farmer ‘respect a limited set of laboratory practices
- disinfection, cleanliness, inoculation, timing and recording’ etc. The key to this
extension of scientific discipline from laboratory to the ‘outside world’, Latour
points out, is the ability of the scientists to extend their ‘translation network to
enlists the actors outside the laboratory - the farmers, government officials, etc.
For this to happen, the non-scientists first had to accept the scientists’ expertise,
that is, to follow the prescribed techniques and accept their scientific statements
as having the authority of ‘truth’. (Latour, 1983 p.150-52)
One of the key criticisms levelled by Latour at the sociology of science is that
it fails to recognise laboratories as one of the few ‘fresh sources of politics’ in
contemporary society. Much sociology of science accepts that the inside/outside
dichotomy does not hold true. However, rather than understanding the scientific
space (the laboratory) as a dynamic source of power, such sociology sees the
laboratory as a fundamentally ordinary place. Latour agrees the substantial
number of anthropological studies of laboratories over recent decades have
dissipated many of the arguments about the special epistemological status of the
natural sciences - that, indeed there is nothing special or unique in the cognitive
and social practices of science. The problem raised by Latour however is that this
fails to account for the importance of science and technology in contemporary
society. His response is to concede that scientific fact is the ‘product of average,
ordinary people and settings, linked to one another by no special norms or
communication forms.’ What makes the natural sciences powerful is in fact
something very simple - the use of inscription devices. (Latour, 1983 p.157- 62)
Hence, the influence of science in society can be explained by bringing
together the three threads of Latour’s approach to actor network theory. First, is
the dissolution of the inside/outside boundary between ‘science’ in the laboratory
and ‘society’ outside. Modern science is very much applied science, or what
Latour and others have called ‘techno-science’. (Latour, 1987) In order to
flourish, such science must be concerned with capturing the interests of others,
that is, it must be able to translate scientific statements in such a way that these
are discursively framed in terms which problematise the development and
application of economic and social interests.257 Second, is the inversion of the
scale of micro/macro levels through the expertise obtained by partitioning and
disciplining micro-phenomena in the laboratory and through mathematical or
computer modelling. This simplification and ‘scaling down’ produces a change of
scale which makes possible a reversal of the actor’s strengths so that what is
overwhelming in ‘the field’ can be made manageable and open to manipulation in
257
Latour (1983) p.145-6.
182
the scientific space. (Latour, 1983 p.145-7; 1987 p.233-7) When successful, such
inversion of scale makes the scientist (and their ‘outside’ allies) powerful where
previously they were weak.258 Third, is the processes of inscription and the
formation of ‘centres of calculation’. Irrespective of the objects or phenomena of
scientific study, the only way they can be rendered manipulable is through the
process of inscribing vast quantities of information and data into a form that can
be measured and compared. That is, information is reduced to a written trace that
not only makes the ‘perceptive judgment of the others simpler’, but it also limits
the modalities (and hence counter-arguments) that a reader can add to the
statements involved. (Latour, 1983 p.161)
When combined with the change of scale referred to above, the laboratory is
at the centre of a series of long chains through which information is gathered and
inscriptions generated, combined, condensed and then re-dispersed and inserted in
the practices of the world beyond the laboratory. In this process the laboratory
becomes a centre of calculation that draws on resources scattered across numerous
networks. Inscription devices and the traces they produce (especially numbers and
statistics) allow the operation of centres that are capable of acting at distance ‘on
unfamiliar events, places and people.’ 259 The use of cartography as a tool of
European colonial ‘exploration’ is used by Latour to illustrate the operation of
such centres of calculation in ‘bringing back’ and disciplining the unfamiliar and
distant. 260
In this way, Latour argues that it is largely meaningless to attempt to
distinguish between the social context of science and the content of science as
produced in the laboratory. There is no clear cut separation between the
laboratory and the ‘outside’ world - rather the laboratory, that which in most
respects is a rather ‘ordinary place’, is powerful precisely because it is a
technological device capable of inverting ‘the hierarchy of forces’ in society
(Latour, 1983 p.159, 164):
258
‘The change of scale makes possible a reversal of the actors’ strengths; ‘outside’ animals,
farmers, and veterinarians were weaker than the invisible anthrax bacillus; inside Pasteur’s lab,
man becomes stronger than the bacillus, and as a corollary, the scientists in his lab gets the
edge over the local, devoted, experienced veterinarian.’ (Latour, 1983 p.147)
259
This is achieved by ‘inventing means that (a) render them mobile so that they can be brought
back (ie to the centre); (b) keep them stable so that they can be moved back and forth without
additional distortion, corruption, or decay; and (c) are combinable so that whatever stuff they
are made of, they can be cumulated, aggregated, or shuffled like a pack of cards.’ (Latour,
1987 p.233)
260
A somewhat parallel notion can be found in Foucault when he deals with spatial issues: ‘Once
knowledge can be analysed in terms of region, domain, implantation, displacement,
transposition, one is able to capture the process by which knowledge functions as a form of
power and disseminates the effects of power.’ (Foucault, 1980c p.69)
183
The specificity of science is not to be found in cognitive, social or
psychological qualities, but in the special construction of laboratories in a
manner which reverses the scale of phenomena so as to make things
readable, and then accelerates the frequency of trials, allowing many
mistakes to be made and registered. (Latour, 1983 p.165)
What makes such an otherwise ordinary technological device socially powerful is
that in order to achieve a similar degree of predictive reliability (and success) in
the application of scientific knowledge outside the microworld of the laboratory,
it is essential to first extend to the outside the highly contrived conditions
responsible for production and verification of statements which exist in the
laboratory. In other words, in order to allow the scientific ‘facts’ to circulate
beyond the laboratory it is necessary to greatly extend those ‘costly networks
inside which they can maintain their fragile efficacy’, and this ‘means
transforming society into a vast laboratory’. (Latour, 1983 p.166)
Here Latour’s argument is similar to that employed by Beck (in the latter’s
analysis of ‘risk society’) when he points out that in modern technological
societies it is science, and not ‘the classical political process’ which is the source
of power. It is the unseen, autonomous, but nonetheless ordinary, everyday
practice of science that shapes so much of politics and social change. These
laboratory forces, argues Latour, ‘can displace society and recompose it by the
very content of what is done inside them, which seemed at first irrelevant or too
technical.’ Indeed, in a rebuff to the argument put by Foucault, Latour insists that
the careful scrutiny of the natural sciences cannot be ignored for the political ‘gets
all its really efficient sources of power from the very laboratories that have just
been deemed uninteresting or too technical to be analysed.’ (Latour, 1983 p.168)
Elsewhere Latour directly addresses the very point raised by Foucault when
he sought to separate the ‘dubious’ human sciences from the ‘highly formalised’
natural sciences. It is worth quoting Latour’s comments on this at length, as they
clearly draw the connection between the highly formalised character of the socalled ‘hard’ sciences and his notion that the strength of these sciences is built up
through centres of calculation operating as a generalised apparatus of power:
When people wonder how ‘abstract’ geometry or mathematics may have
some bearing on ‘reality’, they are really admiring the strategic position
taken by those who work inside the centres on forms of forms. They
should be the weakest since they are the most remote (as it is often said)
from any ‘application’. On the contrary, they may become the strongest
by the same token as the centres end up controlling time and space: they
design networks that are tied together in a few obligatory passage points.
Once every trace has been not only written on paper, but rewritten in
geometrical form, and re-written in equation form, then it is no wonder
that those who control geometry and mathematics will be able to
184
intervene almost anywhere. The more ‘abstract’ their theory is, the better
it will be able to occupy centres inside the centres. ... The more
heterogeneous and dominating the centres, the more formalism they will
require simply to stay together and maintain their imperium. Formalism
and mathematics are attracted by the centres, if I dare make this
metaphor, like rats and insects to granaries.’ (Latour, 1987 p.245)
Thus the very formalism and abstractness that Foucault took as signalling the
detachment of the natural sciences from power relations is shown by Latour to be
precisely mechanism by which science and technology are able to profoundly
shape such power relations.
Latour and Foucault: affinities and differences
The literature on actor network theory is scattered throughout with largely
positive references to Foucault. This suggests an intellectual affinity between the
two that nonetheless remains largely in the background.261 The reason that this is
‘in the background’ is undoubtedly related to the fact that actor network theory is
concerned with the power of the natural sciences (‘technoscience’) and Foucault
was not. However, in an interview published in 1993 Latour commented on
Foucault’s work in more detail. (Crawford, 1993) Here Latour admits that he has
used and read Foucault quite ‘a lot’, in particular Discipline and Punish, which he
regards as ‘a fascinating field study on the dissemination of power.’ He singles
out Foucault’s notion of the ‘regime of statements and how they spread’,
suggesting that this approach lends itself very effectively for use as a network
argument. The importance of Discipline and Punish, according to Latour, was that
it demonstrated not simply that knowledge is necessary to the exercise of power,
but more importantly, showed for the first time that a specific apparatus of power,
a dispositif, is necessary to establish and maintain both society and knowledge.
(Crawford, 1993 p.251) Latour expresses particular interest in Foucault’s work on
the panopticon, which he sees as an example of the same general form of
‘intellectual technological dispositif’ that he has pointed to in the scientific
laboratory. In fact says Latour,
In that sense, the dissemination of laboratories, their ability to reverse
scale, to completely reverse micro and macro order, is very much a
confirmation of Foucault’s tradition. But of course, there are many more
dispositifs than the panopticon. (Crawford, 1993 p.253 - emphasis added)
Likewise, Latour’s comment on centres of calculation quoted above suggests
a parallel with Foucault’s notions of panopticism and the dispositif, although such
261
See for example the following references to Foucault: Callon (1995) p.51, 62 and (1986)
p.224; Latour (1986) p.279 and (1991) p.13; Law (1991a) p.169-170, 173, 187, (1997) p.3 and
(1994).
185
an analogy also throws differences into relief. 262 Kusch points to Foucault’s
differentiation between micro-relations of power at the level of the individual (or
small groups), and macro-level mechanisms of power as embodied in systems of
institutional coercive. (Kusch, 1991 p.143) While Foucault undoubtedly saw these
two levels of power relations as interconnected, they are nevertheless different
and distinguishable. In particular Foucault drew attention to the often unforeseen
and unintended effects of the emergence of macro-relations of power, in the
course of which ‘micro-mechanisms’ of power were ‘invested, colonised, utilised,
involuted, transformed, displaced, extended, etc by ever more general
mechanisms and by forces of global domination.’ (Foucault, 1980e p.99) 263 These
more general apparatuses of power, the dispositifs, were of course embedded in
the institutions of the prison, the clinic, the asylum etc which Foucault saw as
intimately intertwined with the rise of the theories and practices of the human
sciences. While Foucault examined the emergence of modern biology, especially
in his earlier archaeological works, his studies of dispositifs and the systems these
formed focused on institutions of social coercion - or more accurately, on
disciplinary institutions and systems of subjectification. His concern was not, as I
have said previously, with the institutions of natural science.
Kusch argues that although Foucault never gave a detailed account in his
writings, he nevertheless appeared to suggest a ‘two-fold explanation’ of the
existence of dispositifs, which relied upon both a description of ‘the structure,
profile or composition’ of institutions and an explanation of the ‘conditions of its
possibility’. (Kusch, 1991 p.145) According to Kusch, understanding the
composition involves studying how micro-relations of power are ‘colonised’ by
institutions and systems. This is a dual task involving the study of the dispositif
‘both as social laboratories, and as the results of this laboratory work.’264,
Understanding the second element, its conditions of possibility, requires in itself a
double task. The first is the identification of what Foucault (1980e p.101) called
‘the immediate social entourage’. Kusch describes this as those groups of social
actors who see the dispositif as in some way having the potential to influence the
scope or efficiency of a given network of power in their favour. (Kusch, 1991
p.147) The second task involves studying processes of subjectification, that is,
262
Latour explicitly makes this connection between panopticism and centres of calculation - see
my discussion later in this chapter and Crawford (1993).
263
See also Foucault (1980a) p.199-200.
264
Hence, Kusch interprets the dispositif as ‘spaces where experimentation with small, closed
power networks, or social ‘microworlds’ is possible, spaces where new technologies of more
efficient, more extensive, more diverse forms of control, manipulation, authority, coercion,
punishment and deterrence are developed.’ (Kusch, 1991 p.146) Kusch’s somewhat negative
interpretation would be better qualified by recognising the role of normalising and selfformative processes of subjectification that could also be a product of such a system - not to
mention the inherent propensity for such institutions to spawn resistance to their schemes.
186
how some actors are constituted as ‘inmates and victims’, while others are
constituted as functionaries and officials, or what Foucault called
‘hierarchisation’.
Foucault cast his notion of power in terms of networks and chains. (Kusch,
1991 p.138) Where he specifically addressed the nature of power, he always
insisted on it being treated as a relationship rather than an attribute. Hence, all
power relations ‘are rooted in the system of social networks’ and power is
‘coextensive with every social relationship.’ (Foucault, 1982 p.224 – emphasis
added) Similarly he argued that power ‘must be analysed as something which
circulates, or rather as something which only functions in the form of a chain ...
Power is employed and exercised through a net-like organisation.’ (Foucault,
1980e p.98 – emphasis added) 265 Indeed in many of the works of his genealogical
period 266 Foucault suggests that the individual actor or subject exists within
networks of power and that these are constitutive of the identity of the subject. 267
This reading suggests that the parallels between the approaches of Foucault
and Latour are substantial. For example, Latour’s emphasis on the importance of
problematisation and capturing others’ interests (what Callon calls interessement
268
) is reminiscent of Foucault’s admonishment that understanding how
mechanisms of power function requires historical investigation ‘beginning at the
lowest level’ to identify the actors responsible for such mechanisms and the ways
in which these became ‘economically and politically useful’ at a ‘precise
conjuncture’ in representing particular interests. (Foucault, 1980e p.101)
Foucault’s studies of the human sciences repeatedly pointed to this process of
problematisation (for example insanity, crime, sexuality) and the ways in which
265
Dean (1998b) acknowledges the substantial elements common to both Foucault’s notion of
‘regimes of practices’ or dispositifs and the actor network theory notions of socio-technical
networks and ‘technological systems’. He also argues that while Foucault shared with Callon
and Latour a ‘constructivist’ understanding of knowledge as being formed within ‘particular
regimes of truth and rationality, then within regimes of practices, and finally in relation to what
might be called “regimes of identity”, his methodology and, more importantly, his purposes,
depart dramatically’ from what Dean sees as the underlying ‘realism’ of actor network theory. I
disagree that actor network theory can be said to embrace realism, at least of a kind that could
be associated with a correspondence theory of truth. See my discussion of translation networks
earlier in this chapter.
266
Darier suggests Foucault’s work can be roughly grouped into an archaeological, genealogical
and ‘final’ periods. See Darier (1999c). McNay (1994) suggests a similar approach.
267
Following Hindess, in the previous Chapter I suggested that in his later works, Foucault
moved away from the view that the actor was largely, if not fully, defined by these relations
and adopted a view which that was perhaps closer to the view of subjectivity traditionally
advanced by critical theory.
268
Callon defines interessement as ‘the group of actions by which an entity ... attempts to impose
and stabilise the identity of the other actors it defines through its problematisation.’ See Callon
(1986) p.207.
187
expertise is instrumental in the formation of specific modes of subjectivity - a
process which thereby defines both the identity and interests of social actors. 269
Similarly, it is possible to discern a clear equivalence between Latour’s rejection
of the inside (laboratory) / outside (society) distinction and Foucault’s emphasis
on the ‘two-way borrowing’ of mechanisms of power (and knowledge) between
disciplinary institutions and the wider social environment. Kusch is surely correct
therefore in concluding that:
In Foucault, the Latourian laboratory is replaced by coercive institutions,
but otherwise the line of thinking is similar: coercive institutions are the
social laboratories for new forms of control and discipline ... and the
results of these social experiments are extended to ever new social
domains. (Kusch, 1991 p.190-91)
Actants and agency
The preceding discussion has avoided consideration of the most significant
difference between Latour and Foucault - that for actor network theory the
distinction between society and nature is blurred to the point where agency cannot
be regarded as a property exclusive to the human subject, as it remained for
Foucault. In this section I therefore turn to a closer examination of the way in
which actor network theory deals with the question of agency. This is a
particularly important issue as, on the surface at least, it is this which radically
undermines the traditional approach to political philosophy, centrally concerned
as it is with the problem of the sovereignty of the human subject. A position, as I
have argued in the preceding chapter, which was not fully relinquished by
Foucault’s attempt at ‘beheading’ the sovereign in political philosophy.
The consequence of the actor network theory claim that a clear ontological
distinction between nature and society cannot be sustained is something that will
be considered further in the Conclusion. Here I examine some specific criticisms
levelled at Foucault by Latour, before turning to consider the way in which Latour
problematises agency. This is useful both because it highlights my contention that
Latour’s approach is in fact not inconsistent with the general intellectual
orientation of Foucault’s work on genealogy and governmentality, and because it
provides some valuable insights into how a biopolitics of the environment 270
might be understood and studied further.
In the interview cited earlier in this chapter in which Latour commented on
the influence of Foucault's work on his own, he also outlines some substantial
269
There is also evident a strong emphasis on this in post-Foucault governmentality studies - see
in particular the importance placed on this by Rose and Miller (1992).
270
Earlier I referred to this in terms of ‘ecological governmentality’. See also Rutherford (1999b)
188
criticisms of Foucault. In doing so he places Foucault within the epistemological
tradition of Canguilhem and Bachelard, ‘a tradition that shows how science
should escape by a succession of breaks from its past and its social condition.’
(Crawford, 1993 p.251) 271 This characterisation is consistent with the argument
Foucault used to explain the distinction between social science and the science of
nature and how the latter was able to separate itself from the disciplinary
technique of the human sciences, especially the examination. 272
Latour sees Foucault as part of a ‘peculiarly French’ tradition in the history of
science, which permits the natural sciences (‘the hard sciences’) to escape serious
criticism.273 Indeed, from a critical perspective, the natural sciences are
‘unstudiable from first principles’ in France because of this, and this is reflected
in the position taken by intellectuals such as Lyotard, Baudrillard etc, whom
Latour regards as ‘completely scientistic as far as science is concerned’. Hence
Latour cautions that it is necessary to bear in mind the extent to which the natural
sciences escape serious criticisms in ‘the French tradition’, a tradition of which
‘Foucault is very much part’. (Crawford, 1993 p.251-2) It is against this
background that Latour criticises Foucault’s work for being unbalanced
(‘asymmetrical’), in that it largely ignored these very sciences. By doing so
Foucault ‘shunned the hard cases’ and as a result says Latour, it is difficult to
fully evaluate the usefulness of his approach for analysing the natural sciences.
