Human Dignity in Italy
Paolo Becchi
Contents
1 Introduction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2 The Use of the Concept of Dignity in the Constitution and Legislation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.1 Dignity in the Constitution . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
2.2 Dignity in Legislation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3 Use of the Concept of Dignity in Constitutional and Ordinary Jurisdictions . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3.1 Dignity in Constitutional Jurisdiction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
3.2 Dignity in Ordinary Jurisdiction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
4 Conclusions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
5 Cross-References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
454
454
454
458
462
462
463
466
468
468
Abstract
This contribution analyses how the principle of human dignity is defined in the
Italian Constitution and case law of the Constitutional Court. In this context, it is
noteworthy that the Italian Constitution heavily focuses on the social dimension
of human dignity. However, the developments in legislation and case law have let
the concept of human dignity in Italy become more and more complex. It is used
in different situations – for the right of the worker to receive a salary and for the
fight against euthanasia as well. This discrepancy has resulted in a lively debate in
Italy.
Keywords
Introduction of human dignity · Historical and conceptual reconstruction ·
Ancient roman world · Christianity · Universalist dimension · Enlightenment ·
P. Becchi (*)
Faculty of Law, University of Genoa, Genoa, Italy
e-mail: paolo.becchi@unige.it
# Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019
P. Becchi, K. Mathis (eds.), Handbook of Human Dignity in Europe,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-28082-0_20
453
454
P. Becchi
Post-war debate · New approaches · New meanings · Conventions and charters ·
Autonomy and its limits · Medical ethics · Euthanasia · Pre-natal human life
1
Introduction
Surely one of the first issues to strike non-native legal scholars as they approach an
analysis of the Italian legal order is the employment of the concept of dignity as it is
framed in the Constitution. Put into force on 1 January 1948, and thus prior to the
adoption of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, the Constitution makes
explicit reference to the concept of dignity three times: Art. 3, § 1 states that all
citizens have “equal social dignity” (“pari dignità sociale”); Art. 36, § 1 establishes
the right of all workers to remuneration that guarantees “a free and dignified
existence” (“un’esistenza libera e dignitosa”) for themselves and their families;
while Art. 4, § 2 stipulates that private economic activity cannot be conducted in a
way that might “jeopardize human safety, freedom and dignity” (“in modo da recar
danno alla sicurezza, alla libertà, alla dignità umana”). This chapter first analyses
the use of the concept of dignity in the Constitution and legislation in Italy (1). Then
it establishes how Italian courts handle the concept of human dignity at both the
constitutional and lower court levels (2). Finally, a conclusion is drawn (3).
2
The Use of the Concept of Dignity in the Constitution
and Legislation
2.1
Dignity in the Constitution
Whilst the German concept of dignity is generally understood in an abstract and
general manner, as if it were a latent human capacity, there is barely any sense of this
notion in the constitutional provisions just cited (for a comparison of the Italian and
German Constitutions – with a particular focus on the question of dignity – see
Becchi (2008) and, more extensively, Becchi (2012a)). The Italian Republic was not
founded on the recognition of an absolute and unconditional principle such as human
dignity, but rather “on labour”, as Art. 1 of the Constitution provides (“L’Italia è una
Repubblica democratica, fondata sul lavoro”). Thus, the subject which is explicitly
associated with the concept of dignity is not the human being in its essence but rather
in its quality as citizen and employee or employer. Even in Art. 41, where explicit
reference is – uniquely – made to “human dignity”, the concept relates to the sphere
of economic activities, which may not exert a degrading or humiliating effect upon
the workers responsible for their execution.
Particular attention ought to be drawn to the formulation “equal social dignity”,
which to my knowledge is not to be found in any other constitution. As was noted in
one of the few extant essays dedicated to a consideration of the term, it “unambiguously refers not to an absolute, but rather a relative concept” (see Ferrara (1974); the
Human Dignity in Italy
455
same interpretational approach, adapted to the modern context of the welfare crisis,
can be found in Marella (2007); see further Grossi (2008); the issue is also addressed
in Vincenti (2009)). In contrast to Art. 1 of the German Grundgesetz (Basic Law),
which was created almost contemporaneously, there is no glimpse here of an
absolute and unconditional, extra positive principle; rather one finds a provision of
positive law that explicitly benefits the general citizenry as a whole.
Even if the three articles of the Italian Constitution which draw on the term
“dignity” do refer to three distinct groups of persons (general citizenry, employees,
employers), the emphasis rests on the social dimension of the concept. In the first
case, this is revealed by the fact that the principle of the general equality of all
citizens also entails the discontinuation of any and all privileges which may previously have arisen from noble titles or from affiliation to a particular social class.
Following the abolition of noble privilege, individual labour (here understood in the
broadest sense of any productive effort) – as a contribution to the development of
society – represents the only point upon which the Italian Constitution refers to
dignity. Formal equality “before the law” is augmented by social equality. Art. 3, §
2 expresses this in its provision for the participation of all citizens – particularly
those whose personal circumstances might otherwise inhibit it – in public life:
“Dignity” is thus not something which is gifted by nature and requires protection,
but rather a concept which must be fostered and formed, namely via the removal of
all obstacles which “prevent the full development of the human personality and the
effective participation by all workers in the political, economic and social organization of the country” (Art. 3, § 2).
In the two other cases, this socially connoted concept of dignity demands that the
employee and his family be guaranteed a minimum material standard of living (Art.
36) and stipulates that the actions of the employer, while free, may not adversely
affect the dignity of the jobholder. Labour must permit the employee to enjoy a
dignified lifestyle (Art. 41). At the same time, dignified working conditions must
also be provided.
It ought to be noted that the Italian Constitution also recognizes the “inviolable
human rights” which accrue from mere existence as a human being and which thus
claim validity not only in the context of the social framework in which the
personality develops, but also in the context of existence as an individual person.
That said, however, there is no trace of an origination of human rights derived
from the moral sources of human dignity. While the concept of dignity is
traditionally associated with the adjective “human”, the Italian Constitution,
inasmuch as it deploys in this context the two adjectives “equal” and “social”,
follows a different approach.
There is a close correlation between the three articles of the Constitution which
refer to dignity in the sense that each of them is founded on the concept of work (see
Cataudella (1989) and, more recently, Politi (2011a, b)), explicitly in the case of Art.
