COMMUNICATION
THEORY
MEDIA, TECHNOLOGY AND SOCIETY
DAVID HOLMES
Communication Theory
Communication Theory
Media, Technology, Society
David Holmes
SAGE Publications
London ● Thousand Oaks ● New Delhi
© David Holmes 2005
First published 2005
Apart from any fair dealing for the purposes of research or
private study, or criticism or review, as permitted under the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, this publication
may be reproduced, stored or transmitted in any form,
or by any means, only with the prior permission in
writing of the publishers, or in the case of reprographic
reproduction, in accordance with the terms of licences
issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency. Enquiries
concerning reproduction outside those terms should
be sent to the publishers.
SAGE Publications Ltd
1 Oliver’s Yard
55 City Road
London EC1Y 1SP
SAGE Publications Inc.
2455 Teller Road
Thousand Oaks, California 91320
SAGE Publications India Pvt Ltd
B-42, Panchsheel Enclave
Post Box 4109
New Delhi 110 017
British Library Cataloguing in Publication data
A catalogue record for this book is available
from the British Library
ISBN 0-7619-7069-X
ISBN 0-7619-7070-3 (pbk)
Library of Congress Control Number available
Typeset by C&M Digitals (P) Ltd, Chennai, India
Printed in Great Britain by TJ International, Padstow, Cornwall
For Elena
CONTENTS
List of Tables and Figures
Preface
Acknowledgements
1 Introduction – A Second Media Age?
Communication in cybercultures
The overstatement of linguistic perspectives on media
The first and second media age – the historical distinction
Broadcast mediums and network mediums – problems
with the historical typology
Interaction versus integration
2 Theories of Broadcast Media
The media as an extended form of the social – the rise
of ‘mass media’
Mass media as a culture industry – from critical theory to
cultural studies
The media as an apparatus of ideology
Ideology as a structure of broadcast – Althusser
The society of the spectacle – Debord, Boorstin and Foucault
Mass media as the dominant form of access to social
reality – Baudrillard
The medium is the message – McLuhan, Innis and Meyrowitz
3 Theories of Cybersociety
Cyberspace
Theories
Social implications
4 The Interrelation between Broadcast and
Network Communication
The first and second media age as mutually constitutive
Broadcast and network interactivity as forms of
communicative solidarity
ix
x
xv
1
3
4
7
11
15
20
21
23
25
29
31
36
38
44
44
50
72
83
83
86
viii
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Understanding network communication in the
context of broadcast communication
Understanding broadcast communication in the
context of network communication
Audiences without texts
The return of medium theory
Recasting broadcast in terms of medium theory
5 Interaction versus Integration
Transmission versus ritual views of communication
Types of interaction
The problem with ‘mediation’
Medium theory and individuality
Reciprocity without interaction – broadcast
Interaction without reciprocity – the Internet
The levels of integration argument
6 Telecommunity
Rethinking community
Classical theories of community
The ‘end of the social’ and the new discourse of community
Globalization and social context
The rise of global communities of practice
Sociality with mediums/sociality with objects
Post-social society and the generational divide
Network communities
Broadcast communities
Telecommunity
97
101
111
113
118
122
122
135
138
140
144
149
151
167
167
168
171
173
174
177
186
188
206
221
References
226
Index
244
LIST OF TABLES AND FIGURES
Tables
1.1
3.1
3.2
4.1
4.2
5.1
5.2
5.3
The historical distinction between the first and
second media age
10
Digitalization as the basis of convergence, wider
bandwidth and multi-media (the ability to combine
image, sound and text)
Features and types of hot and cool mediums
66
71
The broadcast event
Medium theory as applied to network and
(retrospectively) to broadcast communication
105
Transmission and ritual perspectives compared
John B. Thompson’s instrumental/mediation paradigm
Broadcast and network as forms of communicative
integration
135
137
119
149
Figures
3.1
Transmission model: high integration/low reciprocity
5.1
Ritual model: high integration/high reciprocity
53
147
PREFACE
A theory of communication must be developed in the realm of abstraction. Given
that physics has taken this step in the theory of relativity and quantum mechanics,
abstraction should not be in itself an objection.
N. Luhmann, Art as a Social System, trans. Eva M. Knodt,
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2000, p. 12
What follows is an interdisciplinary communication theory book which
sets out the implications of new communications technologies for media
studies and the sociology of communication.
The cluster of texts which came out over the last decade dealing with
computer-mediated communication (CMC), virtual reality and cyberspace
has significantly established new theoretical domains of research which
have been accepted across a range of disciplines. The current book proposes
to integrate this literature in outline and summary form into the corpus of
communication studies. In doing so it explores the relationship between
media, technology and society. How do media, in their various forms,
extend the social, reproduce the social, or substitute for other aspects of
social life?
Most books dealing with communication and media studies invariably address traditional concerns of content, representation, semiotics
and ideology. Whilst including an appreciation of these approaches, the
current book makes a contribution to theoretical analysis of media and
communications by charting how the emergence of new post-broadcast
and interactive forms of communication has provided additional domains
of study for communication theory, renovated the older domain of broadcast, and suggested fresh ways of studying these older media.
In doing so, this book advances a critique of the ‘second media age’
thesis, which, I argue, has become something of an orthodoxy in much
recent literature. It rejects the historical proposition that a second media
age of new media, exemplified by the Internet, has overtaken or converged
with an older age of broadcast media. Yet at the same time, the value of
analytically distinguishing between the most significant architecture that
is attributed to the first media age – broadcast – and that which is attributed to the second media age – interactive networks – is upheld. The basic
dualism between broadcast and interactivity structures the main themes of
the book. To the extent that individuals in media societies experience
changes in the means of communication as a ‘second media age’, we are
compelled to re-examine the postulated ‘first media age’ in terms of
Preface
xi
medium or network form rather than simply content or ‘text’. The sense in
which this distinction is made should not be confused with questions of
form versus the content of narrative, where content is what a text says, and
the form is how it says it. Rather, a non-textual distinction is being made
here. In doing so, a sociological appreciation of broadcast can be arrived at
rather than a media studies or cultural studies perspective, which is
invariably grounded exclusively in either behaviourist or linguistically
centred approaches to analysis. However, insofar as this book is ‘sociological’, sociology is not being opposed to communication and media studies;
on the contrary, a central argument of the book is that emergence of new
communication environments has more or less forced traditional media
and communication studies to be sociological. For this reason the current
volume is very interdisciplinary (between communication, media and
sociology), but this has less to do with the perspective adopted than with
changes in how media are experienced.
These recent changes in media infrastructure have necessitated a shift
in the order in which communication theory is treated. For example,
information theory, which often prefigures semiotic analysis of media, is
introduced in the current textbook as instructive for the second media
age, where it more appropriately belongs with analyses of the Internet. In
fact, in seeing just how relevant information theory is to CMC rather than
broadcast, it is surprising how significantly it came to figure in studies of
broadcast in the first place. At the same time, the book tries to incorporate
most of the traditions of twentieth-century communication theory in
order to locate their relevance to studying the sociological complexities of
contemporary convergent communications.
Through this argument the distinction between medium and content,
media and messages, is persistently returned to. On the scaffold of these
distinctions the book also presents a central argument about the difference between communicative interaction and integration. With the aid of
recently emerging ‘ritual’ models of communication it is possible to
understand how the technical modes of association manifested in broadcast and interactive communication networks are constitutive of their
own modes of integration. Thus it is possible to identify media-constituted
communities in broadcast communities and so-called ‘virtual communities’, which is to argue that such networks do not so much ‘mediate’ interaction, as facilitate modes or levels of integration to which correspond
specific qualities of attachment and association. It is also to argue that
media-constituted communities aren’t merely a continuation of older
face-to-face or geographic communities by technical means (the mediation argument) but are rather constitutive of their own properties and
dynamics. Of course, such ‘levels’ of integration are not isolated but
co-exist, in ways which are outlined in successive chapters (particularly
Chapters 4 and 5). A third major theme that is explored is the urban and
economic context of media-constituted communities, the way in which
dependence on technical-communicative systems facilitates expanded
xii
COMMUNICATION THEORY
commodification and rationalization of cultural life: spheres which could
never have been so influenced before the emergence of these systems.
It is not only the second media age text which is to be reappraised in
developing the book’s themes but also some classical texts on the sociological dynamics of broadcast as well as key readers pertaining to frameworks
of ‘media studies’. Where this book differs from ‘media studies’ texts is in
integrating the significance of ‘cybersociety’ into the general corpus of communication theory. It does so by way of a critique of the second media age
orthodoxy which imagines a new era that is derived from yet another
progress-driven ‘communications revolution’. At the same time, the discourses of ‘telecommunications convergence’ are critically assessed for
overstating a technologically reductive distinction between ‘broadcast’ and
‘interactivity’ in order that they can be portrayed as undergoing ‘convergence’, again at a solely technological level.
To turn to the chapter composition of the book: the introduction
establishes the rationale guiding the organization of the book: the contrast between broadcast and network forms of communication. The predominance of semiotic accounts of media is criticized as unwarranted,
distracting attention from the techno-social dimensions of media environments. At the same time, a linear model of progression from a first to
a second media age is found to be too simplistic to address the complexity of contemporary media formations. The linear model is premised
largely on an interaction approach to media culture, which in this chapter is counterposed to the more fruitful analyses that are made possible
by ‘integration’ models. A variant of the linear second media age perspective is the ‘convergence’ thesis, which presupposes two media forms
(of broadcast and interactivity) not historically, but technologically.
These themes, of first versus second media age, of a multiplicity of form
versus content, of ‘convergence’ as a product of medium dichotomization, of interaction versus integration, are announced as guiding the development of the whole volume.
Chapters 2 and 3 are stand-alone expositions of theories of ‘broadcast
communication’ and ‘network communication’, respectively. These chapters
introduce key theoretical perspectives that are relevant to understanding
broadcast and network communication. In addition, an historical and
empirical discussion of broadcast in the context of urbanization and the rise
of industrial society is presented, whilst in Chapter 3 the major innovations
which underlie the second media age thesis are considered. Chapter 2 reproduces much of the ‘classical’ literature on media (e.g. theories of ideology)
whilst also recasting it within the macro-framework of the techno-social
medium approach (e.g. Althusser’s often difficult theory of ‘interpellation’
and ‘ideology-in-general’ is re-explained as an effect of the structure of
broadcast. Chapter 3 attempts to formalize the still very young perspectives
on cybersociety and proposes to give them a sense of definition as a way of
ordering the current burgeoning literature. In doing so, it identifies a ‘second
media age’ perspective, a CMC perspective, convergence perspectives and
Preface
xiii
the reclamation of older perspectives (McLuhan, Baudrillard) whose
relevance to cyberculture is arguably greater than it is to media culture.
Chapter 4 considers the interrelation between broadcast and network
mediums1, and argues that they are quite distinct in their social implications but are also parasitic on each other. In this light, what is called ‘convergence’ is really an outcome, rather than a cause, of such parasitism, a
consequence which is mistakenly seen to be only working at the level of
technical causation, or predestined historical telos. But this distinctively
broader meaning of convergence can only be arrived at if correspondingly
broader meanings of network and broadcast are deployed, to spheres not
confined to media and communications. In the context of such criticism,
media technologies, whether they be broadcast or interactive, increasingly
reveal themselves as urban technologies, which are constantly converging
with the logics internal to other urban technologies (the shopping mall, the
freeway). For example, the argument that virtual communities restore the
loss of community that is said to result from the one-dimensionality of
the culture industry does not contrast virtual and ‘physical’ communities,
which can be done by looking at the dialectic between media culture and
urban culture. Raymond Williams’ under-regarded concept of ‘mobile privatization’ is explored as a departure point for the way in which media
extend social relations on the basis of private spatial logics.
Finally, the economic complementarity of broadcast and network
mediums is established. Life on the screen is one in which individuals are,
if they so choose, able to live a culture of communication without the
spectacle and advertising fetishes of broadcast. However, in an abstract
world of communicative association this new mode of ‘communication as
culture’ itself provides a market for communication products, both hardware and software, that is growing on a scale which is rapidly catching up
with the political economy of broadcast.
Chapter 5, ‘Interaction versus Integration’, critiques various models
of interaction (instrumental views of communication, transmission views,
‘mediation’ views) as not being able to adequately address the socializing
and socially constituting qualities of various media and communication
mediums. In doing so it turns its attention toward the promising body of
theory which can be gathered under the heading of ‘ritual communication’. This comprises works such as James Carey’s Communication as
Culture and is informed by anthropological perspectives and New Media
theory. An argument is made for the need to develop an understanding of
‘levels’ of ritual communication: face-to-face, mediated and technically
extended. The advance that John B. Thompson makes in this regard in The
Media and Modernity is a useful stepping stone, but one that is based on
interaction rather than ‘integration’. Integration formulations (Meyrowitz,
Calhoun, Giddens) are then explored in order to demonstrate the shortfalls of the interaction model as well as to sketch a model which can begin
to attend to the complexity of both broadcast and network forms of
communication processes.
xiv
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Chapter 6, on telecommunity, appraises the significance of the
concept of community in media culture in two ways. Firstly, how do
‘communities’ arise that are said to be constituted entirely by technical
mediums? Secondly, why is it only recently, after over a hundred years,
that there has been a radical renewal of thinking of community? With
regard to the first question, the idea of a virtual community is explored,
but in relation to the much neglected idea of broadcast communities,
which, if anything, offer more powerful forms of integration than do their
cyberspace counterparts. Whereas in broadcast communities there is little
or no interaction with others in embodied or quasi-embodied form, there
is a high concentration of identification and the constitution of community by way of extended charismatic affect. Thus, both kinds of community can be characterized as virtual in the way in which they privilege
relations with media and mediated association.
In its emphasis on the priority of techno-social mediums over content, the volume draws on the recent wave of publications that have
dealt with the Internet and communication theory. At the same time it
attempts to chart the relationship between traditional and new media
without exaggerating the impact of the latter. Not only does broadcast
remain central to modern media culture, but it makes possible, in codependent ways, the social conditions which underpin cyberculture,
from its first steps to its last.
Note
1
Whilst the term ‘media’ might normally be considered the plural of medium, in this book
I make the distinction between media and mediums which is not restricted to a singular/
plural distinction. In using ‘mediums’ I am trying to retain a strong sense of media as
environments, rather than as either ‘technologies’ or institutions. Denoting ‘mediums’ as
‘media environments’ or ‘media architectures’ facilitates insights drawn from medium
theory which cannot be served by the term ‘media’.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The analysis presented in this book has emerged from almost ten years of
teaching and researching sociology of media. I have been fortunate to
present my research across sociology and communications forums, and
have benefitted from the challenges of organizing my ideas for classrooms
of inquiring minds. I am grateful to the Humanities Research Program at
the University of New South Wales for providing assistance in the middle
phase of writing, as well as colleagues both there and at Monash for ongoing conversation, encouragement and thoughtfulness. In particular, I
would like to thank Paul Jones and Ned Rossiter for rewarding conversations around themes and figures central to the book. For assistance with
some research tasks, thanks are due to Aaron Cross and Olivia Harvey.
With production I would like to Fabienne Pedroletti at Sage Publications
and in Melbourne, Andrew Padgett, who has been invaluable with the
final productive phases. Finally, my gratitude to my partner Vasilka Pateras
for her patience and love, and our daughter Elena, for being an aspiration.
ONE
INTRODUCTION – A SECOND MEDIA AGE?
In the last few years … widespread talk of ‘cyberspace’ has brought
new attention to the idea that media research should focus less on the
messages and more on communication technologies as types of social
environments. (Meyrowitz, 1999: 51)
In an essay, ‘Learning the Electronic Life’, written just before the ‘widespread talk of cyberspace’ that accompanied the so-called ‘Internet
Revolution’ of the 1990s, James Schwoch and Mimi White (1992) set about
to describe a typical day’s activity for their American family – from waking
up, to putting in hours as teachers in the education sector, to trying to relax
in the evening.
At first light they relate how they are woken by the baby monitor
which links their room to their son’s. Next thing they are heating up the rice
cereal in a microwave. While their boy is in the playpen, James and Mimi
commence some exercise in front of the TV with remote control handy.