While Foucault redefined the relationship between knowledge and power in the
social sciences, he did not do the necessary work in relation to the ‘hard sciences’.
Latour questions whether Foucault’s vocabulary and concepts could usefully be
transferred to such an analysis, arguing that the real test of the Foucauldian
redefinition of power would be to see whether or not it could be extended to those
sciences concerned with non-human entities. He concludes, while acknowledging
the influence of Foucault’s work on his own, 274 with the ‘suspicion’ that
271
For a detailed study of Foucault’s relationship to French history of science, and especially
Canguilhem and Bachelard, see Gutting (1989).
272
This is discussed in an earlier chapter. Interestingly, Foucault did concede that the ‘forms of
inquiry and examination’ could interact ‘and as a consequence the sciences of nature and man
also overlapped in terms of their concepts, methods and results. I think that one could find in
geography a good example of a discipline which systematically uses measure, inquiry and
examination.’ (Foucault, 1980c p.74-5). This suggestion that geography involves an
‘intersection’ of the human and natural science is particularly interesting given the important
contribution of geography in the nineteenth century to the development of a specifically
environmental discourse. It is perhaps not accidental that contemporary universities still
frequently locate environmental studies within their geography programs.
273
This is hardly a peculiarly French phenomenon, although it is perhaps stronger in French
intellectual culture than some others.
274
Latour says ‘I have used Foucault and read him a lot, so he might be absorbed in my thinking
probably much more than I recognise.’ Crawford (1993) p.252.
189
‘Foucault retained the typically French attitude - a complete belief in the solidity
of the hard sciences.’ (Crawford, 1993 p.252)
Latour’s criticism of Foucault’s ‘asymmetry’ towards the natural sciences
should not be understood simply as the complaint that he paid too little attention
to the natural sciences. Rather it reflects a methodological concern central to actor
network theory and its particular reinterpretation of agency. Both Callon (1986)
and Latour (1994) propose the adoption of what they describe as a ‘generalised
principle of symmetry’. This is an extension of the principle of symmetry put
forward by David Bloor for the ‘strong program’ in the sociology of science.
Bloor argues that both truth and falsity, and rational and irrational behaviour,
should be analysed in the same terms rather than segregating these into two
incompatible spheres. In his studies of the human sciences Foucault clearly
adopted a position that consistent with this methodological principle. However
Latour and Callon extend this principle further to encompass the study of human
and non-human behaviour - that is, in studying both ‘nature’ and ‘society’ they
insist we should not switch analytical frameworks when moving from the social to
the technical aspects of a problem. Latour sees this as not only consistent with,
but as a logical development of, Bloor’s approach. The difference is that instead
of explaining society and nature in social terms as does Bloor, Latour argues that
both sorts of phenomena should be analysed in terms that are neither social nor
technical but rather socio-technical or collective. (Crawford, 1993 p.255-6;
Latour, 1993 p.4-5) By collective Latour means the tangling together or
‘hybridisation’ of society and the ‘objective world (things-in-themselves)’.
(Latour, 1994 p.793) Such an approach, Latour readily admits, blurs the
boundaries between subject and object, and as a result is frequently accused of
either anthropomorphism (Schaffer, 1991) or the mechanisation of subjectivity.
(Collins and Yearley, 1992)
For actor network theory, an agent or actant is a semiotic definition. An
actant is something that acts, without any necessary implication of its being
human; it can, says Latour ‘literally be anything’ provided it is the source of an
action. (Latour, 1997) 275 Hence, within actor network theory the notion of agency
does not provide, nor is it intended to provide, a model of human subjectivity or
275
Elsewhere Latour and Callon comment on their notion of an actor in the following terms: ‘To
replace the usual divisions (micro/macro, human/animal, social/technical), which we have
shown to be unprofitable, we need terms in keeping with (our new) methodological principles.
What is an ‘actor’? Any element which bends space around itself, makes other elements
dependent upon itself and translates their will into a language of its own. An actor makes
changes in the set of elements and concepts habitually used to describe the social and natural
worlds ... [A]n actor can make ... asymmetries last, can lay down a temporality and a space that
is imposed on others ...Weak, reversible interactions are replaced by strong interactions. ...
Instead of swarms of possibilities, we find lines of force, obligatory passage points, directions
and deductions.’ (Callon and Latour, 1981 p.286)
190
even a catalogue of basic human competences. Indeed, the most fundamental
argument of actor network theory is that every entity, whether the self, society or
nature is the product of semiotic work - each involves the building of the actant
through ‘attributing, imputing (and) distributing action, competences,
performances and relations’. The claim that actors are ‘infinitely pliable’ and
heterogeneous is not meant to describe any ‘real observed actor’, but is the
semiotically ‘necessary condition for the observation and recording of actors to be
possible.’ (Latour, 1997 p.6) This semiotic work is performed through the
heterogeneous processes of translation and problematisation within networks, and
importantly this leads to what Latour describes as an ontological claim about the
network-like character of the actants themselves. Actor network theory therefore
shares with Foucault the view that the actor is defined by relations of power and
the accompanying capacity for action within those relationships. However, actor
network theory carries the assumptions about the types of historical and discursive
(semiotic) work needed to build an entity beyond those bearing on human
subjectivity, and extends this methodological approach to all actants.276
One key consequence of this application of Latour and Callon’s generalised
principle of symmetry is that the opposition between society and nature, and the
distinction of passive ‘things’ from active human ‘subjects’ is of very limited
heuristic value. Rather than separate branches of an unbridgeable dichotomy,
these previously ‘fundamental’ categories are best seen as the reified extremes of
a continuum established by translation networks. As Callon suggests, if there is
still a need to speak of nature and society, it is preferable to see this in terms of a
‘socio-nature’ woven by translation networks, as an ‘in-between that is inhabited
by actants whose competences and identities vary along within the translations
transforming them.’ To be sure, both ‘passive beings and genuine actors’ populate
socio-nature, but an ontologically unambiguous ‘dividing line’ cannot be laid
down. (Callon, 1995 p.58)
Against the background of the preceding discussion, the actor network theory
approach to agency can be summarised. Following John Law (1991a p.173, 187),
an agent can be defined as a structured set of relations stable enough to generate
a durable series of power effects. This definition encompasses Foucault’s
characterisation of power as action on the actions of others (ie active human
subjects), however, it also covers the broader range of network building and
translation activities discussed by Latour and Callon. It therefore should be taken
as including what Foucault referred to as relationships of communication and
objective or technical capacities. This is consistent with Foucault’s approach
276
This sort of approach is implicit to the argument I have put forward regarding the extension of
Foucault’s concept of biopolitics to environmental issues. See Chapters 6 and 7 of this thesis.
See also Rutherford (1999b) and Tully (1997).
191
when he suggested that blocks of ‘capacity-communication-power’ could come to
‘constitute regulated and concerted systems’. (Foucault, 1982 p.218)
Further, agents are at the same time both sets of relations and ‘nodes in sets
of relations’. This recalls something very much like Deleuze’s notion of
assemblage (‘agencement’) which combines the idea of arrangement or
organisation with the suggestion of agency. Hence, an assemblage is neither a
unity nor a totality, but a multiplicity, in which what is crucial is not the
constituent elements but the relations between the elements. (Cooper, 1997 p.3-4)
In Latour’s words, ‘a network is not a thing but the recorded movement of a
thing’. The network cannot exist independently of the act of constituting it
(‘tracing’) - the ‘nodes’ are actors whose definition of the world simultaneously
delineates the network, while they themselves are shaped by the networks of
relations within which they exist. (Latour, 1997 p.9)
In addition, entities other than people may be agents. This runs counter to the
general direction of Foucault’s work, for while arguably he accepted that social
groups and even institutions could exhibit agency, he would not extend this to
non-social entities. Non-human entities may be drawn upon as technical capacities
to support power relations in the formation of disciplinary blocks, but power
relations proper for him were inseparable from the ‘person who acts’. Hence for
Foucault agency is strictly anthropocentric - agency (‘the exercise of power’) is
‘always a way of acting upon an acting subject or acting subjects by virtue of their
acting or being capable of action.’ (Foucault, 1982 p.220)
Finally, the relations which constitute agents are rarely, if ever, purely social
relations. Rather, as Law puts it:
they are heterogeneous, partly social, partly technical, partly textual, and
partly to do with naturally occurring events, objects and processes - and
most usually combine elements of all of these; this, of course, means that
actors are similarly heterogeneous; and it means that there is almost never
any such thing as a purely social actor. (Law, 1991a p.173)
Such an approach differs from that of Foucault. As noted above, he distinguishes
power relations from those of communication and technical capacities. Yet he also
notes that these three types of relationship ‘in fact always overlap’ and support
each other in a reciprocal manner. (Foucault, 1982 p.218 - emphasis added) 277
Again, while this is perhaps a question of emphasis, the overall conclusion is
inescapable that for Foucault power relations and agents are exclusively social.
The consequences of actor network theory’s redefinition of agency are potentially
significant, although not fundamentally at odds with the general concerns that
277
See also Foucault (1984b) p.48.
192
underlay Foucault’s work on genealogy and governmentality, as suggested at the
start of the current chapter. The issue here is whether or not there is a strong basis
for maintaining different models of representation for human and non-human
entities?
Representation and the modern constitution
In Chapter 7 I discussed what Hindess (1996) referred to as Foucault’s
incomplete critique of sovereignty. I also noted his comment that aside from
sovereignty, the other constitutive fiction of modern political thought is that of
political community. In the concluding section of is chapter I wish to explore how
actor network theory may contribute to a consideration of these issues within the
general philosophical perspective developed by Foucault.
Consistent with his argument regarding the collective or hybrid nature of
‘socio-nature’, Latour provides a critique of the modern notions of representation.
He defines ‘modern’ to be ‘when the political constitution of truth creates … two
separate parliaments’ – or modes of representation – ‘one hidden for things, the
other in the open for citizens.’ (Latour, 1991 p.15; 1993 p.10-11) His discussion
of this draws on the work of Shapin and Schaffer (1985) which examines the
debate between the founder of the Royal Society, physicist Robert Boyle, and
political theorist Thomas Hobbes, on the relationship between politics and
science. Shapin and Schaffer detail the ways in which during the eighteenth
century these key progenitors of modern science and politics struggled to establish
the now familiar demarcation between the politics and science. Shapin and
Schaffer’s historical research showed how the ‘experimental community’
established by Boyle energetically elaborated and deployed a set of ‘boundaryconventions’, which defined the inside/outside of science and were able to
‘transport politics outside of science’. (Shapin and Schaffer, 1985 p.342) In this
regard, their work can be regarded as falling within the mainstream of the
Edinburgh School of science studies with its focus on explaining science in its
social context.
Latour’s interpretation and use of this work goes beyond that intended by the
authors and they certainly do not share Latour’s conclusions. Nevertheless, Latour
argues that if the logic of Shapin and Schaffer’s detailed historical work is
pursued, 278 the debate in question can be seen to be about far more than Hobbes
278
That is, if Shapin and Schaffer did not apply an ‘asymmetrical’ approach to their study by
privileging the ‘social’ context. They take great care says Latour, to understand scientific facts
as a historical and political invention, but ‘they take no such precautions where political
language itself is concerned. They use the words ‘power’, ‘interest’, and ‘politics’ in all
innocence. … criticising science but swallowing politics as the only valid source of
explanation’ … (as does Hobbes) … with his construction of a monist macro-structure in
which knowledge has a place only in support of the social order.’ (Latour, 1993 p.15-27)
193
and Boyle defining separate discourses about the proper conduct of science and
politics. In fact, between them Hobbes and Boyle played a central role in the
‘invention’ of the modern world - a world ‘in which the representation of things
through the intermediary of the laboratory is forever dissociated from the
representation of citizens through the intermediary of the social contract.’
(Latour, 1993 p.27) Both of these modes of representation - the state
(Commonwealth) and the laboratory experiment - can clearly be demonstrated to
be inventions, ‘artificial constructs’. Indeed argues Latour, Boyle and Hobbes
were the eighteenth century drafters of the ‘modern constitution’; they invented
and articulated the modern dichotomy between the political representation of
sovereign subjects and the scientific representation of non-human objects.
(Latour, 1991 p.13)
This dichotomy only appears tenable if the two sides are thought of as strictly
separate. Political representation for Hobbes was the product of sovereign,
rational citizens with interests whose common consent constitutes the Leviathan.
This is an inherently paradoxical entity, for it is at one and the same time a
creature composed of the wills of the individual citizens and the sovereign who
personifies the common will. Yet despite this, the political state is nothing other
than relations between sovereign human subjects, that is, social relations and
these alone. Parallel to this political representation, Boyle defines the
representation of nature through the equally artificial apparatus of the laboratory
and scientific method. In the laboratory, through the application of machines and
instruments, facts are extracted from nature, but to ensure the recognition of facts
(as distinct from mere impressions), Boyle’s science set strict limits on who was
to be authorised to interpret the meaning of data obtained through experiment.
Boyle establishes, through the Royal Society, the community of scientists,
disinterested witnesses who meticulously represent the facts, that is, he invents
the modern notion of the expert. But asks Latour, who is speaking when the
scientist speaks? In itself nature is mute. Notwithstanding, Boyle and those who
follow him claim that the facts speak for themselves, because through the
discipline of the scientific method, nature can be seen to behave meaningfully
(although not intentionally). Thus nature, which would otherwise remain mute, is
‘capable of speaking, writing, signifying’ within the artificial realm of the
laboratory and through the scientific community who translate the behaviour of
objects. (Latour, 1993 p.29)
Latour describes these boundary-defining activities in terms borrowed
directly from Foucault. What Hobbes and Boyle (and their intellectual successors)
were engaged in was the drafting of ‘a political constitution of truth’, or what
Foucault called the political economy of truth. (Latour, 1993 p.29) Through the
work of Shapin and Schaffer it can be seen that the debate between Hobbes and
Boyle was not simply two competing views of representation, in which Hobbes
194
was the social theorist and Boyle the theorist of nature.279 Rather argues Latour, as
Shapin and Schaffer’s historical study demonstrates, both Hobbes and Boyle were
rationalists and mechanists resolutely opposed to the ‘pre-scientific past’. Both
advanced theories of science and politics in their struggle with the other, yet as
Latour comments
Hobbes is a scientist whose science has been completely eliminated from
later accounts. He is taken seriously only as a political philosopher, while
Boyle had a political philosophy, which has been completely eliminated
from later accounts. He is taken seriously only as a physicist. (Latour,
1991 p.12)
As with the construction of any ‘regime of truth’, the detail of why and how
particular outcomes occur are very much matters for historical or genealogical
investigation. The point is however that the two modes of representation, which
together are at the centre of modern thinking, are both historical constructs, not
necessary or transcendental truths. They are the product of a particular history
(albeit forgotten or subjugated) and like all such historical products subject to the
possibility of further change. Indeed, once the historicity of not only political
representation, but also the scientific representation of nature is recognised, both
must be seen as subject to the central critical question posed by Foucault: in that
which appears universal and necessary, what in fact is the product of arbitrary or
at least historically contingent constraints? (Foucault, 1984b p.45)
Latour's criticism of political philosophy and its attitude to representation then
is similar to Foucault’s critique of political sovereignty. However, his focus goes
beyond political representation to the attitude of ‘well-meaning social theorists’
who accept the asymmetrical view that the representation of nature is largely nonpolitical and unproblematic. 280 However Latour's criticisms extend further, for in
accepting this dichotomous model of representation, political and social theory
ignores not only the ‘family resemblance’ and interconnection between the natural
and social sciences, they also perpetuate the false separation between ‘society’
and ‘nature’. By maintaining such modernist divisions political philosophy denies
the collective, hybrid character of entities, and remains incapable of
understanding that all human interaction is socio-technical, and indeed that ‘the
very shape of humans, our very body, is already made in large part of sociotechnical negotiations and artefacts.’ (Latour, 1994 p.806) Social theory and
political philosophy therefore remain bound to a mode of thought that is incapable
279
Latour claims that the great contribution of Shapin and Schaffer’s work was that it ‘unearthed’
Hobbes’ scientific works so neglected by political science and rescued ‘from oblivion’ Boyle’s
political theories which had been equally neglected in the history of science. Latour (1993)
p.16-17.
280
That is, ‘They accept as a given the result of a political constitution of truth that has first
dispatched speech, deafness, and dumbness.’ (Latour, 1991 p.14)
195
(and increasingly more so) of understanding and explaining the mechanisms of
societal production and action within the very ‘society’ for which it purports to
provide a social science.
In fact, Latour argues the modernity that is supposedly built on the division of
representation, the achievement of which more than any other marks the modern
from the pre-modern, does not now and never has really existed. This is not to
deny the obvious power and achievements of what we call modern politics,
science and technology, but rather to challenge the assumption that a radical
separation of society and nature has ever been effected. In reality suggests Latour,
the power and achievements of ‘modern’ society have been possible precisely
because it has increasingly afforded more efficient means and opportunities for
the production of socio-technical hybrids and collectives. At the same time,
Latour’s analysis shows why the problems that arise from this blindness to the
realities of socio-nature are, paradoxically, both the most intractable for, and at
the same time the clearest illustration of the failure of, the modern mode of
representation. He points to global environmental problems such as the
greenhouse effect, stratospheric ozone depletion, radiation exposure, etc. Here
perhaps more than any other area the tangling together of the scientific, the
political and the technological-economic illustrates the pervasiveness of sociotechnical crossovers involving the exchange of properties between social and nonsocial entities. (Latour, 1991 p.4, 16-18; 1994 p.795-97)
The term ‘modern’ as used by Latour thus refers to two quite different sets of
practices, which the modern attitude seeks to separate, but which in contemporary
society are increasingly blended together. The first of these are the practices of
translation discussed earlier in this chapter, which constantly give rise to sociotechnical networks and hybrids. The second Latour designates as practices of
‘purification’, aimed at the creation of the ‘distinct ontological zones’ of the
human and non-human. This second set of practices corresponds to the modern
critical stance. Latour uses an environmental example to suggest how the
practices of translation would ‘link in one continuous chain the chemistry of the
upper atmosphere, scientific and industrial strategies, the preoccupations of heads
of state, the anxieties of ecologists’. The practices of purification, on the other
hand, establish the separation between an objective nature, and the historicity of
society, replete with ‘predictable’ human interests. (Latour, 1993 p.12) What
characterises modern thought is the separation of these two sets of practices; once
we become aware that both sets of practices have historically proceeded side by
side, we can start to abandon the modern attitude, or at least question it. It is clear
that modernity is framed in terms of humanism – either through the attempt to
define the unique characteristics of the human subject or by declaring the death of
the subject. As we have seen Foucault, at least to a degree, tends to fall on the
latter side of this ‘divide’. However, as I have argued, Foucault’s work also
196
retains elements of the belief that at its core, subjectivity must be defined in terms
that are bound up with notions of the sovereignty of the human agent.
