IGI PUBLISHING
ITJ3751
International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007 2
701 E. Chocolate Avenue, Suite 200, Hershey PA 17033-1240, USA
Tel: 717/533-8845; Fax 717/533-8661; URL-http://www.igi-pub.com
This paper appears in the publication, International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, Volume 3, Issue 3
edited by Bernd Carsten Stahl © 2007, IGI Global
Giving and taking offence in a
Global context1
John Weckert, Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics,Charles Sturt
University, Australia
AbstrAct
This article examines the concept of offence, both its giving and taking, and argues that such an examination can shed some light on global ethical issues. It examines the nature of offence, what, if anything, is
wrong in giving offence, the obligations on the offended, whether or not offence is objective, and offence in
a global setting. It argues for the view that choice and context provide some way of distinguishing between
offence which is a serious moral issue and that which is not. It is morally worse to offend those who have
no choice in the area of the offence, for example race, than in areas where there is choice. Intermediate
cases such as religious belief, choice depends largely on education and exposure to alternatives. Context
is important in that offending the vulnerable is morally worse than offending those in more powerful, or
privileged groups.
Keywords:
cultural values; global ethics; internet ethics; offence; religious values
IntroductIon:
Why bothEr WIth
oFFEncE?
A study of the concept of offence can shed
some light on global ethical issues. While offence is frequently not taken very seriously,
the contention here is that it should be. A better understanding of why offence is taken and
why some instances of giving offence are
reprehensible and others are not can assist
our understanding of what is necessary in a
global ethics. The argument here focuses on
the morality of giving offence rather than on
what kinds of offence, if any, should be subject
to legal restrictions. The recent case of the
Danish cartoons illustrates the importance of
the notion of offence. Unless offence is taken
seriously, that case has no interesting moral
dimension. It is simply an instance of someone
exercising their legitimate right to freedom of
expression and others unjustifiably objecting.
The Danish publisher was right to do what he
did and the offended Muslims were wrong to
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
2 International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007
object. If, however, offence is taken seriously,
then the question of who was right and who
was wrong becomes more problematic, and
the issue can be seen as a real clash of values.
In liberal democratic states, freedom of expression is highly valued, but this is not universal.
Perhaps it should be, but when considering
ethics in a global context, we are not starting
with a clean slate. The realities of the world are
where we start. In some parts of the world the
general the notion of freedom of expression is
not even entertained. It simply is not an issue
to be taken into account. Social cohesion and
religious beliefs are all important. The society
rather than the individual comes first. Once that
is realised, the offence that was taken is more
comprehensible. From the perspective of the
offended, there is a good reason for taking offence; there has been a violation of an important
religious value for no apparent reason other than
denigration of the Muslim faith. While the situation was undoubtedly more complicated and
some took advantage of the cartoons for their
own ends, the fact is that it was relatively easy
for them to do this, partly because of a lack of
understanding of the importance of freedom of
speech in most Western countries and the feeling
that their religion was not being respected.
It is impossible to limit offence to national
or cultural borders given the current state of the
electronic media, particularly the Internet. Some
action, acceptable in one country or culture, can
be extremely offensive in another. As noted
above, cartoons have played a prominent role
in recent times in causing offence in countries
other than those in which they were published,
particularly those published in Denmark.
Those cartoons depicted the prophet Mohammad in ways that much of the Muslim world
considered blasphemous. Earlier a cartoon in
Australia depicted a scene in which certain
Israeli actions were compared with Nazi actions at Auswitch. This cartoon was severely
criticised because of its offensiveness to Jews
and was withdrawn. More recently an Indonesian newspaper published a cartoon showing
the Australian Prime Minister and Minister for
Foreign Affairs as copulating dogs. This was
in response to Australia granting temporary
visas to a group of illegal immigrants from the
Indonesian province of Papua. In retaliation, an
Australian newspaper published a cartoon of
the Indonesian President and a Papuan as dogs
copulating, with the President in the dominant
position. Each of these cartoons was condemned
in the other country as being offensive. These
cases highlight various cultural differences,
for example, different views on freedom of
speech and expression, and on blasphemy.
Where there are incompatible positions on
fundamental issues, some way must be sought
to solve or avoid conflict. In the Danish case
mentioned, the offence caused by the cartoons
led to a tragic loss of life as well as to tension
between various countries. The offensiveness
of the cartoons of the copulating dogs too led
to an increase in tensions, in this case between
Indonesia and Australia. Given the importance
of the concept of offence in the global arena, it
warrants examination in that context.
