Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 1
A Second Look at David Bloor’s ‘Knowledge & Social Imagery’
Peter Slezak
School of Science & Technology Studies
University of New South Wales
P.O. Box 1, Kensington, 2033
N.S.W., Australia
*Forthcoming in Philosophy of the Social Sciences
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 2
A Second Look at David Bloor’s ‘Knowledge & Social Imagery’1
Abstract
The recent republication of David Bloor’s ‘Knowledge and Social Imagery’ in a second edition
provides an occasion to reappraise this celebrated work which launched the so-called ‘Strong
Programme’ in the sociology of scientific knowledge. This work embodies the general outlook and
foundational principles in a way which is still characteristic of its descendents. Above all, the recent
re-publication of Bloor’s original book is evidence of the continuing interest and importance of the
work, but it also provides the clearest evidence of the shortcomings of the enterprise.
The arguments presented in the bulk of the book have received relatively little attention by
comparison with the principal tenets enunciated in the first few pages. Accordingly, a detailed
examination is made of these original arguments which were so influential in establishing the
sociology of scientific knowledge. A close analysis reveals their seemingly unnoticed vacuity as well
as a vast discrepancy between the radical tenets of the Strong Programme and the theses which are
actually defended in the body of Bloor’s text. In this sense, the present essay serves to complement
and reinforce Mario Bunge’s (1991, 1992) recent masterful survey of the field which he describes
as “a grotesque cartoon of scientific research”.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 3
Introduction: A Second Look
The recent republication of David Bloor’s Knowledge and Social Imagery in a second edition
provides an occasion to reappraise this celebrated work which launched the so-called Strong
Programme in the sociology of scientific knowledge. Despite the various ways in which the field has
developed, with alternative schools of thought emerging within the broader discipline, it is
appropriate to subject the original manifesto to critical scrutiny. This work embodies the general
outlook and foundational principles in a way which is still characteristic of its descendents. Above
all, the new edition is evidence of the continuing interest and importance of the work. Accordingly in
this essay I undertake a detailed examination of the original arguments in the book. This exercise is
of interest in view of the fact that the arguments presented in the body of the book have received
relatively little attention compared to the principal tenets enunciated in the first few pages. It is
instructive to look closely at the supposed force of the arguments which were so influential in
establishing the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK). I will seek to demonstrate that the vacuity
of Bloor’s case is so striking as to provide some insight into the social construction of social
constructionism - that is, the way in which the new sociology of science is perhaps the only
confirming instance of its own thesis that science is not founded on considerations of evidence, logic
or rationality.
Accordingly, the exercise of examining Bloor’s arguments one at a time may provide something like
a manual for intellectual self-defence against the undeniably seductive force of such writing. It was a
safe bet that few among Bloor’s sociologist or historian audience would have read Frege’s
Begriffsschrift or Dedekind’s Essay on the Theory of Numbers cited in his bibliography. Bloor’s
success may be connected to his undoubted ability to “extract compliance” from an audience who
could be expected to know little, and care even less, about these philosophical subtleties. This will be
the predictable pattern as Bloor touches on a range of subjects from Popper on historicism to
Cantor’s paradoxes of the transfinite numbers.
The Poverty of Historicism
The move to overcome earlier “failure of nerve” and to inquire after the sociological causes of the
contents of scientific and other beliefs leads Bloor into consideration of an argument from Popper’s
(1957) Poverty of Historicism. Though the issue has not received much attention, Bloor was right to
address this particular question as relevant to the overall conception and ambitions of his enterprise.
By the term ‘historicism’ Popper means “an approach to the social sciences which assumes that
historical prediction is their principal aim, and which assumes that this aim is attainable by
discovering the ‘rhythms’ or the ‘patterns’, the ‘laws’ or the ‘trends’ that underlie the evolution of
history” (1957, p.3). Bloor’s sociology of scientific knowledge falls clearly under Popper’s
‘historicism’ by virtue of its commitment to the historically contingent, contextual character of
knowledge and also by virtue of Bloor’s conception of his project as “The search for laws and
theories in the sociology of science” which he takes to be “identical in its procedure with that of
any other science (1976, p. 17). Although some of his more recent followers (e.g. Woolgar, 1988)
have not wished to embrace Bloor’s own commitment to pursuing science, Bloor’s virtue is that he
conceives his project as having “all the characteristics of straightforward scientific hypotheses”
(1976, p.141): “The overall strategy has been to link the social sciences as closely as possible with
the methods of other empirical sciences. In a very orthodox way I have said: only proceed as the
other sciences proceed and all will be well.” (1976, p.141). In the present case, then, this
commitment involves seeking laws which specify the contents of theories and beliefs and, in
particular, envisages the possibility of predicting them.
In Popper’s preface to The Poverty of Historicism he announces that he has found a strictly logical
refutation of historicism where his earlier arguments merely showed it to be a poor, fruitless method.
Popper’s argument leads to the conclusion that there can be no historical social science which would
correspond to, say, theoretical physics in its predictive power. The argument turns on a certain
paradox of self-knowledge: If it is assumed that the course of human history is influenced by the
content of scientific ideas, then predicting the future course of history would depend on being able
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 4
to predict the future contents of our science. For example, it would mean being able to anticipate
today what the substantive contents of, say, physics would be at some time in the future. Certainly,
the contingent, causal connection claimed to hold between science and society, content and context,
entails that we should be able to predict the substance of scientific theories given the details of the
social, cultural milieu. Recall that the much-touted case studies of the Strong Programme are taken
to have established precisely this kind of connection. However, Popper offers a formal, logical
argument to the effect that no scientific method can possibly yield its own future results, and hence
predicting the future course of human history is also impossible to the extent that this is influenced
by the contents of scientific theories.
Acknowledging this connection, Bloor notes that the relevance of Popper’s argument to the Strong
Programme derives from the fact that social determinism and historical determinism are closely
related ideas. “To believe that ideas are determined by social milieu is but one form of believing that
they are, in some sense, relative to the actor’s historical position” (1976, p.15). Bloor reads the
possible consequences of Popper’s argument for his own project as follows:
This argument appears to depend on a peculiar property of knowledge and to result in a gulf
between the natural sciences and the social sciences in as far as they dare to touch man as a
knower. It suggest that the aspirations of the strong programme with its search for causes and
laws is misguided and that something more modestly empirical is called for. Perhaps
sociology should again restrict itself to no more than a chronicle of errors or a catalogue of
external circumstances which help or hinder science. (1976, p.15)
Evidently, Popper’s arguments are a threat to the most central conceptions of Bloor’s programme
and Bloor undertakes to “refute” Popper’s criticisms.