36, § 1 and Art. 41, § 2, implicitly in that of Art. 3, § 1. The former two ought to be
read in conjunction with Art. 2099 ff. and 2087 of the Italian Civil Code, which state
that working conditions must “guarantee the physical and psychological integrity of
the worker”.
456
P. Becchi
Art. 3, § 1, which recognizes the equal dignity of all citizens, can also be related to
work – whether it be with respect to Art. 3, § 2 and the guarantee of the effective
participation of all workers in the organization of the country contained therein, or
with regard to Art. 4, § 1, which posits the “right to work” (“The Republic recognizes
the right of all citizens to work and promotes those conditions which render this right
effective”). Art. 4, § 2, meanwhile, establishes the duty of the citizen “to carry out an
activity which contributes to the material or spiritual progress of society according to
one’s personal aptitude and individual choice”.
The leading idea here is that the individual can only achieve full development of
his or her personality – and, by extension, dignity – via labour. Dignity is linked to
both the duty of the citizen to social involvement and to the demand that the state
must provide for all the opportunity to enact such engagement in a dignified fashion.
Much as labour is a right as well as a duty, dignity is something which must be
earned through the citizen’s contribution to society.
In one specific regard, dignity is even a condition for the exercise of an important
civil right: Art. 48, § 3 provides that the right to vote can be restricted in “cases of
moral ‘undignity’ established by law” (“casi di indegnità morale indicati dalla
legge”) (Grossi 2008). The loss of active voting rights is foreseen in other legal
orders, probably only in Italy, however, on the grounds of “moral indignity”. The
Italian legal order does not, in any event, automatically confer dignity upon every
individual, but rather expects it from each citizen, to the extent that, should it not be
forthcoming, he or she loses the active right to vote.
What circumstances, then, could lead to a loss of voting rights? In principle, legal
sanctions might, for instance – in accordance with the Constitution – be brought against
persons who do not exercise their right to vote without due justification or even against
those who do not perform their duty to contribute to the progress of society (Art. 4, § 2)
sufficiently (e.g. Mortati 1991). Such laws have not yet been established. It would have
been possible, meanwhile, to deny, on the grounds of the Twelfth Transitional Provision
of the Constitution, voting rights to the “responsible leaders of the fascist regime,” much
as was the case with brothel owners, gambling operators and bankrupt business owners.
Since the brothels and their operations have been outlawed, the two remaining possible
cases of “moral indignity” no longer lead to the loss of voting rights (see the legal
revisions of 16 January 1992, No. 15 and 9 January 2006, No. 5, Art. 52).
While “indignity” thus no longer plays a role in voting rights, it does nonetheless
come into play in other contexts: most recently in the case in which the president, in
the course of the Parmalat scandal, revoked Calisto Tanzi’s title of “Cavaliere”
(Order of Merit of the Italian Republic) by decree (D.P.R. – Decreto del Presidente
della Repubblica of 17 September 2010 in Gazzetta Ufficiale, Serie Generale,
No. 223 of 23 September 2010) – which had been granted to him in 1984.
On this point let just the following final comments be made. There may be cases
in which the restriction of voting rights is justified. Explicit reference to “moral
indignity” is in this regard an idiosyncrasy of the Italian Constitution. Significant for
the purposes of our discussion here is the consideration that dignity does not emerge
as something to be protected or fostered by the state, but rather as a civic duty whose
non-observance is sanctioned.
Human Dignity in Italy
457
Viewed in this context, the constitutional provision of Art. 22, according to which
“[n]o person may be deprived of legal capacity, citizenship, or name for political
reasons”, appears to be worded in an unfortunate way. On the one hand, the
provision creates a clear limit: the sanctioning of political convictions. On the
other hand, a literal interpretation could lead to the conclusion that the revocation
of one of the listed statutory laws on other grounds – namely for reasons of “moral
indignity” – would not amount to a violation of personal dignity, at least not in the
context of its formulation in the Constitution. This provides further evidence that the
Italian Constitution does not unconditionally attribute dignity to every person, to the
extent that even the gravest criminal offender cannot forfeit it. Even if the Constitution deploys the concept of dignity in various ways, it appears at all times as
something that the citizen can both acquire and lose, depending upon his or her
social conduct. In my opinion, Paolo Ridola gets to the crux of the matter when he
writes that, in the Italian Constitution, “the reference to dignity is striking in that it
connects to concrete living conditions (see ‘social dignity’ in Art. 3, § 1). Thus
dignity has here neither the same cultural anchoring nor the same almost universal
validity that Menschenwürde has in the German Basic Law. It cannot content itself
with the allocation of rights as it is committed to an ‘image of man’, the social
conditioning of which it cannot renounce” (Ridola 2006, p. 128).
It should be made clear at this juncture that I do not mean to draw from the
preceding discussion the conclusion that the Italian Constitution offers no latitude
for a wider use of the concept of dignity. What cannot be denied, however, is that
the word “dignity” does not explicitly appear in any further-reaching context.
Witness, for example, Art. 13 on personal liberty, the fourth paragraph of which
prohibits “any act of physical and psychological violence against persons whose
freedom is subjected to state restrictions”. The reference to dignity is also implicit
in Art. 27, § 3, which – first negatively – affirms, that punishments “may not
contradict humanity” and – then positively – holds that they “must aim at the
(social) re-education of the convicted” (on this point see Ruotolo (2002, 2005,
2011)). Thus, in the context of the criminal law protection of human rights, the
principle that no convicted person may be treated in a degrading or humiliating
fashion is recognized. At the same time, however, the social dimension holding
that the purpose of the punishment is to further the social reintegration of the
convicted is also reinforced. In light of all this, it comes as little surprise to note
that even Art. 32, § 2 – an article which today stands at the centre of numerous
bioethical debates – one need only think here of the Welby and Englaro cases (see
infra) – and affirms that “nobody may be forcefully submitted to medical treatment
except as regulated by law” (and that the latter “may in no case violate the limits
imposed by respect for the human being”) – does not make explicit reference to the
concept of dignity (for the beginning of life, see Marzocco (2018)).