The work of both Latour and Rouse point to this incomplete critique of
sovereignty as being closely connected to a failure to break with a belief in the
epistemic ‘solidity’ of the knowledge produced by the natural sciences. Latour
and actor network theory’s critique of agency, by undermining the ‘double
separation’ that modernist thought has constructed,281 calls into question what
Barry Hindess describes as the other modern ‘constitutive fiction’ – political
community. Actor network theory’s recasting of agency in terms of ‘collectives’
and socio-technical hybrids challenges this pillar of the modern political thought.
For no matter how the critique of the subject proceeds, as long as it continues to
locate the historical formation of the subject in social processes, it reinforces the
modern critical stance. In this perspective agency is always and necessarily a
property attributable to human beings. Inasmuch as such human subjects are
understood as exercising agency within some form of sociality, the twin concepts
of political sovereignty and political community are also necessarily defined in
terms of the capacity for human agency and autonomy. The approach of actor
network theory, and Latour in particular, thus immediately complicates any
analysis of agency and hence relations of power between agents.
Latour's criticism of modernism, of the project of purification, urges us to
recognise that we have never been modern because the separateness upon which
this is premised cannot be achieved. His approach calls not for an anti-modern or
even post-modern attitude, but rather what he describes as a ‘non-modern’ one.
(Latour, 1991 p.17) Such a non-modern attitude recognises that ‘there are not two
problems of representation, just one.’ (Latour, 1993 p.143) It takes seriously the
double ambiguity of modernity towards representation, where there is a constant
suspicion that political representation (and hence sovereignty) can be corrupted
and turned into domination on behalf of particular interests, and similarly that the
scientific representation of nature can be corrupted by the interests of those
claiming to speak on behalf of the facts. Such fears are themselves premised on
the belief in the possibility of purification, of separating two modes of
representation.
Latour claims that actor network theory is not a revolutionary call for change,
but rather it simply requires that we ‘publicly’ ratify what we have always done,
given that power (ie politics and science) have always involved the shaping and
mobilisation of socio-natures. Thus, the pretence of double representation must be
281
‘The double separation is what we have to reconstruct: the separation between humans and
nonhumans on the one hand, and between what happens ‘above’ and what happens ‘below’ on
the other.’ (Latour, 1993 p.13)
197
replaced by the explicit admission that there is in fact a single ‘parliament of
things’ within which
the continuity of the collective is reconfigured. There are no more naked
truths, but there are no more naked citizens, either. … Let one of the
representatives talk, for instance, about the ozone hole, another represent
the Monsanto chemical industry, a third the workers of the same chemical
industry, another the voters of New Hampshire, a fifth the meteorology of
the polar regions; let still another speak in the name of the State; what
does it matter, so long as they are all talking about the same thing, about a
quasi-object they have all created, the object-discourse-nature-society
whose new properties astound us all and whose network extends from my
refrigerator to the Antarctic by way of chemistry, law, the State, the
economy, and satellites. The imbroglios and networks that had no place
[in modernist representations] now have the whole place to themselves.
They are the ones that have to be represented; it is around them that the
parliament of Things gathers henceforth. (Latour, 1993 p.144)
Such an approach radically challenges modern notions of the limits of
political community, despite Latour's claim that it amounts to little more than
openly acknowledging that modernity already constantly (if ‘unofficially’)
produces a proliferation of socio-technical hybrids and quasi-objects.282 Latour
suggests that we can see the beginning of a public acknowledgment of this monist
notion of representation in events such as the 1992 UN-sponsored Earth Summit,
in which humans and non-humans are brought together ‘under the same
continuous protection.’ (Latour, 1991 p.18)
Conclusion
Despite Latour's tendency at times to sound like a radical environmentalist
moralistically affirming the right of nature, actor network theory does offer
theoretical insights that complement the work of Foucault and his successors on
biopolitics and governmentality. Indeed, as I have suggested, 283 Foucault’s
analysis of biopolitics provides a potentially useful approach to understanding
environmental discourse and problematisations. In particular, Latour's work
explains why the problem of nature should not be understood in terms of the
modernist opposition between different modes of representation. Of the social
theorists discussed in this thesis, the work of Habermas reflects the pursuit of
what Latour calls ‘the project of purification’ at its most sophisticated. However
282
There is a clear parallel here with Beck’s argument regarding the ‘sub-politics’ of science and
technology in risk society. See Beck (1992b). I discuss Beck in Chapter 4 of the current thesis,
and return to this issue in the Conclusion (Chapter 9).
283
See Rutherford (1999b; 1999a; 1997a)
198
as I have argued, the modern critical perspective, which is premised on this
philosophical separation of the representation of the human subject from the
representation of nature, is continued in the work of Foucault and most scholars
influenced by his approach.
One need not accept that there is an ‘absolute equivalence’ between the
regulatory practices which operate on human and non-human entities to
appreciate the significant capacity of actor network theory to provide both a more
genealogical understanding of environmental problems and a critical
appropriation of Foucault's work for this task. 284 Indeed, one of the strengths of
Latour’s work is that it allows us to frame the problem of nature in a way that is
open to the sort of detailed study of governmental practices which have been
characteristic of works on governmentality in other areas. The approach drawn
here from the work of Foucault and Latour enables environmental problems to be
studied as ‘organised forms of practice’ that bring together the four dimensions of
government referred to in the introduction to this thesis.
Through its critique of the asymmetrical approach of both political
philosophy and science studies to agency and its epistemic representation, actor
network theory permits the ‘Foucauldian’ study of the complex matrix of
government. It does this in a way that more fully takes account of what Tully
describes as the third dimension of government, that is ‘the practical rationalities
in accordance with which human aptitudes are exercised on nature through
various (material) technologies.’ (Tully, 1997 p.6) 285 By being alert to the hybrid
character of agency, such an analysis is able to recognise the importance of
material technologies and the capacities of non-human entities and processes to
the existence of structured relations that are stable enough to generate a durable
series of power effects. The role of science and technology in shaping power
relations must be seen as central to understanding the ecological dimension of
biopolitics, rather than as ancillary and external to the actions of agents as human
subjects. The perspective suggested here rejects both sociological and
technological determinism in favour of a genealogical approach that takes
seriously the claim that the relations which constitute both agents and the
governmental rationalities, and which shape their conduct, are almost never either
purely ‘social’ or wholly ‘technical’ or ‘natural’. The implications of such an
approach for social and political theory are significant, and are considered further
in the Conclusion.
284
In his comments (personal communication) to me on a previously published article
(Rutherford, 1994a) that discussed Foucault’s approach to the natural sciences, Rose indicated
his reluctance to follow Callon and Latour to the extent of asserting an ‘absolute equivalence’
between regulatory practices operating on non-human and human entities.
285
And it should be added, the ways in which various material technologies shape human
aptitudes.
199
200
Chapter 9
Conclusion: ecological modernisation or
governmentality ?
Introduction
Two substantially different ways of approaching the problem of nature
emerge from the examination of social theory in this thesis, although there is also
a common emphasis in each on the importance of processes of rationalisation. A
major difference is evident in the way in which Foucault and those influenced by
his perspective (I include Latour and actor network theory here) are inclined to
see ‘rationalisation’ much more in terms of a diverse multiplicity of rationalities
and governmental technologies. Those influenced by the critical theory tradition
on the other hand see rationalisation in more generalised social systemic terms
and linked to a view of global processes of modernisation. The latter approach
tends to see modernisation as progressing towards some emancipatory form of an
idealised democracy, whereas the former is more inclined to an analysis of the
ways in which relations of power are shaped by political rationalities which have
local, and quite specific concerns.
This difference can be expressed another way by saying that the problem of
nature can be analysed within two distinct conceptual frameworks. The first is that
of ecological modernisation, 286 an approach that is seen most clearly in the work
286
I have argued elsewhere that the notion ecological modernisation is a potentially fruitful way of
connecting the macro-sociological perspectives developed by theorists such as Beck and Eder,
with the recent institutionalisation of specific regulatory practices and policies. See Rutherford
(1999a). However, it is necessary to make a distinction between ecological modernisation as a
governmental rationality and the term as used here. Here I am referring to ecological
modernisation as a social theoretical approach that specifically places the problem of nature at
the centre of contemporary processes of modernisation in advanced industrial society. The use I
have made elsewhere of the term ecological modernisation reflects what is in effect a technical
or governmental program in the sense discussed by Miller and Rose (1992). In that context I
use ecological modernisation to describe specific changes which have occurred in the
formulation and implementation of enviornmental policies in the 1980s in Western Europe.
These changes were a response by environmental agencies to perceptions about the limits of
state regulation in achieving improved environmental management. As such this governmental
program involved a whole range of policy approaches and instruments aimed at the integration
of ‘clean production’ into economic activities. The institutional transformations that arose from
this program resulted in significant changes to investment patterns and production techniques
201
of Eder and Beck and which draws on a critical theoretical tradition going back to
Weber. The second is that of ecological governmentality, an approach which I
have argued can be drawn from Foucault’s work on biopolitics and subsequent
works on governmentality, and which is capable of being significantly enriched
by the insights of actor network theory.
In this chapter, I summarise the key themes and arguments considered in the
thesis. I conclude that by bringing together the work of governmentality studies
and actor network theory in a way that extends Foucault’s genealogies of power to
the natural sciences and associated material technologies, a significant advance
over the ways either of these bodies of work are currently employed is possible.
Based on this approach, I suggest some directions for future research.
Reflecting these two tasks, this chapter is divided into two main parts. The
first reviews the key themes and arguments presented in the earlier chapters of the
thesis. The second discusses some of the theoretical implications to emerge for
social theory and political philosophy from my discussion of the problem of
nature and its relationship to the notions of agency and power. My conclusions are
couched in terms of their relevance to the analysis of contemporary ecological
problems, but are likely to have a wider applicability to all those areas where
science and material technologies play a significant role in the way in which
social behaviour is configured.
Key themes
(1) The problem of nature for critical theory
Chapter 2 of this thesis considered how the early Frankfurt School identified
what I described as the ‘negative dialectic of progress’, which pointed to
contradictory elements inherent in the growth of reason. Horkheimer and
Adorno’s critique of the dialectic of enlightenment drew an indivisible link
between the domination of the outer natural world by science and technology, and
the repression of inner human nature by social institutions and practices. The
defining characteristics of modern society were thus cast in terms of the radical
separation between subjectivity and nature. This is a theme central to later
ecological critique of modern industrial society both in Green theory and, as
emphasised in my discussion in Chapter 4, in the recent work of Eder and Beck.
This early critical theory posited a dialectical relationship of the subject to
nature, while also rejecting the identity of inner and outer nature. The notion of
historicised nature played a central role in the critique of the present, with the
(particularly in the manufacturing and energy sectors) and in the relationship between the state,
industrial interests and environmental groups. See Weale (1992); Christoff (1996)
202
concepts of history and nature functioning as cognitive tools for such critique each being employed to destabilise the ontological primacy of the other. As
indicated by Habermas, the problem for Horkheimer and Adorno was how the
notion of emancipatory reason could resist the generalised critique of modernity,
given that the totalising force of reason they saw as inherent to conceptual
thinking and language per se, and as such inseparable from the domination of the
natural and human worlds. The solution to this problem for the early Frankfurt
School, not unlike that of the romantic radicalism of some environmentalist
movements, was to seek a refuge for emancipatory reason in an aesthetic notion of
reconciliation of the two natures.
Habermas rejected Horkheimer and Adorno’s rendition of the dialectic of
enlightenment and the notion of reconciliation with nature. Despite this, as I have
demonstrated in Chapter 3 the problem of nature continues to play a pivotal,
although somewhat subterranean role in Habermas’ attempt to reconstruct social
theory. The core aim of this reconstruction of social theory was to ‘rescue’ a
rational grounding for universal standards of validity and truth, and to avoid their
conflation with power in Nietzschean-inspired perspectivalism. As I have argued,
while Habermas’ theoretical approach changed over time, he nevertheless
maintained that it was necessary to distinguish between the logic of instrumental
action as applied to our relations with nature, and that of communicative action
involved in relations between human agents. Based on this ‘differentiation of
reason’, Habermas argued contrary to Horkheimer and Adorno, that in itself
science was not part of the ‘dark-side’ of modernity but one of its greatest
achievements. For him the problem of the social relation to nature (and the
environmental problems arising from this) are not caused by the functioning of
science as a technological force. To the extent that there is an ‘ecological crisis’,
and Habermas is ambiguous on this, it is caused by the failure of the social system
to restrict technical reason to its proper domain (science and relations with nature)
and prevent its intrusion into the domain of politics (ie moral-practical reason).
It is therefore clear from my discussion of Habermas’ approach to the
problem of nature (Chapter 3) that while he argues all knowledge is historically
situated, he also retains a conception of science as producing an ‘objective’
knowledge of the natural world. 287 His criticisms of scientism are directed at
attempts to use the model of natural science as an ideological tool of positivist
social sciences to justify social domination. This stance is reflected in his
rejection of the Frankfurt School’s critique of instrumental reason, which he
287
Of course as I have noted, for Habermas the objectivity of science is not absolute. Interests
condition it, but these are primarily the interest in survival of the human species, that is, of the
‘quasi-transcendental subject’. While this does allow objectivity to be understood as having an
historical genesis, he still nevertheless interprets it as a more or less unitary evolution of the
human capacity.
203
similarly sees as undermining the possibility of both ‘objective’ knowledge and
social emancipation. By stressing the differentiation of reason Habermas seeks to
emphasise the pragmatic utility of the natural sciences on the one hand, while
wanting to quarantine politics and ethics from the objectifying logic of those
sciences. In this context, I have argued that Habermas’ shift to the theory of
communicative action meant that his approach became even more
anthropocentric. For Habermas, communicative reason is the defining
characteristic of human nature precisely because it is intrinsic to the evolution of
the species as language user.
Despite the shift from cognitive interests to communicative action, Habermas’
argument was not substantially different from that he had previously advanced
against the early Frankfurt School and his more recent critics who suggested that
his theory was too anthropocentric and hence incapable of usefully responding to
contemporary environmental issues. Whereas the Frankfurt School saw modern
science and technology as central to the domination and suppression of both ‘first’
and ‘second’ nature, in the hands of Habermas this is transformed into the
relatively unproblematic issues of ‘system maintenance’ and the aesthetic
‘grammar of life’. Chapter 3 therefore concluded that in the end Habermas’
characterisation of modern science and technology tends to seriously gloss over
the impact these have on the natural environment, and as a consequence, ignores
the significance of ecological problems, which are marginalised both for politics
and for social theory.
(2) The centrality of ecological problems in Eder and Beck
As I discussed in Chapter 4, both Eder and Beck recognise a ‘dark’ side to
modernisation and in particular the role of scientific knowledge and technology in
producing the self-destructive, negative side effects of progress. Unlike
Habermas, they see the problem of nature as absolutely central to contemporary
social relations and the discourse on modernisation. Both view the social relation
to nature as far more problematic than does Habermas, identifying ecological
problems as the basis for new social divisions and conflicts.
Each of these two authors argue that social theory must shift its focus from
traditional concerns – the political and economic reproduction of society – to
include the problems of ecological reproduction (Eder) or the distribution of
ecological risk (Beck), which amounts to much the same thing. Key to both Eder
and Beck is their understanding of an ecological modernisation that is constitutive
of a new type of society, based on forms of social conflict which differ
substantially from those which dominated social development in earlier phases of
modernity. These new fields of ecological conflict increasingly shape the
development of society. For Eder this is centred on competition between different
cultural models of the social relation to nature, while for Beck it reflects the
204
emergence of a sub-politics produced by the systemic shift from problems of
wealth distribution to those of the distribution of technically induced ecological
risks.
I have argued that the work of Eder and Beck provides a more satisfactory
social theoretical approach to the problem of nature than does that of Habermas.
Perhaps most importantly the work of Eder and Beck allows us to link social
systemic processes with political struggles (particularly environmental ones) that
have little place in Habermas’ analysis. In particular both theorists provide ways
of understanding the roles played by ecological movements, citizens groups and
scientific expertise in the emergence of these new fields of ecological conflict.
This is one area where the generality and theoretical abstractness of both
Habermas and the Frankfurt School is particularly unhelpful.
Eder’s work is particularly useful because it provides a subtle and nuanced
reading of the role of ecological movements in contemporary environmental
discourse and governmental practices, demonstrating that these movements have a
deep rooted cultural history embodying both the utilitarian and purity cultural
models of the social relation to nature. (see Chapter 4) These movements are often
taken as reflecting an anti-modernism, which Habermas identifies with the
counter-cultural perspective of the radical new social movements. However, this
purity model is never very far from, and constantly interacts with, the
utilitarianism and rationalism of modern scientific ecology, as Eder and historians
such as Worster (1987a; 1993b) and Grove (1995) have shown. 288 Ecological
conflicts, as both Eder and Beck suggest, take on the form of doctrinal or cultural
struggles over the appropriate path to modernity, rather than being ‘antimodernist’ as such. They reflect, that is, discourses centred on different
rationalities for governing the social relation to nature.
Similarly, a particular strength of Beck’s work is that it points to the way in
which both the production and definition of technological risks, and the
mobilisation of ecological movements and ‘counter expertise’, takes place outside
the formal political framework. Modern ecological hazards and risks arise as the
result of private economic decisions regarding the use of science and technology
288
Grove’s detailed historical study of the roots of modern global environmental consciousness
warrants closer attention than it has received in this thesis. He traces the interaction between
the emerging environmental sciences (eg hydrology, climatology, forestry etc) and the
practical administration of environmental management in the colonies of the European powers
between 1660 and 1860. Of particular importance to the present context is Grove’s
identification of the interaction between the scientific elites in the colonies and the local ‘nonEuropean epistemologies of nature’. New environmental knowledge emerged in these colonial
situations and embodied a complex interaction of environmental romanticism and State
interests, which often brought together notions of ‘moral economy’ and ‘utilitarian ideals about
the desirability of new state structures or roles.’