WhAt Is oFFEncE?
Offence is some sort of hurt or pain, displeasure,
disgust, mental distress or mental suffering
of some variety (see Feinberg, 1985, p. 1).
Something is offensive if some people do not
like it in a certain way; it hurts their feelings, it
disgusts them, or something of that ilk. Strictly
speaking, things do not give offence; people
do through their actions. An outcrop of rock
shaped like some part of the human anatomy is
not offensive although a sculpture of the same
shape might be. While it is common to talk of
pictures, cartoons, and language as offensive,
what is really offensive is that someone has
acted in some way, by photographing, painting, drawing, talking, writing, or some similar
activity. Giving offence involves intention. It
need not be the case that the action is intended
to offend (although it might be) but the action
must be intentional (to emphasis the point, I am
ignoring the fact that actions are often defined
as intentional). An intentional action can give
offence in a way that an unintentional one will
not. Public nudity is often considered offensive
but if on some occasion, it is a result of someone
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007 27
escaping a burning house, it is not likely to be
seen as such. Many things done intentionally
cause offence unintentionally. Often we do not
know that something that we do will be offensive
to some. Much offence too is a result of carelessness. Some people may not bother perhaps too
much about the feelings of others. It is not that
they want to cause offence, it is rather that they
do not care enough to avoid causing offence or
perhaps are just not perceptive enough.
Many things are described as offensive,
ranging from public nudity and copulating to
racist and religious actions and blasphemy, from
snubs from acquaintances to insults about one’s
appearance. These offences are what Tasioulas
(2006) calls norm-governed. In these cases
certain norms have been violated, or at least
the offended party believes so. Tasioulas
distinguishes these offences from what he
calls primitive offences. Offensive smells, for
example, dihydrogen sulfide (rotten egg gas),
are an example. Norm-governed offences are
the ones of interest here.
Discussions of giving offence are commonly conducted in the context of freedom of
speech and possible restrictions that might be
justified by offensive material, or in the context
of criminalisation of certain actions (Feinberg,
1973; Tasioulas, 2006). Much everyday offence
is of course more personal. I am offended when
I alone am not invited to the party, or when
someone implies that I am incompetent or
poorly dressed. Most of this kind of offensive
behaviour is not seen as the proper concern of
the law, except perhaps in the workplace where
it can be related to harassment or bullying. The
most important instances of offence however,
at least in the public arena, concern things like
racist language, blasphemy, and indecency (although personal offence to a prominent figure
can cause widespread public offence).
Taking offence might be said to involve
three elements: the hurt, the judgement that
the action was wrong, and some action, for
example, demanding an apology or recompense. The argument here will be that, contra
Barrow (2005), action is not properly part of
taking offence but that, contra Tasioulas, some
judgement is.
First, Barrow suggests that offence involves
a demand of an apology or compensation and on
this he builds his case for there being a duty not
to take offence, an argument to which we will
return later. The position taken here, however,
is that any demand for an apology or compensation is a consequence of taking offence but not
part of taking offence itself. If I am offended
I might or might not demand that anything be
done about it. It depends on the severity of the
offence, my timidity, and other factors.
Taking offensive, however, does involve a
judgement that the offending action is wrong,
something that should not be done. Tasioulas
(2006, p. 152-153), argues that this, while
perhaps commonly the case, is not necessary.
His counter-example is of a middle-aged man
who has overcome his strict upbringing but
still takes offence at a same-sex couple holding hands in public, even though he does not
believe it wrong. He simply cannot overcome
his feelings. It seems to me that a better way of
describing this situation is that he does not take
offence at all but merely feels uncomfortable.
Having been raised a fundamentalist Lutheran, I
feel uncomfortable, sometimes extremely, with
certain blasphemous language even though I
no longer believe it to be wrong in itself (even
though I almost expect a bolt of lightening to
strike the blasphemer), but to describe my feelings as offence would be inaccurate. I might
judge it wrong, however, in certain contexts
because it offends others.
WronGnEss And
oFFEnsIvEnEss
Taking offence is clearly associated with our
beliefs, in that taking offence at any particular
action can only occur in certain contexts where
certain beliefs are held. If I say or do something
potentially offensive but nobody takes offence, it is not at all obvious that I have given
offence. Perhaps it will be objected that what
is important is not giving offence but offence,
pure and simple. However, unless there is an
objective norm-governed offence, something
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
2 International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007
that will be contested, it is not clear that there
is anything interesting in offence apart from its
giving and taking. When offence is discussed
as a reason for criminalising or banning certain
behaviour, it is because it is offensive, that is,
it gives offence and some people take offence.