Out of the house and, if not a walk-to-work day, into the car, lowering the
garage door with the automatic opener as we drive away on errands. Stop
at the bank – or rather, the nearest automatic teller machine to get some
cash for groceries and shopping (done with cash, checks, and credit cards,
with access to the first electronically verified by a local computer network,
the latter two verified at point of purchase by a national computer network) –
and upon returning home, check the phone machine before going off to the
office or upstairs to the study to work on the computer. A typical work day
can include not only personally interacting with students and colleagues,
but also interfacing with long distance telephone calls, photocopies, printouts, hard drives, programs, modems, electronic mail, floppies, audio and
video tape, and once in a while a fax. If we do not work into the evening, a
typical night may well include (along with returning phone calls) radio
listening, recorded music (albums, tapes or compact discs), broadcast television, cable television, or videocassettes. The most probable result, of
course, is some combination of the above choices, with too many TV nights
degenerating into an uninspired channel-hopping via remote from the comfort of the couch. In the background the baby monitor provides the sound
of sleeping baby, a sound that accompanies us into bed each evening. The
cycle, with a slight degree of variation, begins anew the next day. (Schwoch
and White, 1992: 101–2)
2
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Schwoch and White describe these interactions as ‘an unremarkable
series of events’ about which ‘few stop to marvel at how quickly and
unthinkingly certain aspects of technology – telecommunications based on
the electromagnetic spectrum and various wire-based telecommunications
networks such as the telephone – become part of our everyday experiences’
(102). Their very prosaicness, they argue, is what makes them so important
and powerful, because it is in our interface with these technologies, the
human–technical interface, that an entire pedagogy of technical competence
is fostered, a pedagogy which becomes almost buried in the thousands of
discrete habits and routines that both help us, connect us and imprison us
in the information society.1
People who live in information societies not only encounter and ‘use’
information and communication technologies; rather, increasingly, their
modes of action are enframed by these technologies. They are not so much
tools as environments. Since Schwoch and White published their essay,
over a silicon century (seven years) has passed, in which time a range of
interactive communication technologies have come become meaningful
in our daily life. We could add to their scenario the emergence of digital,
optic-fibre and packet-switching technologies which have made the
Internet possible, and the normalization of satellite-based communications
and information devices like satellite phones and global positioning
systems (see Dizzard, 2000). More often than not, we are not even aware
of the extent to which these technical systems precondition the simplest of
activities – an ignorance which was aptly epitomized by the trillion-dollar
anxiety over the millennium bug, the dreaded Y2K.2
But this lack of awareness does not signal that we have become ‘overloaded’ with information, images or technology, as subscribers to the
‘saturation’ thesis suggest.3 Media saturation tends to encourage a view of
some order of unmediated experience, which is menaced by impersonal
scales of instrusive media. In this book, we will see that, in fact, attachment to media can be very personal and as meaningful as embodied relationships, and that appreciating the strength of these attachments requires
a broadening of the concept of ‘cyberspace’.
The exponential explosion in webs of CITs (communication and information technologies) has, at a phenomenological level, shifted the orientation many of us have to ‘objects’ to an extent that can change our sense of
otherness.4 As face-to-face relations are replaced by ‘interface’ with technological ‘terminals’ of communication, electronic devices acquire a life of
their own. Outside our own bodies the world fills with objects that are also
animated, an animation which might compete with the human – as suggested by Sherry Turkle’s notion of the computer screen as a ‘second self’
(Turkle, 1984). Whilst the non-human might be competing with the human,
individuals themselves increasingly find that they are part of contexts in
which they are ‘objectualized’.5 Studies that have been conducted on these
phenomena show high degrees of attachment to media and communication
technologies, whether this be people’s need to have a television on in the
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
3
background even if they aren’t actually watching it, the near desperation
that many Internet users have in downloading their email, or individuals
who find security in having a mobile phone even if they use it only
seldom.
But of course, behind our surface contact with this system of objects
are definite social relationships, relationships which new communication
and information technologies enable to be extended in time and space
(see Sharp, 1993). At the same time, however, the particular way in which
they are extended can also be considered a relationship itself, which is
capable of acquiring an independence from the function of extending ‘pretechnological’ or pre-virtual relationships, even if they somehow might
take different kinds of reference from these relationships.
What this book proposes is that these electronically extended relationships are constitutive of their own dynamics, dynamics which can be
studied beyond the bewildering array of object technologies which, in
their very visibility, render the social relation largely invisible.
In particular, the social dynamics that will be analysed on the basis
that they can be analysed as part of this technologically extended sphere
of social integration are broadcast integration and network integration. By
the end of this volume, I aim to show that these kinds of integration are
ontologically distinct – that is, distinct in external reality, not just theoretically distinct – whilst at the same time mutually constitutive.
Communication in cybercultures
The technologically constituted urban setting which Schwoch and White
describe is increasingly typical of contexts of everyday life which preside
in the processes of modern communication. Communication does not
happen in a vacuum, nor does it happen in homogeneous contexts or
simply by dint of the features of a natural language, but in architectural,
urban, technically and socially shaped ways.
This book explores the interrelation between these contexts and the
character of a range of communication events. It is about the contexts of
communication in so-called ‘information’ societies as well as the kinds of
connection that these contexts and the communications themselves make
possible. The urban and micro-urban realities that can be described in the
everyday experiences of James and Mimi are integral to the understanding
of contemporary communication processes. Is there a relationship between
the increase in the use of CITs and the increase in the number of people
living alone in America, Australia and Britain? Is there a logic which links
the privatization of public space like shopping malls and the dependence
on broadcast and network mediums?
In the last ten years, the convergence between technologies of urban
life and new communications technologies has been remarkable. It has
4
COMMUNICATION THEORY
even led some commentators to argue that the privatizing concentration
of so many context-worlds, be they electronic, architectural or automobilederived, is what really amounts to ‘cyberspace’. This convergence is perhaps nowhere more powerfully represented than it is by the Internet,
which is itself a network as well as a model for ‘cyberspace’ relations.6
It was in the final decade of the twentieth century that the emergence
of global interactive technologies, exemplified by the Internet, in the everyday sphere of advanced capitalist nations dramatically transformed the
nature and scope of communication mediums. These transformations
heralded the declaration of a ‘second media age’, which is seen as a departure from the dominance of broadcast forms of media such as newspapers,
radio and television. Significantly, the heralding of a second media age is
almost exclusively based on the rise of interactive media, most especially
the Internet, rather than the decline of broadcast television. Empirically,
some have pointed out how certain technological forms of mass broadcast
have waned or fragmented in favour of ‘market-specific communication’
(see Marc, 2000), although this is seldom linked to the rise of extended
interactive communication. Rather, what is significant for the second media
age exponents is the rapid take-up of interactive forms of communication.
Whether this take-up warrants the appellation of a second media age,
which can so neatly signal the demise of a ‘first media age’, is contested in
this book. Certainly, the second media age thesis points to and contains
insights about definite changes in the media landscapes of nations and
regions with high media density. But the conjunctive as much as the disjunctive relationships between old and new media are very important.
Nevertheless, the arrival of what is described as the ‘second media age’
has two important consequences: one practical and the other theoretical.
The extent and complexity of these practical consequences, which this
book outlines, concern the implications which ‘the second media age’ has
for contemporary social integration. The theoretical consequence of the
second media age is that it has necessitated a radical revision of the sociological significance of broadcast media as addressed by traditions of
media studies.
The overstatement of linguistic perspectives on media
Under the influence of cultural studies, European traditions in media
studies have, since the 1970s, typically focused on questions of content
and representation rather than ‘form’ or ‘medium’. This is perhaps itself a
reaction to the preoccupation which ‘process’ models developed in the
United States had with ‘media effects’ and behavioural epistemologies.7
Analysing media content – the employment of perspectives on
language, beginning with Marxist conceptualizations of ideology, followed
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
5
by the influence of ‘semiotics’, ‘deconstruction’ and ‘New Criticism’ – was
conceived as a matter of studying the meaning of texts and discourse and
the way in which the ‘mass’ media influence cultural values and individual
consciousness. Throughout the 1970s and 1980s, differences between these
approaches to studying texts were debated around the problem of social
reproduction and how dominant discourses of a ‘dominant ideology’ were
related to broader social form.8 Under the umbrella of the linguistic paradigm,
media studies has also concerned itself with ‘media’ over ‘medium’ – with
the textuality of writing, still and moving images, music and speech – more
than with the institutionalized adoption of these media in broadcast and
network settings.9 Together with the related discipline of cultural studies,
media studies has been a discipline which has invariably confined questions of identity (individuality and ‘the subject’) as well as questions of
power, ideology and community to the great model of language and the
frameworks of understanding that have derived from the influence of
the ‘Copernican revolution’ in the humanities inaugurated by the work of the
Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure at the turn of the twentieth century
(see Chapter 2).
With the exception of a few theorists writing throughout the period
of the dominance of media studies such as Marshall McLuhan, Guy
Debord and, to a certain extent, Jean Baudrillard, there was very little
attention given to questions of form and medium.10 It was as though the
fascination with the content of ‘the image’ and the discourses surrounding it had somehow concealed the very modes of connection which gave
them circulation. Some areas of communication studies, in particular
positivist and behaviourist perspectives,11 have examined the interactive
processes which are deemed to exist between two speakers – and dyadic
models of communication analysing the relation of sender, receiver and
message abound (see Chapter 2). However, the social implications of
the actual structures of communication mediums (network and broadcast) have received relatively little attention (save exceptions such as
the above).
From the early 1990s onwards, a few years after the Internet began its
now infamous exponential growth, the theoretical necessity of analysing the
social implications of communication ‘mediums’ had become paramount,
if not unavoidable. It was as though, by the turn of a key, there had been
a transformation in the opportunity to understand the integrative dimensions of media that aren’t subordinate simply to linguistic derivatives. It
was as if media studies had been waiting for an historical object – the
Internet – in order to acquire the appropriate lens for understanding
communication as medium.12
The consequences of this theoretical period of change were that, firstly,
some of the early ‘medium’ theorists like McLuhan and Innis began to be,
and are still being, reclaimed (see Chapter 3). Secondly, new distinctions
are being made to reflect the renewed importance of distinguishing
6
COMMUNICATION THEORY
between ‘form and content’ such as ‘ritual’ versus transmission accounts
of communication. The understanding of communication as ‘ritual’ is a
radical paradigm shift from the hegemonic status of ‘transmission’ views
of communication, which all but saturated communication theory for the
most part of the twentieth century. Put simply, ritual views of communication contend that individuals exchange understandings not out of selfinterest nor for the accumulation of information but from a need for
communion, commonality and fraternity (see Carey, 1989). Following this
approach, transmission models of communication, on the other hand,
view communication as an instrumental act – the sending and receiving
of messages in ways which individual actors are largely in rational
control of.
The latter model of communication, which has in the main dominated
communication theory, has been critiqued, either implicitly or explicitly,
by philosophers of language who have attacked the identitarian, essentialist, ‘logocentric’ and ‘phonocentric’ underpinnings of such a model
(see Wittgenstein, Lyotard, Kristeva, Lacan). The project of Jacques Derrida,
for example, has been to criticize the idea that language affords a stable
stock of meanings for which it is the job of any particular communication
to convey. To characterize communication in this way, as ‘a transmission
charged with making pass, from one subject to another, the identity of a signified
object’ (Derrida, 1981: 23), is to make all kinds of metaphysical investments
in the derivation of meaning and the privileging of communication agents
as rational, autonomous selves. These assumptions are radically criticized
by Derrida and we will return to them in trying to understand the way in
which he claims they are tied to variations in contexts of communication.
At the same time it will be possible to see how Derrida’s work is also
celebratory of a second media age, because the latter’s apparent openendedness unmasks the ‘metaphysics of presence’ that is able to operate
in the more restricted (but never totally) contextual setting of broadcast
forms of communication.
However, for the most part, whilst philosophical ‘deconstructions’ of
essentialism are instructive, they have also, it is argued, been overstated.
Instead of only examining the way meaning works within texts, this book
will focus on how technological infrastructures of communication also
need to be examined for an understanding of forms of connection, social
integration and community. These material changes, it is argued, also
offer a challenge to essentialism, and make it harder to sustain. Hence the
need for communication theory which can not only challenge the ‘media
studies’ paradigm, but also show how it is coming to be recast. At the
same time, however, media studies, as a theoretical domain concerning
itself with the first media age and as harbinger of ‘content analysis’,
remains relevant to the fact that broadcast and the nature of spectacle in
modern society are integral to social organization in advanced capitalist
societies.
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
7
The first and second media age – the historical distinction
The commitment to the idea of a ‘second media age’ is one that had been
gaining ground by the middle of the 1990s with an array of texts – some
utopian, others pessimistic concerning the rise of Internet culture and the
concomitant demise of broadcast or ‘media’ culture. Such literature, exemplified by the publication of Mark Poster’s book The Second Media Age in
1995, has exhibited either a kind of enthralled fascination with the liberating social possibilities of new technology, or, conversely, has encouraged
us to rethink what older technologies mean for social processes. But the
idea of a second media age had been gaining ground during the 1980s in
embryonic form within rubric notions of the information society which
was somehow different from simply ‘media society’. Indeed the discipline
of ‘media studies’ has become far more ambiguous as its object of study
has been made much more indeterminate by the transformations that are
currently underway. The term ‘media’ itself, traditionally centred on the
idea of ‘mass media’, is addressed in the United States by the discipline of
‘mass communications’. But media studies (and mass communication
studies) in its traditional form can no longer confine itself to broadcast
dynamics, and in contemporary university courses it is being subsumed
by the more generic scholarship of communication studies – where the
accommodation of the distinction between first and second media age is
able to be best made.
However, the formalization of the distinction between these two
kinds of era has, I would argue, received its greatest momentum in the
wake of the domestic take-up of the Internet from the early 1990s. Since
that time we have seen a plethora of literature taking over bookshop
shelves dealing with everything from technical guides to interactive
computing to numerous interpretive texts about the influence the Internet
will have on our lives. It is also implicit in a range of journalistic writings
in the mid-1990s including Howard Rheingold’s The Virtual Community
(1994), George Gilder’s Life After Television (1994), Nicholas Negroponte’s
Being Digital (1995) and the corporate musing of Bill Gates in The Road
Ahead (1996), but also in other, more critical texts like Poster’s, Sherry
Turkle’s Life on the Screen: Identity in the Age of the Internet (1995), Pierre
Lévy’s Cyberculture (2001) and various collections like Steven Jones’
Cybersociety (1995) or David Porter’s Internet Culture (1997), culminating
in the compilation of readers by the late 1990s (Bell and Kennedy, 2000;
Gauntlett, 2000; Lievrouw and Livingstone, 2002; Wardrip-Fruin and
Montfort, 2003). Not surprisingly, a ‘new media age’ had also come to feature in numerous texts regarding media policy, in claims that broadcast
was rapidly dying and that regulation of digital media forms presented
the only remaining policy challenge (see, e.g., Steemers, [1996] 2000). At
the same time the heralding of a ‘new Athenian age of democracy’ by Al
Gore, and Third Way political advisers in Britain, became very audible.13
8
COMMUNICATION THEORY
By the end of the 1990s the second media age thesis had rapidly become
an orthodoxy, and entered the mainstream of New Media thinking.
In Australia, for example, Trevor Barr’s account of the Internet,
‘Electronic Nomads: Internet as Paradigm’ (Barr, 2000), exclaims: ‘The
Internet’s extraordinary growth and global reach of the platform in recent
years, the passion of its adherents and its maze of unresolved issues all
qualify it as a paradigm shift’ (117). Whilst wanting to specify whether or
not the Internet will offer ‘promise or predicament at the dawning of a
new communications era’ (144), Barr maintains:
An inherent strength of the Internet is its anarchy compared to the established modes of ownership and control of traditional media: there are no
direct equivalents to the ‘gatekeepers’ of content and form which characterize the major media of the past few decades, the press and broadcasting. Everyone who has access to the Net can become their own author,
expressing their own sense of identity to other Net users scattered throughout the world. (143–4)
Even non-specialist media thinkers like Manuel Castells (1996) have
taken up a version of a second media age thesis as a critique of McLuhan,
arguing that the onset of cable and digital television audiences has brought
about more personalized and interactive media culture: ‘While the audience
received more and more diverse raw material from which to construct
each person’s image of the universe, the McLuhan Galaxy was a world of
one-way communication, not of interaction’ (341).
It is the ‘interactive society’ which has replaced such a world, according to Castells, in the wake of a symbolically transitional period of ‘multimedia’ which has given way to a ‘new system of communication, based in
the digitized, networked integration of multiple communication modes’
(374). Castells claims that only within this integrated system do messages
gain communicability and socialization: All other messages are reduced to
individual imagination or to increasingly marginalized face-to-face subcultures. From society’s perspective, electronically-based communication
(typographic, audiovisual, or computer-mediated) is communication’ (374).
Castells is saying that whilst non-electronically based communication may still exist, it is progressively losing its status. This makes access
to the ‘interactive society’ a crucial question, as the world becomes
divided into the ‘interacting’ and the ‘interacted’:
… the price to pay for inclusion in the system is to adapt to its logic, to its
language, to its points of entry, to its encoding and decoding. This is why it
is critical for different kinds of social effects that there should be the development of a multinodal, horizontal network of communication, of Internet
type, instead of a centrally dispatched multimedia system, as in the videoon-demand configuration. (374)
These characterizations have not changed much from the arguments of
the early to mid-1990s. Early second media age thinkers, Poster, Gilder,
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
9
Rheingold, Negroponte and Lévy, are quite coherent in expressing the way
in which they claim that the Internet (and interactive technologies in
general) enables quite a radical departure from prior forms of social bond.
For them the Internet is redemptive in the way it is said to liberate individuals from centralized apparatuses of information, be they state- or
corporate-controlled, as exemplified by television. George Gilder (1994),
who prides himself with having predicted the demise of television and the
birth of the telecomputer as far back as 1989 (101), singles out television,
‘the Cathode Ray Tube’ and the wireless technology of radio as instrumental in the formation of a pervasive medium empire, the ‘“master–slave”
architecture’ of ‘a few broadcast centers’ that ‘originate programs for millions
of passive receivers or “dumb terminals”’ (26). By contrast ‘the much richer,
interactive technologies of the computer age’ will enhance individualism and creativity rather than mass culture and passivity (23, 32). For
Negroponte (1995), decentralization is a major feature of what he calls the
post-information age.14 In providing an alternative to the homogenizing
structure of broadcast communication, the Internet is said to offer almost
unlimited democratic freedom to track down information, to correspond
with thousands of other enfranchised individuals and spontaneously form
virtual communities which would not otherwise be possible.