205
in the market. Yet while these risks are defined and socially evaluated post facto
(by experts, the courts, social movements and the media etc) prior decisions are
rarely taken at the formal political level about whether or not such risks are
acceptable. This is really the central point of Beck’s analysis as discussed in
Chapter 4 - the formal political system in the West is premised on the strict
differentiation of parliamentary politics from the sub-politics of the technoeconomic pursuit of interests. Ecological risks (and their associated social
consequences) appear as the autonomised, latent side effects of scientific and
technological decisions that are not subject to institutionalised political
authorisation and legitimation. Beck’s point that these decisions are often taken
outside of the representative institutions of the State suggests a clear parallel with
the sorts of arguments, referred to in Chapter 6, of governmentality theorists Rose
and Miller in their analysis of advanced liberal modes of rule.
As Beck is able to demonstrate, these processes lead to three highly
significant changes in the character of politics in risk society. First, the established
cultural consensus that there is an inherent link between technical-economic
development and social progress begins to weaken. Second, the scientifically
generated awareness of ecological risks and the hazards of technology gives rise
to increasing demands within society for political control and accountability of
processes that are to a substantial degree outside the public sphere. Third, there is
a breakdown of the notion of the State as a political centre capable of controlling
the processes of technological development. Somewhat paradoxically, there is
also at the same time (as a result of the heightened awareness and political
problematisation of ecological risks) an extension of efforts by the State and
others (such as social movements) to monitor and regulate risks. Thus again, as
the general approach taken in the work of Rose and Miller would suggest,
ecological risks problematise specific forms of ‘dangerous’ conduct amongst the
population, which in turn spurs further attempts (often unsuccessful) to govern
these risks.
These processes are analysed by Beck as generating the sub-politics of risk
society. There are two sides to sub-politics. The first, which I have just referred
to, is concerned with the way in which ‘non political’ decisions made outside of
the formal political institutions have profound political influence on the direction
of social change and the choices available to citizens regarding acceptable levels
of ecological risk. The other aspect of sub-politics is the emergence of ecological
and environmental movements and citizen action groups that represent centres of
counter-expertise. It is these groups which articulate the demand for greater
political accountability and control over the generation of risks. Beck’s analysis
therefore throws considerable light on the nature of contemporary ecological
politics.
Beck’s approach it is not incompatible with that of Eder. Indeed, Eder’s
suggestion that within the environmental movement we can identify both cultural
206
movements which question the moral-aesthetic relation to nature, and social
movements which seek a more ecologically sustainable management of nature,
permits a further refinement of the sub-political dynamics of contemporary
society. Cultural movements that embody the purity model of the social relation to
nature (as found in the Deep Ecology movements for example) are far more likely
to question the authority of science, to reject the equation of technical and social
progress and to favour life style changes and direct action on environmental
issues. Social movements based on the justice model are more likely to be
concerned with greater State regulation of economic-technological development
in order to ensure a more scientifically based management of the social relation to
nature. Such movements are far more likely to accept ‘good’ ecological science
and to engage with the formal political system via lobbying, participation on
science-based policy consultative and advisory bodies. 289 Indeed, these latter
types of movements and citizens groups often participate in what I describe in
Chapter 6 as ‘regulatory science’.
I therefore concluded in Chapter 4 that the sort of approach adopted by Eder
and Beck is far more theoretically useful than that of Habermas in understanding
the relationship between ecological problems and modernisation. It recognises
that environmental movements represent a variety of cultural discourses (or
political rationalities, to use Foucault’s terminology) about the problem of nature
and the future direction of societal rationalisation. Such a perspective helps
overcome Habermas’ inability to satisfactorily link the material reproduction of
society at the system level with the actions of ecological movements in a way that
does not relegate such movements to the status of irrational, ‘anti-modernist’
reactions to social complexity.
(3) Biopolitics and the problem of nature in Foucault
Chapter 6 developed the central argument that Foucault’s work on biopolitics
is very much linked to the problem of nature, or as Foucault himself argued,
biopolitics has its origins in the problematisation of the relationship between
populations and resources. The element of nature that interested Foucault was that
of ‘second nature’, that is the processes whereby relations of power form modern
human subjects. While recognising this, I have argued that there is no compelling
reason not to extend Foucault’s analysis of biopolitics to the issues of ‘first
nature’ and the way in which this is shaped by, and itself influences, the social
relation to nature as represented in the natural environment.
Foucault suggested that the need for the administration of populations and
their biological conditions lead to the growth of the human sciences. In Chapter 6,
289
See Luke (1999) for an analysis of ecological politics in the United States which draws on the
governmentality approach.
207
I argued that this also gave rise to the problematisation of the natural
environment, including the development of the practices that constituted ‘the
environment’ as an object of management and control, and in time, as an object of
scientific study in all its (ecological) relations. Indeed, a key theme of this thesis
has been that the disciplining of individuals and populations was not possible
without the inception of measures concerned with the disposition and regulation
of the ‘external’ conditions of life of the population. I have therefore argued that
the more recent development of the science of ecology and the subsequent growth
of technical and political interest in the idea of managing the environment should
be regarded as an expression or articulation of biopolitics along the lines explored
by Foucault. When Foucault talked of the ‘entry of life into history’ this was
precisely because the biological conditions of life and the relationship of these to
welfare at the level of the population had become the object of expert knowledges
and hence political calculation. This is a process that is clearly extended by
contemporary practices for the management of the human relationship to the
natural environment.
Foucault and his successors have demonstrated that the emergence of
liberalism lead to a re-conceptualisation of the relationship between expert
knowledge and government. 290 In a similar manner, I have argued (in Chapter 6)
that the role of expert knowledge of the science of ecology has been central to the
way in which environments are constituted and managed as dynamic systems.
Indeed, the programs of government that have been built around environmental
problems in the past 40 years, illustrate the centrality of such ecological expertise
in the contemporary attempts at the administration of life. I have suggested that
scientific ecology should thus be regarded as providing the basis for the
emergence and subsequent institutionalisation of an ecological governmentality.
A key proposition of this thesis is therefore that a contemporary analysis of
biopolitics must also encompass the forms of ecological governmentality as
presented through programs of government that draw on systems ecology and
associated sciences of global modelling. The science of ecology and other
environmental discourses problematise the social relation to nature and at the
same time elaborate programs of environmental intervention and management.
Through the sub-politics of natural sciences such as ecology, and the counter
expertise and cultural models of ecological movements, ‘the environment’ has
been brought increasingly into the domain of conscious political calculation and
made a domain of life which is ‘susceptible to diagnosis, prescription and cure by
calculating and normalising intervention.’ (Rose and Miller, 1992 p.182)
290
The work of Rose and Miller (1992); Burchell (1996); and Dean (1994;1998b) is particularly
significant in this regard.
208
(4) Foucault: the incomplete critique of sovereignty
Despite my claims that there are good historical and methodological reasons
for arguing that the analysis of biopolitics and governmentality should be
extended to the study of the environmental discourse, Foucault himself did not
explore this possibility. There is in fact a paucity of Foucauldian analysis of the
role of natural sciences, including the ecological sciences.291 Nevertheless, I
sought to demonstrate in Chapter 7 that Foucault’s lack of interest reflected
important, although largely unexamined theoretical difficulties in his work. One
such problem is that Foucault appears to have taken the view that, in contrast to
the human sciences, ‘the sciences of nature’ where somehow able to detach
themselves from the social relations of power. This is a view for which he did not
provide a satisfactory explanation, other than to suggest it is a function of the
degree of formalisation and ‘objectivity’ such sciences have acquired over long
periods of development in the West.
In my consideration of the debate between Foucault and Habermas on power
and rationality (see Chapter 5), I argued that contrary to the view suggested by
critics such as Habermas and Honneth, Foucault’s work was not a general critique
of rationality. Rather it was directed at specific social applications of biology (eg
medicine) and the human sciences. Nevertheless, I have also presented arguments,
in Chapters 7 and 8, that Foucault’s philosophical position was not as radical as is
sometimes suggested. The most important manifestation of this was the
distinction he made between social relations of power and instrumental capacities
to ‘modify, use, consume, or destroy’ things. Power, Foucault insisted, applies to
relations between human agents. In this case, then, power cannot apply to the
relations between people and non-human things. In his later studies of the
processes by which power disciplines and actively forms modern subjects, power
and freedom are intimately connected - power in this positive sense presupposes
the ability to act on others. Power relations are always dynamic relationships
between agents and consequently freedom (as the capacity of agents to act) is an
essential feature of such relations.
As I have shown, the difference between power and capacity for Foucault was
that ‘forces’ and ‘capacities’ act directly on bodies and things, they do not involve
mutual adjustments of, and influence on, the actions of other agents. Power
involves acting subjects, and this human freedom to act is regarded by Foucault as
the ‘ontological precondition’ of politics and ethics. There is clearly implied in
this a basic difference between those actions involving the instrumental
manipulation of things, and those of agents or subjects. Implicit also is a further
291
For the most substantial attempt to date to apply the insights of Foucault’s work to
environmental issues, see Darier (1999a).
209
distinction that assumes there is a fundamental difference between relationships
between people and between people and nature. Drawing on the work of Patton I
argued that the view of the subject in Foucault’s later work was an essentially
Nietzschean one, which attributed an underlying potential for autonomy in the
subject. One aspect of this autonomy derives from the power for ‘self-directed’
use of the biological capacities of the human body. Another key element is tied to
the Nietzschean notion of the will to power, in which the bodily capacity for
action is accompanied by the self-reflexive experience of agency. It is this
positive, self-conscious feeling of successful action that is experienced as
autonomy. For Nietzsche such self-consciousness, and therefore the capacity to
experience agency, is linked to a vital biological interest of the human species in
self-preservation – a position that, as I have noted, has parallels with Habermas’
cognitive interest theory.
Foucault’s later work drew strongly on this underlying conception of
subjectivity as the capacity for autonomy. Following Hindess, I argued that the
difficulty with this was not the suggestion that domination would be resisted
because of the active nature of the subject. Rather, it was that Foucault went
further and suggested that the critical role of philosophy was to argue that
domination should be kept to a minimum. There was thus a shift from the
recognition of resistance as one effect of power, to Foucault appearing to set
down a universal (or at least potentially universalisable) normative injunction.
While Foucault had always at the methodological level rejected notions of
generalised emancipation and universal ethical standards, in his last works his
comments both on the function of philosophy and on the nature of freedom
appeared to resurrect some of the central concerns of critical theory.
For the reasons detailed in Chapter 7, Hindess criticises this as another
version of ‘the utopian critique of power’. To be consistent with his own analysis
of the productivity of power, Foucault must also recognise that some degree of
domination and subjectification is necessary for the existence of organised social
structures and institutions. I thus argued that Hindess is correct to see Foucault’s
inconsistency on this question as stemming from an incomplete critique of
sovereignty. Foucault fails to fully disengage from the ‘modern obsession with the
idea of the person as autonomous agent, and consequently, with the idea that a
community of such persons can, and should, be governed by consent of its
members.’ (Hindess, 1996 p.157) Foucault’s critique of political sovereignty
therefore does not go far enough. Hindess suggests that what is needed is not only
a political philosophy that is not built around the problem of sovereignty but also
one that frees itself from that other political fiction – ‘political community’. My
discussion of actor network theory and Latour's criticisms of Foucault in Chapter
8 sought to provide the basis for such a break from the notions of political
sovereignty and community.
210
Further support for the claim that Foucault failed to consistently carry through
his critique of sovereignty is provided by my discussion of the work of Rouse.
This demonstrates that despite Foucault’s reticence to apply his critique to the
established natural sciences, there is a strong argument that do so would be both
possible and consistent with his general analysis of the relations between power
and knowledge. In fact, Foucault’s general genealogical approach not only
problematises any notions of an essential human subjectivity, at the same time it
also challenges traditional concepts of representation and action. Hence Foucault
can legitimately be taken to task and asked why any assertion of a strong
epistemic or political distinction between nature and society should not be subject
to the key critical question underpinning his work in general. 292
It is therefore reasonable to suggest, as Rouse has done, that Foucault’s
critique of political sovereignty should both logically and methodologically be
part of a wider critique of epistemic sovereignty. The sorts of objections Foucault
raised against political sovereignty also apply to questions of epistemic
sovereignty, in that both ignore the multiple and local micropractices of power
that produce both organised scientific discourse and define their objects of study.
A key conclusion of this thesis therefore is that Foucault’s incomplete critique of
sovereignty explains why he made a distinction between capacities exerted over
non-human things and relations of power among acting human subjects. It also
helps explain why the natural sciences which take as their object the study of nonhuman nature, were seen by him as capable of detaching themselves from
relations of power.
(5) Latour: the critique of modern representation
In Chapter 8, I argued that the approach of Latour and actor network theory to
agency provides a crucial insight into how the natural sciences can be analysed in
a way that is generally consistent with Foucault’s approach to biopolitics and the
recent work of others on governmentality. One of Latour’s major criticisms of
both contemporary science and technology studies, and social theory in general is
their failure to recognise that in modern societies many of the most efficient
sources of power come from the sciences and not from the traditional political
process. To the extent that Foucault treats natural science as able to free itself
from relations of power, Latour's criticism can also be directed at Foucault.
I demonstrated in Chapter 8, that it is possible to draw on Latour’s work to
explain how the natural sciences are able to exercise what Foucault described as
the ‘the centralising powers which are linked to the institution and functioning of
292
That is, ‘in what is given to us as universal, necessary, obligatory, what place is occupied by
whatever is singular, contingent, and the product of arbitrary constraints’? See Rouse (1993)
p.138-9.
211
an organised science in a society such as ours.’ (Foucault, 1980e p.84) Latour’s
analysis points to three main factors that are responsible for these ‘centralising
powers’ of the natural sciences. First, the practices of modern science render any
inside/outside boundary between ‘science’ in the laboratory and the ‘society’
outside arbitrary and deceptive. Modern science, which by its very nature is
applied techno-science, systematically dissolves this distinction. In order to
function, science must capture the interests of allies, that is, must be able to
‘translate’ scientific statements so that these are framed in terms which
problematise their development and application for economic and social interests
beyond the laboratory (eg companies, interest groups, government agencies, etc).
Second, by partitioning and disciplining micro-phenomena in the laboratory,
science is able to invert the micro/macro levels of social theory. Simplification
and scaling down in the laboratory produce a change of scale which makes
possible a reversal of the actor’s strengths so that what was formerly
overwhelming in ‘the field’ can be made manageable and manipulable. Third,
through the processes of inscription, science is able to build powerful centres of
calculation. Only through inscribing vast quantities of information and data in a
form that can be measured and compared, can the objects and phenomena of
science (ie ‘nature’) be rendered manipulable. When combined with the change of
scale referred to above, the laboratory is at the centre of a network through which
information is gathered and inscriptions generated, combined and condensed.
Those inscriptions are then re-dispersed and inserted in the practices of the world
‘outside’ the laboratory, but only to the extent that the wider society itself is first
reconfigured and disciplined in ways which permit the reproduction of the
contrived conditions of the laboratory. In this process science builds centres of
calculation that mobilise resources scattered across numerous and diverse
networks, and becomes capable of acting at distance on hitherto unfamiliar events,
locales and actors.
Foucault regarded the natural sciences as too problematic, involving questions
about the link between scientific knowledge and power that were ‘excessively
complicated’ and in which the ‘threshold of possible explanation (is) impossibly
high.’ (Foucault, 1980d p.109-10) As I have shown in Chapter 8, what Latour
calls centres of calculation can be seen as extensions of Foucault’s notion of the
dispositif. However, in extending Foucault’s approach to the ‘hard’ natural
sciences, Latour’s work directly undermines the very reasons put forward by
Foucault for not studying the connection between these ‘highly formalised’
natural sciences and power relations.
I argued in Chapter 7 that one reason Foucault was not able (or willing) to
advance beyond the view of the natural science as ‘detached’ from power was that
despite his anti-humanism, he remained tied to the ideal of human autonomy. His
focus on the critique of the human sciences reflected his underlying view that it
was these and the disciplinary practices they imposed upon human agent, which
212
potentially most threatened that autonomy. Latour and his colleagues however are
able to show that those scientific activities that sociology and social theory
(including Foucault’s) have deemed ‘irrelevant or too technical’ are in fact one of
the most efficient, new sources of power in modern societies, precisely because
they appear so technical and remote from ‘politics’. Latour’s work makes it clear
that it is science’s abstract and complex networks of translation that allows it to
become so powerful. This is because the ‘abstract’, formalised sciences are able to
occupy strategic positions within extended translation networks, by establishing
‘obligatory passage points’ that successfully tie social and technical resources
together. Thus the ability, noted by Foucault, of the natural sciences to invest
particular discourses (and those who engage in them) with a special power and
authority rests on the way in which scientific spaces (eg laboratories) occupy
these strategic centres. It is from these spaces or centres that scientists (perhaps
quite unwittingly) engage in practices that ‘can displace society and recompose it
by the very content of what is done inside them.’ (Latour, 1983 p.168)
In Chapter 8, I also discussed Latour’s specific criticisms of Foucault. The
most significant of these is related to Latour and Callon’s methodological
principle of general symmetry, which cautions against assuming agency is
necessarily a uniquely human characteristic. This approach is intended to
problematise the representation of subject and object as ontologically distinct
classes of being. It recasts agency as a property of hybrid entities composed of
social and technical elements, thereby undermining any implication that this is
necessarily or exclusively a human characteristic.
As I have emphasised, a key result of this is that the notion of agency does
not provide, nor should it be intended to provide, a model of human subjectivity
or even a description of minimal human competences. Rather actants are seen
both as possessing the ontological characteristics of a network, and as the product
of the semiotic work of heterogeneous processes of translation, attribution, and
problematisation within networks. Actor network theory therefore shares with
Foucault the view that relations of power and the capacities for action
accompanying those relations define the actor. However, it carries the
assumptions about the types of historical and discursive work needed to constitute
an entity beyond those bearing on human subjectivity and agency, and extends
this approach to anything capable of being the source of an action. One key
consequence of the application of the principle of generalised symmetry is thus
that the distinction made by Foucault between passive things and active human
subjects is highly problematic. Thus rather than a separate nature and society, it is
preferable to see these as constituting a ‘socio-nature’ composed of the hybrid
entities produced by translation networks.