The behaviour might still be wrong in the
absence of giving or taking offence but that is
another matter that has nothing to do with offence. Feinberg divides offensive actions into
two categories, those that are offensive because
they are wrong and those that are wrong because
they are offensive. Racist language is offensive
because such language is wrong while not being invited to a party is wrong, if wrong at all,
simply because it is offensive. I prefer to say
that racist language is both wrong and offensive.
It is wrong because, at least, it is disrespectful
to a race and it is offensive when members of
that race are subjected to it and take offence.
When those racial members are subjected to
it, it is doubly wrong; wrong because of the
lack of respect and because it gives offensive.
If there is nobody around to take offence, it is
still wrong but hardly offensive.
The focus of this article is on behaviour that
is, in Feinberg’s terminology, wrong because it
is offensive, that is, offensive nuisances. This of
course includes, for the purposes here, behaviour
that is both wrong in itself and wrong because
it is offensive if offence is taken, but the focus
here is on the latter.
Is giving offence really wrong? We are
talking here, it must be emphasized, of things
that are wrong (if they are wrong as all) because
they are offensive, not things that are wrong in
themselves and are offensive on that account
alone. Nor are we talking about everything that
the offended parties judge to be wrong on the
grounds that they are offended. Essentially what
we are talking about are those cases of offence
where the offended justifiably judge that they
have been wronged. One may be inclined to say
that there are no such cases; that is, that there is
nothing really wrong with giving offence where
the only wrong is the offence itself. After all, if
people are so sensitive that they become offended
at something heard or seen, so much the worse for
them. While this contains an element of truth, it
is not the whole story. It is probably true that any
offence taken at not being invited to a dinner
might not matter much, but the mocking of a
physical disability or a tragedy, for example,
might be extremely hurtful and offensive even for
those not overly sensitive. However, most offence
discussed in the contest of freedom of expression
or criminalization is not of these kinds. Rather it
involves blasphemy, sexually explicit language,
racial vilification, ridicule of culture, public nudity,
or sexual activity, and a host of other things.
In order to understand more about what is
wrong with giving offence, if anything is, we will
consider why people take offence. Obviously,
offence is taken for different reasons by different
people and over a wide range of areas. Three areas
will be considered. The first of these concerns
things which are not necessarily directed at
any person or group, such as sexually explicit
language and public nudity. Some people are
offended by certain language and pictures. Part
of the explanation for the offence taken clearly
has to do with upbringing and socialization. This,
however, is not a complete explanation. Taking
offence is more than merely not liking. There
are many things that I do not like that do not
offend me, for example, certain types of music
and art. If I find something offensive, I take it
personally in some way. I am hurt. A reasonable
explanation of why I am hurt is that I identify
closely with beliefs that this sort of behavior or
material is wrong, and in a way I feel violated.
If you expose me to these things that you know
I do not like, then you are not showing me the
respect that I deserve as a person. Even if it was not
directed at me in particular, I may feel that people
like me, those who hold the beliefs that I hold,
are not respected enough. In both cases, that is,
where it is directed at us in particular and where it is
not, we may feel devalued as persons
The second, and related, area is the ridiculing,
mocking or even just criticizing of beliefs, commitments, and customs, particularly those based on
religion and culture. We tend to identify with a set
of beliefs or with a group in a way that makes those
beliefs or that group part of our self-image. So when
ridicule is directed at those beliefs or that group,
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007 2
we feel that we are being mocked or ridiculed,
and again can feel that we are not being respected
as persons. Those who are mocking or criticizing
portray themselves as being superior to us.
The third and final area is the offence taken at
language or conduct which is racist or sexist. What
these share is that there is no choice involved in being a member of either of these groups. There is a
real sense here in which our identity and self-image
is inextricably linked with groups of these types
of which we find ourselves members. Here there
seems to be a particularly close link between offence
and self-respect.