For Lévy (2001), the Internet is a ‘Universal without Totality’ (91–103),
creating a knowledge space where, ‘[a]s cyberspace grows it becomes
more “universal” and the world of information less totalizable’ (91). But
one of its most important aspects is that it provides an alternative to mass
media, to ‘communications systems that distribute organized, programmatic information from a central point to a large number of anonymous,
passive and isolated receivers’ (223).15
This model of decentred association is said to be seductive for
thousands of consumers who have access to the Internet insofar as it spectacularly overcomes what is seen to be the tyranny of the first media age –
broadcast media. Where broadcast media are characterized as a relation of
the one to the many, as one-way, centralized communication, they are said
to be fragmentary of (geographic) communities in denying interactivity
and homogenizing cultural form.
For Poster and Rheingold, who are examined more thoroughly in
Chapter 3, an analysis of the architecture of cyberspace relations shows –
they claim – that the newer, extended electronic public sphere defies the
kinds of instrumental and monopolized centralized control that have
traditionally been accompanied by practices of normalization and regulation wrought by broadcast (Rheingold) and the culture industry (Poster).
This view persists in much of the second media age literature despite the
fact that the Internet has itself become a frontier of monopoly capital.16
Compared to broadcast forms of media, the Internet is said to offer
free-ranging possibilities of political expression and rights of electronic
assembly which encounter far fewer constraints, whether technical, political or social. The celebrated democratizing character of the Internet is
10
COMMUNICATION THEORY
The historical distinction between the first and
second media age
Table 1.1
First media age (broadcast)
Centred (few speak to many)
One-way communication
Predisposed to state control
An instrument of regimes of
stratification and inequality
Participants are fragmented and
constituted as a mass
Influences consciousness
Second media age (interactivity)
Decentred (many speak to many)
Two-way communication
Evades state control
Democratizing: facilitates universal
citizenship
Participants are seen to retain their
individuality
Influences individual
experience of space and time
rooted in its decentralized technical structure. Based on ‘packet-switching’,
a technical network system developed by Rand Corporation in the 1960s,
messages, images and sounds on the Internet are always sent in a fragmented fashion by way of multiple routes. This principle was Rand’s
solution to information held in a database being destroyed in military
conflict. Information is always on the move, fluctuating between decipherability and indecipherability and indeterminate in its mobility. Because
of this the Internet cannot be controlled either technically (by hackers or
programmers) or politically (by states or corporations).17 In the twentieth
century, which was characterized by the control of broadcast apparatuses
by governments and corporations, the Internet was also popularly seen to
represent an unlimited technical medium for the reconstitution of a ‘public
sphere’. As Table 1.1 suggests, the public sphere enabled by the second
media age restores a two-way reciprocity that is otherwise seen to be denied
by one-way communications of broadcast. In addition, the constituency
addressed by broadcast is constructed as, and so regarded as, an undifferentiated and largely indeterminate mass, whilst on the Internet the
individuality of communicants is redeemed.
In this historical typology, the periodization of an ‘age’ or era of
interactivity – the digital age, the age of the Internet or the second media
age – is almost always contrasted with a dark age of mass media.18 It is a
particular expression of an historicist discourse on technology which
fetishizes the new and accentuates any differences there might be from
the old.19
The critique of broadcast is remarkably coherent, whether it be from
liberals concerned with public choice and free speech (like Gilder, 1994;
Negroponte, 1994; and Rheingold, 1994) or from those employing Marxist
frameworks (post-Frankfurt School), or postmodern concerns for the
rhizome (as in Deleuze) or the shadow of the silent majority overcoming
the simulation machine (Baudrillard, 1982).20
Celebrants of the Internet herald its claimed democratic and redemptive virtues either as being able to re-establish lost communities through
interactivity or as making possible new kinds of community that transcend
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
11
modern forms of state control. To quote from Poster (1997), who is working
from a broadly postmodernist point of view, the Internet connotes ‘a
democratization’ of subject constitution because ‘the acts of discourse are
not limited to one-way address and not constrained by the gender and
ethnic traces inscribed in face-to-face communications’ (222). This is to be
contrasted with the broadcast media as a medium of centralized, unilinear
communication: ‘The magic of the Internet is that it is a technology that
puts cultural acts, symbolizations in all forms, in the hands of all participants; it radically decentralizes the positions of speech, publishing, filmmaking, radio and television broadcasting, in short the apparatuses of
cultural production’ (222).21
Further, insofar as the electronically produced space of the Internet
displaces institutional habitats, it breaks down hierarchies of race, gender
and ethnicity (see Poster, 2000: 148–70). By allowing the construction of
oppositional subjectivities hitherto excluded from the public sphere, the
Internet’s inherently decentralized form is heralded as its most significant
feature – allowing the collision and superimposition of signifiers and
semiotic worlds in which the some sense of an authoritative meaning –
a logos or a grand narrative – can no longer be sustained. This, Poster
argues, allows the Internet to subvert rationalized and logocentric forms
of political authority, which has imbued the European model of institutional life since the Middle Ages. As cyberspace identities are experienced
in much more mobile and fluid forms, the public sphere enlarges in the
midst of state apparatuses but, at the same time, acts to undermine statist
forms of control. This tension is partly played out in those state-originating
anxieties concerned as much with the encryption of information against
cyber-terrorism as with the use of communications technologies in
surveillance.
Broadcast mediums and network mediums – problems
with the historical typology
The conviction that we are coming to live in a post-broadcast society,
envisaged in the claim that the Internet is going to eclipse broadcast media,
is one that has been made by journalists and cyber-theorists alike. The idea
that an entire communicational epoch can be tied to key technologies – print
technologies, broadcast technologies or computerized interaction – is
central to making the distinction between the first and second media age.
The distinction is relative rather than absolute, as we shall see, owing to
the fact that the significance of the interaction promised by the second
media age is defined almost exclusively against the said rigidity and
unilinearity of broadcast.
At an empirical level, the distinction between the two epochs is
supported by statistics regarding the rapid take-up of interactive CITs, to
12
COMMUNICATION THEORY
the point of eclipsing immersion in broadcast environments. There are,
however, two problems which come immediately to the fore in tying these
epochs so closely to both the innovations in technological development
and the take-up of these technologies by consumers of all kinds.
Firstly, all of the various celebrants of the second media age thesis
overlook continuities between the first and second media age which, if
recognized, would, I argue, shake up many of their social and political
claims. However, we should not throw out the distinction between broadcast and interactivity altogether; as we shall see in Chapters 4 and 5, this
is an indispensable distinction for a form analysis of modes of communicative integration.
Nevertheless, the second media age thesis does not acknowledge just
how much interactive CITs share some of the dynamics of broadcast that
they have supposedly transcended, and, what is more, the degree to
which they are dependent on and parasitic of broadcast. These continuities,
which are addressed in Chapters 4 and 6, involve the way in which CITs,
whether we are speaking of interactive or broadcast, operate with similar
logics as technologies of urbanization. Secondly, they both produce economic imperatives which are mutually reinforcing, rather than distinct.
When looked at from an economic perspective, we shall be able to see
how both the Internet and television, network media and broadcast media,
‘need’ each other.
A second difficulty with the historical distinction made by second
media age theorists is the particular alignment of the two epochs with
what are seen to be monumental technological developments. It is as though
the various possibilities of communication are positively determined by the
technology itself (a tendency toward technological determinism) rather
than by the recursive relation between technical, political, social and economic environments. Then there is the necessity to distinguish between
the structure of communication environments (decentred, centred, oneto-many, many-to-many) and the technical forms in which this structure
is realized. Broadcast can be interactive as much as interactivity can be
facilitated within broadcast.
Television, print, radio, the Internet and the telephone provide for
elements of broadcast and interactivity; it is just that these are realized
differently, and at different levels of embodiment in different ‘techno-social’
relations.
Broadcast can be any form of public spectacle or public address either
technologically extended or not; i.e. a lecture amplified by a microphone
or not. Interactivity can be technologically extended (the Internet) or
simply face-to-face. From the point of view of technologically extended
forms themselves, we can also speak of a co-presence of different kinds of
media formation. Thus, the significance of the Internet is not that it is a
more powerful medium than other channels, but that it provides a platform whose sub-media contain both broadcast and interactivity.22 Tanjev
Schultz has observed that ‘on the Web some sites ... become more popular
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
13
than others. Then they serve as “mass media” on the platform Internet that
allows for all kinds of media and types of communication’ (2000: 208).
Also, those Internet sites which are mirrors of professional established
media, such as newspapers, simply add to the original reach which the
publication or broadcast already has (see Schultz, 2000: 209).
It is not, therefore, the technologies themselves which bring about
these properties in a direct correspondence to a medium. A capacity for
broadcast is inherent in a range of technological forms, from the telephone
to writing. At the same time the simulation of presence is just as possible
in computer-mediated environments as it is with cinema and television.
The fact that so many of these examples have considerable histories
to them makes the New Media discourse on ‘convergence’ theoretically
flawed. Convergence is already immanent in old as well as new technologies, but mainly through their interrelation with technologically extended
social relations in general.
However, the principal basis upon which convergence is presented as
a New Media phenomenon is related to digitization. A review of the
history of media and telecommunications technology shows that digitization is not a necessary condition of the convergence of broadcast and
network architectures. Convergence may increase the inter-operability
needed to access both architectures from one individual portal, but this
has much more to do with the historically produced demand for personalization. Nor does digitization particularly privilege interactivity and
network over broadcast, as the second media age theorists maintain.
Rather, as we will see in Chapter 3, both these theses place technology
before any understanding of the anthropology that is at work in contemporary communication environments.
To clear up these confusions caused by what might be called New
Media historicism, I argue, in this book, for the need to characterize ‘the
second media age’ not as an epochal shift but as a level of communicative
integration which is in fact not new at all but is internal to a range of communicational mediums which have co-existed with broadcast long before
the Internet. Brian Winston’s instructive history of means of communication from telegraph to Internet illustrates this fact well (Winston, 1998).
That new technical mediums somehow have their own aesthetic and
social qualities which are separated from ‘outdated’ mediums is, he
reveals, a common misconception resulting from the fetishization of
the ‘new’.
Winston shows, for example, how economic factors, rather than technology, imposed the primary limitations on the bandwidth of cable communication in the last century. But political and ideological factors which
saw broadcasting as a ‘centralizing social force’ (Winston, 1998: 307) were
also instrumental in eschewing cable. Throughout all of the time in which
wireless broadcast prevailed, however, ‘the wires never really went
away’, ‘the early radio and television networks were wired and the
transoceanic telephone cables have kept pace with the development of the
14
COMMUNICATION THEORY
international telecommunications satellite system’ (305). For Winston, the
networks are as old as telecommunications itself, and the inflated claims
about the potentials of simply linking computers together are relatively
hyperbolic.
Nevertheless, for cultural and historical reasons, the arrival of the
Internet has ‘institutionalized’ the idea of network as a normative ‘medium’,
and in doing so it has allowed some theorists to rethink broadcast also as
a medium. The term ‘second media age’ is useful to the degree that it
implies a cultural shift in perception toward media environments – insofar
as network structures of communication have become much more visibly
prominent since the emergence of Internet communication. As we shall
see in this book, the turn to reality TV genres away from narrative programming is a part of this shift. Insofar as even broadcast mediums, in
a limited sense, also provide a kind of network between communicants –
a network based on ritual – the rise of the Internet as a concrete and
tangible network allows us to see this.
One of the major reasons why media analysts tie individual technologies so closely to communicational qualities is to do with the way in
which CITs are largely empiricized. The significant relationship is seen to
be that between the technological doorway to a medium and the consumer. This doorway is one to which we are said to have either an active
or passive relationship – typified by the Internet and television, respectively. George Gilder (1993) proposes, ‘TV ignores the reality that people
are not inherently couch potatoes; given a chance they talk back and
interact’. At the ‘interface’ level of interaction, this might be referenced
to the consumer’s control of the remote control, which is seen to be relatively passive, as opposed to control over the mouse, which is seen to
be active.
In the case of the Internet consumer as opposed to the television consumer, there is an appearance of control over the interaction. This illusion
of control is one in which a technology is reduced to that of ‘reproduction’
(Jones, 1995) – the reproduction of forms of life based on less technologically constituted modes of exchange like the face-to-face and writing.
Here, when experienced as a ‘use-technology’, the Internet is seen to be
very much instrumentally subordinated to the carrying on of a social
contract by more technically powerful means. The individual who is
idealized as participating in this contract is the embodied subject, whose
embodiment is somehow overcome and extended. In being a TV consumer, on the other hand, the idea that there is an embodiment to extend
is more ambiguous. Instead it is through our selectivity of the channels of
messages that we experience that we can participate in pre-constituted
modes of life in a technologically extended way.
However, whilst this distinction between activity and passivity can
be held up in the situation where CITs are thought of as technologies of
reproduction (as tools, or instruments of extension), it weakens considerably when they are accorded the role of technologies of production
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
15
(as networks and electronic assemblies).23 The idea of a CIT of production
refers to the consideration of information mediums as environments
(see Meyrowitz, 1999; Poster, 1997) constitutive of altogether new kinds of
behaviour and forms of identity.24 That is to say, they are not just reproducing existing kinds of social relations, but bringing about new ones.
Interaction versus integration
Media of communication … are vast social metaphors that not only transmit information but determine what is knowledge; that not only orient us
to the world but tell us what kind of world exists. (Carey, 1972: 285)
The distinction between activity and passivity as well as that between
mediated and unmediated communication falls well within the interactive paradigm, based as it is on the face-to-face or ‘transmission’ analogue
for communication. This long-standing preference in communication
theory for the transmission model can largely be attributed to the prevalence of ‘interaction’ as its basic communicative building block, from
which are built the various accounts of communication.
The emerging alternative account is to distinguish between interaction
and integration. In this distinction, interaction is still important, but needs
also to be viewed in terms of the fact that all concrete interactions occur
in the context of dominant frames of communicative integration – which
is enacted through abstract ‘rituals’ of communication (see Chapter 5).
The integration thesis rejects the idea that the study of communication is
reducible to documenting empirically observable kinds of interaction, be
these interpersonal or extended.25 In tribal society, for example, face-toface relations, and the significance of the body in communication rituals,
envelop the social whole. This is observable from the point of view of the
rituals and categories of seeing the world that are developed within such
forms of social tie (i.e. the anthropomorphizing of animals and objects in
the natural world). A person formed within this setting does not actually
have to engage in constant face-to-face interactions in order to be enveloped
by the set of relations that are bound up in its ontology. Even when such
interactions are not occurring, the ontology of the face-to-face as a centre of
cultural formation comes to frame all other forms of interaction. So, distant forms of communion are made over ‘in the image’ of face-to-face.
Similarly, if we take technologically extended forms of communication as
characterizing a social tie of a different order again, we might say that in
modern media-saturated societies, mediums like television or the Internet
frame our lives even when we are not viewing or using them. This does
not mean that we avoid face-to-face relations, or are ‘addicted’ to technologically mediated interaction; rather it means that we conduct our faceto-face relations ‘through’ the dominant mediums or social interchange.
Here are some examples:
16
COMMUNICATION THEORY
• When we watch a soap opera, we typically are viewing countless
thousands of face-to-face interactions between talking heads, whilst, in
the very act of such viewership, we forgo our own engagement in faceto-face interaction. Most of the needs we might have for the face-toface may be achieved via the screen.
• Studies show that people in the city, who have much more access to
high volumes of face-to-face contact, use the telephone far more than
do people in rural areas.
• Studies of Internet relationships show that anonymous interactants are
more likely to divulge intimate information, as if they had a long-term
face-to-face relationship, than they would with strangers in embodied
interactions.
• Commonplace in the etiquette of Internet communication is the use of
‘emoticons’ as a substitute for the gestural communication that interactants feel is lost in the medium.
The prominence of the way in which technologically extended communication has become a dominant mode of integration can even mean that we
may idealize some kind of unmediated face-to-face sense of community as
a reaction to the pervasiveness of extended forms of ‘communication at a
distance’. Conversely, we might also fetishize communication technology
itself as being capable of delivering us the interactive immediacy that is
denied to abstract kinds of community (the dream of virtual reality). These
two kinds of reactions to contemporary media integration can also be
found in much of the more populist variety of second media age literature
and cyberstudies texts which privilege the concept of interaction.
