CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
Volume 2 | Issue 1: Interpassivity
132 – 158 | ISSN: 2463-333X
Other Others: further remarks
on transferential materialism
Gabriel Tupinambá
1. A question concerning transference
I would like to begin with a concrete example which might help to
introduce us to a rather unexplored domain of psychoanalytic theory and
to Robert Pfaller's important contribution to its development.
The Testimony Clinic – "Clínica do Testemunho" – is a clinical
apparatus created in Brazil, under guidance of the Amnesty Commission,
with the aim of providing psychic aid to victims of State violence .
1
Originally developed as a recourse to deal with the subjective effects of
the civil-military dictatorship which lasted for 21 years, it was later
expanded to also address the problem of State violence as it perpetuates
itself within the democratic regime, especially through the State's
interventions – and lack thereof – in the slums and peripheries of the
country .
2
Three interconnected aspects of this project are worth mentioning
here. First of all, the Testimony Clinic, as its name already attests to,
seeks to explore the possible clinical responses to situations of socio-
historic catastrophe. The qualifier is warranted, because the very notion
132
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
of "testimony" has been introduced into theoretical consideration in the
last fifty years as a way to describe the predicament of those who
underwent a particular sort of traumatic experience: traumas which
pierce through not only the fabric of the individual's symbolic universe,
but of the social space out of which that particular symbolic texture is
woven. In other words, what is at stake in these situations is not only the
difficulty of finding and constructing the signifiers which might
symbolically allow for the subject to speak of what has taken place, but
also the difficulty of having these signifiers recognized as "significant" to
3
begin with.
The question of the witnessing of war atrocities and police brutality
is not only the question of the elaboration of the trauma by the subject,
but above all the question of the paradoxical condition through which the
very possibility of speaking about what has taken place contradicts and
empties out the legitimacy of what is being stated - one has witnessed
something which is deemed impossible to exist, therefore if there is a
witness, nothing has been witnessed . This paradox, however, is not the
4
same as the intrinsic contradiction between the position of enunciation
and of the enunciated, central to psychoanalytic theory: it is not a matter
of recognizing that "the fact of saying disappears under what is heard in
what is said", to paraphrase Lacan, but rather that the fact of saying is all
that is heard from what is said. One might work through a traumatic
experience, find a way to transmit it to others – and yet, nothing gets
passed on, as the very process of transmission which makes it
commensurable with other signifiers also makes it incommensurable
with what is being signified. One can only testify to it, to make oneself a
witness, but not signify, making oneself a subject, of what took place.
Even though most discussions around this clinical apparatus
seem to revolve around the category of the subject – with Lacanian
psychoanalysts questioning with suspicion the elaboration of a setting
which defines beforehand a determinate region of experience as the site
for clinical intervention - the essential impasse of the Testimony Clinic
seems to lie elsewhere, in the figure of the Other. As I briefly mentioned,
the paradox of the testimony is somewhat distinct from the contradictory
133
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
nature of signification: it concerns a suffering that is not caused by one's
indelible estrangement from what is said – I say or do something, but it
means something other than what I thought it did – it is not a matter of
the dialectics in which speech, once deposited or inscribed in the Other,
becomes other to me, but rather a suffering connected to the
impossibility of inscribing speech into this shared symbolic space
without this very act preventing - rather than promoting - the implication
of the subject's position in the autonomy of what is said. A witness is
someone who cannot become other to themselves through speech, they
are rather other to their speech. This is why the debate about the subject,
albeit relevant, misses the crucial point: without a previous inscription in
the Other of the possibility of certain impossible experiences, there might
be no symbolic space for such a trauma to possibly inscribe itself, not
even as the signifier of an impossible signification. What is at stake in the
public affirmation that the Testimony Clinic deals with State violence is
therefore not a countertransferential strategy which imbues speech with
meanings extracted from the analyst's own desire, but rather the process
of shaping the Other to render it commensurate or homogeneous to the
particular quality of social traumas.
But this raises an interesting and quite unexplored question: what
is then the effect of funding this project through the State? That is, what
are the effects for the transferential setting of analysts presenting
themselves before patients as representatives of the State? This enquiry
is relevant not only in the case of the Testimony Clinic, but also of other
sites of psychoanalytic intervention in Brazil, as most of the popular
access to analysis or analytic-inspired treatments in the country is
subsidized by the government. But in this particular case, the question is
quite central to the very idea of the project, as the presence of the State
as a backdrop to the clinical setting participates in the institutional
recognition of the existence of this form of suffering. Still, if it contributes
to inform the otherness of the clinical setting – connecting the "small
5
other" of the analyst to a "big Other" who knows that the dictatorship did
include the (not so) secret horrors of torture, kidnaps and missing
persons - it also adds a new sort of dynamic to that space: for example,
could one trust an analyst who has been paid by the State to listen to the
134
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
crimes of that same State? It is not a matter of settling this question, but
of realizing that it makes the subject's relation to an otherwise abstract
and intangible agency concrete and interpretable.
But what does this mean for the concept of the Other? How can
there be different symbolic spaces in which speech and experience are
made significant in different ways? This is a question which neither
Freud nor Lacan directly addressed, and we will return to it later on. For
now, it is worth noting that once we realize that the border between the
insignificant and the significant can be shifted not only by a change in
the subject's position, but also by the institutional context of the clinical
space, we can then return to the classical, private clinical setting and
inquire about its own institutional contribution to the settling of this
border. What might be relegated to insignificance not due to vacillations
in the desire of the analyst, but by the logistical and institutional
commitments required for a private clinic to exist? After all, many people
who seek the Testimony Clinic had their own private analysts before and
during this parallel treatment, but some of them only go through the
process of working through the experience of the dictatorship when their
speech within the clinical setting organized by the latter .
