The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
Indian Nihilism: An Exposition of Nāgārjuna’s Philosophy
Dr. Banajit Sharma
Assistant Professor, Dept. of Philosophy
Bongaigaon College, Assam
ABSTRACT
Nihilism believes that human existence has no objective meaning, purpose, or
intrinsic value. As such a nihilist bows to no authority and accepts no doctrine. The nihilistic
interpretation of the world and thought process is quite different than that of common
interpretation. The western nihilism found in the philosophy of Nietzsche and Heidegger, is
very familiar to the academic world. Indian nihilistic philosophy, very precise and logical in
its articulation, was flourished in the second century AD in the philosophy of Nāgārjuna, a
follower of Madhyamika School of Buddhism. This paper is an exposition of Nāgārjuna‟s
view of nihilism. It is also an attempt to enquire whether Nāgārjuna can be considered as a
nihilist or not.
Key Words: Nāgārjuna, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Mādhyamika School, nihilism, śūnyatā,
svabhāva.
Introduction:
Nāgārjuna, the “greatest sceptic-mystic dialectician of the Voidist School of
Mahāyāna Buddhism” (Honderich,Ted. Oxford Companion to Philosophy, p. 637) is widely
known for interpreting Buddha‟s „middle way‟ as emptiness of all things. Buddhism as a
school of philosophy, which has its roots in the life and teachings of Lord Buddha, has a long
series of philosophical heritage. Philosophers and critics are of the view that the birth of
Buddha (c.560–480), „the awakened one‟, is a birth of a bud which was blossomed with the
exposition of Nāgārjuna. The Encyclopaedia of Buddhism writes:
In the West, attempts have been made to compare Nāgārjuna‟s thought with
Immanuel Kant, G. W. F. Hegel, or Francis Herbert Bradley, and more recently
with Jacques Derrida (deconstruction, particularly of egocentricity) and Ludwig
Wittgenstein (liberation of others from philosophical predicaments that result
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1782
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
from fundamentally confused preconceptions; return to the everyday world of
praxis). Emptiness has also been portrayed as a philosophy of relativity, or
ecological co-subsistence. (p. 582)
Nāgārjuna is traditionally regarded as the founder of the Mādhyamika school of
Mahāyāna philosophy. Very little can be said concerning Nāgārjuna‟s life. Scholars generally
place Nāgārjuna in South India in approximately the second century AD. He is the most
important, influential, and widely studied Mahayana Buddhist philosopher who is
traditionally regarded as the founder of the Mādhyamika School of philosophy. Nāgārjuna
has been a name around which tradition has woven a number of myths and legends. In the
prologue of his book, The Philosophy of Nāgārjuna, Vicente Fatone writes “His name
Nāgārjuna, can be explained because he was the conqueror of the Nāgas; like a Nāga, he was
born to the true doctrine from the depths of the ocean, and because his doctrine, like the
ocean, does not have limits” (p. 5). Again, it is said that the eyes of the Nāgas are fiery and
resplendent and Nāgārjuna burns and illumines with the fire of his teachings.
Mādhyamika tradition is also otherwise known as the tradition of “middle way”.
Nāgārjuna accepts the middle path between two extremes. On the one hand he denies the life
of extreme asceticism, and on the other hand, the life of luxury. Again, from the point of view
of metaphysics, he prefers the middle path between the upanisadic philosophy and Buddhism,
that is to say, the way between the two extremes of self-indulgence and self mortification,
eternalism and nihilism. Nāgārjuna attempted to expand the notion of the middle way into the
philosophical sphere, identifying a middle way between existence and nonexistence, or
between permanence and annihilation.
Objective of the Study:
Nihilism as a string of thinking has important bearing upon the world of philosophy
and literature. The present paper tries to explore the development of Indian nihilism in the
philosophy of Nāgārjuna. Though this study is purely analytical, there is a trace of historical
development of nihilism under the light of Madhyamika School of Buddhism. The available
secondary source of literature is consulted for this paper.
Meaning of Nihilism:
The word “nihilism” is originated from the Latin word nihil which means nothing.
