“The Human Barnyard” and Kenneth Burke’s Philosophy
of Technology
Ian Hill, University of Illinois
Abstract:
Ian Hill corrects our simplistic notions of Burke as a Luddite. This article
elucidates Burke’s philosophy of technology and his deployment of technology throughout his
texts.
In a letter written in the Spring of 1946, Malcolm Cowley described the benefits of a newlyordered “garden tractor” to his friend Kenneth Burke. Cowley arrested his product promotion
before delving into detail. He wrote, “Can’t imagine you buying such, although it would greatly
simplify your lawn problem, which, I suppose, you don’t want simplified.” With Burke’s
probable negative attitude toward his tractor in mind, Cowley proposed that the “moral lesson
that he drew from Burke’s most recent book, Grammar [of Motives],” was “Don’t use
Machinery!”[1] Cowley realized that Burke, a self-proclaimed “anti-technologist,” would not
purchase the mass-produced tilling machine.[2]
Kenneth Burke spent copious time grappling with the meanings and ramifications of
technological behavior. He recognized the waste and destruction that technologies entailed, and
these problems constituted one of the central themes that Burke confronted throughout his
writings: “Big Technology.” Technology was so central to Burke’s writings that he included
“separated by instruments of his own making” as one of his five defining characteristics of
humankind.[3] Beyond mere “instruments,” Burke’s concept of technology referred to complex
technologies and techniques, like television, gene-splicing, and atomic bombs. Complicated
systems of human behavior, such as the “‘technology’ of money as motive,” also contributed to
what Burke called the creation of the “technological empire” that “establishes . . . the conditions
of world order.”[4]
Indeed, Burke’s writing was fraught with technological anxiety, and his negative attitude toward
technology developed over many decades. Burke’s life further exemplified an anti-technological
style of behavior; he lived on a rustic farm without running water or electricity well into the
1960s. This anti-technological attitude was manifested in Burke’s initial recognition of the
‘absurdity’ of planned obsolescence.[5] Within a handful of early writings, Burke identified that
the codependent problems of economics and technology created a prodigious amount of wasteful
overproduction. In his first book, Counter-Statement, he wrote that “overproduction” enabled by
“applied science . . . has been, up to now, the most menacing condition our modern civilization
has had to face.”[6] Burke emphasized the deleterious effects of technology practice, but he had
yet to develop the full apocalyptic overtones that he later assigned to Big Technology. In 1972,
Burke reflected upon the years 1930-1931 during which he published Counter-Statement and the
essay “Waste—or the Future of Prosperity” that satirized the overproduction economy. He wrote,
“I then viewed the cult of excessive technologic ‘progress’ rather as a mere cultural absurdity
than as the grave economic problem it now shows signs of ‘progressively’ becoming.”[7] What
he once considered an ‘absurd’ threat appeared more alarming, and Burke’s initial attitude later
coalesced into a deep distrust of most technological behavior. Technology thus came to serve as
a central locus of Burke’s critical agenda.
The “most menacing condition” still threatens humanity’s eradication with atomic bombs,
however, so Burke desired to supplant technological authority with something else: he called for
a corrective to technology motivated by “symbolic actions.” Burke defined symbolic actions as
“modes of behavior made possible by the acquiring of a conventional, arbitrary symbol system, a
definition that would apply to modes of symbolicity as different as primitive speech, styles of
music, painting, sculpture, dance, highly developed mathematical nomenclatures, traffic signals,
road maps, or mere dreams.” Such actions are behaviors not necessitated by humanity’s
physiological demands.[8] Symbolic actions are the creative individual contributions to the
formation of society, and all attempts to change dangerous behaviors, such as the production of
species-threatening technologies, must derive from symbolic forms.
Change motivated by symbolic action constitutes the crux of Burke’s response to technology and
his “Critic’s Credo.” In the “Critic’s Credo” from a letter to Cowley in the Fall of 1931, Burke’s
“program” calls for critics to direct their criticism to a specific context, or “a program, a
discussion as to what effects might be desirable at the critic’s particular time in history.”[9]
Although he did not mention technology in his “Credo,” the first paragraph of CounterStatement’s “Program” focused attention on the increasing destructive power of chemical
weapons technology. Such weapons served as a primary element of the “particular cluster of
conditions” that constituted the technological context in 1931, when “A more fitting emphasis
[than heroism in war] now may be the analogy between war and mosquito extermination.”[10]
The “desirable effects” in 1931 were to not annihilate humanity with mustard gas. Hence, his
program entailed symbolically countering such problematic technology. In turn, his
terminological transformation of technological behavior would be inherently facilitated by
rhetoric.
I argue that Burke enacted a rhetorical philosophy of technology, and that the corpus of
“boikwoiks,” a term Burke coined to describe his oeuvre, outlined a critical program to counter
Big Technology.[11] Before I explore the intertwining of technology and rhetoric in his texts, I
outline how Burke framed his conception of the technological problem in response to 20th
century American society. This “particular cluster of conditions” was dominated by problems
like industrial pollution, genetic experimentation, and advanced weaponry. Then, I argue that his
“entelechial principle of perfection” shows both how Burke’s philosophy of technology is rooted
in anxiety about the self-extinction of the human race and how it provides a conceptual link
between technological extinction and his Rhetoric. I subsequently demonstrate how Burke’s
-2-
rejection of the instrumental attitude, owing to its reliance on dangerous “terminisitic screens,”
provides an example of an imperfect attempt to invent pure technology and “pure persuasion.”
The failure of instrumental symbolism to correct its own problems thus led Burke to argue that
the way to alter dangerous technology practice lay in a symbolic transformation that would
mitigate technology’s symbolic control of human relations. I conclude by arguing that the
agglomerated effect of Burke’s conception of technological behavior indicates that he
constructed a rhetorical philosophy of technology. By “rhetorical philosophy of technology,” I
mean that Burke’s concept of technology entailed that rhetoric motivates technology, and that
technology motivates behavior. For Burke, the realms of technology and rhetoric are inseparable
because technology and motivation are fundamental conditions of human existence.
“The Human Barnyard”: Observing and Reacting to the
Technological Situation
From the massive conglomeration of modern troubles, Big Technology emerged as one of the
defining characteristics of “The Human Barnyard.”[12] Burke infused his corpus with responses
to the technological situation, and thereby constructed his own critical circumference and
terminology to depict ills like chemical wastes and nuclear holocausts. As Burke noted in A
Grammar of Motives, “To select a set of terms is, by the same token, to select a
circumference.”[13] Burke himself selected terms whose circumference of meaning
encompassed Big Technology both explicitly and through association with other societal ills that
Burke used to exemplify modern society. The technological nature of industrialism, capitalism,
and war further characterize the violence of the American “Give and Take.”[14] In the remainder
of this section, I elaborate how Burke’s observations about technology and his conception of
situation revealed a preoccupation with technological destruction as the preeminent problem both
resulting from and facing human relations. Then, I examine how Burke’s conceived his critical
purpose as a rhetorical corrective to Big Technology.
As Burke began his authorial career, a number of technological breakthroughs and tragedies
occurred. WWI saw a dramatic increase in killing proficiency; agriculture transformed the
Midwest into the Dust Bowl; industrial machinery enslaved factory workers as managers turned
to automation; capitalism wasted more and more resources through planned obsolescence and
consumerism; and automobiles transformed the American landscape. Politically, Burke watched
the technological horrors of Nazi Germany and its concentration camps unfold in fascist Europe,
and the Soviet communist experiment transform into brutal Stalinism. At home, democracy did
nothing to check the ever expanding powers of corporations and their attendant technological
demands. These problems received ample attention from science fiction literature and film,
genres that flourished during Burke’s career.[15] Other literary and cultural critics like Upton
Sinclair, John Dos Passos, and Lewis Mumford, chronicled the plight of modern factory workers
enmeshed in industrial oppression. Of course, the Bomb added urgency to the technological
menace. Nazism, Stalinism, global pollution, and advanced weaponry characterize Big
Technology in Burke’s depiction of The Scramble.
-3-
This technological situation demanded a comprehensive response, a response as comprehensive
as the one provided by French sociologist Jacques Ellul. Ellul’s conception of The Technological
Society viewed the entirety of modern human behavior as a manifestation of la technique. He
defined “technique” as “the totality of methods rationally arrived at and having absolute
efficiency . . . in every field of human activity.” Ellul therefore argued that technique pervades
society; it “is related to every factor in the life of modern man; it affects social facts as well as all
others.”[16] Burke’s attitude toward technology may appear, like Ellul’s, to overemphasize
technology in relation to other problems that plague society.
Burke provided an example of his tendency to amplify “technology” in “In Haste.” Responding
to a “strung-out logo” on TV for a telecommunications company Burke admitted that he
committed “a kind of ‘synecdochic fallacy,’” in which he mistook “a part of the whole.”[17]
Instead of hearing an advertisement about a set of specific telephonic artifacts, Burke wrote, “all
I intrinsically hear is ‘whether it’s Technology, Technology, Technology, Technology, or
Technology, . . . Technology.”[18] Given Burke’s apprehension of technology’s allpervasiveness, Mike Hübler’s pentadic analysis of Jacques Ellul’s philosophical conception of
technology is apt. In “The Drama of a Technological Society,” Hübler argued that Jacque Ellul’s
conception of la technique, which portrayed the rampant invasiveness of technology into every
sphere of human life, provides a significant entry point for defining “a rhetoric of
technology.”[19] Although Burke did not address technology in as systematic and extensive a
statement as Ellul, Burke’s piecemeal elucidation of Big Technology did rival Ellul’s
comprehensive assessment of “The Technological Society.”
