Historia Mathematica 38 (2011) 548–560
www.elsevier.com/locate/yhmat
Notes and Sources
Completing Diophantus, De polygonis numeris, prop. 5
Fabio Acerbi
CNRS, UMR 8163 «Savoirs, textes, langage» B.P. 60149, 59653 Villeneuve d’Ascq Cedex, France
Available online 30 June 2011
Abstract
The last proposition of Diophantus’ De polygonis numeris, inquiring the number of ways that a number can
be polygonal and apparently aiming at “simplifying” the definitory relation established by Diophantus himself,
is incomplete. Past completions of this proposition are reported in detail and discussed, and a new route to a
“simplified” relation is proposed, simpler, more transparent and more “Greek looking” than the others. The
issue of the application of such a simplified relation to solving the problem set out by Diophantus is also discussed in full detail.
Ó 2011 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Résumé
La dernière proposition du De polygonis numeris de Diophante est incomplète. Elle cherche en combien de
manières un nombre peut être polygone et vise apparemment à “simplifier” la définition donnée par Diophante
lui-même. L’article présente et discute les restaurations de cette proposition proposées par les exégètes. Il parvient à une relation “simplifiée”, plus facile, moins opaque et davantage conforme au style mathématique grec.
Il discute aussi de manière détaillée le problème de l’application de ladite relation simplifiée à la résolution du
problème proposé par Diophante.
Ó 2011 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
MSC: 01A20
Keywords: Diophantus; De polygonis numeris; Polygonal numbers
1. Introduction and position of the problem
The Greek mathematician Diophantus (maybe III century of our era) is well-known for
his thirteen-book treatise Arithmetica, containing numerical problems solved by a variety of
techniques. Much less known is the fact that Diophantus wrote also a short tract devoted to
E-mail address: fabacerbi@gmail.com
0315-0860/$ - see front matter Ó 2011 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.hm.2011.05.002
Diophantus, De polygonis numeris 5
549
polygonal numbers, that I shall designate henceforth by its traditional Latin title De polygonis numeris; in its actual form it contains only five propositions. The first edition of the
Greek text of Diophantus’ treatises was published, along with a Latin translation and an
extensive commentary, by Claude Gaspard Bachet de Méziriac in 1621; the first critical edition, and to date the only one, was achieved by Paul Tannery [1893–95].
In his De polygonis numeris, Diophantus succeeded in shaping a sound mathematical theory, the only one that has come to us from Greek antiquity, about objects that were part of
arithmetical folklore since early times (cf. Aristotle, Physica III.4, 203a10–15). A treatise on
polygonal numbers is ascribed by the late Byzantine lexicon Suda (U 418) to Philip of Opus,
a pupil of Plato, but we know nothing of its contents. Diophantus himself states that Hypsicles (II century before our era) gave a sound mathematical definition of polygonal numbers: they can be obtained as partial sums of suitable arithmetical progressions. The II
century polymath Nicomachus, Introductio arithmetica II.6–12, offers a long description,
without a supporting demonstrative apparatus, of the construction and of the main properties of the most simple species of polygonal numbers.
Any number, if represented by a set of identical objects, can be given a “natural” geometrical shape: there are triangular, square, pentagonal, hexagonal, . . . numbers. An obvious
example are the “square” numbers, whose representative sets can most naturally be
arranged as squares. “Polygonal numbers” is simply the generic name for the collection
of these numerical species—as a matter of fact, the set of the polygonal numbers coincides
with the set of positive integers, number 2 excluded (ancient authors included the unit for
reasons that are of no interest here). A sound mathematical theory of polygonal numbers
can be developed once it is realized, as Hypsicles did, that all polygonal numbers of a given
species can be obtained as partial sums of a suitable arithmetical progression, the parameter
distinguishing among the species being the ratio of the progression. Nicomachus has it in
the following terms:
(1) Each species is generated by successively adding numerical “layers”, traditionally
called «gnomons», to a unit; in the case of triangular numbers the successive gnomons
coincide with the integers, in the case of square numbers the gnomons are obtained
from the integers by picking up every second term (these are the odd numbers), in
the case of pentagonal numbers they are obtained from the integers by picking up
every third term, etc. Nicomachus formulated the general rule in this way: «the difference of the gnomons of each polygonal is less by a dyad than the quantity of angles
‹indicated› in its name» (Ar. II.11.4).
(2) The side of any particular polygonal number of any species is greater by a unit than
the number of gnomons involved in its construction (Ar. II.8.3).