As noted, my concern here is not directly with the implications of Popper’s argument as such, but
with the characteristic inadequacies of Bloor’s treatment. Bloor could rely on few of his readers
being familiar with Popper’s 1950 article ‘Indeterminism in Classical Physics and in Quantum
Physics’ where these arguments had been set out.2 As he explicitly points out in The Poverty of
Historicism, the force of Popper’s argument purports to be that of a formal, logical proof based on
certain problematic features of self-reference. However, Bloor construes the issue as one of ordinary
limitations on empirical knowledge arising from ignorance. Based on this egregious misreading, his
diagnosis is that Popper’s point is “correct though trite” (1976, p.15) and that it actually serves
only to make a point precisely opposite to the one Popper had thought. Where Popper had thought
his argument showed an intrinsic difference between the social and the natural sciences, Bloor
claims that the argument, in fact, “merely serves to emphasise the similarities”. Bloor “refutes”
Popper by means of an analogy which he suggests “will jerk our critical faculties into action”
(1976, p.15). Bloor’s argument uses the analogy as a reductio ad absurdum which, if correct,
would prove that the physical world is unpredictable. The unacceptability of this argument is
supposed to show the inadequacy of Popper’s analogous argument. Bloor’s argument is as follows:
It is impossible to make predictions in physics which utilise or refer to physical processes of
which we have no knowledge. But the course of the physical world will depend in part on the
operation of these unknown factors. Therefore the physical world is unpredictable. (1976,
p.15,16)
Bloor suggests that the correct conclusion to draw from this argument is that our predictions will
often be wrong due to our limited knowledge, not that nature is unpredictable. Correspondingly, the
same conclusion should be drawn from Popper’s argument concerning historical laws, - namely,
that our historical and sociological predictions will often be false simply because we inevitably be
ignorant of, and hence cannot take into account, many relevant factors in human actions. Above all,
Bloor reassures us that “There is nothing in the argument which need discourage the sociologist of
knowledge” since the problem arises merely from our inevitably “limited knowledge and the vast
scope for error” (1976, p. 16). This is certainly a banal point and does not warrant any principled
skepticism.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 5
Indeed, Bloor’s account of Popper’s argument makes it seem so entirely trivial that one might be led
to wonder why Popper should have been so impressed with this platitude. However, for any of
Bloor’s readers who might have checked for themselves, Popper’s arguments will have appeared
considerably more subtle and more significant than Bloor has conveyed. Moreover, Bloor’s
supposed parallel between the two arguments is entirely misconceived, though Bloor does not
attempt to set out the comparison explicitly. Doing so would have revealed the source of the
disanalogy. While Bloor has simply assimilated Popper’s argument from the knowledge of history
to any kind of knowledge whatever, Popper is concerned with aspects of historical knowledge which
are sui generis. Bloor gives no grounds for ignoring the special features of knowledge in this
domain on which Popper’s argument depends, and he relies on his readers’ willingness to suspend
their own critical faculties. He mis-states the import of Popper’s argument as depending on a
“peculiar property of knowledge” as such, whereas, of course, the peculiarity is to be found
specifically with our knowledge of history and, in particular, our possible knowledge of scientific
knowledge itself. This latter kind of knowledge is atypical in ways which are specifically relevant to
Popper’s argument. Although Bloor mis-states the point, the issue can be inferred from Bloor’s
own sentence in which he reports Popper’s concern with predicting future knowledge which, as
Bloor says, “would itself amount to the discovery of that knowledge” (1976, p.15). Popper’s
argument turns on a formal paradox in the conception of any predictor which might be supposed to
predict its own future results. Even without entering upon any of the subtle details of the argument,
it should be evident that the puzzle of self-knowledge arising here is quite different from the
problems of inadequate knowledge in general. The puzzles attending foreknowledge of one’s own
knowledge cannot be simply assimilated to the familiar limitations on all knowledge due to
ignorance and fallibility. Bloor’s unargued collapsing of these cases to “refute” Popper is empty
and question-begging, quite aside from its evident scholarly shortcomings. Aside from making
Popper appear to have been proclaiming mere truisms about our fallible knowledge, Bloor neglects
to explain what he himself describes as Popper’s “logical point about the nature of knowledge”.
Again Bloor clearly relies on, and encourages, a certain uncritical sloppiness in his reader, not to
mention considerable uncharitableness. Where Popper claims to have discovered a formal, strictly
logical proof, Bloor portrays him as offering, at best, a falsehood inferred from a prosaic platitude.
In fact, the “analogous” argument which Bloor presents, to the extent that it is intelligible, is itself a
non-sequitur. The premise is “It is impossible to make predictions in physics which utilise or refer
to physical processes of which we have no knowledge”. Aside from the category error in its
suggestion that a prediction might utilise a physical process, we may suppose this sentence to assert
merely that we cannot refer to things about which we are ignorant. This tautology is supposedly
parallel to Popper’s main claim that “we cannot anticipate today what we shall know only
tomorrow”. In Bloor’s parallel argument, then, the conclusion that the physical world is
unpredictable in principle clearly does not follow from our ignorance and from the fact that the
world’s behaviour depends on many unknown factors. However, Popper’s argument cannot be
charged with this same non-sequitur because the unpredictability in question (i.e. of history) does
not follow from mere ignorance but from Popper’s formal proof of his foregoing statement - the
unpredictability of our own future knowledge.
It would be tedious to attempt further elucidation of these questions, but I hope that enough has been
said to reveal Bloor’s serious misrepresentation of Popper’s argument. It is enough to note that
where Popper announces a rigorous, purely formal proof, Bloor reports “Really Popper is offering
an inductive argument based on our record of ignorance and failure” (1976, p.16; emphasis added).
It is difficult to see how Bloor could conceivably construe Popper’s argument in this way. The fact
that he should do so, and that no-one seems to have noticed, is a telling commentary on the entire
subject. Philosophically, the issue is hardly a minor one, since, on Bloor’s own account, Popper’s
argument has profound implications for the Strong Programme. Accordingly, since this argument
remains intact, Bloor’s enterprise is more seriously challenged than Bloor has acknowledged.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 6
Bloor’s Theory-Laden Perceptions.
When we turn from Bloor’s efforts at defense and critique to his positive arguments in support of
the sociological program, their most striking feature is their lameness by comparison with the
radicalism of the programmatic tenets. For example, following a rehearsal of familiar ideas
concerning the theory-ladenness of perception, Bloor simply announces: “the social component in
all this is clear and irreducible” (1976, p.28). This typically bold assertion is supposed to follow
from the arguments about theory ladenness, but, in fact, Bloor makes absolutely no connection
between these ideas at all. Bloor appears to think that the phenomenon of theory-laden perception
must ipso facto establish that the theories with which perceptions are laden must be sociological in
some way. Evidently, no argument is thought necessary and Bloor gives none. The situation here is
sufficiently peculiar to deserve emphasis: The problem with Bloor’s discussion here is not merely
that his arguments are weak or open to challenge in some way. Rather, Bloor actually gives no
argument of any kind whatsoever.