It is true that in the constitutional draft of the “Commission of 75” an Art. 26 was
foreseen whose § 2 sought to prohibit “medical treatments, which violate human
dignity”. That this formulation was not ultimately taken up in the Constitution
provides further evidence of how the stress lay less on human dignity and more on
social dignity.
458
P. Becchi
It is hardly astounding, therefore, that the Italian Constitutional Court, in the first
year following the entry into force of the Constitution, made only “extremely careful
and restrained” use of the concept of dignity (for an in-depth discussion see Ruggeri
and Spadaro (1991) and, more recently, Gambini (2005) and Pirozzoli (2007,
pp. 103–137) (there one finds the most extensive overview of constitutional jurisdiction); see further Di Ciommo (2010, pp. 158–175), and Monaco (2010)). And if
the administrative jurisdiction has made more frequent reference to dignity, it is the
dignity of the worker which represents far and away the most common example in
relevant judgements (for a more detailed analysis see Alpa (1997) and, further,
Cataudella (1989) and Gambini (2005)).
A more extensive analysis of the text of the Constitution would necessarily entail
close engagement with the individual provisions. Such an enquiry cannot and will
not be provided in the context of the present discussion. More important here is the
following observation: that explicit use of the term “dignity” in the Italian Constitution is limited to its social dimension – that is to say, to a notion of dignity which
presupposes the fundamental equality of all citizens. Further, there exists a second
mode of usage, whereby “dignity” is understood as an extra positive principle, albeit
only implicitly. The somewhat peculiar sounding phrasing “equal social dignity”
used by the constitutional legislator has not – the few noted examples excepted –
found much traction in the doctrine. Evidence in support of this can be gleaned from
the two monographs that address the issue of dignity in the constitutional context, in
which the term “equal social dignity” appears only cursorily (see Bartolomei (1987,
pp. 20–21), and Pirozzoli (2007, pp. 125–126)). In Fabrizio Politi’s recent volume,
one also finds only laconic comments such as “the discussion regarding the question
of whether social dignity might be equated to human dignity tout-court is ongoing”
(Politi 2011a, p. 151). A glance at the mainstream constitutional commentaries (the
most important of these are listed under the short entry for “pari dignità sociale” in
the Commentario alla Costituzione; see Celotto (2006)) and legal lexika suffices to
uphold this assessment. Only the Enciclopedia giuridica Treccani includes an entry
on dignity; even there the reference is, however, restricted to the dignity of the
worker (Cataudella 1989). Interest in the subject is, however, on the rise, as the
entries on “dignity” in the Trattato di Biodiritto (see Resta (2010), which provides
the best extant Italian language overview of bioethics, and Resta (2014)) and in the
recently published fourth volume of the Enciclopedia di Bioetica e di Scienza
Giuridica (Mastro Pietro et al. 2012) indicate. Notably, the meaning of the concept
of dignity now stands at the centre of numerous discussions within the field of
bioethics, whether it be in relation to the beginning (artificial conception) or end
(termination of treatment, euthanasia) of life. We shall return to this point in fuller
detail later.
2.2
Dignity in Legislation
Prior to considering more closely certain interesting pronouncements in the jurisdiction, it is appropriate to first cast a glance at ordinary legislation. Although the
Human Dignity in Italy
459
term “dignity” appears neither in the Italian Civil Code nor the Criminal Code, it is
nonetheless used repeatedly in legislation (for a more detailed discussion see Becchi
(2009)). It is against the backdrop of the paramount importance attached to the
person of the worker in the Italian Constitution that one must, for instance, consider
regulation of the position of the worker, enshrined in Law No. 300 of 20 May 1970,
in which reference to dignity is of central significance. Insofar as the legislation
embellishes the protection of the employee with certain control mechanisms (which
remain the responsibility of the employer) concerning both working operations and
personality, he can be seen to implement current constitutional law. In recent years,
this protection has been continually extended – with regard to instances of bullying,
for example (see Decree Law of 11 April 2006, Equality Act), and sexual harassment, which often goes hand in hand with the former and is seen as equally
discriminatory (see in general Ballestrero and De Simone (2003) and, specifically,
Barbera (1992)).
Departing from the person of the worker, the protection of dignity has, moreover,
been extended to other groups whose members also require protection in their
respective living conditions – examples include prisoners, women, the infirm or
disabled, foreign nationals, consumers, even the dead and – further, ever more
specific differentiations – drug addicts and the dying. In contrast to this, no relevant
reference to the concept of dignity in relation to human embryos has found its way
into legislation. The much disputed Law No. 40 from 2004 does not refer directly to
dignity, even though its first article holds that the rights of all affected persons,
“including those of unborn children”, should be protected (noteworthy amongst the
recent literature are the conference reports included in Carusi and Castignone
(2011)). Certain laws do, however, appeal to the concept of dignity, and it is to
those which we shall now turn.
With regard to the treatment of prisoners, for instance, Law No. 354 of 26 July
1975 already implements the constitutional provisions in holding that “penitentiary
treatment must be consistent with the humanity of and must ensure respect of the
dignity of the person” (for additional information, see Gonnella (2014)). Regarding
the protection of women we might recall Law No. 194 from 22 May 1978 on
abortion, in which it is provided that legally mandated treatment must be undertaken
“while protecting the dignity and privacy of the woman” (Art. 5). With regard to the
treatment of the sick, Law No. 833 from 23 December 1978, which established the
“Servizio Sanitario Nazionale” and refers to Art. 32 of the Italian Constitution, can
be seen to be path-breaking in that it holds that even court-ordered medical treatment
must be carried out so as to “protect the dignity of the human person” (Art. 33).
Oriented particularly to the case of drug addicts, the law governed by Presidential
Decree No. 309 of 9 October 1990 (the later modifications brought forth in Law
No. 49/2006 are not relevant to the present discussion) similarly prescribes that
resocialization therapy must be designed so as to “protect the dignity of the human
person”.
