Croatian Journal of Philosophy
Vol. IX, No. 25, 2009
Linguistic Explanation
and ‘Psychological Reality’1
PETER SLEZAK
Program in Cognitive Science
University of New South Wales
Chomsky’s generative approach to linguistics has been debated for decades without consensus. Questions include the status of linguistics as
psychology, the psychological reality of grammars, the character of tacit
knowledge and the role of intuitions. I focus attention on Michael Devitt’s
critique of Chomskyan linguistics along the lines of earlier critiques by
Quine, Searle and others. Devitt ascribes an intentional conception of
grammatical knowledge that Chomsky repudiates and fails to appreciate the status of Chomsky’s computational formalisms found elsewhere
in cognitive science. I argue that Devitt’s alternative to the psychological
view – a “linguistic reality” of physical objects as the proper subject matter of linguistics – neglects the problems of tokens as opposed to types
and misses the force of Chomsky’s arguments against Behaviourism.
Furthermore, I suggest that Devitt’s case against intuitions misunderstands their standard, central role throughout perceptual psychology. Of
more general interest, I argue that Devitt’s position exemplifies compelling errors concerning mental representation seen throughout cognitive
science and philosophy of mind since the 17th Century.
Key words:
1. “Original Sin” and “Rather idle controversy”
When a debate persists over decades or even centuries without shift
in the opposing positions, there is good reason to think that the ad1
I am indebted to Michael Devitt for his gracious responses to my criticisms in
exchanges and in comments on an early version of this paper which have helped to
improve it both in form and content and to correct mistakes and misattributions.
Thanks also to John Collins and Georges Rey for most helpful remarks. For discussion
I am grateful also to Deborah Aarons, Mengistu Amberber, Eran Asoulin, Stephen
Crain, Clinton Fernandes, Iain Giblin, Peter Menzies, Nick Riemer, Benjamin
Schulz, Michael Slezak, Phil Staines, and participants in the UNSW cognitive
science discussion group.
4
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
versaries are talking past one another. The debate about knowledge of
language is prima facie a case in point. Moreover, I will suggest that the
misunderstandings involved are not unique to linguistics but pervasive
throughout cognitive science and philosophy of mind since the seventeenth century (See Slezak [2002a,b], [2006]).
For Fodor [1968] the generative approach provided a model for psychological explanation of the sort also articulated also in Pylyshyn’s
seminal work – namely, the computational view of cognition that “presupposes that we take seriously such distinctions as those between
competence and performance” ([1984], 223). A decade earlier, writing
on ‘Competence and Psychological Reality’, Pylyshyn ([1972], [1973])
explained “One reason why the notion of competence is particularly important is that it is the first clear instance of the influence of … mathematical imagination on the study of cognition” ([1972], 548) referring
to studies by Turing, Gödel, Church and others in the foundations of
mathematics and the theory of computation. Over thirty years later, it
is clear that these ideas have not become less controversial.
Michael Devitt [2006a,b] has mounted an extended critique of the
generative enterprise and compares the situation to quantum physics
where there are not only successful explanatory theories but also controversy about foundations. Devitt says in linguistics, by contrast, “There
is not a similar controversy about how to “interpret” these theories but
I think that there should be.” However, on the contrary, there has been
just this controversy from the earliest days of generative linguistics,
and we will see that Devitt is simply rehearsing the most persistent objection to the “psychological reality” of grammars as internal representations. Quine [1972] and Stich [1972] had made identical objections,
repeated by Searle [1980b], Ringen [1975] and Botha [1980].2 By 1978,
one philosopher remarked that “More has been written, much of it exasperatingly shallow, about the confusions surrounding the concept of
competence and knowledge-as-competence than almost any other topic
in recent philosophy” (Nelson [1978], 339).
In light of this history, any engagement with the issues today should
be accompanied by some diagnosis of the peculiar recalcitrance of the
debate being rehearsed. I will suggest that the interest of Devitt’s work
goes beyond the issues of linguistics with which it is directly concerned
to deep and pervasive problems throughout cognitive science. Devitt’s
work may be seen as a case study in what Rorty ([1979], 60) has called
“the original sin of epistemology” – to model knowing on seeing ([1979],
146). In a telling metaphor, Devitt suggests “If we could look into the
brain and simply “see” if there were representations of this and that, as
we can look in a book and see if there are representations … then that
would of course settle the matter” ([2006b], 51).
Devitt’s verdict is a calamitous judgment on Chomsky’s conception
of his linguistics. He writes:
2
See Slezak [1981]
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
5
I urge that linguistics is not part of psychology; that the thesis that linguistic rules are represented in the mind is implausible and unsupported; that
speakers are largely ignorant of their language; that speakers’ linguistic intuitions do not reflect information supplied by the language faculty … that
there is little or nothing to the language faculty … (Devitt [2006b], vi)
In short, on Devitt’s view just about everything in Chomsky’s conception of the status and character of the generative enterprise is wrong.
Devitt’s critique rests on two pillars: his negative critique of Chomsky’s psychological realism regarding grammars, and his positive case
for an alternative conception of a “linguistic reality” of physical tokens
that grammars are about. Devitt’s positive alternative program, the second pillar of his book (sections 12, 13 below), entails nothing less than
undoing the mentalism of the “cognitive revolution” in a return to the
nominalistic aspects of Skinnerian, Bloomfieldian behaviourism. Devitt ([2006b], 27) protests that he is not a behaviourist, 3 but embracing
“outputs/products” is precisely a concern with the data of performance
of which Chomsky had remarked it is not an arguable matter. He said
“It is simply an expression of lack of interest in theory and explanation” ([1965], 193). In this regard, we may recall Chomsky’s remarks
on “this rather idle controversy” being revived by Devitt. Remarkably,
it remains apt to characterise Devitt’s work in Chomsky’s words forty
years ago as “a paradigm example of a futile tendency in modern speculation about language and mind” [1967].
