OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
Chapter 82
The Psych opat h ol o g y
of Psych opat h s
Jérôme Englebert
Introduction
The objective of this article is to present a holistic conception of psychopathy inspired by
phenomenological psychopathology and to compare it with the mainstream nosographic
diagnosis. First, two major theoretical works dedicated to this nosographic entity are
discussed. One is German: Schneider’s Psychopathic Personalities (Schneider 1923). The
other is American: Cleckley’s The Mask of Sanity (Cleckley 1941). The well-known work of
Hare (Hare 2003) is then summarized, including the so-called Hare Psychopathy Checklist
(PCL-R), as well as the critique by Cooke et al. (Cooke and Michie 2001; Cooke et al. 2004,
2007, 2012).
Next, I illustrate how a structural-phenomenological approach enhances the psychopathological investigation of psychopathy. I first compare Binswanger’s conception of
mania with psychopathic functioning. Patients’ behavior is similar but the difference
relates to the dialectic between the ego and the alter ego. A patient with mania is affected
by a fundamental crisis of the ego, which a psychopath does not have. A second dimension relates to emotions and the adaptive dimension of psychopathy. An epistemological
discussion of the concept of emotions reveals that psychopaths are competent at managing emotional stimuli, which bestows a psychological advantage upon them. Finally, a
reflection enlightened by the contributions of phenomenological philosophy (Stein 1989;
Scheler 2008; Zahavi 2005, 2011) on empathy and sympathy clarifies the presentation of
“psychopathic being-in-the-world.” Starting with the tension between clinical practice and
criticism of the dominant diagnostic scales, we consider the “essential characteristics” of
the psychopathic disorder to be: reification of the alter ego without an ego-related disorder, emotional coldness as it provides adaptive benefits, and empathic skills without
sympathy.
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
868
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
Phenomenological Psychopathology of Psychopathy?
869
Phenomenological Psychopathology
of Psychopathy?
As a discipline, the purpose of phenomenological psychopathology is to identify the logical
structure of psychological functioning; it favors an approach based on understanding over
interpretation or explanation (Stanghellini 2009; Cutting 2012; Englebert 2013). One of its
aims is to identify the specific psychological features inherent to nosographic entities (the
dimension of eidetic phenomenology which focuses on the study of essences and identification of the basic components of phenomena—in the specific field of phenomenological
psychopathology, we speak about specific being-in-the-world). This method partly derives
from Minkowski’s legacy (1927, 1966), who suggested engaging in a “psychology of the pathological” rather than a “pathology of the psychological,” that is, seeking a structural understanding of psychological organization. This approach to psychopathology is intrinsically
clinical; the fundamentals of its research topics—phenomena—emerge from clinical practice (Stanghellini 2009; Nordgaard et al. 2013). This theoretical essay is informed by clinical
situations involving psychopaths who were interviewed in prison or in forensic centers.
If phenomenological psychopathology is interested, largely, in psychotic issues,
many studies do analyze other psychopathological disorders and psychopathological
manifestations (Broome et al. 2013). Work on the consideration of psychopathy in a phenomenological paradigm, as far as it is concerned, is recent. These studies are particularly
interested in the subject’s experiential dimension of time and show deficits in the imagination of the future and massive deficits with respect to mental time travel (McIlwain 2010;
Levy 2014; Berninger 2017). Let’s also mention the amazing approach of philosopher Glover
(2014) at Broadmoor high-security psychiatric hospital, in England, which analyzes the
moral and ethical dilemmas of the psychopathic subjects he went to meet (along with other
diagnoses). If they observe cognitive and moral bias in their speech, Glover’s hypothesis is
precisely to consider that such biases are in parallel to those seen in many people considered
normal (Glover 2014). Finally, let’s notice that the work of phenomenological psychopathology centered on psychopathy also discusses the emotional dimension of this disorder
(Beringer 2016; Englebert 2013b, 2015).
Strictly speaking, psychopathy or “psychopathic personality” is not a medical/psychiatric diagnosis. As we shall see, the psychopath is in fact absent from domineering nosography as in the DSM or ICD. However, this diagnosis is of considerable importance in many
contemporary debates on psychopathology because of its many clinical and societal issues.
Important links are identified between the psychopathic trait and other disorders such as antisocial personality disorder (Hare 2003; Hare et al. 1991), borderline personality (González
et al. 2016), and schizophrenia (Abu-Akel et al. 2015). From a developmental point of view,
many studies underline connections between certain psychological disorders of childhood
and adolescence (including Callous-unemotional line) and the development of psychopathic characteristics into adulthood (Bird and Viding 2014; Frick et al. 2014; Henry et al.
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
869
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
870
The Psychopathology of Psychopaths
2016; Muratori et al. 2016). Finally, a clarification of psychopathy is very important for the
forensic field and for the psychopathological reflection on criminal matters (Kiehl and
Sinnott-Armstrong 2013; Englebert 2013).
Historical and Contemporary Nosographies
Historical Background
Psychopathy was described in the early nineteenth century by Pinel. He observed that some
subjects presented a state of “manie sans délire” [insanity without delusion]1 (Pinel 1800: 151).