The dignity of dying persons is mentioned in the recent, controversial draft law on
“the patient–doctor relationship, patient information and patient decrees”, albeit only
in a declaratory reference: although the law “recognizes and protects the dignity of
460
P. Becchi
all persons and places this above the interests of society and scientific and technological applications”, it nonetheless does not shy away from violating precisely this
sense of dignity in further substantiating articles (e.g. when it is not possible, in the
context of the patient decree, to supply artificial nourishment, or in emergency
situations in which the treatment of a patient can be undertaken without consent,
even in cases where he or she is capable of making a judgement) (see further Becchi
(2011b, 2012c)). In the context of legislation on foreign nationals, Law No. 40 of
6 May 1998 affirms in Art. 12 that in cases where the deportation of sans-papiers is
not possible, “the foreign national is to be accommodated in a transit centre in such a
way as to ensure the availability of medical attention and the protection of his or her
dignity” (this stipulation remains unchanged in the more recent Law No. 125 of
24 July 2008 – with the exception that “transit centre” has now been replaced by
“personal identification and removal centre”). In a presidential decree of 30 March
2001 note is made of the necessity to monitor “the degree of discriminatory
treatment [. . .], which may violate the dignity of the foreign national”. With regard
to persons with disabilities, Framework Law No. 104 of 5 February 1992 on the
assistance, social integration and rights of disabled persons is of particular significance, guaranteeing as it does in Art. 1 “the full protection of human dignity, together
with the rights to freedom and self-determination, of disabled persons”, as well as
support for his or her “complete integration in the family, school, work and society”.
A newer law (Law No. 7 of 9 January 2006) provides for specific protection of
disabled persons from discrimination, here understood as “harassment or unwanted
conduct which relates to the disability and violates the dignity and freedom of the
disabled person, or creates a climate of intimidation, humiliation or animosity
towards him or her” (Art. 2, § 4). In the context of consumer protection, though
the immediately relevant law (Law No. 281 of 30 May 1998) makes no explicit
reference to dignity, the concept does appear in Law No. 39 of 1 March 2002, which
prescribes in Art. 52 a ban on “teleshopping, insofar as it degrades human dignity”
(the Italian text uses the term “vilipendio”). The use of “vilipendio” is striking here –
the term is otherwise only found in Italian legislation with regard to elements of
criminal norms which punish violations against legally protected institutions, artefacts and symbols; the only reference to a “vilipendio” of a person comes in the
context of questions of confession and the exercise of personal faith or in relation to
the desecration of graves. In the previously cited context, the legislation clearly uses
the term in a different sense. As a final point on consumer protection, we might
consider Decree No. 206 of 6 September 2005, which enacted the “Codice del
Consumo”: according to Art. 27 bis, the protection of human dignity must be
safeguarded in the codes of conduct of producer organizations, while Art. 30, §
1 provides that “teleshopping, insofar as it violates human dignity, is prohibited”.
With regard to the deceased, references to dignity appear in several regional laws
which regulate burial and funeral processes and which, in more or less explicit terms,
affirm the necessary protection of the “dignity of the deceased” (e.g. Art. 1 of the
Law of the Umbrian Region of 21 July 2004, No. 12).
One of the – ever more specific – areas in which the protection of dignity has
acquired particular significance is that of membership of non-profit-making
Human Dignity in Italy
461
associations. Art. 2 of Law No. 383 of 7 December 2000, for example, makes
reference to the “dignity of association members”. To underscore this aspect of the
dignity which relates to a person’s role in social entities, we might also consider the
codes of practice of several professional associations, in which the term “dignity” is
used to characterize their own profession. Thus, the concept of dignity, which was
originally applied to the labour force, has been extended to the liberal professions
such as those of journalists, lawyers, doctors and pharmacists.
Until recently, attention was primarily – if not exclusively – paid to the social
dimension of dignity and to the ways in which it might be violated in different social
contexts. Today, however, dignity is also threatened by society at large, specifically
when the latter seeks to rob the individual of the core of his privacy, which ought to
remain protected from the indiscrete glare of the public. Each person not only
has the – positive – claim to be protected in his or her social position but also
a – negative – claim to the protection of that which he or she does not wish to be
disclosed publicly. In this context, dignity is not assigned to the worker, the woman,
the disabled person, but rather to all individuals, each of whom has the right to
protection against an invasion of privacy. In this sense, the concept of confidentiality,
of privacy, represents the flipside of social dignity. The relevant legislation in the
area of data protection (Legal Decree No. 196/2003) takes account of the aforementioned claims. Revealingly, the data protection law did not limit itself to a general
abstract listing of definitions of offences under which the courts ought to subsume
specific cases but rather made provision for the appointment of a data protection
commissioner charged with the task of judging any and all violations of privacy.
Two applicable laws are of particular interest in this context: in the first
(of 9 November 2005) regarding data processing in the health care sector, it is
stipulated that such actions must be undertaken “with total respect for the dignity
of the person in question” and that “the protection of the personal dignity of all
persons who undergo medical treatment must be guaranteed, especially with regard
to vulnerable groups such as those who are physically and psychologically disadvantaged, minors, the elderly and those in need or poverty” (Data Protection
Commissioner, Healthcare Facilities: Respect of Human Dignity, Advisor: Pizzetti).
Thus, although “personal dignity” is granted to all, vulnerable persons receive
special protection in this regard.
The second applicable law pertains to an area which legislation has not yet
regulated in detail: the bugging of private telephone conversations. Following the
repeated publication in the press of transcripts of recorded telephone conversations,
the data protection commissioner issued on 21 June 2006 a decision in which it was
affirmed that the right to freedom of information and the related freedom of the press
exist only insofar as they do not compromise the “total respect of personal dignity”.
Finally, we might also mention here an international legal document: the Convention on the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with
Regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine (Convention on Human Rights
and Biomedicine), which was drafted by the Council of Europe on 19 November
1996 and signed in Oviedo on 4 April 1997. The convention makes repeated
reference to dignity and has also been ratified by the Italian government (Law
462
P. Becchi
No. 145/2001). However, because the convention has not been ratified – as provided
for in Art. 33 – it has yet to enter into force (see further Becchi (2007)).
In summary: ordinary legislation has permitted the emergence of a differentiated
protection of dignity, which has developed in scope from the original social dimension with its notion of material equality, as envisaged in the Constitution, into
entirely new areas. All of this is reflected, as shall be shown in what follows, in
both the constitutional and ordinary jurisdictions.