Making a further leap into abstraction with respect to Hypsicles’ definition, the first four
propositions and a subtle additional argument of Diophantus’ De polygonis numeris prove
the validity of the following definitory relation of each species of polygonal numbers:
«Every polygonal, multiplied by the octuple of the number less by a dyad than the multiplicity of the angles, and taking in addition the square on the number less by a tetrad than
the multiplicity of the angles, makes a square» [Tannery, 1893–95, 450–72]. In symbolic language, a polygonal number P with v angles satisfies the relation
8Pðv 2Þ þ ðv 4Þ2 ¼ square:
550
F. Acerbi
Prop. 4 makes it explicit what is the side of the square; its expression contains the side l of
the polygonal number P: the full-fledged relation is
2
2
8Pðv 2Þ þ ðv 4Þ ¼ ð2 þ ðv 2Þð2l 1ÞÞ ;
amounting to a definition of a specific polygonal number, that is, to an identification of any
number greater than 2 as a specific polygonal one.
This relation has a natural output, namely, a polygonal number P, and two inputs, the
number of its angles v and its side l. Diophantus immediately applies it to set up two procedures, the one the inverse of the other. They describe how to find, once the “name” or
“species” v of a polygonal P is assigned, the number P with given side l and vice versa
(in the inverse procedure it is of course assumed that P is polygonal). Both procedures, that
are formulated in natural language and without resorting to denotative letters, always produce an output, and the output is univocally determined. These facts are warranted, and in
some sense licensed, by a preliminary “analysis” formulated in the “language of the givens”
[Tannery, 1893–95, 472–6].
Of course, another use of the definitory relation is possible: given a number P, to find the
values of v and l, if any, that satisfy the above definition–using the words of the enunciation
of Diophantus’ prop. 5: «Given a number, to find in how many ways it can be polygonal».
It must be stressed that this problem always has a solution: every number starting from 3 is
polygonal with l = 2 and v equal to the number itself. On the other hand, the problem can
have non-trivial solutions: for instance, 6 is of course hexagonal with side 2, but also triangular with side 3. Now, the definitory relation 8Pðv 2Þ þ ðv 4Þ2 ¼ ð2 þ ðv 2Þð2l 1ÞÞ2
is quite unsuited to explicating v once P and l are given. It is then reasonable to assume that
prop. 5 proceeded first to “simplify” this relation, solving then the proposed problem. I say
«to assume» because prop. 5 breaks off, after a good deal of manipulations that look very
much like aiming at a simplification, in the middle of a passage: the text of the De polygonis
numeris is incomplete [Tannery, 1893–95, 476–80].
In his critical edition of Diophantus’ works, Tannery deemed prop. 5 a worthless attempt
of a commentator [«commentatoris vanum tentamen» at 1893–95, 477 in app.]. He thereby
followed a dismissive attitude that can be traced back at least to Bachet, the first editor of
the Greek Diophantus. Bachet, however, solved the problem independently by introducing
a number of simplified relations that he did not try to connect with prop. 5. Let us read his
4. canon, proved in prop. 6 of the first book of the Appendix with which he supplemented
his edition of the Greek text: «Sume triangulum à latere dato unitate multato, quem ducito
in numerum angulorum binario multatum, producto adde datum latus, fiet qusitus polygonus» [Bachet, 1621, 30]. This reads «Take a triangle with given side minus one, multiply it
by the number of angles minus two, add the given side to the product: it becomes the sought
for polygonal». The associated relation can be written P = ½l(l 1)(v 2) + l; deducing it
from Diophantus’ definitory relation is a matter of a few elementary steps if we are allowed
to use algebraic techniques. What is more, Bachet set forth other rules equivalent to the one
just given; they are formulated in the canones 1. to 3., proved in his props. 3 to 5, and in
symbols read, respectively: 2P ¼ ððl 1Þðv 2Þ þ 2Þl; 2P ¼ lðl 1Þðv 2Þ þ 2l; 2P ¼
l 2 ðv 2Þ lðv 4Þ.
Bachet’s arguments in props. 1 and 2, from which the others are immediate consequences, show that directly proving any of these relations was within easy reach for
Diophantus. In fact, the crucial steps in Bachet’s proofs—namely, (1) how to separate
the contributions of the first term and of the accumulating ratios in the generic term of
an arithmetic progression and (2) that each polygonal number is obtained as the sum of
Diophantus, De polygonis numeris 5
551
a suitable arithmetic progression—are already demonstrated in De polygonis numeris, prop.
2 and the argument following prop. 4. One might wonder why, if Diophantus really
obtained any of the simplified relations in the missing portion of his prop. 5, he did not
directly prove and use it as a definitory relation. Bachet himself must have wondered
why, since he claims that his canones are more elegant, easier, and shorter than those
handed down by Diophantus [«elegantes, & quidem faciliores & compendiosiores eo quem
tradit Diophantus» at 1621, 30].
