FEDERALISM: TRAGIC COMPROMISE
AND CONFLICTS*
Federalismo: compromiso trágico y conflictos
Giacomo Delledonne
Postdoctoral researcher in Comparative Public Law
Institute for Law, Politics and Development (Dirpolis)
Scuola Superiore Sant’Anna, Pisa
giacomo.delledonne@santannapisa.it
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95
Recibido: 11.05.2019
Aceptado: 21.06.2019
Abstract
The internal balance of power of federal orders is a major theme in Kelsen’s constitutional thought. His theory of federal conflicts is indebted both to the achievements
of his inquiries into legal theory and to his direct involvement in constitutional policy
debates in the 1920s and 1930s. In so doing, he took a strong stance at the time of the
Prussian coup, a major constitutional crisis in whose handling Carl Schmitt also
played a significant role. In my essay I will build on Paolo Carrozza’s analysis of
Kelsen’s contribution to the constitutional theory of federations. My goal is to make
some points on its relevance for a proper understanding of the most recent developments in federal systems, including the aftermath of secession crises in Europe.
Keywords
Federalism; Constitutional Law; Kelsen; secession.
*
Cómo citar / Citation ‘Chicago-Deusto’ (Autor-fecha / Author-date / Lista de referencias / Reference list entries): Delledonne, Giacomo. 2019. “Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts”. Estudios de Deusto 67, n.º 1: 83-95. http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/
ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95.
Estudios de Deusto
1
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
83
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
Resumen
El equilibrio interno de poder de las órdenes federales es un tema importante en
el pensamiento constitucional de Kelsen. Su teoría de los conflictos federales está en
deuda tanto con los logros de sus investigaciones sobre la teoría del derecho como
con su participación directa en los debates de política constitucional en los años
veinte y treinta. Al hacerlo, adoptó una postura firme en el momento del golpe prusiano, una importante crisis constitucional en cuya gestión Carl Schmitt también
desempeñó un papel importante. En mi ensayo, me basaré en el análisis de Paolo
Carrozza sobre la contribución de Kelsen a la teoría constitucional de las federaciones. Se trata de resaltar su relevancia para una comprensión adecuada de los desarrollos más recientes en los sistemas federales, incluidas las consecuencias de las crisis
secesionistas en Europa.
Palabras clave
Federalismo; Derecho constitucional; Kelsen; secesión.
Estudios de Deusto
84
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
2
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
Sumario: I. IntroductIon. II. FederalIsm and tragIc compromIse.
III. HomogeneIty clauses and constItutIonal HomogeneIty In
Federal orders. IV. exIstentIal conFlIcts In Federal orders.
V. concludIng remarks.
I. INTRODUCTION
In assessing the significance of Hans Kelsen’s contribution to constitutional law scholarship, Paolo Carrozza repeatedly mentions federalism1.
Carrozza hints at three aspects of Kelsen’s thought that are of interest in
this respect: they have to do both with Kelsen’s work as an academic and
with his participation in the drafting of the Austrian Federal Constitutional
Law (Bundes-Verfassungsgesetz) of 1920. First, the emphasis put by
Kelsen on a value-free notion of constitution is probably indebted to the
peculiar conditions which followed the collapse of the Austro-Hungarian
dual monarchy and led to the establishment of an Austrian Republic as a
result of compromise between the Socialist and Catholic parties (not to
mention the freiheitlich, All-German camp). The federal structure of the
Austrian Republic was part of this compromise. Second, the very origin of
judicial review of legislation and the establishment of one of the first constitutional courts in Continental Europe did not stem from the conception
of the Constitution as higher law but, rather, from the federal structure of
the Austrian Republic: these innovations were seen as instrumental in providing a “solution of federal litigation”, with the Court acting “as an arbiter
of federal litigation in order to neutralize political conflicts” 2. Carrozza
builds on Alessandro Pizzorusso’s comparative analyses3 and highlights
the persistent influence of the tradition of Staatsgerichtsbarkeit in Central
Europe by the time the Austrian Federal Constitutional Law was being
drafted. Finally, Carrozza looks into the relevance of Kelsen’s thought,
most notably of the Stufenbau theory, for a proper understanding of the
multilevel hypothesis. On a different note, Carrozza’s works on federalism
pay great attention to the formal and informal links between the institutional layers of federal and regional orders, the coexistence of legal and
Paolo Carrozza, «Kelsen and Contemporary Constitutionalism: The Continued
Presence of Kelsenian Themes», in this issue.