2. The “Natural” Interpretation of Chomsky
Devitt attributes an implausible intentional, propositional attitude conception of grammar to Chomsky as the most “natural interpretation”
despite Chomsky’s explicit rejection of it.4
3
Devitt (correspondence) objects to this imputation but his intentions are
irrelevant since I am drawing attention to the unnoticed implications of his doctrines.
Chomsky [1959] showed that Skinner was, malgré lui, up to his ears in psychological
assumptions, a closet mentalist, while professing a strict behaviourism. In the same
way, I am suggesting that Devitt is a closet behaviourist while professing an orthodox
mentalism.
4
Devitt claims “strong evidence” ([2006b], 10), “a great deal of evidence” ([2006c],
572) and even “massive evidence” ([2006b], 7) for the attribution to Chomsky of a
“strong commitment to RT” ([2006b], 71), while at the same time retreating behind
a formal disclaimer on the grounds that the question concerning Chomsky’s view
“is surprisingly hard to answer” ([2006b], 62). In any case, he says, “interpreting
Chomsky is not my major concern” ([2006b], 7). On the exegetical question of what
Chomsky means by the central term “represent” Devitt professes agnosticism and
refers the reader to the exchange between Rey [2003a,b] and Chomsky [2003].
However, Rey not only construes ‘representation’ in the same way that Devitt does,
but defends its attribution to Chomsky on the basis of the most uncharitable personal
attributions. Devitt gives no indication that he dissents from either the substance
or tone of Rey’s ad hominem remarks, including the charge that Chomsky holds the
intentional view despite his denials. Devitt [2007] has correctly pointed out an error
in my earlier portrayal of his attribution of RT in which I cited comments bearing on
a different issue. However, my portrayal does not depend on this erroneous evidence
6
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
The Representational Thesis (RT): A speaker of a language stands in an unconscious or tacit propositional attitude to the rules or principles of the language,
which are represented in her language faculty. ([2006a], 482, [2006b], 4)
Devitt ([2006b], 5) illustrates the doctrine with the very example of
a picture that Chomsky ([2003], 276) uses to distinguish it from his
own and RT is attributed to Chomsky despite the familiar merits of
his computational conception found elsewhere throughout cognitive science. Devitt characterises Chomsky’s view of linguistic knowledge as
“propositional knowledge of syntactic rules,” ([2003], 108) suggesting
that speakers have access to the linguists’ theories ([2003], 4). 5 Devitt
imputes the view that linguistics is the study of “the system of rules
that is the object of the speaker’s knowledge” ([2003], 109). However,
for Chomsky, the rules are not the intentional object of the speaker’s
knowledge, but rather constitute this knowledge. Chomsky’s frequent
comparisons with insects and bird-song could hardly make sense on any
other interpretation.
Devitt ([2003], 109) defends his interpretation of Chomsky because
it “takes his talk of ‘knowing that’, ‘propositional attitudes’, and ‘representation’ at face value.” He asserts “The natural interpretation attributes RT to Chomsky” ([2006b], 7). It is telling that Rey [2003b] uses
the same curious expression “the natural interpretation” as if we are
dealing with hermeneutics of the Dead Sea Scrolls whose author’s intentions are obscure or unavailable. By any reasonable measure, the
natural interpretation is clearly the one that Chomsky has repeatedly
articulated and insisted upon in specific response to the very construals offered by Devitt and Rey. Stone and Davies ([2002], 278) writing of
‘Chomsky Amongst the Philosophers,’ reflect on the fact that “Philosophers object to linguistic theories, not on the grounds that these theories fail to account adequately for the empirical evidence, but because
they fail in other ‘philosophical’ ways.”
Devitt discovers a supposed anomaly in Chomsky’s approach: “What
is puzzling about this is that a strong commitment to RT seems inappropriate in the absence of a well-supported theory of language use that
gives RT a central role” ([2006b], 71; emphasis added.). That is, Devitt
foists a view onto Chomsky that he doesn’t hold and is then mystified
by his failure to take it seriously. This exegetical strategy leads Devitt
to discover the same mystery repeatedly among other theorists such
as Fodor, Bever and Garrett [1974] and Berwick and Weinberg [1984].
Devitt says again: “This raises the old puzzling question: why be so
convinced about RT given this ignorance about its place in a theory of
processing?” ([2006b], 79]; emphasis added). Of course, the puzzle disappears if the theorists are taken at their word and not assumed to hold
RT or positing processing mechanisms.
but on remarks of the kind just noted that are difficult to reconcile with professions
of agnosticism.
5
B.C. Smith [2006] makes the same point.
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
7
3. Theory and Object
Devitt attributes implausibly naïve errors to Chomsky such as “a certain use/mention sloppiness” and a neglect of the elementary distinction between a theory and its object. Devitt says “Chomsky seems uninterested in the difference” ([2006b], 69). However, Devitt has evidently
missed Chomsky’s ([1965], 25) explicit warning about the systematic
ambiguity of the term “grammar” used to refer both to the speaker’s internally represented “theory” and also to the linguists’ account of it.6 On
its own, this oversight fatally compromises Devitt’s critique of the generative enterprise since his ascription of the intentionalist thesis RT to
Chomsky is just this mistaken attribution. Thus, it should be needless
to say that Chomsky does not suggest that the formalisms of a grammar
themselves are in the head.7 Attributing the conflation of theory and
object follows from failure to appreciate the literal, realistic construal of
abstractly specified psychological rules and representations.
4. Savoir and Connaître
In his Dioptrics Descartes proposes that the mind determines the distance
of an object by means of an implicit triangulation or parallax calculation
based on the separation of the eyes and their orientation. Descartes says
“this happens by an action of thought which, although it is only a simple
act of imagination, nevertheless implicitly contains a reasoning quite similar to that used by surveyors, when, by means of two different stations,
they measure inaccessible places” ([1637/1965], 106). This is, of course, just
Chomsky’s conception of a formal competence theory that captures our tacit
knowledge – a mathematical, computational model describing what we know
unconsciously and underlying our intuition or “simple act of imagination”
(see Slezak [2006]). Wolf-Devine ([1992], [2000a,b]) notes Descartes’ use of
the verbs savoir and connaître, suggesting that Descartes is guilty of “hopeless over-intellectualization of perception” ([2000a], 513). In the same terms
Devitt is critical of Chomsky’s “highly intellectualist” account ([2006b], 60),
a constant refrain in the chorus of criticism that Devitt joins concerning the
“psychologically reality” of formal rules and representations.