6
Similar experiences – albeit with significant differences worth
exploring in their own right – can be found in various clinical projects in
which the listening of suffering is informed by a previous commitment to
the existence of some dimension of social and private life which defines
a common symbolic inscription. To mention a few, all of them happening
in Brazil: the Refugees of Belo Monte project, which sought to provide
psychic aid to the families which lost their homes in the Mariana disaster
– here, in fact, the population did not recognize the legitimacy of the
project while they did not sever their ties with State funding – the Oficina
Acadêmica, which focuses on the effects on the youth of having been
granted increasing formal access to the university without the material
basis to allow for the same academic experience as other students - a
project which struggles to remain a para-academic address, as it
focuses on the experience of those who do not fully "belong" in
academia - and the Circle of Studies of Idea and Ideology, which offers a
135
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
place for militants who are mourning the end of the previous sequence
of Leftist politics in Brazil – and which constantly struggles with defining
its place, neither outside nor itself political practice. In all of these cases,
there is not so much a singling out of who should access or make use of
these spaces, but rather the effort of constituting an Other
commensurate with the impossible experiences of social catastrophes,
failed social expectations and political utopias.
We will return later on to the political import of this investigation,
but what this preamble already helps us to pinpoint is a certain relation
between the structure of the otherness at stake in different traumas and
fantasies and the structure of otherness which, shaping the clinic, can as per Lacan's famous definition of transference - make actual the reality
of the unconscious .
7
2. The theory of formal otherness
I have previously tried to address this formal articulation between
impossible objects and the transferential setting in a text called
Transferential Materialism (Hamza & Ruda, 2015), which explored the
ontological commitments of Freud's theory of transference, showing that
the materialism at stake not in the Freudian theory, but the analytic
technique, answers through artificial means to the principle that
"something that is formally other-to-thought can only be thought by
another of a certain form" (2015: 145). This was a first attempt to
theoretically highlight a principle of "ontological homogeneity" which
conditions which sort of social relation might serve as a effective model
for some phantasmatic scene: traumas which concern the subject as an
object of desire for her father, as in the case of Dora, have the "shape" of
a dual setting in which the personhood of the analyst is enough for it to
be transitive with the otherness of this impossible love encounter - even
though Dora cannot think the object she is for the Other without ceasing
to be that object, through the otherness of the analyst this thought can be
"dramatized" and indirectly enjoyed in situ. One cannot intervene upon
someone's libidinal attachments in effigie.
136
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
Lacan famously developed the concept of the "subject supposed
to know" to account for the inner-structure of transference in the analytic
clinic, the process through which there comes to be a "knowledge that
only delivers itself to the mistaking of the subject' (Lacan, 2001: 335). The
concept of the subject supposed to know helps us to grasp the dynamics
of transference and the role of the analyst in the production of knowledge
without the need to assume that the analyst knows anything about what
is "truly" going on with the analysand – that is, it highlights the purely
formal role of his position in the circuit of speech in analysis.
Even though this was not Lacan's own approach to the matter, the
clearest way to locate the function of the subject supposed to know in
analysis is to consider it as a consequence of the paradoxical status of
psychoanalysis' "golden rule", the rule of free association. What does it
mean to speak under the rule that one should say "whatever comes to
mind"? On the one hand, this rule seeks to suspend any extrinsic
normative commitments: there is no one topic, situation or crazy thought
which is by default excluded from pertinence. On the other, the rule to
follow no extrinsic rules in the choice of what to say creates an
impossible situation: whatever regularities appear in speech now can no
longer be explained away by an explicit pact to keep to that topic, or to
preserve some level of politeness or morality – one is implicated in the
rules that end up being followed in analysis: even the strategy of doing
"exactly" what the free association rule asks us to do, to speak about
anything, attaches itself to the speaker as something which implicates
her in what it said. In other words, the rule of free association suspends
extrinsic constraints in order to make intrinsic constraints legible, that is, it
makes speech interpretable. If the patient speaks in an almost aleatory
form, or speaks about past traumas, or avoids saying certain things or
repeats a certain expression in vastly different contexts – all of this
becomes significant, that is, it all points to the subject of enunciation that
disappears under the implicit normativity guiding what is being said.
The concept of the subject supposed to know makes intelligible
the role of the analyst in all of this - this is the concept which accounts for
137
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
how the inherent otherness of these constraints in speech can appear to
the speaker by taking the form of a constraint that is other to the speaker.
To use a simplified example, when faced with the impossible rule to
freely associate, one might suppose that, underneath that vague
injunction, the analyst really wants to hear about our sexual history, and
therefore start describing our sexual encounters or preferences. The
supposition of what the analyst knows - that some hidden meaning is
locked in the sphere of sexuality – becomes the means through which
the normativity we are following for no extrinsic reason can make itself
legible. The very mistaking of the subject – which many times appears as
an attempt to avoid "duping" the analyst, to speak what is "truly"
important – is what effectively produces the knowledge which can then
be returned to the subject in an inverted form: the only sovereign of this
rule is the subject herself, no one asked of her to speak of sex – and,
more importantly, to speak of it in the way she did. The subject supposed
to know, as the instance mobilized by the speaker as a mediator
between speech and the intrinsic rules of speech, participates in the
dialectics that produces some information about the speaker – not about
the external referents of what has been said, but about the constraints
which shaped this signification process: knowledge not about what
speech refers to as having taken place, but about what is taking place
while we speak in the clinic. In this way, Lacan can simultaneously
demonstrate the necessity of the analyst in the clinical setting – a
position without which this mistaking would never take place – without
this implying that the analyst should try to read into what is being said by
the analysand: the mistaking is the source of the knowledge about the
subject of that speech, a knowledge that is constituted by speaking,
rather than communicated through it.
The concept of the subject supposed to know therefore highlights
the empty but necessary role of the analyst in mediating the passage
from an otherness within speech to an Other to the speaker. It does so by
highlighting the way the analyst helps to shape the space of free
association, adding a sort of "ideal point" into this space, a point of
obscurity regarding what is being heard, which turns any trajectory of
signification into an attempt to signify the desire of one's interlocutor. This
138
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
is why analytic interpretation is a second-order intervention: the effort of
making sense of an impossibility actually falls upon the analysand everything said in analysis acquires this hermeneutic quality due to the
free association rule - and the analyst rather intervenes to display the
intrinsic constraints of this signification process, to question the
"meaning of meaning" in the analysand's speech.