These three examples all show that there is
a close connection between the taking of offence
and respect, both respect for others and self-respect
or esteem. When someone makes a remark or
exhibits conduct that we find offensive, we may
feel that we are not being respected as persons in
the way that we ought to be. Our self-respect
may be lessened to some extent. Too much of this
conduct may cause us to see ourselves as people of
little worth. If something which is an integral part
of me is mocked – say, my height, race, gender, or
intelligence – this is evidence that others do not
value me as a person to the extent that they ought.
They are not showing me the respect that I deserve
as a person. If I identify very closely with a political
party or with a religion and if that party or religion
is mocked, I may feel the same (although it will be
argued later that there are relevant differences in these
cases). So perhaps we can say that what is wrong with
giving offence in general is that it is showing a lack
of respect for others and that it may cause them to
lose some of their self-respect.
It is not being argued here that showing disrespect to someone will always lead to a loss of
self-respect by that person, nor does it imply that
all that is wrong with showing a lack of respect is
this link with self-respect. However, it is claimed
that there is an important link. Not everyone has
enough self-confidence to disregard all instances
of perceived disrespect.
This account that links offence with respect
fits our intuitions in at least two ways. First, it
explains why offence connected with race, gender,
and physical disability, for example, seems to
be much more serious than offence related to
football or political allegiances, musical taste or
sensitivity to pictures of naked humans or to not
being invited to the party. If we make a commitment to something, or admit that we do not like
something, we should be prepared, to some extent
anyway, to accept the consequences of making that
commitment or admission. At any rate, there is an
important difference between areas in which we
have some choice, like football team allegiance, and
those in which we do not, for example, race.
There are, of course, some cases which are
anything but clear-cut, for example, religious
belief. We will return to that in a later section.
The second way that this account of offence
fits in with common feelings is that it also helps
to explain why it seems more objectionable
to mock or ridicule the disadvantaged than the
advantaged. If someone takes offence at some
mockery of an advantaged group, that person must
first identify him or herself with that group; that
is, they must see themselves as privileged in
some way. If they can only take offence to the
extent that they identify with some favored section
of society, their self-respect is unlikely to suffer
much. Barrow (2005, pp. 272-273) discusses this
kind of case and comes to a conclusion not so
different from that espoused here. He argues that
he, as an Englishman and clearly in a privileged
position in English society, can be offended by
certain anti-English remarks, but that he has no
grounds for taking any action; he has not been
morally wronged.
thE duty not to tAkE
oFFEncE
Barrow argues that there is a duty not to take
offence. He cannot, and does not, mean that
there is a duty not to have the hurt feeling. We
have little choice about that, at least in the short
term. We may over time no longer feel the hurt
over certain comments or actions that we once
did, but it is not something that we can just turn
on and off like a tap. His view is more plausible
if taking offence involves judging to be wrong.
We might not be able to stop the hurt but we
might have some control over whether or not we
judge something to be wrong. But again, while
over time we change our minds regarding what
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
30 International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007
we judge to be wrong in some cases, it is not
something that can be done just on cue. What
he really means is that there is an obligation
not to demand an apology or compensation or
something of that ilk when one takes offence,
and this is certainly plausible. In essence, this
is a plea for tolerance. I might be offended by
some action; that is, I feel the hurt and I judge
the action to be wrong, but it does not follow
that I have a right to demand anything in return.
This is of particular importance in the global
context created by the electronic media. Given
the variety in cultures, customs, and religions
that now come into regular contact at many
different levels of society, there is bound to
be much that is said and done that many find
offensive. If there is to be any hope of living
together more or less peacefully, not only must
there be an effort not to give offence but also,
and equally important, tolerance of the views
and actions of others even when we find them,
perhaps, extremely offensive. It has been argued
here that the actions to which Barrow objects
are not part of taking offence itself, so it is
more accurate to say that there is a duty not
to demand compensation or retribution when
offended. While there is no duty not to take
offence, there is a duty not to demand action
as a result of the offence taken.
ArE somE oFFEncEs
objEctIvE?
Tasioulas argues so (2006, pp. 157ff). We are
talking here just of norm-governed offences,
those that violate some norm. Objective offences
are, or are supposed to be, actions that are offensive in themselves regardless of whether
anyone takes offence at them. They violate some
moral norm and moral norms can be objective
and therefore so can offence. Objective offences
have properties that constitute a reason for
being offended. Tasioulas gives two examples
of such offences: racist language and public
copulation. The former has more plausibility
than the latter. Racist language reveals lack of
respect and lack of respect is always wrong.
