Evidence does not equal knowledge
Philosophical Studies
An International Journal for
Philosophy in the Analytic
Tradition
ISSN 0031-8116
Volume 153
Number 2
Philos Stud (2009) 153:235-242
DOI 10.1007/
s11098-009-9488-1
1 23
Your article is protected by copyright and
all rights are held exclusively by Springer
Science+Business Media B.V.. This e-offprint
is for personal use only and shall not be selfarchived in electronic repositories. If you
wish to self-archive your work, please use the
accepted author’s version for posting to your
own website or your institution’s repository.
You may further deposit the accepted author’s
version on a funder’s repository at a funder’s
request, provided it is not made publicly
available until 12 months after publication.
1 23
Author's personal copy
Philos Stud (2011) 153:235–242
DOI 10.1007/s11098-009-9488-1
Evidence does not equal knowledge
Aaron Rizzieri
Published online: 5 December 2009
Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009
Abstract Timothy Williamson has argued that a person S’s total evidence is
constituted solely by propositions that S knows. This theory of evidence entails that
a false belief can not be a part of S’s evidence base for a conclusion. I argue by
counterexample that this thesis (E = K for now) forces an implausible separation
between what it means for a belief to be justified and rational from one’s perspective
and what it means to base one’s beliefs on the evidence. Furthermore, I argue that
E = K entails the implausible result that there are cases in which a well-evidenced
belief necessarily can not serve as evidence for a further proposition.
Keywords
Epistemology Evidence Justification Knowledge
1 Introduction
Timothy Williamson has argued that one proposition e can serve as evidence for a
hypothesis h for a subject s under two conditions. The first condition is that the
proposition e must be known, and the second condition is that the probability of h on
e must be greater than the probability of h alone.1
It is my purpose to challenge this first constraint on evidence (E = K for now). In
Sect. 1, I argue by counterexample that (E = K) forces an implausible separation
between what it means for a belief to be rational, justified, and properly guided in its
formation on the one hand, and evidentially supported on the other. These
1
For Williamson’s views on evidence see his (2000, Chs. 9 and 10). This essay will concern chapter 9
exclusively.
A. Rizzieri (&)
Humanities Department, LaGuardia Community College, 31-10 Thompson Avenue,
Long Island City, NY 11101, USA
e-mail: aaron.rizzieri@gmail.com
123
Author's personal copy
236
A. Rizzieri
arguments are similar in spirit to arguments that evidentialists and other epistemic
internalists have used against reliabilist views of justification.2
In Sect. 2, I suggest a possible response to these arguments that is in accord with
how Williamson handles cases of perceptual illusion. I then argue that this response
leads to the implausible conclusion that a false belief can have the property of being
evidentially supported and yet necessarily cannot itself serve as evidence for further
beliefs. Furthermore, I argue that there are cases involving ‘‘forgotten evidence’’
(Goldman 1999) in which it becomes especially awkward to insist that the false
belief that is serving as an immediate ground of an inferred belief is not part of the
evidence base for that belief.
2 An argument by counterexample
Let us consider a situation in which it can be argued that a person’s evidence base
contains a false belief. In cases of inferred beliefs, it is especially plausible to hold
that a belief that p is justified if and only if one properly bases this belief on
evidence that one possesses in favor of that p. A reliabilist, for example, might deny
that having justification for our basic beliefs entails having evidence for these
beliefs. It should be noted that Williamson holds that having a justified belief that p
entails having evidence that p.3 The examples that will occupy our attention involve
inferred beliefs that are justified because there is evidence for them.4
Consider the following case. I believe that nobody can enter my office (O for
now) because I believe that I have just locked the door (LD for now). Let us
stipulate that I have inferred (O) from (LD). I pushed the lock in and gave it a quick
twist to the left, which usually does the trick; however, my lock is damaged and
does not work. Hence, (LD) is false.
If Williamson’s proposal that (E = K) is correct then (LD) can not serve as an
evidential ground for (O). This generates problems for (E = K). The first difficulty
is that it is very plausible that (LD) does partially constitute my evidence for (O).