The principle of generalised symmetry can be applied to the analysis of the
notion of modernity itself. As Latour argues, what we understand as ‘modern’ is
based on the philosophical division of representation. Latour however shows that
213
what we call ‘modern’ consists of two different sets of practices - the processes of
translation which gives rise to socio-technical networks and hybrids, and the
practices of ‘purification’ that create and enforce the ontological separation of
human from non-human. This second set of practices corresponds to what Latour
describes as the ‘modern critical stance’. As my examination of Habermas in
Chapter 3 demonstrated, maintaining this philosophical division of representation
is fundamental to his defence of modernity. It is also in these practices of
purification that we see the grounding of Foucault’s position on the difference
between the human and natural sciences. As I argued in Chapter 7, Foucault’s
failure to extend his critique of political sovereignty to a broader critique of
epistemic sovereignty is closely connected to his apparent belief in the solidity of
the natural sciences and their ability to detach themselves from power. It is also
connected to his identification of the human subject’s capacity for autonomy as
fundamental to power and agency.
The actor network theory critique of the modern dichotomy of representation
also calls into question the ideal of political community, which Hindess identifies
as the other key modern constitutive fiction. Such a radical critique of the
modernist notions of representation and agency, if accepted, clearly would have
far reaching implications for how we understand politics and power. In the final
part of this chapter, I therefore consider the implications of the conclusions of this
thesis for our understanding of the problem of nature and ecological politics.
Ecological modernisation or ecological governmentality?
What can be said about the implications of the theories examined in this thesis
for our understanding of the problem of nature? Habermas’ critical theory seeks to
impose a far too artificial and rigid separation between modes of rationality and
action. Beck, while working in an idiom that is far from alien to that of critical
theory, is in many respects highly critical of Habermas. Nevertheless, as useful
and thought provoking as Beck’s analysis of risk society undoubtedly is, in the
end he does not venture significantly beyond the task Habermas had set for
himself. Habermas’ objections to Horkheimer and Adorno’s critique of
instrumental reason and the dialectic of enlightenment are at their core directed at
completing the ‘unfinished project of modernity’. This is a project that for
Habermas means carrying the processes of rationalisation forward so that all
realms of social action are subjected to the rule of reason.
Beck’s critique of risk society is far more attuned to dealing with the problem
of nature than is Habermas’. Beck seeks an ‘ecological enlightenment’ based on
the understanding that the simple modernity defended by Habermas is in the
process of being transformed into a qualitatively new reflexive modernity, in
which the relation to nature has become central to both further modernisation and
to social theory. However Beck appears more radical in his diagnosis of the
214
symptoms of the problem than in his proposals for dealing with this. His analysis
of science and technology does not significantly go beyond that given by
Habermas several decades earlier. In particular, this is evident in the way Beck is
critical of the role of science and technology because it leads to unseen,
autonomised social changes. He is critical of this precisely because it imposes
social change that is not legitimated by political discourse and democratic
decision-making.
Risk society is for Beck based on a ‘category error’ in which the
technological verification of hazards simultaneously excludes proper recognition
of the social genesis of those hazards. (Beck, 1995b p. 110) Of course Beck sees
in reflexive modernisation an immanent basis for the overcoming of this problem.
Yet his solution is not one that goes beyond the Habermasian concern for the
revitalisation of the public sphere and the rejection of scientism and technocratic
consciousness, which Habermas argues, transforms science and technology from a
progressive force into ideology and an obstacle to emancipation. (Habermas,
1971) Thus Beck insists
Only by breaking the law of unseen side effects, by elevating decision
making on technologies to public and political processes before and
during the genesis of hazards, can we return the fate of the hazard
civilisation to the realm of action and decision making. We must reverse
the prevailing practice of developing and financing new technologies
first, and then investigating the effects and hazards, and finally publicly
discussing them under the guillotine of manufactured objective
constraints. (Beck, 1995b p.110)
He thus argues for institutional responses that will bring this autonomised
technological change into the realm of a democratic and discursive decision
making. He suggests that we need a public, deliberative forum – ‘perhaps a kind
of ‘Upper House’ or ‘Technology Court’ that would guarantee the division of
power between technology development and technology implementation.’ Such
processes, while not abolishing conflict and guaranteeing consensus, he hopes
could at least ‘practice and integrate ambivalences, as well as revealing winners
and losers, making them public and thereby improving the preconditions for
political action.’ (Beck, 1995b p.29-31 – emphasis added) In other words, what
Beck is concerned with is precisely the revitalisation and extension of the political
sovereignty of those affected by technological change.
It will also be noted that Beck is effectively calling for the ‘proper’ separation
of technical rationality from political decision making about the applications of
science. As I indicated earlier, he also dismisses the notion of a new ethical
relationship to nature. He is therefore not that far from Habermas when it comes
to his views on how to deal with the problem of nature. The issue for Beck, just as
it is for Habermas, is not an excess of rationality as suggested by Horkheimer and
215
Adorno. Indeed, Beck claims that the problems of risk society can be cured ‘not
by a retreat but only by a radicalisation of rationality, which will absorb the
repressed uncertainty.’ (Beck, 1995b p.33) It is important however to recognise
that Beck is not simply talking of the creation of formal institutions which would
give form to the reflexive re-invention of politics. Risk society gives rise to a
‘life-and-death politics’ that permeates everything from the most global ecological
problems to the inner most depths of private life. (Beck, 1995b p.44-7) 293 Indeed,
Beck argues that the ‘ecological culture’ of risk society undermines the apolitical
character of the private sphere. Hence while we can see clear parallels with
Habermas, we can also see others which reflect elements of Foucault’s diagnosis
of biopolitics.
Beck points to the collapse of the traditional ideals of scientific rationality, in
which there is a distinction between ‘basic’ or ‘pure’ research, and ‘applied’
science and technology. A ‘new type of manufacturing tinker-science’ has
replaced this traditional model of science, according to Beck. He argues that in
this sort of science, the spatio-temporal relationship between experiment and
application has been reversed, so that experimentation is exported beyond the
laboratory and ‘society is made into a laboratory’.294
This may superficially appear to echo the view put forward by Latour,
however it reveals a key problem in Beck’s approach. Rather than advancing a
view consistent with Latour, Beck is in fact making one of the mistakes Latour
cautions against; that is, Beck’s analysis assumes the ‘inside/outside’ distinction
between laboratory and society. Hence, Beck is mistaken to see this ‘reversal’ of
experiment and application as a fundamental feature of a new type of science.
Rather, as Latour and Callon demonstrate, this has always been an essential
feature of modern science (‘techno-science’). What is probably true is that the
problematisation of the ecological and bio-technical consequences of this type of
science has increasingly rendered the myth of the separation between laboratory
and society untenable. Beck is of course correct when he suggests that the
undermining of the ‘ideal’ of traditional science ‘opens the door to public
disputes, fears, and viewpoints’ which call into question the objectivity of science.
(Beck, 1995b p.105)
As I have suggested, Beck’s work in key respects suffers from the same
underlying totalising approach to rationalisation, as does that of critical theorists
such as Horkheimer, Adorno and Habermas. In Beck’s analysis of reflexive
293
See also Beck’s (1992b, Part II) detailed treatment of how risk society individualises gender,
family and labour relations.
294
For example, he argues that ‘Nuclear reactors must be built, artificial biotechnical creatures
must be released into the environment, and chemical products must be put into circulation for
their properties, safety, and long term effects to be studied.’ (Beck, 1995b p.104)
216
modernisation this leads to an overly generalised view of risk, and a tendency to
portray risk as operating fairly much in the same way across contemporary
technological society regardless of the specific sectoral or national context. His
analysis of the emergence of a new stage of modernisation is premised on the
assertion that the advent of ecological ‘mega-risks’ makes risk incalculable, and
consequently, all attempts to calculate and manage the costs of these become
technocratic obsfucation.
However, as Dean (1998b) has very clearly demonstrated, the problem of the
calculability of technological risk is far more usefully approached within the
conceptual framework of governmentality. Thus, he emphasises the importance of
directing our attention to analysis of ‘the specific form of risk rationalities’ rather
than engaging in ‘a global narrative of risk society.’ He suggests four dimensions
to the government of risk, and indeed, I would argue that it these questions which
should form the starting point for any future research which seeks to understand
the ways in which environmental risks are linked to the formation and articulation
of ecological governmentality. Dean frames the key questions that should be
asked of ‘risk’ as follows:
First, how we come to know about and act upon different conceptions of
risk, ie the specific forms of risk rationality. Second, how such
conceptions are linked to particular practices and technologies. Third,
how such practices and technologies give rise to new forms of social and
political identity. Fourth, how such rationalities, technologies and
identities become latched onto different political programs and social
imageries that invest them with specific ethos. (Dean, 1998b p.32)
In contrast to Beck, Latour’s approach has the considerable merit of
extending the sorts of critical genealogical questions posed by Foucault to our
attempts to understand the interaction between the human world and non-human
nature. Latour’s call for the abandonment of the ontological bifurcation of the
‘modern constitution’ appears to open up the possibilities of some form of
political representation for nature. It is thus possible to see Latour as providing a
strong social theoretical perspective that has generally been lacking in Green
political thinking. However, neither Green theory nor Latour overcome the
problem of humans speaking on behalf of the non-human. If determining who can
legitimately speak for whom is a problem in human societies, it is doubly
problematic for non-human entities who can only ‘speak’ through the inscription
media of a human constituted natural science. It is perhaps unfair to expect Latour
to respond to this problem, despite his rhetoric about the ‘Parliament of Things’,
for in reality it probably makes little sense to speak of a political community that
includes nature. Of more significance is Latour’s emphasis on a broader
‘collective’ or ‘hybrid’ view of agency. By calling into question any simple
correspondence between speaking human subjects and agency Latour’s work
opens the way for a view of power which is far more nuanced and thus receptive
217
to extending the sorts of analysis developed by Foucault to those areas, including
the environmental, in which science and technology play a central role.
It seems to me that nothing is lost and much may be gained by adopting the
perspective of actor network theory, and saying that in many instances it is not
particularly helpful to assume that it is only people who act or exert power. This
theme is implicit in my critique of Foucault, for while his characterisation of
government as the ‘conduct of conduct’ is undoubtedly a powerful analytical turn,
it is nevertheless arbitrarily self-limiting if we always take this to refer to only the
actions of persons on others. I have been critical of Foucault (and by implication,
of those who have taken up aspects of his work) for not paying sufficient attention
to the role of the natural sciences in shaping power relations. I have attempted to
argue that this is not so much an ontological question about the objects of study of
the human versus the natural sciences. Instead it is a question of the extent to
which particular forms of knowledge (and associated governmental practices)
bear upon the realm of positivity – which today is shaped by ecology, molecular
biology and atmospheric physics as much by the human sciences. 295
The substantial merit of taking the actor network theory approach seriously,
and hence adopting Callon’s methodological principal of generalised symmetry in
the study of the problem of nature, is that this allows us to reflect critically on a
particular form of relation to nature rather than being compelled to unreflectively
work within the limits set by a view of nature taken from the natural sciences. It
seems clear that if the social relation to nature is understood along the lines
suggested here, then we must also take seriously the proposition that not only are
we, as Tully (1997) says, ‘partly constituted as subjects acting on nature in (the)
complex practices of knowledge, power, ethics and technologies’, but also that
such practices constitute the nature we act upon. This in turn requires that we give
appropriate weight to the ways in which the non-human world (both nature and
material technologies) is a repository of capacities that are significant resources
for the translation networks and centres of calculation that are integral to the
power of modern science.
One consequence of extending this sort of analysis to the natural sciences is
that the processes of thematisation, discipline and normalisation must be seen to
be as much a part of our knowledge of, and relation to, nature as they are in the
human sciences. The natural environment has increasingly become the subject of
political rationalities, which have not only altered the ways in which its ‘reality’ is
conceptualised, but also generated a complex array of moral and political
justifications for the proper disposition of authority and government. Such a view
is not inconsistent with Foucault’s project of understanding power and its
295
I am indebted to Nikolas Rose for articulating this distinction in his comments to me on an
earlier published work (Rutherford, 1994a).
218
production of truth, even when extended to the natural science. In arguing thus I
have draw on the work of Nikolas Rose and Peter Miller on governmentality.
Governing conduct is linked to political rationalities, which make the domain to
be governed intelligible and susceptible to strategic (including moral) action. 296
Such rationalities are brought to bear on conduct through governmental
technologies. Rose suggests that such technologies should be regarded as ‘an
assemblage’ of a range of forms of practical knowledge, practices of calculation,
human capacities and non-human objects and devices, including inscription
devices. (Rose, 1999 p.52 – emphasis added)
Rose views such technologies of government as ‘human’ technologies, and
argues counter to the Frankfurt School, that it is meaningless to counterpose
human freedom to technology simply because ‘freedom is the mobile outcome of
a multitude of human technologies’. Yet despite this, Rose appears reluctant take
the broader view of power suggested by authors including Latour, Callon and
Rouse. His view of the inventiveness of science appears to remain overly tied to
the experimental methodology of scientists within the laboratory to the neglect of
how this is only ever of lasting significance to the extent that is able translated
outside the laboratory. Rose and Miller draw on Latour and Callon’s notions of
inscription devices and translation networks (and the role of these in enabling
‘action at a distance’) as central to neo-liberal modes of rule. Given this, and
Rose’s (1999) recognition that even material technologies involve ‘a certain
shaping of conduct’, it must be said that Rose has not presented a clear argument
as to why the actor network theory position on agency should be unacceptable. 297
If it is accepted that a rigid separation cannot be made between those elements of
governmental technologies that rely on non-human capacities, objects, and
devices, and those whose elements are social, then it is difficult to see why agency
cannot be attributed to ‘hybrid’ actants as suggested by Latour.
At a general level, despite his reluctance to develop conceptually his fairly
scattered comments on the natural sciences, Foucault could clearly be said to
regard discipline and biopolitics as mechanisms by which otherness was
thematised, problematised and brought into the realm of normalising calculation.
Indeed, Foucault cautioned that
We must not imagine that the world turns towards us a legible face which
we would have only to decipher; the world is not the accomplice of our
knowledge; there is no prediscursive providence which disposes the
world in our favour. (Foucault, 1981d p.229)
296
See Rose (1999) p.15-60 for a detailed exposition of ‘governing’.
297
I have posed a similar question in a review of Hindess’ recent work. See Rutherford (1997b).
219
It is in comments such as this that we see the common threads between Foucault’s
work and that of Horkheimer and Adorno, who argued that in Enlightenment
thinking the ‘mere idea of outsideness is the very source of fear’. (Adorno and
Horkheimer, 1986) It is here that we can understand the link between
rationalisation, discipline and normalisation. Foucault (1990 p.142) argued that
the emergence of biopolitics coincided with the modern scientific thematisation of
life, making for the first time in history what was formerly the ‘inaccessible
substrate’ of human life an object of power. Scientific objectification, whether of
the human body or non-human nature problematises that otherness which
threatens to escape governmentalisation and normalisation. Foucault often
emphasised that problematisation and discipline were the products of specific
rationalities. There is in Foucault recognition of what could be described as the
dark side of the thematising project and of reason more generally. 298 However,
the problem is not the same one identified by critical theory (and Green theorists)
299
as that of excessive instrumental rationality. As Jane Bennett has pointed out, it
is ‘misleading to reduce the problem to instrumental rationality (as) each and
every categorical organisation, however expressive or anti-instrumental, will be
exclusionary in some way.’ (Bennett, 1987 p.145) Such a view is not that far from
Horkheimer and Adorno’s treatment of ‘identity thinking’ in Dialectic of
Enlightenment. 300
The effect of the scientific thematisation of nature is taken up by Beck. He
claims that the further differentiation of industrial modernity in risk society means
that nature no longer retains its ‘pre-ordained character’ and has become part of
the ‘inner nature’ of post-industrial society. He argues that the meanings of
‘nature’ and ‘society’ are re-thematised and integrated into a ‘social-nature’. In
the process nature is appropriated to political functions:
‘Nature’ becomes a social project, a utopia that is to be reconstructed,
shaped and transformed … and (this) makes the production of matters and
bodies of fact possible (and) … produces a world of living creatures
which can conceal the manufacturing character it creates and represents.
(Beck, 1994 p.27)
Ecological problems and environmental movements are therefore as much
involved in the thematisation of nature, as are the economic and technical forces
298
It is this side of Foucault’s work that Habermas and Honneth seized on when attributing to him
a view of a disciplined society, similar to Horkheimer and Adorno’s ‘totally administered
society’.
299
See Eckersley (1992) and Chapter 2 of this thesis.
300
See Rutherford (1993) and Luke (1988) for discussion of how expressivist forms of
environmentalism, especially ‘deep ecology’, seek a new subjectivity modelled on an uncritical
acceptance of ecological constructs..
220
of advanced industrialism. As Beck emphasises, such movements and
problematisations, while they appear to call for the ‘salvation of nature’ in fact
‘accelerate and perfect’ the consumption (of nature)’. (Beck, 1994 p.27) The
problem is that Beck is unable to explain how this is brought about.
Latour’s critique of the modern bifurcation of nature and society points in
deliberately Foucauldian terms to the need for a new ‘political constitution of
truth’ which would recognise the hitherto denied and subterranean production of
socio-natural ‘collectives’ and ‘hybrids’. What this involves is not simply the
recognition that the realm of positivity is in fact a tangle of the human and nonhuman. Rather Latour sees this as also very much a continuation of the democratic
spirit of the Enlightenment, and specifically asks, ‘Is it not worth the effort to
pursue the Enlightenment into the dark tangles of science and society mixtures?’
(Latour, 1991 p.18) For him this is a question of creating, along the lines
suggested by Foucault, a new regime of truth and a new anthropology appropriate
to the task – a task involving the intellectual disciplines of political philosophy
and science studies. 301 He insists that this does not require a ‘revolution’, only the
public ratification of what has always in fact happened in practice but has been
denied by modern epistemology.