What is usually not mentioned here, though, is that Lacan's formal
treatment of the subject supposed to know allows us to see how
transference comes to acquire the same form as that of love. In Freud's
The Dynamic of Transference (1912), the reason why transference in
analysis has the structure of an idealized love relationship - where one
seeks to find out what sort of object of desire one is for the Other - is
explained genetically: transference takes this form of suppositions and
love attachments to the analyst because our libidinal history is only
composed of such relationships and therefore this is what emerges back
when we suspend other constraints. But with Lacan's formal treatment of
the structure of transference no metapsychological commitment to the
general form of fantasy is needed: if transference is conditioned by the
formal structure of the setting, then we can accept the thesis that
analysis is capable of intervening upon the phantasmatic suppositions
which emerge under these conditions without supposing that every
fantasy can acquire actuality through this clinical setting. A dual setting,
in which the private person of the analyst "absorbs" the obscure effects
of the rule of free association by making oneself its guarantor, is
commensurate with a circuit that expresses "love type relations",
because otherness in love splits the loved one in this same way between their private being and their intimate, unfathomable kernel. To
render the otherness of love thinkable, we require an other that could be
loved.
Slavoj Žižek's theory of the "subject supposed to believe" was a
crucial contribution to the development of this implicit consequence of
Lacan's theory of transference. The concept was introduced by Žižek in
the context of understanding the underlying transferential operation at
stake in commodity fetishism:
139
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
Beneath the apparently humanist-ideological opposition of
"human beings" and "things", there lurks another, much more
productive notion, which is that of the mystery of substitution
and/or displacement: how is it ontologically possible that the
innermost "relations between people" can be displaced onto (or
replaced by) "relations between things"? In other words, is it not a
basic feature of the Marxian notion of commodity fetishism that
"things believe instead of us, in place of us"? The point worth
repeating again and again is that, in Marx's notion of fetishism, the
fetishist inversion lies not in what people think they are doing, but
in their social activity itself
8
The crucial strategy here is that Žižek recognizes that commodity
fetishism brings into play the same "mystery of substitution" that
psychoanalytic transference does, but without assuming an ontology
which only allows - like in the case of the analytic setting - for "relations
between people" to be displaced onto new relations between people.
The enigma of how relations between people can be displaced onto
relations between things therefore invites analytic consideration, but
rejects the ontological limitations imposed by the form of transference
theorized by Freud and Lacan. On the one hand, Žižek maintains that this
displacement, like in the case of transference, is not the posterior
displacement onto others of something we previously knew or directly
assumed - like in transference, the mistaking participates in the
constitution of the phenomena under consideration, as "there is no
immediate, self-present living subjectivity to whom the belief embodied
in "social things" can be attributed and who is then dispossessed of it".
However, if commodity fetishism does make use of a supposition
onto others that is not merely derivative, but constitutive, Žižek
nonetheless affirms that this process is essentially distinct from that of
clinical transference:
The two notions, that of the subject supposed to believe and that
of the subject supposed to know, are not symmetrical because
140
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
belief and knowledge themselves are not symmetrical. At its most
radical, the status of the (Lacanian) big Other qua symbolic
institution is that of belief (trust), not that of knowledge, since belief
is symbolic and knowledge is real (the big Other involves, and
relies on a fundamental "trust"). Belief is always minimally
3
"reflective", a "belief in the belief of the other" ("I still believe in
Communism" is the equivalent of saying "I believe there are still
people who believe in Communism"), while knowledge is precisely
not knowledge about the fact that there is another who knows. For
this reason, I can BELIEVE through the other, but I cannot KNOW
through the other. That is to say, owing to the inherent reflectivity of
belief, when another believes in my place, I myself believe through
him, but knowledge is not reflective in the same way: when the
other is supposed to know, I do not know through him.
9
Žižek makes two crucial distinctions here. The first concerns the
difference in terms of reflexivity: when we suppose someone else holds a
belief, this displacement still carries some transitive value - something of
the displaced belief remains operative for us, even though we only
"believe the other believes", as supposing and believing are ultimately
the same activity - while the same is not true for knowledge, as
supposing the other knows does not entail that we have any access to
that knowledge: it does not constitute a knowledge about the other's
knowledge. This difference is of capital importance if we keep in mind
the discussion concerning the commensurability between, for example,
love attachments and the form of otherness in analytic transference. We
suggested that the fantasies which are actualized in the clinical space
have the form of an interrogation of the Other's desire not because this is
the structure of all fantasies, but because this is the "shape" of the Other
in the private clinical space - that is, the intransitive structure of
knowledge, where supposing a knowledge is not knowing it ourselves,
participates in the process of turning the otherness of desire, this
unknowable, into the supposition of another's knowledge and then,
through interpretation, into a knowledge about the lack of knowledge.
The structure of belief, on the other hand, informs a different space of
displacements: the fact that a belief supposed in the other does not need
141
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
to be ever directly assumed in order to become what it is allows the
substitution process to involve passive others - for example, by
displacing beliefs onto objects - as well as to involve positions which are
incommensurate not only with our individual identifications, as in the
case of the libidinal unconscious, but incommensurate with individuality
as such.
Such is, in fact, the precise status of the belief displaced onto
commodity fetishism: the social contract between commodities, through
which all commodities abdicate the right to function as the "relative
form" of value in the name of one single representative, the money-form,
is objectively more vast in scope than any social contract binding a given
community, as money circulates across the boundaries of different
symbolic spaces, languages and value-systems . No individual can
10
vouch for this sovereign pact, not because we pretend like we do not, but
because this belief in the sovereign status of the money-form is
indifferent to the scale of individual decisions. It is a belief that would not
be the belief that it is were it to be directly assumed - the exchange of
money for commodities is not guaranteed by the fact that the actors
involved in the exchange believe in money as a general equivalent, but
on our belief that others, no matter in which shared system of value, take
it to function as such. To displace the relation between (millions of)
people to the relation between (two) things is thus formally
commensurate with the otherness of the belief: there is an underlying
homogeneity which makes use of the transitive status of the structure of
belief so that, in believing others believe in the social contract binding the
"equivalent" and "relative" sides of the form of value, I am closer to the
actual belief I have than if I were to directly assume it.