According to Burke, technology seemed monolithic owing to its global effects. In Attitudes
Toward History Burke wrote, “that in going from ‘tool-using’ or ‘tool-making’ to ‘technology’
we have gone from the ‘universal’ or ‘generic’ to the ‘global’ . . . We use the term ‘world
empire’ with relation to technology because technology’s vast and ever-changing variety of
requirements means in effect that areas hitherto widely separated in place and culture are
integrally brought together.”[20] Thus Burke’s conception of technology rivaled Ellul’s
conception of la technique, because diverse examples of problematic human technology practice
both demonstrated the universal scope of the dangerous technological situation and demanded a
corrective response.
Like Ellul, Burke recognized the interconnectedness of all spheres of human activity with
technology. According to Burke, “though men’s technological innovations are but a fraction of
the ‘human condition’ in general, the great clutter of such things that characterize modern life
adds up to a formative background.”[21] The Human Barnyard resulted from a multitude of
motivating factors, such as high finance, politics, religion, aesthetics, and the long list of
persuasive “God-terms” that Burke compiled in his Rhetoric.[22] In Burke’s conception of
situation, “technology” could therefore serve either as a god-like motivating term, in the manner
of la technique and Big Technology, or it could serve as a mere factor in a vast, open-ended
range of activities. Either way, Burke’s observations of technology again and again emphasized
its destructive capacity.
-4-
The destructive power of technology and its intertwining with economics and politics comprised
what Burke called “The Rhetorical Situation.” In order to define the general “rhetorical
situation,” Burke identified the American “human situation” as “characterized by the present
conditions of technology, finance, and sociopolitical unrest.” Indeed, “Our identification with
these two great unwieldy leviathans—technology and the state—is central to the rhetorical
situation as we now confront it.” Burke clarified that the interrelatedness of technologies and
terminologies “does not allow me to make a flat distinction such as that, say, between the words
one is using and the nonverbal circumstances in which one is using them.”[23] Any response to
technology is thus inherently a rhetorical response, since Burke defined rhetoric as “the use of
language as a symbolic means of inducing cooperation in beings that by nature respond to
symbols.”[24] Owing to the influence of technology on the “rhetorical situation,” rhetors “induce
cooperation” with “symbolic action” to maintain or alter Big Technology.
The primary role that Burke assigned himself in response to Big Technology was that of worldtransforming critic aiming to counter the problems derived from “Counter-Nature.”[25] Burke
elucidated his conception of the active critic as part of his motivational purpose. Looking over
the entire corpus of boikwoiks, his repeated allusions to technological predicaments and his
repeated exhortations to solve them in part defined the circumference of his project. Burke
argued that the situational “interrelationships” that a writer covers “are his motives. For they are
his situation; and situation is but another word for motives.”[26] Burke framed writing as a
motivating symbolic act defined by its situational characteristics, so he thereby declared his own
motivation to counter Big Technology by emphasizing it again and again.
Burke defended the importance of fomenting attitudes antithetical to the “cult of powers” that
controlled, in part, technology. He wrote to Cowley in early 1942:
[S]o far or so long as I am able, to go on trying to increase our awareness (my own and others’)
of the ways in which motives move us and deceive us, and what kind of knowledge the nature of
motives demands of us, if we are not to goad one another endlessly to the cult of powers that can
bring no genuine humaneness to the world. It would be silly to think that any book, or even a
whole library of books, could solve such difficulties. But such books are, I know, one of the
steps in the right direction. Until the steamrollers flatten out all.[27]
In the face of approaching steamrollers, Burke kept writing in an attempt to hold the
technological menace at bay. Despite the odds against the success of his critical program, Burke
considered it his mission to counteract technology’s ills. When Burke’s writing career entered its
final stages, the steamrollers still approached, so the critical imperative to counter-counter-nature
remained a primary concern.
Thus, the proclivity of humanity to drive itself to the brink of extinction formed the technological
context in which Burke formulated his philosophy of technology. This pervasive technological
condition also comprised the “rhetorical situation.” As such, technology and rhetoric are
inextricably bound together. Technologies and terminologies either maintain or transform
society. All the while, humans tend to promote annihilation. In order to integrate this proclivity
to exterminate each other into his own critical circumference, Burke generalized that people goad
-5-
each other to fulfill their goals to the utmost perfection possible. He termed this propensity to
seek symbolic perfection “entelechy,” which formed an important component of Burke’s
counter-technological critical program.
Rotten with Perfection: Terminologies and Technologies
In a letter written to Cowley on the day of Nagasaki’s bombing, Burke lamented that, “There
seems now no logical thing to do but go on tinkering with this damned thing until they have
blown up the whole damned world.”[28] Burke referenced the probable technological result of
“entelechy,” his gloomy “principle of perfection,” which forecasted the innovation of evergreater, and hence more perfect, destruction. Engineers, politicians, manufacturers, and militaries
exemplified the principle of perfection by constructing the Bomb, but the entelechial principle’s
ultimate fulfillment as a weapon entails humanity’s self-extinction.
In “Why Satire, with a Plan for Writing One” Burke defined “Entelechy” as “tracking down the
implications of a position, going to the end of the line.”[29] Indeed, Burke’s own thoughts often
went “to the end of a line,” and Burke insisted that technology would attain “perfect fulfillment
in a perfect apocalyptic holocaust” in nuclear war or “the total pollution of our once handsome
planet.”[30] Burke witnessed the perfection of form and matter in not one, lone bomb, but rather
the Bomb – the global military system, not in one polluted stream, but global pollution “among
the Seven Vast Oceanic Sewers.”[31] “Tracking down the end of the line” of technology always
appears to lead to global destruction, so technology represents one of the most rotten forms of
perfection to pursue with both rhetorical and technological invention. However, the Bomb failed
to annihilate humanity. Despite the motivation to build a perfect weapon, the Bomb thus
displayed an imperfect quality.
Burke considered entelechy another of his defining ontological conditions, and he linked it with
the rhetorical concept of hierarchy. He argued that “Man is goaded by the spirit of hierarchy (or
moved by the sense of order) and rotten with perfection.” As per this ontological condition,
Burke argued that all rhetorics, whether technological or not, tended toward perfection.
According to Burke the entelechial concept was “central to the nature of language as motive,” so
human language would always attempt perfection in form.[32] And, because both symbol use
and tool use defined human existence for Burke, entelechy linked these two realms of human
behavior. Intertwined attempts to attain perfection in either technology or rhetoric tended to
materialize in imperfect forms. Like the failure of technological rhetoric to goad complete
technological suicide, all rhetorics fail to attain “pure persuasion.”[33] The concept of entelechy
thus links the difficult tasks of utter technological destruction and “pure” rhetoric.
Burke’s entlechial principle provides a pivot point for Burke’s program to counter Big
Technology. Entelechy demonstrates how the same terminological motivation that may induce
human extinction may also, with critical intervention, correct the problem with rhetoric. “The
principle of perfection” united the motivational drive to produce perfectly rotten rhetoric with the
drive to produce perfectly rotten technology, as well as the motivational drive to symbolically
correct the problem. In the remainder of this section, I describe how Burke conceived his
-6-
“entelechial principle of perfection.” Then, I argue that conceptualizing entelechy as a primary
human characteristic entailed equivalence between destroying the world with technology and
destroying the world with words. The continued existence of the world, however, indicates that
the “trained incapacities” of rhetors and engineers have produced neither persuasion nor
technology yet capable of goading self-extinction. Thus Burke rooted his rhetorical philosophy
of technology in the rotten perfection of both machines and language as they failed to materialize
species extinction.
Burke appropriated Aristotle’s concept of entelechy, or the “actuality” of the human soul, to
show how human motivations compel people to complete their tasks regardless of the harm they
may cause. In De Anima, Aristotle used the term entelekheia to describe the realization of form
and matter in the soul. In Aristotle’s formula, the soul is the actuality, or form, of matter’s
potential embodiment.[34] Burke reinterpreted the concept to apply to all realms of human
behavior, thereby “casuistically stretching” the term to include the materialization of the full
range of human relations.[35] Burke defined casuistic stretching as a process in which “one
introduces new principles while theoretically remaining faithful to old principles.” Burke
elaborated about entelechy in Dramatism and Development where he wrote of his casuistic
stretch that, “the resources of symbolic action culminate in a possibly non-Aristotelian
application of the Aristotelian ‘entelechy.’”[36] Because of his casuistic stretching of entelechy
to reflect the “principle of perfection” operating as a definitional aspect of human society, Burke
noted that the climax of his entelechy faithfully differed from Aristotle’s entelechial actualization
of the mind and body within the individual human soul.[37] Burke thus amplified the term’s
contingency from individual anima to species survival while he also generalized the term,
applying it to subjects beyond “the soul.”