However, this claim that all that is needed mere ‘ratification’ is not as simple
as Latour’s presentation of it suggests. Even if his argument for the hybridisation
of social and natural entities were accepted, the call to bring Enlightenment to
bear on the entities of socio-nature would carry the process of thematisation and
objectification to a new level of intensity. Latour’s ‘Parliament of Things’, the
recognition that power and agency inhere in networks composed of human actions
and material capacities of things, requires on his account a further extension of the
301
Dean argues that despite the commonalities between actor network theory and Foucault, the
two part company because authors such as Callon and Latour adhere to a particular variant of
realism which focuses on the way in which socio-technical reality is constructed, whereas
Foucault adopts a far more nominalist approach which refrains from pronouncing on the nature
of social reality. Foucault’s methods, argues Dean ‘arise once we examine the full
consequences of what we might call “the social construction of knowledge” while abstaining
from providing an alternative account of reality (the reality of subjects, of society, of
humanity).’ Hence, what is at issue is in fact ‘the realm of effectivity of the construction of
truth.’ Nevertheless, Dean argues that there is a limit to Foucault’s nominalism, that he ‘refrains
from the inference that everything is thereby a construction. Yet at the same time the real
‘remains too indecipherable ever to be able to be summed up into a formula (a theory of the
subject, of power, of a constructed object, a realm of facts, a network, a social reality). … This
is Foucault's irrealism, his agnosticism. (Dean, 1998a p.193-5)
Space does not permit an excersus into the philosophical debates on realism and constructivism.
However, I am not convinced by Dean’s argument on this issue. I think that he overlooks the
degree to which actor network theory is compatible with the sort of nominalism attributed to
Foucault. In any case, I do not see the approach taken by Callon and Latour as a realist one. I
am more comfortable with Rouse’s position, which is “against realism and anti-realism”. On
this see Rouse (1987).
221
dividing practices and scientific classification that Foucault’s work pointed to as
central to modern power/knowledge. Thus, Latour says that we need
The meticulous sorting of quasi-objects to become possible – no longer
unofficially and under the table, but officially and in broad daylight. In
this desire to bring to light, to incorporate into language, to make public,
we continue to identify with the intuition of the Enlightenment. But this
intuition never had the anthropology it deserved. (Latour, 1993 p.142)
As Foucault and others have shown, the other side of such thematisation is
problematisation, programs of government, normalisation and discipline. The way
in which such programs of ecological governmentality would play themselves out
is not something to which Latour pays much attention. His approach does
however suggest something of a celebratory proliferation of hybrid diversity.
There is no doubt that the processes of translation and relations of power analysed
by actor network theory would not be abolished by abandoning the modern
constitution. Indeed, there is in what Latour says no suggestion of the abolition of
power. However, his rhetoric regarding a ‘Parliament of Things’ confuses,
perhaps deliberately, different meanings of representation so that recognition of
the actor-network qualities of agency is not disentangled from notions of political
sovereignty. The value of Latour’s critique of the modern constitution is that it
undermines any arbitrary division of representation between human and nonhuman entities. This critical genealogical approach makes ‘no a priori distinction
between the size of actors, between the real and the unreal, between what is
necessary and what is contingent, between the technical and the social.’ (Callon
and Latour, 1981 p.292) This is particularly important when the realm of
positivity in question is the ecological. In such circumstances it focuses attention
on the ways in which capacities and power are aggregated, through centres of
calculation, to act across complex assemblages of political (both institutional and
sub-political), scientific, economic, ethical, and technological practices at both the
local and global level.
All of the theoretical approaches considered in this thesis lead us to consider
the ways in which modern scientific knowledge and expertise shapes the
distribution of power and the social relation to nature. Foucault’s insistence that
we understand particular institutions and accompanying relations of power as the
result of historically specific political rationalities, rather than as the result of
some generalised (and totalising) process of societal rationalisation is an
important corrective to that tendency in theorists such as Habermas and Beck.
Foucault’s notion of biopolitics can, as I have argued, be linked to the emergence
of contemporary scientific ecology as a mode of regulatory science. This is not to
suggest that contemporary environmental discourse is a unity, much less that it
reflects the triumph of technical or instrumental rationality in general. Instead, the
more limited suggestion has been made that the ecological sciences (such as
systems ecology) and projects such as the International Biological Program can be
222
understood as a form of political or governmental rationality. Systems ecology is
one such rationality among a plurality of rationalities, even within the domain of
environmental discourse.
If this governmentality approach is applied to Eder’s work, for example, it
suggests that what he calls the ‘purity’ or romantic model of nature has been very
much a marginalised rationality in Western culture and politics. Nonetheless,
historically it has interacted with and influenced the expression of the dominant
rationality, the utilitarian or ‘justice’ model of nature. Something similar can be
found in Beck’s notion of sub-politics, in which he argues that risk society
produces discourses about the generation and distribution risk that increase
opportunities for social movements and counter-experts to help shape
contemporary society ‘from below’. Latour and Callon also show that sociotechnical action at the local level (in the laboratory, the factory or on the farm)
and at the macro-level of the ‘social system’ is not fundamentally different. In
each case it is rather a question of local actors making themselves ‘bigger’ and
more powerful by extending the reach of translation chains and enrolling the
resources of allies, and by occupying obligatory passage points or centres which
channel translations and resources to enhance their strength. As Rose points out,
what is at stake in all of these sorts of struggles are not contestations ‘between
power and its others, but between diverse programs, logics, dreams and ideals,
codified, organised and rationalised to a greater or lesser extent.’ (Rose, 1999
p.279)
The similarity with Foucault here is obvious. Foucault argued that a power
relation is ‘an agonism’, a ‘permanent provocation’. Power relationships are
dynamic and therefore always potentially unstable. Consequently, under particular
circumstances, even long-established states of domination may be subject to
reversal. Thus Eder’s purity model and aspects of Beck’s sub-polity can be seen
as resistance to the dominant, scientised understandings of nature, or what
Foucault described as an ‘insurrection of subjugated knowledges’, those ‘naïve’,
‘disqualified’, localised, non-scientific discourses which oppose the ‘tyranny’ of
particular globalising scientific disciplines. (Foucault, 1980e p.81-5) However,
the point in making such a contrast is not to counterpose, in the style of
Habermas, modern, rationalised knowledge to anti-modern, irrational forms of
belief, which are thereby devalued and excluded. Indeed, perhaps Foucault’s
comments on ‘resistance’ betray a lingering valorisation of the autonomy and
sovereignty from which I have argued he failed to fully break. Perhaps, as Rose
suggests, there is no need for a notion of resistance. Rather we may need to think
simply in terms of the dynamic ‘ways in which creativity arises out of the
situation of human beings 302engaged in particular relations of force and meaning,
302
Or indeed, of any ‘actant’, not only human ones.
223
and what is made out of the possibilities of that location.’ (Rose, 1999 p.279)
Foucault of course saw identification with the resistance of ‘disqualified’
discourses as a practical genealogical task aimed at establishing ‘a historical
knowledge of struggles’ which could be made use of tactically in contemporary
political and social contests. (Foucault, 1980e p.83) No doubt there are many
disqualified and subjugated knowledges where this is appropriate, yet it is also
relevant to recall Hindess’ comment that organised social existence (and the
freedoms that this provides) is not possible without some degree of domination. It
is arguable that in environmental matters, some forms of domination may be
particularly important if both humans and other species are to enjoy certain basic
ecological ‘rights to life’. This however touches on the issue of an environmental
ethics – a task beyond this thesis. 303
The focus of this thesis suggests that a research agenda into ecological
problems is likely to have much to gain from drawing on the work of both
governmentality studies and actor network theory. While I have commented
above on the role of environmental movements, the study of environmental
discourse cannot be concerned solely, or perhaps even principally, with the
struggle between scientific and non-scientific rationalities. It would also need to
examine the competition and manoeuvring within scientific ecology itself (ie
between systems ecology and population ecology, community ecology, etc), and
to consider how these apparently esoteric, technical debates influence the
historical formation of the regulatory sciences and ecological programs of
government.304 This thesis has argued that the development of scientific ecology,
particularly systems ecology, provided both a guiding political rationality and the
technical apparatus of calculation and assessment that by the late 1960s began to
make possible a form of regulatory science that was capable of governmentalising
society-environment relations.
A need exists for substantial further research into the ways in which the
ecological research institutions (particularly in the United States, but also in other
countries) developed as centres of calculation able to translate their emerging
research interests into key elements of the new rationalities of ecological
government. Such historical research would seek to explain how scientists were
able to make the technical agendas of ecology the cornerstone of powerful
alliances with conservation groups, political executives, legislatures and State
agencies to create new regulatory regimes focused on the problematisation of the
environment and the social relation to nature. The role of the USA has been
303
For some recent and very interesting attempts to consider what an environmental ethic
informed by a Foucauldian perspective might involve (and not involve) see Darier (1999b) and
Tully (1997).
304
For some excellent historical studies of the conflicts within scientific ecology in the postWorld War 2 period see Mitman (1988); Palliadino (1991) and Taylor (1988).
224
significant, inasmuch as it was the first place that saw the emergence of
contemporary industrialised ‘big science’. This was initially very much influenced
by national characteristics. However, given the transnational character of
scientific research agendas (eg the International Geophysical Year and the
International Biological Program), and the hegemony of US science in much of
the post-World War Two period, there is evidence of a widespread (but by no
means universal) internationalisation of ecological techniques (eg Environmental
Impact Assessment) and ecological theories originating in the USA. 305 How these
‘laboratory’ developments were translated both nationally and internationally, and
were aligned with economic and social interests requires further investigation.
While the focus of many governmentality studies has been the practices of
government within the context of particular nation-states, actor network theory
provides useful conceptual tools to look at scientific networks that extend beyond
such boundaries. It is important not to over-emphasise the nation-state and
national cultures at the expense of analysing the problematics of government in a
way that gives appropriate weight to the global (or at least transnational)
assemblages of forces and networks of authoritative scientific-policy judgement
that can have a significant influence on shaping contemporary social relations.
Included in this would be consideration of the role of international organisations,
and the link between science and international environmental policy (eg ozone
depletion, climate change etc.).
Dean has argued the Foucauldian concern with the ‘problematic of
government is not so much a solution to the paradoxical nature of the state but a
research agenda into the contingent trajectories by which the state assumes its
present and changing form’. (Dean, 1994 p.181) As ecological problems
demonstrate, that form is increasingly one in which national structures are
overlaid by international patterns of governance which embody processes of both
marketisation and regulation, and which rely on expertise and knowledge that is to
a significant degree denationalised (if not globalised). In the context of ecological
problems, it is therefore important to try to unravel the relations between such
denationalised scientific expertise on the one hand, and on the other, the political
rationalities and various governmental programs for ecological management
conceived in terms of a global, systemic interdependence between society and
nature.
The many apparently contradictory elements of environmental discourse
(scientific, economic, ethical, cultural, etc) can be understood in terms of the
305
For detailed discussions of the influence of US science on the growth of contemporary
ecological theories, see Golley (1993); Jamison (1993) and McIntosh (1985). For detailed
consideration of the political institutionalisation of environment protection in the USA, see
Harris and Milkis (1989); Jasanoff (1990); (1992) and Marcus (1991).
225
notion of governmentality. The significant work of Rose and Miller (1992) on this
has identified three key characteristics of governmental rationalities. If the
discourse on the problem of nature is considered in the light of these three
elements, we can move beyond the general assertion that both ecological
modernisation and counter-cultural resistance are immanent in modernity, and
instead begin to consider how and why these elements fit together in
contemporary practices for governing the environment.
According to Rose and Miller (1992 p.178-82) governmental rationalities are
characteristically moral, epistemological and idiomatic. They are expressed in
moral terms that elaborate the ideals and principles with which government
should properly be concerned. Ecological governmentality is particularly
concerned with questions of justice and equity – questions such as intergenerational equity, the relation between development and environmental
protection, and the relations between the needs of human society and the biotic
rights of non-human nature. Thus a significant element in the environmental
debate is the concern to develop an appropriate environmental ethics.
Governmental rationalities also have an epistemological character. They are
articulated in terms of a specific knowledge of the objects and problems to be
addressed. This epistemology is in large part derived from scientific ecology,
which as I argue in Chapter 6, represents an essentially economic model of
nature.306 It is scientific ecology (and related sciences of global environmental
modelling) that provides the authoritative accounts of the sorts of entities and
processes which must be managed – ecosystems, global climatic and atmospheric
processes, habitat and species diversity, population and carrying capacity, and so
forth. Finally, all governmental rationalities are expressed in a distinctive idiom,
which functions as an intellectual means for making reality ‘thinkable in such a
way that it is amenable to political deliberations.’ (Rose and Miller, 1992 p.179)
Hence the relationship of society to the natural environment is conceived in terms
of the language of security and risk (or ecological crisis). Ecological hazards and
insecurity are characteristically posed as problems that must be addressed through
governmental technologies that minimise dangerous behaviours and the risks to
which they give rise. The idiom of ecological rationality is paradigmatically
represented by ‘the precautionary principle’, 307 which reverses the onus of
scientific proof to insist that practices and actions cannot be deemed safe simply
because there is not scientific certainty of the potential for environmental harm.
Government, as the conduct of conduct is inherently a problematising activity
in which the ‘articulation of government has been bound to the constant
306
On this see Worster (1987a) and (1993a).
307
This is was clearly enunciated as the key principle of sustainable development in the famous
“Brundtland Report” (Brundtland, 1987).
226
identification of the difficulties and failures of government.’ (Rose and Miller,
1992 p.181-83) Ecological governmentality is a problematising political
rationality, which continuously seeks to improve the techniques for managing the
environment and those social activities that impact upon ecological processes.
Ecological governmentality therefore continually problematises the social relation
to nature at a basic ontological (and moral) level. In many respects, ecological
thought articulates the fundamental philosophical dilemma of the dialectic of
enlightenment, in which modernity, with its dependence on instrumental,
scientific knowledge, embodies a self-destructive social relation to nature.
However, as Klaus Eder (1996) has argued, differing and sometimes even
incommensurable validity claims mean that the conflict over the social relation to
nature cannot be resolved by reference to the ‘implicit validity claims’ of critical
theory.
It is however possible to develop a historically grounded theoretical
framework for the analysis of these sort of ecological discourses, conflicts and
practices by drawing on the work of Foucault, recent governmentality studies, and
Latour and actor network theory. Such an approach, while cognisant of the macrosociological dimensions of biopolitics, is also able to relate this to specific,
localised governmental programs and technologies involved in governing the
social relation to nature. The work of Rose and Miller in particular draws on
Latour and Callon. In doing so it emphasises that programs of government emerge
as a means of establishing ‘translatability between the moralities, epistemologies
and idioms of political power, and the government of a specific problem space,
(which) establishes a mutuality between what is desirable and what can be made
possible through the calculated activities of political forces.’ (Rose and Miller,
1992 p.178-82)
An important research agenda for scholars who seek to understand the
relations of power and knowledge in contemporary ecological discourse is the
application of the insights derived from governmentality and actor network
studies to an environmental ‘history of the present’. Such research would involve
the meticulous, empirical study of the three dimensions of governmental
rationalities, and the ways in which these are shaped by the dynamic interactions
of scientific knowledge and expertise, material technologies, ecological
movements, state-based regulatory regimes, and the influence of global forces of
marketisation.
227
Bibliography
Adorno, T., and Horkheimer, M. 1986, Dialectic of Enlightenment, Verso,
London.
Alford, C. 1985a, 'Jurgen Habermas and the Dialectic of Enlightenment: What is
Theoretically Fruitful Knowledge', Social Research, 52, pp: 119-49.
Alford, C. 1985b, Science and the Revenge of Nature: Habermas and Marcuse,
Florida University Press, Gainesville, Fl.
Bahro, R. 1986, Building the Green Movement, GMP, London.
Barnes, B. 1988, The Nature of Power, Polity Press, Cambridge.
Barret-Kriegal, B. 1992, 'Michel Foucault and the Police State', in Michel
Foucault Philosopher, T. Armstrong, (ed.), Harvester Wheatsheaf, Hemel
Hempstead.
Barrett, M. 1991, The Politics of Truth: From Marx to Foucault, Polity Press,
Cambridge.
Barry, A., Osborne, T., and Rose, N. 1996, (eds.), Foucault and Political Reason:
Liberalism, neo-liberalism and rationalities of government, UCL Press, London.
Bartlett, R. 1990, 'Ecological Reason in Administration: Environmental Impact
Assessment and Administrative Theory', in Managing Leviathan: Environmental
Politics and the Administrative State, R. Paehlke and D. Torgerson, (eds.),
Belhave Press, London, pp: 81-96.
Baxter, H. 1987, 'System and Life-world in Habermas's Theory of Communicative
Action', Theory & Society, 16, pp: 39-86.
Beck, U. 1992a, 'From Industrial Society to Risk Society: Questions of Survival,
Social Structure and Ecological Enlightenment', Theory, Culture & Society, 9, pp:
97-123.
Beck, U. 1992b, Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity, Sage, London.
228
Beck, U. 1994, 'The Reinvention of Politics: Towards a Theory of Reflexive
Modernization', in Reflexive Modernization: Politics, Tradition and Aesthetics in
the Modern Social Order, U. Beck, A. Giddens, and S. Lash, (eds.), pp: 1-55.
Beck, U. 1995a, Ecological Enlightenment: Essays on the politics of the risk
society, Mark Ritter, translator, The Humanities Press, New Jersey.
Beck, U. 1995b, 'The world as laboratory', in Ecological Enlightenment: Essays
on the Politics of the Risk Society, Humanities Press, New Jersey, pp: 101-10
Benhabib, S. 1984, 'Epistemologies of Postmodernism: A Rejoiner to JeanFrancois Lyotard', New German Critique (33), pp: 103-27.
Benhabib, S. 1986, Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of
Critical Theory, New York University Press, New York.
Bennett, J. 1987, Unthinking Faith and Enlightenment, New York University
Press, New York.
Bernauer, J., and Rasmussen, D. 1988, The Final Foucault, MIT Press, Boston.
Bernstein, R. 1985, Habermas and Modernity, Polity Press, Cambridge.
Betz, H. 1991, Postmodern Politics in Germany: the Politics of Resentment, St
Martins Press, New York.
Bocking, S. 1995, 'Ecosystems, Ecologists, and the Atom: Environmental
Research at Oak Ridge National Laboratory', Journal of the History of Biology, 28
(1), pp: 1-47.
Bookchin, M., (as Herber, L.) 1962, Our Synthetic Environment, Knopf, New
York.
Bove, P. 1988, 'The Foucault Phenomenon: The Problematics of Style', in
Foucault, G. Deleuze, (ed.), University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp: viixl.
Bowerbank, S. 1999, 'Nature Writing as Self-Technology', in Discourses of the
Environment, E. Darier, (ed.), Blackwell, Oxford, pp: 163-78.
