zy
zyxwv
zyxwv
zyx
zy
zyxwv
zyxwvu
zyxw
zyxwv
T o m G. Palmer
G. A. COHEN O N SELF-OWNERSHIP,
PROPERTY, AND’EQUALITY
,
ABSTRACT:G.A. Cohen has produced an influential criticism o f libertarianisrir that posits joint ownershk o f everydiing in the world other than labov,
with each joint owner having a veto r&$t over any potential use of the world.
According to Cohen, in that world rationality would require that wealth be divided equally, with no d@erential accorded to talent, abilitn or eJort. A closer
examination shows flint Colterr’s argument rests on two central errors of reasoning and does not support his egalhrian conclusions, even granting his assumption of joint ownership. That assumption was rejected by Locke,
Pufendotf and other writers on property f o r reasons thnt Cohen does not
rebut.
In a number of articles,G. A. Cohen has set out an intricate set of arguments rebutting attempts to derive property claims in alienable objects (“world ownership”) and non-patterned distributions of income
(“capitalist inequality”) from property claims in one’s person (“selfownership”).’ As Cohen (1995, 14)describes his enterprise in SeE
Ownership, Freedom, and Equality, “I entertained an alternative to Nozick’s ‘up for grabs’ hypothesis about the external world, to wit, that it
is jointly owned by everyone, with each having a veto over its
prospective use. And I showed that final equality of condition is as-
CriticalRevieill 12, no. 3 (Summer 1998).ISSN 0891-3811.Q 1998 Critical Review Foulidation.
Tom G. Palmer, Senior Fellow in Moral and Political Thought, Cat0 Institute, 1000 Massachusetts Avenue NW, Washington, DC ZOOOI,telephone (202) 769-5299, telefax (202) 8423490. e-mail tpalmer@cato.org,thanks G. A. Cohen. Chandran Kukathas,John Gray,Raymond Plant, and odicr readers for comments on carlicr versions of this paper.
22.5
226
zyxwvuts
zyxw
zyxw
Critical Review Vol. fa, No. 3
sured when that egalitarian hypothesis about ownership of external
resources is conjoined with the thesis of self-ownership.” Cohen concludes that “equality had indeed been derived with no breach of the
rules of self-ownership” (ibid.), a result that, when conjoined with
additional arguments, “succeeded in exploding the libertarian posi*
tion” (ibid., IS).
The argumeneonce one gets past Cohen’s strange assumptions-is
ingenious and has been extraordinarily influential. W
i
l
l Kymlicka
(1990,I I ~ ) for
,
example, asks, in his Contemporary Polirical Philosophy:
A n Introduction, “What would happen if the world was [sic] jointly
owned, and hence not subject to unilateral privatization? There are a
variety of possible outcomes, but in general they will negate the inegalitarian implications of self-ownership.”2 Kymlicka cites, without
rehearsing his argument, Cohen’s authority in support of this strong
claim. More recently, Justin Weinberg (1997,324) has reproduced
parts of Cohen’s argument in an article in Critical Review, concluding
that “Cohen shows that libertarianism cannot be defended in the way
that most libertarian philosophers want to defend it.”3
The conclusion that Cohen reaches and that has been so iduentid
is, however, based on errors in Cohen’s reasoning. There are numerous steps in the argument that may be open to objection, but even
granting all of his assumptions, the logic of the argument fails.
I shall first outline Cohen’s aims and general procedure. Second, I
shall identify two crucial moves in his influential argument. Third, I
shall show that the fvst move is insupportable. Fourth, I shall show
that the second move is based on a confusion. I examine only two
steps of Cohen’s argument, but they are vitally important to his conclusions and, if they are wrong, his polemic against property in one’s
person, and against attempts to ground several property on this foundation, is severely weakened.
Finally, I will conclude with some general remarks about where
this leaves Cohen and the issue of property rights. Cohen asserts that
libertarianism is unjustified if we grant his assumption-offered without any argument whatsoever-that communism is justified. I conclude by rebutting this strange position.
Before turning directly to Cohen’s case, I should offer a justification for plunging the reader into an often complicated and technical
argument, so much so that few readers have bothered to read it carefully. Cohen’s mistakes, although fatal to his enterprise of undermining libertarianism, are instructive. Cohen does not succeed in “ex-
zyxwvu
zy
zy
zy
zyxw
Palmer Cohen on Property and Eqi#ality
227
ploding the libertarian position’’ (1995,Is), but his failed effort does
draw our attention profitably to such matters as the role of expectations in determining bargaining outcomes, the limitations of purely
laypothetical models for moral and political theory, and the importance of the history of fegal and political institutions and of the history of moral, legal, and political thought. In his attack on property,
Cohen conjoins the unjustified and untenable assumption of initial
communism with fauIry reasoning and an argument so convoluted
that he becomes entangled in his own scenarios and confuses them,
to the destruction of his enterprise.
zyxw
zyxwvut
zyxwvu
zyxwv
zyxwvut
Joint Ownership
Cohen’s principal concern is to defend a thoroughgoing egalitarian
distribution of income, which he considers to be incompatible with an
inegalitarian pattern of ownership. He asserts that “a union of seK
ownership and unequal distribution of worldy resources leads to indefinitely great inequality of private property in external goods and,
hence, to inequality of condition, on any view of what equality of
condition is” (1995,69).His concern is to delegitimize the appropriation oCexternal resources by individuals or groups, by which they
might come to have a property in such resources that would exclude
the rival claims of others. Cohen takes as his sole target Robert Nozick’s remarks on property in hurchy, State, and Utopia and attempts to
unravel the relationship Nozick asserts between private (or several)
property and individual liberty. In doing so, Cohen affirms the plausibility of (without indicating ultimate agreement with) Nozick’s insistence on each person’s property in her p e r ~ o n Cohen
.~
then reduces
Nozick’s entire theory of appropriation to Nozick’s version of the
“Lockean proviso,” which holds that “a process normally giving rise
to a permanent bequeathable property right in a previously unowned
thing will not do so if the position of others no longer at liberty to
use the “thing is thereby worsened” (Nozick 1974,178).Cohen (1995,
76) considers the proviso, not as a proviso to a theory of appropriation, but simply to be Nozick‘s theory of appropriation; thus, the proviso just quoted,“with Nozick’s elaboration of it, is Nozick‘s doctrine
of appropriation; or, speaking more cautiously, if Nozick presents any
doctrine of appropriation, then the quoted statement is the controversial element in his doctrine, and therefore the element which re-
3238
zyxwvuts
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxw
zyxw
Critical Review VoL
12,
No.3
quires close scrutiny.’’ I shall set to the side questions about whether
Cohen has fairly characterized Nozick’s proviso as constituting his
principle of appropriation: and will merely reproduce the conclusion of his treatment, as prolegomenon to his central argument that
“self-ownership” can be so construed or integrated with other
arrangements as to necessitate completely equal distribution of wealth
andincome.
.
Cohen (1995,90) insists that any appropriation will make someone
worse off, for no other reason than that someone will no longer be
able to appropriate the now-appropriated item: “It is clear beyond
doubt that an appropriation of private property can contradict an individual’s will just as much as levying a tax on him can.” If contradicting one’s will is the criterion for a theory that is supposed to be
based on liberty, then, according to Cohen, no private appropriation
could meet the requirements of a suitably formulated Nozickian proviso, for, even if a latecomer finding no unappropriated resources lefr
to appropriate were to be compensated by greater material wealth,
this compensation could not undo the fact that the latecomer’s will
has been overruled. As Cohen (ibid., 89) argues, “Nozick disallows
objectively paternalist use of people’s private property. But he permits
objectively paternalist treatment of people in ocher ways. For, since
he permits appropriations that satisfy nothing but his proviso, he allows A to appropriate against B’s will when B benefits as a result, or,
rather, as long as B does not lose.” If someone were to chop off my
arm, even if he later made me better off,we would still say that my
rights had been violated.