2
See also Beniamino Caravita, Corte “giudice a quo” e introduzione del giudizio
sulle leggi, I, La Corte costituzionale austriaca, (Padova: Cedam, 1985), 39.
3
See Alessandro Pizzorusso, «Giustizia costituzionale (dir. comp.)», in Enciclopedia
del diritto, Annali I (Milano: Giuffrè, 2007), 678-679.
1
Estudios de Deusto
3
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
85
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
political safeguards of federalism, and the difficulty of elaborating reliable
classifications of composite constitutional orders4.
This paper focuses on the nature of the constitutional compromise underlying federalism and the possible conceptual framework for existential conflicts within federal jurisdictions.
II. FEDERALISM AND TRAGIC COMPROMISE
Some of the most important analyses of federalism are marked by a distinctively optimistic tone. As improper generalisation is not desirable, Elazar’s interpretation of federalism can be cited as a paradigmatic example:
federalism moves from a realistic view of the human nature but is also
marked by a genuine confidence in the possibility of its capacity to reconcile
quite diverging elements and to foster further advances:
«Federalism tries to take people as they are “warts and all”, in Abraham Lincoln’s felicitous phrase assuming humanity to have the capacity
for self-government but the weaknesses that make all human exercise of
power potentially dangerous. So the first task of federalism is to harmonize
human capacity with human weakness, to create institutions and processes
that enable people to exercise their capacity for self-government to the
maximum and even grow in that capacity. At the same time federalism
attempts to prevent the abuse of power derived from inherent deficiencies
in human nature and, wherever possible, direct the results of those deficiencies to useful ends»5.
Similarly, an optimistic tone can be detected in Elazar’s adaptation of
covenant to federalism6.
However, very different views of the significance of federalism can also be
found: they argue that more often than not the decision to adopt a federal system of government is the hardly desirable product of irreconcilable divergence:
«consociation, decentralization, and democracy can all be plausibly
viewed as part of the effort to achieve political optimality under particular
sets of circumstances. Their creation and elaboration serve as positive
4
See Paolo Carrozza, «Principio di collaborazione e sistema delle garanzie procedurali (la via italiana al regionalismo cooperativo)», le Regioni 17, n° 2 (1989): 473-509; id.,
«I rapporti centro-periferia: federalismi, regionalismi e autonomie», in Paolo Carrozza,
Alfonso Di Giovine and Giuseppe Franco Ferrari (eds), Diritto costituzionale comparato
(Roma-Bari: Laterza, 2009), 761-818.
5
Daniel J. Elazar, Exploring Federalism (Tuscaloosa, AL: University of Alabama
Press, 1987), 86.
6
See Michael Burgess, In Search of the Federal Spirit: New Theoretical and Empirical
Perspectives in Comparative Federalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 203.
Estudios de Deusto
86
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
4
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
steps towards the achievement of this much-desired goal. Federalism, in
contrast, belongs to a world where there are no optimal solutions, where
conflicts are irreconcilable, where political conditions are more likely to
get worse than better. It is a grim expedient that is adopted in grim circumstances, an acknowledgment that choices must be made among undesirable alternatives. The instinct to conflate it with other features of government is understandable, for these optimistic strategies obscure the tragic
character of federal solutions and provide them with a patina of optimality
and optimism»7.