The answer is that no general definition of a polygonal number as a numerical species can
make explicit reference to the “value” of its side, very much as happens in geometry, where
a pentagon is defined as a figure with five angles (pente gōniai in Greek). Accordingly, Diophantus formulates his definitory relation without saying explicitly which is the side of the
square, even if the proof of prop. 4 determines it univocally. None of the above, simplified,
relations allows one to do that. This explains also the contrived deductive structure of the
De polygonis numeris, where a “simple” relation, thought easily derivable, is obtained only
as a simplification of a more complex one, taken to be primary with respect to the other.
What is more, by choosing as his main definition the one that generically refers to a square,
Diophantus exposes himself to the following objection. Take for instance P = 2 or 4; they
respectively satisfy the relations 24P + 1 = square and 40P + 9 = square, but it is obviously
not the case that 2 is pentagonal or 4 is heptagonal [cf. Bachet, 1621, 21]. The condition
8P(v 2) + (v 4)2 = square is sufficient but not necessary to the identification of the single species of polygonals, whereas of course the condition in which the expression of the
square is made explicit is also necessary. In order to rescue Diophantus, it is enough to note
that no ancient authour would have admitted polygonal numbers less than the number of
their vertices, and all counterexamples that can be adduced are of this kind. It is easy to see
that all the aberrant polygonals are such as to have either an integer, but negative, side:
l = – 1 in both cases, or a non-integer one: l = 4/3 or l = 8/5. In a modern perspective, the
presence of these “spurious solutions” is quite obviously linked with the fact that the definitory relation is not the simplest possible one.
The problems I want to address in this note are the following:
(1) Whether any of Bachet’s simplified relations can be obtained in a straightforward way
by completing prop. 5.
(2) Whether any of Bachet’s relations can be used to solve the problem of determining in
how many ways a given number can be polygonal, namely, the problem posed by
prop. 5.
Of course, these questions have already been given answers, in particular by Wertheim
[1897] and Heath [1910, 256]: they completed or rewrote prop. 5 in order to arrive at relation 2P = l(2 + (l 1)(v 2)). However, I shall explain why one should regard these
answers as unsatisfactory, and shall submit ones that I think are better suited to the techniques displayed by Diophantus in his works. In addition to this, I shall add some historical
flesh to my reconstruction, a move that, apparently, no interpreter regarded as worth doing.
2. Completing De polygonis numeris 5
That a “simplified” relation already circulated in antiquity is confirmed by a Latin
agrimensural text of uncertain autorship and date (but it cannot be much later than the
III century of our era), the so-called «excerpts from Epaphroditus and Vitruvius Rufus».
552
F. Acerbi
Figure 1.
It gives rules for calculating the area of a regular polygon of assigned side, from the pentagon up to the dodecagon included [Bubnov, 1899, 534–45]. These figures are in fact treated as polygonal numbers; two algorithms are described for finding the “area” of the
polygon given its side and vice versa; the relation employed to this end is a simplified
one: P = [(v 2)l2 (v 4)l]/2. Let us read the procedure and the related algorithm in
the case of the enneagon (ibid., 540; the aeram of the text is not a typo for aream: it designates the assigned number; the translation of the procedure is as ungrammatical as the
Latin original is):
Omnis ennagonus aequis habetur lateribus, cujus latus unum in se multiplico et iterum
septies facio, ipsam aeram quinquies deduco, dimidiam partem sumo, ennagonum dico.
Si fuerit ennagonus cuius latera singula habeant ped. X, quaero quot ped. area colligat.
SQ. Multiplico unum latus in se: fit C. Et hoc duco septies: fit DCC. Hinc deduco ipsam
aeram quinquies: fit L. Reliqui DCL dimidiam partem sumo: fit CCCXXV. Tot ped.
hujus ennagoni area est.
Every enneagon having equal sides, whose one side I multiply by itself and again I add
seven times, I subtract five times the number itself, I take one half, I declare the
enneagon.
If there is a enneagon each of whose sides is of 10 feet, I seek how many feet collects the
area. Seek this way. I multiply one side by itself: it becomes 100. I add seven times: it
becomes 700. Therefrom I subtract five times the number itself: it becomes 50. I take half
of the remainder 650: it becomes 325. Of so many feet is the area of this enneagon.
As we shall see at the very end of this note, Bachet drew the two leitmotive of book I of his
Appendix exactly from these excerpts. I now pass to the first problem stated in the
introduction.