Such literature is framed by a social interaction model – i.e. that face-toface interaction is being supplanted by extended forms of communication –
and this is seen to be derived from technology somehow intervening and
separating individuals from some ‘natural state’ of interaction which is the
face-to-face. This powerful model inspires not only nostalgic communitarians, such as Rheingold, who claims that individuals in information societies
are looking for ways to get back to that which they have lost – the face-toface – but also postmodernists, like Félix Guattari, who, while sharing the
view that face-to-face relations are no longer significant, sees in this no cause
for lament. Instead, he argues that it is important to embrace post-individual
networks of communication, and realize that the subject is a fiction and
always was (see Guattari, 1986). But this kind of negative theology is,
I would argue, merely parasitic of the misconception that the face-to-face
was ever historically lost in the first place. That is to say, if the face-to-face
is considered as a form of social integration rather than interaction, these
kinds of political oppositions become, I would argue, untenable. It is
because, anthropologically, the face-to face is an important mode of connection in information societies that the Internet becomes such a powerful
mode of connectedness – but one that can never consummate the mode of
integration it supposedly stands for.
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
17
Integration and ritual models, on the other hand, look to the kind of
background communicative connections which provide the hierarchy of
agoras of potential assembly, be these public, institutional or virtual, which
are independent of individual communicative acts. The crucial point here
is this independence. It is necessary to understand how, even when we are
not watching television or listening to the radio, the broadcast communication environment still frames our individual lives. We can experience the
telephone as though it is an extension of the face-to-face, or, conversely, we
engage in the concrete act of face-to-face communication and yet we are
somehow ‘away’ on the telephone or the Internet, only kind of half-present
because, really, it is extended forms of communication that are mediating
even how we experience the face-to-face. This latter thesis, that the dominant background connections or mediums by which a given group of individuals are socially integrated come to mediate other levels of interaction,
is one persistently explored throughout this volume.
In working through this argument, the pertinence of distinguishing
between a first and second media age is appraised, and alternative models
of understanding how broadcast media and interactive network media are
related to each other and to social reproduction will also be presented.
Notes
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
This is why Schwoch and White are concerned with ‘an analysis of the pedagogy of technological determinism in American culture’ (101).
The process of learning the electronic life and the importance of the everyday is a matter
to which I will return in the final chapter on telecommunity.
This claim is made for both traditional ‘images’ (see Gitlin, 2002) and New Media (see
Postman, 1993; Virilio, 2000). The idea of a ‘saturated self’ is also central to this (see
Gergen, 1991).
See the innovative article by Karin Knorr-Cetina, ‘The Society with Objects: Social
Relations in Postsocial Knowledge Societies’ (1997). Knorr-Cetina puts forward an ‘end
of the social’ thesis in referring to the process of ‘objectualization’ in which increasingly
‘objects displace human beings as relationship partners, and embedding environments,
or that they increasingly mediate human relationships, making the latter dependent on
the former. “Objectualization” is the term I propose to capture this situation’ (1).
In information societies, the intensity of kinship relations and face-to-face relations has
declined in a number of ways. Families are getting smaller and more people live alone.
But even the nuclear family, as in the case of Schwoch and White, is increasingly characterized by technological mediation, if not technological constitution.
Throughout this book, the term ‘the Internet’ refers to the ‘network of networks’ which
has been globally standardized since 1991. Although many other CMC systems which
facilitate Internet Relay Chat, email, newsgroups, bulletin board systems, MUDs and
MOOs may not be, strictly speaking, part of the Internet, as Wellman and Gulia (1999:
189 n. 3) point out, they are rapidly becoming connected to it.
Some of the papers produced by the Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies, such as
Stuart Hall’s influential essay ‘Encoding/Decoding’ (Hall, 1980), took as their departure
point a critique of the process model. Hall, in a later interview, explains that he first gave
the paper at Leicester University, where the communications programme was particularly
dominated by process pedagogy (Hall et al., 1994: 253).
18
COMMUNICATION THEORY
8 This debate, between Marxist and postmodern forms of media studies, agreed about the
importance of discourse, but conceived entirely different ends to their analysis, with
Marxism interested in the role of ideology in the reproduction of a social totality, and
postmodernism ontologizing the contingency of discourse itself as a denial of totality.
Certainly the sociological merits of the Marxist approach would prove to be limited by
remaining within the linguistic paradigm. By the 1990s Christopher Williams was asking, is it not ‘the case that ideology has become a hopelessly unusable term?’ (cited in
Corner, 1997: 453). Indeed, in the face of New Media, it can only be wielded as a ‘clumsy
club’, whereas it once had a central role in the unification of media studies.
9 For example, John Hartley (1992a) adheres to a basic theoretical tenet ‘that communication
is textual, not behavioural’ (14). The other tenet he gives is that communication is ‘social,
not individual’. It is because Hartley conflates all communication with broadcast, or, at
least, with understandings that an analysis of broadcast most often yields (the book in
which he wrote this is about television), that he overemphasizes texts. My modification of
this tenet is that the textual or behavioural qualities of communication are conditioned by
the architecture of the medium in which it is realized. I agree with Hartley’s second tenet,
but the social nature of communication once again has to be related to the means and
media of communication. The social is not some abstraction which can be posed over and
against the individual, or the means of communication in which individuality is realized.
10 I would suggest that it is because of this imbalance, rather than the incommensurability
of different approaches, that media studies has developed what John Corner (1997) has
called a ‘knowledge problem’.
11 Positivism and behaviourism each subscribe to instrumental views of technology, which
are based on a stark separation between the human and the technical. For example, positivist methodologies tend to talk about the ‘use’ of technologies, ‘the user perspective’
or rational choice perspective, in which a technology is reduced to a most visible and
tangible element, e.g. that on the Internet we use a mouse and make choices. Alternatively,
behaviourist models come from the opposite direction in which the individual is rendered entirely passive – their aim being to examine the ‘influence’ that technology has
on individual (only sometimes social) behaviour.
12 But this does not mean that ‘media studies was nearly dead’, as Gauntlett extravagantly
claims in hailing ‘long live new media studies’ (Gauntlett, 2000: 3); rather, traditional
media can be looked at in a new way.
13 For an assessment of Gore’s proclamations on the Internet and the ‘technocommunitarianism’ of Demos, the New Labour think-tank in Britain, see Robins and
Webster (1999: 229–31).
14 On decentralization see pp. 157–9. For Negroponte, the post-information age refers to a
post-broadcast age of an ‘audience the size of one’ (164), where information is extremely
personalized and not distributed in homogeneous volumes.
15 Moreover, ‘Cyberspace . . . is based not on such a hub-and-spoke model of distribution
but on one of shared spaces where everyone can have his say’ (223–4).
16 Studies indicate that the same gigantism that afflicts the old media now dominates the new.
Despite the Internet’s myth of indestructible diversity, cyberspace is also vulnerable to
monopolistic tendencies. ‘[In 1999], 60 percent of all time spent on the internet was on sites
owned by 110 companies. By 2001, fourteen companies captured the largest share of the
user’s time and 50 percent of all time is spent with four companies’ (Buzzard, 2003: 207).
17 See Chapter 3. A list of useful guides to the technical details of the Internet is given in
Jones (1995: 8).
18 As Silverstone (1999) observes,
The new ideology of interactivity … [is] … one which stresses our capacity to
extend reach and range and to control, through our own choices, what to consume, both when and how. It is hailed to undo a century of one-to-many broadcasting and the progressive infantilization of an increasingly passive audience. It
is an expression of a new millennialism. These are the utopian thoughts of the
Introduction – A Second Media Age?
19
new age in which power is believed to have been given, at last, to the people:
to the people, that is, who have access to, and can control, the mouse and the
keyboard. (95)
19 However, some recent correctives to this orthodoxy criticize ‘information revolution’ as
hyperbole, and the modernist myth of the new. Bolter and Grusin (1999) show how
processes of ‘remediation’ of older media by newer media (e.g. TV remediating film or
photography remediating painting) are not exclusive to a digital or post-broadcast ‘era’.
For Winston (1998) the term ‘revolution’ is wrongly applied to ‘New Media’, as he proposes to show how the pace of change today is actually slower than in previous periods
of technological diffusion and transformation in the means of communication. The
’Information Revolution’ is ‘largely an illusion, a rhetorical gambit and an expression of
technological ignorance’ (2).
20 The broad contours of this critique are already anticipated in Bertolt Brecht’s short reflection on ‘the radio as an apparatus of communication’ ([1932] 2003).
21 There is a great deal riding on these claims, stakes which broadcast corporations themselves are now interested in. Geoff Lealand (1999) argues that studies in the USA are
being conducted by media corporations, who have commissioned sociologists and communications analysts to study this decentring, and are part of strategies for more comprehensive forms of deregulation.
22 However, this does not mean that the Internet should be seen as producing the same
‘field of recognition’ as television. For example, some have tried to depict the Internet as
television with millions of channels, and millions of broadcasters. The problem is that
each channel is weakened in its broadcast power the more channels there are, diluting
the exposure of any message or persons who become its ‘content’. As we shall see, it is
impossible to be famous on the Internet.
23 An overemphasis on CITs as technologies of the production of ‘new’ social relationships can
be seen to be a precursor to the advent of ‘complexity theory’ – the idea that volume and
speed of emergence of causal interconnections between social (or physical) phenomena
become so complex and chaotic as to produce new and sometimes chaotic behaviours and
properties. (For a postmodern expression of this phenomenon as it applies to communication processes, see Kroker and Weinstein, 1994.)
24 Nowhere is this more spectacular than in the widening generation gap that is emerging
between net-literate youth and not-as-literate adults, especially in school classrooms.
There is a burgeoning amount of literature in the education journals relating to this (see
Downes and Fatouros, 1995; Green and Bigum, 1993; Holmes and Russell, 1999; Russell
and Holmes, 1996).
25 Most typical, for example, of the humanist anthropology and behavioural traditions of
communication research (see Finnegan, 2002).
TWO
THEORIES OF BROADCAST MEDIA
It is not possible to understand the central dynamics of network
communication, or why the second media age thesis has become an
orthodoxy, without understanding the nature of broadcast as a medium. In
fact, as we shall see, the two communicative forms can be argued to be, in
the contemporary period, mutually constitutive. That is, I argue, they are
mutually related in their practical reality and are also related therefore in
how we should understand them.
Understanding broadcast and network as distinct communicative
architectures also entails making some fundamental distinctions
about the kinds of communication effects which are internal to them.
The distinction between ‘transmission’ versus ‘ritual’ communication is
one which provides a useful way of classifying the different kinds of
perspectives on broadcast media which emerged in the twentieth
century. These perspectives correspond to qualitatively different kinds
of communicative processes which are evident in the mass media, and
which broadly correspond to content versus form, respectively. The
transmission view is by far the predominant one, and is only recently
being criticized from the point of view of its overstatement.
Instructively, the impetus of this rebuttal is not to be found in the large
body of critical writings1 but can be found in the rise of new kinds of
communicational realities which expose transmission views of broadcast as inadequate. The critical literature on ‘transmission’ views of
community has been led in recent decades by a number of French
theorists, exemplified by the work of Jacques Derrida, discussed in
detail in Chapter 5.
What this and the next chapter aim to do is to introduce the main perspectives on broadcast and network cultures of communication respectively before going on to look at the way in which the perspectives on
broadcast need to be critically reassessed. This will mean that shortcomings of instrumental perspectives will become apparent in light of an
understanding of network communication, but, in later chapters, we shall
also see how broadcast can be seen to carry very important forms of reciprocity and community, contra the claims of many of the second media
age thinkers.
Theories of Broadcast Media
21
The media as an extended form of the social – the rise of ‘mass media’
The massive changes wrought by the industrial revolutions that have
unevenly transformed the developing world have represented important
preconditions to the formations of populations living in conditions of density whilst at the same time connected by the framework of the nation-state.
The sheer scale of population increases within modern nation-states combined with the migration of people from pastoral regions to cities has
created metropolitan densities conducive to the maturing of so-called ‘mass
society’. Infrastructures necessary to service such growth have led to the
mass production of transport and goods, the mass delivery of education
and of course the ‘mass media’ (see Giddens, 1990; Thompson, 1995).
In the period of the breakdown of traditional societies characterized
by a high intensity of integration by religion, the fragmentation of nationally framed polities by way of urbanization, the separation of individuals
from feudal means of production and the creation of labour-power as a
commodity collectively gave rise to a range of perspectives on the ‘massification’ of society ranging from mass/elite frameworks to liberal-pluralist
ones.2
The mass/elite framework had its most salient beginnings from the
1930s onwards, which was also the time when the media were first
‘mapped out as a field of study in a formal or academic sense’ (Bennett,
1982: 38). It was at this time that the co-emergence of cinema and radio
combined with rising unemployment and mass armies of disposable
workers which culminated in the Great Depression. What all of these
frameworks have in common is the idea that the masses once formed by
the aforementioned disintegrations are, in late modernity, in need of a
mechanism of incorporation for social integration to occur. This may be
politically, by way of the gradual enfranchisement of successive groups,
or economically, by, for example, the law of value operating in the
market to facilitate equivalence between labour-power and commodities.
At the same time, however, the mass society framework of the 1930s gave
rise to a concern for ‘effects analysis’ which focused on ‘stimulus’ and
‘response’ and the influence that ‘the media’, deemed to be somehow
external to the formation of a person’s identity, comes to exert over that
identity and culture in general.3 These studies oscillated between celebrating the media as agents of the education of the masses to condemning them for hypodermically injecting audiences with ‘propaganda’.4
Most of the empirical research was concerned with what people ‘think’
as a result of being influenced by the media. On some rare occasions, the
‘mass psychology’ of the media was also studied, such as when, in 1938,
H.G. Wells’ famous novel The War of the Worlds was broadcast in radio
form on CBS, resulting in the now difficult to understand apocalyptic
hysteria over a Martian invasion.
22
COMMUNICATION THEORY
The mass/elite model of society has been criticized by Marxist
perspectives on communication and more recently within cultural studies.
The Marxist critique labels mass/elite theory as an ideology of erasing a
politics of class (neutralizing the realities of the ruling class versus the
working class), whilst cultural studies is concerned with the way in which
the framework treats audiences as ‘passive’.5 Interestingly, the Marxist
and cultural studies critiques dismiss ‘mass society’ perspectives insofar
as they are deemed to be serious contenders for a sociological framework.
Tony Bennett argues, for example, that as a theory of society, it is generally imprecise, that its historical commitments are at best romantic and
at worst vague, and that there is no account of the transition between
periods of social integration (Bennett, 1982: 37). Yet it is, of course, precisely
because it developed in the period when broadcast media were in ascendance that this ‘imprecise’ theory came about. My own argument is that
the mass society outlook, if thought about in relation to the media, is
an entirely appropriate response to the embryonic dynamics of mediaconstituted integration. I agree with the above critiques that it cannot be
taken seriously as a sociological framework, but as a theoretical expression
of, as well as response to, the way broadcast media are able to reconstitute
social relations it provides some early conceptual tools for this – even if
these are inadequate by today’s standards.
For example, mass society theory is sometimes accused of homogenizing media forms themselves. As John Hartley suggests, ‘it is difficult to
encompass the diversity of what constitutes print, cinema, radio and television within one definition’ (in O’Sullivan et al., 1994: 172). But this is
only true if we are interested in the significatory properties of these media.6
Where these media do converge, however, is in the capacity to act as bearers of a homomorphic medium of communication, which produces audiences whose field of recognition is vertically constituted.
It is significant that it was only during the period of the massive rise
of broadcast through television in the 1950s and 1960s that literature again
began to appear dealing with the age of the masses (see Bell, 1962;
Kornhauser, 1960; Shils, 1957). This is the time when another, very different kind of mass society theory made its debut in the form of what Stuart
Hall has called ‘American Dream Sociology’. This kind of sociology, represented by the writings of Daniel Bell, Seymour Lipset and Edward Shils,
argued that the general liberalization of society, supposedly measured by
the participation of the working class in politics and the growth of welfare, had solved earlier conflicts arising within civil society to the point
where a new consensus had been achieved by which resources were at
last being distributed according to a harmonious pluralist pragmatism.
This thesis, known as the ‘end of ideology’ thesis, argued that the fundamental political problems of the industrial revolution have been solved:
the workers have achieved industrial and political citizenship; the conservatives have accepted the welfare state; and the democratic left has
recognized that increase in overall state power carried with it more
Theories of Broadcast Media
23
dangers to freedom than solutions for economic problems (Lipset, 1963:
406). The 1950s renaissance of mass society theory was therefore one with
‘the elite’ subtracted from it where the masses had been redefined as the
melting pot of democratic evolution. Shils was working earlier than the
other theorists at revising the 1930s formulations in which the masses had
achieved the long march from the outskirts of the social, cultural and
political landscape to the democratized and pluralized community or universal speech. Such speech was, of course, guaranteed rather than truncated by the mass media. It is as if in fact such a democratization of
the masses had not been possible without the rise of the media. In this
way, American Dream Sociology saw the media as simply a transparent
extension of the democratic public sphere, a continuation of the social by
other means, where the media act in service to the community. As Stuart
Hall (1982) describes it, ‘in its purest form, pluralism [American Dream
Sociology] assured that no structural barriers or limits of class would
obstruct this process of cultural absorption: for, as we all ‘knew’, America
was no longer a class society. Nothing prevented the long day’s journey
of the American masses to the centre’ (60).