Nihilism is a theory according to which nothing is believable and no sort of distinction is
significant. A nihilist is a person who believes that human existence has no objective
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1783
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
meaning, purpose, or intrinsic value and therefore, bows to no authority and accepts no
doctrine. In metaphysics, the word nihilism is used to claim that the world and human life do
not have any value and meaning which we believe them to have. In epistemology, the word
nihilism holds that no knowledge is possible. There is a great significance of the term
nihilism in ethical perspective because moral philosophy deals with the practical aspect of
human beings‟ conduct. In moral philosophy, the word nihilism supposes that there is no
ground to justify any absolute moral value. Ted Honderich writes:
(Nihilism is) the extreme view that there is no justification for values and, in
particular, no justification for morality. It is sometimes used to mean the active
rejection of an attack on such values. The word was invented by the Russian
novelist Turgenev to describe young rebels in Tsarist Russia. Ever since, the word
has been used to condemn those who refuse to accept certain preferred prevailing
values.” (Oxford Companion to Philosophy, p. 659)
In Indian philosophical tradition, the term “nihilism”is understood as “sunyata”. The
term sunyata can be understood as “openness,” “inconceivability,” or “unlimitedness.”But
the easy way to translate it is as “emptiness” or “voidness.” It refers to what dharmas really
are through what they are not: not as they appear, not conceptualizable, not distinguishable,
and, above all, lacking permanent, independent, intrinsic existence.
In western philosophical tradition, nihilism is associated with the German
existentialist Nietzsche, who gave a detailed account of it as a widespread phenomenon of
Western culture. Nietzsche held that “God is dead”. According to him recent developments in
modern science and increasing secularization of European society had killed the Christian
god, who had served as the basis for morality. Death of god leads not only to the denial of
cosmic or physical order but also to the denial of absolute values which he considers as the
absolute basis for morality and it leads to nihilism. Nietzsche challenged the imagined
values of society, the morality of the west and believes that such morality makes people weak
and negativistic. It produces only coward and pessimistic people and stands in the way of
producing new and superior kind of human being. Particularly, he targets Christian morality
which he believes as a producer of dull and static life that discourages human potential and
achievement. Nietzsche uses the term in a variety of ways, with different meanings and
connotations, both positive and negative. Nietzsche claimed to have developed an idea of
moral nihilism and holds that the world lacks value and meaning. Of course, he considered
this particular sense of value and meaning as we conceive them in a traditional way. That
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1784
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
means, Nietzsche tried to devaluate all values and tried to provide a motive to seek new
values.
According to Heidegger, when all our concerns have been reduced to the common
denominator of "experience," in the form of art, religion, sex, education etc. we will have
reached the last stage of nihilism. Heidegger argues that we once had values but that we do
not have values now and that we should regain our values or chooses new ones, is just
another symptom of the trouble. Heidegger claims that thinking about our deepest concerns
as values is nihilism.
There are certain interpretation of life and the universe as a whole which have invited
Nāgārjuna the charge of involving nihilism. According to Nāgārjuna, “There absolutely are
no things, nowhere and none, that arise” (Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, I, 1). This paper is an
attempt to focus on Nāgārjunian philosophy where the element of nihilism is distinctly
visible, but the underlying thought of his writings reflects the other stories.
Nihilism of Nāgārjuna:
According to Nāgārjuna, the world of experience is imperfect because if it is
considered as perfect, improvement would have been impossible. The effort of Nāgārjuna is
to show the path of perfection. For this choosing, both the theoretical and practical aspects
are important. For Nāgārjuna ignorance, which is the source of all suffering, is the belief in
svabhāva, a term that literally means “own being” and has been rendered as “intrinsic
existence” and “self-nature.” It is the belief that things exist autonomously, independently,
and permanently. Svabhāva means substance or essential nature of things. To deny the
essential nature of substance or svabhāva is the main objective of the philosophy of
Nāgārjuna which is elaborately explained in his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. In the process of
knowledge there are certain fundamental concepts, known as categories, without which the
interpretation of the process becomes impossible. Categories are the most general kinds of
things. They are the highest genera of entities in the world. They may contain species but are
not themselves species of any higher genera. Nāgārjuna in his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā
denies any kind of permanent existence. He denies the concept of substance, space, time,
causality etc. It is observed that denying these concepts implies the denying the very basic
age old beliefs of metaphysical basis.
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1785
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
Nihilistic approach is based on some epistemological rationale. According to
Nāgārjuna, knowledge is intimately related to the knower and the known object. So, these
three terms, namely, knowledge, knower and known are interconnected in an inseparable
series of a complete process. If any of these three is proved to be weak, then the others do
also necessarily fall short to stand to be existent. The possibility of this sort of short or
incomplete or false knowledge, like the experience of a snake on a rope, is always attached to
the knowing process. As such, all these knowledge, knower and known are total void.
Again, when we experience a jar, then whether we experience the total jar or the part
of the jar is also an important question according to Nāgārjuna. If we know the whole jar,
then there arises the problem of co-relating the parts with the whole. Again, if we see the jar
as the collection of its parts, then also the jar will no longer continue to be a jar, but simply as
the collection of atoms. As atoms are not visible, Nāgārjuna argues, the collection of atoms
does also no longer continue to be visible. Therefore, we can never say whether the jar is or is
not.