By conceptualizing the realization of form in matter via soul, Aristotle provided Burke with a
term capable of defining human goals as being inducements to speculative perfection. Burke
considered this motivation to perfect tasks both a delightful freedom and a rotten necessity. He
wrote that the “‘entelechial’ motive . . . is equatable with both necessity and freedom in the sense
that the consistent rounding out of a terminology is the very opposite of frustration. Necessary
movement toward perfect symmetry is thus free.”[38] The result of such perfect motivation
could result in beneficial perfected behaviors, or menacing perfected behaviors, depending on the
“trained incapacities” and “occupational psychoses” that guided a specific enterprise.
The concepts of “trained incapacity” and “occupational psychosis” explained that individual
behaviors and convictions entailed potential catastrophe if entelechially pursued. In Permanence
and Change, Burke appropriated “trained incapacity” from Thorstein Veblen, who “meant the
state of affairs whereby one’s very abilities can function as blindnesses.” In a similar vein, by
“occupational psychosis” Burke meant that everyone had a certain orientation to the world, and
that a person’s occupations would determine his or her reality, “since they focus attention on
different orders of relationship.” One problem with the occupational psychosis is that, “one tends
to state the problem in such a way that his particular aptitude becomes the ‘solution’ for it.”
Everyone has trained incapacities and occupational psychoses—terms that are somewhat
interchangeable—but those of the engineers, technocrats, capitalists, etc. pose the greatest threat
-7-
to humanity through the relentless entelechial demand for technological progress at the expense
of humaneness and the environment.
Owing to its destructive importance to 20th century society, Burke called the “technological
psychosis” the “master psychosis,” the psychosis most in need of corrective symbolic change. He
further clarified that humanity’s reliance on technology put the “technical psychosis” forward as
the most ominous trained incapacity: “In and about all these [occupational psychoses], above
them, beneath them, mainly responsible for their perplexities, is the technological psychosis. It is
the one psychosis which is, perhaps, in its basic patterns, contributing a new principle to the
world. It is at the center of our glories and our distress.” [39] Because all occupations take their
terminologies “to the end of the line,” people occupied by technology do the same.
Technological problems therefore resulted from the terminological endeavors whose ‘end of the
line’ terminated in artifacts like the Bomb and Flit. Thus, the perfection of technology in the
production of innovative artifacts proved the success of trained incapacities’ ability to build
glorious machines as well as rotten machines. This terminological inability of humanity to
perfect universally beneficial technology resulted in a state of ineptitude in which perfection
equaled total annihilation. Although goaded toward perfection, the results of ‘progressive”
behavior appeared much less than perfect. Rotten technologies and their attendant terminologies
were imperfect enough to imperil individual physiologies, and incapable of reversing the
problems they created.
As a technological critic, Burke did not discount his own culpability for dangerous technologies.
Literary pursuits tend toward rotten perfection just as much as technological pursuits. Therefore,
rotten perfection further intertwine terminologies and technologies because literary products rival
the entelechial motion toward rottenness of technological products. In “Definition of Man”
Burke wrote of the pervasiveness of the “‘entelechial’ principle” that, “Each [scientific] specialty
is like the situation of an author who has an idea for a novel, and who will never rest until he has
completely embodied it in a book. Insofar as any of those terminologies [scientific] happen also
to contain the risks of destroying the world, that’s just too bad; but the fact remains that, so far as
the sheer principles of the investigation are concerned, they are no different from those of the
writer who strives to complete his novel.”[40] Burke thus argued that the novelist and the
engineer produced artifacts and rhetorics according to their respective trained incapacities that
goaded them to rotten perfection. Both technological invention and rhetorical invention, aiming
for perfection, tended to end up threatening life itself. As a writer, Burke’s rhetoric participated
in this rather imperfect process.
The implications of entelechy for Burke’s philosophy of technology mean that humanity faces a
constant drive to follow its projects through to their completion, regardless of the probable
negative ramifications. In addition, rhetoric facilitates the technological drive to perfection, and
itself represents a terminological drive to perfection. Both motivations tend to fall short of
perfection and end up leaving humanity to deal with a series of rotten situations, many of which
threaten human survival. Even though entelechy has failed to deliver total species eradication,
the continued increase in technological problems left Burke to critically attempt to correct the
mounting detritus of bombs and Flit by grappling with “instrumentalism,” the attitude and
-8-
philosophical school that facilitated and propagated the technological conditions that menaced
human relations.
Confronting the Instrumental ‘Bulldozer Mentality’ and its
Terministic Screens
Burke punned in “In Haste” that, “Technology is the issue, the instrumental principle.”[41] Both
clauses in this sentence represented different, but intertwined problems for Burke’s response to
Big Technology. Burke recognized both the “issue” of dangerous instruments and the terministic
and rhetorical motivations that empowered the instrumental destructions of places rendered
infamous by their atomic eradications and DDT defoliations. Because both dangerous
instruments and dangerous instrumental attitudes threatened humanity, he identified the
“instrumental principle” as Big Technology’s central motivating force. Burke therefore desired
to correct the entelechial technological and rhetorical behaviors attributable to people engaged in
inventing, producing, selling, buying and, implementing technology under the guise of
instrumentalism. Any correction to Big Technology had to address technology’s terminological
as well as mechanical roots. Because of the inseparability of technologies and their terms a
corrective to instrumentalism must address its terms but not succumb to its terministic screens.
In fact, Burke’s rhetorical philosophy of technology absorbs instrumentalism’s terminology in
order to redeploy the terms to transform technology. To elucidate how Burke performs this
appropriation of terms, I first define Burke’s conception of the instrumental problem. Then, I
show how Burke rejected instrumental ideals by disagreeing with the conflation of human and
machine communication. For Burke, conflating humans and machines exposed the terministic
screens that facilitated instrumentalism. Burke’s anti-instrumental attitude did not purely reject
its terminology, but appropriated it to advance his own critical program. His rhetorical
philosophy of technology thus constitutes an anti-instrumental instrumentalism.
Langdon Winner provided a standard definition of instrumentalism in his critique of Autonomous
Technology. According to Winner, proponents of “instrumental norms and motives” believed
that, “the technically adapted side of one’s personality begins to exercise control over the rest of
the personality.” Adherents to this perspective formulated a conception of “social situations such
that all problems are ultimately defined in terms of instrumentality and only instrumental
concerns have any influence.”[42] The instrumental attitude facilitates the increased destructive
power of technology as humans imbue instruments with the same faith that they place in each
other to solve problems that derive from technology.
Because Burke made his anti-technological feelings clear, any theoretical approach that either
put faith in technology’s supposed inactive neutrality, or the supposed ability of technology to
solve its own problems did not suffice for him, to say the least. In his “Dramatism” essay Burke
described the attitude that fostered instrumentality as a “bulldozer mentality that rips into natural
conditions without qualms.” The activities that characterize this mentality are, “the many
enterprises that keep men busy destroying in the name of progress or profit the ecological
-9-
balance on which, in the last analysis, our eventual wellbeing depends, and so on.”[43] In
another critique of instrumentalism in “Variations on ‘Providence,’” Burke responded to “the riot
of new disorders that arose as unintended by-products of . . . innovations.” He called the
technological attitudes that motivated people to ‘predestine’ the counter-natural Scramble the
“instrumentalist fallacy.”[44] This fallacy argues that designing behavior to mimic machines will
benefit humanity, and that technological innovation should continue unabated. Instrumentalists,
or “technologers,” utilize language that understands the semblance of humans and machines as a
basic premise.[45] Blinded by technological spectacle, instrumentalists tend to excuse the
“unintended byproducts of technology” as necessary to “progress.”
Burke called the use of such reductive, blinding language a “terministic screen.” Terministic
screens emerge as the language used to describe and defend any human activity. Burke argued
that, “Even if any given terminology is a reflection of reality, by its very nature as a terminology
it must be a selection of reality; and to this extent it must function also as a deflection of reality.”
An instrumentalist’s terms reflect the successful completion of technological projects, and
therefore they select beneficial technological artifacts as argumentative proof of progress.[46]
Therefore instrumental language deflects its destructive reality. A nuclear engineer’s
experiments and livelihood emphasize the benefits supplied by atomic power while downplaying
the menace of atomic holocaust.
According to Burke, terministic screens act as rhetorical blinders, channeling human behavior in
certain directions predetermined by the selection of terms. He argued:
Not only does the nature of the terms affect the nature of our observations, in the sense that the
terms direct the attention to one field rather than another. Also, many of the “observations” are
but implications of the particular terminology in terms of which the observations are made. In
brief, much that we take as observations about “reality” may be but the spinning out of
possibilities implicit in our particular choice of terms.[47]
Engineers, technocrats, scientists, and capitalists ‘spin out’ their observations with technological
terms. Engineers identify technology with humanity through their scientific worldview, so they
choose the terms of technology to represent human reality, which makes species-threatening
technology seem a fated ontological necessity. Entelechially “spinning out” dangerous
technologies into doomsday scenarios reflects engineers’ livelihoods, so doomsday terminology
facilitates this reality, even while attempting to deflect negative perceptions of the Bomb.