Contrary to the way in which the presumed homogenizing function
of the media was celebrated, several of the empirical studies of a behaviourist and positivist kind conducted at the height of this perspective
confirmed the opposite effect, that audiences were in fact highly differentiated and heterogeneous (e.g. Lazarsfeld and Kendall, 1949).7 Such studies
were effectively repositioned by Shils in yet another twist in the tale of
mass society theory, as proof of the confirmation of the ‘homogeneous’
pluralistic tolerance of mediatized democracies.
What is characteristic of both the early and later versions of mass
society theory is their adherence to empiricist and positivist epistemologies
of the media. That is to say, in arguing that the media are able to extend the
democratic process,8 by circulating views, a number of metaphysical commitments are made which have since been critiqued by linguistic perpectives on the media (semiotic, structuralist and post-structuralist). The media
are largely assumed capable of providing a transparent reflection of reality
(language is transparent), whether this be as a reflection of events (the news),
of culture (popular culture), or of morality and art (film and literature).
Secondly, the status of the individual is unproblematic for this model. For
example, the position (qua perspective) from where a media product might
be consumed is disregarded. Thirdly, all individuals (subjects) are deemed
to have the same opportunity for observation.
Mass media as a culture industry – from critical theory to cultural studies
A major counter-perspective to the liberal-pluralist idea that the mass
media are a democratizing extension of social forms is represented in the
24
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Marxist tradition of the critique of ideology as well as the critique of the
unequal ownership and control of the means of communication according
to class divisions in capitalist societies. The critique of ideology, which
will be explored in the following section, views the media as a powerful
apparatus for ‘ideologies’ – which are not simply just ideas – for reproducing the values and structures that are active in the maintenance of
class inequality. But the media are also significantly an industry in themselves, an industry in which commodities are bought and sold.
As the markets and innovations for developing subsistence commodities become exhausted, modern capitalism has tended to turn its
attention to industries for which demand has fewer limitations, and has
targeted altogether new needs that are created by historical circumstances.
Service industries, military industries and leisure industries (tourism,
music, entertainment, sport) each provide economic markets which are
potentially unlimited and insatiable. The earliest thinkers on this phenomenon were Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, who, in the mid-1940s,
published their now canonized critique of the culture industry: ‘The Culture
Industry: Enlightenment as Mass Deception’ (1993).
The culture industry carries all of the hallmarks of capitalist production. Its products are standardized, emptied of aesthetic merit and capable
of mass production, and they are consumed on scales as vast as those on
which they are produced. The primary consequence of this massification
of culture was, for Adorno and Horkheimer that it had profound implications for aesthetic reception. Art is appreciated not for its special ability to
communicate truth or beauty but for its marketability. A Hollywood movie
has to have a sex scene and a car chase, done in a certain way. The contemporary novel must have a minimum number of elements in order to be
a ‘best-seller’. The weekly ‘life’ magazine must have the requisite revelation on weight loss, improving sex life or overcoming relationship and family disorders. But it is not just the conventions within genres that become
standardized; new genres appear which even mock the masses they are
purporting to represent, such as the spectacle of humiliation characterizing
‘candid camera’, celebrity-hosted talk shows, ‘world’s funniest home
videos’ or ‘funniest advertisements’, or even ‘world’s dumbest criminals’.
Conversely, celebrities have their own television genres, like ‘Lifestyles of the
Rich and Famous’ or ‘Entertainment Tonight’. Alternatively, serious social
issues like AIDS, Third World relief or the environment receive modest
attention, unless they are promoted by a music or film celebrity. From the
period when the control of information, communication and entertainment
is concentrated in the hands of a few to be sold to the many, culture itself
can become a commodity in all kinds of forms.
Insofar as culture becomes massified through broadcast principle,
Adorno and Horkheimer see it as replacing religion and the smaller units
of integration of the feudalist world. This thesis at its broadest is therefore
continuous with the mass society tradition in accounting for the social
acceptance and role which broadcast achieves.
Theories of Broadcast Media
25
To take their opening claim:
The sociological theory that the loss of the support of objectively established
religion, the dissolution of the last remnants of precapitalism, together
with technological and social differentiation and specialization, have led to
cultural chaos is disproved every day; for culture now impresses the same
stamp on everything. Films, radio and magazines make up a system which
is uniform as a whole and in every part. (Adorno and Horkheimer, 1993: 30)
But the culture industry does not only produce standardized content;
it also produces the audience itself by way of ‘a circle of manipulation and
retroactive need in which the unity of the system [of the production and
consumption of meanings] grows ever stronger’ (31). This formulation
places emphasis on the fact that broadcast produces content for audiences
at the same time as it produces audiences for the content – one of the first
statements of how the media themselves are a system of social integration
which, despite its function as servile to the needs of commodity capitalism,
nevertheless facilitates a common culture. In other words the mass is
constituted by broadcast; it is not some kind of pre-given amorphous
body that has broadcast imposed on it.9
For Adorno and Horkheimer, perhaps the most significant feature of
the culture industry is that it inculcates ‘obedience to hierarchy’ (38). In
the very structure of the few producing on behalf of the many, it discourages the mass from taking initiative or from questioning the initiative
being taken by the elite. It is little wonder that the culture industry produces a loss of individuality (see 41) – a phenomenon which mass society
theory, as we saw, does not so much describe as promote in its selection
of methodology.
Interestingly, the culture industry thesis shares with the liberalpluralist perspective the idea of the media as an extension of social relations.
However, where there is a fundamental disagreement is over what exactly
is extended, which for the Frankfurt School is a replication of obedience to
hierarchy continuous with pre-media social relations. Moreover, for them,
the mass media collude in the reduction of social life to the flat, onedimensional intellectual and emotional habits of commodity consumption,
thereby completing the process of the spiritless circulation of commodities.
The media as an apparatus of ideology
For contemporary Marxist perspectives on the media, the culture industry
is an ‘industry’ in itself, but is less important as a site of the production of
‘new’ social relations that might be exclusively derived from mass media than
it is as a site of the reproduction of existing social relations – particularly
class divisions, but also the divisions of gender, ethnicity and race. The
Marxist approach is therefore interested in the meanings that are negotiated
26
COMMUNICATION THEORY
within the media, and its influence in the reproduction of forms of
consciousness that accord with the reproduction of capitalist social relations. In this section, we will therefore be surveying the idea of ‘ideology’
as the content of broadcast apparatuses rather than as implicated in the
very structure of broadcast, which will be examined in the next section.
Whilst Marxist perpectives largely subscribe to the argument that the
media offer an extension, by reflection, of social relations, this is only so in
a distorted form. In a class society, it is quite normal that the ‘true’ character
of social relations, of power and of inequality, is misrepresented. In class
societies, wealth is distributed away from its producers, but, more importantly, this process is usually masked in some way. This, at least, is the
‘false consciousness’ argument of orthodox Marxism – the earliest Marxist
formulation of the concept of ideology.10 The ‘false consciousness’ thesis
posits ideology as a distorted, inaccurate representation of the world,
which is cultivated by the ruling class and its managerial servants against
the interests of the working class. This early formulation persists today in
the ongoing concern that some Marxists have with the ‘ownership and
control’ of broadcasting and, in particular, its recent globalized form.
However, this theory has been widely criticized as being based on a
correspondence theory of truth – the notion that ideas should transparently reflect the ‘real’ world. In fact this doctrine of false consciousness
has many more continuities and affinities again with liberal-idealist conceptions of ideology than with later Marxist and cultural theory.
In Marx and Engels’ writings a number of more sophisticated senses
of ideology appear, which were subsequently developed by twentiethcentury Marxists for studying media.11
Firstly, there is the idea of ‘commodity fetishism’, a definition found
in Marx’s later work which laid the ground for a theory of what Georg
Lukács was later to call ‘reification’. Unlike ‘false consciousness’, which
some Marxists have attempted to apply to all kinds of class society,
Marx’s theory of fetishism is specific to the capitalist mode of production.
In turning to Marx’s major late work Capital, we find a conception of
ideology that is related to a fundamental distinction between essence and
appearance. In Capital, economic relationships as experienced in everyday
life do not ‘reflect’ or correspond to the underlying structural mechanisms
of which they are an effect. Here, the appearance of capitalism as it actually presents itself obscures from individuals the systemic inner forces
which govern their lives. The important point here is that the misrecognition of the ‘true’ character of social relations is not a ‘defect’ of the subject;
rather it is a result of how social relations present themselves.
Thus in Marx’s discussion of the fetishism of commodities in Volume I
of Capital the fact that individuals exchange their labour-power (as a
commodity) for other commodities is experienced as an equal exchange
around which an entire realm of legitimation is erected – what Marx calls
the ‘noisy sphere, where everything takes place on the surface in full view
of everyone’ (Marx, 1976: 279; see also Hall, 1977: 324). Marx argues that
Theories of Broadcast Media
27
the ‘essence’ of commodity exchange is really an (abstract) exchange of
labour, the source of social value, whilst to the individuals who exchange
this labour this only ever appears to them as the concrete relations
between things (in the form of price). Whilst this obscures the social character of labour, this essential reality is displaced to the sphere of exchange,
which becomes all the more real: ‘To the producers, therefore, the social
relations between their private labours appear as what they are, i.e. they do
not appear as direct social relations between persons in their work, but
rather as direct social relations between things’ (Marx, 1976: 166–7, my
italics). From this it may be seen that the ‘appearance’ is in a sense ‘real’,
especially because it is convincing. Real as it may be, Marx reminds us
that it conceals the essence, an essence which explains the appearance and an
essence which is not manifest to individuals: ‘... by equating their different
products to each other in exchange as values, they equate their different
kinds of labour as human labour. They do this without being aware of it’
(166–7). In other words, it is not necessarily ideas which represent the
world ‘inaccurately’; rather it is the nature of capitalism itself to present
itself in an inverted form.
In terms of the distinction between content and form that is to be
examined in relation to the media, Marx’s account of the commodity is
instructive. Later we shall see how it has influenced the work of Jean
Baudrillard and Guy Debord, in which the media themselves, in the form
of signs, become intrinsically bound up with the exchange circuits of commodities. In fact, for Baudrillard and Debord, the world of image and
spectacle becomes the ultimate form of commodity reification. This important concept, which had its first comprehensive development in the work
of Lukács, denotes a phenomenon in which the relations between individuals are said to acquire a ‘phantom objectivity, taking on autonomous,
all-embracing and rational relations between things (Lukács, 1971: 83).
The production of commodities comes to dominate the whole of society
constituting appearances consisting of complexes of isolated facts. It permeates the division of labour within the state, bureaucracy, industry and
especially science.
The final sense of ideology in Marx and Engels to be examined here
is that of ideological incorporation, formulated in their book The German
Ideology:
The ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas, that is, the
class which is the ruling material force in society is at the same time its ruling intellectual force. The class which has the means of material production
at its disposal, has control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that thereby, generally speaking, the ideas of those who lack
the means of production, are subject to them. (Marx and Engels, 1970: 65)
The understanding of ideology that is purveyed here is one in which the
ideas of one group, the ruling group, become generalized to the whole of
28
COMMUNICATION THEORY
society. This is often interpreted as a mechanical relationship. But as this
was later developed, the fact that one class may monopolize the means of
mental and material production does not guarantee that it can simply
impose its ideas; rather, these ideas are negotiated in a way in which their
rule is accepted.
This stance on ideology was developed by the Italian Marxist
Antonio Gramsci – by way of the concept of hegemony. This refers to an
ideological struggle in which the ruling class compromises with the working class in return for its leadership in society as a whole. It is a consensual
form of power in which Gramsci identified the mass media as central.
This does not require direct editorial control of media by the capitalist
class; rather, managers, who identify politically and ideologically with the
ruling class, provide ‘the organic intellectuals’ who are at the front line of
hegemonic struggle.
In the Gramscian framework of hegemony, ‘false consciousness’ is a
myth in that people are seen as having ‘“true” conceptions in their heads
of society as it actually presents itself’ (see Alford, 1983: 8) – that is, they
have ‘common-sense’ experience of exchange relations and the division of
labour. Therefore ‘direct’ human experience is the point of origin, the
source of their ‘real’ conceptions, which explains why they acquiesce in
their conditions, as ‘there is no conceivable alternative to the commodityform’ (Alford, 1983: 7). Thus, individuals’ ‘common-sense’ experience of
the world tells them not only what exists but also what is possible. In this
framework, ideology is merely a more systematic version of common
sense, which legitimizes doctrines of particular social groups involved in
the organization of the presentation of hegemony. Gramsci problematizes
the doctrine that ideology is only ever an expression of class interests (and
so an individual’s ideological position can be ‘more or less read off’ from
their economic position) as being far more contradictory, and he sees class
relationships as potentially more fragile.
For Gramsci, the dominant classes don’t merely prescribe ideology
for working-class consumption; rather, they have to continually strive to
limit the boundaries of the making of meaning to exclude definitions of
social reality which conflict with their horizon of thought – the struggle for
hegemony is won and lost not just in the media, but in the institutions of
civil society (such as the family, the churches, the education system, but
also in more coercive apparatuses: the law, the police, the army, etc.).12
Gramsci’s examination of the institutions of civil society was taken
up in the 1960s and 1970s by the French Marxist Louis Althusser, who
reworked the analysis in developing a very strong link between ideology
and the power of the state. Althusser claimed that ideology, and what he
called the ‘ideological state apparatus’, had become much more important
in the twentieth century than the repressive and coercive state apparatuses of the nineteenth century. This change could be attributed to the
important addition which Althusser makes to the state apparatus, which
is the apparatus of broadcast.
Theories of Broadcast Media
29
Interestingly, it is not merely apparatuses of communication that are
important here, but also those of the structure of ideological processes
which occur in all institutional settings of power – religious, educational,
political and workplace. For Althusser, the growth of electronic broadcasting institutions (particularly visual broadcasting) merely consolidates
the consensual integration of individuals that occurs in the structure
rather then the content of ideology.
In what follows, we shall investigate Althusser’s radical departure in
thinking on the nature of ideology from both the early Marxist and liberal
notions. His innovation involves questioning the very notion of what it
means to be an individual in a communication process, an innovation
which has been echoed ever since in the analyses of what today is called
‘post-structuralism’.
Ideology as a structure of broadcast – Althusser
Althusser’s most striking point of departure from the humanist Marxists
is to question the categories in which ideology is thought. Ideology is not
found in the content of messages, nor is it adopted in the consciousness of
individuals; rather, it is nothing less than the mechanism by which the
individual experiences selfhood – as an autonomous knowing subject in a
world of knowing subjects.
Althusser’s account of ideology is almost a reversal of the conventional humanist accounts. For Althusser, there is no such thing as ‘given’
individuals with an experience of the real; rather, the very idea of individuality is created in the communication process itself. By his account,
this process by which the individual is constituted only intensifies in the
age of ‘mass media’. Indeed it makes possible the ‘cult of the individual’
which Émile Durkheim first discussed at the turn of the twentieth century.
For Althusser, individuals (subjects) are never essential but are constituted (an ‘effect’ of ideology). The centrepiece of his theory is his distinction between the individual and the subject. His major proposition in
this regard is that ‘the category of the subject is only constitutive of all ideology
in so far as all ideology has the function (which defines it) of ‘constituting’
concrete individuals as subjects’ (Althusser, 1971: 160). In other words,
Althusser is not denying the existence of individual ‘personality’; it is just
that such ‘personality’ is only possible in and through a communication
process. The mechanism by which this occurs he describes as ‘interpellation’, where he says that ‘all ideology hails or interpellates concrete individuals as concrete subjects’ (162).
For Althusser, ideology only exists by the subject and for the subject,
and its function is to constitute people as subjects. While it may seem
‘obvious’ that individuals are unified, autonomous beings whose consciousness and unique personality are the source of their ideas and beliefs,
30
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Althusser maintains that this obviousness only comes from people
‘(mis)recognizing’ themselves in the way that ideology ‘interpellates’
them, calls them by their names and in turn ‘recognizes their autonomy’
(162). It is in this imaginary misrecognition that the subject is constituted;
the subject is therefore formed in an imaginary relation – ‘it cannot be the
pure subject of the empiricist notion of experience because it is formed
through a definite structure of recognition’ (Hirst, 1976: 387). Ideology
does not constitute individuals in a singular divine act; rather, ‘ideology
has always-already interpellated individuals as subjects’. For Althusser,
individuals are always-already subjects in the same way that ideology itself
is ‘always-already’ known (Althusser, 1971: 175–6).
As ‘autonomous’ subjects with a unique ‘subject-position’ in the
social formation, individuals willingly ‘work by themselves’ (181) as a
‘centre of initiatives’ (182). However, whilst the subject is a ‘centre of
initiatives’ responsible for its actions, it is also a subjected being who submits freely to the authority of the Subject – God, Father, institution, the
boss, etc. – that is, a subject through the Subject and subjected to the Subject.