I first transcribe in symbolic notation what remains of prop. 5 (see Fig. 1), then the two
reconstructions of Wertheim and Heath, explaining why I regard them as unsatisfactory,
and finally propose my own reconstruction. I use the sign q(AB) for «the square on AB»
and r(AB, BC) for «the rectangle contained by AB and BC», that is, the product of the numbers AB and BC; the references to the Elements are my additions.
(a) Here is the transcription of what remains of De polygonis numeris 5:
Set P = AB, BC = v, and in BC set CD = 2 and CE = 4. One starts with the definitory
relation
ð1Þ
qðZHÞ ¼ 8rðAB; BDÞ þ qðBEÞ;
where ZH is not further specified. Set AH = 1 and split up
8rðAB; BDÞ ¼ 4rðAH; BDÞ þ 4rðAB þ BH; BDÞ:
Diophantus, De polygonis numeris 5
553
Setting
4ðAB þ BHÞ ¼ DK
one obtains
4rðAB þ BH; BDÞ ¼ rðKD; DBÞ
and
4rðAH; BDÞ ¼ 2rðBD; DEÞ
for ED is a dyad.
Therefore,
ð2Þ qðZHÞ ¼ rðKD; DBÞ þ 2rðBD; DEÞ þ qðBEÞ:
But, by El. II.7,
2rðBD; DEÞ þ qðBEÞ ¼ qðBDÞ þ qðDEÞ:
Hence
ð3Þ qðZHÞ ¼ rðKD; DBÞ þ qðBDÞ þ qðDEÞ:
But also, by El. II.1,
rðKD; DBÞ þ qðBDÞ ¼ rðKB; BDÞ;
and therefore
ð4Þ
qðZHÞ ¼ rðKB; BDÞ þ qðDEÞ:
Now, since DK, that is equal to 4(AB + BH), is greater than 4AH, that is, greater than 4,
and DC is a dyad, CK as a remainder is greater than a dyad CD: therefore, the middle point
of DK will fall between C and K; let it be K. It follows that we can apply El. II.6:
rðKB; BDÞ ¼ qðBKÞ qðKDÞ;
or
rðKB; BDÞ þ qðDKÞ ¼ qðKBÞ;
or
qðKBÞ qðKDÞ ¼ rðKB; BDÞ:
Therefore
ð5Þ qðZHÞ ¼ qðBKÞ qðKDÞ þ qðDEÞ:
Summing q(DK) on both sides one gets
qðZHÞ þ qðDKÞ ¼ qðBKÞ þ qðDEÞ;
or
ð6Þ qðKDÞ qðDEÞ ¼ qðKBÞ qðZHÞ:
Now, since ED ¼ DC, we can again apply El. II.6:
rðEK; KCÞ þ qðCDÞ ¼ qðDKÞ:
Therefore,
ð7Þ
qðKDÞ qðDCÞ ¼ qðKDÞ qðDEÞ ¼ rðEK; KCÞ ¼ qðKBÞ qðZHÞ:
554
F. Acerbi
Figure 2.
Set ZM = BK—for BK is greater than ZH, since it was proved that qðZHÞþ
qðDKÞ ¼ qðBKÞ þ qðDEÞ and q(DK) is grater than qðDEÞ because it is also greater than
qðDCÞ. Therefore
ð8Þ
qðZMÞ qðZHÞ ¼ rðEK; KCÞ:
Now, since DK ¼ 4ðAB þ BHÞ and DK is bisected at K; DK ¼ 2ðAB þ BHÞ, of which
DC ¼ 2AH; therefore, CK ¼ 4HB and so, because EC ¼ 4 ¼ 4AH, one has EK ¼ 4AB.
As a consequence,
rðEK; KCÞ ¼ 16rðAB; BHÞ:
Therefore, by transitivity with (8) and El. II.4,
ð9Þ 16rðAB; BHÞ ¼ qðMZÞ qðZHÞ ¼ qðHMÞ þ 2rðZH; HMÞ;
so that HM is even. Let it be bisected at N. The text ends abruptly at this point.
One must stress that Diophantus, before the interruption, does not set out explicitly the
expression of the side ZH of the square; in particular, he does not introduce the side of the
given polygonal. This makes all completions of prop. 5 arbitrary to a high degree.
(b) What follows is Wertheim’s reconstruction (1897), which we find also transcribed in
Heath [1910, 257–8]. It uses the same denotative letters as Diophantus’. I do not report the
symbolic transcription that both Wertheim and Heath present in a facing column parallel
to the text, but I shall briefly comment on it later—to give the reader an idea of the
difficulties involved in this transcription, here is what is facing step (9) above:
2½2 þ ð2l 1Þðv 2Þ½2ð2P 2Þ 2ðv 2Þðl 1Þ þ ½2ð2P 2Þ 2ðv 2Þðl 1Þ2 ¼ 16PðP 1Þ.