In the process of making this move, allegedly showing that Nozick’s approach cannot justifi appropriation by individuals (or groups)
&om an unowned commons, Cohen suggests that Nozick‘s baseline
of comparison-what one could get in a condition of no appropriation or ownership at all-is arbitrary, and that a variety of collective
ownership arrangements should be considered as candidates for the
baseline, as well.6 There are, according to Cohen (1995, 78), “other
intuitively relevant counterfactuals, and . . they show that Nozick’s
proviso is too lax, that he has arbitrarily narrowed the class of alternatives with which we are to compare what happens when an appropriation occurs with a view to determining whether anyone. is harmed
by it.” The alternative rhat he singles out as “intuitively relevant” is
that ofjoint ownership,according to which a resource
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxwvu
.
zyxw
zyxw
zy
zyxw
zyxw
zyxw
zy
Palmer Cohen on Property and Eqrcaliiy
229
is owned, by all together, and what each may do with it is subject to
collective decision. The appropriate procedure €or reaching that decision may be hard to define,but it will certainly not be open to any
one of the joint owners to privatize all or part of the asset unilaterally,
no matter what compensation he offers to the rest. . .. . So if joint
ownership rather than no ownership is, m o d y speaking, the initial
position, then B has the right to forbid A to appropriate, even if B
would benefit by what he thereby forbids. (Ibid., 83)
In setting up the problem, Cohen (1995,92) strives to “reconcile
self-ownership with equality (or not too much inequality) of condition, by constructing an economic constitution which combines selfownership with an egalitarian approach to raw worldly resources.’’
(Cohen never makes clear what “not too much inequality” can or
should mean, or how one might know how much was too much.)
The principle of joint ownership, according to Cohen, when combined with strict “self-ownership,” would: I) preclude individual ‘or
subgroup property rights (or property in severalty through subdivision) through fkee agreement, and 2) generate completely equal distributions of income (or, if any inequalities were to be allowed, they
would not reflect differences in control over productive powers, i.e.,
they would not be due to one’s property in one’s person). Cohen
tries to base both of those conclusions on the rationality of the parties. The point of Cohen’s exertions is to attempt to show that selfownership would not entail rights to several property, or world-ownership, under conditions of initial joint ownership of resources other
than labor. Cohen claims that no individual or subgroup appropriation can meet a properly formulated Nozickian proviso against harm,
so there can be no legitimate individual or subgroup appropriation
&om a condition of no-ownership. His next two steps are to argue
that rationality would preclude mutually agreeable individual or subgroup division of the jointly owned assets, and that it would be irrational forjoint owners to agree to unequal distribution of their joint
product. These are the steps I will now contest.
Is Unequal Division ofjointly Owned Resources Irrational?
The first of Cohen’s two rationality-based arguments concerns the
division of assets (“appropriation”).He rejects individual or subgmup
230
zyxwvutsr
zyxwv
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxwvuts
Critical Review Vol. J2, No. 3
zyxwvu
zyx
division or appropriation of jointly owned assets on the grounds that
“B might have good reason to exercise his right to forbid an appro-
priation by A fiom which B himself would benefit. For, if he forbids
A to appropriate, he can then bargain with A about the share of out-
put he will get if he relents and allows A to appropriate. B is then.
likely to improve his take by an amaunt greater than what A would
otherwise have offered him” (Cohen 1995,84). According to Cohen,
B does not seek a more equal distribution of assets, but the improvement of his “share of output” of the jointly owned asset.
It is not at all clear fkom the text how B’s veto threat would “improve his take” unless B might later relent and allow A to appropriate,
in which case the output would no longer be jointly owned and subject to distribution. The argument that B might forbid A’s appropriation in order to hold out for a larger share of output is thus incoherent, for if A were to be allowed to appropriate, there would be no
joint product to share.
Setting aside the above confusion, it bears noting that Cohen is
careful to indicate that an agent “might” have good reason to refhe
an appropriation,for the agent ako might very well have good reasons
to agree to such an appropriation. There are many observable cases,
afiter all, in which jointly owned resources (e.g., in business partnerships and in marriage partnerships) are divided on the basis offiee
agreement. These occasions happen when some one or more of the
following situations obtain:
(A) The parties no longer wish to cooperate, because of differences
unrelated to the physical productivity of cooperation. (They may, for
example, mutually prefer not to be subject to the veto powers of joint
owners over the disposition of jointly owned assets.)
(B) The size or composition of the group of joint owners entails
transaction costs, in corning to agreement over the disposition of the
jointly owned asset, that are greater than the sum of the losses that
would be suffered by even the worst off under a loss of the right to
an aliquot portion of the income stream generated by a jointly
owned asset. This would entail that those who would fare worst
under division could still be compensated for their losses from the resources fieed up by the elimination of the high transaction costs attributable to joint ownership. Under such conditions, and assuming
that the transaction costs of a one-time negotiation and arrangement
of a division were not prohibitively high, then it would be rational
for the joint owners to agree to division of their jointly owned assets.
Palmer Cohen on Property and EquaZity
zyx
zyx
23 I
zyx
zy
(C) One or more of the parties believe that she or they could
manage a subdivided portion of the currently jointly owned resource
better than the collectivity could, thereby generating a surplus. From
this surplus she or they could offer the other joint owners compensation for the lost aliquot portion of the income stream they would
have received h m the asset were it to remain jointly owned.
@) The joint owners differ in their discounting of future income
streams, and have correspondingly different preferences for savings
versus consumption, such that a division into several property would
allow them to allocate income between investment and consumption
differently For example, if A prefers a policy of “Eat, drink, and be
merry, for tomorrow we may die,” whereas B prefers a policy of “A
penny saved is a penny earned” (or if A simply has a shorter time
horizon than B,due to advanced age or impending death, for example), then they may find it impossible to agree on whether to sacrifice
current consumption for future satisfaction, and if so, what would be
the best tradeofE whereas with division, each would be able to satisfj.
her own preference,even if it were to come at the cost of a lower aggregate physical product.
Cohen’s arguments attempt to show that, under conditions of joint
ownership, division (appropriation) resulting in some inequality of assets would be irrational, but his arguments fail to justif+ that conclusion. Cohen is not clear on whether it is appropriation per se or appropriation that would result in unequal distribution of “output” that
matters to him. Whichever it is, though, the argument fails.7
Cohen does allow for the possibility, at least under conditions of
unanimity, of a precisely equal division of initial assets, in the manner
favored by Hillel SreinerS8Joint ownership, unlike equal division,
“forbids a Nozickian formation of unequal private property by placing alI resources under collective control” (Cohen Iggs,~oz).Cohen
(ibid., 10s) admits that, under conditions of unanimity, joint ownership and equal division “may readily be converted into the other.“
But arrangements other than strict equality, and not including the entirety of the human race, or of all rationd agents, seem to be ruled
out tout court?
Of course, if property resources were to be divided and several
property established,joint ownership could be voluntarily reestablished by the several owners agreeingjointly to recombine their assets
into jointly owned assets.1° But Cohen’s insistence that joint owners
zyxw
zyxwvu
zyxwv
232
zyxw
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvuts
Critical Review Vol. 12, No. 3
zyxwv
would not-or would be irrational to-agree to division is unsupported.