The structure of all ideology, interpellating individuals as subjects in the
name of a Unique and Absolute Subject, is specular, i.e. a mirror-structure,
and doubly specular: this mirror duplication is constitutive of all ideology
and ensures its functioning. Which means that all ideology is centred, that
the Absolute Subject occupies the unique place of the Centre, and interpellates around it the infinity of individuals into subjects in a double-mirror
connection such that it subjects to the Subject. (Althusser, 1971: 168)
*
*
*
Althusser’s theory represents something of a paradigm earthquake for the
study of broadcast media and its social significance. In suggesting that, firstly,
ideology is not simply a moment of signification but is the very condition
by which it is possible to act as a self-conscious subject, and, secondly, that
structures of interpellation which exhibit specular and centred structures are
the most significant sites of ideology, broadcast media become an extremely
important kind of state apparatus. Althusser’s theory points to a sense in
which ideology – what he calls ideology-in-general – can be considered a
structure of broadcast rather than just content. Ideology as content he
refers to as ideology-in-particular. For Althusser, particular ideologies may
change but ideology-in-general is an enduring structure. This is why, as
Sprinker (1987: 279–80) has argued, the behaviour of media audiences
should be seen not as psychological but as social.
Because, for Althusser, ideology is the very condition of a subject
being a subject at all, he argues that no one in any society can do without
ideology – without a representation of themselves as subjects, of their
world and of their relation to the world. This is why ideology is not
merely a representation of people’s conditions of existence (distorted or
Theories of Broadcast Media
31
otherwise) but rather is ‘a “representation” of the imaginary relationship
of individuals to their real conditions of existence’ (162). For Althusser, as
a Marxist, the political point of this statement is that in a social formation
where production relations (and inequality) are obscured, where conditions
which govern people’s existence aren’t manifest to them, ‘they necessarily live these absent conditions in an imaginary presence “as if” they were
given’ (Hirst, 1976: 386). Therefore ideology is active in maintaining the
status quo of the existing relations of production – active in the reproduction of social relations. However, as we shall see in Chapter 5, Althusser’s
theory is also important for an understanding of forms of social integration
which can be seen to be quite independent of the needs of the reproduction
of capitalism.
The society of the spectacle – Debord, Boorstin and Foucault
The power attributed to ideology-in-general in social integration and social
reproduction provides a useful theoretical backdrop to understanding the
‘spectacle’ thesis in French media theory – in particular the theories of Guy
Debord and later Jean Baudrillard. This thesis also argues for the basic
externalization and objectification of social reality in the media, but it is less
a function of narrative than it is of the role of spectacle in the generation of
a world of simulation. Their theory is a post-representational one in which
the fact of the image rather than what the image says becomes the most
important aspect of present-day broadcast societies. The system of images
transforms the mundane into a hyperreal carnival of totemic monuments
through which the ‘masses’ achieve congregation.
Debord, Boorstin and Foucault
In understanding the significance that is attributed to the image in the
various theories of spectacle, it is important to specify the fact that ‘the
image’ derives its power almost exclusively from the medium of broadcast. We will see in the next chapter that, with the Internet, there is no such
thing as ‘the image’, as the Internet does not provide a field of visibility
in the same way as broadcast does. The image is a function of media in
which there is a concentration of the attention of the many on a particular
monumental event or representation. When such representations are
repeated over time – when images become icons – the image is able to take
on a life of its own – where the things it refers to become secondary. Indeed
the referent may disappear altogether.
An early and original theorization of the phenomenon of the reification (cf. Lukács, above) of the image in modern society is given in Guy
Debord’s well-known monograph The Society of the Spectacle (1977). First
32
COMMUNICATION THEORY
published in France in 1967, this text takes a ‘situationist’ perspective on
broadcast media. Debord’s argument is that capitalist culture presents
itself as an immense assemblage of spectacle. But spectacle for him is not
just ‘a collection of images, but a social relation among people, mediated
by images’ (epigram no. 4). The spectacle even promotes itself as an agent
of the unification of society as a whole. It is the domain of society which
‘concentrates all gazing and all consciousness’ (epigram no. 3).
For Debord, the modern media, for which he contends the term ‘mass
media’ is a ‘superficial manifestation’ (aphorism 24), are agents both of
political power and of urbanization. They secure the complacency of the
population to inequality and hierarchy:
The oldest specialization, the specialization of power, is at the root of the
spectacle. The spectacle is thus a specialized activity which speaks for all
the others. It is the diplomatic representation of hierarchic society to itself,
where all other expression is banned. (aphorism 23)
At the same time the spectacle is a practical agent for the dual unification
and separation of individuals around the principle of private consumption:
The spectacle originates in the loss of the unity of the world, and the gigantic
expansion of the modern spectacle expresses the totality of this loss: the
abstraction of all specific labor and the general abstraction of the entirety
of production are perfectly rendered in the spectacle, whose mode of being
concrete is precisely abstraction. (aphorism 29)
Debord describes the situation of the spectacle – as simply one representation of the real – splitting off and separating from the real as though it
has transcended it:
The spectacle is nothing more than the common language of this separation. What binds the spectators together is no more than an irreversible
relation at the very centre which maintains their isolation. The spectacle
re-unites the separate, but re-unites it as separate (aphorism 29).
In Debord’s account, a view which is restated by Fredric Jameson (1991)
nearly two decades later, the image is – following a somewhat Lukácsian
trajectory – presented as ‘the final form of commodity reification’.
Six years prior to Debord’s publication, across the Atlantic, the
phenomenon was receiving theoretical attention in the form of Daniel
Boorstin’s publication of The Image (1962).13 Boorstin saw television and
cinema as an extension of the de-naturing and de-realization of modern
society wrought by the electronic management of the environment. In
modern society,
distinctions of social classes, of times and seasons, have been blurred as
never before. With steam heat we are too hot in winter; with air conditioning
Theories of Broadcast Media
33
we are too cool in summer. Fluorescent lights make indoors brighter than
out, night lighter than day. The distinctions between here and there dissolve.
With movies and television, today can become yesterday; and we can be
everywhere, while we are still here. In fact it is easier to be there (say on the
floor of the national political convention) when we are here (at home or in our
hotel room before our television screen) than when we are there. (231–2)
For Boorstin, broadcast technologies are servile to what he described as the
‘homogenization of experience’, in which differences between individuals
are flattened rather than expressed – leaving individualism itself as the
remainder. Nowhere is this more salient than in public opinion polls:
… the rising interest in public opinions and public opinion polls illustrates …
the rise of images and their domination over our thinking about ourselves. …
Public opinion, once the public’s expression, becomes more and more an
image into which the public fits its expression. Public opinion becomes
filled with what is already there. (239, 240)
A consequence of Boorstin’s claims is that, in the age of the image, public
opinion is no longer able to be surveyed or polled. Polling itself, a positivist gesture of research, cannot quite cope with the fact that it is attending to a thoroughly anti-positivist reality.
Debord and Boorstin’s depiction of the social function of spectacle
bespeaks striking continuities with that of Michel Foucault’s account of
public displays and torture in eighteenth-century Europe.14 J.B. Thompson
(1995) gives a good account of this in sketching the formation of modern
forms of power:
The societies of the ancient world and of the ancien régime were societies
of spectacle: the exercise of power was linked to the public manifestation
of the strength and superiority of the sovereign. It was a regime of power in
which a few were made visible to the many, and in which the visibility of the
few was used as a means of exercising power over the many – in the way,
for instance, that a public execution in the market square became a spectacle in which a sovereign power took its revenge, reaffirming the glory of
the king through the destruction of the rebellious subject. (132)
Thompson argues that Foucault’s work is instructive for a theory of
the media, less in his promotion of discourse analysis than in showing
how the older spectacular forms of power became manifested in institutional life in routine fashion, imbuing surveillance and disciplinary
regimes in an involutory way. That is, the ‘disciplinary society’ which
Foucault details in Discipline and Punish is one in which ‘the visibility of
the few by the many has been replaced by the visibility of the many by the
few’ (Thompson, 1995: 133).15
Of course Adorno and Horkheimer would argue that these two forms
of recognition relation are intertwined. That is to say, the visibility of the
34
COMMUNICATION THEORY
few by the many which is organized by the few is also the means by
which the few are able to control the many through economic and cultural
subordination. In an article on television, Adorno (1954) comments: ‘the
more inarticulate and diffuse the audience of mass media seems to be, the
more mass media tend to achieve their “integration”’ (220). The gaze of
the audience is sold to advertisers, at the same time as selection of the
content of media programmes is itself highly coded within dominant
ideological interests.16
In the context of modern mass media, the institutionalization of this
commodification of the gaze is one which imposes an entire order of symbolic inequality, in which the masses associate via the image and the
celebrity (for further discussion, see Chapter 6).
This inequity in the production of ‘cultural capital’ that is central to
broadcast as a system of reproduction of late capitalist societies occasionally surfaces at the level of discourse. The central operation of the performative nature of broadcast is not itself visible. We know from Althusser
that, in fact, the very operation of ‘interpellation’ and of the calling function of ideology is one that is upside-down. Althusser puts it in psychoanalytic language – that it is conscious on the condition that it is
unconscious – but the effect is the same. For Althusser, the structures of
the system of interpellation are, by definition, impossible to examine.
However, it is possible to argue that at the level of discourse, the
structure of interpellation sometimes surfaces in narratives which, when
the analysis of what constitutes broadcast is taken into account, can be
seen to be self-referential: an abstract reflection of the medium itself but
explainable in terms of the medium. Here are three such discourses.
The discourse of ‘ordinary people’
It is only in the media cultures dominated by ‘spectacle’ that it is possible
to speak of ordinary people. The now familiar way in which individuals
who do not work for the culture industry, or are not subject to any significant media attention, behave when interviewed by a television network
or press or radio is instructive here. A very common narrative of a person
being called on to describe their role in an event, a process or in society at
large is one which runs, ‘I am just an ordinary person doing my job.’ But
even news narratives replicate this ‘interpellation’ of the individual in
describing how ‘ordinary men and women are to be affected by this or that
government decision’. Ordinariness cannot simply be explained as some
deeply constituted residue of feudal class dynamics in which one’s position is more or less determined by birth. The discourses of ‘ordinariness’
can be seen to closely coincide with the rise of ‘mediated publicness’.
It is only under the conditions of the polarization between celebrity and
ordinary culture that a film such as Forrest Gump could be made. An interesting film from the point of view of defying any easy genre classification,
Theories of Broadcast Media
35
it centres on the character of Gump, who, with humble means and simplistic
technique, is able to achieve an extraordinary range of things, from
marathon running, to heroic war service, to gridiron stardom. Whilst the
film is predominantly concerned with celebrating the culture of opportunity said to underwrite the moral superiority of the United States, it is also
about how even the most ordinary person can, in a society of celebrities
and spectacle, be noticed and satisfied.
The discourse of ‘the system’
In this discourse anonymity is rejected in favour of a reflexive critique of
abstract domination. Just as ordinariness has replaced the specification
of ‘underclass’ or working class, something distinctively co-emergent with
the mass media, so too the specification of politicians and the ruling
classes has been replaced in populist discourse by a rebelliousness to
something called ‘the system’. A phrase which was taken up by the
counter-cultures since the 1960s, it has entered into popular discourses in
ways which denote everything from the suffocation of expression and
creativity, to the inevitability of domination, to a generalized cynicism of
power.
The discourse of ‘they’
‘They’ are building a new freeway. ‘They’ have discovered a cure for
cancer. ‘They’ are opening a new shopping centre. ‘They’ aren’t telling the
public the full story. Perhaps the most pervasive term to accompany the
rise of the mass media is that of ‘they’. Who, exactly, are ‘they’? The fact
that the mass which is constituted by broadcast media is indeterminate as
far as particular messages go implies that the individuals who are part of
this mass are also indeterminate to each other. In other words, broadcast
makes possible scales of association which are difficult to achieve by any
other means. On the one hand, we can talk about a high level of integration via the image and the celebrity, but, on the other, we see relatively
weak kinds of connection at the horizontal level of the division of labour.
In media societies, ‘otherness’ is completely concentrated in the fetish of
the spectacle or the celebrity, whilst at the level of the everyday, it is
radically diluted. But what kind of other are ‘they’?
There are many theses. ‘They’ is simply a shorthand for the institutional nature of the entity being described – the roadbuilders, scientists
and doctors, developers, the government, etc. ‘They’ could also be a
default way of saying ‘I can’t elaborate on the detail’ or ‘It is more complex than my description warrants.’ ‘They’ could also simply be an
absent-mindedness, a carelessness about ‘who’ it is that makes the daily
news. ‘They’ might be a polite way of saying also that we can’t know
36
COMMUNICATION THEORY
‘who’ ‘everyone’ is, nor would we want to. But when considered in relation
to the structure of broadcast media, it is clear that, for example, celebrities
are not they; their own identity is well defined, so much so that the media
produce genres of programming and magazines which are exclusively
about celebrities. Obversely, they aren’t written about and yet seem to be
everywhere. ‘They’ substitutes for the modern loss of specificity. We are not
quite sure how it works, we are not invited to participate, but they know.
‘They’, in this reading, is the emblem of individual disconnection and
disembodiment – of the fact of the loss of various practical knowledges
which are based in cultures of mutual presence and oral culture.
With all of these discourses, the question arises as to whether ‘they’
are peculiar to broadcast integration or to technologically extended
culture in general – of which the Internet is a part. This will be reassessed
in Chapter 4.
Mass media as the dominant form of access to social reality – Baudrillard
In the last section we saw how, whilst spectacle has become a highly
visible social reality, its influence over social behaviour is not so visible.
This influence is nevertheless manifest in specific discourses, which provide rare cases in which the field of recognition created by the broadcast
medium condenses into the content of that medium.
The way in which the attention of the audiences is concentrated
though spectacle is not unlike a contemporary form of ‘reification’ of
social relationships where the fetish of representations overtakes the conditions of that representation. The spectrality of the image, and the
successive forms by which it becomes detached from social relations in
general, is also a central concern of media sociologist Jean Baudrillard.
But unlike the spectacle thinkers, Baudrillard argues that the ascent of a
culture of images produces a crisis in representation itself. In media societies, processes of signification are no longer underwritten by a metaphysics of presence or the promise of recovering some kind of original,
authentic or privileged meaning.
The eclipse of ontology by the image rests with what Baudrillard sees
as the power of ‘simulacra’. This term refers to the way in which what we
consume from media becomes more real than what it supposedly refers
to. In elaborating the evolution of simulacra in his essay ‘The Precession
of Simulacra’ in Simulations (1982), Baudrillard takes us through four
phases of the representation the image. The image in its different guises:
•
•
•
•
is the reflection of a basic reality;
masks and perverts a basic reality;
masks the absence of a basic reality;
bears no relation to reality whatsoever: it is its own pure simulacrum.
Theories of Broadcast Media
37
Baudrillard examines the cultural status of representation in European
society to suggest that it evolves through the above forms of phenomenality.
The first phase is easily recognizable in the code of journalists today,
who, with their narrow conventions and frameworks of objectivity, bias
and neutrality, embrace the prospect of a correspondence between reality
and the representations they produce. The second phase is also recognized in various understandings of ideology discussed above, that representation is largely a distortion of real conditions. The third phase is
probably the most difficult to understand. Here, Baudrillard argues that
an objective representation of the real is impossible, because the referent
is already a simulational reality. Therefore, representation hides not ‘the
truth’ but the fact that there is no ‘truth’. His most famous example is
probably his claim that the function of theme parks like Disneyland is to
encourage us to think that the rest of society is somehow ‘real’ – whereas
for Baudrillard the entire world has today become, in a sense, a giant
theme park (see, in particular, Baudrillard, 1988).
The fourth phase marks the end of social reality itself as an available
referent. This is easy to understand. The connection to the referent can
become lost altogether – something which is indicated by the emergence
of a number of interesting genres like ‘reality TV’. What is represented on
TV is supposed to be more significant than other forms of experience.
At the same time, the television itself can be found colonizing our public
lives everywhere we turn, in taverns, shopping malls, delis, laundromats,
airports, train stations, hardwares and local stores. As McCarthy (2001)
argues, ‘TV integrates into our everyday environments so well that we
barely notice its presence’ (2). Indeed, according to Baudrillard, these two
senses of the screen becoming the real (the screen colonizes the real, and
the real is only ‘real’ if it is on a screen) mean that images begin to refer to
each other rather than to the ‘real’ world.
This relationship is not unlike the kind of relationships involved in
commodity fetishism, which Marx investigates. As discussed earlier, for
Marx, it is only via the commodity that individuals experience their connection to each other. We can recall that whilst commodity fetishism conceals the ‘essence’ of the commodity (which for Marx is labour), the
‘appearance’ of the commodity in the advertisement and on the shelf is
also ‘real’ and therefore convincing.
For Baudrillard, it is the image itself that becomes the measure of
all things, including our access to social reality. ‘Everywhere socialization
is measured according to exposure through media messages. Those
who are under-exposed to the media are virtually asocial or desocialized’
(Baudrillard, 1983: 96). The image is highly convincing and we do not
seem to be able to live without it. But the greater our exposure to the mass
of images, the more ‘information’ we receive, the more we come to live in
a world of less and less meaning: ‘Information devours its own contents;
it devours communication and the social’; it ‘impodes’, and for two
reasons: firstly: ‘[i]nstead of causing communication, it exhausts itself in
38
COMMUNICATION THEORY
the act of staging the communication; instead of producing meaning, it
exhausts itself in the staging of meaning’. Here Baudrillard argues that
meaning is devoured more rapidly than it can be reinjected insofar as
information and the image become self-referential – ‘a closed circuit’ (99).