The first step of Wertheim’s reconstruction directly links to the last one of the surviving
text (see Fig. 2).
Therefore,
4rðZH; HNÞ þ 4qðHNÞ ¼ 16rðAB; BHÞ;
that is, dividing out by 4,
ð10Þ
rðZH; HNÞ þ qðHNÞ ¼ 4rðAB; BHÞ
and hence, by El. II.1,
ð11Þ
rðZN; HNÞ ¼ 4rðAB; BHÞ:
Setting ZP = 2AB and PR ¼ HN, which entail HR ¼ PN, one obtains
ZR ¼ ZP PR ¼ 2AB PR;
ZN ¼ ZP þ PN ¼ 2AB þ PN;
HN ¼ PR ¼ 2AB ZR;
Diophantus, De polygonis numeris 5
and equality (11) becomes
ð12Þ ð2AB þ PNÞð2AB ZRÞ ¼ 4rðAB; BHÞ;
or
ð13Þ
4qðABÞ 2rðAB; ZR PNÞ rðPN; ZRÞ ¼ 4qðABÞ 4rðAB; AHÞ;
and therefore
ð14Þ
2rðAB; ZR PNÞ þ rðPN; ZRÞ ¼ 4rðAB; AHÞ;
or
ð15Þ 2rðAB; 2AH þ PN ZRÞ ¼ rðPN; ZRÞ:
But
PN ¼ ZN ZP ¼ ZM NM ZP ¼ ZM ½HM ZP
¼ BK ½HM 2AB ¼ BD þ ½DK ½HM 2AB
¼ BD þ 2AB þ 2BH ½HM 2AB ¼ BD þ 2BH ½HM
and
ZR ¼ ZP PR ¼ 2AB ½HM;
as a consequence
PN ZR ¼ BD þ 2BH 2AB ¼ BD 2AH
PN ZR þ 2AH ¼ BD:
One then gets
PN ¼ BD þ 2BH ½HM ¼ BD þ 2BH ½BK þ ½ZH
¼ BD þ 2BH ½BD ½DK þ ½ZH ¼ ½BD þ 2BH ½DK þ ½ZH
¼ ½BD þ 2BH ðAB þ BHÞ þ ½ZH ¼ ½BD þ BH AB þ ½ZH
¼ ½BD AH þ ½ZH ¼ ½ðBD þ ZH 2AHÞ:
But
ZH ¼ ð2l 1ÞBD þ 2;
or
ZH þ BD ¼ 2lBD þ 2;
or
ZH þ BD 2AH ¼ 2lBD;
that is,
PN ¼ lBD:
Equality (15) thus becomes
ð16Þ
2rðAB; BDÞ ¼ lrðBD; ZRÞ
or, by eliminating the common height BD,
ð17Þ
2AB ¼ lZR;
555
556
F. Acerbi
Figure 3.
Since AB = P and ZR ¼ 2 þ ðl 1Þðv 2Þ one finally has
2P ¼ lð2 þ ðl 1Þðv 2ÞÞ:
The drawbacks of this reconstruction are the excessive length of the intermediate transitions between equalities (15) and (16) and the ad hoc introduction of the quantity ZR. These
difficulties are highlighted by the fact that, in the facing algebraic transcription, the
almost-final equality 2Pðv 2Þ ¼ lðv 2Þð2 þ ðl 1Þðv 2ÞÞ is already obtained at step
15. What follows, in fact half of the entire deduction, has the sole function of making
the common height BD ¼ v 2 appear and of “cleaning up” the deduction from the
complex partitions of ZM Wertheim introduced at the beginning of it. These facts show
that Wertheim’s approach is algebraically-driven, and his cumbersome restoration is an
unsuccessful attempt at reshaping it in geometric terms.
(c) Heath [1910, 256] (see Fig. 3) proposed a far simpler reduction, but he did not try to
complete the surviving fragment of prop. 5:
Let FG ¼ 2 þ ð2l 1Þðv 2Þ. Cut off FR = 2, and produce RF to S so that RS = v 2.