3
Use of the Concept of Dignity in Constitutional
and Ordinary Jurisdictions
3.1
Dignity in Constitutional Jurisdiction
Within the scope of this chapter, it is not possible to present a fully detailed analysis
of the relevant jurisdiction. For a more in-depth discussion see Ruggeri and Spadaro
(1991) and, more recently, Gambini (2005) and, above all, Pirozzoli (2007,
pp. 103–137), where one will find the most extensive overview of constitutional
jurisdiction. See also Di Ciommo (2010, pp. 158–175), Monaco (2010) and Turco
(2017). Instead, we shall limit ourselves to locating certain fundamental trends.
Firstly, let us consider the case law of the Constitutional Court. Overall, the court
has made careful use of the concept of dignity. Judgement 3 from 1957 attempts to
define “equal social dignity” in the following terms: “Every citizen, irrespective
of all differences in standing and profession – and any corresponding differences
in social conditions – must be granted equal dignity.” The concept of dignity is
thus outlined in a sense in accordance with the Italian Constitutio, which
prohibits all forms of discrimination; at the same time, it is also regarded as a
means of reinforcement and support in relation to the inviolable human rights
protected in Art. 2. Certain – mainly recent – judgements even go so far as to
characterize human dignity as being open to a balancing of interests (e.g. Judgement
No. 196 from 2004).
In comparison, only a few judgements grant dignity an autonomous significance
– whether it be to create the foundation for a new constitutionally protected right or
to delineate a limit which cannot be transgressed, even by other constitutional rights.
In the first of these contexts, the court, in its Judgement No. 37 of February 1985 –
and albeit only for this individual case – drew from the concept of dignity a
“constitutional right to alimony payments”; it characterized the duty to pay alimony
as being “directed towards the protection of existential needs and human dignity”
(Tarantino 2018).
In the second context, the court considered dignity – beyond all trade-offs – as an
absolute boundary value to which all other constitutionally protected rights must
give way. In Judgement No. 293 of July 2000, the Constitutional Court sat in
judgement on the culpability of the mass media publication of real but offensive
pictorial material and footage and recognized in the concept of dignity an impassable
boundary, to which freedom of expression must yield – “the dignity of the person” is,
Human Dignity in Italy
463
according to the finding, “a constitutional value which cuts through all positive law”.
Thus, there exists in the view of the Constitutional Court a “minimum content” of the
respect of the human being which goes beyond the (legitimate) plurality of ethical
attitudes at large in society. This minimum content is located in the principle of
dignity, which emerges, as such, as a key norm of the entire legal order.
The view of dignity as an “inviolable core” or “impassable boundary” also comes
to the fore in certain judgements on medical treatment (e.g. Judgement No. 509 of
13 November 2002, cited in Judgement No. 11 of 2005 and Judgement No. 282 of
19 June 2002). Also relevant in this regard is the recent Judgement No. 151 of 8 May
2009, which – via reference to Art. 3 and Art. 32 of the Italian Constitution –
characterized a provision of the law on artificial procreation as unconstitutional
(albeit without explicit reference to “dignity”).
As already mentioned, the examples of the judgements cited, in which dignity as
such is protected in terms of its autonomous significance, represent specific cases.
More frequently, the concept of dignity is not applied to human persons as such, but
rather to a particular characteristic which inheres in the personal or professional
situation of the individual. Thus, the following characteristics are granted protection:
the dignity of army servicemen in general (Judgement No. 189/1976) and the dignity
of hierarchically lower-ranked servicemen in particular (Judgement No. 45/1992);
the dignity of the housewife as a worker (Judgement No. 85/1985); the dignity of
persons subjected to forensic examination (Judgement No. 54/1986); the dignity of
minors made available for adoption (Judgement No. 303/1996); the dignity of
prisoners in general (Judgement No. 526/2000) and of prisoners in particular
(Judgement No. 158/2001); the dignity of disabled children (Judgement
No. 465/2002); the dignity of a judge (Judgement No. 204/2004); the dignity of
Sicilians (Judgement No. 283/2002); the dignity of homosexuals (Decree
No. 129/2005); the dignity of Jewish persons (Judgement No. 268/1998); and
above all – and repeatedly – the dignity of the worker. It is this focused concentration
on the part of the Constitutional Court on concrete individuals – primarily those
“weaker members of society”, who may be made easy targets for discrimination –
rather than on abstract persons which brings to the fore the unique character of the
concept of dignity within the Italian constitutional order.
3.2
Dignity in Ordinary Jurisdiction
This unique character also comes to light, however, in the ordinary jurisdiction (for a
deeper analysis see Alpa (1997) and, further, Cataudella (1989) and Gambini
(2005)). In view of what was said earlier, it should hardly come as a surprise that
the dignity of the worker is the example which occurs most frequently in the relevant
judgements. We might here consider the following quotation from an important
decision of the Court of Cassation (No. 5977 of 29 November 1985):
The dignity of the worker is an expression of the human person who, with regard to both a
common goal – the development of the economic, social and spiritual community in which he
464
P. Becchi
lives – and the advancement of his own personality, strives to fulfil his activities to the highest
degree. Any working duty which is degrading or degrades the person charged with its execution,
or which is conducted under duress in an undignified manner, is thus not permissible.
The manner in which the court here emphasizes the significance of labour and the
dignity of the person charged with its performance is matched by the constitutional
provisions and provides evidence of the central importance ascribed to labour (and
the worker) in Italian social and economic life.
Recently, the concept of dignity in the sphere of work and labour has been linked
to new phenomena such as bullying and harassment, particularly of a sexual nature.
As in the constitutional jurisdiction, there emerges in the ordinary jurisdiction,
moreover, the same previously noted tendency to grant the protection of dignity to
specific categories of persons: minors (Court of Cassation, Department of Criminal
Law, Judgement No. 39927 of 17 November 2005), disabled persons (Court of
Rome, 26 May 1997), drug addicts (Court of Ivrea, 14 November 1996), prisoners
(Court of Cassation, Department of Criminal Law, No. 8411 of 3 February 2004),
non-EU citizens (Court of Cassation, Department of Criminal Law, No. 26783 of
5 December 2005) or the deceased (Court Of Cassation, Department of Criminal
Law, No. 23356 of 27 April 2001).