Under this perspective, the notion of tragedy should be understood in its
classic meaning, pointing at contradictions for which there are no viable
solutions. Federalising processes both in the 19th and the 20th centuries can be
interpreted in light of a tragic conceptual framework. A prime example is the
establishment of Canada as a reluctant federation under the British North
America Act in 1867. Also because of the events and disputes that had led to
the American Civil War, the Canadian Fathers of Confederation did not hold
in high regard the federal model of their southern neighbour. Moreover, their
main goal was to create a system of government «similar in Principle to that
of the United Kingdom», as the Preamble to the BNA reads. In this line, the
adoption of federalism was the result of the need to accommodate the claims
of the French-speaking community in what is today the Province of Quebec.
In its landmark Reference re Secession of Quebec, the Canadian Supreme
Court explicitly addressed this distinctive character of the constitutional settlement of 18678. At the same time, the Court highlighted that federalism
«enable[es] citizens to participate concurrently in differently collectivities
and [to pursue] goals at both levels of government»9.
Similarly, the fact that five out of the twenty Italian regions are granted
special status (Regioni a statuto speciale) should be explained having in
mind the legal and political scenario in the founding years of the Italian
Republic, amid military defeat, secession attempts and pressure from the
neighbouring countries10. In theoretical terms, the peculiar circumstances
7
Malcolm M. Feeley and Edward Rubin, Federalism: Political Identity and Tragic
Compromise (Ann Arbor, MI: The University of Michigan Press, 2008), 39.
8
Supreme Court of Canada, Reference re Secession of Quebec [1998] 2 S.C.R.
217, 244.
9
Jean Leclair, «Legality, Legitimacy, Decisionism and Federalism: An Analysis of
the Supreme Court of Canada’s Reasoning in Reference re Secession of Quebec, 1998»,
in Alberto López-Basaguren and Leire Escajedo San-Epifanio (eds.), Claims for Secession and Federalism: A Comparative Study with a Special Focus on Spain (Cham:
Springer, 2019), 71.
10
See Giacomo Delledonne and Matteo Monti, «Secessionist Impulses and the Italian
Legal System: The (Non) Influence of the Secession Reference», in Giacomo Delledonne
Estudios de Deusto
5
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
87
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
underlying the recognition of a special status for Sicily, Sardinia and the
three border regions also explain why it is still recommendable to make a distinction between special regions and the possible development of the regimes
of some of the ordinary regions along asymmetric lines11.
Finally, of course, the federal structure of the newly established Austrian
Republic in 1920 was the result of perplexed compromise between the
Catholic and Socialist parties. The long-lasting implications of the frail constitutional consensus underlying Austrian federalism are somehow mirrored
by the very different interpretations of the rationale of the Austrian federalising process among local constitutional law scholars12.
These examples show that multiple understandings of federalism are possible. Federal arrangements are often a grim expedient, as Feeley and Rubin
defined them, and the implications of the grim circumstances of the founding
moment are often recognisable in the long run. Still, the joint operation of
constitutional practice and the interpretation of constitutional provisions
sometimes scales down some of the existential challenges inherent in the federal compromise.
III. HOMOGENEITY CLAUSES AND CONSTITUTIONAL
HOMOGENEITY IN FEDERAL ORDERS
Homogeneity clauses are among the most typical constitutional tools for
addressing existential challenges that threaten the stability or the very existence of federal orders. By homogeneity clauses are meant constitutional provisions that lay down some basic principles of the overarching constitutional
order that also apply to the constitutional orders of the constituent units of the
federal polity. Among the most important examples, the Guarantee Clause of
the United States Constitution (Article IV, Section 4) and the Homogenitätsgebote in the successive constitutions of the Paulskirche in Frankfurt (Article
186), the Weimar Republic (Article 17) and the Federal Republic of
and Giuseppe Martinico (eds.), The Canadian Contribution to a Comparative Law of Secession: Legacies of the Quebec Secession Reference (London: Palgrave 2019), 185-207.
11
See Giancarlo Rolla, «Alcune considerazioni in merito al fondamento costituzionale del regionalismo speciale. L’apporto del diritto comparato», le Regioni 43, n° 2
(2015). 333-356.