5. Fitting and Guiding.
Chomsky ([2000], 94) suggests that in its modern guise we can trace
the argument about “psychological reality” of grammars back to Quine’s
distinction between rules that are “guiding” and those merely “fitting”
or perhaps “respected,” in the way that a planet obeys Kepler’s Laws.
Above all, on such views, we must not attribute “psychological reality” to such rules. Chomsky ([1975b], 190, 198) wrote of the “singularly
misleading analogy” that is frequently made between respecting math6
The same clarification was made in Chomsky ([1972], 116) and ([1975a], 37).
See Devitt ([2006b], 4). Smith [2006] characterizes Devitt’s position as “wildly
amiss”.
7
8
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
ematical laws of physics and the rules of a grammar. However, Devitt’s
main criticism of Chomsky’s grammars is just an elaboration of this
Quinean distinction between “fitting” and “guiding” rules. Devitt’s version of Quine’s qualms is expressed as the following principle:
Distinguish processing rules that govern by being represented and applied
from ones that are simply embodied without being represented. ([2006b], 45)
Devitt says that his thesis that linguistics is not part of psychology rests
in part on this principle that he asserts is “not controversial” ([2006b],
46). However, apart from the fact that Chomsky has disputed it for forty
years, the principle is also central to intense disputes elsewhere in cognitive science (see sections 8,9 below).
6. Simply embodied: The Birds and the Bees
Devitt finds a deep paradox in the fact that Chomsky allegedly “has no
worked out opinion about, or even much interest in, how that grammar
in the head plays a role in language use” ([2007b], 71). However, on the
contrary, Chomsky has suggested plausibly that his abstract, idealized
approach to ‘competence’ is the best way to discover underlying processing correlates of grammars ([1980b], 197). Far from lacking interest in the question, Chomsky is simply responding to the obvious fact
acknowledged in Devitt’s own words that “we don’t even know enough
about what to look for” or, in Fodor’s ([1998], 145) words quoted approvingly by Devitt ([2006b], 52), “there isn’t one, not one, instance where
it’s known what pattern of neural connectivity realizes a certain cognitive content.” Thus, Chomsky expresses exactly Devitt’s own sentiment,
saying “we might go on to suggest actual mechanisms [underlying abstract rules], but we know that it would be pointless to do so in the
present stage of our ignorance concerning the functioning of the brain”
([1980b], 206,7).
Symptomatic is Devitt’s egregious misuse of Chomsky’s key technical term ‘competence’ in something like the colloquial sense of “a competence to produce” or “a competence to process” ([2006b], 17). Thus, Devitt identifies a bee’s “internal state of competence to produce the dance”
with “the processing rules within a bee that enables it to perform this
remarkable feat” – that is, “how the bee performs this dance” ([2006c],
575). This is precisely the opposite of Chomsky’s use of the crucial term
and exactly what he means by its contrasting “performance.”8
On one alternative to the “most natural” reading of Chomsky’s words,
he is taken to hold that language rules are merely embodied “without
being represented” ([2006b], 7, [2003], 109). However, Rey, like Devitt,
finds it implausible that an ant might represent “the system of vector
8
See also Smith ([2006], 449). Here Devitt [2007] seems to be correct in his
response to Smith, since the issue can’t turn on whether von Frisch’s account is
empirically correct or not but only on the distinctions it is used to illustrate.
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
9
algebra itself” ([2003b], 153).9 Instead, Rey suggests “That system is, at
best, merely implemented somehow in the ant’s nervous system.” However, given Devitt’s stipulation of how “representation” is to be used,
this is simply an arbitrary terminological matter of no theoretical interest. Indeed, as we will see, from another point of view Devitt is merely
re-stating Chomsky’s own competence/performance distinction.
Devitt says “We need psychological evidence to show which grammar’s rules are in fact playing the role in linguistic processing, evidence
we do not have.” Indeed, Devitt adds, “We need evidence that the syntactic rules of any grammar are processing rules. These rules may simply be the wrong sort of rules to be processing rules” ([2006b], 37). There
could be no more explicit indication of the source of the persistent worry
about the formalisms of a competence theory. Searle [1980b] made the
stereotypical complaint in terms now repeated almost verbatim by Devitt, Searle explained:
Additional evidence is required to show that they are rules that the agent is
actually following, and not mere hypotheses or generalizations that correctly
describe his behavior. … there must be some independent reason for supposing that the rules are functioning causally. ([1980b], 37)
Devitt’s scepticism about rules is a refusal to accept the abstract idealizations of grammars when their underlying processing realization
is unknown. However, if the term “psychological reality” is granted as
referring by stipulation to processing mechanisms, then the debate collapses, Devitt’s position being no more than a restatement of the competence-performance distinction – a point also noted by Laurence ([2003],
87). This charge is easy to substantiate, as we can see from Devitt’s
statements:
It is not enough to know that there is something-we-know-not-what within
a speaker that respects the rules of her language … We would like to go beyond these minimal claims to discover the ways in which the competence of
the speaker … respect these rules. ([2006b], 38)
Chomsky writes:
…we are keeping to abstract conditions that unknown mechanisms must
meet. We might go on to suggest actual mechanisms, but we know that it
would be pointless to do so in the present stage of our ignorance concerning
the functioning of the brain. ([1980b], 197)
Chomsky’s phrase “abstract conditions that unknown mechanisms
must meet” is precisely Devitt’s “Respect Constraint” (see section 11
below). Devitt [2007] insists that this is insufficient for “the grammar
alone … does not tell us what there is in the speaker that does the respecting” and “the grammar alone gives us no reason to suppose that
the formalisms are descriptive about the mind.” Chomsky [1980a] has
parodied exactly this question since, unless “descriptive” concerns per9
Rey ([2003b], 157,8) responds to Chomsky with sarcasm, accusations of
inconsistency or insincerity and the evidence of his colleagues’ shared incomprehension
(Rey [2003b], 160 fn 19).