We have now
8P:SR ¼ qðFGÞ qðSF Þ ¼ qðSG SF Þ qðSF Þ ¼ qðSGÞ 2rðSG; SF Þ:
Bisect SG at T, and divide out by 4; therefore
2P:SR ¼ qðSTÞ rðST; SF Þ ¼ rðST; ST SF Þ ¼ rðST; FTÞ ¼ rðST; FR þ RTÞ
Now, ST ¼ lSR, and FR = 2, while RT ¼ ðl 1ÞSR ¼ ðl 1Þðv 2Þ. It follows that
2P ¼ lð2 þ ðl 1Þðv 2ÞÞ:
This derivation is in fact nothing but a dressing in denotative letters of quite a straightforward algebraic reduction: it simply assumes what is set out to prove. Of course, Heath was
unable to see that his derivation is in fact a circular one; the words with which he introduces
it are quite typical of his way of approaching ancient texts: «The only thing, so far as I can
see, tending to raise doubt as to the correctness of [Wertheim’s] restoration is the fact that
[. . .] it can be done much more easily than it is in Diophantus’ proposition as extended by
Wertheim» (ibid.).
(d) My completion of prop. 5 produces any of Bachet’s relations without resorting to
algebraic manipulations, is simpler and more transparent than Wertheim’s and is, in my
opinion, more “Greek looking” (see Fig. 4):
Therefore,
ð10Þ
4rðZH; HNÞ þ 4qðHNÞ ¼ 16rðAB; BHÞ;
or, by El. II.1,
4rðZN; HNÞ ¼ 16rðAB; BHÞ;
that is
ð11Þ
rð2ZN; 2HNÞ ¼ rð4AB; 4BHÞ:
Recalling that ZM = BK, one has
ZM ¼ BK ¼ BD þ DC þ CK:
Diophantus, De polygonis numeris 5
557
Figure 4.
Furthermore, since DC is a dyad,
ZH ¼ DC þ rððBX þ UXÞ; BDÞ ¼ DC þ 2BW BD ¼ DC þ 2DW þ BD;
where the definitory relation of a polygonal number has been used and
BW ¼ rðBX; BDÞ ¼ BD þ DW ¼ BD þ rðUX; BDÞ has been set; BX is the side of the polygonal number AB and a unit BU has been cut off from BX (a similar position involving the
same numbers, followed by the introduction of a ‘solid’ number as I shall do below, is made
in prop. 4). Therefore, recalling that also ED is a dyad,
2ZN ¼ ZM þ ZH ¼ EK þ 2BW;
2HN ¼ ZM ZH ¼ CK 2DW;
and equality (11) becomes, recalling again that the definition of DK and its being bisected at
K entail 4AB = EK and 4BH ¼ CK,
ð12Þ
rððEK þ 2BWÞ; ðCK 2DWÞÞ ¼ rðEK; CKÞ:
This is an equality between two rectangles having the rectangular domain of sides EK and
CK 2DW in common. By subtracting it from both sides one gets
ð13Þ
2rðEK; DWÞ þ 4rðBW; DWÞ ¼ 2rðCK; BWÞ;
or, setting CK ¼ EK EC and dividing out by 2,
ð14Þ rðEK; DWÞ þ 2rðDW; BWÞ ¼ rðEK; BWÞ rðEC; BWÞ:
Recalling that BW ¼ BD þ DW and operating by partial «restoration» and «reduction»,
ð15Þ rðEK; DBÞ ¼ 2rðDW; BWÞ þ rðEC; BWÞ;
that is, since EC is a tetrad and DE is a dyad,
rðEK; BDÞ ¼ 2rðDW; BWÞ þ 2rðDE; BWÞ ¼ 2rðEW; BWÞ:
Bisecting CK at X and since D bisects EC one has
2rðDX; BDÞ ¼ 2rðEW; BWÞ;
that is, dividing out by 2,
ð16Þ
rðDX; BDÞ ¼ rðEW; BWÞ:
But if two rectangles are equal, their sides are reciprocally proportional (El. VI.14):
ð17Þ DX : EW :: BW : BD:
Now, BW ¼ rðBX; BDÞ and therefore BW : BD ¼ BX. As a consequence, introducing the
sign sðAB; BC; CDÞ for the solid number contained by AB, BC, and CD,
ð18Þ
DX ¼ rðBX; EWÞ ¼ rðBX; BWÞ rðBX; BEÞ ¼ sðBX; BX; BDÞ rðBX; BEÞ;
558
F. Acerbi
or, since BU is a unit and DE a dyad,
ð18bisÞ DX ¼ rðBX; EWÞ ¼ rðBX; BWÞ rðBX; BDÞ þ rðBX; DEÞ
¼ sðBX; BX; BDÞ sðBX; BU; BDÞ þ 2rðBX; BUÞ ¼ sðBX; UX; BDÞ þ 2BX:
Setting DX ¼ 2AB ¼ 2P; BD ¼ v 2; DE ¼ 2 and BE ¼ v 4; BX ¼ l (and hence
UX ¼ l 1) one can rewrite these equalities as
2P ¼ l 2 ðv 2Þ lðv 4Þ;
or
2P ¼ lðl 1Þðv 2Þ þ 2l;
from which
P ¼ ½lðl 1Þðv 2Þ þ l:
Of course, Diophantus would have formulated the last three lines in display in natural
language. Furthermore, he would have had no qualms in proposing equalities between
non-homogeneous terms, as this is already done in De polygonis numeris, prop. 4.