After all, I am justified in believing (LD), (LD) supports (O), and an explicit
inference from (LD) is my most immediate basis or ground for (O). I have other
indirect grounds for (O) as well. For example, whatever my evidence for (LD) is
(see below), is also evidence for (O). Why should my indirect grounds for (O), count
as evidence for (O) when (LD) does not? Obviously, Williamson’s answer is going
2
I have in mind Laurence Bonjour’s clairvoyance argument and Stewart Cohen’s ‘‘new evil demon’’
argument. See Bonjour (1980) and Cohen (1984).
3
For Williamson’s discussion of the relationship between justification and evidence see his (2000, pp.
207–208). This might be a little bit surprising because Williamson’s account of evidence is externalist in
nature in both the conceptual and epistemic senses of the term ‘external.’
4
It is common for epistemologists to distinguish between propositional justification and doxastic
justification. Imagine that I see a chair in front of me, but I fail to form a belief that a chair is present on
the basis of that evidence. Instead, I base this belief on the superstition that every time I am in this room
on a Thursday a chair will be in the room. The proposition ‘‘a chair is present’’ is justified for me in the
sense that I have ready access (the chair is in my visual field) to evidence for this belief. My belief that a
chair is present remains unjustified. It is doxastic, as opposed to propositional justification, that is the
sense of justification that is a candidate for being a necessary condition for knowledge.
123
Author's personal copy
Evidence does not equal knowledge
237
to be, ‘‘because (LD) is false but the beliefs that provide evidence for (LD) and
ultimately (O) as well are true.’’5
However, there are features of the evidential support relation and the details of the
case at hand that make it difficult to deny that (LD) is part of my evidence base for (O).
Consider the following features of the evidential support relation and the present case:
(F1) Proposition e is evidence for S’s belief that p only if that p is based on e. (see
Footnote 4)
(F2) Inferring one belief from another is a paradigmatic way of basing one belief
on another.
(F3) (O) was inferred from (LD).
(F4) (LD) is itself justified and reasonable for me to accept.
(F5) (LD) renders (O) more probable than (O) would be otherwise; this is
Williamson’s probability constraint on evidence.
When all of these features are laid out it is easy to understand the intuitive pull
behind including (LD) in my evidence base for (O). Some of these features highlight
the significance of the basing relation in regards to the evidential support relation
and the accrual of epistemic justification (F1–F3). Others make explicit the intimate
connections that hold between the family of terms justified, probable, reasonable,
and evidenced (F4–F5).
3 A possible rejoinder
What could someone that accepts (E = K) say in response to this argument by
counterexample? The (E = K) theorist can deny that (LD) is a part of my evidence
base for (O) and yet not surrender the intuition that (O) has evidence in its favor
which on Williamson’s own view is necessary for one’s having a justified belief that
(O). Perhaps my evidence for (O) is constituted by these propositions:
(1)
(2)
I appear to have locked my door.
In the past when I have appeared to have locked my door, I have actually
locked my door.6
Williamson adopts a similar strategy in regards to cases that involve perceptual
illusions:
If perceptual evidence in the case of illusions consists of true propositions,
what are they? The obvious answer is: the proposition that things appear to be
that way.7
5
I go into more detail later concerning what constitutes this indirect, or perhaps implicit, evidence.
Basically, I have in mind my grounds for affirming (LD) itself. This would be my belief that the door
appears to be locked and my belief that doors that appear to be locked are likely to be locked.
6
(2) might not be necessary. This depends on whether or not (1) justifies the conclusion that the door is
locked all by itself, without one having to make any additional justified assumptions. The ‘‘problem of
easy knowledge’’ is relevant here. See White (2006) and Cohen (2002).
7
Williamson, ibid. p. 198.
123
Author's personal copy
238
A. Rizzieri
In regards to (1) and (2), it is plausible that these two propositions are the grounds
of my false belief (LD) that I inferred (O) from.