This leads us to the second important distinction between the
subject supposed to know and the subject supposed to believe, the fact
that Žižek takes the phantasmatic structure of displaced beliefs to be the
general case, while the supposition of knowledge is the special one. For
Žižek, the operator of a subject supposed to know is "not the standard,
but the exception, and that it gains its value in contrast to the subject
supposed to believe as the standard feature of the symbolic order". In
142
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
fact, when we accept the previous hypothesis that clinical transference
renders actual only the fantasies commensurate with the private relation
between analysand and analyst, it is not hard to see that this form is
essentially commensurate with personal and familial relations, which, in
our contemporary social world form a subclass of the social relations we
are actually engaged in. The reason why other unconscious relations are
not expressed in the analytic clinic - except "in effigie", that is, as
signifieds - its because the clinic is structured in such a way as to only
render actual those relations in which otherness is "informed" by the
impersonal dimension of personality itself.
3. Pfaller, a transferential materialist
Robert Pfaller is not only an important contributor in the development of
Žižek's theory of the subject supposed to believe, but has himself taken
this theory much further by systematizing the class of phenomena he
calls the "illusions without owners" and the general structure of
"interpassivity" which underlies our relation to them. In this section, I
would like to reconstruct some of the central claims of his brilliant book
On the Pleasure Principle in Culture: Illusions without Owners (2014),
which both consolidates and extends the reach of some of the insights
discussed thus far.
Pfaller defines the object of his enquiry by its particular properties:
"we are dealing with illusions that (1) seem to have no bearer; (2) are not
dismissed by knowing better, but instead seem to be strengthened by it;
(3) exert themselves in the form of a compulsion, albeit foreign and kept
at a distance through knowledge; (4) often remain unnoticed; and (5)
appear to be without content" (2014: 5). He is quick to highlight that these
properties "are based on a difference in the forms of illusion rather than a
difference in their content: it is a distinction based on the relationship
between subject and illusion, on the different ways in which people refer
to these illusions" (1). As Pfaller remarks, while there are illusions which
participate in the economy of the subject's identity and enjoyment illusions which are proudly and directly assumed as if they were true, like
a belief in God or in self-regulating markets, etc - there are also illusions
143
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
which only appear at a distance from the subject, which have practical
but no subjective inscription in our lives. We would never say "I know it's
silly, but I believe in free markets" - such a belief requires, in our society,
to be assumed in first person, under the guise of some ethical or moral
stance - but this is precisely the way we express our relationship with
other equally illusory instances: we "know better", we "know it's stupid"
but still we believe in the horoscope, scream at malfunctioning
machines, feel a sense of accomplished duty just by downloading digital
copies of books, etc. We also "know better" than to think a piece of paper
is in itself a form of wealth, but it is still money that we put under our
mattresses when we fear for our savings in a time of crisis. What is
remarkable in these cases is that this distance introduced by knowledge
does not lead us, for example, to stop talking to a car that doesn't start,
but rather guarantees the efficacy of this underlying belief - it prevents us
from ever finding a situation which could unsettle this belief, as it was
unsettled and de-legitimized from the very beginning.
Pfaller, like Žižek, is well-aware that this theory of the form of
illusions keeps a paradoxical relation with psychoanalysis: referencing
Lacan's "mirror stage theory", Pfaller remarks that the existence of these
intransitive illusions, illusions which cannot be directly assumed, "is even
more surprising in that illusions, as psychoanalytical theory has
recognized, work to form the subject". After all, for both Freud and Lacan,
it is out of certain fantasies that a subject carves its own consistency, as
certain illusions come to structure and mediate the subject's inclusion in
the world. But this is precisely what seems to be missing from the
illusions that interest Pfaller here: "Although it may indeed be true that
without illusions there are no subjects, it nonetheless seems that there
are, at least, illusions without subjects." (2014: 33). These are illusions
which - to return to Žižek's analysis of commodity fetishism - do not
support a subject's self-transparent permanence in face of the
contingency of her real conditions of existence, but rather structure those
real conditions themselves. There is a profound formal difference
between the belief that possessing this or that commodity changes or
improves who I am - an illusion with a subject - and the belief at stake in
the act of exchanging that commodity for some money, that is for the
144
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
future possibility of the seller exchanging that money for something else.
This second belief is operative regardless - and in fact because of - our
"better knowledge" that money is "just paper", just a promissory note. As
we said, it is rather a belief about the belief of others - it "goes on",
functioning without us, while subjectively we can construct for ourselves
an identificatory circuit that only includes our desire and the commodity
we just purchased.
In The Structure of World History (2014), Kojin Karatani
distinguishes the social pact at stake in the logic of state sovereignty, by
which citizens collectively abdicate of their autonomy and invest it onto
one person, which then gives expression, through his personhood, to the
state as a whole, from the logic of the "social pact between
commodities". For Karatani, the passage between simple, total and
money-form in the first volume of Marx's Capital is isomorphic to the
logic of sovereignty, in that all commodities come to abdicate their role
as formal equivalents of the value of other commodities so that this
function falls upon one sole commodity, the general equivalent.
However, the difference between these two processes is clear enough:
while the social contract concerns the proprietors of commodities - who
in the interest of their security and wealth abide to a common law - the
"social contract between commodities" is not performed by us: it is a
pact between things themselves, so much so that a world-economy
requires world-money to circulate between different states and lawful
spaces, and therefore cross frontiers beyond which we simply would not
recognize any communion with others. While we could call "interactivity"
the positive reinforcement cycle between, in Rousseau's terms, the
particular and the general will, between the citizen as subject and as
sovereign, as rule-follower and rule-creator - in short, the logic of political
participation - Robert Pfaller calls "interpassivity" (Pfaller, 2017) the
negative or inverse cycle through which our subjective disengagement
with a certain social process is precisely what constitutes its efficacy: the
less everyone believes in a capitalist free economy the more it is an
efficacious form of social synthesis between different subjectivized belief
systems.