This early description is very important as it will enable us to explain the problem inherent
to modern conceptions of psychopathy. The work of Schneider and Cleckley gradually led
to a common and still current definition of psychopathy: a serious disorder or imbalance of
the character or personality that does not include psychosis or significant mental deficiency
(Schneider 1923; Cleckley 1941).
In contemporary nosographic work, psychopathy occupies an ambiguous position. This
uncertainty is reflected in its absence from the DSM-IV and DSM-5 and from the ICD-10
and future ICD-11.
According to Schneider (1923), psychopaths present antisocial manifestations and character disorders such as instability, irritability, inability to adapt, increased tendency to
commit crimes and consume drugs and alcohol, etc. In addition, psychopathy is said to be
characterized by a firm opposition to social rules and norms (see Table 82.1). Cleckley (1941)
identifies sixteen key signs that tend to describe a typical psychopath. This is an individual who
is characterized by superficial charm and high intelligence, who does not suffer from delusions
or irrational thinking, but also does not present signs of neurosis, guilt or shame. Lacking in
insight and presenting emotional reactions described as poor, a psychopath is also unable to
behave appropriately in interpersonal relations. Hypocritical and untruthful, egocentric and incapable of love, this is a person who cannot be counted on, is unable to learn from experience, or
follow a life plan. Finally, in addition to engaging in inadequately motivated antisocial behavior, a
psychopath demonstrates fantastic and objectionable behavior under the influence of alcohol, has
an impersonal and trivial sex life, and is unlikely to attempt suicide (see Table 82.1).
The Hare Psychopathy Checklist—Revised
Despite the lack of a definition in the international classifications, an important movement
in the literature attempted to formulate a pragmatic definition of psychopathy, based on
1 The traditional English translation is certainly not the best since it translates the word “manie”
[mania] with “insanity” as in French we mean by the word “folie.” For our purposes we will retain the
notion of mania to be able to dialogue with the theses of Binswanger on the manic state and to refine our
critique of the scale of Hare (see section on “Mad?: The Dialectics of Ego and Alter Ego in Psychopaths
and Manic Subjects”).
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
870
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
Historical and Contemporary Nosographies
871
the work of Hare (2003). The Hare Psychopathy Checklist—Revised (PCL-R) presents a set
of behavioral, interpersonal, and affective characteristics, including egocentricity; manipulation; insensitivity to others; irresponsibility; unstable relationships; impulsivity; lack of
empathy, remorse or guilt; and poor behavioral control. All of the PCL-R items is presented
in a summary table below (see Table 82.1). These signs are most likely to manifest in antisocial behavior (Hare 2003; Cooke et al. 2004). These antisocial characteristics are part of
the clinical picture, but they are not sufficient to diagnose psychopathy: a psychopathic subject necessarily has an antisocial personality, but the opposite is not necessarily true (Hare
2003; Hare et al. 1991; Cooke et al. 2004). According to this conception, one might consider
psychopathic personality to be a way of adapting to the world through affective and interpersonal experiences (Cooke et al. 2004), whereas the antisocial dimension is primarily a
set of behaviors involving transgressions against social laws and standards (Hare 2003; Hare
et al. 1991).
This work adds a specific set of items to the diagnosis of antisocial personality disorder in
order to isolate psychopathy as a specific nosographic entity. These items mainly concern the
interpersonal sphere and the affective dimension.
Table 82.1 Summary of criteria for psychopathy
Schneider’s criteria
Cleckley’s criteria
Hare’s criteria
Antisocial manifestations
Instability
Irritability
Inability to adapt
Tendency to commit
crimes
Drugs and alcohol
consumption
Characterized by a
firm opposition to
social rules and
norms
Superficial charm and high
intelligence
Does not suffer from delusions or
irrational thinking
Does not present signs of neurosis,
guilt, or shame
Lacking in insight
Emotional reactions described
as poor
Unable to behave appropriately in
interpersonal relations
Hypocritical and untruthful
Egocentric and incapable of love
This is a person who cannot be
counted on
Unable to learn from experience or
follow a life plan
Engaging in inadequately
motivated antisocial behavior
Demonstrates objectionable
behavior under the influence of
alcohol
Has an impersonal and trivial
sex life
Is unlikely to attempt suicide
Glibness and/or superficial charm
Grandiose sense of self-worth
Need for stimulation and/or
proneness to boredom
Pathological lying
Conning and/or manipulative
Lack of remorse or guilt
Shallow affect
Callous and/or lack of empathy
Parasitic lifestyle
Poor behavioral controls
Promiscuous sexual behavior
Early behavior problems
Lack of realistic, long-term goals
Impulsivity
Irresponsibility
Failure to accept responsibility
for own actions
Many short-term marital
relationships
Juvenile delinquency
Revocation of conditional release
Criminal versatility
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
871
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
872
The Psychopathology of Psychopaths
Other Instruments
I should make it clear that my goal is not to present a comprehensive examination of all
contemporary models of psychopathy. I will only include the presentation of three other
instruments: the Psychopathic Personality Inventory (Lilienfeld and Widows 2005; Uzieblo
et al. 2010; Skeem et al. 2011), the Triarchic Psychopathy Model (Patrick et al. 2009) and the
Self-Report of Psychopathy–Short Form (Paulhus et al. 2015). The former was revised in 2005
to become the PPI-R and now comprises 154 items organized into eight subscales (Lilienfeld
and Widows 2005). The items are grouped into two overarching and largely separate factors
(Factor 1—Fearless dominance: Social influence, Fearlessness, Stress immunity; Factor
2—Impulsive antisociality: Machiavellian egocentricity, Rebellious nonconformity, Blame
externalization, Carefree nonplanfulness), plus a third factor that is mainly dependent on
scores on the other two (Cold-heartedness).