12
See e.g. Peter Pernthaler, Die Staatsgründungsakte der österreichischen Bundesländer. Eine staatsrechtliche Untersuchung über die Entstehung des Bundesstaates
(Wien: Wilhelm Braumüller, 1979); Karl Weber, Kriterien des Bundesstaates. Eine systematische, historische und rechtsvergleichende Untersuchung der Bundesstaatlichkeit
der Schweiz, der Bundesrepublik Deutschland und Österreichs (Wien: Wilhelm
Braumüller, 1980); Rudolf Thienel, «Der Bundesstaatsbegriff der Reinen Rechtslehre», in
Robert Walter (ed.), Schwerpunkte der Reinen Rechtslehre (Wien: Manz, 1992), 123-136.
Estudios de Deusto
88
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
6
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
Germany (Article 28(1)) can be mentioned. Since the 18th century, the purpose of homogeneity clauses can be described as connecting federalism and
constitutionalism and allowing the normative claims of constitutionalism to
permeate federal orders13. This is particularly true of Germany both in the
19th century and after 1949, with the fight for constitutionalisation and later
democratisation inevitably questioning the basic structures of the constitutional orders in the Länder. However, the history of homogeneity clauses
seems to show that they can only be interpreted as constitutional provisions
for the «bad weather»14: they express a minimalistic constitutional consensus
and may offer a last resort for existential crises. In line with Carl Schmitt’s
thought, homogeneity clauses might be interpreted as a sort of secularised
katechon. The history of the American Guarantee Clause as an apparently
dormant constitutional provision seems to vindicate this claim. On the whole,
homogeneity clauses might be described as a permanent sign of the hardfought compromise underlying federal constitutions. In this respect, existential conflicts lend themselves to be described as a later re-emergence of an
utterly unresolvable contradiction.
In my view, this is only one part of the story. Constitutional homogeneity
cannot be reduced to its best-known manifestation, namely homogeneity
clauses. Rather, constitutional homogeneity in a federal system should be
seen as an «ordinating principle»15, characterising and shaping the constitutional life of the system from its establishment. According to Martinico, federal constitutional homogeneity can be defined as a «stream function»16 that
makes internal diversity sustainable over time: its ultimate goal is «to ensure
a virtuous connection between diversity and unity with a series of mechanisms aimed at preserving loyalty and adhesion to the fundamental values of
the national system»17. This has at least two implications: first, the contents
of constitutional homogeneity are inherently dynamic, as the oscillating
interpretation of the Guarantee Clause over the last two centuries show18.
13
See Giacomo Delledonne, L’omogeneità costituzionale negli ordinamenti composti (Napoli: Editoriale Scientifica, 2017).
14
As defined by Francesco Palermo, La forma di Stato dell’Unione europea. Per una
teoria costituzionale dell’integrazione sovranazionale (Padova: Cedam, 2005), 144.
15
Frank Schorkopf, Homogenität in der Europäischen Union – Ausgestaltung und
Gewährleistung durch Art. 6 Abs. 1 und Art. 7 EUV (Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 2000),
34; Roberto Miccù, «Proteggere la democrazia, rinnovare il “contratto sociale” europeo»,
federalismi.it, n° 3 (2014), 11.
16
Giuseppe Martinico, «Le costituzioni come strumento di gestione del rischio. Il
caso della secessione», Governare la paura (2017), 31.
17
Giuseppe Martinico, «”A Message of Hope”: A Legal Perspective on the Reference», in Delledonne and Martinico (eds.), The Canadian Contribution…, 252.
18
See Delledonne, L’omogeneità costituzionale…, 106-112 and 134-143.
Estudios de Deusto
7
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
89
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
Second, homogeneity clauses are the most visible and important manifestation of the ordinating principle of constitutional homogeneity in the legal
order: however, they are far from being the only ones to perform this function. The issue of constitutional homogeneity does not only affect the relationship between the constitutions of the two institutional layers, i.e. between
the federal layer and the constituent units. Rather, it also applies to those
states or territories that wish to join the federation. In Minor v Happersett, the
Supreme Court held that «All the states had governments when the Constitution was adopted. … These governments the Constitution did not change.