10
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
formance or processing, there can be no other answer besides repeating
the evidence on which the grammar is proposed. Terminology aside,
Chomsky’s competence-performance distinction might well be encapsulated in Devitt’s own supposed challenge: “A grammar may have nothing more to do with psychological reality than comes from meeting the
Respect Constraint” ([2006b], 37).
7. “Cognize”
It is clear that the “debate” has long ago degenerated into a ritual talking past one another. Chomsky and Katz [1974], 363) replied to Stich’s
[1972] “projectile” argument saying: “At best, it is an open question
whether more than an uninteresting issue of terminology is involved.”
Regarding the terminological issue, Devitt says “The term ‘know’ is
mostly used for the propositional attitude in question but, when the chips
are down, Chomsky is prepared to settle for the technical term ‘cognize’”
([2006b], 4; emphasis added). We may note the irony of Devitt’s accusation of a certain “looseness of talk of ‘knowledge.’” Devitt says “I think
that linguistics would do better to avoid the talk” of knowledge ([2006b],
5). However, it was precisely because of Devitt’s sort of misapprehension arising from the misleading connotations of the term “know” that
Chomsky ([1986], 265) himself suggested that it might be replaced with
the neologism “cognize.” Devitt evidently misses Chomsky’s very effort
to dispel confusion, adopting it as his own, while seeing Chomsky’s proposal as a compromise or implicit concession to his critics.
8. “Epiphobia”
Responding to persistent complaints about “psychological reality” Chomsky describes the term as “hopelessly misleading and pointless” and
arising from a methodological dualism that makes invidious distinction
between linguistics and other sciences. Seeking the deeper sources of
this error, we may note Fodor’s [1990] diagnosis of “epiphobia” – as he
dubs the neurotic fear of the causal inertness of the mental. Evidently
harbouring this fear, Devitt says “we should only posit such representations [of rules] if we can find some serious causal work that they have
to do” ([2006b], 52). Chomsky’s grounds for attributing causal efficacy
to rules is just that they have a place in our best explanatory theories
(Chomsky [1980a,b]). Devitt regards this argument as “fast” and “dirty”
([2006c], 574), but Fodor notes that the case against the reality of psychological posits would also require epiphenomenalism with regard to
all non-physical properties: “If beliefs and desires as are well off ontologically as mountains, wings, spiral nebulas, trees, gears, levers, and
the like, then surely they’re as well off as anyone could need them to be”
([1990], 141). Rules are psychologically real for the same reason, even if
we have no idea about the underlying realization – “what there is in the
speaker that does the respecting” (Devitt [2007]).
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
11
9. “But it doesn’t really”
Essentially the same problem concerning the reality of rules has arisen
for connectionist models too (Bechtel & Abrahamsen [2002], 120) Typical of a vast literature,10 almost at random we can pick Smolensky’s
remark that in the case of a certain connectionist model, “It’s as though
the model had those laws written down inside it” but he adds the curious qualification “But it doesn’t really” ([1998], 20). That is, “The system is … not really satisfying the hard rules at all.”11 In the same vein,
Clark ([1990], 292) writes that in connectionist systems “the processing
can hardly be sensitive to structures which aren’t there.” In these remarks we see the familiar idea that, although a system might conform
to (or “respect”) rules, they are not real. Pinker and Prince note the
basis for such rule-skepticism: Instead of “explicit” representations, we
have weighted connections and activation levels among which “one cannot easily point to rules, algorithms, expressions, and the like” ([1988],
76; emphasis added).
Theorists evidently use a certain implicit criterion for literal attribution of structure – namely, whether it is apparent to inspection for the
theorist.12 However, we see the crucial point made by D. Kirsh ([1990],
351) who observes “what humans are able to see is irrelevant.”13 He
gives an apt diagnosis of just this problem arising from “the bewitching image of a word printed on a page” ([1990], 350) – Devitt’s “original
sin.” We will see that this is a key insight into the illusion of explanatory adequacy derived from tacit dependence on our own interpretative
abilities.
10. Functionalism
Fodor ([1968], ix) noted that Chomsky’s grammars illustrate the functionalist conception of mind – the modern statement of what it means to
do psychology in the information processing paradigm and to attribute
internal representations. Chomsky’s writes:
The mentalist … need make no assumptions about the possible physiological
basis for the mental reality he studies. … One would guess … that it is the
mentalistic studies that will ultimately be of greatest value for the investigation of neurophysiological mechanisms, since they alone are concerned with
determining abstractly the properties that such mechanisms must exhibit
and the functions they must perform. ([1965], 193)
Failing to appreciate Chomsky’s ([1982], 10) idealizations, like Marr’s
([1982], 28), Devitt says “it is hard to see how it [a grammar] could be
a theory at the computational level” ([2006b], 66). For example, Chom10
See Van Gelder [1990]; Pinker, S. and Mehler, J. (eds) [1988]; Horgan, T. &
Tienson, J. (eds) [1991]; Ramsey, W., Stich S., & Rumelhart, D.E., (eds) [1991].
11
See also Waskan & Bechtel [1997].
12
See van Gelder ([1992], 180), Ramsey, Stich & Garon [1991].
13
See also Cummins [1996] and McDermott [1981].
12
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
sky’s conception of associating a sound with a meaning is misunderstood
as a causal, mechanical, processing matter, whereas for Chomsky it is a
purely formal, descriptive one, as Pylyshyn explains ([1973], 44). Even
where Devitt ([2006b], 68) acknowledges the purely mathematical sense
of the notion of “generate” he fails to appreciate the precise force of this
conception according to which one says that an axiom system generates
its theorems.14 Above all, this formal sense of the term ‘generate’ is not
“merely metaphorical” in any sense, as Devitt seems to think.