145
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
Still developing this interlocution between Pfaller, Žižek and Marx,
we can also see how the theory of the subject supposed to believe, with
its corresponding interpassive subject, is equally connected to a theory
of "delegated enjoyment" (2014: 18). If Žižek had already suggested that
the class of fantasies which are structured by the other's beliefs is more
general than of those structured by the other's knowledge, Pfaller
proposes that "the delegation of conviction and feelings creates special
cases of the general principle of delegated enjoyment" (ibid: 19). The
delegation of consumption is, for him, logically prior to the delegation of
a certain belief onto the other.
And, in fact, this finds an interesting counterpart in Marx's own
theory of value. In the very first section of Capital, Marx reminds us that
even though a commodity must have use value, "a thing can be useful
and the product of human labor without being a commodity" - that is, to
become a commodity it is not enough to be a product of labor or to have
use-value for oneself: the product must have "use value for others". To
which he quickly adds: "not only for others (...) to become a commodity, a
product must be transferred to another, whom it will serve as use value
by means of an exchange" (1992:124). And as Marx makes increasingly
clear - especially in the chapter dealing with the "metamorphoses" of the
commodity in the exchange process (ibid: 198) - the reference to usevalue inherent to the commodity structure can be infinitely postponed: in
fact, this is what allows it to become capital, the very fact that I can buy
or produce it in order to sell it, that is, in order for another to consume it.
The paradox is, thus, that even though nothing can be produced as a
commodity if it is not produced for another's consumption, when we do
become the consumers of a certain product we are only accidentally
occupying the place of this other - structurally it could be further
postponed, for example, if we decide to buy this product in order to resell it for a higher price somewhere else. In this sense, the formal
reference to another's enjoyment precedes and underlies the social pact
between commodities, and, therefore, the delegated belief that mediates
their interactions.
146
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
Two features allow Pfaller to develop this line of investigation
further than Žižek had taken it. First of all, rather than focus on the
functioning of ideological fantasies in our contemporary political
predicament, he departs from an analysis of different phenomena of
delegated consumption in art works. This leads him to explore cases - at
stake for example in the case of "service art" - of "consumers who want
to be replaced by something that consumes in their place" (Pfaler, 2014:
20; 2017: 10). But, at the same time, Pfaller is also able to redirect Žižek's
research by not focusing only on the strategies through which one seeks
to consume the impossible - that is, what psychoanalysis calls
"enjoyment" - but extending his investigation to deal with the delegation
of pleasures which could be directly had as well. For him "interpassivity is
not just a method of 'extended', indirect consumption that increases
one's (necessarily limited) direct consumerist capacities" - instead, Pfaller
claims that "interpassive subjects are actually feeling from their
enjoyment. They even avoid it in those situations where personally
experiencing it would be easy. Owners of recording devices, for example,
watch less television once they have the recorder than they did when
they owned only the television set. And travellers, who are certainly
capable of viewing scenic attractions themselves, hold a camera to their
eyes as if by reflex" (2014: 20).
This more general approach to the problem places new questions
before us: why create an indirect structure for consumption when we
could directly enjoy something? Or: how could these substitute actions such as praying through praying wheels, recording television shows, etc
- be placed in equivalence with the direct experience of consumption?
Even further: how can all of this even take place without this very strategy
being itself assumed by these interpassive subjects? After all, no one
who records television shows, never to watch them, or makes hundreds
of photocopies, never to read them, would claim "the recorder is
watching in my place". This is how delegated enjoyment meets the
Žižekian theory of displaced beliefs: only are certain substitutive actions
displacing the consumption of religious comfort, tv series and literature
onto things and other people, but they also displace the belief in this very
strategy. Pfaller concludes:
147
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
There are always two levels of delegation - namely the delegation
of enjoyment and the delegation of belief (in the enacted
performance of enjoyment). Interpassivity is always carried out
simultaneously on both of these levels: on the one hand,
consumption is delegated to a consumption medium - for
example, reading to a photocopier; on the other hand, the belief in
the equivalence between consumer and their vicarious
consumption media must also be delegated. The interpassive
subject does not personally believe that he or she has read via the
copy machine; this belief is transferred to the scene's virtual
audience. Delegated enjoyment this always entails feigning
enjoyment for an observing agency with the help of a
consumption medium, and simultaneously surrendering belief in
this feigned fiction to the observing agency. (2014: 30).
But what is the status of this "observing agency"? One of the great
contributions of Pfaller's theory of interpassivity is the idea of the "naive
observer" (2014: 233) - the "virtual audience" which believes, in our place,
in the equivalence between photocopying and reading, or between
spinning a praying wheel and praying. We surely "know better" than to
equate these two sets of actions, but it is actually our ignorance that we
displace onto this observing agency - while we remain perfectly aware
that these substitutive acts are silly and inconsequential, for some other
instance the substituted and the enacted behaviours are the same. The
theory of the naive observer allows us to conceptualize beliefs that
remain fully operative even in a society where everyone "knows better"
than to believe in them.
Pfaller's attention to the full spectrum of interpassive phenomena,
beyond those instances where this strategy allows us to vicariously enjoy
impossible objects, leads him to question the status of pleasure in
general: "might all forms of pleasure that culture is able to produce be
associated with objective illusions?" (2014: 33). That is, if delegation of
consumption is at play even in situations in which we could otherwise
directly reach its object, so that, economically, the pleasure arrived at by
148
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
means of delegation is greater than the direct experience of the
pleasurable object, could we then define pleasure as such in terms of
such anti-participatory structure? Rather than focusing on the dramatic
forms of indirect enjoyment at stake in the "beyond the pleasure
principle" – those impossible experiences which we repeat in order to
(fail to) master, making them commensurable with us in their very virtual
insistence – Pfaller explores the inverse path, infusing pleasure itself with
an indirect character. Beyond the interesting theoretical consequences of
such an investigation, his enterprise has the additional benefit of
dismantling a certain ideology which attaches subjective authenticity to a
transgression of limits or to sacrifice – an ideology Lacan did not escape,
for example in his apology of heroism in his seventh seminar - proposing
instead a new vision in which the capacity to experience pleasure in
culture is linked to culture's capacity to sustain certain autonomous
social structures.