They were accepted precisely as they were, and it is therefore to be presumed
that they were such as it was the duty of the states to provide»19. But things
went differently when territories applied for being admitted to the Union or
when the Southern states were readmitted to it after the end of the American
Civil War, with Congress being granted the exclusive power to «determine
whether it is republican or not»20.
Among the comparable cases that deserve mention, the debate about the
imminent admission of the five Eastern Länder in the run-up to the reunification of Germany: should have they adapted to the core principles of the
(West) German Basic Law before joining the Federal Republic?21 Similarly,
attention should be paid to the role of the successive enlargement waves and
the conditionality mechanisms in leading the European Communities and
then the Union to enucleate its own founding principles (later labelled as values). However, this point should be assessed having in mind the peculiar features of the European federalising process22.
These cases show that constitutional homogeneity requirements do not only
apply to the constituent units that are part of one federal order but also to those
polities that apply for membership. In this respect, constitutional homogeneity
may be invoked not only when existential crises surface: rather, it should provide guidance at all stages in the evolution of a constitutional order.
Over the last few decades, a further element has acquired greater prominence: it has to do with the attempts to address secessionist claims by
19
U.S. Supreme Court, Minor v. Happersett (1874) 88 U.S. 162, 175-176.
U.S. Supreme Court, Luther v. Borden (1849) 48 U.S. 1, 42. See also Matteo Nicolini, «Regional Demarcation, Territorial Alteration, and Accommodation of Divided Societies», Revista de Derecho Político, n° 94 (2015), 69-70; Andrea Buratti, La frontiera
americana. Una interpretazione costituzionale (Verona: Ombre Corte, 2016), 88.
21
See Josef Isensee, «Staatseinheit und Verfassungskontinuität», in Veröffentlichungen
der Vereinigung der deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer, vol. 49, Deutschlands aktuelle Verfassung
(Berlin: de Gruyter, 1990), 59; Thomas Giegerich, Europäische Verfassung und deutsche
Verfassung im transnationalen Konstitutionalisierungsprozeß: Wechselseitige Rezeption,
konstitutionelle Evolution und föderale Verflechtung (Berlin: Springer, 2003), 427.
22
See Delledonne, L’omogeneità costituzionale…, 223-234.
20
Estudios de Deusto
90
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
8
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
resorting to constitutional law, in the wake of the abovementioned Quebec
Secession Reference. According to the Canadian Supreme Court, the conduct
of the affected parties during the negotiations that may lead to secession and
the establishment of a new state «would be governed by the same constitutional principles which give rise to the duty to negotiate: federalism, democracy, constitutionalism and the rule of law, and the protection of minorities»23.
Although the recognition of a right to secession is very rare in the comparative scenario, the attempts to regulate these processes
«can be read as forms of “exit related conditionality”, by ensuring an axiological continuity between the new order and the old one. This might
appear paradoxical, but it is actually a process in which the old system
accepts the detachment of the seceding entity by making it conditional
upon the adhesion to its fundamental values. According to this scheme, the
constituent phase of the seceding legal system is partly guided and influenced by the values of the old constitution. This way the revolutionary
character of secession is partly “exorcised”»24.
IV. EXISTENTIAL CONFLICTS IN FEDERAL ORDERS
The preceding paragraphs have looked into views of federalism that are
quite foreign to the Kelsenian framework. Quite to the contrary, the notion of
constitutional homogeneity, which had been deeply rooted in the political
thought since the 18th century, was popularised in the first half of 20th century
by public law scholars of the likes of Carl Schmitt25. This paragraph gets
closer to Kelsen’s thought and his contribution to a theory of conflicts within
federal orders. Again, his writings can both be traced back to his theory of the
constitution and to his reaction towards constitutional crises in Central
Europe in the late 1920s and early 1930s.