One argumentative symptom of the instrumental ‘master psychosis’ that Burke often confronted
was the equating of machine and human communications in order to prove the benefits of the
automated control of people. This process reduced humanity to its most machine-like
characteristics, much like mathematician Norbert Wiener’s cybernetic arguments. Wiener’s book
The Human Use of Human Beings exemplifies the type of instrumental language that Burke
criticized, because Wiener modeled his concept of feedback and automated control on human
communication.[48] He believed that mechanisms best represent the communicative potential of
humanity. Because humans receive “feedback” about actions through memory and language,
-10-
Wiener modeled his machine communication systems to imitate the human capability to react to
information. He wrote:
[T]he physical functioning of the living individual and the operation of some of the newer
communication machines are precisely parallel in their analogous attempts to control entropy
through feedback. Both of them have sensory receptors as one stage in their cycle of operation:
that is, in both of them there exists a special apparatus for collecting information from the outer
world at low energy levels, and for making it available in the operation of the individual or of the
machine.[49]
Communication appears machine-like because of the innovations that enabled feedback. Because
Wiener’s machines process information in a similar way as humans, the distinction between the
two entities blurred. The analogy reduces humans to one defining aspect, and Wiener used the
conflation of terms to justify his method. He wrote, “Now that certain analogies of behavior are
being observed between the machine and the living organism, the problem as to whether the
machine is alive or not is, for our purposes, semantic and we are at liberty to answer it one way
or the other as best suits our convenience.”[50] Thus, Wiener’s ‘semantic’ equivocation of the
word ‘life’ empowered him to redefine human existence in terms of cybernetic innovation. His
terministic screens re-construed human existence as the model for and successful mimicry of
cybernetic machines.
Because Burke believed humanity overemphasized the relationship between human and
machine, he considered their conflation in instrumental metaphors troublesome. Burke therefore
rejected the instrumental attitude that equated machine and human communication. Instead, he
posited the failure of instrumental conceptions of technology to account for the full range of
communication. In “Mind, Body, and the Unconscious,” Burke argued that, “The fact that a
machine can be made to function like a participant in human dialogue does not require us to treat
the two kinds of behavior as identical . . . [M]an differs qualitatively from his machines, since
these man-made caricatures of man are too poor in animality.”[51] In an earlier objection to
instrumentalism’s terministic screens from Permanence and Change, Burke argued that, “The
exclusively mechanistic metaphor is objectionable not because it is directly counter to the poetic,
but because it leaves too much out of account. It shows us merely those aspects of experience
which can be phrased with its terms.”[52] Although capable of communicating, machines lack
the poetic sensibility to react to changing conditions with altered symbolism. Therefore machine
metaphors, like Wiener’s, that buttress instrumentalism lack the power to communicate symbolic
action.
Burke’s anti-instrumental attitude did not purely reject instrumental terminology, however.
Despite rejecting machine metaphors for human communication, he appropriated instrumental
terminology to advance his own critical program. Burke’s own anti-instrumental instruments, or
his critical concepts, absorbed instrumental terminology in order to correct it. He therefore
offered a technological “Perspective by Incongruity.” According to Burke’s definition, a
Perspective by Incongruity is a term that “belongs by custom to a certain category—and by
rational planning you wrench it loose and metaphorically apply it to a different category.” Such
metaphorical wrenching characterized the realm of symbolic action, the impious poetic
-11-
manipulation of symbols of authority. The incongruous repossessing of words led the way to
“repossess[ing] the world” from the technocrats.[53] Only an unorthodox, impious “perspective
by incongruity” can instigate a symbolic change to save the earth from the dangers posed by
technology by taking instrumental terms and applying them to anti-technological projects.
Burke’s rhetorical philosophy of technology thus enacted an anti-instrumental instrumentalism.
He utilized his own conceptual terminology to correct the technology and terminology used by
“technologers” to produce bombs and pollutants.
As noted above, Burke made his anti-technological stance quite clear in Counter-Statement.
However, Burke’s appropriation of instrumental language imbued his own writings with an
explicit instrumental character. In the book’s preface, Burke appropriated an instrumental
metaphor to describe his critical means. He wrote of the “Lexicon Rhetoricæ” that “it is frankly
intended as a machine—machine for criticism . . . It is a kind of judgment machine, designed to
serve as an instrument for clarifying critical issues.”[54] The self-declared instrumental nature of
Burke’s “judgment machine” led Star A. Muir to argue that, “Burke expresses a preference for
an organic frame of reference, yet the development of his schema of analysis is methodological
and instrumental at points.”[55] Indeed, other commentators on Burke’s corpus have noted the
instrumental application of Burke’s concepts. William H. Rueckert diagrammed the five
dramatistic terms into a “Pentad Matrix” to demonstrate the instrumental “bureaucratization” of
Burke’s own critical terministic screens.[56] Although Burke did not contend that his dramtistic
pentad was a judging machine, or matrix, like the claim he made of the “Lexicon,” its systematic
character has become a critical tool, applied to human behavior in an instrumental fashion. Jeff
Pruchnic described two more instrumental manifestations of Burke’s concepts. First, he noted
“Burke’s digital reincarnation” as the internet chat room-patrolling Burkebot, and second, argued
that “Burke’s Perspective by Incongruity is essentially a technology for retraining human
response.”[57] Divorced from his complex corpus, all of the concepts found in the boikwoiks
toolbox can be taken out and utilized to hammer out Burke-ian criticism. His concepts are critical
instruments that enable the programmed application of Burke’s dramatistic and logological
insights. Burke’s instrumentalism, however, was not a pure instrumentalism; Burke did not
construct a machine, even metaphorically. Rather, as part of his critical program to counter
technology his judging machines are capable of transcending mere matter in motion because they
are imbued with symbolic action.
Furthermore, because Burke rejected the concept that technological problems must be solved
with technological fixes, his anti-instrumental instrumentalism needed to introduce an
incongruous, and therefore transformational, terminology into the language of atomic engineers.
Burke suggested an anti-instrumental instrumentalism to symbolically correct the type of
philosophy of technology espoused by instrumentalists like Wiener. The destructive problems
caused by instrumentalism demanded a corrective technological language. This demand led
Burke in A Grammar of Motives to suggest utilizing the terms “technologism” and
“operationalism”[58] to constitute an anti-technological attitude. He wrote that, because
“something so unnatural as technology developed under the name of naturalism, we might
ironically expect that, were ‘technologism’ to become the name for ‘naturalism,’ the philosophy
would be the first step towards a development away from technology.” Burke then calls on
-12-
everyone to call technology “operationalism” in the hope that doing so “would lead to the
stabilization of technological operations rather than to the development of new ones. As
‘naturalism’ would lead us, via technology, away from nature, so perhaps ‘operationalism’ might
be a way of leading us, in the name of technological operations, away from technology.”[59 As a
disabling Perspective by Incongruity, Burke advocated appropriating the technological
psychosis’s own terminology to undermine it. In order to counter dangerous terminologies, a
critic needed to symbolically dismantle problematic attitudes, like that of instrumentalism, by
impiously utilizing the attitude’s own terms. This appropriation would, in theory, be a symbolic
act, a potentially transformative corrective force. Burke’s rhetorical philosophy of technology
thus both rejects instrumental terminology as well as it embraces it. Corrective symbolism
derives from an impious appropriation of the problematic symbolism.
The Rhetorical Purpose: Logological Transformation
According to Burke, the over-arching symbolic structures of society originated in poetic forms,
so Big Technology’s corrective must also derive from symbolism. The flippant substitution of
‘operationalism’ to describe the motion of nature that Burke suggested above hardly constituted
an anti-technological critical program. Instead, Burke’s more sustained attempt to utilize
aesthetic forms, the entelechial principle, and anti-instrumental instrumental terminology
coalesced around his Helhaven satire. Burke’s satire served as his symbolic enactment of the
critical program to counter-technology
Because Burke argued that the way to reverse dangerous technology practice and mitigate
instrumentalism’s control of human activity is symbolic change, a transformative force must
alter all of the symbolic behaviors that empower technology, such as money, politics, and art.
Burke’s concept of symbolic change thus calls for a transformation of society on all levels, not
just the technological. In this section, I first provide an overview of Burke’s general concept of
transformative symbolic action before I juxtapose “symbolic action” with Martin Heidegger’s
concept of poiēsis to further define Burke’s philosophical technology corrective. Then, I describe
Burke’s satirical attempt to correct technologically-driven ecological peril. Thus, Burke enacted
his own rhetorical philosophy of technology by attempting to goad transformation of cultural
values with his own satirical symbolic action.
Burke’s concept of symbolic transformation entailed overturning trained incapacities with a
Nietzschian “transvaluation of all values” – what Burke called a “kind of verbal atom
smashing.”[60] In Ecce Homo, Nietzsche defined the “revaluation of all values” as the “formula
for an act of extreme self-examination on the part of humanity, become flesh and blood in me.”
The act of revaluing involved countering accepted values and truths, so Nietzsche claimed, “I
contradict as has never been contradicted before and am nevertheless the opposite of a No-saying
spirit.”[61] Burke appropriated Nietzsche’s “revaluation of values” to examine humanity’s
pieties and “reorient” them.[62] Burke also recognized his own motivation as a critic to counter
and contradict dangerous, yet accepted, truths that motivate human behavior. Thus, whereas
Nietzsche contradicted the norms of 19th century European industrial culture, Burke contradicted
the norms of 20th century American capitalism and its attendant technological threats.