Here, too, a detailed analysis would go beyond the scope of our discussion. One
particular case shall, however, be considered more closely, as it clearly exemplifies
the development of the jurisdiction. The judgement in question concerns the conviction (which was confirmed by the Court of Second Instance) of a frigate commander for the verbal abuse of a subordinate. The commander justified his appeal to
the highest court with the claim that no account had been taken in previous proceedings of the statement of the subordinate, who acknowledged that, in his opinion,
the commander had not meant the vulgar comments in question maliciously but
rather jocularly. The Supreme Court rejected the appeal, however, on the grounds
that it is irrelevant “that the addressee did not feel attacked by the insults, as the
object of criminal protection is to be recognized in a much wider context, namely in
the value of human dignity as such” (Court of Cassation, Department of Criminal
Law, Judgement No. 15503 of 1 April 2004). It is clear that dignity is here elevated
to an objective value that is removed from subjective assessments, including those of
the affected parties. Thus, we have found our way from the protection of the social
dignity of the worker to the protection of a notion of dignity as a value which is both
sacrosanct and inalienable, even by its bearer.
Most judicial references to the concept of dignity are to be found, however (and
particularly since a famous judgement passed by a jury trial in Florence on
18 November 1990), in connection with medical treatment. To avoid going beyond
the scope of this chapter, we shall limit ourselves to a few further comments on two
difficult cases which have triggered widespread debate in Italy: the tragic fates of
Piergiorgio Welby and Eluana Englaro respectively (for a more detailed description
of the two cases see Becchi (2011a, 2012b)).
In the Welby case, the legal representatives of the patient, who was suffering from
progressive muscular dystrophy, made recourse to the concept of dignity to justify
Human Dignity in Italy
465
their demands for the cessation of artificial ventilation. They submitted that,
although the life of the patient could have been extended, this could only have
been accomplished under conditions which Welby himself considered humiliating
and degrading. The respect for dignity was thus linked to the right to selfdetermination, which accords patients the right to forego any medical treatment
which they do not wish to receive. Although this right is – as we have seen –
protected by the Italian Constitution, its enforcement was, in this particular case,
more difficult than one might suppose. The doctor who – after assuring himself of
the patient’s will in the matter – turned off the ventilator was prosecuted for killing
on request; he was, however, subsequently acquitted by the judge in charge of
conducting the proceedings, who qualified his actions as a justifiable performance
of duty. In her explanatory memorandum, the judge described Welby as a patient
“who was already thoroughly aware that he had given up all hope of a life which
could be characterized as such and which would uphold the necessary dignity that
attends human existence” (Court of Rome, Judgement No. 2049 of 23 July/
17 October 2007). Although this reference to dignity is of only secondary significance, it is notable that the judge recognized – if only implicitly – that the continuation of the life of the patient was not, under the given conditions, compatible with
his understanding of human dignity.
It is precisely in regard to this aspect that the second case – that of Eluana
Englaro, a patient who was involved in a car accident which left her in a permanent
vegetative state – is interesting . Even if we can only sketch here the most important
waystations in the lengthy process, this will nonetheless suffice to shed a clear light
on the shift in meaning which the concept of dignity thereby underwent.
In its judgement of 1 March 1999, the first instance Court of Lecco reached the
conclusion that the artificial feeding of the patient, who had already been in a
permanent vegetative state for some years, was to be continued: “Art. 2 of the Italian
Constitution protects the right to life as the most important of all inalienable rights of
the individual, whose dignity arises from the absolute value of the person and is not
dependent upon the conditions of life, even should they be so bleak.” Dignity is thus
understood in the judgement as an absolute and unconditional value.
A quite different argument was put forth by the appeal instance: “The life of the
person is not construed biologically [. . .], but rather in terms of the possibility of
social relationships and self-realization, in accordance with the personality and
sovereignty of the individual. Thus, the irreversible loss of consciousness must set
a limit to all medical treatment, as it destroys any chance of a dignified existence”
(Appeals Court of Milan, 26 November 1999).
Where the first instance sought to protect life always and everywhere, the second
distinguished between biological and biographical life and granted dignity only to
the latter. A dangerous boundary was thereby drawn between a life worth living and
one that is not but rather is marked by the irreversible loss of consciousness. The
absolute value of dignity thus appears to be relativized.
The third and final act in the process came with the famous judgement of the
Court of Cassation (No. 21748 of 16 October 2007), which acceded to the cessation
of life-prolonging measures. This judgement attempted to create a synthesis –
466
P. Becchi
equally interesting and problematic – of an abstract and a relative understanding
of dignity. On the one hand, the court upheld the notion of human dignity in
its general applicability and abstractness, while on the other – and at the same
time – recognizing the right to experience the final phase of existence according to
subjective understandings of dignity: “One ought certainly not to differentiate
between a life which is worth living and one which is not. This does not, however,
preclude the possibility of there being cases of artificial life-extension, in which
the only goal is the victory of medical science over the natural process of dying [. . .].
Life as such – as a gift – can never become unworthy, only the artificial extension
of life [. . .].”
The argument put forward by the Supreme Court can be summarized thusly: an
individual who finds him- or herself in a permanent vegetative state is legally still
considered a person with all attendant rights and duties and must be protected in his or
her constitutional rights, beginning with the right to life and medical provision – all the
more so as the severely weakened physical condition of the patient renders him/her
incapable of a personal assertion of those rights. And yet alongside those who consider
the longest possible artificial prolongation of life to serve the interests of the patient
(even if he or she is unconscious), there are also other opinions to be heard; those who
regard personal dignity to be inextricably connected to the experiential world, and who
link the latter to consciousness, view the indefinite extension of life in a condition
without perception of the external world to be entirely incompatible with their
convictions. A state like Italy, which is constitutionally committed to a plurality of
values and which places the principle of self-determination and freedom of choice at
the centre of the patient-doctor relationship, has no choice, according to the Court of
Cassation, but to also respect this latter decision.
This argument is interesting insofar as – without speaking of “a life which is
worth living and one which is not” – it permits the individual to place his or her
dignity above the right to life, which in turn makes dignity a potential barrier to the
most important fundamental right. At any rate, the issue of the finis vitae opens a new
horizon of interest and raises the question whether dignity is a principle which stands
above even life as such.