Before proceeding to the next serious error in Cohen’s argument, a
short digression about Cohen’s misunderstanding of Nozick is in
order, although this correction is not necessary to show the errors in
Cohen’s reasoning. Cohen (1995, 84) claims that,”Nozick must suppose that the world’s resources are, morally speaking, nothing like
jointly owned, but very much up for grabs, yet, far tiom establishing
that premiss, he does not even bother to state it, or show any awareness that he needs it:’ This is untrue; Nozick (1974,178)clearly states
that he believes that any ownership claim must be justified, whether
collective or individual or mixed: “It is not only persons favoring pivate property who need a theory of how property rights legitimately
originate. Those believing in collective property, for example those
believing that a group of persons living in an area jointly own the territory, or its mineral resources, also must provide a theory of how such
property rights arise; they must show why the persons living there
have rights to determine what is done with the land and resources
there that persons living elsewhere don’t have (with regard to the same
land and resources).” Rather than Nozick being guilty of “not even
bothering to state , . . or show any awareness that he needs” such a
theory, it is Cohen who fails to provide a theory of how or why joint
ownership might be, or might have been, justified, beyond asserting
that it is “intuitively relevant!’
Again, however, this clarification is not essential to showing the
error in Cohen’s argument. Even granting Cohen’s assumption of initial joint ownership, he has failed to show that it would be irrational
to agree to divide ownership of assets.
zyxwv
Is Unequal Division of/ointly Produced Output Ivvational?
Cohen’s second and more complex argument is an attempt to show
that, assuming inescapably joint ownership (i.e., insisting that, contrary to historical experience and the considerations listed above, it
would be irrational to agree to division),’unequalcontributions to a
jointly produced product (i.e., a product to which all factor inputs
save one-labor-are
jointly owned) will result in precisely equal distribution of the joint product (“final equality of condition”). (This
conclusion further assumes equal preference for leisure over labor;
zyxwvu
zyxwvu
zyx
zyx
zyxw
zyx
Palmer
-
Cohen on Property and Equality
233
what Cohen is concerned to show is that unequal marginal productivity, under such conditions, will not result in an unequal distribution of the joint product.) Cohen assumes, like Rawls, that all income
is jointly produced and that the distribution of the joint product is to
be the result of some sort of agreement among the joint owners.
Where Cohen differs fiom Rawls is in granting, for ihe sake ofhis attempted refutation of Nozick,that the parties to the agreement know
what their productive abilities are and have property in those natural
talents. Joint ownership of external resources means that each owner
has a full veto right over any proposed distribution of the joint product, because each has a veto right over the disposition of the factor
inputs, other than labor, that contribute to the production of the joint
product. Thus, Cohen writes that “I entertained an alternative to
Nozick’s ‘up for grabs’ hypothesis about the external world, to wit,
that it is jointly owned by everyone, with each having a veto over its
prospective use. And I showed that final equality of condition is assured when that egalitarian hypothesis about ownership of external
resources is conjoined with the thesis of self-ownership” (14). Carehl
examination demonstrates, however, that Cohen’s arguments do not
show that “final equality of condition is assured!’
Cohet) (1995, 94) proposes that we consider a two-person world,
populated by “Able” and ‘‘hfirrn,” in which there is an asymmetry in
the productive capabilities of the. two parties, who are jointly owners of
all available external resources. In this situation,“Each owns himself and
both jointly own everything else.” Cohen (ibid., 95) then describes
three cases in which b.ar@g
between the two parties is impossible:
zy
I
i. Able cannot pmduce.per day what% needed for one person for a
day, so Able and Infirm both die.
ii. Able can produce enough or more than enough for one person, but
not enough for two, Infirm lets Able produce what he can, since only
spite or envy would lead him nor to. Able lives and Infirm dies.
iii. Able can produce just enough to sustain both himself and Infirm.
So Infirm forbids him to produce unless he produces that much. Able
consequently does, and both live at subsistence.
In these three cases there is no surplus over which to bargain. The
two cases in which bargaining over a surplus might take place are de-
scribed as follows:
.
234
zyxwvuts
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvutsr
Critical Review Vol.12, No.3
iv. If Able produces at all, then the amount he produces is determined
independently of his choice, and it exceeds what is needed to sustain
both Able and Infirm. They therefore bargain over the distribution of
a fixed surplus. The price of failure to agree (the ‘threat point’) is no
production, and, therefore, death for both.
zyxwvu
v. Again, Able can produce a surplus, but now, more realistically, he can
vary its size, so that Able and Infirm will bargain not only, as in (iv),
over who gets how much, but also over how much will be produced.
(Cohen rg9s. 9s)
zyx
Cohen (1ggs,96) acknowledges that Able and Infrrm may differ in
their preferences for leisure or labor (which he rather oddly characterizes as “the disutility of labour for Able and the disutility of infirmity for Infirm”),11 and that this asymmetry may be a factor in the
bargaining process, presumably allowing divergences from complete
equality of product. Such differences in preferences, Cohen asserts,
are unrelated to abilities. Thus, “the crucial point is that Able’s talent
will nor, just as such, affect how much he gets. If the exercise ofahis
talent is irksome to him, then he will indeed get additional compensation, but only because he is irked, not because it is his labour which
irks him” (ibid.).
Cohen thus tries to establish that under conditions ofjoint ownership of assets, the more productive would never receive a share of
output proportional to productivity or otherwise unequal to purely
egalitarian division, i,esIsimple division of the total product by the
number of joint owners. If Able works 10 hours and picks IOO
bushels of apples and Infirm works 3 hours and picks 10 bushels of
apples, their mutual rationality demands that at the end of the day
Able will receive 5s bushels and Infirm will receive 5s bushels. Perhaps because this is so wildly implausible, Cohen tries to suggest a
reason why Able might get more than $5 bushels after all, to wit, that
picking apples is unpleasant (it “irks” her). This may be the strangest
part of Cohen’s exposition and simply heaps confiasion on confusion,
as he tries to make a distinction without a difference. Cohen conjures
up the distinction between one’s abilities and one’s preferences in
order to justiQ, on the basis of pure rationality, divergences &om strict
egalitarianism. In effect, he argues that if joint owners were to agree
to unequal division, it could only be because of different preferences
for leisure (the irksomeness of labor) and never because of unequal
talenrs or abilities.
zyxwv
zyx
zyx
zy
Palmer Cohen on Property and Equalfty
,
235
zyx
zyx
Thus, Cohen (1gg5,96) states that “if the exercise of [Able’s] talent
is irksome to him, then he will indeed get additional compensation,
but only because he is irked, not because it is his labour which irks
him.” But there is no rneaningfbl sense to the term “additional” here,
since the questions are what amount of product will be produced and
the ratio at which it wiU be shared between Able and Infirm. Infirm
may be able to demand a price for her consent to the use of the
jointly owned assets, but whether she wiu be successful in doing so
and how much she will get depend on her bargaining abilities. Given
that in Cohen’s model leisure and labor are directly convertible, at
least above the mutual subsistence baseline, an irksome decrease of
leisure is precisely convertible into an irksome increase of labor, so if
Able is irked, it must be because of the irksomeness of labor.12
Cohen’s distinction between labor and the irksomeness of labor is
both co&sing and confused. It fails to make his argument any more
plausible.