Meanwhile, the Triarchic model (Patrick et al. 2009) suggests that different conceptions
of psychopathy emphasize three observable characteristics to varying degrees: boldness (low fear including stress-tolerance, toleration of unfamiliarity and danger, and high
self-confidence and social assertiveness), disinhibition (poor impulse control, including
problems with planning and foresight, lacking affect and urge control, demand for immediate gratification, and poor behavioral restraints), and meanness (Lacking empathy and
close attachments with others, disdain of close attachments, use of cruelty to gain empowerment, exploitative tendencies, defiance of authority, and destructive excitement seeking).
Finally, the Self-Report of Psychopathy–Short Form (SRP-SF) (Neumann and Pardini 2014;
Paulhus et al. 2015). Derived from and shown to correlate highly with the PCL (2003), the
SRP was developed for use in nonforensic populations as a practical and brief method to assess psychopathic traits. The latest version of this scale contains twenty-nine items and may
provide an efficient method of measuring psychopathic traits among larger samples. The
items are grouped into four dimensions of psychopathy: affective callousness, interpersonal
manipulation, antisociality, and erratic lifestyle.
Despite the interest of these tools, I formulate my critical discussion on the basis of the
PCL-R alone, as it remains the reference tool in criminological and psychopathological
assessments in the field of forensics. I also specify that none of these tools falls within the
scope of psychopathological phenomenology. Let’s now discuss Cooke et al.’s criticism of
the PCL-R’s factor structure, and particularly the presence of antisocial characteristics in
the diagnosis of psychopathy (this critique is also not made from a phenomenological point
of view).
Critique of the Presence of an Antisocial Dimension
Cooke et al.’s work (Cooke and Michie 2001; Cooke et al. 2004, 2007, 2012) stimulated a lively
debate on whether antisocial behaviors are or are not necessary in characterizing a subject
as a psychopath (Patrick 2006; Vitacco 2007). This ambiguity already existed in the work
of Schneider (1923) and Cleckley (1941). However, Cleckley was the researcher who most
clearly considered the possibility of a diagnosis of psychopathy without the presence of antisocial or illegal behavior (Cleckley 1941; Patrick 2006).
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
872
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
For a Psychopathological Approach of Psychopathy
873
The Comprehensive Assessment of Psychopathic Personality (CAPP) (Cooke and Michie
2001; Cooke et al. 2004, 2007, 2012) supports a different premise for defining the psychopathic entity. This conception, which has also been strongly influenced by Cleckley’s work,
is a multidimensional model of personality that consists in six dimensions and includes
each of the dysfunctional traits observed in psychopathic personality disorder, except for
the antisocial factor (and those related to sexual promiscuity and short-term cohabitation
relationships in the PCL-R). These authors consider the antisocial factor as “secondary
symptoms,” which follow from the psychopathic lifestyle. Thus, the model excludes the
elements related to the subject’s behavioral and criminal history. According to this criticism, the interpersonal and affective facets are the “central constituents” of the psychopathic
personality.
These developments are very important and allow one to go one step further in understanding the psychopathic individual’s psychology, but they still seem to stop short of one crucial step: carrying out an in-depth psychopathological study of psychopathy. I formulate my
critical discussion on the basis of the PCL-R alone, as it remains the reference tool in criminological and psychopathological assessments in the field of forensics.
For a Psychopathological Approach
of Psychopathy
My objective is to seek out the meaning structure and the signification that links different
signs of the disorder. According to Jaspers’s proposal (Jaspers 1913), the purpose in psychopathology is to understand the puzzle that is presented, observe the phenomena, and seek to obtain a significant overall picture. The starting point I suggest, paradoxically, is to examine manic
being-in-the-world.
Mad?: The Dialectics of Ego and Alter Ego in Psychopaths and
Manic Subjects
Ludwig Binswanger (1960) conducted a systematic analysis of the “reification of the alter ego” in
manic subjects. One of the fundamental characteristics of mania, in this author’s view, is seeing
other people as “interchangeable” and “utilitarian.” Although Binswanger does not address this
question, we can make an analogy with psychopathic functioning, which also presents this tendency to reify others. Psychopathic patients may say, for example: “The others are objects I use
when I need them; in my eyes, they are no more”; “What counts for me is the pleasure I get from
what I’m doing; the role of other people isn’t very important”; “I wanted to carry out a successful
robbery and no one was going to stop me. To succeed, I had to kill him. He didn’t represent anything more than an obstacle to me” [Source: own clinical experience].