Let us now come to the second of the problems listed in the introduction. One would like
to use any of the above relations to find in how many ways a number can be polygonal.
This is equivalent to finding, once a polygonal P is assigned, the number of its angles v corresponding to a given side l or vice versa. The first task was taken up by Bachet [1621, 38,
and see also the conditions of possibility discussed ibid., 39]:
Exponantur ab unitate omnes in infinitum ordinatim numeri, puta 1.2.3.4.5.6.7.8. & illis
subiiciantur ab unitate triangulares omnes ordinate dispositi, puta 1.3.6.10.15.21.28. ut
factum vides in apposita tabella, qu potest in infinitum extendi. Tum propositus numerus 120. dividatur sigillatim per numeros triangulos, & observetur, quoties residuum ex
divisione quale erit lateri proximo maioris trianguli, toties enim numerus 120. polygonus erit, cuius latus erit ipsum residuum divisionis. At quotiens ostendet differentiam
progressionis huiusmodi polygonorum constitutiv, seu quod idem est, idem quotiens
binario auctus, numerum angulorum indicabit.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
1
3
6
10
15
21
28
36
45
55
66
78
91
105
120
Set out, beginning from a unit, all numbers in order as far as infinity, say 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8,
and let all triangular numbers beginning from a unit be placed in order below them, say 1
3 6 10 15 21 28, as you can see done in the table set out below, that can be extended to
infinity. Let then the assigned number 120 be divided in succession by each of the triangular numbers, and let it be remarked that the number 120 will be polygonal exactly
when the remainder of the division is equal to the side of the immediately greater triangle, the side of the polygonal being the remainder itself of the division. In its turn, the
quotient will show the difference of the constitutive progression of the polygonals, or,
what amounts to the same, the same quotient plus two will indicate the number of angles.
In our language, dividing a polygonal P by the triangular number ½l(l 1) of side and order
l 1, one obtains the side of the triangular number of order l as a remainder and a number
Diophantus, De polygonis numeris 5
559
less by 2 than the number of angles of P as a quotient: this amounts to find v at fixed P once l
is given by using relation P ¼ ½lðl 1Þðv 2Þ þ l. The procedure does not give an output in
every instance, as is natural: no number is polygonal with any number of angles even though
any number is polygonal with some number of angles. Bachet formulates this state of affairs
with the correlative quoties. . . toties. . ., by requiring that the division of the assigned number
P by a triangular number give as a remainder the side of the subsequent triangular number. In
Greek mathematical jargon, this is a true diorismos, as it indicates in general terms the number or solutions of the problem (one or zero in this trivial instance) in function of the value of
the “givens” of the problem itself. Both the “validation” of the procedure and the formulation of the diorismos can easily be formulated in Diophantine language, following the model,
still contained in the De polygonis numeris as we have seen at the beginning of this note, of the
procedure for finding, once the species v of the polygonal is assigned, the number P with given
side l and vice versa. Bachet’s procedure is rewritten in symbols, and adapted to his own simplified relation 2P ¼ lð2 þ ðl 1Þðv 2ÞÞ, by Wertheim [1890, 314–5], who adds 325 as an
example to Bachet’s 120. The conditions of possibility are in this case that l must divide
2P exactly and that ð2P=l 2Þ=ðl 1Þ must be an integer. As usual, Heath [1910, 259] makes
up his exposition by a verbatim plagiarism of Wertheim, without mentioning any of his
predecessors.