Bramwell, A. 1989, Ecology in the Twentieth Century: A History, Yale University
Press, New Haven.
Brown, L. et al, 1990, The State of the World, Allen & Unwin, North Sydney.
229
Brundtland, G. 1987, Our Common Future, Oxford University Press, New York.
Buck-Morss, S. 1977, The Origin of Negative Dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno,
Walter Benjamin and the Frankfurt Institute, Harvester Press, Hassocks, UK.
Burchell, G. 1991, 'Civil Society and the System of Natural Liberty', in The
Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P.
Miller, (eds.), Harvester Wheatsheaf, London, pp: 119-50.
Burchell, G. 1996, 'Liberal government and techniques of the self', in Foucault
and Political Reason: Liberalism, neo-liberalism and rationalities of government,
A. Barry, T. Osborne, and N. Rose, (eds.), UCL Press, London, pp: 19-36.
Burchell, G., Gordon, C., and Miller, P. 1991, The Foucault Effect: Studies in
Governmentality, Harvester Wheatsheaf, Hemel Hempstead.
Butler, J. 1989, 'Foucault and the Paradox of Bodily Inscriptions', The Journal of
Philosophy, LXXXVI, pp: 601-7.
Butler, J. 1993, 'Sexual Inversions', in Foucault and the Critique of Institutions, J.
Caputo and M. Yount, (eds.), Pennsylvania State University Press, University
Park, Pa., pp: 81-98.
Buttel, F., and Taylor, P. 1992, 'Environmental Sociology and Global
Environmental Change: A Critical Assessment', Society & Natural Resources, 5,
pp: 211-30.
Caldwell, L. 1991, 'Globalizing Environmentalism', Society & Natural Resources,
4, pp: 259-72.
Callon, M. 1986, 'Some Elements of a Sociology of Translation: Domestication of
the Scallops and Fishermen of St Brieuc Bay', in Power, Action and Belief: A New
Sociology of Knowledge?, J. Law, (ed.), Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, pp:
196-233.
Callon, M. 1995, 'Four Models for the Dynamics of Science', in Handbook of
Science and Technology Studies, S. Jasanoff, G. Markle, J. Petersen, and T. Pinch,
(eds.), Sage, Thousand Oaks, pp: 29-63.
Callon, M., and Latour, B. 1981, 'Unscrewing the Big Leviathan: How Actors
Macro-structure Reality and How Sociologists Help Them Do So', in Advances in
Social Theory and Methodology: Towards an Integration of Micro- and Macrosociologies, K. Knorr-Cetina and A. Cicourel, (eds.), Routledge & Kegan Paul,
Boston, pp: 277-303.
230
Carson, R. 1962, Silent Spring, Penguin, Hammondsworth.
Christoff, P. 1996, 'Ecological Modernisation, Ecological Modernities',
Environmental Politics, 5 (3).
Clegg, S. 1994, 'Weber and Foucault: Social Theory for the Study of
Organizations', Organization, 1 (1), pp: 149-78.
Cohen, J. 1985, 'Strategy or Identity: New Theoretical Paradigms and
Contemporary Social Movements', Social Research, 52 (4), pp: 664-716.
Collins, H., and Yearley, S. 1992, 'Epistemological Chicken', in Science as
Practice and Culture, A. Pickering, (ed.), Chicago University Press, Chicago, pp:
301-26.
Commoner, B. 1971, The Closing Circle: Nature, Man and Technology, Alfred
Knopf, New York.
Connolly, W. 1985, 'Taylor, Foucault and Otherness', Political Theory, 13 (3), pp:
365-76.
Cooper, R. 1997, Assemblage Notes, Centre for Social Theory and Technology,
http://www.keele.ac.uk/depts/stt/staff/rc/pubs-RC1.htm - Keele University.
Council on Environmental Quality, 1981, The Global 2000 Report to the
President of the United States, Pergamon Press, New York.
Cramer, J., Eyerman, R., and Jamison, A. 1987, 'The Knowledge Interests of the
Environment Movement and its Potential for Influencing the Development of
Science', in The Social Direction of the Public Sciences, S. Blume and et al,
(eds.), Reidel Publishing Co, Dordrecht & Boston, pp: 89-115.
Crawford, T. 1993, 'An Interview with Bruno Latour', Configurations, 1 (2), pp:
247-68.
Crosby, A. 1986, Ecological Imperialism: The Biological Expansion of Europe
900-1900, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Dallmayr, F. 1991, Life-world, Modernity, and Critique: paths between
Heidegger and the Frankfurt School, Polity Press, Cambridge.
Darier, E. 1995, Environmental Governmentality: The Case of Canada's Green
Plan, Series 95-4, School of Policy Studies, Queen’s University, Canada.
231
Darier, E. 1999a, (ed.), Discourses of the Environment, Blackwell Publishers,
Oxford.
Darier, E. 1999b, 'Foucault against Environmental Ethics', in Discourses of the
Environment, E. Darier, (ed.), Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, pp: 217-40.
Darier, E. 1999c, 'Foucault and the Environment: An Introduction', in Discourses
of the Environment, E. Darier, (ed.), Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, pp: 1- 33.
Dean, M. 1994, Critical and Effective Histories: Foucault’s Methods and
Historical Sociology, Routledge, London.
Dean, M. 1998a, 'Questions of Method', in The Politics of Constructionism, I.
Velody and R. Williams, (eds.), Sage, London, pp: 183-99.
Dean, M. 1998b, 'Risk, Calculable and Incalculable', Soziale Welt (49), pp: 25-42.
Deleuze, G. 1988, Foucault, Sean Hand, translator, University of Minnesota
Press, Minneapolis.
Dews, P. 1987, Logics of Disintegration: Poststructuralist Thought and the
Claims of Critical Theory, Verso, London.
DiNorcia, V. 1974, 'From Critical Theory to Critical Ecology', Telos (22), pp: 8595.
Donnelly, M. 1992, 'Foucault's Use of the Notion of Biopower', in Michel
Foucault Philosopher, T. Armstrong, (ed.), Harvester Wheatsheaf, Hemel
Hempstead, pp: 199-203.
Donzelot. 1993, 'The Promotion of the Social', in Foucault's New Domains, M.
Gane and T. Johnson, (eds.), Routledge, London, pp: 106-38.
Donzelot, J. 1979, Policing the Family, Hutchinson, London.
Douglas, M. 1966, Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of Pollution
and Taboo, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Douglas, M. 1975, Implicit Meanings: Essays in Anthropology, Routledge &
Kegan Paul, London.
Dreyfus, H., and Rabinow, P. 1982, Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and
Hermeneutics, Harvester Wheatsheaf, New York.
232
Eckersley, R. 1989, 'Green Politics and the New Class: Selfishness or Virtue?',
Political Studies, 37, pp: 205-37.
Eckersley, R. 1990, 'Habermas and Green Political Thought: Two Road
Diverging', Theory & Society, 19, pp: 739-76.
Eckersley, R. 1992, Environmentalism and Political Theory, UCL Press, London.
Eckersley, R. 1995, Markets, the State and the Environment, Macmillan, South
Melbourne.
Eder, K. 1982, 'A New Social Movement?', Telos (52), pp: 5-20.
Eder, K. 1988, 'Critique of Habermas’s Contribution to the Sociology of Law',
Law and Society Review, 22 (5), pp: 931-44.
Eder, K. 1990a, 'The Cultural Code of Modernity and the Problem of Nature: A
Critique of the Naturalistic Notion of Progress', in Rethinking Progress:
Movements, Forces and Ideas at the End of the 20th Century, J. Alexander and P.
Sztompka, (eds.), Unwin Hyman, London, pp: 67-85.
Eder, K. 1990b, 'The Rise of Counter-culture Movements Against Modernity:
Nature as a New Field of Class Struggle', Theory, Culture and Society (7), pp: 2147.
Eder, K. 1993, New Politics of Class: Social Movements and Cultural Dynamics
in Advanced Societies, Sage, London.
Eder, K. 1996, The Social Construction of Nature, Sage, London.
Egerton, J. 1983, 'The History of Ecology: Achievements and Opportunities (Part
1)', Journal of the History of Biology, 16 (2), pp: 268-71.
Ehlrich, P. 1968, The Population Bomb, Ballantine Books, New York.
Foucault, M. 1970, The Order of Things, Pantheon, New York.
Foucault, M. 1972, The Archaeology of Knowledge, Pantheon, New York.
Foucault, M. 1979a, 'Curvier’s Position in the History of Biology', Critique of
Anthropology, 4 (13/1), pp: 125-30.
Foucault, M. 1979b, Discipline and Punish, Vintage Books, New York.
233
Foucault, M. 1980a, 'Confessions of the Flesh', in Power/Knowledge, C. Gordon,
(ed.), Pantheon, New York, pp: 194-228.
Foucault, M. 1980b, 'The Politics of Health in the Eighteenth Century', in
Power/Knowledge, C. Gordon, (ed.), Pantheon, New York, pp: 166-82.
Foucault, M. 1980c, 'Questions on Geography', in Power/Knowledge`, C. Gordon,
(ed.), Pantheon, New York, pp: 63-77.
Foucault, M. 1980d, 'Truth and Power', in Power/Knowledge, C. Gordon, (ed.),
Pantheon, New York, pp: 109-33.
Foucault, M. 1980e, 'Two Lectures', in Power/Knowledge, C. Gordon, (ed.), pp:
78-108.
Foucault, M. 1981a, 'Foucault at the College de France. I. A Course Summary:
history of systems of thought, 1978', Philosophy & Social Criticism, 8 (2), pp:
236-42.
Foucault, M. 1981b, 'Foucault at the College de France. II. A Course Summary:
history of systems of thought, 1979', Philosophy & Social Criticism, 8 (3), pp:
351-59.
Foucault, M. 1981c, 'Omnes et Singulatim: Towards a Criticism of Political
Reason', in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, S. McMurrim, (ed.),
University of Utah Press, Salt Lake City, pp: 225-54.
Foucault, M. 1981d, 'The Order of Discourse', in Untying the Text: a Poststructuralist Reader, R. Young, (ed.), Routledge & Kegan Paul, Boston.
Foucault, M. 1982, 'The Subject and Power', in Michel Foucault: Beyond
Structuralism and Hermeneutics, H. Dreyfus and P. Rabinow, (eds.), Harvester
Wheatsheaf, New York, pp: 208-26.
Foucault, M. 1983, 'Structuralism and Poststructuralism: An Interview with
Michel Foucault', Telos (55), pp: 195-211.
Foucault, M. 1984a, 'Nietzsche, Genealogy, History', in The Foucault Reader, P.
Rabinow, (ed.), Penguin, Hammondsworth, pp: 76-100.
Foucault, M. 1984b, 'What is Enlightenment?', in The Foucault Reader: An
Introduction to Foucault's Thought, P. Rabinow, (ed.), Penguin,
Hammondsworth, pp: 32-50.
234
Foucault, M. 1988a, 'The Ethic of Care for the Self as a Practice of Freedom', in
The Final Foucault, J. Bernauer and D. Rasmussen, (eds.), MIT Press, Boston, pp:
1-20.
Foucault, M. 1988b, 'The Political Technology of Individuals', in Technologies of
the Self, L. Martin, H. Gutman, and P. Hutton, (eds.), University of
Massachutsetts Press, Cambridge, pp: 14-69.
Foucault, M. 1988c, 'Truth, Power, Self: An Interview with Michel Foucault', in
Technologies of the self, L. Martin, H. Gutman, and P. Hutton, (eds.), University
of Massachutsetts Press, Cambridge, pp: 9-15
Foucault, M. 1990, History of Sexuality, Volume One, Penguin, Hammondsworth.
Foucault, M. 1991a, 'Adorno, Horkheimer, and Marcuse: Who Is a Negator of
History?', in Remarks on Marx, Semiotext(e), New York, pp: 115-29.
Foucault, M. 1991b, 'The Discourse on Power', in Remarks on Marx, Semiotex(t),
New York, pp: 147-81.
Foucault, M. 1991c, 'Governmentality', in The Foucault Effect: Studies in
Governmentality, G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P. Miller, (eds.), Harvester
Wheatsheaf, London, pp: 87-104.
Foucault, M. 1991d, 'The Subject, Knowledge, and the History of Truth', in
Remarks on Marx, Semiotext(e) Books, New York, pp: 43-82.
Foucault, M. 1991e, 'What Is Enlightenment?', in The Foucault Reader, P.
Rabinow, (ed.), Penguin, Hammondsworth, pp: 32-50.
Fox, W. 1990, Towards a Transpersonal Ecology: Developing New Foundations
for Environmentalism, Shambala, Boston.
Fraser, N. 1989, 'Foucault on Modern Power: Empirical Insights and Normative
Confusions' in Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse and Gender in Contemporary
Social Theory, Polity Press, Cambridge, pp: 17-34.
Gane, M., and Johnson, T. 1993, (eds.) Foucault's New Domains, Routledge,
London.
Gemes, K. 1992, 'Nietzsche's Critique of Truth', Philosophy & Phenomenological
Research, Vol LII (No 1).
Giddens, A. 1982, Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory, Macmillan, London.
235
Glacken, C. 1967, Traces on the Rhodian Shore, University of California Press,
Berkeley.
Goldsmith, E. 1972, A Blueprint for Survival, Stacey Ltd, London.
Golley, F. 1993, History of the Ecosystem Concept in Ecology, Yale University
Press, New Haven.
Gordon, C. 1980a, 'Afterword', in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interview & Other
Writings, 1972-1977, C. Gordon, (ed.), Pantheon, New York, pp: 229-59.
Gordon, C. 1980b, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interview & Other Writings,
1972-1977, Pantheon, New York.
Gordon, C. 1986, 'Question, Ethos, Event: Foucault on Kant and Enlightenment',
Economy and Society, 15 (1), pp: 71-87.
Gordon, C. 1991, 'Governmental Rationality: An Introduction', in The Foucault
Effect: Studies in Governmentality, G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P. Miller, (eds.),
Harvester Wheatsheaf, London, pp: 1-51.
Gordon, G. 1987, 'The Soul of the Citizen: Max Weber and Michel Foucault on
Rationality and Government', in Max Weber: Rationality and Modernity, S. Lash,
and S. Whimster, (eds.), Allen & Unwin, London, pp: 293-316.
Grove, R. 1990, 'Colonial Conservation, Ecological Harmony and Popular
Resistance: Towards a Global Synthesis', in Imperialism and the Natural World,
J. Mackenzie, (ed.), Manchester University Press, Manchester, pp: 15-50.
Grove, R. 1992, 'Origins of Western Environmentalism', Scientific American.
(July), pp: 42-7.
Grove, R. 1995, Green Imperialism: Colonial Expansion, Tropical Island Edens
and the Origins of Environmentalism, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Grumley. 1989, History and Totality: Radical Historicism from Hegel to
Foucault, Routledge, London.
Grundmann. 1991a, 'The Ecological Challenge to Marxism', New Left Review
(187), pp: 103-18.
Grundmann. 1991b, Marxism and Ecology, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
236
Gutting, G. 1989, Michel Foucault's Archaeology of Scientific Reason, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Habermas, J. 1971, 'Technology and Science as Ideology', in Towards a Rational
Society, Heinemann, London.
Habermas, J. 1974, Theory and Practice, Heinemann, London.
Habermas, J. 1976, 'Theory and Practice in a Scientific Civilization', in Critical
Sociology: Selected Readings, P. Connerton, (ed.), Penguin, Hammondsworth, pp:
330-47.
Habermas, J. 1978, Knowledge and Human Interests, Heinemann, London.
Habermas, J. 1981a, 'The Dialectics of Rationalisation', Telos (49), pp: 5-31.
Habermas, J. 1981b, 'Modernity Versus Postmodernity', New German Critique
(22), pp: 3-14.
Habermas, J. 1981c, 'New Social Movements', Telos (49), pp: 33-7.
Habermas, J. 1982a, 'The Entwinement of Myth and Enlightenment: Re-reading
Dialectic of Enlightenment', New German Critique (26), pp: 13-30.
Habermas, J. 1982b, 'A Reply to My Critics', in Habermas: Critical Debates, J.
Thompson and D. Held, (eds.), Macmillan, London.
Habermas, J. 1984, Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 1, Beacon Press,
Boston.
Habermas, J. 1985, The Philosophical Discourse on Modernity, Polity Press,
Oxford.
Habermas, J. 1987, Theory of Communicative Action, Volume 2, Beacon Press,
Boston.
Habermas, J. 1989, 'Taking Aim at the Heart of the Present', in The New
Conservatism, J. Habermas, (ed.), MIT Press, Boston.
Hacking, I. 1983, Representing and Intervening, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Hacking, I. 1986a, 'The Archaeology of Foucault', in Foucault: A Critical Reader,
D. Hoy, (ed.), Basil Blackwell.
237
Hacking, I. 1986b, 'Making Up People', in Reconstructing Individualism, T.
Heller et al (eds.), Stanford.
Hallman, M. 1991, 'Nietzsche's Environmental Ethics', Environmental Ethics, 13,
pp: 99-125.
Hardin, G. 1968, 'The Tragedy of the Commons', Science (162), pp: 1243-48.
Harris, R., and Milkis, S. 1989, The Politics of Regulatory Change, Oxford
University Press, New York.
Hart, D., and Victor, D. 1993, 'Scientific Elites and the Making of US Policy for
Climate Change Research, 1957-74', Social Studies of Science, 23, pp: 643-80.
Hass, P. 1990, 'Obtaining International Environmental Protection through
Epistemic Consensus', Millennium, 19 (3), pp: 347-63.
Hayim, G. 1992, 'Naturalism and the Crisis of Rationalism in Habermas', Social
Theory & Practice, 18 (2), pp: 187-209.
HazNews. 1998, ‘US hazwaste market stabilizing?’, HazNews (124), pp: 1.
Held, D. 1980, Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas,
Hutchinson, London.
Hewitt, M. 1983, 'Biopolitics and Social Policy', Theory, Culture & Society, 2 (1),
pp: 67-84.
Hindess, B. 1987, 'Rationalisation and the Characterization of Modern Society', in
Max Weber: Rationality and Modernity, S. Lash and S. Whimster, (eds.), Allen
and Unwin, London, pp: 137-53.
Hindess, B. 1996, Discourses of Power: From Hobbes to Foucault, Blackwell,
Oxford.
Honneth, A. 1986, 'Foucault and Adorno: Two Forms of the Critique of
Modernity', Thesis Eleven (15).