According to Nāgārjuna, there is nothing whatever arises not from itself, not from
another, not from both itself and another, and not without a cause. There are just four
conditions of the existence of anything: efficient cause, supporting condition, precipitating
condition, and dominant condition. There is no fifth condition. Among the four conditions of
the existence of a thing, there is found no substantial essence (svabhava) of the thing. If
things have no substantial essences, then there can be no real relations between different
things. In the book Mūlamadhyamakakārikā, Nāgārjuna tries to refute different Dharmas like
Indriyas, the notion of aggregates or skandhas and Dhātus. Indriyas are the organs of sense
perception. Skandhas are the aggregate likes of matter or consciousness or predispositions or
sanskāras. Form or Rupa is of great significance, because reality of substance is known only
by it. Dhatus are air, water, fire, consciousness etc. These Dhātus are considered as eternal by
many schools of philosophy. According to Nāgārjuna, by refuting the unreality of svabhava,
these can be easily refuted.
Again, Nāgārjuna tries to refute personality or individuality of any sort. He refutes the
notions of karma, karmafala, personality, the notion of four noble truths. According to
Nāgārjuna if all were empty of essence, then nothing could arise or dissolve. As such, even
the Four Noble Truths could not exist. If the Four Noble Truths did not exist, then true
knowledge, renunciation of the world, spiritual progress, and enlightenment would be
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1786
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
impossible. If knowledge, renunciation, spiritual progress, and enlightenment did not exist,
then the four fruits would not exist; and if the fruits did not exist, then there would be no
attaining of the fruits and thus no advancement toward Nirvana. Thus, the doctrine of
emptiness negates the existence of actions, of the four fruits, of the Dharma, and also of the
things taken for granted in the ordinary and everyday thought of the unenlightened.
The early Buddhism apparently shows that anything lacking an independent nature is a
conceptual fiction and not ultimately real. According to Nāgārjuna, emptiness is a property
possessed by each thing without exception. It is the property of lacking intrinsic existence as
a result of being one way or another, the result of causal processes. C. J. Bartley writes:
Everything is empty of intrinsic nature (svabhāva-śūnya). Emptiness (śūnyatā)
must always be understood as meaning „absence of essence‟. It does not mean
non-existence. He often says that what we normally consider things, and the
concepts with which we carve up reality, are neither real not unreal. That is to
say, while our discursive conceptual schemes and the entities that they posit do
serve our purposes to an extent, they cannot be the whole truth. (An
introduction to Indian philosophy, p. 57)
Nāgārjuna‟s concept of nihilism has a teleological basis. He is of the view that
realization of emptiness is essential for the attainment of liberation from the suffering all
sorts. Therefore, he tried to systematize the assertion made in the Prajñāpāramitā of early
Buddhism and says that all things are empty, that is, that is devoid of „own essential nature‟
(svabhāva). By this assertion he tried to refute the view that says that anything exists solely in
virtue of its own inherent nature. Thus, it can be said that if all things are empty, nothing is
ultimately real. Like German existentialist Nietzsche who declared that God is dead,
Nāgārjuna did also in the 10th chapter of his Twelve-Gate Treatise, argued, “God could not be
our father because children should have some resemblance with their father, but in our
suffering we are most ungodly. Being self-existent, God should also have no needs, yet
obviously he needed to create, otherwise he would be whimsical like an infant. As
omnipotent, God should not have any obstacles to his desire, so what explains the gradual
unfolding of creation instead of creation of everything all at once? Finally, if God is the
maker there should be no evil or ugliness in things, but obviously there is.”
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1787
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
Can Nāgārjuna be charged as a nihilist?
Nihilism is very often charged as a negative term. Nāgārjuna asserts that emptiness is
nihilistic only for those who ignore the distinction between two truths: the ultimate, in which
everything truly lacks intrinsic existence; and the conventional, in which, precisely because
they are empty (that is, interdependent), things exist and function, and concepts are valid. The
Encyclopaedia of Buddhism writes:
Nāgārjuna‟s works embody arguments in the style of a sceptic, debunking
concepts like existence and nonexistence, causation, perception, time, motion,
and even religious concepts like the Buddha, or enlightenment itself. Nāgārjuna
also offers methodological reflections on what he is doing, why he is not a
nihilist or even really a sceptic, and how his practice fits into the overall
Buddhist project. For Nāgārjuna this project is a deep “letting-go,” which
nevertheless also facilitates compassionate reengagement. (p. 581)
It is observed, therefore, that Nāgārjuna cannot be considered as a nihilist in the true sense of
the term. Nāgārjuna simply used nihilism as a method for establishing a philosophical truth. Again,
David E. Cooper writes, “What Nāgārjuna is denying is the existence of things in the philosophers‟
sense of substances, things, that is, which enjoy independent being-in themselves, which exist purely
from their own side, without any necessary reliance on anything else” (World Philosophies A
Historical Introduction, p. 48).