-13-
According to Burke, complete transvaluation best occurs when derived from artistic symbolism
as a precursor to greater change, but poetic production is only the bare minimum of generating
symbolic change. An aesthetic symbolic action will, in theory, precede other actions that art
might goad. He conceded that culture alone would not cause symbolic change, even though he
believed change would arise from aesthetics. Aesthetics provide only the initial locus of change.
Indeed, one personal motivation to criticize derived from Burke’s effort to create change by
altering attitudes with symbols. In “War, Response, and Contradiction” Burke wrote, “To an
extent, books merely exploit our attitudes—and to an extent they may form our attitudes.”[63]
Burke wanted his own books to form attitudes against technology and capitalism, hence his
literary output and work as a propagandist and sloganeer. However, Burke also knew that for
true change to occur the aesthetic kernel must transcend mere art and with great rapidity affect
all forms of human relations. Burke watched the revolutionary potential of Marxist collectivism
stall out, failing to instigate viable correctives to either technology or capitalism. He remained
hopeful, however, because historical precedent, as outlined in the first four acts of his historical
drama in Attitudes Toward History, demonstrate that symbolic change does occur. The question
that remained was whether humanity would survive to see such change take place. In CounterStatement, Burke argued:
Symbolic change through poetic action must come, or humanity’s future is threatened: Since the
body [biological, human] is dogmatic, a generator of belief, society might well be benefited by
the corrective of a disintegrating art, which converts each simplicity into a complexity, which
ruins the possibility of ready hierarchies, which concerns itself with the problematical, the
experimental, and thus by implication works corrosively upon those expansionistic certainties
preparing the way for our social cataclysms.[64]
Thus, as early as his first book, Burke located the potential of art to overturn technology’s
symbolic power. This appeal to art constituted one of the main focuses of Counter-Statement’s
“Program.” Burke further elucidated his identification of aesthetics as “counter-statements” to
technological problems. He wrote:
In so far as the conversion of pure science into applied science has made the practical a menace,
the aesthetic becomes a means of reclamation. Insofar as mechanization increases the complexity
of the social structure (to the point where nothing short of great virtue and great efficiency can
make it function without disaster) the aesthetic must serve as anti-mechanization, the corrective
of the practical.[65]
This concept of aesthetic “anti-mechanization” corrected the “practical menace” by corrupting
technological operations. “Bohemian” aesthetic forms debilitated the efficiency of industrialism.
Thus, Burke argued that art can correct dominant social institutions and practices, such as the
forces of mechanization.
Since Burke advocated a corrective aesthetic program, he did not condone passivity in the face of
dangerous technology practice. Just as fanatical adherence to instrumental pieties created
problems, so too did dissipation, or resignation in the face of overwhelming negativity.[66] On
the contrary, Burke posited that immoral, impious, unorthodox action causes the kind of societal
change necessary to preserve the species, whereas moral and pious “nonsymbolic motions” only
uphold the status quo’s path to annihilation. People must transform the symbols that bolster
-14-
“technologism” in order to rescue society from its “bulldozer mentality.” In his own work Burke
attempted to perform such a transformative symbolic action. In one example of his symbolic
enactment, his speech to the American Writers’ Congress in 1935, Burke argued that in order to
garner further political support the communist movement needed to stop referring to “the
worker,” and start referring to “the people.” Burke wrote, “As a propagandizer, it is not his work
to convince the convinced, but to plead with the unconvinced, which requires him to use their
vocabulary, their values, their symbols, insofar as this is possible.”[67] Just as symbolic action to
counter capitalism requires the adoption of the capitalist “people,” symbolic action against Big
Technology requires direct engagement with the terministic screens that empower
instrumentalism.
Burke’s conception of symbolic correctives to technology comes quite close to Heidegger’s
conception of the ability of poiēsis to do the same, as described in “The Question Concerning
Technology.”[68] Heidegger posited that only a revolutionary form that transforms all aspects of
human relations empowers the ability to produce change in technology, politics, economics, and
aesthetics. The symbolic is the form in which change must occur, because the fundamental
element of humanity’s relationship with the world is language.[69] Thus, Heidegger’s solution to
dangerous technology is also intertwined with the strategic deployment of aesthetic forms.
Heidegger argued, “the coming to presence of technology harbors in itself what we least suspect,
the possible arising of the saving power.” The saving power turned out to be the other form of
Technē, art. For Heidegger, both art and technology represent forms of revealing, so the same
inventive spirit that reveals dangerous technology in practice and in language also reveals the
solution. He concluded that, “Because the essence of technology is nothing technological,
essential reflection upon technology and decisive confrontation with it must happen in a realm
that is, on the one hand, akin to the essence of technology, and, on the other, fundamentally
different from it. Such a realm is art.”[70] Heidegger described the “essence of technology” as
the generation of meaning. He wrote, “Technology is therefore no mere means. Technology is a
way of revealing. If we give heed to this, then another whole realm for the essence of technology
will open itself up to us. It is the realm of revealing, i.e., of truth.” Furthermore, “Technē belongs
to bringing-forth, to poiēsis; it is something poietic.” The revealing that occurs through invention
thus brings forth an insight into the natural relationship of humanity to the world. However, the
revealing involved with modern technological progress engenders a different relationship to
nature, and hence to humanity. According to Heidegger, “the revealing that holds sway
throughout modern technology does not unfold into a bringing-forth in the sense of poiēsis. The
revealing that rules in modern technology is a challenging, which puts to nature the unreasonable
demand that it supply energy that can be extracted and stored as such.” In turn, the challenging
of nature through technology altered humanity’s relationship to the world: “Everywhere
everything is ordered to stand by, to be immediately at hand, indeed to stand there just so that it
may be on call for a further ordering. Whatever is ordered about in this way has its own standing.
We call it the standing-reserve.” The transformation of nature into standing-reserve to be used
for technological ends, such as profit building and efficiency, obtained authority over everything,
including humanity. Heidegger argued, “The name ‘standing-reserve’ assumes the rank of an
inclusive rubric. It designates nothing less than the way in which everything presences that is
-15-
wrought upon by the challenging revealing”[71] The all-inclusive nature of the relationship
between man and nature under standing-reserve thus became the basis of human interaction not
only with nature but with other humans. In order to recuperate the saving power of Technē,
Heidegger posited an inventive reappraisal of poiēsis, because poiēsis offered imperiled
humanity a means to counter technology, first aesthetically, but later technologically as humanity
socially reinvents itself.
The rising of the saving power through the revealing of poiēsis rivaled Burke’s idea of symbolic
action because “thinking” for Heidegger contains the possibility to change the essence of
technology. Heidegger’s thinking is a form of symbolic action because it jolts humanity into a
new conception of the world similar to the change in perspective that arose from the eclipsing of
religion’s importance by science and technology. Thus, both theorists believed that humanity has
the capability to control the dangerous nature of technology as long as art germinates a
corrective. Art does not act as a corrective itself, but instead creates new interactions between
technology and humanity. In Heidegger’s terminology, humanity will no longer grant technology
the power to enframe inventiveness in a threatening manner, and in Burke’s terminology,
humanity will create a less dangerous orientation to technology through symbolic change.
Despite the numerous similarities between Burke’s and Heidegger’s philosophies of technology,
Burke never gave up on the potential for symbolic change, and he laid out a more detailed
method for fomenting revolution through aesthetics. In contrast, Heidegger did not provide a
specific program for an artistic corrective, and infamously later concluded that “Only God Can
Save Us” from technological catastrophe.[72]
In order to perform a “verbal atom smashing,” Burke enacted two intertwined concepts – the
comic corrective and satire. The corrective strategy that Burke espouses was comic, and the
corrective form was satire. Because Burke argued that a corrective to instrumentalism must also
derive from problematic technological terms, Burke used entelechial, instrumental terms to
produce his own satirical response to “Big Technology.” Burke’s concept of the comic corrective
first appeared in a discussion of humor and the grotesque in Permanence and Change, but he
gives more attention to the two poetic categories in Attitudes Toward History.[73] Unlike other
poetical forms, a “comic frame of motives” contains both the ideal and the material, and hence it,
perhaps, avoids the bureaucratization that idealistic frames of reference suffer when people milk
ideals for profit.
Burke advocated the comic corrective as the only solution to technological progress as late as
Language as Symbolic Action (1966). He had yet to offer his own comic corrective to technology
practice, however. That critical situation changed as Burke composed and recomposed
“Helhaven.” This series of satires humorously, or humorlessly depending on one’s attitude
toward dark comedy, lampoons problems derived from Big Technology.[74] Whether or not
Burke’s satirical program is humorous or not, “Helhaven” performs many of his critical
paradigms, and it represents his symbolic counter to technologism. Indeed, he based his satire on
the “unhappy fact” of “technological pollution,” and he noted that his satire appeared more tragic
than comic.[75]
-16-
“Helhaven” utilized the entelechial terminology that fueled technological catastrophe to
constitute counter-instrumentalism. In “Towards Helhaven,” Burke depicted the entelechial
result of technology as the complete destruction of the Earth via pollution. The essay combined a
short analysis of satire with a modest proposal that borrows a lot from clichéd science fiction
plots and images. “Helhaven, the greatest apocalyptic project this side of Mars,” depicts a bubble
community on the moon built to escape the ecological ravishes of technological progress on the
home planet.[76] Like a reprise of his Depression-era work, Helhaven essays mirror the satirical
enterprise of “Waste—The Future of Prosperity,” which offered an entelechial critique of
capitalistic planned obsolescence and overproduction.[77]
Using satire, Burke could “track down the implications” of “Big Technology” and “CounterNature” by “going to the end of the line,” he wrote in “Why Satire, with a Plan for Writing One.”