Clearly, though, from a clinical perspective, mania and psychopathy are very different
phenomena. In what ways? When Pinel describes psychopathic behavior as “manie sans
délire,” it is important to define what is meant by “madness.” The work of Binswanger suggests
“the constitution of the alter ego” and “the ego” as a basis for discussing the dysfunctions
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
873
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
874
The Psychopathology of Psychopaths
of manic being-in-the-world (Binswanger 1960).2 His thesis is that, in manic subjects, a disorder affecting the constitution of the alter ego coexists with a disorder of the constitution of
the ego, or I:
If in mania the alter ego is not completely constituted, and thus remains largely a stranger, or
even a strange thing—a mere object taken, pushed aside and rejected, used and consumed by
something—then the causes are naturally not in the alter ego but in the ego.
(Binswanger 1960: 93; my translation)
This observation is critical since it presents mania as a subclass of psychosis, which
Binswanger considers, based on Husserl’s work, as a failure of “appresentation” [Appräsentation]. When two people meet, “what is present to us is different but is accompanied by
the same appresentation” (Binswanger 1960: 75). These two people share a set of common
representations that allow them to consider each other as an alter ego and to share a common
world. Thus, in Binswanger’s understanding of the term, appresentation is an intersubjective, intuitive, and precognitive phenomenon that enables one to form relationships and that
must necessarily be shared by the various partners. This a priori is crucial for the sharing of
common meaning and natural self-evidence in social exchanges. It is precisely this faculty
that is said to be deficient in psychotic pathologies (including mania).
Binswanger cites the example of one of his manic patients, Elsa Strauss, who entered a
church and interrupted the ceremony to compliment the pianist and ask him for private
lessons, offending the whole congregation. Words and actions, taken out of context, are not
fundamentally incoherent or delirious, but they show a “failure of appresentation in mania
and . . . the impossibility of constituting a common world” (Binswanger 1960: 78). The essence of psychosis in Binswanger’s view is to escape this implicit common appresentation.
This thesis can be superimposed on modern concepts of psychosis according to phenomenological psychopathology (Parnas et al. 2002; Stanghellini 2004; Sass 2014). For Binswanger,
the manic reification of the other and the problem affecting the alter ego can be situated in a
disorder affecting a psychotic ego. The determining factor in discriminating between manic
and psychopathic subjects is at this level: the former have a disorder of the constitution of the
alter ego explained by a disorder of the ego, while the latter have the same disorder but with
an intact ego.
The Core Characteristic of Psychopathy: Reification of Others
Without an Ego-related Disorder
The major difference between manic and psychopathic reification of the other is clearly
identifiable by clinicians. For manic patients, other people are just a casual means of
implementing their own projects, of enjoying themselves or their grandiosity. Their
instrumentalization of others is direct, clearly pre-reflexive, even “naïve.”
They do not even try to imagine what goes on in other people’s minds, because this does
not play a role in their projects. Their empathetic awareness of other people is non-existent
2
For an overview of the concept of being-in-the-world, refer to selected papers of Ludwig Binswanger
(1963) and for a presentation of the manic mode of being-in-the-world, see Broome et al. (2013: 197–203).
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
874
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
For a Psychopathological Approach of Psychopathy
875
(however, they can also be exquisitely sensitive to the emotions of others and can feel
responsible—in a grandiose way—for all of their suffering). In contrast, for psychopaths,
other people are a means of gaining power and pursuing their goals in a cold, insidious way.
Their instrumentalization of others has a reflective, well-thought-out component, which is
somewhat “Machiavellian.” They may well use imagination and “theory of mind” in order to
deceive, lie, and misuse others to achieve their own ends.
Thanks to Binswanger’s analysis of the crisis of the ego and the alter ego, we can refine
this description. The radical and fundamental difference between manic and psychopathic
subjects is that the latter do not present problems with the ego or I; to put it more simply, they
do not have psychotic symptoms. A psychopath presents a disorder affecting the alter ego,
via the reification of others (a symptom shared with manic subjects) but without presenting
an ego-related disorder (a symptom not shared with manic subjects). Unlike a manic subject, a psychopath is able to maintain a stable ego and a coherent identity while still reifying
others. For the psychopath, the alter ego problem is not secondary to a problem with the ego
in its function as an appresentative structure.
Now let us reconsider the twenty items of the PCL-R. Based on the recommendations
of the CAPP (Cooke and Michie 2001; Cooke et al. 2004, 2007, 2012), I eliminate the socalled secondary items, which are less relevant to a psychopathological approach. The remaining thirteen items are as follows: 1. Glibness and/or superficial charm; 2. Grandiose
sense of self-worth; 3. Need for stimulation and/or proneness to boredom; 4. Pathological lying;
5. Conning and/or manipulative; 6. Lack of remorse or guilt; 7. Shallow affect; 8. Callous and/
or lack of empathy; 9. Parasitic lifestyle; 13. Lack of realistic, long-term goals; 14. Impulsivity; 15.
Irresponsibility; 16. Failure to accept responsibility for own actions.
The semiological picture presented above describes manic subjects just as well as
psychopaths. Needless to say, I don’t think these two diagnostic entities are the same. Because
it limits its analyses to a survey of interpersonal and affective dimensions considered as isolable signs, and does not provide a structural and psychopathological synthesis, this model is
unable to explain the difference between mania and psychopathy.