Cohen also assumes that the outcome will be in the form of a percentage share and argues that a solso split is the only rational outcome. A percentage split in the case of Able and Infirm would be
unlikely in scenario v, in any case, since, for any percentage split
(40160, $o/so, or whatever) of output and any quantity of labor
input, a lump-sum distribution to Infrm would be preferable fiom
both Infirm’s and Able’s perspectives. Consider the case of Cohen’s
preferred so/$o split at the expenditure of Able’s labor that produces
100 units of product. Infirm and Able will each receive 50 units,
meaning that Able faces a so percent average tax rate and a so percent marginal tax rate. By accepting a lump-sum payment of 50 units
plus I, Infirm is made better off and Able’s marginal tax rate over 51
units is reduced to zero, which, if he has a normally shaped supply
curve for labor, will generate a larger expenditure of labor. Thus, both
Able and Infirm would be better off by substituting a lump-sum payment to Infirm for her agreement to allow Able to labor on the
joinrly owned resources; hence, Cohen’s insistence on a so/so split of
output, regardless of the amount of output, is not to the advantage of
either party, Cohen’s argument for a strictly egalitarian (50/50) distribution of income fails even at the level of insisting that a percentage
of final product is rationally preferable to a lump-sum payment.
I now turn to the most serious confbsion in Cohen’s convoluted
argument. The fact that Infirm has a full veto power over Able’s ef-
zyxwv
zyxwvu
zyxwvuts
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxw
zy
zy
1:
236
Critical Review
MI. 32, No.3
forts entails, according to Cohen, that the distribution of the product
will not be influenced by Able’s greater ability. Able
gets nothing extra just because it is he, and not. Infirm,who does the
producing. Infirm controls one necessary condition of production (relaxing his veto over use of the land), and Able controls two, but that
gives Able no bargaining advantage. If a good costs $iPr, and you have
one hundred of the dollars and I only have one of them, then, if we
are both rational and seK-interested. you will not get a greater share of
the good if we buy it joinilyjust because you supply so much more of
what is required to obtain it. (Cohen 1ggs,96)
This claim is based on a confusion, however, as it assumes that “ a
good costs 8101’’
(my italics), ie., that there is no variability in the
ratio of inputs and outputs. (For $101 you get the minimal amount of
the good, but for $100you get none, and for $102 you get no more.)
Cohen is here confusing cases iii and iv with case v, which is the
more normal and certainly the most interesting case. Cohen has stipulated in cases iii and iv that Able cannot decide to produce more or
less, so the total product to be divided is rigidly fNed.
Both of these scenarios are radically different &om the situation
described by case v, for in this (most realistic) case the input of labor
is variable, so there is not “ a good” costing a fxed amount, as there is
in cases iii (where the maximum possible product is the minimum
necessary to sustain both Able and Infirm) or iv (where the only possible output is greater than the minimum necessary to pustain both
Able and Infirm, but variation of neither input nor output is possible). In case v, both factor input and product are variable. Able has
the option of varying her expenditure of labor in return for varying
product; if the $100were to represent the amount of labor necessary
to sustain both Able and Infirm, and the $I were the relaxing of Infirm’s veto over Able’s activities, then the interesting question is what
would happen to the increased production made possible by Able’s
additional investments of $ 5 , $30, $68.43, etc., since Infirm has nothing other than the magical $I (necessary to make production possible) to contribute. All that we can say with certainty is that, given
Cohen’s assumptions, Infirm will receive at least the minimum necessary to sustain her, as she would not, under any circumstances,agree
to less; above that it is a matter of bargaining. Puce Cohen, there is no
reason to insist that any increased production over the input of Able’s
$100 and Infirm’s $I would be shared equally. The distribution de-
*
zyxwvu
zyxwv
zy
zyxwv
zy
zyx
Palmer * Cohen on Property and Equality
337
pen& not only on Able’s preferences for leisure over labor, but also
on the expectations of the parties, and this involvement of expecta-
tions by itself entails a radical indeterminacy of result, for, as Thomas
Schelling (1960,~)
points out, such situations “ultimately involve an
element of pure bargaining-bargaining in which. each party is
guided mainIy by his expectations of what the other Will accept. But
with each guided by expectations and knowing that the other is too,
expectations become compounded.”
In a case of the sort that Cohen describes, in bargaining over a surplus the bargainer who can precommit credibly will get the share she
prefers, so long as the other party has not precommitted simultane~ u s l y .What
* ~ Cohen’s remarks tell us is that G. A. Cohen has committed himself, through the vehicle of his published writings, to a
certain strategy (fully equal division) in the sorts of cases that he describes (as it would, presumably, entail a loss of face or of academic
reputation if he were to practice other than he preaches). Anyone
who finds herselfin a pure bargaining situation with G. A. Cohen
. may expect that the only viable move will be to demand one-half of
whatever is at stake-no more and no less-which is the complementary equilibrium strategy to an irrevocably committed strategy of
demanding one half.14But that strategy may not work with bargainers other than G.A. Cohen. Strict egalitarianism is not the uniquely
rational bargaining strategy that Cohen claims it is.
Cohen believes that his example of the $100 and the $I necessary
jointly to purchase a good proves that “there will be no . . . inequality, or its source will not be Able’s ownership of his own powers, but
the influence of the parties’ utility functions on the outcome of the
bargaining process.” This conclusion has not, however, been supported by Cohen’s arguments.
Cohen proceeds to consider what he calls “a relatively minor objection to the argument” which is, however, fatal to Cohen’s claim
that “self-ownership” conjoined with joint ownership of everything
else will necessarily result in equal income.
The objeztion is that an owner of a factor of production could
threaten to destroy the factor or,what amounts to the same thing (all
relevant effects being relative here), to allow it to decay in value or to
fail to augment its productivity, Able, in the cases considered above
(iv and v), “has it in his power to let (part of) his talent decay”
(Cohen 1ggs,97). However, according to Cohen (ibid., 97), ‘What is
unclear, because of difficulties in the concept of rationality is whether
zyx
238
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvuts
zyxw
Crltical Review Vol. 12, No. 3
such a Schellingian threat would be credible, and, therefore, effective,
under the assumption h a t everyone is rational. If it would be, then those
z
zy
with greater power to produce could get more in a jointly owned
world for reasons which go beyond the consideration that their labour
.
’
might be irksome to them” (emphasis orginal). (In an earlier published
version of the essay Cohen 11986, 821 had written,“What I do not
know how to assess, because of my uncertain grasp %f bargaining theory, is whether such a Schellingian threat would be credible. . . !’)
Cohen (1995.97) dismisses this objection as “minor” because “it
achieves purchase only in the rather peculiar case in which Able can
indeed diminish his own productive power.” Cohen implies that Able
would threaten to diminish her own present powers, perhaps by cutting off her feet or blinding herselt and Cohen seems to believe that
such a strategy may be less than credible. But let us look at the cases
Cohen describes in which such a threat might be made. Such a strategy would be pointless in cases i and ii, and would not be credible in
case iii, since the maximum product is stipulated to be only enough
to sustain Able and Infirm, with no surplus available for bargaining,
so that the outcome is clear: Infirm w
ill insist that Able work and
produce the maximum possible, which is precisely enough to sustain
them both (regardless of whether it is distributed equally), but no surplus is available for distribution above survival level. Such a strategy
may or may not be credible in case iv, in which labor inputs cannot
vary but there is a surplus available for distribution; the credibility is
entirely a matter of Able’s ability to commit herself and to convince
Infirm that she will abide by the threat, which may be difficult to do
in the absence of a third party with whom to contract for enforcement, or some other way to limit Able’s post-agreement options. (It
bears noting that Infirm could also precommit to demanding onehalf‘, or a greater-than-one-half‘ share, as well; nothing in case iv stops
Infirm from precommitting to exercise her veto in order to extract a
greater-than-equal share of the surplus potentially available for bargaining.) But Cohen cannot conclude fiom the unavailability of such
a strategy in case iii, and the questionable credibility of such a strategy
in case iv, that it is not credible in the much-more-realistic scenario
of case v, in which labor inputs can vary over the amount necessary
to ensure that both Able and Infiim are sustained and that a correspondingly variable surplus can be generated by Able’s labor; all that
Able has to do in case v is exercise her claim rights and liberty righa
not to work, i.e., to withdraw her labor &om the productive process.