If I am shown lack of respect, then I have a
reason for being offended. Public copulation
is more problematic. While it in fact violates
norms in, for example, Australia, it is not at all
clear that it necessarily does. A society could
presumably function perfectly well if public
copulation were the norm. In such a society
it would not be showing any lack of respect
and nobody would be harmed in anyway, and
it would be difficult to make a case that it was
objectively morally wrong. If public copulation
were the norm and was not showing any lack of
respect for those who might witness the event,
it is difficult to see how it could have properties that would constitute a reason for taking
offence. In countries where it does violate a
norm, as in Australia, it can still be considered
wrong on the grounds that it is offensive (and
not merely because it is against the law), but
that implies nothing about it being objectively
wrong in any sense.
Is racist language objectively offensive?
Suppose that in some homogenous society,
racist language is common. No one takes offence because there is nobody of the despised
race around and none of the locals care. A good
case can be made that the behaviour is wrong
regardless of whether anyone takes offence
because, if for no other reason, it reinforces
the view that one race is inferior to another.
But that seems quite different from saying
that it is offensive. Things are offensive in a
context. Jokes ridiculing particular Australian
traits are not offensive if told by an Australian
in a room full of Australians, but might be in
another context. In any case, not everything that
is wrong is offensive, except in a trivial sense
in which our moral sensibilities are offended by
all wrong actions, but then the offence taken at
those actions is not worth discussing. We can get
what we want just by considering the wrongness
of the actions. It might be argued that the fact
that it is happening at all is offensive to people
of that race simply because they know that it
is occurring even though none is exposed to it.
We will return to this issue later.
It could still be argued of course that the
mere fact that nobody is in fact offended by
racist language does not show that it is not inherently offensive. Consider offensive smells.
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007 31
Certain smells just are offensive to humans.
That is just a fact of the way that we are, and
presumably is a result of our evolution. There
was survival advantage in avoiding things with
particular smells. So in this sense some smells
are objectively offensive. Why then resist the
view that some actions are also objectively
offensive? Offensive smells, as we know, frequently become less offensive once we have
been continually exposed to them for some
time. By analogy certain actions are offensive
in themselves, and the fact that some people
do not see them as such is no argument that
they are not. Some people and some cultures
simply have become desensitised or have not
yet developed the sensitivities to recognise
them as such. It is well-known that we can
develop our sense of smell (and other senses)
by practice. We can learn to notice smells that
we had not before and learn to make distinctions that previously we had missed. The point
of this is not that offensive smells are subtle
and require learning to be noticed. Rather it is
that the fact that some smell is not noticed or
recognised does not show that it is not there in
an objective sense. Similarly, actions might be
offensive but not recognised as such simply as
a result of undeveloped sensitivities.
It is odd though to say that some smell that
we no longer find offensive is really offensive.
If the smell, in the sense of a physical event,
does not cause an offensive olfactory sensation,
then surely it is not an offensive smell, and in
the same way, if racist language does not cause
offence it is not offensive, even if wrong. Something about the smell is objective, its physical
properties, but its offensiveness is not objective.
The utterance of the racist language is objective,
but the offensiveness is not.
It might be objected that the analogy is
not a good one because the offensiveness of
smells does not rely on beliefs in the way that
norm-governed offences do. But the situation is
not so simple. The information that we receive
through our senses is mediated to some extent
by our beliefs and concepts; it is to some extent “theory-laden”, so the difference between
primitive and norm-governed offences is one
of degree rather than one of kind, at least with
respect to beliefs. What is different is that in
the second case, but not the first, we make a
judgement about the moral wrongness of an
action, but that is irrelevant here where we are
only concerned with the supposed objectivity
of some offensiveness.
oFFEncE In A GlobAl
contExt
We will now focus on offence in a global setting. The previous sections have discussed or
raised various aspects of offence that will be
used to highlight its importance in discussions
of global ethics. In particular we will consider
the subjectivity of offences, the role of choice,
that is, the difference between offences related
to what we choose and those related to what we
are, the context in which the offensive actions
were performed, and finally indirect offence,
that is, offensive actions that those offended
only hear about or otherwise know about but
do not directly experience.