11. “R - E - S - P - E - C - T: Find out what it means to me”
(Aretha Franklin)
Devitt ([2006b], 57) elaborates five possible positions on language use,
some having two versions, and three versions of the idea that rules
might be internally represented. He also enunciates eight numbered
precepts, four methodological points, various named theses and technical distinctions. However, once we adjust for Devitt’s choice of terminology, particularly his notable misuse of the key term ‘competence’, we
have only a re-statement of Chomsky’s own views, though much less
perspicuous than the original. Devitt says “I emphasize that ‘respecting’
as I am using it, is a technical term” to distinguish processing rules from
“structure rules” that are merely conformed with or “respected.” Thus,
“something counts as a chess move at all only if it has a place in the
structure defined by the rules of chess” as distinct from “the rules governing the psychological process by which [a player] … produces chess
moves.” Devitt irrelevantly but tellingly characterizes the latter as “interesting,” but his analysis simply restates Chomsky’s competence/performance distinction. Devitt’s “interesting” rules are those concerning
the “heuristic” aspect of problem solving of the kind exemplified in the
work of Newell and Simon [1972], but must be distinguished from the
‘epistemological’ or formal approach (see Pylyshyn [1973], 22). That is,
the first pillar of Devitt’s account – his critique of Chomsky (where it
goes beyond the misattribution of RT) – collapses into a verbal quibble.
Devitt seems to appreciate the point in a footnote: “I do not take it [a
grammar] to be real simply in virtue of its meeting the Respect Constraint. But this difference may be just verbal” ([2006b], 67).
12. Unimaginative Nominalist.
Gurgling and Throat Clearing.
Devitt’s central thesis that linguistics is not a branch of psychology
rests on his argument that “there is something other than psychological
reality for a grammar to be true of: it can be true of a linguistic reality”
([2006b], 17). This “linguistic reality” is constituted by the “outputs of
competence” such as “physical sentence tokens” and the “properties of
14
See Collins ([2006], 495).
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
13
symbols” or “certain sounds in the air, inscriptions on paper” ([2006b],
v)
Surprisingly, Devitt ([2006b], 26) acknowledges that his position
corresponds with the Bloomfieldian ‘nominalism’ that was supplanted
by ‘conceptualism’ on the basis of Chomsky’s powerful criticisms. However, Devitt says: “Yet, so far as I can see, these criticisms are not of the
nominalism of the structuralists but rather of their taxonomic methodology” ([2006b], 26). Devitt thinks that a “linguistic reality” of physical
tokens has an epistemic and explanatory priority over a psychological
reality, but the situation is exactly the reverse. Devitt ([2006b], 88) professes acceptance of Chomsky’s critique of Behaviourism but he sees the
critique as bearing only on “a crude empiricist dislike of things unseen;
an unwillingness to posit theoretical entities that explain the observed
phenomena.” However, Chomsky’s remarkable review exposed not just
the fear of hypotheses about “things unseen”, but Skinner’s unwitting
commitment to mentalist conceptions. This fatal flaw in the behaviourist apparatus is not the same as the mistake of assuming that behaviour
is under stimulus control, as Devitt seems to think ([2006b], 87). Thus,
Devitt’s very identification of “outputs of a competence,” employs what
Chomsky describes as a device that is “as simple as it is empty” for it
“simply disguises a complete retreat to mentalistic psychology” ([1959],
32). Devitt reveals that he is victim of Kirsh’s ([1990], 350) “bewitching
image” or interpretative illusion, saying: “This work and talk [by linguists] seems to be concerned with the properties of items like the very
words on this page” ([2006b], 31).15
As Smith has put it, “Without the cognitive wherewithal to represent sounds as symbols they would be heard as no more than inarticulate gurgling or throat clearing” ([2006], 438). The theorist cannot help
himself to the linguistic properties of these physical tokens since, as
Rey [2006a,b], Laurence ([2003], 89) and Bromberger ([1989],73) have
argued, there is an important sense in which they don’t exist at all independently of minds. In short, Devitt’s nominalism reduces either to a
futile interest in heterogeneous physical data or an unwitting inquiry
into psychological competence after all. Bromberger notes that linguists
“habitually conflate mention of tokens with mention of types” but “tokens are not what linguistics is primarily concerned with. Types are”
([1989], 59). With Halle he writes:
Types turn out to be rather innocuous things to which only the most unimaginative nominalists should object. ([1992], 15)
Bromberger concludes “linguistics is not just about types and tokens
but is also inescapably about minds.”
13. They ain’t nothin’ until I call ‘em.
Devitt asks: “What makes a physical object a pawn?” taking the anal15
See also Hadley [1995].
14
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
ogy with chess to show that linguistic investigation is not psychological.
However, the physical pieces and their moves do not have explanatory
priority. Clearly, anything might serve as a token of a knight or bishop.
Pieces of wood and their movements don’t even count as tokens of symbols or “outputs of competence” except insofar as they are classified in
this way by prior conceptualisation according to mentally represented,
intentional rules – a point long familiar in the philosophy of social sciences.16 Of course, we might investigate the Queen’s Gambit, Sicilian
Defence and Nimzovich variation without concern for their status as
human knowledge. The central issue is not the independence of the abstract rules governing these objects, but their very status. In the same
way, Chomsky claims that language has no existence apart from its
mental representation ([1972], 169). Without legislating what enquiry
to pursue, he says that study of the outputs of competence like horseshoes and language tokens has proven to be sterile.
14. Possible Idealized Horseshoes
The ‘cognitive revolution’ and the study of generative grammar involved
the very shift that Devitt unintentionally seeks to reverse – the shift
described by Chomsky “from behavior or the products of behavior to
states of the mind/brain that enter into behavior” ([1986], 3; emphasis
added).17 Devitt explains that he “is not concerned simply with the actual outputs”, but also with “possible idealized outputs” ([2006b], 24) of
a system “when it performs as it should.” That is, the theory idealizes
from actual products of behaviour to concern “with any of an indefinitely large number of outputs that they might produce” ([2006b], 18).