,
zyxwv
zyx
zyx
zyx
zyx
Paher Cohen on Property and Equality
239
Given the disutility of labor that Cohen presupposes, ie., that each
unit of disvalued labor can be converted into a unit of valued leisure,
and the fact that only Able has the power and the right to decline to
work, Able’s threatened refusal to work is a highly credible strategy,
indeed. Thus, it is not incredible that Able would refuse to work beyond the labor necessary for both Able and Infirm to subsist without
being compensated in accordance with, say, her marginal product.
To clarify matters further, we can distinguish two cases. In the first,
one allows one’s ability to decay by eliminating one’s own options.
(Burning one’s bridges can increase one’s bargaining power, and such
moves are neither irrational nor otherwise objectionable; they are
quite common to bargaining situations,) In the second case, on which
I have focused, one simply withdraws one’s labor, but without diminishing one’s productive capacity or otherwise limiting one’s options.
Either is a credible strategy, although the latter is certainly more commonly observed. It is precisely the strategy of “going on strike” that
Cohen (xgg5,zso) condemns-consistendy for a socialist “saddened”
by what looked, at the time Cohen wrote one of the essays in the
book, “to be the impending final abandonment of the Bolshevik experiment.” Strikes, after all, were not allowed in the Soviet Union. In
response to the libertarian challenge, Cohen seeks to root out of socialist theory the idea that one has a right to property in one’s person,in one’s labor, or in one’s product.
zyxwvu
The Reality of Socialist Practice
Cohen writes as if his experiment has never in fact been carried out
in practice and that we have only his a priori speculation as the basis
for thinking rationally about the joint-ownership scenario that he describes. But: there is ample experience of joint ownership being imposed on people, and it does not bear out Cohen’s conclusions in any
way. The Engsh colony at Jamestown offers a clear example of what
happens when joint ownership is imposed on those living on land
that was “good and fiuitfull.” As one eyewitness wrote:
So great was our famine, that a Savage we slew and buried, the poorer
sorte tooke him up agine and eat him;and so did divers one another
boyled and stewed with roots and herbs. It were too vile to say, and
scarce to be beleeved, what we endured but the occasion was our
240
zyxwvu
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvuts
zyxwv
Critical Review Vol. 12, No. 3
own, for want of providence, industrie and government, and not the
barrennesse and defect of the Country, as is generally supposed. (In
Bethell 1998,34)
Sir Thomas Dale, upon his arrival in Virginia in May of 1611,noted
that the colonists were bowling in the streets rather than working. It
was the introduction of several property that put an end to the “starving hime” that resulted f%omjoint ownership of assets and egalitarian
distribution of the joint product.
Cohen’s experiment was also tried at Plymouth Colony a few years
later. As Governor W
illiam Bradford noted:
The experience that was had in this common c o m e and condition,
tried sundry years and that among godly and sober men, may well
evince the vanity of that conceit of Plato’s and other ancients applauded by some of later times: that the taking away of property and
bringing in community into a commonwealth would make them
happy and flourishing; as if they were wiser than God. For this community (so far as it was) was found to breed much confksion and discontent and retard much employment that would have been to their
benefit and comfort. For the young men, that were most fit and able
for labour and service, did repine that they should spend their time
and strength to work for other men’s wives and children without any
recompense. The strong, or man of parts, had no more in division of
victuals and clothes than he that was weak and not able to do a quarter
the other could; this was thought injustice. The aged and graver men
to be ranked and equalized in labours and victuals, clothes, etc., with
the meaner and younger sort, thought it some indignity and disrespect
unto them. And for men’s wives to be commanded to do service for
other men, as dressing their meat, washing their clothes, etc., they
deemed it a kind of slavery, neither could many husbands well brook
it. Upon the point all being to have alike, and all to do alike, they
thought themselves in the like condition, and one as good as another;
and so,if it did not cut o b those relations that God hath set among
men, yet it did at least much diminish and take off the mutual respects
that should have been preserved amongst them. And would have been
worse if they had been men of another condition. Let none object this
is men’s corruption, and nothing to the course itsell: I answer, seeing
all men have this corruption in them, God in His wisdom saw another
course fitter for them. (In Bethell 1 9 9 8 , ~ ~ )
zyxwvu
When Cohen’s thought experiment has been run in reality, it turns
out that Able (“the strong, or man of parts”) does not agree to work
zyxwv
zyx
zy
Palmer Cohen on Pyoperty and Equality
241
hard and then share equally with Infirm (“he that was weak and not
able to do a quarter the other could“), but simply refuses to work, resulting in starvation for all.
The extreme egalitarian typically blames the moral failings of the
parties involved, rather than the abolition or attenuation of several
property for the failures of such collectivist schemes. Thus, Cohen
zy
zyxwvu
(rggsa, 396) has criticized the reliance on incentives, in the form of
the possibility of unequal holdings or unequal division, with which
Rawls amends pureIy equal division of assets and income, on the
grounds that it effectively institutionalizes immorality:
My principal cot&ention about Rawls is that (potential) high fliers
would forgo incentives properly so-called in a f
d compliance society
governed by the difference principle and characterized by fraternity
and universal dignity. I have not rejected the Mereme principle in its
lax reading as a principle of public policy: I do not doubt that there
are contexts where it is right to apply it, What I have questioned is its
description as a principle of (basic) justice, and I have deplored Rawls’s
willingness to describe those a t the top end of a society governed by it
as undergoing the fullest possible realization of their m o d natures.
Recall, however, Governor Bradford’s observation that joint ownership and enforced equal division failed miserably “amongst godly and
sober men” and “would have been worse if they had been men of another condition.” To what, then, are we to attribute the fact that such
schemes result, not in harmony and prosperity, but in famine and cannibalism?Who or what bears the blame? The question was never put
more directly than by Vasily Grossman (1986,164),a witness to the
imposition of joint ownership on the peasant farmers in Ukraine:
zy
Some went insane. They never did become completely still. One
could tell from their eyehecause their eyes shone. These were the
people who cut up and cooked corpses, who killed their own children
and ate them. In them the beast rose to the top as the human being
died. 5 saw one. She had been brought to the district center under
convoy. Her face w a s human, but her eyes were those of a wolf. These
are cannibals, they said, and must all be shot. But they themselves, who
. drove the mother to the madness of eating her own children, are evidently not guilty at all! For that matter, can you really find anyone
who is guilty? Just go and ask, and they will all tell you that they did it
for the sake of virtue, for everybody’s good. That’s why they drove
mothers to cannibalism!
242
zyxwv
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvuts
zyxw
zy
Critical Review Y,l. 12, No.3
It would require too long a digression to offer a full critique of
what is wrong with blaming the victims of communism for failing to
live up to its “high” moral standards. I will merely suggest an hypothesis that seems simpler and more straightforward than the claim that
human beings have not yet proven good enough for socialism: social. ism is not good enough for human beings.