subjectivity
It is plausible to argue that some things are
just wrong regardless of any cultural beliefs or
practices. For example, murder, human sacrifice,
female genital mutilation, and slavery are surely
wrong even if they are an accepted part of some
culture. Bernard Gert (1999) argues that there
are morals that all impartial, rational persons
would support and lists 10:
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
•
Do not kill
Do not cause pain
Do not disable
Do not deprive of freedom
Do not deprive of pleasure
Do not deceive
Keep your promises
Do not cheat
Obey the law
Do your duty
While these are not absolute and can be
overridden, they are objective in the sense that
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
32 International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007
they would be agreed to by impartial, rational
persons. If this is correct, then there is an
obvious starting point for a global ethics. If it
were the case that some offences were wrong
in themselves, that is, objectively, then another
rule could be added to Gert’s 10, something like
“Do not perform any actions that are objectively
offensive”. If some actions were offensive in an
objective sense, then those actions, even if only
wrong because offensive, would be wrong irrespective of culture. Suppose, for example, that
blasphemy is objectively offensive. Publishing
the Danish cartoons then was wrong regardless of the attitudes toward them in Denmark
and other Western countries. We have argued
however that offence is not objective, so if it
is to play any role in a global ethics, that role
must lie elsewhere. The offensiveness rule could
of course be modified to “Do not perform any
actions that are offensive” but this is much
too broad and could prohibit almost anything.
What is required is some way of distinguishing
between different offences that does not rely
on some being objective. It will be argued that
choice and context give some indication of how
to delineate those instances of giving offence
that are serious and those that are not.
choice
The question of choice was raised in an earlier
section where it was noted that there is, or seems
to be, a difference between mocking one for
wearing outlandish clothes and mocking one’s
race. It could be argued, as it has been by Barrow, that saying something that could be taken
as offensive, for example, ridiculing religious
beliefs, could be a sign of respect. That person is
considered an autonomous human being who is
mature enough and secure enough in his or her
beliefs not to take offence when those beliefs
are criticised or held up to ridicule. There is
something in this. Treating people as mature
adults is showing more respect than treating
them as people who must have their feelings
protected. This argument, if it holds at all, only
holds in those areas where there is genuine
choice. I have no control over my race, so ridiculing that can hardly be a sign of respecting my
maturity regarding my beliefs. Ridiculing my
outlandish clothes, at the other extreme, does
not seem so important. I choose to wear them
and could wear others, in a way that I cannot
become a member of another race. Culture and
religion, often closely interwoven, present an
intermediate and more difficult case. Religion
and culture are a bit like race in that they help
define who we are. I identify with them as I do
with my race. On the other hand, I do have some
choice in a way that I do not with my race. I
can choose to be a Christian but cannot choose
to be Caucasian. The situation clearly is not so
straightforward. While I can chose to become a
Christian or choose to leave the faith if I were
one, it is not quite like choosing a new brand
of breakfast cereal. The choice will usually be
a culmination of belief changes over time. But
choose to join or leave religions we do. There
is however a difference between those with a
moderately good education and those without.
An educated person who knows about other
religions, about scientific explanations of the
world and so on, can make an informed choice
in a way that someone lacking those advantages
cannot. They have a greater ability to weigh up
evidence and to then make their choices based
on that process. An illiterate peasant farmer has
probably never entertained the possibility that
his religious beliefs might be, or even could
be, false. Given upbringing and culture, there
is little choice but to believe.
What does this have to do with giving offence? We are talking here of actions that are
wrong because they are offensive. The suggestion is that there is a relationship between the
degree of wrongness and the amount of choice
that someone has. Mocking of race is worse than
mocking of the wearing of outlandish clothes
because (at least partly) one has no choice in
the former while one does in the latter. Mocking
the religious beliefs of an uneducated peasant,
who has no real choice, is worse than mocking
the religious beliefs of a well-educated person
who has the ability to weight up the evidence
and make a informed choice. In the latter case,
the mocking could be a sign of recognising that
person’s autonomy and affording him or her
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007 33
the opportunity to defend his or her beliefs. In
the former case, this is not so. It can only be
interpreted as showing disrespect.
This issue of choice clearly has relevance
for offence in the global arena, even apart from
offence related to race. A large proportion of
the world’s population is poor and relatively
uneducated and without easy access to sources of
information, including the Internet, that would
increase their range of options regarding lifestyle and belief. If the argument of this article
is correct, it is more important to try to avoid
actions that would be offensive to these people
than to those who are more privileged. Mocking
those without choice is not respecting them as
they deserve to be respected as persons.
context
The context in which offensive actions are
performed is important in assessing their
wrongness. What are essentially the same
actions can be very different with regard to
their offensiveness. It is instructive to consider
Barrow’s examples (2005, pp. 267, 272-273).