Bloor explains that processes such as education must be invoked to explain the existence of prior
beliefs or theories which will condition perceptions and concludes that this argument “entails that
no belief falls outside the sociologist’s purview. There is a social component in all knowledge”
(1976, p.28). The possibility that the relevant prior beliefs might have sources other than social ones
evidently does not occur to Bloor, and certainly he gives no consideration to such alternatives.
Bloor’s entire case here amounts to asserting that all knowledge must have a social component
simply as a consequence of the theory-ladenness of perception. This is a monumental non-sequitur.
Undoubtedly, many perceptual judgements will be influenced by socially conditioned knowledge
and belief, but this is a long way from establishing Bloor’s thesis that all knowledge must
necessarily have such social conditioning. There is nothing at all in the now-familiar point about
perception as such which warrants a claim about the social character and origins of the prior beliefs.
Obviously, this must be independently established for any particular instance of perceptual
judgement. In fact, the arguments made familiar to philosophers by Hanson (1958) have received
extensive support from psychology and physiology, and it is clear that the phenomenon of “topdown” influences on sensory processes is an essential feature of normally developed perception in
mammals generally. Crucial insight into these mechanisms was provided by the work of Hubel and
Wiesel and Held with their studies of the visual cortex of cats. Above all, the relevant “theories”
which are acquired and which come to influence judgements are derived from environmental stimuli
which are not necessarily social in any sense. This point has been re-inforced by the studies on
machine vision within artificial intelligence: it seems clear that purely “bottom-up” attempts to
interpret raw intensity information from optical inputs cannot succeed without the guidance of “topdown” knowledge of objects and other high-order conceptual information. It should be needless to
say that none of this top-down conceptual information concerning world knowledge need be social
in any sense. It is simply a matter of providing appropriate formal constraints on the otherwise
intractable problem of finding a solution to an information processing problem. The underdetermination of this problem is a familiar one and is essentially the same problem as the
underdetermination of theory by evidence in the philosophy of science. This underdetermination has
been repeatedly cited by sociologists to warrant sociological constraints, though this is entirely
gratuitous in the absence of specific argument and evidence in particular cases. The related issues of
underdetermination and theory ladenness of perception cannot be cited on their own as if sufficient
to justify invoking sociological factors. This non-sequitur has been among the foundational
principles of the sociological studies of science.
Bloor is to be applauded for wishing to incorporate the insights of psychology into his theory
(1976, p.28), but one might have wished for a more capable account, quite aside from the other
inadequacies of his arguments. It must be noted that if the bald assertion of a claim without
argument here were an isolated case, it would not merit particular attention. Though it may become
tedious to enumerate examples from Bloor’s work to justify the charge, it is instructive to see that,
far from being an exception, Bloor’s treatment here is characteristic of the book throughout.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 7
Explanatory Role of the Material World
We see the same deficiency in Bloor’s following arguments which are taken to establish the crucial
role of social factors in historical developments in science. These arguments purport to demonstrate
the dispensability of the ideas of truth and reality in favour of a conventionalist account of science.
However, we can see that what is actually being defended is nothing more than a triviality, indeed, a
tautology. The reassuring appearance of this truism serves to promote a false sense of theoretical
substance and the illusion that the Strong Programme has been further supported. As we will see
presently, there is a vast discrepancy between the radical tenets of the Strong Programme and the
theses which are actually defended in the body of Bloor’s text.
Bloor wishes to illustrate the symmetry and impartiality principles of his Programme by means of
an example from the history of chemistry. He compares the nineteenth century laboratories of
Thomson at Glasgow with that of Liebig at Giessen to show that the different fates of the two
research schools must be attributable to a variety of social factors and not “the material world”.
Notwithstanding the differences in their research results, namely Liebig’s success and Thomson’s
failure, Bloor argues that we must invoke identical kinds of explanation in both cases: “The
symmetry resides in the types of causes” (1976, p.31), meaning that the respective results in
chemistry were not enough to explain the varying outcomes in the two cases:
There is no denying that part of the reason why Liebig was a success was because the material
world responded with regularity when subject to the treatment given it in his apparatus. By
contrast if anyone behaves towards the material world in the precise way in which Thomson
did then no such regularity will appear. (1976, p.31)
In other words, paraphrasing Bloor, we may say that Liebig got results and Thomson did not.
Nevertheless, Bloor explains that notwithstanding these differences in scientific success,
The differences in laboratory findings is just part of the overall causal process which
culminated in the different fate of the two schools. It is not itself a sufficient explanation for
these facts.
In particular, Bloor wishes to deny that we can say that in some sense “the chemistry alone was the
cause of a difference” (1976, p.31). However, the elaboration of this example and the characteristic
attempt to re-describe the events simply disguises the truism being maintained. Bloor’s point
amounts to the claim that “taking into account the way that the material world behaves does not
interfere with either the symmetry or the causal character of sociological explanations” (1976, p.30,
31). For example, Bloor notes that the fates of the two schools might easily have been reversed if
various social circumstances had been otherwise even if the experimental outcomes of the two
laboratories had been exactly the same. Bloor suggests that Liebig might have been ignored just as
Gregor Mendel had been.
Bloor’s argument amounts to the truism that social factors influence social outcomes. He offers this
profundity in opposition to the idea that the “material world” or the facts of chemistry alone might
somehow be sufficient to explain these social outcomes. In this way, Bloor presents his tautologous
thesis against an imaginary opponent as if there were some significant issue at stake here. Certainly
no opponent of the Strong Programme would wish to assert the competing claim. And, equally, no
opponent would wish to deny the tautology that social factors were causally responsible for the
social outcomes. Above all, Bloor’s example cannot be construed as supporting the symmetry
principle of the Strong Programme if this is taken to assert that both true and false beliefs must
receive the same kind of sociological, causal explanation in general. This thesis goes well beyond
Bloor’s example in requiring the counterfactual situation in which the unsuccessful outcomes of
Thomson’s laboratory might have received the same reception and acclaim as those of Liebig. The
point is not whether “the chemistry alone was the cause of the difference” as Bloor suggests, but
rather that people’s beliefs are determined, inter alia, by rational considerations including the
evidence. Bloor’s mythical opponent is being saddled with a curious category mistake according to
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 8
which the facts of chemistry themselves are somehow supposed to be causally efficacious. But this
is a characteristic failure to appreciate the true nature and force of the position opposing Bloor’s
Programme. Just as no-one ever held that true or rational beliefs are entirely uncaused as Bloor had
claimed (Slezak 1991), so no-one ever held that the facts about the material world themselves
directly cause social outcomes. In sum, the Strong Programme does not merely assert the truism that
social causes may be symmetrically cited for the varying social circumstances surrounding scientific
developments. Rather, its radical thesis is that it must be sociological rather than psychological
causes which must be invoked to explain true and rational beliefs, just as in the case of false and
irrational ones. The careers of Thomson and Liebig do not establish this claim.