Cohen errs in thinking that rational parties would never refuse to
work or bargain or allow their abilities to decay if they were not
compensated unequally. He simply dismisses the possibility: “No
libertarian would want to defeat the Ablehfirm argument (for the
consistency of equality and self-ownership) on so adventitious a
basis” (Cohen r995,97).According to Cohen (ibid., 97-98), the libertarian “would want, instead, to overcome it by pressing . , , [a]
more fundamental objection , that to affirm joint ownership of
the world is, as the story of Able and Infirm might be thought to
show, inconsistent with achieving the purpose and expected effect
of self-ownership.” But Cohen’s hypothetical opponent need not
choose on which basis to refute Cohen’s arguments, for the
Able/Infirm story does not show what Cohen claims that it shows,
Cohen has not demonstrated that joint owners would not or should
not agree to division of their assets; nor that the distribution of a
surplus over what is necessary to sustain both Able and Infirm must
be evenly divided; nor that Able couId not bargain for a greater
share on the basis of a threat to diminish her productivity or her
productive effort. Finally, real-world experience with joint ownership contradicts Cohen’s rosy egalitarian description and raises the
issue of why joint ownership should ever be seriously considered in
the first place.
.
..
Positive vs. Negative Community
Cohen’s conclusions are frequently repeated, but his arguments are
rarely read. Those arguments fail to show that property in one’s person is irrelevant to the distribution of wealth and income, even accepting their underlying assumptions.
Cohen does direct our attention, perhaps contrary to his intentions, to the question of why joint ownership should be assumed in
the first place. No argument is given as to why such assers should be
assumed, even for the sake of argument, to be jointly owned; they
*.1 ’
*.:
t :
z .:
i...
ri’:..
!
I
?.
i-
<-
.
..
.
zyxwv
zyx
zyx
Palmer Cohen on Property and Equality
243
may be, but why must or should they be? Classical liberals and libertarians are open on the question of whether particular bits of land or
other resources should be consideredjointly or individually owned.15
What is unatgued for by Cohen (aside fiom asserting that it is “intuitively relevant”), but is of dubious plausibility, is the idea that every
resource other than our own persons should be considered the joint
property of all human beings, or perhaps of all rational agents. If rational agents were to be discovered on Mars, would the joint owners
of Earth be required to obtain the permission of every rational Martian before any terrestrial resource might be used, and would the
agreement have to be unanimous across species? This would be a
strange basis on which to build a theory of jurisdiction over scarce
resources. As almost all previous writers on property have emphasized, requiring the permission of everyone before anyone could pick
an apple would result in the extinction of humanity. Joint ownership
. requiring unanimous approval to every act of transformation of resources is ultimately rejected by Cohen, on the ground that it interferes with any reasonable sense of autonomy, but it is not clear why it
should even be entertained in the first place.
There may be good reasons to believe that very early in its actual
history, property took one of various forms of positive community,
principally familial, as Fustel de Coulanges (1864), Maine (1888), and
other anthropologists and historians of property have shown; but that
is not Cohen’s argument. Nor are the forms of positive community
described by legal historians consistent with the egalitarian ownership
described by Cohen as “joint ownership,”for they did not encompass
all humans or all rational agena, but were always forms of community
that established rights against all nonmembers ofthe owning communities. As Locke noted of common property, “And though it be common, in respect of some Men, it is not so to a l l Mankind, but is the
joint property of this Country, or this Parish” (Zuo nedises, 11.35). In
this respect, “negative community~’i.e., the idea that all have a right
to appropriabe unowned objects, is a far more egalitarian starting
point than any form of “positive community,”which in every form
ever observed was a nonuniversal, group-limited right. This issue was
carefully considered by the modern natural-law writers on property,
who distinguished between negative community and positive community, the latter corresponding to the joint ownership that Cohen
proposes as the pmper baseline.16
It is remarkable that figures such as Cohen persistently overlook
zy
zyxw
244
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvut
Critical Review Vol.12, No.3
the distinction between negative and positive community when considering claims, by Locke and other writers on several property, that,
prior to appropriation, the world was open to mankind in common.
As Pufendorf (1994,178) noted quite explicitly,
’
It is plain that before all human agreements there was a=communionof
a l l things. Not a positive communion, of course, but a negative one;
that is, all things were available to all and belonged no more to one person than to another. But since things are not use&l to men unless at
zy
zyx
least their fmits are laid hold of, and indeed, since this is done in vain if
others are in turn allowed to seize what we have already actively intended for our own use, the first agreement among mortals concerning
things is understood to have been this: Whatever anyone had taken for
himself from the common stock or its fruits, with the intention of using
it for himself, would not be seized from him by another.
Cohen reproduces the argument against liberal property put forth
an apologist for royal absolutism:
by Sir Robert Pilmer (1991,234),
Certainly it is a rare felicity that all the men in the world at one instant
of time should agree together in one mind to change the natural community of things into private dominion. For without such an unani- .
mous consent it was not possible for community to be altered. For if
but one man in the world had dissented, the alteration had been unjust, because that man by the law of nature had a right to the common
use of all things in the world, so that to have given a property of any
one thing to any other had been to have robbed him of his right to
the common use of all things.
Locke, who was replying to Filmer, rejected joint ownership of this
sort (in which each joint owner has a veto right, requiring unanimity
for anything to be appropriated and consumed) as a baseline: “If such
a consent as that was necessary, Mankind had starved, notwithstanding
the Plenty God had given him” (flu0neutises, 11.28). By asserting
property in one’s person, Locke managed to avoid the trap set by
Filmer, for
Though the Earth, and all inferior Creatures be common to all Men,
yet every Man has a Property in his own Person. This no Body has any
Right to but himself. The Labour of his Body, and the Work of his
Hands, we may say, are properly his. Whatsoever then he removes out
of the State that Naturehaih provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his
zyxwvu
zyx
zyx
zy
zyx
Pulmer * Cohen on Property and Equality
245
Labour with, and joyned to it something that is his own, and thereby
makes it his Properfy. (Ibid., 11.27)’’
It is property in one’s person that justifies the appropriation of that to
which everyone earlier had a right. Cohen’s attempted.rebuttal does
not shake this connection; Cohen’s case against libertariatlism rests on
basic errors of reasoning and fails on its own terms.
There are certainly many observable scenarios in which one or
another form of joint ownership is highly desirable, such as partnerships, co-ops, various sorts of clubs and religious institutions, and
marriages, but there is no reason to posit that joint ownership is the
only rational or desirable arrangement, nor that property in severalty is irrational or immoral. Nor does Cohen even offer any good
reason as to why joint ownership should be seriously entertained at
all; the only justification that Cohen offers for attempting to work
through the logic of joint ownership is that joint ownership is “intuitively plausible.” To say that one’s intuition tells one that a claim
is reasonable or probable is hardly to offer an argument on its behalf’,
and, in any case, ‘‘joint ownership” or “positive community” has
certainly been considered by defenders of several property and decisively rejected for very good reasons, as opposed to mere intuition.
Finally, Cohen has failed to demonstrate that the unequal division
of joint products is irrational (much less. that it is immoral).
The central pillars of Cohen’s polemic against conjoining property
in one’s person with several property rest on errors of reasoning; his
argument against the conjunction of property in one’s person with
several property will have to proceed without his often-cited but erroneous claims about the bargaining situation of self-owners who
own the world jointly. His bare assertion of the “plausibility” of positive community is not an argument for a policy that has been rejected
for clear and compelling reasons by many other writers on the topic.
It may be that libertarian claims about the conjunction of property
in one’s person and property in the world are false, but, if so,it is not
for the reaso‘ls that Cohen has advanced.
zyxwvu
NOTES
r. Cohen’s criticisms have appeared in numerous forms and publications, notably Cohen 1985,Cohen r986a, Cohen 1986b, and Cohen 1989,and have
been revised and collected together in Cohen 1995.