Burke argued, “It is thus that satire can embody the entelechial principle. But it does so
perversely, by tracking down the possibilities or implications to the point where the result is a
kind of Utopia-in-reverse.”[78] His satire thus appropriates instrumental language for his
dystopian vision. He desired to transvalue instrumental values that excuse pollution and atomic
weaponry by redistributing them in an anti-technological narrative.
The series of “Helhaven” satires also performed Burke’s rhetorical dictum that technologism’s
corrective needed to be embodied. In “In Haste” Burke wrote, “I beg, at least, you take to heart
my doctrinal lines anent the thesis that out technological (instrumental) innovations become
personalized.”[79] Indeed, as a victim of such technological carnage, Burke’s speculative corpse
would materialize the catastrophic results of the earth’s saturation with toxic chemicals. This
embodiment became tied up with the symbolism that empowered the “technological psychosis”
that produced the need for the “apocalyptic project” in the first place.
Thus, Burke argued that symbolic action can lead to change, and humanity can avoid “a
universal holocaust” of the likes depicted by his post-earth moon society. Indeed, in A Rhetoric
of Motives, written long before Burke embarked on his “Helhaven” project, Burke tied the
importance of rhetoric directly to the importance of averting total species suicide. He wrote, “let
us observe, all about us, forever goading us, though it be in fragments, the motive that attains its
ultimate identification in the thought, not of universal holocaust, but of the universal order.”[80]
The terms that Burke direct us to consider in this description of the means to correct humanity’s
entelechial pursuit of global extermination outline his theory of rhetoric: goading, identification,
hierarchical order. Rhetoric is therefore key to saving humanity from technology’s unintended
byproducts, and it points toward the defining feature of Burke’s philosophy of technology: the
function of technological rhetoric.
Conclusion: Burke’s Rhetorical Philosophy of Technology
Taken together, Burke’s technologically inflected “rhetorical situation,” his anti-instrumental
attitude, his “entelechial principle of perfection,” and his satirical corrective to Big Technology
suggest that Burke formulated a novel conception of technology rooted in rhetorical principles.
Beyond Aristotle’s conception of rhetoric as a type of technical faculty, or Technē, that facilitates
-17-
persuasion, Burke’s concept of rhetoric delineates a Technē that affects the deployment of
Technē’s own creative output – language and technology.[81] Burke’s concept of rhetoric
functions as a fulcrum that negotiates the creation of language and artifacts to induce action.[82]
Rhetoric mediates natural, physiological human necessity by upholding or altering the demands
of the counter-natural technological environment: people mold technology, technology molds the
situation, and people utilize rhetoric to induce remolding technology to transform society.[83]
Burke’s rhetorical philosophy of technology incorporates the close intertwining of technologies
and terminologies that determine humanity’s ontological status. Burke argued that humans need
to perform inherently rhetorical symbolic actions to counter instrumentalism’s “symbol-guided
techniques of technology” with a different set of terms that could perfect less catastropheinducing behaviors.[84] Because Burke’s theory of rhetoric is so intertwined with bodily survival
and the technological threat thereto, I argue that Burke’s critical program embodies a
technological rhetoric. To further demonstrate how Burke elucidated his philosophy of
technology, in conclusion I will analyze how technological concerns inflect “Logology,” one of
the key rhetorical concepts Burke utilized to explicate the function of language.
Burke’s simple definition of Logology was “words about words.” Beyond the linguistic locus of
Logology, Burke stressed that words emanate from bodies, and therefore language and criticism
depend on humanity’s physiological safety. Logology therefore emphasizes the intrinsic
physiological contingency of language use. In another definition of Logology from “Variations
on ‘Providence’” Burke wrote:
Logology, as I thus use the term (meaning etymologically ‘words about words’) starts from a
definition that applies physiologically . . . to every human being . . . Namely: our history and
prehistory, viewed logologically, from the standpoint of ‘words about words,’ is the written
and/or unwritten story of a biological organism that is gestated as wordless foetus in a maternal
body, is born wordless, and develops out of its infancy (that is, its state of wordlessness) while
acquiring a verbal medium which, in effect, builds up a set of duplicates for its nonverbal
environment.[85}
This concept emphasizes the intrinsic interrelationship between human language and bodies that
communicate. As a consequence of language’s bodily contingency, the various symbolic
manifestations of language, including rhetoric and technology, are also dependent on human
physiology.
Owing to Burke’s emphasis on the body, recent scholarship has explored the physiological
contingency of rhetoric and “words about words. In “Burke on Drugs,” Debra Hawhee argues
that Burke’s experience ghost writing an anti-drug book for the Bureau of Social Hygeine led
Burke to develop, “a heightened interest in the body’s role in rhetoric and identity
production.”[86] Since Burke emphasized the physiological contingency of logology, such
examinations of body rhetoric are warranted. In another examination of Burke’s embodied
rhetoric, “Rhetoric, Cybernetics, and the Work of the Body,” Jeff Pruchnic posits that
technological rhetoric is a plausible extension of Burke’s theory of language. Pruchnic wrote,
“Rhetoric emerges not only as a technology for persuading others but also as a technology of the
-18-
self used by rhetors to discipline and transform their own habits of response.”[87] As Pruchnic
suggests, the physiological embodiment of rhetoric comprises just one possible embodiment of
his rhetorical theory. The intertwining of humanity’s symbol use with its technology use entails
that rhetorical embodiment is also logologically technological. Burke noted the technological
embodiment of Counter-Nature in “Motion, Action, Words.” He wrote of the technological
transformation of rationality that, “Before technology was developed, the course of human
rationality was straining in this direction, guided towards it as towards a beacon. But now that so
many of its ideal possibilities have been embodied in material instruments, the promises that
originally infused such rationality have become transformed into problems.”[88] Technological
materialization embodies the terminological thrust of human inventiveness, and it serves as a
rational justification for additional technological behavior.Technology therefore motivates future
technological production. Thus, in the logological framework, human physiology shares with
technology a potential to be transformed by symbolic action.
Technology is not only altered by symbolic action, however. Burke argued that technologies, as
a form of symbolic action, are also characterized by their world-making function. Burke wrote
that technological pre-destiny and “bureaucratization” are “implicit in my provisional
Logological schematizing with regard to the destiny of the relation between language and
Technology, due to Technology’s radical role in generating a realm of Counter-Nature.”[89]
Technology thus possesses a creative force that motivates human behavior by determining, in
part, the scene in which humans act.
Logology further stresses the inseparability of technological artifacts and their terms in Burke’s
rhetorical framework. As terminologies are deployed for persuasive effect, so too are
technologies. Burke argued that because “humanity developed” in a “nonhuman ‘context of
situation,’ does not mean that technology is all powerful. Technological ideas and terms “are not
merely ‘derived’ from material conditions; they are positively ‘creative’ of material
conditions.”[90] As a type of symbolic action, the invention of technologies calls for specific
behaviors. In “Variations on ‘Providence,’” an essay that Burke uses to explore the relationship
of the term “Technology” to Logology, he emphasized that technologies have a rhetorical
character. He wrote, “I would stress the fact that the state of technology itself provides the
conditions which open up avenues of ‘pure’ speculation. Instruments and methods are like
images, in suggesting new sets of implications.”[91] Therefore the societal role of technology is
not mere instrumentation. In addition to technology’s functionality, technology embodies the
force to persuade new conceptions of the world.
Thus, Logology, or Burke’s theory of words about words, explicates Burke’s rhetorical
philosophy of technology, and his proposed method of correcting the problems derived from Big
Technology. Logology necessitates a comprehensive confrontation with the primary threats to
human survival – dangerous technologies – in order to invent effective symbolic actions. As a
result of the contingency of rhetoric on technological behavior, the potentially transformative
function of both rhetoric and technology intermingle to either correct our technological problems
or facilitate our probable doom. In contrast to competing philosophies of technology that
advocate a political, aesthetic, or instrumental solution to technological ills, Burke conception
-19-
incorporates all of these perspectives, and any other perspective rooted in human interaction,
owing to its comprehensive interrelationship with words, and therefore rhetoric. If technology
changes, such transformation will only be motivated by persuading people to action with
symbolism, a condition of change necessary to all realms of human behavior. By presuming the
overall need for a transformative corrective, Burke did not isolate any one domain of technology
or aesthetic as central to this radical change, because he called for widespread changes in all
human behavior, not just technology.[92] Burke thus inhabits a view of technology that
advocates a programmatic, overarching cultural change that transforms technological thought,
language, and practice, in addition to all culture and all society, through symbolic means.