Furthermore, if I retained (1) and (2) but eliminated (LD) from my noetic
structure, I would still be in an equally strong position to evaluate the truth of (O).
(1) and (2), unlike (LD), have the property of being known. The conjunction of (1)
and (2) also meet Williamson’s probability constraint on evidence in relation to (O).
Hence, thus far we have not unearthed anything approaching an absurdity for the
(E = K) theorist since the (E = K) theorist can still give a full defense of (O) on her
theory of evidence.
4 Cases that involve a false essential premise
Let us introduce a more sophisticated case. Consider a subject s that has a set of
beliefs that constitutes her evidence base e. Suppose that e supports a theory t1 much
better than a rival theory t2. There is a proposition, that p, that is entailed (or at least
well-supported) by t1, but not by t2. Hence, it would not be reasonable for s to
believe that p without also believing t1 and understanding that this theory supports
that p.
In such a situation t1 is an essential premise for s’s belief that p. By ‘‘essential
premise’’ I mean that it would not be reasonable for s to accept that p without also
accepting t1. This makes it especially difficult to deny that t1 is a part of s’s evidence
base even if t1 is false. Whether or not a premise is essential for a person will depend
on what other beliefs they hold and what inferences they are capable of making. For
example, s might believe a set of propositions that happen to support a further
proposition (that s also believes) and not be able to make the relevant inference. In
such a case s could not use that set of beliefs to accrue doxastic justification for her
further belief. Even if s had the cognitive skill to pull off such an inference, if s had
not in fact made the inference from the set in question to her further belief, then the
members of that set are not what is furnishing s with doxastic justification for the
latter belief.
Assuming (E = K), if t1 is known then t1 must be included in s’s evidence base
for that p. However, if t1 is not known (because t1 is false for example) then t1 is not
evidence for that p even though s must believe that t1 on the basis of her more
foundational beliefs and understand that t1 supports that p in order for those more
foundational beliefs to provide s with evidence for that p. Hence, on (E = K) it is
possible for an essential premise to fail to be a part of one’s evidence for that p. An
(E = K) theorist is forced to hold that a well-evidenced false belief can be necessary
for an agent to have a reasonable belief that p on a particular occasion even though
that false belief is not itself evidence for that p. Again, we have a result that is
counterintuitive.
Rules of inference such as modus ponens have similar properties. When we use
the modus ponens argument form we do not consider this inference pattern itself as
part of the evidence for our conclusion; yet, unless we are capable of using inference
rules such as modus ponens we will not be able to have well-evidenced inferred
beliefs. On (E = K) well-evidenced false beliefs that serve as essential premises
123
Author's personal copy
Evidence does not equal knowledge
239
would function a lot like our general inference rules in that they would serve to
transmit, but would fail to constitute, evidence for beliefs that are inferred from
them. That a specific contingent belief or theory could function in this manner is
another odd result.
5 The asymmetry argument
This brings us to my next (and related) concern that I will call ‘‘the asymmetry
argument’’. Williamson agrees that a set of known propositions can lend inductive
support to a further proposition, even if that proposition is false and therefore
unknown. Williamson is stuck with the conclusion that well-evidenced false beliefs
necessarily have a strange asymmetry in regards to their evidential warrant. They
can be well-evidenced but necessarily cannot serve as evidence for a further belief
that p.
How bad is this result? Must every belief that has evidential warrant be capable
of serving as evidence for a further belief? Here I think the answer is no. Williamson
provides an example (2000, Ch. 8). Suppose that I draw balls n (assume that n is a
relatively large number) times from a bag (with replacement) that contains a small
number of balls and all the drawn balls are red. I have a well-evidenced belief that
the next ball n ? 1 that I draw will be red also, but this well-evidenced belief can
not be used as evidence for the conclusion that ball n ? 2 will be red. Williamson’s
diagnosis is that I can not make this move because I do not know that the next ball
will be red; I merely have a justified/well-evidenced true belief that it will.