According to comparative scholarship in Continental Europe, homogeneity clauses are not alone in «corroborating» federal sovereignty26: rather, they
go hand in hand with other tools, including the power of the federal
23
Supreme Court of Canada, Reference re Secession of Quebec [1998] 2 S.C.R. 217,
266.
24
Martinico, «”A Message of Hope”…», 253; see also Delledonne, L’omogeneità
costituzionale…, 209-214.
25
However, German liberal scholars like Hugo Preuss also played a meaningful role
in elaborating constitutional homogeneity as a constitutional law concept (see Dian Schefold, «L’omogeneità nei sistemi multilevel. Cenni sull’attualità di Hugo Preuss tra sviluppo storico, vecchie analisi e nuova terminologia», Giornale di storia costituzionale, n° 19
(2010): 141-157).
26
Giuseppe de Vergottini, Diritto costituzionale comparato (6th edition, Padova: Cedam, 2004), 306.
Estudios de Deusto
9
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
91
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
government to take action in order to ensure the respect of obligations stemming from the federal constitution. These instruments, e.g. federal execution
(Bundesexekution) in Germany and state coercion (coacción estatal) in
Spain, aim to ensure the cohesion of the legal system by enabling the federal
government to resort to extraordinary powers. When the federal government
decides to trigger the federal execution procedure, conflicts are not potential
but actual.
Kelsen was personally involved in the controversy regarding the resort to
extraordinary presidential powers under Article 48 of the Weimar Constitution27. This provision, which was used four times in order to face political
unrest in specific German Länder, played a crucial role in the gradual transition towards authoritarian presidential governance.
In Kelsen’s view, federal execution under the Weimar constitution was
marked by a tight connection of theoretical and practical issues: this clause
showed that legal theory heavily depended on political assumptions28. In line
with Kelsen’s interpretation of federalism, federal execution is triggered by a
violation of the Gesamtverfassung of the federal order. Therefore, it is
unconceivable that the power to resort to extraordinary powers lies with the
federal government: the «objectivity of the organ called to make a decision
on the facts that may trigger federal execution is the only safeguard of this
principle, stemming from the very idea of the federal state»29. Because of its
objectivity, a constitutional court, like the one regulated by the Federal Constitutional Law of Austria, was better placed to do this job: in Austria, «the
«1. If a Land does not fulfil the obligations laid upon it by the Reich Constitution
or the Reich laws, the President of the Reich may use armed force to compel it to do so.
2. In case public safety is seriously threatened or disturbed, the President of the Reich
may take the measures necessary to re-establish law and order, intervening if need be with
the assistance of the armed forces. In the pursuit of this aim he may suspend the civil
rights described in articles 114, 115, 117, 118, 123, 124 and 153 partially or entirely.
3. The President of the Reich has to inform the Reichstag immediately about all
measures undertaken that are based on paragraphs 1 and 2 of this article. The measures
have to be suspended immediately if the Reichstag so demands.
4. If danger is imminent, the Land government may, for their specific territory, implement steps as described in paragraph 2. These steps have to be suspended on the demand
of the President of the Reich or the Reichstag.
5. Further details are provided by Reich law».
28
See Hans Kelsen, «L’esecuzione federale. Contributo alla teoria e alla prassi dello
Stato federale, con particolare riguardo alla costituzione del Reich tedesco e alla costituzione federale austriaca», in La giustizia costituzionale. Translated by Carmelo Geraci
(Milano: Giuffrè, 1981), 75. See also Lars Vinx, The Guardian of the Constitution: Hans
Kelsen and Carl Schmitt on the Limits of Constitutional Law (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2015).
29
Kelsen, «L’esecuzione federale…», 118.
27
Estudios de Deusto
92
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
10
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
primitive legal technique of federal execution has been completely overcome»30. The Constitution of the 2nd Spanish Republic also trusted the Tribunal de Garantías Constitucionales to act as an arbiter between the state
government and regional governments.