I
’
246
2.
zyxwv
zyxwvu
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxwvutsr
Critical Review Val.
12,
zyxwi
No. 3
Other recent works that have cited without criticism or have incorporated
at least some of Cohen’s basic claims into their critique of several property
include Waldron 1988, Munzer 1990,Ingram 1994, Haworth 1.994, Christ-
f
man 1gg4a and ~ggbb,and Sreenivasan 1995. Cohen’s approach has been
criticized by David Gordon (1990)and by Jan Narveson (~ggo),although
?%
i$
without raising the problems I point out in this critique. Unlike the criticisms of Gordon and Narveson, my rehtation of Cohen’s central arguments
is immanent.
3. Part of Weinberg’s claim is that Cohen’s critique of libertarian views on liberty is a decisive refutation of libertarians’ claims to be defenders of fieedom.
I deal with that issue in my separate reply to Friedman in this issue of Critical
Review, in response to his claim that “one stipulative definition is as good as
so I will instead focus my criticism here on
another” (Friedman 1997,432)~
Cohen’s critique of “self-ownership,” which Weinberg (1997,324)considers
to be, if anything, “too sympathetic an analysis of libertarian concepts.”
Weinberg cites in support of this claim a particularly outlandish attack on
Cohen by Brian Barry for even bothering to address classical liberalism at all.
(See Barry 1996 and Cohen’s response [1gg6].)
4. Cohen quite oddly proceeds to define each person’s property in herself in
terms of its very negation, viz., “According to the thesis of self-ownership,
each person possesses over himself, as a matter of moral right, all those rights
that a slaveholder has over a complete chattel slave as a matter of legal right,
and he is entitled, morally speaking, to dispose over himself in the way that a
slaveholder is entitled, legally speaking, to dispose over his slave” (68).This is
a strange way of understanding “selCownership,” one that would not generally be endorsed by defenders of property in one’s person, but which has
been taken up as paradigmatic by many who have recently followed in
Cohen’s footsteps. The possibility of the inalienability of certain rights is a
clear case in which the (illegitimate)property claimed by a slaveholder in her
slaves is misleading, rather than illuminating, as a paradigm of property in
one’s person, Although misleading in other respects, the definition need not
be disputed to show that Cohen’s conclusions do not follow from his
premises.
5. See for a correction Gordon 1990,78-80. Gordon (1990.83) also takes
Cohen to task for “seizing on the exact words while ignoring their sense” in
misunderstanding Nozick‘s point concerning redistribution of wealth gained
under a determinate system of rights-namely, that “things come into the
worJd already attached to people having entitlements over them” (Nozick
1974,x6o)as a claim about inifid appropriation.
6. Cohen is demanding, in effect, that it be shown not merely that appropriation may be permissible, but that it must be optimal as well. See the discussion
of the two kinds ofjustification in Simmons 1994.
7. It is worth noting that even “indivisible” goods can be divided on the basis
of agreement, and quite commonly are. H. Peyton Young describes “eight
I.:
.$:
g.
*g
@.
$
g
<,<.
>I.
z
1;
f:
jij
t:;
I
f ..i
ti
!
I‘I;.:
t‘i;I.’
I:
!’
i
i
:
zyxwvutsr
zyx
zyxwvu
zyxwvutsrqponmlkji
zy
zyxw
Palmer. Cohen on Property and Equality
247
fairly universal techniques for defining ex ante property rights in an indivisible good” (Young 1996,373).
I
8, See, for example, Steiner 1994,especially the epilogue on just redistributions.
9. It is worth pointing out that, in many actual cases,joint-ownership arrange-
ments have generated voluntary divisions of land (as also of other resources),
and Cohen offers no evidence that the joint owners who. have agreed to division were suffering kom irrational delusions. For some of the relevant literature and case studies, see Ellickson 1993. especially 1388-92, and Libecap
1989. For a historical study of voluntary division of jointly held common
property, see Norberg 1988. Norberg (1988,a68) notes, of popular votes on
division of common lands in Revolutionary France, that “whether the peasants voted €or or against partition, they generally did so by very large mar. gins, often unanimously.” Of communities with commons, 71.gs percent
voted for partition in the 1793 referenda (ibid., 271).
10. The conditions under which such arrangements prove mutually beneficial
are set out and used to illuminate case studies in Lueck 1993.
11. It is not clear how Infirm’s infirmity can be a source of disutility for her in
the way that Able’s labor is a source of disutility for her, as Infirm cannot, by
hypothesis, vary her infirmity in the way that Able can vary her labor effort.
Whether it was Cohen’s intention or not, such remarks color the situation he
describes by engaging natural feelings of sympathy for the unfortunate,
thereby introducing elements that are not explicitly acknowledged in the description of the bargaining situation. Such feelings of sympathy are also
brought to the fore by the specification of the bargaining situation as one of
IWO persons dealing with one another face to face, and therefore probably on
an intimate, and not on an anonymous, basis, rather than the situation of
anonymous interaction among strangers who do not meet each other face to
face. Thus, although Cohen (19gs,gs)
stipulates that Able and Infirm are “rational, self-interested, and mutually disinterested,” the situation he describes is
not the sort in which such motivations are common, and his description
evokes sentiments that are common to small-group, face-to-face, and intimate settings. The importance of distinguishing between the two kinds of
settings has been highlighted by E A. Hayek (1988,IS), who points out that
“the structures of the extended order are made up not only of individuals
but also of many, often overlapping, sub-orders within which old instinctual
responses, such as solidarity and altruism, continue to retain some importance
by assisting voluntary collaboration, even though they are incapable, by
themsehres, of creating a basis for the extended order. Part of our present difficulty is that we must constantly adjust our lives, our thoughts and our emotions, in order to live simultaneously within different kinds of orders according to different rules. , So we must learn to live in two sorts of worlds at
once!’
12. A nail is driven into the “preference vs. productivity” coflin by Alexander
Rosenberg (1988,IS), who notes that “the economic effects of a talent or a
disability may be exactly the same as those of a preference or taste,” using the
..
248
zyxwv
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvutsr
Critical Review Yo(. 12, No. 3
example of acrophobia or acrophilia and the talent for tree climbing among
coconut harvesters; the preference for high places would generate an economic “rent” (or profit) indistinguishable tiom the “rent” or profit generated
by a talent for climbing, and thus preferences and talents are difficult, if not
impossible, to distinguish.
r3. The party who can make an “irrevocable comqitment” will be able to
“squeeze the range of indeterminacy down to the point most favorable to
him“ (Schelling 1960,24).
14. For a treatment of complementary strategies, see Sugden 1986.6749.
IS. For an informed discussion of the variety of land regimes possible and consistent with classical liberal views, see Bllickson 1993.
16. The issue is usefully canvassed in Buckle rg91, especially 36,93, 104-5,
16447, and 183-87. See also the careful discussion of the issue in Pufendorf
1994,especially 176-8s.
17.Alan Ryan (1994) criticizes the notion of “property in one’s person,’’ but he
does not consider the advantages to the concept of “property in” objects.