Ian Hill is a doctoral student in the Department of Communication at the University of Illinois
Notes
1. Kenneth Burke and Malcolm Cowley, (1988). The Selected Correspondence of Kenneth
Burke and Malcolm Cowley: 1915-1981. Edited by Paul Jay. New York: Viking, 273274.
2. Burke did not hide his feelings about technology. In a later letter to Malcolm Cowley
from early 1952, Burke griped about the interest in technology his son displayed, calling
him the “perfect son of an anti-technological pap!” Selected Correspondence, 303.
3. Burke (1966) often used the term “Big Technology by the time he published “Definition
of Man.” In addition to defining humans as “separated from [their] natural condition by
instruments of [their] own making,” they are symbol using, inventers of “the negative,”
“goaded by a sense of hierarchy, and “rotten with perfection.” “Definition of Man.”
Language as Symbolic Action: Essays on Life, Literature, and Method. Berkeley:
University of California Press, 13 and 19-20.
4. Kenneth Burke, (1985). “In Haste,” Pre/Text. 6.3-4: 338, and Kenneth Burke, (1984).
Attitudes Toward History. 3rd edition. Berkeley: University of California Press, 357.
5. In the third chapter of Made to Break: Technology and Obsolescence in America, Giles
Slade (2006) documented the increasing prevalence of planned obsolescence as it became
a normative business strategy in the late 1920s and early 1930s. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
6. Kenneth Burke, (1968). Counter-Statement. Berkeley: University of California Press, 31.
7. Kenneth Burke, (1972).; Dramatism and Development. Barre, MA: Clark University
Press, 17.
8. Kenneth Burke, (1978). “(Nonsymbolic) Motion/(Symbolic) Action.” Critical Inquiry.
4.4: 809.
9. Burke and Cowley, Selected Correspondence, 198.
10. Burke, Counter-Statement, 107. Edmund Russell, in War and Nature: Fighting Humans
and Insects with Chemicals from World War I to Silent Spring (2001), demonstrated that
the equating of human and insect extermination was a common metaphor used by the
chemical industry as it attempted to justify the peacetime production of military
chemicals. New York: Cambridge University Press.
11. Burke and Cowley, Selected Correspondence, 384.
-20-
12. Kenneth Burke, (1969). A Rhetoric of Motives. Berkeley: University of California Press,
23.
13. Kenneth Burke, (1969). A Grammar of Motives, Berkeley: University of California Press,
90. In his “Dramatism” essay, when commenting on the Scene-Act ratio, Burke made a
similar claim: “In the selection of terms for describing a scene, one automatically
prescribes the range of acts that will seem reasonable, implicit, or necessary in that
situation” (450).
14. Burke, A Rhetoric of Motives, 19 and 23.
15. How aware Burke was of the science fiction movement is difficult to judge, given his
predominant interest in more scholarly literature, but he definitely had some awareness of
the genre. In A Rhetoric of Motives Burke writes a brief passage about “science mystery
fiction” (212), and in a letter to Malcolm Cowley written on the day of the Nagasaki
bombing, Burke laments about the suddenly non-fictional “era of the Mad Scientist of the
B movie” (268). The clearest example that Burke knew science fiction comes from his
Helhaven essay. The essay combined a short analysis of satire with a modest proposal
that borrowed from stereotypical science fiction plot lines and imagery. “Helhaven, the
greatest apocalyptic project this side of Mars,” described a bubble community on the
moon built to escape the ecological ravages of technological progress on the home planet.
Kenneth Burke, (1971). “Towards Helhaven: Three Stages of a Vision.” The Sewanee
Review. 79.1: 20. The Helhaven essay mirrored the satirical enterprise of “Waste—The
Future of Prosperity.” When Burke reprised the Helhaven satire, he made the
understatement: “I am not good at science fiction.” Kenneth Burke, (1974). “Why Satire,
With a Plan for Writing One.” Michigan Quarterly Review. 13.4: 320.
16. Jacques Ellul, (1964). The Technological Society. Translated by John Wilkinson. New
York: Vintage, xxv-xxvi, emphasis his.
17. Kenneth Burke, (1973). “Semantic and Poetic Meaning.” The Philosophy of Literary
Form: Studies in Symbolic Action, 3rd ed. Berkeley: University of California Press, 138.
18. Burke, “In Haste,” 353.
19. Mike Hübler, (2005). “The Drama of a Technological Society.” K .B. Journal. 1.2:
<2005http://kbjournal.org/>.
20. Burke, Attitudes Toward History, 357.
21. Kenneth Burke, (1966). “Medium as ‘Message’: Some thoughts on Marshall McLuhan’s
Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man (and, secondarily, on The Gutenberg
Galaxy).” Language as Symbolic Action: Essays on Life, Literature, and Method.
Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 410.
22. Burke enumerated these in A Rhetoric of Motives, 298-301. Such a multitude of
terminologies that determined technology practice and that technology practice
determined led Burke to posit in his essay on “Dramatism” that, depending on a critic’s
perspective, “an agent’s behavior might be thought of as taking place against a
polytheistic background; or the over-all scene may be thought of as grounded in one god;
or the circumference of the situation.” Kenneth Burke, (1968). “Interaction: Dramatism.”
The International Journal of the Social Sciences. Edited by David L. Sills. New York:
Macmillan and The Free Press, 446.
-21-
23. Kenneth Burke, (1973). “The Rhetorical Situation.” Communication: Ethical and Moral
Issues. Edited by Lee Thayer. New York: Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, 263
and 270.
24. Burke, A Rhetoric of Motives, 43.
25. In “Variations on ‘Providence,’” Burke defined “counter-nature” as “the resources made
possible by the anthropomorphizing genius of technology.” He grounded his concept of
Logology in “Counter-Nature,” or “‘Fulfillment’ via Technology.” Kenneth Burke,
(1981). “Variations on ‘Providence,’” Notre Dame English Journal. 13.3: 167 and 181183.
26. Kenneth Burke, (1974). The Philosophy of Literary Form: Studies in Symbolic Action,
3rd edition. Berkeley: University of California Press, 20. In this essay, Burke also stated
the importance of judging an author’s output and motivations only after the writer had
completed his work (20).
27. Burke and Cowley, Selected Correspondence, 249. Other examples of Burke’s linkage of
the role of critics and the problems of technology include his afterword to Permanence
and Change, in which Burke rewrote the book’s original final sentences to read: “The
unending assignment will be to consider in detail the range of transformations (with
corresponding transvaluations) involved in the turn from an ‘early’ mythic orientation . . .
to our ‘perfect’ secular fulfillment in the empirical realm of symbol-guided Technology’s
Counter-Nature.” Burke further clarified the intertwined importance of language and
technology in “Variations on ‘Providence’” where the main argumentative thrust that
outlined his concept of Logology also called for providential ecological-technological
management, necessitated by human language and bodies’ physical, elementary
connections to ecological conditions.
28. Burke and Cowley, Selected Correspondence, 268.
29. Burke, “Why Satire,” 314.
30. Burke, “Definition of Man,” 21, and “Why Satire,” 311 and 323.
31. Burke, “Why Satire,” 333.
32. Burke, “Definition of Man,” 16, emphasis his.
33. Burke, A Rhetoric of Motives, 285. Burke argued that “you can expect ‘pure persuasion’
always to be on the verge of being lost, even as it is on the verge of being found.” The
“Pure Persuasion” chapter of A Rhetoric of Motives linked the imperfect endeavors of
innovating perfect technology and perfect rhetoric. Burke noted that the line between
technology and language in modern technology “becomes quite obscured” (289).
34. See Aristotle, (2001). “De Anima (On the Soul).” Translated by J. A. Smith. The Basic
Works of Aristotle. Edited by Richard McKeon. 555-556 (II.412a-b).
35. Philoponus’s commentary on Aristotle’s On the Soul (2005) indicated that Aristotle
referred to individual perfection, such as a steersman’s, rather than Burkian global
perfection. Philoponus said of the term’s etymology and definition that Aristotle “finds
that the soule is asubstance in the way of form, which form he calls ‘actuality’
[entelekheia], taking the world from ‘one [hen], ‘perfect’ [teleion] and ‘holding together’
[sunekhein]; for the form is the cause of being one for the matter, and of being perfect,
since it both is the perfection of the subject and holds it together. So here he gives the
definition of soul, saying it is ‘actuality’, that is, form and perfection.” Further,
-22-
Philoponus argued that this perfected form existed as an end, not as a potential
materialization. On Aristotle’s “On the Soul 2.1-6.” Translated by William Charlton.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 8 and 11.
36. Burke, Dramatism and Development, 32.
37. Burke, Attitudes Toward History, 229. Burke also said of entelechy in “Why Satire, With
a Plan for Writing One,” that, “Aristotle applied the term in a quite broad sense.” Burke
“would settle for less” (314). Burke’s amplification of entelechy has some basis in
Aristotle’s text, because Aristotle noted that everything knowable and sensible becomes
actualized in the soul. Aristotle wrote, “Let us now surmise our results about soul, and
repeat that the soul is in a way all things; for existing things are either sensible or
thinkable, and knowledge is in a way what is knowable, and sensation is in a way what is
sensible: in what way we must inquire” (595 (III.431.b).
38. Kenneth Burke, (1966). “Goethe’s Faust, Part I.” Language as Symbolic Action: Essays
on Life, Literature, and Method. Berkeley: University of California Press, 155.