Correspondence and Social Convention: Prediction as Initiation Rites
It is no accident that Bloor’s ascriptions are not accompanied in the customary fashion by
references to authors who might be credited with these ideas. He sees the Strong Programme as
opposing a claim to direct access to ‘things in themselves’ or ‘ding an sich’ as underlying our
scientific theories. Again, it is unclear who is alleged to hold this view or why it must be vanquished
in order to defend the sociological programme.
Bloor provides an historical illustration by elaborating the example of Joseph Priestley’s
experiments concerning phlogiston. The pages of elaboration are quite irrelevant to the general point,
since this could have been made just as well with any example from science at all. It is not irrelevant,
however, to draw attention to this point concerning presentation, since it is part of the way in which
Bloor’s text achieves its ends: The details of the illustration are supposed to exemplify or support
the thesis in question, though they serve only to distract the reader from the essential point being
made. Specifically, the concept of truth as correspondence and the relation of theories to the world
are issues of complete generality arising for all scientific theories. Accordingly, we may ignore the
specific details of the case in question in order to focus on the central thesis supposedly drawn from
it. Bloor sees the notion of truth as misleading here, and in particular the idea of a correspondence
between theories and reality is seen to present difficulties which must be clarified. The discussion is
justified by Bloor as following upon the preceding argument:
The strong programme enjoins sociologists to disregard ... [the concept of truth] in the sense
of treating both true and false beliefs alike for the purposes of explanation. It may appear that
the discussion in the last section violated this requirement. Put bluntly, didn’t Liebig’s
laboratory flourish because it really discovered truths about the world and didn’t Thomson’s
fail because of the errors in his findings? (1976, p.32)
This rhetorical question is evidently supposed to be answered in the negative, as we have seen.
Bloor’s purpose, then, is further to support this negative view by demonstrating the irrelevance of
truth to understanding science. With the example of Priestly, Bloor wishes to show that when
expectations fail in an experiment we may wish to describe this as a “lack of correspondence”
between theory and reality. This mundane matter is taken by Bloor to raise deep metaphysical
worries about the relation of our theories to the ‘ding an sich’, since he says, “No glimpse behind
the scenes was needed to evoke this awareness of non-correspondence” (1976, p.34). Bloor is, of
course, perfectly correct here. As he rightly points out,
At no stage is this correspondence ever perceived, known or, consequently, put to any use. We
never have the independent access to reality that would be necessary if it were to be matched
up against our theories. All that we have, and all that we need, are our theories and our
experience of the world ... (1976, p.34).
Bloor explains further that “Reality had not deemed the theory false because of a lack of
correspondence with its inner workings” since neither Priestly nor we “have been permitted access
to the hidden aspects of reality” (1976, p.34). Now, there can be no doubt that the philosophical
problem of realism is a difficult one, but my point is that Bloor is simply muddled in thinking that
this metaphysical issue must be raised at all in order to understand the actual workings of science.
The ordinary manner in which experimental predictions might fail is hardly one which requires
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 9
solving, or even raising, the spectre of deep and dark Kantian metaphysics. Specifically, the question
of access to “hidden aspects of reality” is not one which any account of scientific practice needs to
answer. Above all, there is no reason why any alternative, non-sociological account of science needs
to be committed to the idea of such privileged access to “hidden aspects of reality”. Bloor is quite
correct in his insistence that “All we have, and all that we need, are our theories and our experience
of the world” (1976, p.34) but this is common ground between Bloor and his opponents. Once
again, Bloor seems to think that a sociological thesis can be automatically extracted from a
philosophical position which is, in fact, entirely neutral in this regard. As before in the case of
theory-laden perception, Bloor articulates an uncontroversial view as if it were a radical alternative to
some opposing philosophical position, whereas it is in fact a commonplace, shared on all sides and
having no special bearing on the sociological claims he wishes to advance. Granting that we have no
special access to the ‘Truth’ in the sense of ultimate realities underlying our theories, we still need to
explain how we come to prefer some theories over others given the available evidence. Above all, our
experimental procedures for testing theories need not raise such deeper question beyond the
possibility of empirical observation itself. We have already noted the manner in which the
underdetermination of theory by evidence is mistakenly construed as directly opening the way for
invoking sociological explanations. But astrological or mystical explanations are equally warranted
on these grounds. Additional arguments are needed to secure a case for the role of sociological
factors, but typically, Bloor fails to see the need for these further arguments, and we have yet
another, analogous, non-sequitur as the basis for the sociological enterprise. Bloor correctly asserts
what is, in effect, the familiar Quine-Neurath point when he says “There is no Archimedian point”
(1976, p.38) outside our theories; however, in doing so he gratuitously assimilates this with the idea
that there are no “supra-social standards” - hardly the same thing! Thus it is that Bloor manages to
conclude that “scientific theories, methods and acceptable results are social conventions” (1976,
p.37).
It is worth remarking on the manner in which the illusion of a substantial theory is maintained by
surreptitiously identifying the radical thesis with one which is rather more ordinary: Bloor explains
the sometimes severe demands made by conventions can be seen in the initiation rites of North
American Indians and equally in the demands made on scientific theories:
That theories and scientific ideas be properly adapted to the conventional requirements that are
expected of them means, among other things, that they make successful predictions. This is a
harsh discipline to impose on our mental constitution; but it is no less a convention. (1976,
p.39)
There is no doubt that science is committed to the success of predictions, but Bloor wishes to
portray this as among the “conventional requirements” of scientists just like the initiation rites of
Indian warriors. But simply calling the requirement a “conventional” one is empty without any
independent argument over and above the cited commitment itself. We see here a pretence that the
bald assertion of a claim can somehow constitute a defence of extreme views. How the
unquestionable role of prediction in science might count as a mere convention is evidently not
thought to require elucidation beyond claiming analogy with the rituals of the Indians. In this case,
without some additional explanation, Bloor’s conventionalism reduces to a mere terminological
variant of orthodox views of science: The “convention” of seeking prediction, like the
“convention” of seeking true theories and explanations is precisely what rationalist views take
science to be all about.