Contemporary imprecise English usage identifies property and object; thus, I
might say that “this land [watch, book, etcJ is my property? The older usage
of speaking of having “a property in a thing” is far more precise and resects
the complex multiplicity of property arrangements that are possible and that
are fully compatible with the libertarian defense of several property Thus, it
may be that each of many different persons has “a property” in a piece of
land; one has the right to live on it, another has the right to walk across it,
yet another has the right to the rental income from it, and so on. As the
Roman lawyers and the modern law-and-economics scholars realize, “ownership” normally represents a bundle of such rights. Presenting the rights that
one has over oneself (not to be raped, not to be killed, not to be beaten, to
express one’s opinions, to consent to one’s marriage, and pthcr bourgeois indulgences) as property in one’s person allows the legal system to rest on a coherent and integrated foundation. The transition fiom the classical formulation (“person X has a propercy in object Y”)to the modern and less precise
formulation (“object Y is X’s property”) has made legal discussion less clear
and has led-in the attempt to focus attention on the right rather than the
object-to the formation of such concepts as “property rights,’’ which means
“right rights.”James Madiron (1983,266)
made a valiant attempt to retain the
precision of the classical formulation, and to relate the righo to keedom of
speech and religion to the rights to dominion over land and other objects, in
his essay “Property”:
zy
This term in its particulat application means ‘that dominion which one
man claims and exercises over the external things of the world, in exclusion of every other individual.’ In its larger and juster meaning, it
embraces every thing to which a man may attach a value and have a
right; and which leaves to euey one else the like adwntage. In the former
sense, a man’s land, or merchandise, or money is called his property In
the latrer sense, a man has a property in his opinions and the free com-
zy
.
zyx
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvu
zyxwvu
zyx
zyxwvu
zyxwv
Palmer Cohen on Property and Equality
249
munication of them. He has a property of particular value in his religious opinions, and in the profession and practice dictated by them. He
has a property very dear to him in the safety and liberty of his person.
He has an equal property in the free use of his faculties and free choice
of the objects on which to employ them. In a word, as a man is said to
have a right to his property, he may be equally said t6. have a property
in his rights.
REFERENCES
Barry, Brian. 1996.“You have to be crazy to believe it!’ Times Literary Supplement,
October 25.
Bethell, Tom. 1998. rite Noblest 7Eumpli: Property and ProsperifyThrough the Ages.
New York St. Martin’s Press.
Buckle, Stephen. 1991. Natural Law and die TIIeory of Properly. Oxford Clarendon
Press.
Christman, John. rgg4a. “Distributive Justice and the Complex Structure of
Ownership.” PliNosophy and Public Ajairs 2 3 : aaj-so.
Christman, John. 1994b. The Myth of Property: Toward an Egalitarian Theory of
Ownership. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cohen, G. A. 1985. “Nozick on Appropriation.” New L.e? Review no. 150: 89-105.
Cohen, G. A. 1986a. “Self-Ownership, World-Ownership, and Equality’’ In Justice
and EquaNty Here and Now, ed. Frank S. Lucash. lthaca: Cornell University
Press.
Cohen, G. A. 1986b. “Self-Ownership, World Ownership. and Equality: Part 11.”
Social Philosophy &.Policy 3(2): 77-96.
Cohen, G. A. r989. “Are Freedom and Equality Compatible?” In Alternafiues fo
Capitalism, ed. Jon Elster and Karl Ove Moene. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Cohen, G. A. IggSa. “Incentives, Inequalityl and Community” In Equal Freedom:
Selected Tanner Lectures on Human Yaues, ed. Stephen Darwall. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press.
Cohen, G. A. rggsb. Seljownetsh@, Freedom, and Equality. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Cohen. G.A. 1996.“Self-ownership and the libertarian challenge:“ Times Literary
supplement, November 8.
de Coul&ges, Numa Denis Fustel. [IS&] 1956. The Ancient City:A Study on die
Religion, Laws, and Institurions of Greece and Rome. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor.
Ellickson, Robert C. 1993.“Propertyin Land.” Yale Lawjournal 102: 1315-1440.
Filmer, Sir Robert. 1991,“Observations Concerning the Originall of Government, upon Mr. Hobs ‘Leviathan,’ Mr. Milton against Salmasius, H.Grotius
‘De Jure Bell?!’ In idem, Patriarcha and Other Writings, ed. Johann P. Sommerville. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
z
z
z
zyxwvut
zyxwv
zyxw
zyxw
zyxwvuts
zyxwvu
..-.
as0
Critical Review Vol. la, No.3
Priedman, Jeffrey. 1997.“What’s Wrong with Libertarianism.” Critical Review
\;
lI(3): 407-67.
Gordon,David. 1990.Resurrecting Maw: The Analytical Mamists on Freedom, Expfoitation, andlustice, New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Books.
2;
i’
I::
Grossman,Vassily 1986.Forever Flowing. New York:Harper & Row.
Haworth, Alan. 1994. Anti-libertarianism:Markets, Philosophy and Myth. London:
Routledge.
Hayek. E A. 1988. 77te Fatal Conceit:77ie Erma dSocialism, ed. W W. Bartley, 111.
London: Routledge.
Ingram, Attracta. 1994. A Political Tlreory of Rights. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Kymlicka, Will.1990. Contempomry PoWal Philosophy:A n Introductjon, Oxford:
i;
ii.
I
f.
F.
1:
Clarendon Press.
Libecap, Gary D. 1989.“Distributional Issues in Contracting for Property
Rights!’Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 145:6-24.
Lueck, Dean, 1993.“Contracting into the Commons!’ In The Political &conomy
Customs and Culture:informal Solutions to the Commons Problem, ed. Terry L.
Anderson and Randy T. Simmons. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Lidefield.
Madison, James. 1983. “Property? In The Papm ofJames Madison, vol. 14: 6 April
2781-26 Match 2799. Charlonesville:University Press ofVirginia.
Maine, Sir Henry Sumner. 1888. ‘hcturec on the Early Hisfory qfhstitutions. New
York Henry Holt.
Muneer, Stephen R. 1990.A Theory OJ Property. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Narveson,Jan. 1990. Tlre U&ertudunIdea, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Norbeq, Kathryn. 1988. “Dividing Up the Commons: Institutional Change in
Rural France, 1789-1799.“Polltiu and Socfety 1 6265-86.
Nozick, Robert. 1974.Anarchy, State, and Utopia. New York: Basic Books.
Pufendorf, Samuel. 1994.The Politlcal Writings of Samuel Pufendotj ed. Craig L.
Carr, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rosenberg, Alexander. 1988.“The Political Philosophy of Biological Endowments.” Social Phfhophy and Polity 5 ( I ) : 1-31.
Ryan,Alan. 1994.“Self-Ownership, Autonomy, and Property Rights,‘‘ In Property
Rights, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, and JeEey Paul. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Schelling,Thomas. 1960. The Strategy ofCot@cf. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Simmons, A. John. 1994. “Original-Acquisition Justifications of Property,’’ In
Property Rights, ed. Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D.Miller, Jr., and Je&y Paul.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sreenivasan, Gopal. 1995,The Limits ofbckean Rights in Property. Oxford:Oxford
University Press.
Steiner,Hillel. 1994.A n Essay on Rights. Oxfotd:Blackwell.
Sugden, Robert. 1986. The Economiu qf mghts, Co-operation and Wehre. Oxford
B a d Blackwell.
!
i’
I.
I.
I..
1:..;
z
.
i
.
.
i
:t
.
zyxwv
zyx
zyx
zyxwvu
zyxwvu
Palmer Cohen on Property and Equality
ZSI
Waldron, Jeremy, 1988.The Right to Private Property. Oxford Oxford University
Press.
Weinberg, Justin. 1997.“Freedom, Self-Ownership, and Libertarian Philosophical
Diaspora.”Critical Review 11 (3): 323-44,
Young, H. Peyton. 1996.“Dividing the Indivisible:’ In Wise Choices: Dedsions,
Gamec, and Negoriafions,ed. Richard 3. Zeckhauaer, Ralph L. Keeney, and
James K.Sebenius. Boston: Harvard Business School Press.’