4
Conclusions
There remains a fundamental question: Is there any connection linking the varied usages
of the concept of dignity in the Constitution, legislation and jurisdiction, or does dignity
rather prove to be a suggestive and stimulating – as well as vague and indeterminate –
notion? What ties, for example, the protection of the dignity of prisoners to the
protection of the dignity of workers? Or the dignity of the latter to that of the terminally
ill? It is clear that “dignity” in each of these situations takes on a different meaning. A
prisoner is entitled to a clean cell and has the right not to be mistreated or tortured and
the right to a minimum measure of privacy. A worker has – first and foremost – the right
to employment and a working environment which is not degrading. Even should one
Human Dignity in Italy
467
consider paid employment to be a form of materialist exploitation, no one – not even the
most orthodox Marxist – would characterize it as a form of torture. The situation
becomes even more complex when one switches attention from socially connoted
conditions to individual circumstances: of what relevance is the dignity of the worker,
which centres upon the right to the complete development of the personality and to
effective participation in social life, to that of the terminally ill patient who – with
recourse to the same concept of dignity – rejects the postponement of death?
Even the same expression of “dignified life” takes on two distinct meanings,
depending upon whether it refers to the right of the worker to a salary which covers
the needs of his or her family or to the right of the dying person to reject the
extension of a life which he or she considers no longer worth living. It is noteworthy
that, precisely in this latter context, the dignity argument is put forward both by those
who fight against euthanasia on the grounds of the sanctity of life and by its
opponents, who adduce from the principle of self-determination a right to death.
Thus, one might be tempted, at first glance, to conclude that the concept of dignity
is not suited to the resolution of the concrete problems posed. Recourse to the
concept appears to be motivated by its inherent indeterminacy, which allows for its
“instrumentalization” to quite different ends; the elasticity of the term permits its
application in a vast range of circumstances. This does not, however, lend itself to
the solving of problems.
Yet such a perspective does not stand the test of closer scrutiny. It is no surprise that
the term “dignity” is used in different senses. Language has an open structure – why
should this apply any less to the word “dignity”, which, like all others, is ambiguous
and, above all, indeterminate? This is reflected in the different usages of the term
which we have considered in this chapter. To be sure, one can discuss whether certain
applications of the term might deviate too far from the “usual” meaning ascribed to it;
the true problem, however, is a different one: Assuming that it exists, what is the core
of certainty that allows us to determine the concept of dignity?
This question cannot be answered in an abstract mode. The foregoing considerations on the use of the term reveal that the main emphasis lies, in the first decades
following the issuance of the Italian Constitution, on the notion of “social dignity”
and its close connection to material equality (Art. 3). In recent times, this understanding has – without losing its significance – been opposed by a different notion –
one that is founded on Art. 32, which aims to guarantee that “respect for the human
person” is never violated in the course of medical treatment and so establishes an
impassable borderline for legislation. It may appear paradoxical that dignity thus
acquires an absolute and unconditional character at a point in the text of the
Constitution at which it does not explicitly appear – even if the dominant modern
legal opinion and jurisdiction interpret the article from the perspective of the
principle of dignity (Turco 2017).
Stefano Rodotà has made the following pointed observation on Art. 32 of the
Constitution:
In setting an insurmountable limit on the legislator, the article represents one of the strongest
provisions of our Constitution; more forceful still than the regulations on personal freedom
468
P. Becchi
provided by Art. 13, which allows it to be limited by restrictions based on legislation and
judicial decisions. Art. 32 goes further. As we approach the hard core of existence – the
necessity to respect the human person as such – we find ourselves confronted by the
undecidable (Rodotà 2015).
Here, too, the principle of dignity stands in close relation to a fundamental right:
that to physical health. The legal debate on the concept of dignity in Italy would thus
appear to be characterized by the point that the principle of dignity almost never
appears as an absolute, unconditional foundation of human rights but rather accompanies the latter.
With regard to the debate in Italy, significance might be granted to the – somewhat
generalizing – comments of Eugenio Ripepe (one of the few legal philosophers to
address the issue): namely, that dignity, rather than itself substantiating something, is
rather no more than the “outcome of a wide range of values” (Ripepe 2008; Becchi
2016), continually variable and dependent upon the development of prevailing opinions. Similarly, the well-known civil law expert Paolo Zatti has recently put forward
the suggestion that the term “constellation” (traceable to Carl Gustav Jung) might be
productively applied for a clarification of the concept of dignity: dignity “constellates”
itself, it interacts with life, with integrity and, thus, with freedom, without losing the
social dimension which has distinguished it in the Italian context from the beginning.
On the other hand, it would, however, be risky to “renounce the fundament of dignity”
(Zatti 2009). Yet this fundament only represents a hard core which is doubtlessly less
flexible but therefore more consistent than a general clause which would not diminish
all the characteristics derived from the varied use of the term; it would, rather, exceed
them. This core cannot, however, be linked to the adjective “social” but rather only to
the adjective “human”, which is no mere addition to dignity but rather an essential
component of it, to the extent that in German, the two terms conjoin to form a single
word: Menschenwürde (human dignity).
The inviolable core of dignity is thus the human person as such. Ultimately, the
ontological conception of human nature is sacrosanct and insurmountable. In the modern
world, this conception finds itself confronted, above all, with the problems of genetic
manipulation, which continue to provoke a wide range of anxieties. On this point, the
debate is ongoing (on the subject of the Oviedo Convention see Furlan (2009)).
5
Cross-References
▶ Human Dignity in Germany
References
Alpa G (1997) Dignità. Usi giurisprudenziali e confini concettuali. Nuova Giurisprudenza Civile
Commentata 2:415–426
Ballestrero MV, de Simone G (2003) Diritto del lavoro. Giuffrè, Milan
Human Dignity in Italy
469
Barbera M (1992) Molestie sessuali: la tutela della dignità. Diritto e Pratica del Lavoro
9:1401–1406
Bartolomei F (1987) La dignità umana come concetto e valore costituzionale. G. Giappichelli,
New York
Becchi P (2007) A dieci anni dalla Convenzione di Oviedo. Una banale questione in tema di
consenso informato. Ragion Pratica 29:565–569
Becchi P (2008) Die italienische verfassungsrechtliche Variante im Vergleich zur deutschen. In:
Brundermüller G, Seelmann K (eds) Menschenwürde. Begründung, Konturen, Geschichte.