Another ideological trope that is challenged by Pfaller's theory equally found in psychoanalysis – is the explicit precedence of totemism
over animism as "grammars" for the subject's relation to the law and
desire. In Freud (Freud, 1913) this is particularly clear, as he makes
certain correspondences between the passage from animism to
totemism, the passage from magic to religion and the sexual
development of children into neurotic adulthood. Equating animisms'
extension of the "I-thou" relation to inanimate things, the corresponding
belief in magic as a technique for affecting things via representations,
and the childish overvaluation of one own's ego, Freud concludes that
"magical thinking" is a primitive mode of libidinal economy, one in which
we cannot yet separate our thoughts about things from things
themselves - to wish is to at least partially obtain what is wished for. This
animistic circuit between ego and object-libido would be increasingly
curbed by "reality testing" – as we constitute ourselves as lacking
subjects – and this would lead to the totemic grammar of neurosis: the
displacement onto an exceptional figure, the father, who is supposed to
enjoy what we do not have. The introduction of lack into this economy,
separating ego and object, transposing satisfaction onto an exceptional
other, would also correspond to the passage from a magical to a
149
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
religious economy - hence the institution of the superego as an
omnipotent other. It is not hard to see that totemism, as the subjectivized
delegation of enjoyment by the many to a phantasmatic exception, is
very much akin to the structure of the social pact between proprietors - in
Freud's case, the proprietors of women - who must abdicate their
freedom and displace their sovereign powers onto an exception.
Animism, on the other hand, has a striking resemblance to the structure
of commodity fetishism, insofar as animism implies the extension to
things of the relations of "I-thou" that people establish amongst
themselves (Karatani, 2014) – its grammar approaches far more closely
the sort of social pact between things at stake in the money-form.
What Pfaller's theory allows us to do is to show that the "discrete
magic of the civilized" is perfectly effective in our enlightened society:
even though psychoanalysis concerns itself almost exclusively with
fantasies which are structured in accordance to the totemic form of
displacement, whereby we know that someone else enjoys in our place,
this cannot be generalized to mean that all phantasmatic formations in
our culture are formed as the consequence of the "reality principle"
making us painfully aware of our limitations to enjoy. Instead, Pfaller
denounces the conviction of Freud and others that animistic cultures
immediately believed in their illusions (Pfaller, 2014: 70), while magic,
superstition and the animistic worldview are in fact perfectly compatible
with the interpassive structure of belief.
This polemical claim has two crucial consequences. First of all, it
separates the basic structure of animism from the theory of infantile
sexuality, by distinguishing between the infantile belief in the power of
our own thoughts to realise our desires from the indirect belief in a naive
other who would then equate our ideas about things and these things
themselves. As Pfaller puts it a propos of magic shows:
magic is not horrible because it disappoints fantasies of
omnipotence. It is not the fact that the presented omnipotence
does not exist that is horrid, but rather the reverse: the awful thing
is that the omnipotence does exist, yet not as the omnipotence of
one's own thoughts, but instead as the omnipotence of a foreign,
150
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
naive observer who fulfils every depicted wish. (...) The
characteristic attitude of magic thus consists in knowing perfectly
well that one cannot help reality through the use of signs, but
nonetheless fearing that someone else who does not know that
will make the meaning of signs come true. (...) Plenty of people
who emphatically claim not to believe in voodoo would
nonetheless still refuse to gouge out an eye in a picture of their
own mother. All such everyday magicians are, in this sense,
'sorcerer's apprentices', as depicted by Goethe: they conjure up
more than they want" (2014: 260-261).
This essential distinction between the omnipotence of the ego and
of the other – and therefore the infantile beliefs of children and of gods becomes the cornerstone for a whole series of further differentiations in
the psychoanalytic theory of obsessive neurotic rituals, perversion and
superego which Pfaller develops throughout the book.
The second crucial consequence of the critique of "perspectivebased illusion" (2014: 70) which leads faith-based cultures to assume
that all other cultures immediately subjectivize their beliefs is that it
becomes possible to investigate the hypothesis that "the initially
universal belief-form of organization of social illusions was later covered
over by the faith-form in some societies" (ibid: 70). Not only does this
hypothesis allow Pfaller to account for the emergence of the delegated
belief that faith-based societies assign to belief-based ones, but it also
leads him to an excavation of belief-based illusions within our own
culture, an investigation which focuses especially on the role of the
"naive observer" in the activity of play (ibid: 79-82) and politeness (ibid:
117-118) to the corresponding theory of a cultural pleasure attainable
only through the mediation of such naive observers (ibid: 193).
The ramifications of the research on interpassivity and delegated
enjoyment are therefore far reaching. For our purpose, however, it
suffices to realize that Žižek and Pfaller's subsequent extensions of
Lacan's theory of the "subject supposed to" remain consistent with its
fundamental properties. First, beliefs that are delegated are not defined
151
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
by their content - as if some beliefs "must" be displaced while others can
be directly assumed - but by the form of the illusion (Pfaller, 2014: 1), that
is, the form in which the belief is organized is responsible for its effectivity
as an illusion, not for its illusory status. The same property can be found
in Lacan's theory of the subject supposed to know: the knowledge that
emerges through this displacement is produced within the analytical
setting, but it was not a secret knowledge, a "truer knowledge" of the
analyst, to be distinguished from the immediate knowledge of the
analysand. Furthermore, just like the theory of the subject supposed to
know - which was based on the division of the analyst between material
medium for the circuit of free association and virtual Other who is
supposed to know the meaning of deviations in speech - the theory of
interpassivity also features a set of substitutive practices which function
as a material medium for the delegation and a virtual observer which is
supposed to equate the substituted and the substitutive actions. With the
essential distinction that while the analyst functions as a medium which
the analysand enjoys - hence the actualization of unconscious love
relations in the clinic - in the case of interpassivity the medium itself is
responsible for enjoying in our place. Accordingly, while we deposit in the
subject supposed to know an explanation as to why we enjoy the way
we do, we assign to the subject supposed to belief some ignorance
which justifies the equivalence between the delegated enjoyment and
our actual pleasure.