He suggests, though does not say explicitly,
that saying offensive things about the English,
Pakistanis, and Nazis is more-or-less the same;
one is no worse than the others. However, being
English or Pakistani is racial, in the sense that
the terms are being used here. In this sense, those
called Pakistanis, even if born in England, are
not considered English, because of their race.
On the other hand, being a Nazi is a result of
choice. On the argument of the preceding section, offending Pakistanis because that is what
they are is worse than offending Nazis. One is
born a Pakistani but one is not born a Nazi.
The main point of this section however is
highlighted by comparing offending the English
and offending the Pakistanis, in England. The
kind of offensive actions in mind are ones such
as mocking of race, culture, or religion. Is it
worse to offend Pakistanis in England than it
is to offend the English in England? Barrow,
as we saw, suggests not, but there are reasons
for thinking otherwise. Consider again the
case of the cartoons published in Denmark that
seriously offended many Muslims around the
world, sparking riots and a considerable number
of deaths. The context in which these cartoons
were published is clearly relevant to assessing
the morality of the action. Many Muslims, if
the press is to be believed, feel under threat.
The powerful Western nations are perceived as
having exploited Muslim nations for decades,
and this perception has been given impetus by
recent invasions and talk of invasions. Regardless of the rightness or wrongness of the wars
in Afghanistan and Iraq, they are clear signs of
who has the military and economy power and
who has not. In this situation, it is not surprising
that the cartoons caused offence. It could be
easily seen as just another sign of Western lack
of respect for the Muslim religion. In a different
context the action might not have been wrong.
Suppose that a Muslim newspaper published
cartoons ridiculing Christ. In countries where
Christians were dominated by Muslims, it may
well cause extreme offence if the Christians felt
under threat, but in the Christian world at large,
it probably would not, at least in the affluent
West. The difference in the situations reflects
how many Christian and Muslim groups see
themselves relative to the other in the current
world.
We will return for a moment to the copulating dogs cartoons published in both Indonesia
and Australia. If the press is to be believed,
there seems to have been more offence in
Indonesia over the Australian cartoon that in
Australia over the Indonesian one. If this is so,
context provides one reason. In recent times, the
relationship between Australia and Indonesia
has been uneasy at best, particularly from the
time that Australia took an active part in East
Timor’s fight for independence from Indonesia.
The granting of visas, albeit temporary ones,
to a group of illegal immigrants from the
Indonesian province of Papua, where there is
also an independence movement, was seen by
the Indonesians as a sign that Australia was
supporting that movement. It was also seen as
evidence that Australia believed the Papuans
claims that they were being persecuted by
the Indonesian authorities. Additionally, the
Australian government had been taking a very
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
3 International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007
hard line against illegal immigrants and the
approach to the Papuans appeared to be much
more lenient. In this context, the retaliatory
cartoon published in Australia could be seen as
just another sign of contempt and lack of respect
for the Indonesians. In Australia, while some
politicians claimed that the Indonesian cartoon
was offensive, the reaction has been more muted.
In Australia there are no independence movements and nothing that could be interpreted as
an attack on its sovereignty by Indonesia. The
context is quite different.
Indirect offence
According to Tasioulas, at least regarding
criminalization, the only offences that should
be taken into account are direct offences, that
is, those that are directly experienced. Seeing a
copulating couple in a public park is offensive in
a way that merely knowing that it is happening
is not. Feinberg’s position regarding pornography
is similar:
When printed words hide decorously behind covers
of books sitting passively on bookstore shelves, their
offensiveness is easily avoided. ... There is nothing
like the evil smell of rancid garbage oozing right out
through the covers of a book. When an “obscene”
book sits on the shelf, who is there to be offended?
Those who want to read it for the sake of erotic
stimulation presumably will not be offended (or
else they wouldn’t read it), and those who choose
not to read it will have no experience by which to be
offended. (1973, p. 45)
The example given by Feinberg makes his
argument look plausible, and it is commonly used
in relation to television programmes containing
explicit sex and violence. It you do not like it, do
not watch it. However, those who find something
offensive commonly do not need to directly experience it to be offended. That it is happening at
all is offensive. Wolgast makes this point in relation
to pornography:
The felt insult and indignity that women protest is not
like a noise or bad odor, for these are group-neutral
and may offend anyone, while pornography is felt
to single women out as objects of insulting attention. ... With pornography there is a felt hostile
discrimination. (1987, p. 112)
A similar point can be made with regard
to the Danish cartoon case. Most of those who
took offence would not have seen the cartoons,
certainly those in regions where the Internet is not
widespread. But this lack of direct experience was
largely irrelevant. The fact that they were published
was offensive.