Könighausen & Neumann, Würzburg, pp 107–116
Becchi P (2009) La dignità. In: Cendon P (ed) Il risarcimento del danno non patrimoniale II, vol
II. Utet Giuridica, Turin, pp 25–49
Becchi P (2011a) Am Ende des Lebens. Rechtliche Fragen im Zusammenhang mit dem Tod in der
heutigen Medizin. In: Caroni M, Heselhaus S, Mathis K, Norer R (eds) Auf der Scholle und in
lichten Höhen. Festschrift für Paul Richli zum 65. Geburtstag. Dike and Nomos, Zurich/St.
Gallen/Baden-Baden, pp 23–54
Becchi P (2011b) Il testamento biologico. Sui limiti delle “Disposizioni in materia di alleanza
terapeutica, di consenso informato e di dichiarazioni anticipate di trattamento”. Morcelliana, Brescia
Becchi P (2012a) La dignità umana nel “Grundgesetz” e nella Costituzione italiana. Ragion Pratica
38:25–44
Becchi P (2012b) La giustizia tra la vita e la morte. Welby, Englaro e il testamento biologico.
Giappichelli, Turin
Becchi P (2012c) Rifiuto di cure e direttive anticipate. In: Carusi D, Castignone S, Ferrando G (eds)
Diritto vigente e prospettive di regolamentazione. Giappichelli, Turin
Becchi P (2016) Das Prinzip Menschenwürde – eine Einführung. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin
Carusi D, Castignone S (eds) (2011) In vita, in vitro, in potenza: Lo sguardo del diritto
sull’embrione. Giappichelli, Turin
Cataudella A (1989) Dignità e riservatezza del lavoratore. In: Instituto dell’Enciclopdia Italiana
(ed) Enciclopedia Giuridica Treccani. Instituto dell’Enciclopdia Italiana, Rome, pp 1–11
Celotto A (2006) Pari dignità sociale. Commentario alla Costituzione Art 1–54:671–672. Utet
Giuridica, Turin
Di Ciommo M (2010) Dignità umana e Stato Costituzionale. La dignità umana nel costituzionalismo
europeo, nella costituzione italiana e nelle giurisprudenze europee. Passigli, Florence
Ferrara G (1974) La pari dignità sociale. Appunti per una ricostruzione. Studi in onore di Giuseppe
Chiarelli 2:1089–1105
Furlan E (ed) (2009) Bioetica e dignità umana. Interpretazioni a confronto a partire dalla
Convenzione di Oviedo. Franco Angeli, Milan
Gambini F (2005) Il principio di dignità. In: Cendon P (ed) I diritti della persona. Tutela civile,
penale, amministrativa, vol 1. Utet Giuridica, Turin, pp 236–242
Gonnella P (2014) Carceri. I confini della dignità. Milan: Jaca Book
Grossi P (2008) La dignità nella Costituzione italiana. In: Ceccherini E (ed) La tutela della
dignità dell’uomo. Editoriale Scientifica, Naples, pp 113–136. Also published in Diritto e
Società 2008 (1):31–63
Marella MR (2007) Il fondamento sociale della dignità umana. Un modello costituzionale per il
diritto europeo di contratti. Rivista Critica del Diritto Privato 25(1):67–103
Marzocco V (2018) Dignità e natura umana. La Corte Costituzionale italiana e lo statuto normativo
dell’embrione. In La Dignità in questione. Un percorso nel dibattito giusfilosofico
contemporaneo, ed. by V. Marzocco. 19–38. Turin: Giappichelli
Mastro Pietro A, Vicini A, Carmignani Caridi S (2012) Dignità. In: Sgreccia E, Tarantino A (eds)
Enciclopedia di bioetica e di scienza giuridica, vol IV. Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane, Naples/
Rome, pp 283–320
Monaco G (2010) La tutela della dignità umana: sviluppi giurisprudenziali e difficoltà applicative.
In: Sciarrone A (ed) Dignità e diritto. Prospettive interdisciplinari. Libellula Edizioni, Tricase,
pp 167–196
470
P. Becchi
Mortati C (1991) Istituzioni di diritto pubblico. In: Modugno F, Baldassare A, Mezzanotte C (eds)
Manuali di Science Guiridiche, vol 1, 10th edn. CEDAM, Padova, p 433
Pirozzoli A (2007) Il valore costituzionale della dignità. Un’introduzione. Aracne Editrice, Rome
Politi F (2011a) Diritti sociali e dignità nella Costituzione Repubblicana. Giappichelli, Turin
Politi F. (2011b) La tutela della dignità dell’uomo quale principio fondamentale della Costituzione
Repubblicana. In: Studi in onore di Franco Modugno, vol III. Editoriale Scientifica, Naples, p
2661
Resta G (2010) La dignità. In: Rodotà S, Tallacchini M (eds) Trattato di Biodiritto, vol I: Ambito e
fonti del biodiritto. Giuffrè, Milan, pp 259–296
Resta G (2014) Dignità, persone, mercati. Turin: Giappichelli
Ridola P (2006) Libertà e diritti nello sviluppo storico del costituzionalismo. In: Nania R, Ridola P
(eds) I diritti costituzionali. Giappichelli, Turin
Ripepe E (2008) La dignità umana: il punto di vista della filosofia del diritto. In: Ceccherini E
(ed) La tutela della dignità dell’uomo. Editoriale Scientifica, Naples, pp 11–38
Rodotà S (2015) L’uso umano degli esseri umani. MicroMega 8:121–131
Ruggeri A, Spadaro A (1991) Dignità dell’uomo e giurisprudenza costituzionale. Politica del Diritto
3:343–337
Ruotolo M (2002) Diritti dei detenuti e Costituzione. Giappichelli, Turin
Ruotolo M (2005) Il principio di umanizzazione della pena e i diritti dei detenuti nella Costituzione
italiana. Diritto e Società 1(3):51–74
Ruotolo M (2011) Dignità e carcere. Editoriale Scientifica, Naples
Tarantino G (2018) Autonomia e dignità della persona umana. Milan: Giuffrè
Turco G (2017) Dignità e diritti. Un bivio filosofico-giuridico. Turin: Giappichelli
Vincenti U (2009) Diritti e dignità umana. Rome-Bari: Laterza
Zatti P (2009) Note sulla “semantica della dignità”. In: Zatti P (ed) Maschere del diritto volti della
vita. Giuffrè, Milan, pp 29–49