I agree that some well-evidenced but unknown beliefs can not serve as evidence
for the further beliefs to which they bear a logical/probabilistic relationship.
However, I do not think that none of them can. Contra (E = K), sometimes a known
belief can not serve as evidence for a further belief even though it renders that belief
more probable than it otherwise would be. Let us consider such a case. We can
imagine a non-skeptical context in which someone asks what my evidence is that
the sun will rise the day after tomorrow out of curiosity, and not out of a motivation
to undermine my inductive knowledge that this will happen.8 Even though I know
that the sun will rise tomorrow, if I know anything by induction, I can not use this
bit of knowledge in response to a challenge to establish that the sun will rise the day
after tomorrow.
This is because the proposition that the sun will rise tomorrow, even though
known, has an epistemic status for me that is similar enough to the status of the
belief that the sun will rise the day after tomorrow, that it would border on begging
the question to use this former belief in defense of the latter. Anyone who is curious
about my evidence that the sun will rise two days from now will also be curious
about what my evidence is that the sun will rise tomorrow. Furthermore, I have
available to me even more well-credentialed beliefs concerning the sun’s rising in
the past that support the truth of this further proposition. It may be conversationally
8
I have tried to set up the example in such a way as to avoid the dispute between contextualists and noncontextualists.
123
Author's personal copy
240
A. Rizzieri
inappropriate to refer to lower quality evidence than one can refer to. This argument
establishes that at best knowledge that p, combined with Williamson’s probability
constraint, is necessary but not sufficient for that p to be a part of one’s evidence
base for a particular further conclusion. I also want to show that meeting these two
constraints is not necessary for one belief to serve as evidence for another.
Let us compare Williamson’s ‘‘ball in urn’’ case with our original locked door
case. (LD) was so well justified for me, that if it were true it would have been
known. This is the key difference between this case and Williamson’s ball case.
Williamson’s case involves a belief that is unknown because it lacked knowledge
level evidence/justification; whereas my case involved a situation in which a belief
is unknown because it is false. Hence, we can account for Williamson’s case
without accepting his diagnosis. My view is that beliefs that are insufficiently
justified to count as known can not serve as evidence for further beliefs, but beliefs
that are sufficiently justified to count as known but are in fact false can serve as
evidence for further beliefs. This diagnosis avoids the asymmetry problem, and
accounts for both the ball in urn and locked door cases.
6 The problem of forgotten evidence
I want to look at one more issue. That issue is the problem of forgotten evidence.
The problem of forgotten evidence was originally forwarded by Alvin Goldman as
an argument in favor of reliabilism concerning justification (Goldman 1999). We
can imagine a case in which I am in my office all day and I can no longer call to
mind what my original grounds were for affirming that I locked the door. I can only
become aware of my conviction that the door is locked.
For the sake of argument let us say that my original grounds were (1) and (2)
above:
(1)
(2)
I appear to have locked my door.
In the past when I have appeared to have locked my door, I have actually
locked my door.
It is implausible that I have zero evidence for (O). This is because (O) is a
justified inferred belief. Yet, I have forgotten what my original known grounds for
(LD) were, and (LD) itself is false. Does it follow that I now have zero evidence for
(O) assuming (E = K)? One possible way around this problem is to hold that (LD)
is itself currently grounded by evidence that the agent has, but no longer has access
to, and that this evidence also serves to ground (O). The problem with this
suggestion is that it is not clear that one can have evidence that they do not have any
access to whatsoever. What exactly does it mean to have evidence that one does not
have any conscious access to?
Perhaps this means that I have a ‘‘memory trace’’ of the original experience of
attempting to lock my door that could be stimulated and made conscious under the
right conditions. I just do not happen to be in those conditions. Let us stipulate that
for whatever reason there is no memory trace of my having attempted to lock the
door that is either encoded in my brain states or is a part of my subconscious. On
123
Author's personal copy
Evidence does not equal knowledge
241
this assumption, the information that I locked my door earlier is completely lost to
me.