However, with this counterfactual, “modal” terminology, Devitt disguises the central idea of generative linguistics as if his project is something
other than Chomsky’s own enterprise. Good horseshoes and potential
horseshoes are not physical in the sense required by Devitt, but a commitment to just the idealization of a grammar Chomsky describes as “a
system of rules that generates an infinite class of “potential percepts”
([1972], 168), or perhaps potential horseshoes.
Pylyshyn noted that “A constant source of misunderstanding and
debate over the relevance of competence theories [to psychology] has
to do with the fact that they define infinite sets” ([1973], 40). Devitt’s
([2006b], 27) preferred talk of there being “no limit” to “nonactual
possible sentences” is simply code for Chomsky’s familiar talk of our
Humboldtian infinite capacity through finite means and the Cartesian
“creativity” of language. In particular, Devitt’s talk of a grammar being
“lawlike” is simply a paraphrase for the generative capacity of recursive
procedures.
16
Rawls [1955]. In a famous anecdote, three baseball umpires remark in turn: ‘I
call ‘em as I see ‘em,’ said the first, an empiricist. ‘I call ‘em the way they are,’ said the
realist. The third, Charlie Moran, explained: ‘They ain’t nothin’ until I call ‘em.’
17
See also Chomsky ([2000], 5).
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
15
15. Intuitions: Destroying the Subject.
Devitt argues that “speakers’ intuitions are not the main evidence for
linguistic theories” ([2006b], 96) and do not support the claims for grammars as mentally represented. Rather than being “the voice of competence”, Devitt suggests linguistic intuitions are “opinions resulting
from ordinary empirical investigation, theory-laden in the way all such
opinions are” ([2006b], 98). However, Chomsky ([1982], 16) has drawn
an analogy with mathematics which can also be construed as a grammar representing tacit knowledge of conceptual structures – essentially
the Intuitionist view according to which mathematical formalisms have
no independent existence apart from the constructions of the mind.18
Gödel’s [1944] famous reference to mathematical intuition as a kind of
perception is crucial here. Despite Devitt’s animadversions, this form
of evidence is commonplace and uncontroversial elsewhere throughout
psychology. Devitt explicitly rejects the analogy of linguistic intuitions
with perceptual experience ([2006b], 112) but he draws precisely the
wrong conclusion from his own allusion to Fodor’s [1983] account of the
visual module.19 Devitt suggests that perceptual judgments correspond
to “what is seen” which would be analogous to the content of what is
said and not syntactic properties of expressions. However, the perceptual judgments that are relevant in the visual case are emphatically
not “what is seen” in the “success” or “achievement” sense of such terms
that Devitt ([2006b], 114) relies upon, but in the sense of what seems to
be the case.20
Devitt ([2006b], 111) refers to “correct” intuitions and expresses
doubts about “Cartesian access to the truth” ([2006b], 106) as if there
is some objective fact of the matter beyond the subject’s perceptions.
Thus, he asks “whose intuitions should we most trust?” ([2006b], 108)
and answers that of “linguists themselves because the linguists are the
most expert” ([2006b], 111). However, in psychology as in linguistics,
there is no relevant expertise about the data beyond the authority of
the subject’s own perceptions. In this sense, we are all experts or, in
Hoffman’s [1998] term, “virtuosos.” The visual module doesn’t provide
the truth about the distal stimulus but only a perceptual judgment, just
like Chomsky’s grammar. The two interpretations of the Necker Cube
are closely analogous to the two meanings of an ambiguous sentence as
percepts of a native speaker. Chomsky explains:
A grammar is a system of rules that generates an infinite class of “potential
percepts”, … In short, we can begin by asking “what is perceived” and move
from there to a study of perception. ([1972], 168,9)
The place of intuition in grammars hardly deserves to be controversial
18
See Gil [1983]. See also Pylyshyn,( [1973], 31); Parsons [1995].
Ironically, Fodor illustrates his point with Ullman’s [1979] algorithmic theory,
exactly the same example used by Chomsky ([1986], 264) to illustrate the nature of
his own computational theory.
20
See Ryle ([1949], 152).
19
16
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
unless the whole of perceptual psychology is also open to the difficulties
alleged to arise for linguistics. Thus, Chomsky explained the interest
of his famous pair ‘John is easy/eager to please’ saying that introspective “data of this sort are simply what constitute the subject matter
for linguistic theory. We neglect such data at the cost of destroying the
subject” ([1964], 79).
17. Conclusion
The widely shared concern about “psychological reality” of grammars
appears to be a manifestation of deep errors that are not difficult to recognize in other recalcitrant debates concerning mental representation
(see Slezak [2002a]). Specifically, the debates turn on a certain illusion
of explanatory adequacy arising when posited representations are intelligible in a direct, intuitive sense, like the “bewitching image of a word
printed on a page” – Kirsh’s echo of Arnauld’s reproach to Malebranche
in the 17th century. Searle’s [1980a] criterion of intentionality in his
‘Chinese Room’ is the intelligibility of symbols to himself, the theorist.
Similarly, pictorial representations have been deemed appropriate explanations of visual imagery because they are intuitively intelligible to
the theorist, as Pylyshyn [2003] has tirelessly complained. For closely
related reasons, Carruthers ([1996], [1998]) has argued that we think
in a natural language (see Slezak [2002b]). Ryle [1968] had warned
against just this kind of error arising from invoking internal representations that have their meaning because we can understand them.
Devitt’s complaint that Chomsky’s grammars may be the wrong sort of
internal rules is implicitly to rely on this mistake, the same mistake as
his assumption that external token physical symbols might have linguistic properties.
Chomsky explained that traditional grammars produce an illusion
of explanatory completeness, but in fact have “serious limitations so
far as linguistic science is concerned” because the success of the grammar depends on being “paired with an intelligent and comprehending
reader”. That is, it is the reader and not the grammar that is doing a
significant part of the work. Chomsky explains:
What he accomplishes can fairly be described as theory construction
of quite a nontrivial kind. … The reader is, of course, not at all aware
of what he has done or how he has done it. … Reliance on the reader’s
intelligence is so commonplace that is significance may be easily overlooked. ([1962], 528,9)
References
Bechtel, W. and Abrahamsen, A. [2002], Connectionism and the Mind, Oxford: Blackwell.