Secondly, the media do not bring about socialization, but the implosion of
social relationships in the only remaining relationship created by the mass
media – the masses. Insofar as all relationships must ‘pass though’ the
media relationship, they suffer the entropic force that is the condition of
simulacra.17 The implosion of meaning right down to the microscopic
level of an individual sign, what a word can mean, is mirrored by this
macroscopic implosion of the social, in a way that echoes McLuhan’s
formula – the medium is the massage.
The ‘mass’-age, in Baudrillard’s terminology, is an exclusive effect
rather than a precondition of the media. The mass and the media are the
shadow of each other, and when dynamics of simulacra prevail, that institution known as the ‘social’ becomes outmoded, absorbed into the image.
In this world the individual becomes ‘a pure screen, a switching centre for
all the networks of influence’ (1983: 133), in a world wherein ‘we form a
mass, living most of the time in panic or haphazardly, above and beyond
meaning’ (1983: 11).
Here the media no longer function as a massive lie in pretending to
represent fiction as the real or the real as fiction. What Baudrillard means
by hyperreality or simulation is different. There can no longer be a contrast with the real; rather, the real is produced out of itself as the performativity of the mass media is amplified above all other events.
For Baudrillard, the masses aren’t the kind of duped underclass that
are to be manipulated by the media and politicians (a notable departure
from the mass/elite and Marxist frameworks); rather, they are a kind of
ground of absorption and massive gravitation which neutralizes all
meaning and creates the conditions for a society of nihilism and cynicism.
The masses are a stronger medium than all the media: ‘it is the
former who envelop and absorb the latter – or at least there is no priority
of one over the other. The mass and the media are one single process.
Mass(age) is the message’ (Baudrillard, 1983: 44).
The medium is the message – McLuhan, Innis and Meyrowitz
The final important perspective on broadcast media that I want to explore
is that of Marshall McLuhan and Harold Innis, which Joshua Meyrowitz
has called ‘medium’ theory. Whilst not having as much currency as the
‘spectacle’ and ideology frameworks, it has recently received a large amount
of attention (see Adilkno, 1998; Bolter and Grusin, 1999; Goodheart, 2000;
Jordan, 1999; Meyrowitz, 1995, 1999; Skinner, 2000; Wark, 2000). Most of
this attention is directed towards seeing McLuhan as a rediscovered
Theories of Broadcast Media
39
prophet of a second media age, but much of it is also interested in an affirmation that it is, after all, important to look at communication media.
McLuhan’s work is based on an historical understanding of successive
waves of communication from print to electronic. His various aphorisms
on the media, including ‘the global village’ and ‘the medium is the message’,
have become absorbed into popular culture, whilst not necessarily understood within McLuhan’s own system of thought. Influential in the academy
in the 1960s, McLuhan underwent a ‘loss of vogue’ (McQuail, 1983: 90)
in the 1970s, which continued until the recent reclamation of his work by
theorists of the second media age and cyberculture.18
The major contribution of McLuhan to communication theory is his
multi-dimensional account of communication ‘mediums’ – a way of looking at technologically constituted social relationships, which each have
their distinct reality or ontology. This approach is very different from, say,
the culture industry thesis, the theory of ideology, or Baudrillard’s precession of simulacra, each of which implies a basic homogenization of
those immersed in media.19
Rather, McLuhan’s contention is that media technologies carry distinct
temporal and spatial specificities to which correspond definite frameworks
of perception. As James Carey (1972) suggests,
The exploitation of a particular communications technology fixes particular
sensory relations in members of society. By fixing such a relation, it determines a society’s world view; that is, it stipulates a characteristic way of
organizing experience. It thus determines the forms of knowledge, the structure of perception, and the sensory equipment attuned to absorb reality.
(284–5)
Historically, however, he does argue, one or more of these frameworks may come to dominate cultural perception as a whole. Thus, he
distinguishes between print-based culture and electronically extended
culture. In print culture, claims McLuhan in Understanding Media (originally published in 1964), our perception of the world tends to be englobed
by literature and the book, which becomes an analogue conditioning
other experiences. This is often experienced as the new mediating the old
and interiorizing it:20 ... ‘the “content” of any medium is always another
medium. The content of writing is speech, just as the written word is
the content of print, and print is the content of the telegraph’ (McLuhan,
1994: 16).21
THE TELEGRAPH
PRINT
WRITING
SPEECH
40
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Today, McLuhan’s schema as applied to the Internet might look like the
following:
THE INTERNET
PRINT
IMAGE
WRITTEN WORD
ICON
SPEECH
VISUAL COMMUNICATION
These layers of technological worlds, past and present, intensify the work
of processing meaning which confronts consumers immersed in the
different mediums. This process work becomes heightened to the point
where we have to be educated and inducted into it as increasingly information has to be produced by the audience or the receiver.
McLuhan’s primary distinction that is relevant here is that between
‘hot’ and ‘cool’ mediums.22 Hot mediums like radio and cinema circulate
a large amount of information, bombarding the viewer or listener.
Relatively little is required in order to interpret them. Cool mediums, on
the other hand, presuppose interaction. McLuhan’s assumption is that in
hot mediums there is an overdose of information, and there is little need
for interactivity, for ‘active’ participants, or for participation at all.
Later in Understanding Media McLuhan begins to describe the demise
of mechanical media like print in making way for technologies of
‘automation’ like radio and television as part of what he calls the ‘cybernation’ transformation of modern society. It is the electronic instantaneity
of radio and TV which consolidates the hegemony of mass media over
older mechanical technologies of reproduction.
Automation brings in real ‘mass production’, not in terms of size, but of an
instant inclusive embrace. Such is also the character of ‘mass media’. They
are an indication, not of the size of their audiences, but of the fact that everybody becomes involved in them at the same time. (McLuhan, 1994: 372)
In other words, the significant property of broadcast which McLuhan
zeros in on is its ‘live’ character. Here it is the fact that a broadcast communication is live for the audience, rather than live at the point of production. The content of the transmission could have been prepared earlier
or at the same time as the audience is consuming it. However, McLuhan
is, of course, not interested in the content, but in the way the audience is
merely a constituted reflex of the medium itself. Insofar as the media
achieve cybernation, ‘the consumer’ of a message also ‘becomes producer
in the automation circuit, quite as much as the reader of the mosaic telegraph press makes his own news, or just is his own news’ (McLuhan,
1994: 372). The value of McLuhan’s analysis here is that he suggests that
an electronic assembly or ‘virtual’ assembly does not have to be dialogical
or equal, or even have ‘high participation’, in order to guarantee mutual
presence. Even if the vast majority of ‘participants’ in a medium are
Theories of Broadcast Media
41
passive (as in a hot medium), they are nevertheless able to experience
mutual presence as the really real.
Most controversial among McLuhan’s theories is his later emphasis
on the human–technical extension argument where the definition of what
qualifies as media is dramatically extended. In a shift from ‘the medium
is the message’ to ‘the medium is the massage’ (see McLuhan and Fiore,
1967), McLuhan views anything that can extend the body’s senses and
biological capabilities (psychic or physical) as earning the status of media.
‘The wheel is an extension of the foot, the book is an extension of the eye,
clothing an extension of skin, electric circuitry an extension of the central
nervous system’ (McLuhan and Fiore, 1967: 31–41). Whilst, as we shall see
in later chapters, there are enormous problems in referring CITs (communication and information technologies) exclusively back to the body in a
kind of corporeal essentialism, McLuhan paradoxically allows us to
understand recent developments in the convergence of CITs with transportational and architectural technologies in a way that is most useful.23
The cryptic eccentricity of McLuhan’s work overshadowed some of
his contemporaries, who, in a number of ways, were more comprehensive
and rigorous in their analysis of technical mediums of communication
and forms of political power.
One such writer, Harold Innis, presented a medium theory which is
perhaps more user-friendly for a theory of broadcast. In The Bias of
Communications (1964, originially published 1951)24 Innis makes a major
distinction between two kinds of ‘empires’ of communication. The first,
corresponding to the printing press and electronic communication, results
in spatial domination (of nations and of populations) – what he calls a
‘space bias’ – whilst the second, ‘time bias’, based on oral culture and the
cloistered world of the manuscript, accommodates memory and continuity. For Innis, the oral tradition needs to be reclaimed. Broadcast belongs
to the empire of space, and in the time he was writing, the early 1950s, it
had come to structure prevailing power relations.
As David Crowley and David Mitchell (1995) depict him:
Innis … saw a recurrent dialectic in History where one medium asserted
primacy in a society, followed by efforts to bypass the social power that gathered around the control of that medium … each new mode of communication was associated with tearing individuals and their entire forms of life out
of their traditional moorings in locality and place and relocating them within
larger and more dispersed forms of influence. With modernity, this process
of co-location of the self within multiple spaces, identities, and influences
intensifies; human agency itself is progressively pulled away from the local
and reconstituted within the expanding possibilities of the modern. (8)
Despite a lapse in the momentum of medium theory in the 1970s, it
certainly had some sophisticated exponents in the 1980s and 1990s,
among whom Joshua Meyrowitz, whose work is explored further in the
following chapters, is exemplary.
42
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Meyrowitz’s major work No Sense of Place (1985) was a carefully
theorized volume which attempted to continue the traditions begun by
McLuhan and Innis. For Meyrowitz, electronic media reterritorialize ‘sense
of place’ and the spatial, political and social conditions of this sense of
place. They do this by their cross-contextuality and reach, the way in
which they can asymmetrically bring together extremely diverse groups
who are otherwise separated in cultural focus, in space, and perhaps also
in time. Media, especially electronic media, make possible arbitrary relations between a concrete space and a sense of place. By undermining ‘the
traditional association between physical setting and social situation’ the
constraints of embodiment such as being in one place at the one time
disappear (7). The value of this analysis is in anticipating what has
recently only been attributed to ‘cyberspace’, the mobility that is afforded
to an Internet consumer, highlighting the ‘virtual’ aspects of broadcast.
The value of the ‘mediationists’, as David Crowley and David
Mitchell describe them, is that they were the first to draw attention to the
interrelation between different media and systems of power. Their work
neither is based on a philosophy of consciousness nor is it behaviourist.
In the next two chapters I discuss it further, firstly, in Chapter 3, in terms
of how network media have heightened the importance of medium theory;
and secondly, in Chapter 4, in terms of how medium theory allows us to
theorize the relationship between network and broadcast media.
Notes
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
The major corpus of critical accounts of the transmission view has come from postSaussurian philosophies of language.
Bennett (1982) gives a useful survey of the different perspectives.
Effects analysis quickly established itself as a serious pursuit of sociological research. In
American sociology, dominated as it was by positivist methodologies, the opportunity
for empirical testing of the various theories about media effects presented itself (see
McQuire, 1995).
For the former function, see, for example, Leavis (1930); for the latter function, see
Chakhotin (1939).
Oddly, this latter critique is confused about the different kinds of ‘mass media’. For
example, in a dictionary definition on the subject, John Hartley distinguishes between
print, screen, audio and ‘broadcast’ media. Broadcast is therefore equated with whatever
might be in some sense ‘live’ throughout a signal radiation apparatus (in O’Sullivan
et al., 1994: 172–3). Here Hartley is caught up in a cosmology of media ‘effects’, the study
of how the media affect audiences. For example, even in critiquing the idea that the
media influence the mass, and arguing that audiences are much more active and intelligent
than mass society theory would have us believe, the very prospect of resistance presupposes an effects model.
The Marxist and cultural studies frameworks are primarily interested in the way media
are industrially and state regulated.
More recently audience studies has become a branch of media studies in its own right,
which stresses the idea of the active and diversified audience. See Ang (1991) and Gitlin
(1998) – the argument that there is no such thing as a single Habermasian public sphere.
Theories of Broadcast Media
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
43
The question of democracy in the first and second media age is discussed in Chapters 3
and 4.
For a 1990s text which empirically investigates the way in which modern audiences are
the product of the management and marketing efforts of media organizations, see
Ettema and Whitney (1994).
Ideology is thus identified with passages from Marx’s earlier work in The German
Ideology as a false, imaginary, upside-down, illusory representation of reality: ‘in all ideology men and their circumstances appear upside down as in a camera obscura’ (Marx
and Engels, 1970: 47).
The literature on Marx and Engels’ concepts of ideology is vast and I will offer here a
summary of them to the extent that they are a useful background for examining the
media as a state apparatus. For a useful overview of Marxist theories of ideology, see
Larrain (1983) and Eagleton (1991).
The struggle for hegemony usually entails the manufacture of consensus by way of the
revival or construction of deviance. These may be internal to a particular nation-state,
such as criminality, counter-cultures and subcultures. External deviance might be projected as a threat posed by other cultures and other nations as either economically, militarily or culturally dangerous – culminating in the modern discourse of ‘terrorism’.
Given that this text is almost entirely grounded in an empiricist epistemology (see my discussion above), Boorstin manages to capture the import of spectacle in a persuasive way.
It is perhaps remarkable that Foucault did not write anything about the modern media,
even though he was writing throughout the heights of the society of spectacle. Certainly
his work is taken up by media studies and cultural studies in substantial ways, but
particularly in the discourse analysis perspective, as we have seen earlier in this
chapter.
The visibility of the few by the many was not always a matter of violent display, but
indeed a common form was also the ‘royal progression’ which continues today in
nations with a monarchical head of state. The regency would conduct routine and regularized regional tours to be visible to his or her subjects on a repetitive basis, as, for
example, the British monarch does today, in relation to the Commonwealth.
The view that the function of broadcast institutions is primarily to sell audiences to
advertisers was first put most strongly by the Canadian Marxist Dallas Smythe (1981).
‘It is useless to wonder if it is the loss of communication which causes this escalation in
the simulacra, or it is the simulacra which is there first.’ There is no first term,
Baudrillard argues: ‘. . . it is a circular process – that of simulation, that of the hyperreal:
a hyperreality of communication and of meaning, more real than the real. Hence the real
is abolished’ (1983: 99).
Especially by the editors of Wired magazine.
For an excellent comparison of Baudrillard and McLuhan, see Smart (1992: 115–40) and
Huyssen (1995).
Recently this process which McLuhan describes has been taken up in the concept of
‘remediation’. See particularly Bolter and Grusin (1999).
However, McLuhan often gets these relationships between forms and content confused.
For example, in one passage in trying to explain how we positivize the content and ignore
the medium, he says: ‘The “content” of writing or print is speech, but the reader is almost
entirely unaware either of print or of speech’ (1964: 26). To be consistant, McLuhan must
surely mean, ‘the reader is almost entirely unaware either of print or of writing’.
See the next chapter for a critique of this distinction.
For example, McLuhan’s outlook is, even if in a limited sense, able to make some of the
basic connections which are being made today between ‘spaces of flow’ (Castells), be these
of bodies or messages. See, for example, Meyrowitz (1985), Morse (1998), Graham and
Marvin (1996), Calhoun (1992).
McLuhan declares his indebtedness to Innis on a number of occasions. In The Gutenberg
Galaxy (1967) he pronounces: ‘Innis was the first person to hit upon the process of change
as implicit in the forms of media technology’ (50).
THREE
THEORIES OF CYBERSOCIETY
Cyberspace
Throughout October 1999, concerts were held in London, New York and
Geneva to launch ‘NetAid’, the Internet equivalent to the ‘Live Aid’
movement of the mid-1980s. The ‘Live Aid’ movement was comprised of
a series of globally broadcast rolling concerts sponsored by corporations
who received a moral injection to their advertising profile, as well as
patrons at the gates who felt that they were doing something for needy
people they had seen on TV.
The later version of empathy-at-a-distance is one in which, by sitting
at Internet terminals, those people living in economically and informationally rich countries can do ‘something to help’. The Secretary-General
of the United Nations was on hand at the concert, to explain: ‘Most people
in needy countries have to get by on less that two US dollars per day; now,
with the click of a mouse, everyone can help. There are no more excuses,
let’s bring on a new day.’1
The heralding of the Internet as universalist and redemptive has, at
the turn of the millennium, become a widespread discourse, in which the
rhetoric of salvation through an electronic assembly has attained theological proportions. Whether by rhetoric or by clever marketing, the rate of
growth of connection to the Internet network is astonishing.
Cyberspace and virtual reality
As suggested in the Introduction, the distinction between the first and
second media age is a relative one, and is founded on a heightened contrast between the new network mediums and the structures of broadcast
mediums. In this chapter we will explore this contrast by examining
‘second media age’ thinkers who contend that the growth of the Internet
is a reaction to the restricted and unequal possibilities of broadcast. As we
will see, there is a surprising degree of agreement from thinkers liberal,
Marxist and postmodernist over the emancipatory qualities of the Internet.
But before presenting this analysis, it is necessary to explain some of the
technical and structural characteristics of new interactive media and
assess the claims made for a second media age.
Theories of Cybersociety
45
Whilst the term ‘cyberspace’, which first appeared in the prophetic
fiction writing of William Gibson, is most frequently used today interchangeably with the Internet, some thinkers have pointed out that it can
be applied in a much wider sense to include a range of technically constituted environments in which individuals experience a location not
reducible to physical space (see Escobar, 1994; Ostwald, 1997).
By this definition, any medium which encloses human communication in an electronically generated space could be a form of cyberspace.