Bloor’s stratagem of gratuitously assimilating contrary orthodox views to his own theory recalls the
remark of Bertrand Russell’s prison officer who inquired about Russell’s religion for the purposes
of the official forms; when Russell replied “atheist”, the jailer looked puzzled and said that he
hadn’t heard of that one, but after all, he averred, “we all believe in the same god”. For Bloor, too, it
seems all theories indifferently support the sociological view of science, including those which are
diametrically opposed to it.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 10
Sources of Resistance to the Strong Programme
We had noted earlier that Bloor takes the absence of any Archimedian point outside of our theories
to be identical with the thesis that there are no “supra-social standards” by which to judge our
science. This remark is of a piece with other evidence Bloor gives of his unwillingness to allow that
there might be any other disciplines besides sociology which might have equal claims in the
explanatory enterprise. In this case, the familiar Quine-Neurath point about there being no vantage
point from outside our theories is not at all the same thing as saying that there is no vantage point
outside our social theories. The same perception is evident in Bloor’s earlier identification of the
“empirical” and the “causal” with the sociological, as if there could be no other kinds. These
independent pieces of evidence combine to reinforce the diagnosis of a kind of unilateral neglect
syndrome - characterised by the inability to notice half of the evidence immediately available to the
senses. We can see further evidence of this where Bloor turns to explain the “sources of resistance
to the strong programme”, for he thinks that the success of any objections to the sociology of
knowledge would somehow reveal a profound limitation on science itself - whereas, in fact, it reveals
only the limitations on sociology.
Bloor devotes a chapter to a kind of psychoanalysis of his opponents by speculating about the
“sources of resistance” to the Strong Programme. This is essentially in the manner that a Freudian
analysis would seek the sources of resistance to unpalatable, repressed desires. Clearly, Bloor is
unable to imagine that anyone might have rational grounds for such resistance based on
considerations of evidence and argument. Specifically, Bloor sees deep fears in those who would
resist the sociology of science and he asks: “why should the sacred character of scientific
knowledge be threatened by a sociological scrutiny?” (42). He suggests that “the aura of the sacred
prompts a superstitious desire to avoid treating knowledge naturalistically” (1976, p.73).
Bloor suggests that if any objections to his thesis had proved insurmountable, “It would have meant
that there was a most striking oddity at the very heart of our culture”. He explains:
If sociology could not be applied in a thorough-going way to scientific knowledge it would
mean that science could not scientifically know itself. ... How is it that it can feel right and
proper to make science an exception to itself when unrestricted generality would seem to be so
obviously desirable? ... The reason for resisting the scientific investigation of science can be
illuminated by appeal to the distinction between the sacred and the profane. (1976, p.40;
emphasis added)
We see here once again most clearly Bloor’s complete failure to conceive of the possibility that the
scientific investigation of science might be anything other than sociological. The failure of any
sociology of knowledge would mean, not that “science could not scientifically know itself”, but
only that science could not sociologically know itself! Science could scientifically know itself in
other ways which are equally “naturalistic”, such as through other disciplines like psychology, for
example. Thus, if studied by any other inquiry besides sociology, science is not necessarily “an
exception to itself”, as Bloor says. And what he characterises as a resistance to “the scientific
investigation of science” is only a resistance to the sociological investigation of science.
As a direct consequence of this blinkered view, we see certain delusions of grandeur in which Bloor
imagines that no-one had ever sought to examine the nature of knowledge prior to the Edinburgh
Strong Programme. He imagines that the “threatening” nature of any investigation into science
itself has been the cause of “a positive disinclination to examine the nature of knowledge in a candid
and scientific way” (1976, p.42). However, in the light of such fears of desecration and the need to
keep knowledge “mystified”, it is hard to understand how every philosopher since Plato has been
centrally concerned with the problem of knowledge and its justification.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 11
Knowledge and Social Imagery
The centrepiece of the book is a chapter which examines a question in the history and philosophy of
science - the issue between Kuhn and Popper concerning the nature of scientific progress. The
chapter is titled “A case study” and is, in fact, an application of the sociological method to the case
of the history and philosophy of science itself. This is somewhat curious and needs to be explained.
Bloor announces that he does “not attempt to contribute to the debate itself” (1976, p.48) in the
sense of engaging the specific substantive issues. Rather, he is concerned with the quasipsychoanalytic project of discerning the underlying motives, and unconscious conceptions which are
supposed to explain the theories in questions.
Somewhat like Freud’s interpretation of dreams, Bloor seeks to show how the manifest content of
theories is really a symbolically disguised representation of a latent content - “an expression of
deep ideological concerns in our culture” (1976, p.48). In other words, theories are not what they
appear to be - that is, about the literal referents of their terms and concepts, but rather these terms are
subtly encoded allusions to hidden meanings. This has become one of the standard approaches in
the sociology of science, exemplified in celebrated case studies such as that of Shapin’s in which
“expressive homologies” and other metaphorical links are found between the contents of scientific
theories and their social milieu. Thus, Bloor might have chosen any episode in the history of science
to make his point equally well, but he attempts to apply the method of sociological analysis to a
debate within the history and philosophy of science itself. He says “My purpose is to bring out the
way in which social images and metaphors govern these rival claims, determining their style, content
and relations to one another” (1976, p.48).
Like its psychoanalytic counterpart, this exercise in depth analysis of metaphors, motives and hidden
meanings is a dubious undertaking. It is notoriously unclear how the relevant connections and
constraints between manifest and latent content are to be determined. Unconcerned, and undeterred
by such problems, Bloor simply proffers his interpretation of the “tone and style” of these
philosophers’ thoughts. Bloor explains “The tone and style of Popper’s philosophy is an important
part of its overall message” (1976, p.49) and “As with Popper’s work, Kuhn’s account of science
has a definite flavour which is at least partly caused by the metaphors which the author finds it
natural to use.” (1976, p.51). In this vein, Bloor elaborates the way in which the philosophies of
Popper and Kuhn may be seen as “an almost pure case of the opposition between what may be
called the Enlightenment and Romantic ideologies” (1976, p.54). In other words, the theories of
Popper and Kuhn are to be explained, not in terms of their arguments and evidence, but as
“reflections of social ideologies” (1976, p.65). This approach has the undoubted advantage of
absolving the analyst from any obligation to take the literal contents of the theories seriously. Thus,
in Hessen’s earlier version of this approach, physicists in 1930 may have imagined that they were
describing the structure of the atom, but in fact they were describing the social structure of Weimar
Germany. By comparison with its sociological counterpart, at least Freudian dream interpretation
provides some heuristic for making the translation between manifest and latent content, though this
is notoriously open to arbitrary invention. Bloor’s sociological interpretations make no pretense of
providing any such heuristic methods for decoding the symbolic meanings of theories and, indeed,
the very notion of the literal meaning of terms or propositions is undermined. Bloor conveys no
awareness of the inherent tenuousness, to say the least, of his metaphorical homologies and
structural identities. On the contrary, he blithely declares “The social ideologies are so pervasive that
they are an obvious explanation of why our concepts have the structures that they do” (1976, p.66).