Subsequent developments can be described as a mixed picture. Tools of
the likes of the Reich execution regulated by the Weimar Constitution are
still a typical component of federal constitutions. Their rationale points at the
emergence of crises for which courts would not be able to provide viable
solutions: therefore, it is for the federal executive to take action in order to
face them. However, procedural safeguards usually ensure that actors other
than the federal executive be also involved in the decision-making process.
In substantive terms, the active protection of the core of the federal constitution should not lead to the demise of the constitution itself.
In the light of this, a procedure like federal coercion (Bundeszwang)
under Article 37 of the Basic Law of the Federal Republic of Germany31 cannot simply be described as the heir to the Reich execution; rather, its regulation tries to “tame” some of the most problematic aspects of the corresponding
provision of the Weimar Constitution. Approval by a majority of the members of the Bundesrat is explicitly mentioned in Article 37, while scholars
have come to the conclusion that respect of the principle of proportionality
and a preliminary judgment of the Bundesverfassungsgericht should be recommended32. Furthermore, the dissolution of the Landtag and the removal of
the executive in the concerned Land are not part of the admissible measures.
In this respect, the current constitutional framework tries to address the complicated legacy of the Weimar Constitution: the events that led to the
so-called Prussian coup (Preußen-Schlag) in 1932 were seen as playing a
crucial role in the terminal crisis of the Republic.
The regulation of coacción estatal in Article 155 of the Spanish Constitution of 197833 is clearly indebted to the German Basic Law. Still, there are
Kelsen, «L’esecuzione federale…», 141.
«1. If a Land fails to comply with its obligations under this Basic Law or other
federal laws, the Federal Government, with the consent of the Bundesrat, may take the
necessary steps to compel the Land to comply with its duties.
2. For the purpose of implementing such coercive measures, the Federal Government
or its representative shall have the right to issue instruction to all Länder and their authorities».
32
See Wilfried Erbguth, «Artikel 37», in Michael Sachs (ed.), Grundgesetz. Kommentar (5th edition, München: C.H. Beck, 2009), 1172-1173.
33
«1. If an Autonomous Community does not fulfil the obligations imposed upon it
by the Constitution or other laws, or acts in a way seriously prejudicing the general interests of Spain, the Government, after lodging a complaint with the President of the Autonomous Community and failing to receive satisfaction therefore, may, following approval
30
31
Estudios de Deusto
11
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
93
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
some differences between them, showing that the Spanish autonomic state
has some distinctive feature if compared with German federalism. These differences were made particularly evident by the need to react towards the initiatives of the Catalan Generalitat in September and October 2017, which
can aptly be described as a secessionist coup. The moves of the Generalitat
had been preceded by a number of unfruitful injunctions from the Spanish
Constitutional Court and the wait-and-see attitude of Mariano Rajoy’s government.
After the Spanish Government lodged a complaint with Carles
Puigdemont, President of the Generalitat and leader of the self-styled Catalan Republic, the Senate of Spain had to move to the forefront of this institutional crisis in the framework of the Article 155 procedure. The Spanish
Senate is routinely described as a very weak second chamber both in structural and functional terms34. As López-Basaguren put it,
«Firstly, the composition of the Senate is decisive in this incapacity to
play an active role in the channelling of interests related with territorial
autonomy. … neither parties nor [Autonomous Communities have] ever
felt the need to channel their territorial interests via the upper House. It is
in the lower House that the interests of the ACs are channelled»35.
In the light of Article 155, the Senate had to decide alone on the measures
envisaged by the Spanish Government, including the removal of the Catalan
executive (Generalitat), the dissolution of the autonomous legislature (Parlament) and the calling of a snap regional election36. This was, however, to
have important consequences. In comparison with the Congress of Deputies,
the partisan composition of the Senate at that time overrepresented the rightof-centre Partido Popular (PP), which held a majority of seats; even more
importantly, none of the 21 senators elected in the four Catalan provinces or
granted by an absolute majority of the Senate, take the measures necessary in order to
compel the latter forcibly to meet said obligations, or in order to protect the above-mentioned general interests.