Under such conditions, it makes more sense to hold that (LD) initially received
its positive epistemic status by being inferred from (1) and (2) and that this positive
epistemic status is simply preserved by the subjects having a rational degree of
confidence in the proposition that matches what the evidence initially supported
even though the agent no longer has evidence for (LD). This interpretation is in line
with Goldman’s strategy of arguing that in cases of forgotten evidence the agent’s
belief is still justified because of the reliability of memory and not because the agent
can recall (and therefore ‘‘possess’’ in the epistemically relevant sense) the initial
evidence for holding her belief (Goldman 1999). I disagree with Goldman
concerning the nature of justification in that I think that the initial accrual of
epistemic justification for a belief necessarily involves an epistemically internalist
constraint on justification. However, I do think that once justification is accrued it
can be preserved by being sustained by reliable belief preserving mechanisms.
Mapping out a theory of how justification, reliability, and evidence relate to one
another is of course beyond the scope of this article. What is important for our
purposes is that one can deny (with Goldman) that being justified that p entails
currently possessing evidence in p’s favor. I would argue that this is the best
interpretation of the (LD) case. I have no evidence at present for (LD), and yet (LD)
retains the positive epistemic status that it received from (1) and (2). This leaves the
question on the table, ‘‘is my occurrent belief (O) evidenced by (LD)?’’
Williamson’s view is that justification entails having evidence. Williamson could
adopt the view that a belief can be justified if I once had evidence for it and I have
maintained a rational degree of confidence in the belief that reflected the original
evidence base. This would be a good explanation for why (LD) is justified, but I do
not think it helps us explain why (O) is justified assuming (E = K). To return to a
well-worn theme, one belief serving as an evidential ground for another is just as
much a psychological relation as it is a quasi-logical/evidential relation. Concerning
the psychological aspect of the grounding relation, our evidence is what guides the
formation of our inferred beliefs in such a manner as to confer positive epistemic
status on those beliefs.
If (1) and (2) have been truly forgotten then (1) and (2) are not at present guiding
the formation of (O); only my commitment to (LD) is. Hence, it would be very odd
indeed to insist that (1) and (2) are my evidential grounds for (O) and that (LD) is
not. I am only assuming here that if two beliefs have never been held at the same
time, then one can not be considered evidence for the other.
If it is the case that (O) must have evidence and that neither (1), (2) nor (LD) is
evidence for (O), then what evidence could the defender of (E = K) appeal to?
Perhaps my current evidence for (O) is the strong sense that I remember having had
good grounds for it and an awareness that when I have had this strong sense I have
usually been right.9 I do not think that this response solves the problem. For one
thing, this response has the problem of the unsophisticated knower. A child might
retain a confidence that the door is locked without having either a memory of
9
I thank E. J. Coffman for this suggestion.
123
Author's personal copy
242
A. Rizzieri
locking the door or a belief that her own memory is reliable. Indeed a child might
not have any beliefs about her memories at all.
7 Conclusion
I have urged several arguments against (E = K) that highlight the connections that
hold between justification, rationality, and the grounding of one’s beliefs in one’s
evidence. I have drawn special attention to the psychological aspect of the evidential
basing relation and to the awkwardness of denying that a well-evidenced belief can
serve as evidence for a further belief on a broad variety of occasions. What I have
not done is canvassed all of the possible responses to the arguments that a defender
of (E = K) could appeal to, nor have I addressed the formidable positive case for
(E = K) that Williamson provides (Williamson 2000, Ch. 10). Hence, my modest
conclusion is that (E = K) faces substantial difficulties.
References
Bonjour, L. (1980). Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–
74.
Cohen, S. (1984). Justification and truth. Philosophical Studies, 46, 279–295.
Cohen, S. (2002). Basic knowledge and the problem of easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65, 309–328.
Goldman, A. (1999). Internalism exposed. The Journal of Philosophy, 96(6), 271–293.
White, R. (2006). Problems for dogmatism. Philosophical Studies, 131, 525–557.
Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
123