If offence is related to respect for others and
to self-respect, as was argued earlier, the issue of
reasonable avoidability does not arise. If women or
some race or any particular group is singled out
for treatment which shows lack of respect and
which is of the type to lower self-respect, it is
not an issue whether or not someone can easily
avoid some instance of that type of offensive action. Some members of the racial group might
avoid hearing some racially offensive language,
some religious members might avoid seeing
offensive cartoons, and some woman might
avoid seeing pornography, but these individuals are still being shown less respect than they
deserve, simply because they are members of these
targeted groups.
It must be noted of course that neither Tasioulas nor Feinberg are claiming that actions
or material are only offensive when directly
experienced. Their argument is rather that in
those cases where it is not, it is not a serious
contender for criminalisation. The suggestion
here is that even in at least some of those cases,
indirect offence needs to be taken seriously.
This is particularly so in the global case. Most
of those offended by some action will be aware
that it has occurred but will not have directly
experienced it, but that is largely irrelevant.
That it occurred is what is important.
conclusIon
The purpose of the article was to examine the
concept of offence and on the basis of that
examination to show its importance in considerations of a global ethic. The argument has
been that offence, even actions that are thought
wrong merely because they are offensive but not
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
International Journal of Technology and Human Interaction, 3(3), 2-3, July-September 2007 3
wrong in themselves, should not be overlooked.
Careful thought should be given to actions that
could be deemed offensive to certain groups,
even if we think that those actions are protected
by freedom of speech or expression, or by some
other right or principle. It was argued that actions
that offend because of attributes over which
people have no choice are of more concern than
those which offend because of attributes over
which there is choice, and context is important.
Giving offence in some contexts, for example,
where the offended already feel vulnerable, is
worse than giving offence in contexts where
they do not. In murky areas such as religious
belief, the amount of choice is related to the
options available, and this in turn is related
to the level of education and the information
readily accessible. This suggests that one way of
alleviating some problems of offence is to make
a greater effort to make more information readily available to a greater number of people. On
the other hand there is a duty not to take action
against those who have offended. Tolerance of
the views of others is always important and is
especially so in a global community where there
is no common legal framework and disputes are
frequently settled by violence.
AcknoWlEdGmEnt
I would like to thank the participants of a
seminar at the Centre for Applied Philosophy
and Public Ethics (Charles Sturt University and
Australian National University) for many useful
comments on a draft of this article. I also wish
to acknowledge the informative discussions that
I have had over recent years with my colleague
Yeslam Al-Saggaf.
rEFErEncEs
Barrow, R. (2005). On the duty of not taking offence.
Journal of Moral education, 34(3), 265-275.
Feinberg, J. (1973). Social philosophy. Englewood Cliffs,
NJ: Prentice Hall.
Feinberg. J. (1985). The moral limits of the criminal law.
Vol. 2: Offense to others. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Gert, B. (1999). Common morality and computing.
Ethics and Information Technology, 1, 57-64.
Tasioulas, J. (2006). Crimes of offence. In A. Simester
& A. von Hirsh (Eds.), Incivilities: Regulating
offensive behaviour. Oxford: Hart.
Wolgast, E. H. (19 8 7). The grammar of justice. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.
EndnotE
1
Parts of this article are based on earlier work
published in Weckert, J. (2003). Giving offense
on the Internet. In S. Rogerson & T. W. Bynum (Eds.), Computer ethics and professional
responsibility (pp. 327-339). Basil Blackwell
Publishers, and in G. Collste (Ed.), Ethics and
information technology (pp. 104-118). New
Academic Publishers.
John Weckert is professorial fellow at the Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics, an Australian
Research Council funded centre based at Charles Sturt University, The Australian National University,
and the University of Melbourne. He is founding editor-in-chief of the Springer journal Nanoethics: Ethics
for Technologies that Converge at the Nanoscale. He has published widely on the ethics of information
technology and more recently in the new area of the ethics of nanotechnology.
Copyright © 2007, IGI Global. Copying or distributing in print or electronic forms without written permission of IGI Global is
prohibited.
Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without permission.