Still, in the light of Pinel’s proposal to consider psychopathy as “insanity without delusion” [“manie sans délire”], we should not be surprised by this finding. The overview of
Binswanger’s work highlighted that the difference between mania and psychopathy is
located not really at the level of strictly behavioral signs but at the psychopathological level,
based on the essential dialectic between the alter ego and the ego. Hence the decisive affiliation of mania with psychosis and not that of psychopathy. The latter should be considered
a personality disorder. This allows us to remember that, of course, these two disorders are
fundamentally and essentially different from a psychopathological point of view and with
regard to their respective mode of being-in-the-world.
Adapted?: Is Psychopathy a Generalized Maladaptation?
One of the problems in understanding psychopathy may be to immediately consider it as a
disorder (Cutting 2012; Englebert 2013), without further thought, and thus viewing it a priori
as a maladaptation. For evolutionary psychopathology (De Block and Adriaens 2011; Brüne
2008; McGuire and Troisi 1998; Stevens and Price 2000; Demaret 2014), many behaviors
considered to be pathological must have an adaptive value in the original environment in
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
875
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
876
The Psychopathology of Psychopaths
which the morphology and psychology of our species were shaped. A change in time (a behavior in another era) or space (a behavior in another context, or social, cultural. or economic situation) may make a symptom appear adaptive (e.g. anorexia nervosa in times of
famine). Regarding psychopathy, one might suggest that:
The social function of psychopaths depends on conditions in the environment. In times of
peace, we lock them up; in times of war, we count on them and cover them with medals.
(Demaret 2014: 29; my translation)
Classically (Schneider 1923; Cleckley 1941; Hare 2003), psychopathy is associated with a
general or specific emotional deficit, affecting the processing and production of emotion.
Basic research tends to partially disconfirm this hypothesis (Poythress and Hall 2011;
Brook et al. 2013; Casey et al. 2013; Maes and Brazil 2013; Bird and Viding 2014). Although
the emotional dimension is considered to be the basis for the process of adaptation and
social interaction and is assumed to have a regulating function (Sartre 1939; Fuchs 2013;
Englebert 2013), the hypothesis that psychopaths have an emotional deficit is contradictory. I suggest instead that psychopaths are able to understand and manage emotional
phenomena. This conception is in opposition to the “poor,” “narrow,” and “immature”
emotional life attributed to psychopaths (Schneider 1923; Cleckley 1941; Hare 2003). It
corresponds to the adaptive conception considered by Demaret (2014). In times of war,
the psychopath does not suddenly regain the emotional competence he had lost in times
of peace.
Emotional Coldness
“Emotional coldness” must be distinguished from “emotional deficit.” Emotional coldness,
if we can agree on a definition, is clearly one of the fundamental clinical signs of psychopathy. Hare (2003) defines emotional coldness as one of the four facets of psychopathy (and
thus an essential trait). I agree with this claim. He then defines it with four items: Lack of
remorse or guilt (item 6), Shallow affect (item 7), Callous and/or lack of empathy (item 8) and
Failure to accept responsibility for own actions (item 16). This second point is not satisfactory because Hare’s definition does not perfectly delimit the concept. Emotional coldness
should instead be considered a way of managing emotional manifestations calmly and
coolly, without precipitation. (This is difficult to relate to item 14 of the PCL-R, “impulsivity,”
which describes antisocial subjects but not true psychopaths, strictly speaking.) Emotional
coldness is a preferred method of managing emotion calmly and keeping some distance, as
well as a tendency to take the time to analyze emotional experiences triggered in oneself or
in others. This tendency should not be considered as being more or less adaptive, effective,
or pathological than a “warm” emotion management style (tendency to react faster, by trial
and error, “naturally,” or “romantically”). It is probably more profitable to have a preferred
method (a style) of emotion management than to manage emotion in a more random, less
coherent way. Depending on an individual’s social, relational, or professional situation, it
may be more adaptive to manage emotions either “coldly” (political leader, emergency physician, etc.) or “warmly” (group facilitator, performing artist, etc.). This means that the emotional coldness generally attributed to psychopaths may be considered partly as an adaptive
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
876
02-Mar-19 12:30:45 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
For a Psychopathological Approach of Psychopathy
877
advantage, which can also be found in numerous people who have no personality disorders
or social or emotional deficits.
Bad?: Empathy or Sympathy Disorder?
Psychopaths are generally said to have an empathy deficit (Hare 1999; Decety et al. 2013).
Once again, it is necessary to define this concept. If we examine the definition more closely,
we can see that a psychopath does not actually have an empathy disorder but a sympathy
disorder. This difference is crucial as it enables us to distinguish between psychopathy (sympathy disorder) and schizophrenia (empathy disorder).
The concept of empathy is evoked so often that researchers often forget to define and analyze it. Some researchers with philosophical background point out that empathy is actually
a phenomenon that is very difficult to delimit, and when closely examined, complicated to
define (Stein 1989; Scheler 2008; Zahavi 2005, 2011). The most widely accepted definition
can be summarized in this way: it is the psychological mechanism whereby an individual
manages to intuitively represent another person’s emotional experience or suffering. In this
definition, the concept of empathy does not consider the subject’s response to this representation. It is therefore a “representational ability” that allows for “understanding of others.” It
can be differentiated from sympathy, the object of which is other people’s well-being (Scheler
2008; De Waal 2008; van der Weele 2011). Empathy is related to intuitive, implicit understanding and knowledge. Sympathy involves compassion and attention to others’ well-being.