The logic of delegated enjoyment is thus compatible with the
Lacanian approach to the transferential dynamic, but, as Žižek had
shown us already, the asymmetry between knowledge and belief
requires us to pay attention to a "hidden variable" in the analytic theory,
challenging the supposition that every delegation to the other is
intransitive - so that I do not know what I suppose the other knows, like a
process of property alienation – and that it will therefore serve as means
to inscribe the subject's lack into speech – turning the unknowable
dimension of my desire into something I don't know, but the other might.
But how could we ever transform beliefs which have no place for us?
152
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
4. Interventions in absentia
I began this essay with an example taken from the fringes of
contemporary psychoanalysis. The Testimony Clinic, like many other of
the projects I briefly mentioned in the introduction, is in fact not
considered strictly psychoanalytic, and the application and relevance of
analytic ideas in the treatment of traumas associated with State violence
remains a point of contention both between therapists of different
theoretical orientations and amongst psychoanalysts themselves. What
should be clear now, however, is that this is not so much a conflict
between different ways to approach the object of intervention, but a
problem internal to this object itself.
To introduce the specificity of dealing with the effects of social
catastrophes, I proposed the definition of social traumas as "personal
effects with impersonal causes". This is a very tentative definition in that,
for Lacanians, traumas always imply this underlying incommensurability
between causes and effects. The intervention of the sexual is already a
sort of indelible indetermination, more akin to a suspension in a causal
chain than the imposition of a cause of greater intensity. Furthermore,
symptoms are also defined as "effects without causes" – as ciphered
messages about a past that did not take place, or better, which seeks to
interpret the gap inscribed by the sexual – hence the classical Freudian
theme of the "proton pseudos" and the retroactive construction of a
traumatic narrative. In other words, the mismatch between causes and
effects was always part of the psychoanalytic definition of trauma - so
why would this define a distinct class of traumatic experiences?
Using our revision of Žižek and Pfaller's theories of delegated belief
and interpassivity, we can now extend this definition. We have seen that
the belief at stake in the money-form is formally "other" to the subject in
the sense that it is a belief about the belief of the receiver of our money about his trust that a third party will accept this paper as payment for
another commodity. What is delegated to the other here is not only a
belief that is not effective when assumed in the first person, it is also a
belief about the consistency of the other's social relation to others. In
153
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
other words, this belief does not participate in the consistency of myself
as an individual, but in the consistency of commodity exchange itself the very possibility of there being an infinite enchainment of use and
exchange-values in a symbolic system. To suspend this belief is not to
expose the inconsistency of the Other for a subject - that is, it is not a
matter of revealing that the big Other does not exist as a guarantor for
the meaning of our desires - it is rather to threaten the consistency of the
Other for the other. We always knew magic is not real, but we believe the
terrible performance of a magic trick could affect a child's sense of
wonder, that is, the other's capacity to respond to the world - we always
knew money is not real, but we believe an economic crisis might affect
the level of trust in the value of our credit system amongst others. In both
cases the trauma does not tear a hole in knowledge, leaving us without
means to speak of what has happened to us, it rather rips the social
fabric itself, the way it appears to itself, and not to us. The effects of such
critical points can therefore be perfectly "ego-syntonic", in that they do
not lead to an increase in our subjective experience of suffering. In fact,
these situations tend to lead to an overcompensation at the level of our
private fantasies, as they imply that we cannot count on the stability of
our "real conditions of existence" to support our "imaginary relationship"
to the world, usually leading us to invest even more in the capacity of our
own immediate libidinal attachments to guarantee our individual
identities.
In cases where psychic suffering is connected to economic crisis,
such as the financial crisis of 2008, natural catastrophes, such as the
Mariana disaster in Brazil, or a State war against the poor in the slums,
we therefore face the additional challenge of listening not only to the
speaker's singular relation to what has happened to them - the way
these events challenged their identifications and interrupted reality by the
more-than-real - but also to the implications these events carry for the
delegated beliefs underlying the efficacy of social institutions. Could a
project which relies on the "naive observer" that believes on the regular
functioning of the State of law serve as the address of cases of State
violence? We do not ask this question in the moral sense, but in the
sense of its very clinical effectivity.
154
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
Consider, for example, the case of a mother who lost her son. A
small-time drug dealer, he was executed without any due processing by
the police after being caught in a police raid in a Brazilian favela, and his
body disappeared, as the police needed to cover their tracks. The
woman seeks help to deal with the pain of this loss – she struggles to
speak out about what happened, as the stigma of her son's occupation
seems, to many, to justify the police's behavior, and the abundance of
similar cases further silences the scandalous nature of his murder. It is
not speech alone which falters before the tragedy, but the other who
lacks the resources to "absorb" the incommensurate cesura between
cause and effects - after all, the very belief in state bureaucracy depends
on the belief on a "naive other" who only rationally executes the law,
without concern for social class and living condition of the state's
citizens. In order to have some effectivity here, the Testimony Clinic must
then carve for itself a place outside of the ideological common sense in
order to restitute the very significance of what this woman can and
cannot say. That is, it must organize itself without the help of this "naive
observer" for whom different citizens are all equal before the law - by
maintaining that the State is capable of such things, the project is in
position to not to "make sense" what took place, but to mediate the
senselessness of this traumatic event.. After individual and group
sessions, which bring together families going through similar
circumstances, the mourning mother is capable of separating the
criminal activities of her son from the phantasmatic belief that his
behavior should somehow justify his violent murder, a distinction which
allows her to work through her libidinal ties to him and to undergo the
mourning process.