Berwick, R.C. and Weinberg, A.S. [1984], The Grammatical Basis of Linguistic Performance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
17
Botha, R. [1980], Methodological Bases of a Progressive Mentalism. Synthese 44, 1-112.
Bromberger, S. [1989], Types and Tokens in Linguistics. In A. George (ed)
Reflections on Chomsky. Oxford: Basil Blackwell; reprinted in his On
What We Know We Don’t Know. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1992.
Bromberger, S. and Halle M. [1992], The Ontology of Phonology. In S.
Bromberger, On What We Know We Don’t Know. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Carruthers, P. [1996], Language, Thought and Consciousness: An Essay in
Philosophical Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Carruthers, P. [1998], Thinking in Language? In P. Carruthers and J.
Boucher (eds) Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chomsky, N. [1959], Review of Skinner’s Verbal Behavior. Language, 35, 1,
26-58; reprinted in L.A. Jakobovits and M. S. Miron (eds) Readings in the
Psychology of Language. Englesood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall.
Chomsky, N. [1962], Explanatory Models in Linguistics. In E. Nagel, P.
Suppes, A. Tarski (eds) Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science.
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 528-550.
Chomsky, N. [1964], Current Issues in Linguistic Theory. In Structure of
Language, J. A. Fodor and J.J. Katz (eds) New York: Prentice-Hall
Chomsky, N. [1965], Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. [1967], Preface to Review of Skinner’s ‘Verbal Behavior’. In
Leon A. Jakobovits and Murray S. Miron (eds) Readings in the Psychology of Language. Prentice-Hall, 142-143.
Chomsky, N. [1972] Language and Mind. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich.
Chomsky, N. [1975a], The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory. New York:
Plenum Press.
Chomsky, N. [1975b], Reflections on Language. New York: Random House.
Chomsky, N. [1980a], Biological Basis of Language Capacities, in Rules and
Representations, New York: Columbia University Press.
Chomsky, N. [1980b], Rules and Representations, and Peer Commentary
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 1-61.
Chomsky, N. [1982], The Generative Enterprise: A Discussion with Riny
Huybregts and Hekn van Riemsdijk. Dordrecht: Foris Publications.
Chomsky, N. [1986], Knowledge of Language: Its Nature, Origin and Use.
New York: Praeger.
Chomsky, N. [2000], New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind.
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Chomsky, N. [2003], Replies. In L.M. Antony and N. Hornstein (eds) Chomsky and his Critics. Oxford: Blackwell.
Chomsky, N. & Katz, J.J. [1974], What the Linguist is Talking About. The
Journal of Philosophy. 71, 12, June, 347-367.
Clark, A. [1990], Connectionism, Competence, and Explanation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 41, 195-222; reprinted in M. A.
Boden ed. 1990, The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
18
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
Collins, J. [2006], Between a rock and a hard place: A dialogue on the philosophy and methodology of generative linguistics, Croatian Journal of
Philosophy, 6, 18, 469-503.
Cummins, R. [1996], Representations, Targets and Attitudes, Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT/Bradford.
Descartes, R. [1637/1965], Discourse on Method, Optics, Geometry, and Meteorology, Translated by Paul J. Olscamp, New York: Bobbs-Merrill.
Devitt, M. [2003], Linguistics is not Psychology, in A. Barber ed. Epistemology of Language, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Devitt, M. [2006a], Intuitions in Linguistics, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 481-513.
Devitt, M. [2006b], Ignorance of Language, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Devitt, M. [2006c], Defending Ignorance of Language: Responses to the Dubrovnik Papers, Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 6, 18, 571-606.
Devitt, M. [2007], Dodging the argument on the subject matter of grammars: A response to John Collins and Peter Slezak, manuscript.
Devitt, M. and Sterelny, K. [1987], Language and Reality: An Introduction
to the Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Blackwell; (Second edition 1999).
Devitt, M. and Sterelny, K. [1989], Linguistics: What’s Wrong with ‘The
Right View’? Philosophical Perspectives, 3, 497-531.
Fodor, J.A. [1968], Psychological Explanation, New York: Random House.
Fodor, J.A. [1983], The Modularity of Mind, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Fodor, J.A. [1990], Making Mind Matter More, in A Theory of Content and
Other Essays, Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.
Fodor, J.A. [1998], In Critical Condition, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Fodor, J.A., Bever T.G. and Garrett, M.F. [1974], The Psychology of Language: An Introduction to Psycholinguistics and Generative Grammar.
New York: McGraw Hill.
Fodor, J.A. & Pylyshyn, Z. [1988], Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis, Cognition 28, 3-71; reprinted in Pinker and
Mehler eds., [1988], Connections and Symbols, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Gil, D. [1983], Intuitionism, Transformational Generative Grammar and
Mental Acts, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 14, 3, 231254.
Gödel, K. [1944], Russell’s Mathematical Logic, In P.A. Schilpp ed., The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, Evanston: Northwestern University Press;
reprinted in P. Benacerraf and H. Putnam eds, Philosophy of Mathematics, 2nd edition, 1983, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hadley, R.F. [1990], Truth Conditions and Procedural Semantics. In Philip
Hanson ed., Information, Language and Cogntion. Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press.
Hadley, R.F. [1995], The “Explicit - Implicit” Distinction, Minds and Machines, 5, 219-242.
Hoffman, D.D. [1998], Visual Intelligence: How We Create What We See,
New York: Norton and Company.
Horgan, T. & Tienson, J. eds., [1991], Connectionism and the Philosophy of
Mind, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
19
Kirsh, D. [1990], When is Information Explicitly Represented? in Hanson,
ed., Information, Language and Cognition, Vancouver: University of
British Columbia Press.
Laurence, S. [2003], Is Linguistics a Branch of Psychology? in A. Barber ed.
Epistemology of Language, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lerdahl, F. and Jackendoff, R. [1983], A Generative Theory of Tonal Music,
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Marr, D. [1982], Vision, New York: Freeman.