In this way the problem posed in prop. 5 is solved. Still, one would like to see Diophantus
setting up a direct-and-inverse procedure like the one he makes to follow to the definitory
relation. However, finding l once v and P are fixed is not immediate: Bachet’s procedure just
described, based on relation P ¼ ½lðl 1Þðv 2Þ þ l, cannot be “inverted” in a natural
way. But les us take instead relation 2P ¼ ðv 2Þl 2 ðv 4Þl, and write it, after an operation of «restoration», 2P þ ðv 4Þl ¼ ðv 2Þl 2 . This is an instance of the case in which
«two species are left out equal to one», whose treatment Diophantus announces in the
introduction of his Arithmetica [Tannery, 1893–95, 14.23–4]. Now, even if the extant
Arithmetica, either in Greek or in Arabic, contains nothing systematic of this sort, in propositions such as Ar. IV.31 and 39 a procedure is explicitly described for solving this kind of
equalities, and conditions are spelled out under which they can be «expressible» (that is,
they have rational solutions). It is immediate to check that the above equality always has
two solutions, one of which is positive. The diorismos to be required is that the expression
corresponding to our discriminant be a square, and that the final division by v 2 gives an
integer. As is to be expected, then, also in this case the procedure may break down before
producing an output. These considerations suggest that Diophantus probably derived more
than one simplified relation in his prop. 5, and that the stylistic register of the De polygonis
numeris, if it included techniques typical of the Arithmetica, was more mixed than we are
entitled to conclude from the surviving portion.
A side problem is how to set a priori limitations on the sides or angles admissible for trial
in the direct or inverse procedure solving the problem posed by prop. 5 [cf. Bachet, 1621, 39;
Wertheim, 1890, 314–5; Heath, 1910, 259]. In general, it must be 2 6 l < P and 3 < v 6 P,
but we can have better. Of course, as any number is polygonal with side 2 and number of
angles equal to itself, the two non-strict inequalities cannot be improved. On the other
hand, the side of a polygonal P cannot be greater than the side of the first triangular number equal to or greater than P, that is, if m is the side of such a triangle, 2P 6 mðm þ 1Þ,
where
p 2P ¼ mðm þ 1Þ can still be solved in m at given P (cf. Ar. VI.6). It results that
l 6 ½ ð1 þ 8PÞ 1=2. A simpler inequality is obtained by applying
the same argument
p
to the square equal to or immediately following P: it results l 6 ð2PÞ. The lower bound
on the number of angles cannot be improved.
560
F. Acerbi
Two final remarks. First, a collection of geometrical problems on polygons, published by
Heiberg in his Mathematici Graeci Minores [1927, 25–65], is ascribed in the manuscript tradition to some «Diophanes», but a second hand in the principal manuscript corrected the
ascription to «Diophantus» (Const. pal. vet. 1, f. 17v). The procedures solving these problems are different from those attested in the Epaphroditus and Vitruvius Rufus excerpts,
yet the names of the polygons are all masculine and not neuter: they are polygonal numbers, not geometrical figures. Second, these same excerpts give, besides the procedures
described above, also a simple rule for summing all polygonal numbers of species v, the unit
included, up to P: the result is ð2P þ vÞðv þ 1Þ=6, a rule that Bachet knew and that he
expressly declares to draw from a book by Epaphroditus and Vitruvius Rufus [«ex libro
Apafroditi & Betrubi Rufi Architectonis» at 1621, 37–8]. Since the excerpts already transmit
a valuable piece of information concerning the De polygonis numeris, I surmise that a derivation of this relation might have been contained in the Diophantine treatise, as an analogical extension of the exposition ending with prop. 5: since polygonal numbers are
obtained as sums of terms having a constant first difference (= an arithmetic progression),
in the same way it might be of interest to see what happens in summing terms having a constant second difference (= a progression of polygonal numbers of the same species).
Acknowledgments
This work has been supported by the Agence Nationale de la Recherche under grant ANR-09BLAN-0300-01.
References
Bachet de Méziriac, C.G., 1621. Diophanti Alexandrini Arithmeticorum libri sex, et de numeris
multangulis liber unus. Lutetiae Parisiorum, Sumptibus Hieronymi Drovart, via Jacobaea, sub
Scuto Solari.
Bubnov, N. (Ed.), 1899. Gerberti Opera Mathematica. R. Friedländer & Sohn, Berlin.
Heath, Th.L., 1910. Diophantus of Alexandria: A Study in the History of Greek Algebra. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Heiberg, J.L. (Ed.) 1927. Mathematici Graeci Minores, Det Kongelige Danske Videnskabernes
Selskabs, Historisk-filologiske Meddelelser XIII,3, København, Bianco Lunos Bogtrykkeri.
Tannery, P. (Ed.) 1893–95. Diophanti Alexandrini opera omnia cum graeciis commentariis, 2 vol.
B.G. Teubner, Leipzig.
Wertheim, G., 1890. Die Arithmetik und die Schrift über Polygonalzalhen des Diophantus von
Alexandria. B.G. Teubner, Leipzig.
Wertheim, G., 1897. Die Schlussaufgabe in Diophants Schrift über Polygonalzalhen. Zeitschrift für
Mathematik und Physik (hist.-lit. Abth.) 42, 121–126.