What this brief vignette helps us to see is that the logistical
conditions of the clinical space – the infrastructure of delegated beliefs it
relies on in its very constitution as an "other space" – plays an important
part in its capacity to serve as an address for psychic suffering that is
traversed by traumas to the other. Perhaps this new field of problems
could help us shed a light as to why it is that the efficiency of the private
clinical setting - which remains the only setting capable of forming new
155
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
psychoanalysts, and therefore a class filter to both analytical theory and
practice - is somewhat compromised in contexts of great socioeconomic instability. What other form of legibility – other than as a
"phallic signifier" or as part of the "dynamics of surplus-enjoyment" could financial problems take in a clinical setting that itself depends on
the belief (without which the analyst would not get paid) that the market
will always take care of itself?
In Lacan's famous Seminar on the Purloined Letter (Lacan, 2006),
he paints the image of the analyst as the "emissaries of all the purloined
letters" - unaware of the meaning of these missives, we nonetheless
accept them, keeping them "en souffrance with us in the transference",
like the great detective Dupin, who is able to spot the significance of the
purloined item without ever knowing what was written on it, simply by
focusing on the circuit of exchanges it underwent in front of him. But
Lacan does not stop there, and continues to ask if "it is not the
responsibility their transference entails that we neutralize by equating it
with the signifier that most thoroughly annihilates every signification -namely, money?" (2006: 27). In other words, it is because we are paid
that our desire as analysts is not at stake in transference, the
responsibility of being addressees of these letters is neutralized insofar
as the purity of the signifier-without-signified is guaranteed by the "purity"
of the general equivalent – "the signifier that most thoroughly annihilates
every signification". Usually this passage has been interpreted as a
reduction of economic logic to the logic of the signifier: money is a
special signifier, one which can "mean" any desire to consume, as it has
no "particular" use-value – no one needs to ask "what do you want from
this?" when there is a monetary exchange taking place. But another
interpretation is possible now: the fact that the very efficacy of
transference - insofar as the formal circuit that binds these significant
normative deviations with a subject supposed to know their meaning might depend on the delegated belief on the money-form. The fetishism
of commodities grounding the fetishism of the signifier - a constitutive
ignorance concerning the necessary social conditions for speech to
acquire the form of a signifier in the clinical setting to begin with.
156
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
1
The project is currently in its second edition and is composed of several centers of
psychological care - two in São Paulo, one in Rio, one in Florianópolis and one in Porto
Alegre - and has three different complementary orientations: to provide psychological
assistance to those affected by State violence during the dictatorship, to promote
training for public servants who work in the mental health department and to produce
directions for the development of public policies. See: http://www.justica.gov.br/seusdireitos/anistia/clinicas-do-testemunho-1 and http://www.justica.gov.br/central-deconteudo/anistia/anexos/livro-clinicas-do-testemunho.pdf
2
It is important to note that both its clinical orientation - psychoanalysis or psychology? -
and its assessment of the relation between the dictatorship and democratic sequences
- continuation or distinction? - are current points of contention within the project.
3
By "significant" I mean that which can be isolated in speech by interpretation. Tom
Eyers calls this the "signifier-in-isolation" (Eyers, 2012 ) and Nancy and LacoueLabarthe, in a forgotten but masterful early work, called "significance" of the signifier, in
opposition to "signification" (Nancy & Lacoue-Labarthe, 1992)
4
Giorgio Agamben, in his famous study Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the
Archive (2002), has provided us with the paradigmatic treatment of this paradox: "In the
relation between what is said and its taking place, it w as possible to bracket the
subject of enunciation, since speech had already taken place. But the relation between
language and its existence, between langue and the archive, demands subjectivity as
that which, in its very possibility of speech, bears witness to an impossibility of speech.
This is why subjectivity appears as witness; this is why it can speak for those who
cannot speak. Testimony is a potentiality that becomes actual through an impotentiality
of speech; it is, moreover, an impossibility that gives itself existence through a possibility
of speaking. These two movements cannot be identified either with a subject or with a
consciousness; yet they cannot be divided into two incommunicable substances. Their
inseparable intimacy is testimony" (2002, 145)
5
I use the expression "inform" in the sense of "giving form" - Lacan makes an interesting
reference to this in his 16th Seminar: "What is indicated here as effect in the field of the
imaginary is nothing other than the fact that this field of the Other is, as I might say, in
the form of a. This in-forming is inscribed in a topology that, to image, (...) presents itself
as holing it" (class of 7th of May 1969)
6
Most of these comparisons have not yet received any formal or theoretical exposition, I
rely here on reports from friends and colleagues, both practitioners and users of the
project.
7
Lacan, 1998
8
Žižek, S. The interpassive subject - available at: http://www.egs.edu/faculty/slavoj-
Žižek/articles/the-interpassive-subject/
9
10
Ibid.
Karatani
157
CONTINENTAL THOUGHT & THEORY: A JOURNAL OF INTELLECTUAL FREEDOM
Interpassivity
Bibliography
Agamben, Giorgio (2002) The Remnants of Auschwitz: The Witness and the Archive
New York: Zone Books
Freud, Sigmund (1912). The Dynamics of Transference. The Standard Edition of the
Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XII (1911-1913): The
Case of Schreber, Papers on Technique and Other Works
––––––. (1913) Totem and Taboo. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Works of Sigmund Freud, Volume XII (1911-1913): The Case of Schreber, Papers
on Technique and Other Works,
Karatani, Kojin (2014) The Structure of the World History. London: Duke Press
Lacan, Jacques (1998 ) Seminar XI: Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis.
New York: W.W. Norton & Co.
––––––. (2001) Autres Écrits. Paris: Seuil
––––––. (2006) Écrits. New York: W.W.Norton & Co.
Marx, Karl (1992) Capital, volume 1. London: Penguin Books
Pfaller, Robert (2014) The Pleasure Principle in Culture: Illusions without Owners.
London: Verso
––––––. (2017) Interpassivity: The Aesthetics of Delegated Enjoyment. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press.
Tupinambá, G. (2015) in Hamza, A. & Ruda, F. Slavoj Žižek and Dalectical Materialism.
New York: Palgrave.
Žižek, Slavoj (1998) Interpassive subject - available at:
http://www.egs.edu/faculty/slavoj-Žižek/articles/the-interpassive-subject/
158