However, as Freud said, sometimes a cigar is just a cigar.
We see here the virtue in Bloor’s choice of theories in the philosophy of science rather than in some
domain of science itself. This permits ignoring the philosophical issues in favour of discerning their
ideological inspiration. Where the theories of Popper and Kuhn might be taken as directly relevant
to Bloor’s own enterprise, instead of considering their merits, we can simply divine their
motivations.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 12
The “holy of holies”
On Bloor’s analysis, the resistance to his sociology of science must be explained by a fear of
“despoiling” the sacred, and by a “superstitious” attempt preserve science from “naturalistic”
exposé. In this somewhat precious scheme, Bloor goes beyond the mere affectation of such
Durkheimian insight. In its “defence of the indefensible”, Bloor’s writing is more akin to Orwell’s
illustrations of the “debasement of language” by entirely controverting actuality. The most
astonishing illustration of this tendency is Bloor’s talk of “The mystifying resources of Kuhn’s
account” and “The Popperian style of mystification” (1976, p.67) to describe perhaps the two
most important philosophical elucidations of science in this century. There can be little doubt,
judging by its reception, that these perversions of usage by Bloor have produced exactly the
“reduced state of consciousness” and anaesthesia of the brain of which Orwell had warned (1984,
362,3). To take another example, how else can one explain Bloor’s ability to describe Gottlob
Frege’s work as “unpromising and imprecise conceptions” (1976, p.93) which have turned the
basic principles of mathematics into “mysterious” objects? In the entire history of intellectual
endeavour, it is unlikely that one could have found an example of clarification and illumination
comparable to Frege’s work! Bloor’s capacity for characterising this as “mystification” simply
defies description.
Bloor would undoubtedly see my own reactions as confirming his account. My own protests can be
seen as “steeped in the rhetoric of purity and danger, and full of the imagery of invasion,
penetration, disparagement, contempt and the threat of ruin” (1976, p.83). Indeed. This is somewhat
like the way in which the strenuous protests of the neurotic against his analyst’s diagnosis are taken
only to confirm the depth of his repressions. However, in the words of an apt joke, just because I’m
paranoid, it doesn’t mean they’re not out to get me. Just because I may be steeped in the “rhetoric
of purity” doesn’t mean that Bloor does not present a real “threat of ruin”. It is not to concede
very much to Bloor to acknowledge that he understands the reactions elicited by work such as his
own. More important is the simple fact that Frege’s position in the history of Western thought is
unrivalled and widely regarded as second only to Kant or even Plato. Clearly, it is impossible to
provide detailed justification for these judgements here, just as it is impossible to convey the case for
Darwinism in a debate with Creationists. For those who may need to be convinced I can only note
the universally acknowledged, singular importance of Frege’s ideas: these had laid the entire
foundations of modern logic which were essentially unchanged since Artistotle. Some
“Mystification”! As Jerry Fodor might have said, I should have such “unpromising and imprecise
conceptions”!
Bloor’s account of Frege in these terms is sufficiently grotesque to disqualify it entirely from
serious consideration. It is of a piece with the kind of externalism which sees the work of a Newton
or Einstein as comparable to the rat’s conditioned response to a food pellet (see Slezak 1991).
Attempting to rebut the charge that Frege’s work was some kind of mystification is impossible in
the compass of a few pages, or even a few books, for that matter. Clearly, if the game of science is
merely acquiring converts and “extracting compliance”, then Bloor’s approach wins easily - at least
among the uninformed. It is only to an audience innocent of Frege’s work and its import that Bloor
could even suggest that Frege failed to appreciate a certain point which Bloor himself declares to be
“quite clear” (1976, p.105).
In a similar vein Bloor seeks to support his sociological reductionism by showing that Frege’s
criticism of J.S. Mill is inadequate in ways which Bloor presumptuously claims to remedy. It is
instructive to see Bloor’s case here, since it reveals the consistency with which his arguments fail to
meet even minimal standards - much less reveal Frege’s failures and misapprehensions.
Bloor rehearses Frege’s critique of Mill’s empirical view of arithmetic as a highly general
description of properties of objects. None of the copious details are relevant, since Bloor attempts to
exploit only Frege’s concept of “objectivity” according to which some things may be neither
“handleable” nor “spatial” nor “actual”. Frege’s examples include the axis of the earth, the centre
of gravity of the solar system and the equator. Bloor complains that Frege’s examples leave open
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 13
the fundamental question about the nature of objectivity, that is, “an account of what objectivity
actually is” (1976, p.85). Thus, Bloor accepts Frege’s examples and wishes to give a further
explication of this notion of objectivity which appears to seek an alternative to what is mental and
what is physical. Bloor proceeds by taking Frege’s example of the equator in order to consider its
status. Frege uses this example in order to illustrate the way in which something may be objective or
real and yet not physical. But nor is the equator merely imaginary or psychological in the sense of
having no external reality. Ironically, Frege’s remarks quoted by Bloor point to the very feature of
such constructs which makes them such implausible candidates for a social constructivism. As if to
answer the Edinburgh programme, Frege says:
If to be recognised were to be created, then we should be able to say nothing positive about the
equator for any period earlier than the date of its alleged creation. (quoted by Bloor 1976, p.
85).
This is, of course, precisely the reason for the absurdity of social constructivism when taken
seriously. Frege makes this point only by way of clarification, though he would be unlikely to have
imagined that anyone might wish to assert the claim seriously. For example, Frege’s remark is the
kind of banality which one feels the need to recite when faced with the thesis of Latour and Woolgar
- namely, that material objects are fictions constructed by social negotiation and do not pre-exist in
the world. Frege’s point is best understood as emphasizing the abstract character of certain posits as
theoretical entities which are no less objective for being more indirectly connected with direct
observations. Things like the equator and the centre of mass of the solar system are properties just
like any other such as size or colour, and Frege may be taken as offering this sense in which
numbers are to be understood as independent objects of knowledge which are not merely imaginary
or subjective psychological states.