Honneth, A. 1991, The Critique of Power: Reflective Stages in a Critical Social
Theory, Baynes, K., translator, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Horkheimer, M. 1985, The Eclipse of Reason, Continuum, New York.
238
Hoy, D. 1986, 'Power, Repression, Progress: Foucault, Lukes, and the Frankfurt
School', in Foucault: A Critical Reader, D. Hoy, (ed.), Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
Hoy, D. 1994, 'Foucault and Critical Theory', paper to Foucault: Politics and
Freedom Conference, Philosophy Department, University of Melbourne.
Ingram, D. 1987, Habermas and the Dialectic of Reason, Yale University Press,
New Haven.
Isenberg, B. 1991, 'Habermas on Foucault: Critical Remarks', Acta Sociologica,
34.
Jamison, A. 1993, 'National Political Cultures and the Exchange of Knowledge:
the Case of Systems Ecology', in Denationalizing Science, E. Crawford, T. Shinn,
and S. Sorlin (eds.), Kluwer Academic Publishers, Amsterdam, pp: 187-208.
Jamison, A., and Eyerman, R. 1994, Seeds of the Sixties, University of California
Press, Berkeley.
Janicaud, D. 1992, 'Rationality, Force and Power: Foucault and Habermas's
Criticisms', in Michel Foucault Philosopher, T. Armstrong, (ed.), Harvester
Wheatsheaf, Hemel Hempstead.
Jasanoff, S. 1990, The Fifth Branch: Science Advisers as Policy makers, Harvard
University Press, Cambridge.
Jasanoff, S. 1992, 'Science, Politics and the Renegotiation of Expertise at EPA',
Osiris (Series 2) (7), pp: 195-217.
Jay, M. 1973, The Dialectical Imagination: a History of the Frankfurt School and
the Institute of Social Research, 1923-1950, Heinemann, London.
Kelly, M. 1994a, Critique and Power: Recasting the Foucault/Habermas Debate,
MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Kelly, M. 1994b, 'Foucault, Habermas, and the Self-referentiality of Critique', in
Critique and Power: Recasting the Foucault/Habermas Debate, M. Kelly, (ed.),
MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Krips, H. 1990, 'Power and Resistance', Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 20 (2),
pp: 170-82.
239
Kusch, M. 1991, Foucault's Strata and Fields: An Investigation into
Archaeological and Genealogical Science Studies, Kluwer Academic Publishers,
Dordrecht.
Kwa, C. 1987, 'Representations of Nature Mediating Between Ecology and
Science Policy: The Case of the International Biological Programme', Social
Studies of Science, 17, pp: 413-42.
Kwa, C. 1993, 'Radiation Ecology, Systems Ecology and the Management of the
Environment', in Science and Nature: Essays in the History of the Environmental
Sciences, M. Shortland, (ed.), British Society for the History of Science, London,
pp: 213-49.
Lash, S. 1984, 'Genealogy and the Body: Foucault/Deleuze/Nietzsche', Theory,
Culture & Society, 2 (2), pp: 1-17.
Lash, S. 1987, 'Modernity or Modernism? Weber and Contemporary Social
Theory', in Max Weber: Rationality and Modernity, Allen & Unwin, London, pp:
335-77.
Latour, B. 1983, 'Give Me a Laboratory and I Will Raise the World', in Science
Observed, K. Knorr-Cetina and M. Mulkay, (eds.), Sage, London, pp: 141-72.
Latour, B. 1986, 'The Powers of Association', in Power, Action and Belief: A New
Sociology of Knowledge? J. Law, (ed.), Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, pp:
264-80.
Latour, B. 1987, Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers
Through Society, Open University Press, Milton Keynes.
Latour, B. 1991, 'The Impact of Science Studies on Political Philosophy', Science,
Technology & Human Values, 16 (1), pp: 3-19.
Latour, B. 1993, We Have Never Been Modern, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
Latour, B. 1994, 'Pragmatogonies: A Mythical Account of How Humans and
Nonhumans Swap Properties', American Behavioural Scientist, 37 (6), pp: 791808.
Latour, B. 1997, On actor-network theory: A few clarifications, Centre for Social
Theory and Technology, http://www.keele.ac.uk/depts/stt/staff/ - Keele
University.
240
Law, J. 1986, Power, Action and Belief: A New Sociology of Knowledge?,
Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Law, J. 1991a, 'Power, Discretion and Strategy', in A Sociology of Monsters:
Essays on Power, Technology and Domination, J. Law, (ed.), Routledge, London,
pp: 165-91.
Law, J. 1991b, A Sociology of Monsters: Essays on Power, Technology and
Domination, Routledge, London.
Law, J. 1994, Organizing Modernity, Blackwell, Oxford.
Law, J. 1997, Typology and the naming of complexity, 'Centre for Social Theory
and Technology Internet draft, 9 July 1997', Keele University,
http://www.keele.ac.uk/depts/stt/staff/jl/pubs-JL3.htm - Keele University.
Leiss, W. 1975, 'The Problem of Man and Nature in the Work of the Frankfurt
School', Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 5, pp: 163-72.
Lowe, P., and Goyder, J. 1983, Environmental Groups in Politics, Allen &
Unwin, London.
Luhmann, N. 1989, Ecological Communication, Polity Press, Cambridge.
Luhmann, N. 1994, 'The Modernity of Science', New German Critique (61), pp: 923.
Luke, T. 1988, 'The Dreams of Deep Ecology', Telos (76), pp: 65-92.
Luke, T. 1999, 'Environmentality as Green Governmentality', in Discourses of the
Environment, E. Darier, (ed.), Blackwell Publishers, London, pp: 121-51.
Lukes, S. 1974, Power: a Radical View, Macmillan, London.
Macey, D. 1994, The Lives of Michel Foucault, Vintage, London.
MacNeill, J., Winsemius, P., and Yakushiji, T. 1991, Beyond Interdependence:
The Meshing of the World's Economy and the Earth's Ecology, Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
Magnus, B., and Higgins, K. 1996, 'Introduction', in The Cambridge Companion
to Nietzsche, B. Magnus and K. Higgins, (eds.), Cambridge University Press, New
York, pp: 1- 17.
241
Marcus, A. 1991, 'EPA’s Organisational Structure', Law and Contemporary
Problems, 54 (4), pp: 5-40.
Marcuse, H. 1968, One Dimensional Man: the Ideology of Industrial Society,
Sphere Books, London.
Margolis, J. 1993, 'Redeeming Foucault', in Foucault and the Critique of
Institutions, J. Y. Caputo, M., (ed.), Pennsylvania State University Press,
University Park, Pa., pp: 41-59.
Marx, K. 1974, 'Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts', in Marx's Concept of
Man, T. Bottomore, (ed.), Penguin, Hammondswoth, pp: 90-196.
Marx, K. 1976, Capital, Volume 1, Penguin, Hammondsworth.
Mathews, F. 1991, The Ecological Self, Barnes & Noble Books, Maryland.
McCarthy, T. 1978, The Critical Theory of Jurgen Habermas, Hutchinson,
London.
McCarthy, T. 1984, 'Translator's Introduction', in J. Habermas, Theory of
Communicative Action, Beacon Press, Boston.
McCarthy, T. 1990, 'The Critique of Impure Reason: Foucault and the Frankfurt
School', Political Theory, 18 (3), pp: 437-69.
McIntosh, R. 1985, The Background of Ecology, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
McNay, L. 1994, Foucault: A Critical Introduction, Polity Press, Cambridge.
McWhorter, L. 1989, 'Culture or Nature? The Function of the Term 'Body' in the
Work of Michel Foucault', The Journal of Philosophy, 86 (11), pp: 608-14.
Meadows, D. H., Meadows, D. L., Randers, J., et al. 1972, The Limits to Growth,
Signet, New York.
Melucci. 1989, Nomads of the Present: Social Movements and Individual Needs
in Contemporary Society, Hutchinson Radius, London.
Miller, M. 1994, 'Intersystemic Discourse and Coordinated Dissent: A Critique of
Luhmann's Concept of Ecological Communication', Theory, Culture & Society,
Vol 11, pp: 101-21.
242
Miller, P. 1987, Domination and Power, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Miller, P., and Rose, N. 1993, 'Governing Economic Life', in Foucault's New
Domains, M. Gane and T. Johnson, (eds.), Routledge, London, pp: 75-105.
Mitman, G. 1988, 'From Population to Society: The Cooperative Metaphors of
W.C. Allee and A.E. Emerson', Journal of the History of Biology, 21 ( 2), pp: 17394.
Moore, R. 1993, 'Law, Normativity, and the Level Playing Field: The Production
of Right in American labor Law', in Foucault and the Critique of Institutions, J.
Caputo and M. Yount, (eds.), Pennsylvania State University Press, University
Park, Pa., pp: 165-89.
Moss, J. 1998, The Later Foucault: Politics and Philosophy, Sage, London.
Mulkay, M. 1979, Science and the Sociology of Knowledge, George Allen &
Unwin, London.
Naess, A. 1977, 'Spinoza and Ecology', in Speculum Spinozanum, S. Hessing,
(ed.), Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Naess, A. 1985, 'Identification as a Source of Deep Ecological Attitudes', in Deep
Ecology, M. Tobias, (ed.), Avant Books, San Diego.
Naess, A. 1986, Self-realization: An Ecological Approach to Being in the World,
Murdoch University, Perth.
Nietzsche, F. 1989, On the Genealogy of Morals, Vintage, New York.
O'Neill, J. 1987, 'The Disciplinary Society: From Weber to Foucault', British
Journal of Sociology, 37 (1), pp: 43-60.
Ottmann, H. 1982, 'Cognitive Interests and Self-Reflection', in Habermas:
Critical Debates, J. Thompson and D. Held, (eds.), Macmillan, London, pp: 7997.
Owen, D. 1994, Maturity and Modernity: Nietzsche, Weber, Foucault and the
Ambivalence of Reason, Routledge, London..
Palliadino, P. 1991, 'Defining Ecology: Ecological Theories, Mathematical
Models, and Applied Biology in the 1960s and 1970s', Journal of the History of
Biology, 24 (2), pp: 223-43.
243
Parsons, S. 1992, 'Explaining Technology and Society: The Problem of Nature in
Habermas', Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 22 (2), pp: 218-30.
Patton, P. 1989, 'Taylor and Foucault on Power and Freedom', Political Studies,
XXXVII (2), pp: 260-76.
Patton, P. 1994, 'Foucault's Subject of Power', Political Theory Newsletter, 6 (1),
pp: 60-71.
Pepper, D. 1984, The Roots of Modern Environmentalism, Croom Held, London.
Platt, M. 1988, 'Nature and an order of rank (according to Nietzsche)', The
Journal of Value Inquiry (22), pp: 147-65.
Porritt, J. 1894, Seeing Green: The Politics of Ecology Explained, Basil
Blackwell, Oxford.
Putz, P. 1981, 'Nietzsche and Critical Theory', Telos (50), pp: 103-14.
Rabinow, P. 1984a, (ed.) The Foucault Reader, Penguin, Hammondsworth.
Rabinow, P. 1984b, 'Introduction', in The Foucault Reader, P. Rabinow, (ed.),
Penguin, Hammondsworth, pp: 3-29.
Richters, A. 1988, 'Modernity-Postmodernity Controversies: Habermas and
Foucault', Theory, Culture & Society, 5, pp: 611-43.
Rose, N. 1993, 'Government, Authority and Expertise in Advanced Liberalism',
Economy and Society, 22 (3), pp: 283-99.
Rose, N. 1999, Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political Thought, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Rose, N., and Miller, P. 1992, 'Political Power Beyond the State: Problematics of
Government', British Journal of Sociology, 43 (2), pp: 173-205.
Rouse, J. 1987, Knowledge and Power: Towards a Political Philosophy of
Science, Cornell University Press, Ithaca.
Rouse, J. 1991, 'The Dynamics of Power and Knowledge in Science', The Journal
of Philosophy, 38, pp: 658-65.
244
Rouse, J. 1993, 'Foucault and the Natural Sciences', in Foucault and the Critique
of Institutions, J. Caputo and M. Yount, (eds.), Pennsylvania State University
Press, University Park, Pa., pp: 137-62.
Rouse, J. 1994, 'Power/Knowledge', in The Cambridge Companion to Foucault,
G. Gutting, (ed.), Cambridge University Press, New York, pp: 92-114.
Rutherford, P. 1993, 'Foucault's Concept of Biopower: Implications for
Environmental Politics', in Ecopolitics VI: Interactions and Actions, I. Thomas,
(ed.), Royal Melbourne Institute of Technology, Melbourne, pp: G7-15.
Rutherford, P. 1994a, 'The Administration of Life: Ecological Discourse as
'Intellectual Machinery of Government'', Australian Journal of Communication,
21 (3), pp: 40-55.
Rutherford, P. 1994b, 'The Political Economy of Environmental Policy - Review',
Australian Journal of Political Science, 29 (3), pp: 597-8.
Rutherford, P. 1997a, 'Policing Nature: Ecology, Natural Science and Biopolitics',
in Foucault: The Legacy, C. O'Farrell, (ed.), Queensland University of
Technology, Kelvin Grove, Qld., pp: 546-62.
Rutherford, P. 1997b, 'Review of B. Hindess, Discourses of Power: from Hobbes
to Foucault', Australian Journal of International Affairs, 51 (1), pp: 121-2.
Rutherford, P. 1997c, 'Review of F. Mathews (ed) Ecology and Democracy',
Political Theory Newsletter, 8 (2), pp: 63-6.
Rutherford, P. 1999a, 'Ecological Modernisation and Ecological Risk', in
Discourses of the Environment, E. Darier, (ed.), Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, pp:
95-118.
Rutherford, P. 1999b, 'The Entry of Life into History', in Discourses of the
Environment, E. Darier, (ed.), Blackwell Publishers, Oxford, pp: 37-62.
Schaffer, S. 1991, 'The Eighteenth Brumaire of Bruno Latour', Studies in the
History and Philosophy of Science, 22, pp: 174-92.
Schneider, W. 1990, 'Geographical Reform and Municipal Imperialism in France,
1870-80', in Imperialism and the Natural World, J. Mackenzie, (ed.), Manchester
University Press, Manchester, pp: 90-117.
Sciulli, D. 1994, 'An Interview with Niklas Luhmann', Theory, Culture & Society,
11, pp: 37-68.
245
Shapin, S., and Schaffer, S. 1985, Leviathan and the Air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle
and the Experimental Life, Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Smart, B. 1983, Foucault, Marxism and Critique, Routledge & Kegan Paul,
London.
Smith, N. 1993, 'Social Power and the Domination of Nature', History of the
Human Sciences, 6 (3), pp: 101-10.
Strydom, P. 1990, 'Habermas and New Social Movements', Telos (85), pp: 15664.
Taylor, C. 1984, 'Foucault on Freedom and Truth', Political Theory, 12 (2), pp:
152-83.
Taylor, C. 1985, 'Connolly, Foucault and Truth', Political Theory, 13 (3), pp: 37785.
Taylor, P. 1988, 'Technocratic Optimism, H.T. Odum, and the Partial
Transformation of Ecological Metaphor after World War II', Journal of the
History of Biology, 21 (2), pp: 213-44.
Taylor, P., and Buttel, F. 1992, 'How do we Know we have Global Environmental
Problems? Science and the Globalization of Environmental Discourse', Geoforum,
23 (3), pp: 405-16.
Tully, J. 1997, 'An Ecological Ethics - an ethic of care of the environment as a
practice of freedom in conditions of conflict', paper to Environmental Justice and
Global Ethics for the Twenty-first Century Conference, 1997, University of
Melbourne.
Turner, B. 1984, The Body and Society: Explorations in Social Theory, Basil
Blackwell, Oxford.
Turner, B. 1987, 'The Rationalisation of the Body: Reflections on Modernity and
Discipline', in Max Weber, Rationality and Modernity, S. Lash and S. Whimster,
(eds.).
Turner, B. 1992, Regulating Bodies, Routledge, London.
Walker, K. 1989, 'The State in Environmental Management: The Ecological
Dimension', Political Studies, 37, pp: 25-38.
246
Ward, S. 1994, 'In the shadow of the deconstructed metanarratives: Baudrillard,
Latour and the end of realist epistemology', History of the Human Sciences, 7 (4),
pp: 73-94.
Warren, M. 1988, Nietzsche and Political Thought, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Wartenberg, T. 1990, The Forms of Power: From Domination to Transformation,
Temple University Press, Philadelphia.
Weale, A. 1992, The New Politics of Pollution, Manchester University Press,
Manchester.
Weber, M. 1968, Economy and Society, Bedminster Press, New York.
Wellmer, A. 1985, 'Reason, Utopia, and the Dialectic of Enlightenment', in
Habermas and Modernity, R. Bernstein, (ed.), Polity Press, pp: 35-66.
Wellmer, A. 1991, 'The Dialectic of Modernism and Postmodernism: The Critique
of Reason Since Adorno', in The Persistence of Modernity, A. Wellmer, (ed.),
Polity Press, Oxford, pp: 36-94.
West, D. 1996, An Introduction to Continental Philosophy, Polity Press,
Cambridge.
White, S. 1988, The Recent Work of Jurgen Habermas, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Whitebook, J. 1979, 'The Problem of Nature in Habermas', Telos (40), pp: 41-69.
Woolgar, S., and Latour, B. 1979, Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of
Scientific Facts, Sage, Beverly Hills.
Worster, D. 1987a, Nature's Economy, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Worster, D. 1987b, 'The Vulnerable Earth: Towards a Planetary History',
Environmental Review, 11 (2), pp: 87-103.
Worster, D. 1993a, 'The Shaky Ground of Sustainable Development', in The
Wealth of Nature, Oxford University Press, New York, pp: 142-55.
Worster, D. 1993b, The Wealth of Nature: Environmental History and the
Ecological Imagination, Oxford University Press, New York.
Worthington, E. 1983, The Ecological Century, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
247
Wynne, B. 1992, 'Carving Out Science (and Politics) in the Regulatory Jungle',
Social Studies of Science, 22, pp: 745-58.
Yearley, S. 1992, 'Green Ambivalence About Science: Legal-rational Authority
and the Scientific Legitimation of a Social Movement', British Journal of
Sociology, 43 (4), pp: 511-32.
Yoxen, E. 1981, 'Life as a Productive Force: Capitalising the Science and
Technology of Molecular Biology', in Science, Technology and the Labour
Process, L. Levidow and R. Young, (eds.), CSE Books, London, pp: 66-122.