Empathetic knowledge is not “intellectual.” Rather, it is a kind of intuitive, implicit knowledge that arises immediately when we meet another person. This is a primary form of intersubjectivity based on bodily expression and intercorporeality. This “implicit empathy”
underlies social exchanges (Stanghellini 2004; Englebert 2013). In addition to this prereflexive tendency, psychopathologists develop a method of understanding other people’s
experiences. This “conative empathy” is a reflexive and explicit practice used to promote the
development of intersubjectivity between the clinician and the patient. We can distinguish
between two “kinds” of empathy: the clinician’s (conative and explicit) and the patient’s
(implicit).
The investigation of implicit empathy needs to go into more depth in the case of psychopathy. A disorder affecting empathy (considered as the faculty of representing other people’s
experiences at the emotional, sentimental, or cognitive level) leads to a diagnosis of schizophrenia, rather than psychopathy. From this point of view, we must formally reconsider
the hypothesis that psychopaths are affected by an empathy deficiency. On the other hand,
it seems very possible that they have a “sympathy disorder.” A psychopath has no difficulty
identifying other people’s feelings and experiences (unlike a person with schizophrenia), but
he finds them completely irrelevant, as is other people’s well-being. The analysis of other
people and their experiences is strictly utilitarian and is unrelated to concern for or attention
to their well-being. For example, a psychopath can describe his victims’ suffering (showing
evidence of empathy) but can coldly explain that they are of no importance to him (he feels
no sympathy). Generally, psychopaths know that other people are bundles of emotions but
they never “lose themselves” in this affective experience. A psychopathic rapist said about
his victims: “What do you want me to say? That won’t change anything for them. Maybe it
did hurt them, but how do you expect that to change things for me? . . . What I think now
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
877
02-Mar-19 12:30:46 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
878
The Psychopathology of Psychopaths
won’t change anything about their situations or mine”; “I can well understand when other
people want to express their feelings but it’s got nothing to do with me. What other people
feel isn’t important to me” [Source: own clinical experience]. This sympathy disorder, which
takes the form of being able to imagine other people’s emotional experiences without being
affected by them, may obviously overlap with the emotional coldness discussed above.
This new way of considering psychopathic affectivity has an impact on clinical practice
but also on the field of research (Englebert 2015). The relationship the psychopath has with
emotions should not be considered a mere deficit but, from a certain point of view, an individualistic adaptive advantage. Discrimination between empathy (psychopathic competence) and sympathy (not a psychopathic skill) points out some weaknesses in diagnostic
tools such as scale Hare (Hare 2003), but also, for example, allows to reconsider an expanding
field of study such as the dimensions of Callous-unemotional traits in individuals at risk
of developing a psychopathic personality, especially among adolescents (Bird and Viding
2014; Frick et al. 2014; Henry et al. 2016; Muratori et al. 2016). The proposals developed in
this article may suggest that the unemotional intrinsic dimension should be discussed again
through a complex consideration and take into account the discrimination between emotional understanding of others (empathy) and emotional response to them (sympathy).
Conclusion
The purpose of this article was to examine psychopathy and the classical approaches to
evaluating it through the lens of phenomenological psychopathology. Despite some behavioral similarities, the psychopathological analysis allowed us to distinguish between
mania and psychopathy, to restore to psychopathy the emotional competence it had been
considered not to have, and to differentiate between empathy and sympathy. The adaptive
qualities that have been preserved, consistently with the mastery of empathy, do not preclude a moral disorder via the loss of sympathy for other people. Finally, this phenomenological study enabled us to identify a fundamental structural characteristic of psychopathy,
namely the ability to reify other people and to keep one’s own ego intact.
The tools of phenomenological psychopathology gave us the means to identify the
structuring and characteristic elements of psychopathic functioning and to point out the
shortcomings of contemporary nosographies and theories related to this specific entity.
Resorting to structural-phenomenological methods proved essential for not reducing this
condition to a mere maladaptation or to an (emotional) deficit, and to try to understand the
being-in-the-world of these particular patients.
Bibliography
Abu-Akel A., Heinke D., Gillespie S. M., Mitchell I. J., and Bo S. (2015). “Metacognitive
Impairments in Schizophrenia are Arrested at Extreme Levels of Psychopathy: The Cut-off
Effect.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 124(4): 1102–1109.
Berninger A. (2017). “Temporal Experience, Emotions and Decision Making in Psychopathy.
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16(4): 661–677.
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
878
02-Mar-19 12:30:46 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
Conclusion
879
Binswanger L. (1960). Melancholie und manie. Phänomenologische studien.
Pfullingen: Günther Neske.
Binswanger L. (1963). Being-in-the-World. New York: Basic Books.
Bird G. and Viding E. (2014). “The Self to Other Model of Empathy: Providing a New
Framework for Understanding Empathy Impairments in Psychopathy, Autism, and
Alexithymia.” Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews 47: 520–532.