We are in a position to see how Bloor finds an opening here for insinuating his sociological
account. Taking the equator as example, Bloor asks what status it has. He answers “The equator is
rather like a territorial boundary ... It would be generally admitted that territorial boundaries have the
status of social conventions ...” (1976, p.85). Q.E.D.! This is Bloor’s argument in its entirety. Even
sympathizers of the sociological programme might concede that something more is required to
establish Bloor’s thesis. The entire detailed elaboration of Mill’s view and Frege’s response has
served only in order to make this “argument”. Having established his point in this way, Bloor
explains:
This example suggests that things which have the status of social institutions are perhaps
intimately connected with objectivity. Indeed the leap may be made to the hypothesis that
perhaps the very special, third status between the physical and the psychological belongs, and
only belongs, to what is social. (1976, p.86)
Of course, the equator is indeed like a territorial boundary in some respects, but it takes considerable
obtuseness to overlook the differences. Bloor’s “leap” here is one of the constituent non-sequiturs
of the entire sociological enterprise. It is, in fact, once again nothing more than the delusion that the
under-determination of theory by evidence requires invocation of sociological factors. The entirely
gratuitous character of this assumption has been often noted (Slezak, 1991, Laudan 1990), and little
more needs to be said here once it has been identified as the essence of Bloor’s case on Mill, Frege
and mathematics. Unlike conventional territorial boundaries, the equator and the centre of mass of
the solar system are theoretical entities and, in this respect, serving in an explanatory function in our
models of the world. Bloor acknowledges this point, but makes the utterly specious distinction
between what is theoretical and what is empirical. He asserts
... these notions have a central role to play in our conception of reality and in particular, in the
mechanical theories which hold pride of place within it. It is vital to remember, however, that
this reality is not an empirical reality but a systematic and highly elaborated world-picture.
(1976, p.86)
Bloor’s idea is that our theories are not empirical because they go beyond what is directly
observable. Furthermore, what is not empirical must be sociological. This is absurd, though it is not
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 14
merely a mistake since Bloor and other sociologists actually rely on this absurdity in order to enable
their sociological claim to acquire some leverage. The implication is that what is theoretical must be
in some way arbitrary and, therefore, open to sociological rather than rational determinants. This
argument is so transparently misguided that it requires little more than articulating it in order to
expose its flaw. As I had remarked earlier, the mere fact of under-determination does not yet, on its
own, secure any sociological thesis, since the decisive factors in theory “choice” could just as easily
be astrological or theological. Some independent grounds must be given for preferring social factors
as the ones which influence the “choice” of a theory from among those compatible with the
observational evidence. (See Laudan 1990 ).
Bloor confirms that we have correctly diagnosed the essential character of his argument where he
explicitly says in this context “... the theoretical component of knowledge is precisely the social
component” (1976, p.86) and he wishes to assert “the identification of the theoretical and the
social” (1976, p.86). A part of this misuse of the under-determination thesis is the illusion that
theory “choice” may be taken in any literal sense as a selection among alternatives and that it is
such selection which requires explanation. Thus, Bloor says that “the sociological component dealt
with the selection of the physical models and accounted for their aura of authority” (1976, p.93).
However, far from being able to make any “choice” among alternative theories, it is usually difficult
to find even a single adequate explanation. The process is better described as scientific discovery or
invention and, while not well understood, clearly does not involve any simple choice among available
alternatives - much less a choice determined by social causes.
Having distilled the entire substance of Bloor’s case down to the residuum of this familiar point, we
can see that there is nothing in the work of Frege or Mill which is at all essential or relevant to his
argument. Accordingly, we may pass on to his other efforts noting only that Bloor’s claims are
assertions without support. Thus he concludes this section of his book with the remarkable claim
that “there is thus a similarity between logical and moral authority” (1976, p.93) and that
“mathematics is about something social” (1976, p.93). This is once again the Durkheimian idea
which underlies Bloor’s entire conception of science - namely, that the very content of scientific
theories are disguised expressions of social facts. Above all, Bloor wishes to reduce the authority of
logical necessity to “social compulsion” (1976, p.117), though he evidently feels no need even to
address the prima facie implausibility of this claim. Bloor professes to see the same mutability and
malleability in our logical principles as in our ethical norms and other conventional rules of conduct.
However, if Bloor is right, on empirical grounds alone, one might have expected to find greater
cultural variability in the observance of logical principles. Equally one might have thought that
evidence for self-conscious breaches of these conventions might have been more abundant. One is
led to wonder whether Bloor has ever made any transgression of social norms and found it easier
than breaking the laws of logic.
By now the pattern should be clear and it is perhaps no longer surprising that it should be
maintained throughout the book. Thus, from the fact that the Azande appear to countenance a
contradiction in their beliefs, Bloor concludes that “there must be more than one logic: an Azande
logic and a Western logic” (1976, p.124)! This view is akin to the notorious doctrine of a “prelogical mentality” except for its pretense that there can be no way to adjudicate their relative merits.
For Bloor, it would seem that in logic, as in ethics and aesthetics, de gustibus non disputandum est.
With his hasty, unargued leap into multiple logics Bloor does not pause long enough to consider the
possibility that there might be a more banal explanation for the apparent contradictions in Azande
belief. The phenomenon is hardly unusual, and the Azande are not unique in this respect. If the mere
presence of contradictory beliefs were enough to warrant positing alternative logics, there would be a
different logic for every human being. The possibility of other, more plausible psychological
explanations for holding contradictory beliefs has not occurred to Bloor. In his blasé readiness to
abandon the idea of logical necessity, Bloor shows a remarkable lack of imagination, quite aside
from any other failings.3
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 15
Conclusion
I have given a comprehensive analysis of the principal arguments of Bloor’s book. This analysis
shows, I believe, that the celebrated Strong Programme was not merely mistaken or controversial in
an ordinary sense. Above all, it is now clear that it has been a mistake to assume that its evident
vacuity will cause it to disappear from the academic scene. On the contrary, it has great appeal and is
enjoying considerable success if judged exclusively by “external” criteria. On the sociologists’
own account, this is all that matters since there are no other criteria by which to judge any theory, but
this desperate point of view may not yet be held universally.
But for true believers in the sociological faith there has been no need of good argument or evidence,
and, indeed, the most remarkable insight to emerge from the close analysis of Bloor’s acclaimed
book is that it is entirely devoid of substance. The revolutionary tenets of the Strong Programme are
boldly declared at the outset, only to be followed by mélange of non-sequiturs and truisms
combined with attacks on mythical adversaries holding extravagant theories. It is significant that,
contrary to usual practice, the sources of these objections to the sociological programme are never
given specific citations. It is clear that the entire exercise is less concerned with serious philosophical
analysis than with rallying the troops by blowing the bugle - mostly with hot air. At best, this
strategy of invoking wildly implausible adversaries reflects a philosophical naiveté which was of no
consequence in the effort to win the hearts and minds of sociologists and historians. Perhaps in
keeping with the constructivist position, the purpose of the exercise has not been serious analysis
but propaganda and conversion. The fictional opponents serve a rhetorical rather than intellectual
purpose. This is akin to the way in which the communist hordes of the “yellow peril” had been
invoked during the cold war days in Australia during the 1950s. The objective reality of the threat is
less important than the goal of rallying one’s compatriots to the cause.