39. Kenneth Burke, (1984). Permanence and Change: An Anatomy of Purpose, 3rd ed.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 7, 36, 44-49, and 242-243.
40. Burke, “Definition of Man,” 19. Also compare Burke, (1960.) “Motion, Action, Words.”
Teachers College Record. 62: 245. Burke wrote in this essay that, “There is no essential
difference between the tracking down of implications in the writing of a novel and the
tracking down of implications in the perfecting of a device that might obliterate all
mankind.”
41. Burke, “In Haste,” 362, emphasis his.
42. Langdon Winner, (1977). Autonomous Technology: Technics-Out-of-Control as a Theme
in Political Thought. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 225 and 231. Further, according to
Winner, “the totalism of technological rule becomes more than evident,” even though the
technology practices of engineers, bureaucrats, and manufacturers operated without
public scrutiny.
43. Burke, “Dramatism,” 451.
44. Burke, “Variations on ‘Providence,’” 165.
45. Burke, “Variations on ‘Providence,’” 171.
46. According to Burke’s “The Vegetal Radicalism of Theodore Roethke” (1966), architects
and engineers would just as likely identify their successfully completed technological
project by pointing to a bridge as they would by talking about a bridge. “A bridge builder,
no matter how special his language, has successfully ‘communicated’ with his fellows
when he has built them a good bridge.” “In this respect, the languages of the
technological specialties confront a different communicative problem than marks the
language of the specialist in verse.” Language as Symbolic Action: Essays on Life,
Literature, and Method. Berkeley: University of California Press, 261.
47. Kenneth Burke, (1966). “Terministic Screens,” Language as Symbolic Action: Essays on
Life, Literature, and Method. Berkeley: University of California Press, 45-46, emphasis
his.
48. Jeff Pruchnic (2006) also made a connection between Burke and cybernetics, including
Wiener in “Rhetoric, Cybernetics, and the Work of the Body in Burke’s Body of Work.”
Pruchnic examined form, affect, and transformation in Burke’s early writings to
-23-
demonstrate how rhetoric folds into both biological and technological matter. Rhetoric
Review. 25.3: 297-315.
49. Norbert Wiener, (1954). The Human Use of Human Beings: Cybernetics and Society, 2nd
revised edition. New York: Doubleday, 26.
50. Wiener, Human Use of Human Beings, 31-32.
51. Burke, “Mind, Body, and the Unconscious,” Language as Symbolic Action: Essays on
Life, Literature, and Method. Berkeley: University of California Press, 64. In a similar
passage Burke wrote, “The machine is so thoroughly human that it is even the caricature
of a human being. It has the efficiency of political cartoons, which over-emphasize some
traits of their subjects while under-emphasizing others.” Kenneth Burke, (1962).
“Motion, Action, Words.” Teachers College Record. 60: 245.
52. Burke, Permanence and Change, 261, emphasis his.
53. Burke, Attitudes Toward History, 308.
54. Burke, Counter-Statement, ix.
55. Star A Muir, (1999). “Toward an Ecology of Language.” Kenneth Burke and the 21st
Century. Edited by Bernard L. Brock. Albany: SUNY Press, 64.
56. William H. Rueckert (1994). “Some of the many Kenneth Burkes.” Encounters with
Kenneth Burke. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 11. Also see Muir, “Toward and
Ecology of Language,” 64.
57. Pruchnic, “Rhetoric, Cybernetics, and the Work of the Body,” 275-276 and 291.
58. In this passage, Burke seemed to used ‘operationalism’ and ‘technologism’ as synonyms
for the attitude he elsewhere called ‘instrumentalism.’
59. Burke, A Grammar of Motives, 54-55. Burke (1943) also used the same lines to conclude
his previously published essay, “The Tactics of Motivation.” Chimera 2: 53.
60. Kenneth Burke, (1978). “Critical Response: Methodological Repression and/or Strategies
of Containment.” Critical Inquiry 5.2: 409.
61. Friedrich Nietzsche, (2000). “Ecce Homo.” Basic Writings of Nietzsche. Translated and
edited by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Modern Library, 782-783.
62. See Burke, Permanence and Change, 87 and 308-309.
63. Kenneth Burke, (1973). “War, Response, and Contradiction.” The Philosophy of Literary
Form: Studies in Symbolic Action, 3rd ed. Berkeley: University of California Press, 235.
64. Burke, Counter-Statement, 105.
65. Burke, Counter-Statement,110-111.
66. In the final section of Permanence and Change added to the second edition, Burke stated
regarding “resignation” that, “we believe that in many respects it is the historical point of
view which leads to such surrender on the grounds that one must adjust himself to the
temporal conditions as he finds them (teaching himself, for instance, to accept more and
more mechanization simply because history points in this direction” (271). In A
Grammar of Motives, Burke defined dissipation as “the isolationist tendency to
surrender” (318).
67. Kenneth Burke, (1989). “Revolutionary Symbolism in America: Speech by Kenneth
Burke to American Writers’ Congress, April 26, 1935.” The Legacy of Kenneth Burke.
Edited by Herbert W. Simmons and Trevor Melia. Madison: University of Wisconsin
Press, 271-272, emphasis his.
-24-
68. Albert Borgmann argued that “technology is the most important topic of Heidegger’s
thought,” and that “The technological culture is for Heidegger the decisive environment
of humans in the late modern era, and their most fundamental welfare depends on their
ability to pass through technology into another kind of world” (420).
69. In one of his few mentions of Heidegger that appeared at start of “Variations on
Providence,” Burke categorized Heidegger’s existentialism as a variety of historicism
that considered people “nothing but the products of the particular age in which we happen
to live (or, as Heidegger puts it, to be ‘thrown’)” (155).
70. Martin Heidegger, (1977). The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.
Translated by William Lovitt. New York: Harper & Row, 28, 32, and 35.
71. Heidegger, “The Question,” 12-14 and 17.
72. Martin Heidegger, (1991). “Only a God Can Save Us: Der Spiegel’s Interview with
Martin Heidegger.” Translated by Maria P. Alter and John D. Caputo. The Heidegger
Controversy: A Critical Reader. Edited by Richard Wolin. New York: Columbia
University Press.
73. Burke, Permanence and Change, 111-113.
74. See William H. Rueckert’s essay (1994) “Kenneth Burke’s Encounters with Walt
Whitman” for an analysis of the Helhaven satire as it appeared in various guises in the
early 1970s. Encounters with Kenneth Burke. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 185221.
75. Burke, “Why Satire,” 311-313.
76. Burke, “Towards Helhaven,” 20.
77. Burke called “Waste” a “rudimentary version of my [Helhaven] satire” in “Why Satire,”
308.
78. Burke, “Why Satire,” 314-315.
79. Burke, “In Haste,” 358.
80. Burke, A Rhetoric of Motives, 333.
81. In “Definition of Man,” Burke noted that defining language as a tool does not convey the
full range of symbolic action. He countered, “Language is a species of action, symbolic
action—and its nature is such that it can be used as a tool” (15).
82. For Burke’s explanation of rhetorical action, see A Rhetoric of Motives, 43-46.
83. This assertion mirrors Burke’s appraisal of his tripartite arrangement of Permanence and
Change. He wrote, “orientation is to formation as disorientation is to de-formation as to
re-orientation is to re-formation” (308).
84. Burke, “Methodological Repression,” 414, emphasis his.
85. Burke, “Variations on ‘Providence,’” 156, emphasis his.
86. Debra Hawhee, (2004). “Burke on Drugs.” Rhetoric Society Quarterly 34.1: 7.
87. Pruchnic, “Rhetoric, Cybernetics, and the Work of the Body,” 294.
88. Burke, “Motion, Action, Words,” 248, emphasis altered.
89. Burke, “Variations on ‘Providence,’” 180-181. In the afterword to Attitudes Toward
History, Burke further characterized the relationship between logology and technology as
one in which “Technology” becomes imbued with a world-making function. He wrote:
-25-
[T]he Logological view of this situation is that no political order has yet been envisaged,
even on paper, adequate to control the instrumental powers of Technology. Even if you
granted, for the sake of argument, that (“come the Revolution”) the utopia of a classless
society becomes transformed from an ideality to a reality, there would remain the evermounting purely instrumental problems intrinsic to the realm of Counter-Nature as
“progressively” developed by the symbol-guided “creativity” of technological prowess
itself (424-425, emphasis his).
90. Burke, “Methodological Repression,” 414.
91. Burke, “Variations on ‘Providence,’” 167.
92. Technology historian Arnold Pacey (1983) advanced a similar argument that any solution
to technological problems must have widespread cultural and societal import. In The
Culture of Technology, he wrote: “In the philosophers’ jargon, it might be seen as the
adoption of a new paradigm – a new pattern for organizing ideas.” Furthermore, “the
world view we use in deciding what kinds of technique to use is a view which must
include perspectives on human organization and their international context as well as
specific concepts of technology.” The Culture of Technology. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 169 and 175.
“The Human Barnyard” and Kenneth Burke’s Philosophy of Technology by Ian Hill is licensed
under a Creative Commons Attribution-No Derivative Works 3.0. Based on a work at
www.kbjournal.org.
-26-