Matthews, R.J. [2006], Knowledge of Language and Linguistic Competence,
Philosophical Issues, 16, 200-220.
Nelson, R.J. [1978], The Competence-Performance Distinction in Mental
Philosophy, Synthese, 39, 337-381.
Newell, A. and Simon, H.A. [1972], Human Problem Solving. Englewood
Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Parsons, C. [1995], ‘Platonism and Mathematical Intuition in Kurt Gödel’s
Thought’. The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 1, 44-74.
Pinker, S. and Mehler, J. eds., [1988], Connections and Symbols, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Pinker, S. and Prince, A. [1988], On Language and Connectionism: Analysis
of a Parallel Distributed Processing Model of Language Acquisition, in S.
Pinker and J. Mehler eds. [1988]. Connections and Symbols, Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Pylyshyn, Z. [1972], Competence and Psychological Reality, American Psychologist, June, 546-552.
Pylyshyn, Z. [1973], The Role of Competence Theories in Cognitive Psychology, Journal of Psycholinguistic Research, 2, 1, 21-50.
Pylyshyn, Z. [1984], Computation and Cognition, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Pylyshyn, Z. [2003], Seeing and Visualizing: It’s Not What You Think, Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Quine, W.V. [1972], Methodological Reflection on Current Linguistic Theory, D. Davidson and G. Harman eds. Semantics of Natural Language,
Dordrecht: D. Reidel.
Ramsey, W., Sitch, S. and Garon, J. [1991], Connectionism, Eliminativism
and the Future of Folk Psychology, in W. Ramsey, S. Stich and D. Rumelhart, eds., 1991 Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, Hillsdale, N.J.:
Lawrence Erlbaum.
Ramsey, W., Stich S., & Rumelhart, D.E. eds., [1991], Philosophy and Connectionist Theory, Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Rawls, J. [1955], Two Concepts of Rules, The Philosophical Review, 64, 3-32;
reprinted in S. Gorovitz ed., Utilitarianism: John Stuart Mill, New York:
Bobbs-Merrill.
Rey, G. [2003a], Chomsky, Intentionality, and a CRTT, in L.M. Antony and
N. Hornstein eds., Chomsky and his Critics, Oxford: Blackwell.
Rey, G. [2003b], Intentional Content and a Chomskian Linguistics, in A.
Barber ed. Epistemology of Language, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rey, G. [2006a], The Intentional Inexistence of Language – But Not Cars,
in R.J. Stainton ed., Contemporary Debates in Cognitive Science, Oxford:
Blackwells.
20
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
Rey, G. [2006b], Conventions, Intuitions and Linguistic Inexistents: A Reply to Devitt, Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 6, 18, 549-569.
Ringen, J.D. [1975], Linguistic Facts: A Study of the Empirical Scientific
Status of Transformational Generative Grammars, in D. Cohen and J.R.
Wirth eds., Testing Linguistic Hypotheses, Washington, D.C.: Hemisphere Publishing Corporation.
Rorty, R. [1979], Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Ryle, G. [1949], The Concept of Mind, London: Hutchinson.
Ryle, G. [1968], A Puzzling Element in the Notion of Thinking, in P.F.
Strawson ed., Studies in the Philosophy of Thought and Action, Oxford :
Oxford University Press, 7-23.
Searle, J. [1980a], Minds, Brains and Programs, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417-24; reprinted in in M.A. Boden ed., [1990], The Philosophy
of Artificial Intelligence, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Searle, J. [1980b], Rules and Causation: Reply to Chomsky, Behavioural
and Brain Sciences, 3, 37-38.
Simon, H.A. and Newell, A. [1964], Information Processing in Computer
and Man, in Z. Pylyshyn ed., Perspectives on the Computer Revolution,
New York: Prentice-Hall.
Skinner, B.F. [1957], Verbal Behavior, NY: Appleton-Century Crofts.
Slezak, P. [1981], Language and Psychological Reality, Synthese, 48, 3, 427440.
Slezak, P. [2002a], The Tripartite Model of Representation, Philosophical
Psychology, 13, 3, 239-270.
Slezak, P. [2002b], Thinking About Thinking: Language, Thought & Introspection, Language & Communication, 22, 353-373.
Slezak, P. [2006], ‘Cartesian ‘Ideas’ and the First (C17th) Cognitive Revolution.’ Ron Sun (ed.) Proceedings of the 28th Annual Conference of the
Cognitive Science Society, Vancouver, BC, Canada, July 26-29, Mahwah,
New Jersey, 798-803.
Smith, B.C. [2006], Why We Still Need Knowledge of Language, Croatian
Journal of Philosophy 6, 18, 431-456.
Smolensky, [1988], On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism, Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 11, 1-74.
Stich, S. [1972], Grammar, Psychology, and Indeterminacy, The Journal of
Philosophy, 69, 22, December, 799-818.
Stone, T. and Davies, M. [2002], Chomsky Amongst the Philosophers, Mind
& Language, 17, 3, 276-289.
Ullman, S. [1979], The Interpretation of Visual Motion, Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
van Gelder, T. [1990], Compositionality: A Connectionist Variation on a
Classical Theme, Cognitive Science, 14, 355-384.
van Gelder, T. [1992], Making Conceptual Space, S. David ed., Connectionism: Theory and Practice, Oxford: Oxford University Press
Waskan, J. & Bechtel, W. [1997], Directions in Connectionist Research:
Tractable Computations Without Syntactically Structured Representations, Metaphilosophy, 28, 1&2, 31-62.
Wolf-Devine, C. [1993], Descartes on Seeing: Epistemology and Visual Perception, Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
P. Slezak, Linguistic Explanation and ‘Psychological Reality’
21
Wolf-Devine, C. 2000a. Descartes’ theory of visual spatial perception, in S.
Gaukroger, J. Schuster, J. Sutton, eds., [2000], Descartes’ Natural Philosophy, London: Routledge, 506-523.
Wolf-Devine, C. [2000b], The role of inner objects in perception, in S. Gaukroger, J. Schuster, J. Sutton, eds., [2000], Descartes’ Natural Philosophy,
London: Routledge, 557-568.