Finally, it must be noted that the new edition of Bloor’s book itself provides the most convincing
confirmation of the foregoing analyses. Bloor employs two tactics whose common purpose speaks
for itself. First, in a new Afterword Bloor displays a selective retrograde amnesia. In the face of
criticism from cognitive science (Slezak 1989) which purports to refute his central theses, Bloor
retreats to the watered-down claim merely that there are “social aspects of knowledge”. This is
undeniably compatible with cognitive science and artificial intelligence, but is a pale copy of the
original, iconoclastic thesis of social causation. It is so uncontroversial that no-one would bother
taking issue with it. Bloor has substituted an entirely innocuous claim whose very blandness testifies
to the falsification of the debate. Recall, Bloor’s Programme was founded on the assertion “There is
no doubt that if the teleological [i.e. mentalist, rationalist, psychologistic] model is true, then the
strong programme is false. The teleological and causal models, then, represent programmatic
alternatives which quite exclude one another” (1976, p. 9). In the new Afterword Bloor protests that
his position is compatible with the claims of individual psychology and cognitive science, but these
conciliatory pronouncements cannot be taken seriously. As developed in his second book (Bloor
1983), Bloor’s enterprise involves an assault on the ‘disease of psychologism’ and on the
postulation of mental states. But, of course, artificial intelligence and and cognitive science are
psychologism and mentalism par excellence. How Bloor is now able to construe his attacks on the
reality of mental states as consistent with cognitive science remains a mystery. Not least, Bloor’s
feigned rapprochement with cognitive science is also somewhat difficult to reconcile with his explicit
endorsement of Skinnerian behaviourism.
Elsewhere (Slezak 1991), I have documented Bloor’s earlier face-saving manoeuvres to avoid the
dire consequences of his commitment to a zero-sum competition between sociological and rationalist
approaches. If this case were not decisive enough on its own, I have set out in detail (Slezak 1993)
the manner in which Bloor has now made some judicious alterations to the original text of the book
whose rationale leaves little doubt about my analysis. In the crucial sections of the book dealing with
the ‘Autonomy of Knowledge’ and the problem of causation, Bloor has altered the text to remove
the attribution of acausal claims to philosophers holding the ‘teleological’, mentalist view. These
changes have the effect of attributing a much less absurd thesis to his rationalist opposition, and is
clearly the other side of the coin to diluting his own untenable sociological thesis. While it is
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 16
pleasing to see that Bloor seems to have adopted a more moderate stance on some of the most
central questions, it is regrettable that he has failed explicitly to signal these changes. Indeed, on the
contrary, Bloor’s preface asserts that “attacks by critics have not convinced me of the need to give
ground on any matter of substance” and he says “I have resisted the temptation to alter the original
presentation of the case for the sociology of knowledge, though I have taken the opportunity to
correct minor mistakes such as spelling errors. I have also made a few stylistic alterations where the
language of the book has become dated. Otherwise the first part is unchanged”. However, despite
these disavowals, I believe that the original text is altered in significant ways which cannot be
regarded as either stylistic changes or spelling corrections. Above all, the changes are systematic
attempts to eradicate or modify precisely those views which were the subject of criticism by Laudan
(1981) and my own subsequent critique of Bloor’s evasions (Slezak 1991). This would appear to be
unmistakable evidence in support of what I had termed ‘Bloor’s Bluff’.
If the case I have been making here has any force, it would seem that the sociology of science has
managed to flourish through the uncritical acceptance of pronouncements without the slightest
concern for their intrinsic plausibility or the force of supporting arguments. David Hume’s essay
On Miracles is apt here: people exercise a certain skepticism when claims are mildly surprising and
only slightly unlikely, but when the claims are truly extraordinary “the passion of surprise and
wonder” leads people to abandon such common sense in favour of complete credulity. In the
present case, the social constructivist program is not only prima facie unlikely, but its selfproclaimed extremism is accompanied by arguments which are less than compelling. In
combination, these two factors are a potent mixture, and evidently a formula for academic success.
Accordingly, I don’t suppose there is good inductive reason to believe that the present efforts at
rebuttal are likely to have much impact. After all, two hundred years later, Hume’s essay On
Miracles has not been noticeably effective in diminishing the prevalence of belief in the supernatural.
References
Bloor, D. 1976. Knowledge and Social Imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Bloor, D.1983. Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge. New York: Columbia University
Press.
Bloor, D. 1991b. Knowledge and Social Imagery. Second Edition, Chicago: Chicago University
Press.
Bunge, M. 1991. ‘A Critical Examination of the New Sociology of Science, Part I.’ Philosophy of
the Social Sciences 21, 4, 524-560.
Bunge, M. 1992. ‘A Critical Examination of the New Sociology of Science, Part 2.’. Philosophy of
the Social Sciences, 22, 1, 47-76.
Hanson, N.R. 1958. Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Laudan, L. 1981. ‘The Pseudo Science of Science.’ Philosophy of the Social Sciences 11, 173-198.
Jennings, R.C. 1989. 'Zande Logic and Western Logic', British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science, 40, 275-285.
Keita, L. 1993. 'Jennings and Zande Logic: A Note', British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,
44, 151-156.
Laudan 1990. ‘Demystifying Underdetermination’, in C. Wade Savage (ed.), Minnesota Studies in
the Philosophy of Science, XIV. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Popper, K.R. 1950. 'Indeterminism in Quantum Physics and in Classical Physics', British Journal
for the Philosophy of Science, 1, 2, 117-133 and 1, 3, 173-195.
Popper, K.R. 1957. The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Popper, K.R. 1982. The Open Universe: An Argument for Indeterminism. London: Routledge.
Slezak, P. 1989. ‘Scientific Discovery by Computer as Refutation of the Strong Programme.’
Social Studies of Science 19, 4, 563-600.
Slezak, P. 1991. ‘Bloor's Bluff: Behaviourism and the Strong Programme.’ International Studies in
the Philosophy of Science 5, 3, 241-256
Slezak, P. 1993. ‘The Social Construction of Social Constructionism’ Inquiry, forthcoming.
Triplett, T. 1988. 'Azande Logic Versus Western Logic?', British Journal for the Philosophy of
Science, 39, 361-366.
Woolgar, S. ed. 1988. Knowledge and Reflexivity. London: Sage.
Peter Slezak: A Second Look etc
version June 28 '93
page 17
Notes
1
I am indebted to Professor I.C. Jarvie for most valuable comments and criticism which have
greatly improved both the form and content of the paper. The comments of the anonymous referee
have also been helpful.
2
The arguments were also elaborated in the second volume of Postscript to the Logic of Scientific
Discovery written in the mid-fifties but not published until much later. See Popper (1982) The Open
Universe: An Argument for Indeterminism.
3
For further discussion of this issue see Triplett (1988), Jennings (1989) and Keita (1993).
View publication stats