2. With a view to implementing the measures provided in the foregoing clause, the
Government may issue instructions to all the authorities of the Autonomous Communities».
34
See e.g. Josep Maria Castellà Andreu, «The Spanish Senate after 28 Years of Constitutional Experience. Proposals for Reform», in Jörg Luther, Paolo Passaglia and Rolando Tarchi (eds.), A World of Second Chambers: Handbook for Constitutional Studies on
Bicameralism (Milano: Giuffrè, 2006), 859-909.
35
Alberto López-Basaguren, «The Secession Issue and Territorial Autonomy in
Spain: Bicameralism Revisited», Perspectives on Federalism 10, n° 2 (2018): 260-261.
36
By the way, the compatibility of these controversial measures with Article 155 of
the Spanish Constitution has been upheld by the Constitutional Court (see Press Release
no. 86/2019 of 2 July 2019).
Estudios de Deusto
94
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
12
Federalism: Tragic Compromise and Conflicts
Giacomo Delledonne
appointed by the Catalan legislature belonged to the Partido Popular.
Because of the relative weakness of the Senate and its perceived anti-Catalan
attitude, the Government felt somehow forced to seek active support from
other parliamentary groups. Thus, the PP engaged in negotiations regarding
the application of the procedure under Art. 155 with the main opposition
party, the Partido Socialista Obrero Español (PSOE). To quote just an
example, the Government was persuaded to give up its plan regarding Catalan public media and to accept that control over them would continue to rest
with the Parlament of Catalonia37.
V. CONCLUDING REMARKS
The above discussion does not aim to sketch a general theory of conflicts
within federal and multi-level orders. Rather, it points at two crucial aspects.
On the one hand, a tragic dimension is inherently related to federal arrangements. Devices like homogeneity clauses and provisions regulating federal
intervention can be described as constitutional “stitches” trying to minimise,
at least to some extent, the unsettling potential that lies at the heart of many
federal compromises. On the other hand, paragraphs 3 and 4 have looked into
the attempts of constitutional law to tame and channel existential challenges.
Constitutional homogeneity has been described as an ordinating principle
that should ensure the compatibility of the federal settlement with the very
basic structure of the constitutional order, including the handling of secession crises. On the other hand, 20th century constitutionalism has strived to
align last-resort mechanisms like federal interventions with some procedural
safeguards. At the end of the day, the current discussion is not so much on the
alternative between political and judicial solutions as on the need for the
involvement of multiple centres of authority in order to reflect the inherent
pluralism of the constitutional system.
37
See López-Basaguren, «The Secession Issue…», 258.
Estudios de Deusto
13
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95 • http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/
95
FEDERALISM: TRAGIC COMPROMISE
AND CONFLICTS
Federalismo: compromiso trágico y conflictos
Giacomo Delledonne
Postdoctoral researcher in Comparative Public Law
Institute for Law, Politics and Development (Dirpolis)
Scuola Superiore Sant’Anna, Pisa
giacomo.delledonne@santannapisa.it
http://dx.doi.org/10.18543/ed-67(1)-2019pp83-95
Copyright
Estudios de Deusto es una revista de acceso abierto, lo que significa que es de libre acceso en su in
tegridad. Se permite su lectura, la búsqueda, descarga, distribución y reutilización legal en cualquier
tipo de soporte sólo para fines no comerciales, sin la previa autorización del editor o el autor, siempre
que la obra original sea debidamente citada y cualquier cambio en el original esté claramente indicado
Estudios de Deusto is an Open Access journal which means that it is free for full access, reading,
search, download, distribution, and lawful reuse in any medium only for non-commercial purposes,
without prior permission from the Publisher or the author; provided the original work is properly
cited and any changes to the original are clearly indicated.
Estudios de Deusto
© Universidad de Deusto • ISSN 0423-4847 • ISSN-e 2386-9062, Vol. 67/1, enero-junio 2019, págs. 83-95
http://www.revista-estudios.deusto.es/