Brook M., Brieman C. L., and Kosson D. S. (2013). “Emotion Processing in Psychopathy
Checklist—Assessed Psychopathy: A Review of the Literature.” Clinical Psychology Review
33(8): 979–995.
Broome M. R., Harland R., and Owen G. S. (2013). The Maudsley Reader in Phenomenological
Psychiatry. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Brüne M. (2008). Textbook of Evolutionary Psychiatry: The Origins of Psychopathology.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Casey H., Rogers R. D., Burns T., and Yiend J. (2013). “Emotion Regulation in Psychopathy.”
Biological Psychology 92(3): 541–548.
Cleckley H. (1941). The Mask of Sanity. St. Louis: Mosby.
Cooke D. J. and Michie C. (2001). “Refining the Construct of Psychopathy: Towards a
Hierarchical Model.” Psychological assessment 13(2): 171–188.
Cooke D. J., Michie C., Hart S. D., and Clark D. (2004). “Reconstructing Psychopathy: Clarifying
the Significance of Antisocial and Socially Deviant Behavior in the Diagnosis of
Psychopathic Personality Disorder.” Journal of Personality Disorders 18(4): 337–357.
Cooke D. J., Michie C., and Skeem J. (2007). “Understanding the Structure of the PCL-R: An
Exploration of Methodological Confusion.” British Journal of Psychiatry 49(s): 39–50.
Cooke D. J., Hart S. D., Logan C., and Michie C. (2012). “Explicating the Construct of
Psychopathy: Development and Validation of a Conceptual Model, the Comprehensive
Assessment of Psychopathic Personality (CAPP). International Journal of Forensic Mental
Health 11(4): 242–252.
Cutting J. (2012). A Critique of Psychopathology. Berlin: Parados.
De Block A. and Adriaens P. R. (2011). “Why Philosophers of Psychiatry Should Care
about Evolutionary Theory.” In P. R. Adriaens and A. De Block (eds.), Maladapting
Minds: Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Evolutionary Theory, pp. 1–32. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
De Waal F. B. (2008). “Putting the Altruism Back into Altruism: The Evolution of Empathy.
Annual Review of Psychology 59: 279–300.
Decety J., Chen C., Harenski C., and Kiehl K. A. (2013). “An fMRI Study of Affective Perspective
Taking in Individuals with Psychopathy: Imagining Another in Pain Does Not Evoke
Empathy.” Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7(489): 1–12.
Demaret A. (2014). Éthologie et psychiatrie. J. Englebert and V. Follet (eds.) 2nd edn., pp. 1–164.
Bruxelles, Belgium: Mardaga.
Englebert J. (2013). Psychopathologie de l’homme en situation. Paris: Hermann.
Englebert J. (2013b). “Some Evidence for a Psychopathological Consideration on Psychopathy.”
Annales Médico-Psychologiques 171(3): 141–153.
Englebert J. (2015). “A New Understanding of Psychopathy: The Contribution of
Phenomenological Psychopathology.” Psychopathology 48(6): 368–375.
Frick P. J., Ray J. V., Thornton L. C., and Kahn, R. E. (2014). “Can Callous-unemotional Traits
Enhance the Understanding, Diagnosis, and Treatment of Serious Conduct Problems in
Children and Adolescents? A Comprehensive Review. Psychological Bulletin 140(1): 1–57.
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
879
02-Mar-19 12:30:46 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
880
The Psychopathology of Psychopaths
Henry J., Pingault J. B., Boivin M., Rijsdijk F., and Viding E. (2016). “Genetic and Environmental
Aetiology of the Dimensions of Callous-Unemotional Traits.” Psychological Medicine
46(2): 405–414.
Fuchs T. (2013). “The Phenomenology of Affectivity.” In K. W. M. Fulford, M. Davies, R. G. T.
Gipps, G. Graham, J. Z. Sadler, G. Stanghellini, and T. Thornton (eds.), The Oxford Handbook
of Philosophy and Psychiatry, pp. 612–631. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Glover J. (2014). Alien Landscapes?: Interpreting Disordered Minds. Harvard: Harvard
University Press.
González R. A., Igoumenou A., Kallis C., and Coid J. W. (2016). “Borderline Personality
Disorder and Violence in the UK Population: Categorical and Dimensional Trait
Assessment.” BMC Psychiatry 16: 180.
Hare R. D., Hart S. D., and Harpur, T. J. (1991). “Psychopathy and the DSM-IV Criteria for
Antisocial Personality Disorder.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 100(3): 391–398.
Hare R. D. (1999). Without Conscience: The Disturbing World of the Psychopaths among Us.
Guilford Press.
Hare R. D. (2003). The Hare Psychopathy Checklist—Revised Manual, 2nd edn. Toronto: MultiHealth Systems.
Husserl E. [1931] (1960). Cartesian Meditations. London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.
Jaspers K. (1913). General Psychopathology, 7th edn. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Kiehl K. A. and Sinnott-Armstrong W. P. (2013). Handbook on Psychopathy and Law.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Levy N. (2014). “Psychopaths and Blame: The Argument from Content.” Philosophical
Psychology 27(3): 351–367.