Brian Dugnan edited book, The 100 Most Influential Philosophers of All Time, has
placed Nāgārjuna among the 100 greatest philosophers of all time. Nāgārjuna defined
emptiness in terms of the doctrine of pratityasamutpāda. According to this theory, things are
not self-arisen but produced in dependence on causes and conditions. According to Dugnan,
“Adopting this view allowed him to avoid the charge of nihilism, which he addressed directly
in his writings and which his followers would confront over the centuries” (p. 70). Brian
Dugnan focuses on the doctrine of the two truths employed by Nāgārjuna, paramārtha satya
(“ultimate truth”) and samvrti satya (“conventional truth”), explaining that everything that
exists is ultimately empty of any intrinsic nature but does exist conventionally. The
conventional is the necessary means for understanding the ultimate, and it is the ultimate that
makes the conventional possible.
The uniqueness of Nāgārjuna lies in the fact that he endeavoured to avoid any
extremism and above all, categories of all sorts. K Venkata Ramanan, in his illustrative book
Nāgārjuna’s Philosophy has rightly said,
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1788
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
The depth of insight, the rigour of logic and the felicity of expression which he
brought to bear upon his work as a teacher of the Great Way (Mahāyāna), the way
of the perfection of wisdom (Prajñāpāramitā) made a revolution almost startling in
the history of Buddhist philosophy and influenced profoundly the subsequent
philosophical thinking both within and outside the Buddhist fold. (Nāgārjuna’s
Philosophy, p. 31)
Nāgārjuna is right in holding that any attempt to entertain the possibility that our
limited conceptual capacities and schemes can capture the ultimate truth, is worthless.
According to him supposition that things have unchanging and enduring natures, either at the
fundamental or macroscopic level, only encourages us to become attached to them.
Conclusion:
If we have to cite any example of a nihilist in the true sense of the term, then we must
take the name of Nietzsche, because he questions the value of such ideals as truth and
morality. Unlike Nāgārjuna, Nietzsche believed that value of such ideals as truth and morality
cast a shadow on more important values. Nietzsche did also accuse the Judaeo-Christian
tradition as having nihilistic tendencies, because they emphasize the „other-worldly‟ and
reject „naturalistic‟ values. But what Nāgārjuna said was that suffering, causation, temporal
succession etc. all are shown to be uncharacterizable in any determinate manner, because all
characterizations are equally empty.
Nāgārjuna‟s world view is free from any sort of misconceptions and preconceptions.
His interpretation is purely logical and a refutation of any sort of philosophical absolutism.
Nāgārjuna, therefore, cannot be charged for indulging in any sort of nihilistic attitude.
Emptiness, for Nāgārjuna is the true nature of reality, is not the absence of existence but the
absence of intrinsic existence. His tact of applying reason for philosophical interpretation, has
given him the unique height of the best logician of Indian soil has ever produced. Reasoning
for entering into the sphere of truth, he says, is the meaning of life. His purposive negation of
the world is logically grounded. Thereby one can see a new light to view the world under the
light of Nāgārjuna‟s world view.
....................................
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1789
The International journal of analytical and experimental modal analysis
ISSN NO: 0886-9367
Notes and References:
Bartley, C. J. An Introduction to Indian Philosophy, New York: Continuum International
Publishing Group, 2011.
Dugnan, Brian. (ed.) The 100 Most Influential Philosophers of All Time.
New York: Britannica Educational Publishing, 2010.
Lindtner, Chr. Nāgārjuniana: Studies in the Writings and Philosophy of Nāgārjuna.
New Delhi: Motilal Banarasidass, 1990.
Fatone, Vicente. The Philosophy of Nāgārjuna. New Delhi: Motilal Banarasidass, 1991.
Honderich,Ted. Oxford Companion to Philosophy, New York: Oxford University Press,
2005.
Chattopadhyaya, D.P. 1977. What is Living and What is Dead in Indian Philoophy,
New Delhi: Peoples‟ Publishing House, 1977.
Santina, Peter Della. Causality and Emptiness: The Wisdom of Nagarjuna.
Singapore: Buddhist Research Society, 2002.
Buswell, Robert E. (ed.). Encyclopaedia of Buddhism. USA: Macmillan Reference, 2004.
Garfield, Jay L. (Trans.) The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nāgārjuna’s
Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. New York: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Ramanan, K Venkata. 1987. Nāgārjuna’s Philosophy. New Delhi: Motilal Banarasidass,
1987.
Venn, Piyadassi Thera. Buddha and His Teaching, Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication Society,
1982.
Hodge, Joanna. Heidegger and ethics, London: Routledge, 1995.
Volume XI, Issue XI, November/ 2019
Page No:1790