Lilienfeld S. O. and Widows M. R. (2005). PPI-R: Psychopathic Personality Inventory
Revised: Professional Manual. Lutz, FL: Psychological Assessment Resources, Incorporated.
Maes J. H. R. and Brazil I. A. (2013). “No Clear Evidence for a Positive Association between
the Interpersonal-affective Aspects of Psychopathy and Executive Functioning.” Psychiatry
Research 210(3): 1265–1274.
McGuire M. T. and Troisi A. (1998). Darwinian Psychiatry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McIlwain D. (2010). “Living Strangely in Time: Emotions, Masks and Morals in
Psychopathically Inclined People.” European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 6(1): 75–94.
Minkowski E. [1927] (2002). La schizophrénie. Paris: Payot.
Minkowski E. [1966] (1999). Traité de psychopathologie. Paris: Les empêcheurs de penser
en rond.
Muratori P., Lochman J. E., Manfredi A., Milone A., Nocentini A., Pisano S., and Masi G. (2016).
“Callous Unemotional Traits in Children with Disruptive Behavior Disorder: Predictors of
Developmental Trajectories and Adolescent Outcomes.” Psychiatry Research 236: 35–41.
Neumann C. S. and Pardini D. (2014). “Factor Structure and Construct Validity of the SelfReport Psychopathy (SRP) Scale and the Youth Psychopathic Inventory (YPI) in Young
Men.” Journal of Personality Disorders 28(3): 419–433.
Nordgaard J., Sass L. A., and Parnas J. (2013). “The Psychiatric Interview: Validity, Structure,
and Subjectivity.” European Archives of Psychiatry and Clinical Neuroscience 263(4): 353–364.
Parnas J., Bovet P., and Zahavi D. (2002). “Schizophrenic Autism: Clinical Phenomenology and
Pathogenetic Implications.” World Psychiatry 1(3): 131–136.
Patrick C. J. (2006). “Back to the Future: Cleckley as a Guide to the Next Generation of
Psychopathy Research.” In C. J. Patrick (ed.), Handbook of Psychopathy, pp. 605–617.
New York: Guilford.
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
880
02-Mar-19 12:30:46 AM
OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF – FIRSTPROOFS, Sat Mar 02 2019, NEWGEN
Conclusion
881
Patrick C. J., Fowles D. C., and Krueger R. F. (2009). “Triarchic Conceptualization of
Psychopathy: Developmental Origins of Disinhibition, Boldness, and Meanness.”
Development and Psychopathology 21(3): 913–938.
Paulhus D. L., Neumann C. S., and Hare R. D. (2015). Manual for the Self-Report Psychopathy
Scale, 4th edn. Toronto: Multi-Health Systems.
Pinel P. (1800). Traité médico-philosophique sur l’aliénation mentale ou la manie. Paris: Caille et
Ravier.
Poythress N. G. and Hall J. R. (2011). “Psychopathy and Impulsivity Reconsidered.” Aggression
and Violent Behavior 16(2): 120–134.
Sartre J.-P. (1939). Esquisse d’une théorie des émotions. Paris: Hermann.
Sass L. A. (2014). “Self-disturbance and Schizophrenia: Structure, Specificity, Pathogenesis.”
(Current issues, New directions). Schizophrenia Research 152(1): 5–11.
Scheler M. (2008). The Nature of Sympathy. New Jersey: Transaction Publishers.
Schneider K. [1923] (1950). Psychopathic Personalities. London: Cassell.
Skeem J. L., Polaschek D. L. L., Patrick C. J., and Lilienfeld S. O. (2011). Psychopathic
Personality: Bridging the Gap between Scientific Evidence and Public Policy.” Psychological
Science in the Public Interest 12(3): 95–162.
Stanghellini G. (2004). Disembodied Spirits and Deanimated Bodies: The Psychopathology of
Common Sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Stanghellini G. (2009). “The Meanings of Psychopathology.” Current Opinion in Psychiatry
22(6): 559–564.
Stein E. (1989). On the Problem of Empathy, Vol. 3. Washington: ICS Publications.
Stevens A. and Price J. (2000). Evolutionary Psychiatry: A New Beginning, 2nd edn.
London: Routledge.
Szilasi W. (1959). Einfuhrung in die Phaenomenologie Edmund Husserls. Tubingen: Niemeyer.
Uzieblo K., Verschuere B., Van den Bussche E., and Crombez G. (2010). “The Validity of the
Psychopathic Personality Inventory—Revised in a Community Sample.” Assessment
17(3): 334–346.
van der Weele C. (2011). “Empathy’s Purity, Sympathy’s Complexities: De Waal, Darwin and
Adam Smith.” Biology & philosophy 26(4): 583–593.
Vitacco M. J. (2007). “Psychopathy.” British Journal of Psychiatry 191(s): 357–358.
Zahavi D. (2005). Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-person Perspective.
London: MIT Press.
Zahavi D. (2011). “Empathy and Direct Social Perception: A Phenomenological Proposal.”
Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2(3): 541–558.
/12_first_proofs/first_proofs/xml_for_typesetting
oxfordhb-9780198803157-part-6.indd
881
02-Mar-19 12:30:46 AM