A further distinction is also often made to designate that such a space may
be very private or shared by others. For example, a personal music listening device with headphones, which Sony Corporation first made famous
with the ‘Walkman’, qualifies as a medium of the enclosure of experience.2
However, it falls short of the conditions necessary for cyberspace in that
it disallows a shared appreciation of the one media ‘event’. The event is
personalized because its ‘performance’ and the environment within
which it is consumed are connected by an individual user.3 Thus, the distinction being drawn here can be recognized in a range of daily media
habits. Meyrowitz (1985) notes: ‘There is a big difference between listening to a cassette tape while driving in a car and listening to a radio station,
in that the cassette tape cuts you off from the outside world, while the
radio ties you into it’ (90).
However, the difference between accessing shared media events and
ones that are personally programmed tends to be overlooked by virtual
reality theorists insofar as they are preoccupied with bandwidth as a leading marker of its definition. In general, virtual realities tend to require
much broader quanta of bandwidth in order to achieve their simulational
properties. Thus, virtual reality is regarded as having found a technological home in digital environments. However, just as peronalization is not
an exclusive feature of digital media or a ‘second media age’, neither is
wide bandwidth.
Across the broadcast medium, significant differences exist between the
virtual qualities of media. Consider the difference between television and
cinema. Cinema offers almost double the bandwidth of TV. An average
size television fills 5% of the visual field, whilst the other 95% is occupied
by possible distractions in the room. Cinema engages 10% of the visual
field, with the other 90% blacked out – eliminating distraction. Cinerama
spans 25% of the visual field, whilst virtual screens fill 100% of the visual
field as such screens receive their data from computer-generated images.
But the technology of projection is merely an extension of broadcast
technologies.4
As I argue in the Introduction to Virtual Politics (Holmes, 1997),
unlike virtual reality, cyberspace does not rely on a deception of the
senses to create the illusion of an integral realism. Rather, it is by the construction of computer-mediated worlds in which (predominantly textbased) communication can occur that an objectivated reality is established
which does not depend on a common deception of sense-impressions. As
Ostwald argues, ‘the critical component of any definition of cyberspace is
46
COMMUNICATION THEORY
the element of community’, because he maintains that a single person does
not exist in cyberspace, but in virtual reality (Ostwald, 1997: 132).
According to James Carey (1995), and, later, Jon Stratton, the most primitive but original place to find the ‘origins’ of cyberspace is in ‘nineteenthcentury attempts to speed up circulation time’ (Stratton, 1997: 254). Therefore
the most fruitful place to look, says Stratton, is to the advent of the telegraph in the first half of the nineteenth century. In the observation of
James Carey: ‘The simplest and most important point about the telegraph
is that it marked the decisive separation of “transportation” and “communication”’ (cited in Stratton, 1997: 254). Stratton contends that it is not
the emergence of the computer and the microchip per se which inaugurates the production of cyberspace, ‘but the increase in the speed of communication over distance to a point where the time taken for a message to
traverse the distance reduces to a period experienced by the receiver, and
sender, as negligible’ (254). By Stratton’s reading, therefore, the development of global telecommunication and of cyberspace is inextricably
intertwined.
Among the major precursors of computer-mediated cyberspace technologies, the telephone can also be counted. As a twentieth-century innovation on the telegraph, the telephone exhibits virtual kinds of features as an
electrically sustained low-bandwidth medium, whilst enabling a limited
kind of electronic assembly. Such an assembly, whilst generally only mutual
for a few persons at a time, nevertheless facilitates a sense of a meeting
place, a place that is augmented by voice mail and answering machine services. The telephone also exhibits a limited number of features of virtual
reality insofar as it is semi-enclosed (a given conversion cannot be heard
simultaneously by anyone other than the interlocutors) and it translates the
voice into a ‘meta-signal’, electrical pulses which convey analogue sounds.
With regard to this latter quality, one of the first theorizations of ‘virtual
reality’ can be found in an early classic on telecommunication by Herbert
and Proctor. The second edition of their work Telephony (1932) distinguishes
electrical current and electrical voltage from what they name as a separate
‘virtual’ current and ‘virtuvoltage’. This distinction is an – albeit crude –
attempt to signify the fact that a telephone exchange, in which individuals
are jacked in to each other by way of operators or agents, purveys an environment that transcends the purely electrical. This other environment stands
somewhere between the human voice and the electrical medium, but lacks
the comprehensiveness of mediums which today earn the appellation of
cyberspace.
Cyberspace and the Internet
The fact that cyberspace is so often conflated with the Internet belies the
fact that there have long been other networks before the Internet which
qualify as domains of the ‘matrix’ or cyberspace. The sum total of these
Theories of Cybersociety
47
networks is sometimes called Barlovian cyberspace, so named after John
Perry Barlow (Grateful Dead band member), who applied Gibson’s term
to CMC as a more complex kind of a space than that which is engaged in
a telephone conversation.
Today the Internet has consolidated into a ‘network of networks’.
Mostly originating from the USA, the major networks which have added
themselves to the Internet include ARPANET (government-funded), Fidonet
(alternative cooperative), Usenet, the WELL, the thousands of corporate
and government intranets, and the World Wide Web. CMC systems that
predated many of these networks, such as email, news groups and bulletin
board systems, are now carried with the expanded Internet network.
One also needs to distinguish between commercial and domestic networks of CMC. Commercial networks have long predated the domestic,
with IBM having its own global intranet some twenty years before the
Internet properly began.5
Certainly, in America, ARPANET was one of the most instrumental in
pioneering the domestic conditions for today’s Internet. Built by a Boston
company under contract, 150 sites had been established across the USA
by the late 1980s. It was designed from the start to allow remote log-in by
passwords, a feature that co-developed with the accelerating speed of
computer modems in the home.
Of surprise to many of the architects of ARPANET was the fact that one
of the most popular sub-media to spring up was email. As Tim Jordan (1999)
explains:
The key point about email is that rather than people using ARPANET to communicate with computers, as the designers expected, people used it to
communicate with other people. This was despite the fact that email was
not programmed into the system but was added unofficially in an ad hoc
way. Email emerged spontaneously as the basic resource provided by
ARPANET and this has been true of virtually all computer networks. People
connect to people using computers, which has given rise to the over-arching
term computer-mediated communication. (38)
However, CMC does not just have to be point-to-point, as what the
various networks have allowed that was unachievable with pre-CMC
communication is correspondence from the many to the many – multiple
authors and readers for which there is no technical limitation. Such a form
of communication achieves an efficiency impossible in embodied form.
Three hundred people can more easily speak to each other in a listserve
conference where each message is recorded in a linear sequence of when
it was sent (an automatic queue for speech) than could the same three
hundred trying to have themselves heard at an embodied conference.
A CMC conference is just one example, therefore, why we should be
dissuaded from seeing cyberspace as merely an extension of social relations which occur outside of it, as clearly it is generative of new relations
that were not previously possible.
48
COMMUNICATION THEORY
The Internet and its sub-media
However, whilst ‘cyberspace’ brings about new possibilities of association,
the form they take is conditioned by the various sub-media that are available
by way of the Internet.
Too often, ‘virtual communities’ are simply tied to some generic
power attributed to ‘the Internet’. It is important to specify the various
sub-media of the Internet and their implications. As is pointed out by a
number of analysts, early fascination with MUDs and MOOs has
declined substantially in proportion to the dominant uses of the Net.
‘While chat rooms, news groups, and multi-purpose Internet conferences
were meaningful for early Internet users, their quantitative and qualitative importance has dwindled with the spread of the Internet’ (Castells,
2001: 118).
For Castells, the Internet is not an amorphous ocean that individuals
dive into, but a galaxy of regulated sub-media: ‘The Internet has been
appropriated by social practice, in all its diversity, although this appropriation does have specific effects on social practice itself’ (118). Drawing
on empirical research, Castells concludes that the on-line identity-building
forums available on the Internet are mostly concentrated among teenagers:
‘It is teenagers who are in the process of discovering their identity, of
experimenting with it, of finding out who they really are or would like
to be ...’ (118).
Castells’ observation that virtual communities have an adolescent
bell curve contradicts the speculative forecasts of the early 1990s that
the Internet can facilitate the formation of very large-scale, so-called ‘virtual
communities’. These assume the form of voluntary spontaneity without
control by a state apparatus as a result of the Internet’s web-like structure,
a structure which is the legacy of a decentred system of sending information.6 The mere fact that it is decentred was argued to be the basis for the
Internet’s alluring emancipation.
The attractions of Internet communication
Of course, the ideological claim that the Internet sets information and its
users ‘free’ was a powerful one in the early years, and was seen by many
writers to be the foundation of a new frontier. The frontier image became
the reigning metaphor of what David Silver has called ‘popular cyberculture’, which refers to that period of civic education of populations into the
attractions of the Internet (see Silver, 2000: 20–1).
But the horizontal/acentric shape of Internet communication offers
attractions that exceed other network architectures (namely, the telephone) – such as bandwidth, the capacity to convey complexity.
Theories of Cybersociety
49
This capacity enables also the possibility of sophisticated reciprocity
in a way which displaces modes of reciprocity in face-to-face, institutionally extended (where a third person becomes an agent of reciprocity) and
electronically extended relations. In making possible more abstract modes
of interchange than these other modes, digital reciprocity engenders the
paradoxical quality of returning to the historically more unmediated of
these modes – the face-to-face as its ideal model – whilst materially annulling
this mode as a cultural ground (see the discussion of ‘re-tribalization’ in
the work of McLuhan below).7 The distinctive features of optical fibre,
which underpins this capacity, are advertised in its potential for computer, voice, graphics and video services, a more extensive host of media
which can guarantee more ‘convincing’ high-fidelity realism to the user.
Such complexity had never been available to analogue forms of electrical
transmission, in a way which could be connected up in instantaneous,
high-speed and multi-data networking. The instantaneousness of the
reciprocity alone is one specific feature which makes possible the metaphorical reconstruction of intersubjective realism – hence the tendency to
conflate ‘cyberspace’ with ‘virtual’ culture.
The production of what are essentially broadband kinds of interactive
environments is qualitatively different from the networks of interchange
based on the electric current alone. This is so because the time-worlds and
space-worlds – the electronically reified environments – that optical fibre
enables are more than merely metaphorical extensions of intersubjective
relations but have the potential to replace and redefine the complexity of
communication systems. Digitally platformed network communication
cannot, like ‘the media’ (remediated or otherwise) that we explored in the
previous chapter, be conceived as a continuation of a system of speech by
other means or even a pretence of the same, in the sense that it enables
constitutively new kinds of interaction that are arguably historically
unique. In particular, the digital nature of this communication places it
beyond the function of extension which analogue technologies are able to
serve (see a longer discussion of this below).
Electrical-analogue time-worlds have never been adequate for the
construction of intersubjective simulation systems. It is only by appropriating the quality of the speed of light, combined with the capacity to convey complexity, that so-called ‘real-time’ and near-instantaneous reciprocity are
made possible in extended form.8
These kinds of technical capacities are also, it is said, remaking the
form and content of technologies traditionally associated with broadcast,
like television. For example, Sherry Turkle (1995) argues that in the ‘age of
the Internet’, television genres have become much more hyperactive in
ways which resemble the random travelling which occurs in cyberspace:
‘quick cuts, rapid transitions, changing camera angles, all heighten stimulation through editing’ (238), a hyperactive style epitomized by MTV –
television’s answer to multi-media.9 This change in tolerance towards a
50
COMMUNICATION THEORY
level of freneticness that has become acceptable to television viewers, and
now commonplace in nearly every rapid-cycle television advertisement
we watch, is mirrored by the fragmentation of the culture industry itself.
As Tim Jordan (1999) points out:
During the 1980s in the USA, the number of independent TV stations grew
from sixty-two to 330, while the share of prime-time audience held by the
three major networks dropped from 90 per cent to 65 per cent. … From
hand-held video cameras that allow the production of home entertainment
to the creation of hundreds of different TV channels, the mass audience
that once constituted the consumers of immaterial commodities has been
shredded. (158)
To the extent therefore that even traditionally well-defined broadcast technologies are, by convergence with interactive technologies or by
diversification, becoming more personalized, more amenable to a sense
of active and interactive control by audiences as well as remarkably
expanded programming choice, it is argued by second media age
writers that a second media age is able to absorb the first media age and
reshape it.
However, as we shall see, what such an argument has to contend
with is the difficulty of distinguishing between broadcast and interactivity as a purely technical distinction, rather than a distinction resting on
forms of social integration.
Theories
The second media age thesis – the Internet as emancipation
from broadcast media
As already argued in Chapter 1, the second media age thesis has become
an orthodoxy in New Media theory, an orthodoxy which has been taken
up almost by default, in many cases with little theoretical engagement or
formulation of positions. In what follows I shall focus on the most cogent
exponents of the thesis as a way of comparatively appraising its significance in relation to other perspectives.
In accordance with the above observations, the Internet stands out as
a comprehensive technoscience world which exemplifies ‘cyberspace’.
With its large range of sub-media (MUDs, ICQs, email and WWW) and its
ability to facilitate complexity, it offers a network medium unparalleled in
its potential and scope.
The contention that the Internet and interactive technologies in general have embedded themselves so substantially in the daily existence of
individuals living in information societies as to have all but usurped the
Theories of Cybersociety
51
power of broadcast media is one that is most forcefully put by second
media age theorists.
In film, radio and television, a small number of producers sent information
to a large number of consumers. With the incipient introduction of the information ‘superhighway’ and the integration of satellite technology with television, computers and telephone, an alternative to the broadcast model, with
its severe technical contraints, will very likely enable a system of multiple
producers/distributors/consumers, an entirely new configuration of communication relations in which the boundaries between those terms collapse.
A second age of mass media is on the horizon. (Poster, 1995: 3)
As discussed in the Introduction, unlike theories of broadcast, which
have been around for some time, theories of cybersociety or the second
media age are, for the most part, very new. Because the Internet, as the
most spectacular technology of electronic network communication, has
only really globally existed in domestically available form since 1991,
communication studies remains in a process of formalizing this new
domain of research. The array of theories, from journalistic to academic,
has been burgeoning. Like the Internet Revolution itself, the rate of
growth in literature about new communication technologies has been dramatic. And as with the pure acceleration of technological change, the
literature is characterized by an urgent impulsiveness which produces
many generalizations and knowledge claims which become redundant at
about the same rate as information technologies themselves.
As noted in the Introduction, since 1991, we have seen a massive
growth in computer-related literature. Prognoses of the paperless society
and the end of the book have not materialized. Instead, book sales have,
if anything, increased, with the weight on each shelf now redistributed to
a flourishing computer section.
Apart from the very short history of cyberspace analysis, there is also
a much larger body of theory relevant to the second media age from preInternet days – theories whose time, it could be argued, has arrived. Of
the broadcast media thinkers, the most prominent to bridge the first and
second media age are probably Marshall McLuhan, Harold Innis and
Joshua Meyrowitz, discussed in the previous chapter. Because content is
of far less importance in studying cyberspace, it is not surprising that the
medium theorists are able to come to the fore.
On the linguistic side there is the work of Derrida, who, in my view,
is the only thinker from the semiotic tradition, apart from Baudrillard,
whose work lends itself to a medium theory. The import of the thought
of these writers will be dealt with later in the present chapter. But first it
is necessary to examine in more detail the claims of the second media age
thinkers.
Theorists of the second media age argue that both broadcast and
interactive communication apparatuses have together constituted the
52
COMMUNICATION THEORY
primary forms of cultural mediation in information societies since the
Second World War. The important point here is that it is not possible, in this
view, to understand the second media age without understanding the first
media age. Traditional media are, as we shall see, central to the distinction
between the first and second media age. Writers such as George Gilder in
Life After Television (1994), Sherry Turkle in Life on the Screen (1995) or Mark
Poster in The Second Media Age (1995) understand the way in which the
second media age has arisen on the back of the conditions produced by the
first. These conditions – the production of an indeterminate mass by broadcast, the separation of individuals from the means of producing their own
contributions to public communication and the disintegration of traditional
community – are all hailed as being overcome by the Internet. But it is an
exaggeration to suppose this overcoming is a permanent condition or that
decentralized network communication simply annuls the power of centralized communication apparatuses. Rather, the power of the former is continuously and relatively parasitic on the power of the latter.
According to the second media age perspective, the tyranny that is
attributed to broadcast lies in its hegemonic role in the determination of
culture (the culture industry) as well as individual consciousnesses
(the theory of hegemony) which derives from its predominantly vertical
structure. This structure is one in which the individual is forced to look to
the image and electronic means of communication to acquire a sense of
assembly and common culture. The second media age, on the other hand,
bypasses this ‘institutional’ kind of communication and facilitates – for
the romantic variety of cyber-utopians, it ‘restores’ – instantaneous, lessmediated and two-way forms of communication.
At the level of interaction, the second media age utopians point to the
empirical increase in the take-up of the Internet and other network technologies, and to the fact that empirically it is true that the Internet is mainly
interaction and very little broadcast whilst television is mainly broadcast
with very little interaction, as evidence for the ‘ontological’ nature of the
second media age as a distinctive trend, movement and modality of social
integration. The importance of the fact that the many can interact with the
many in cyberspace is almost exclusively related to the way it is said
to break the ‘lock-out’ predicament which individuals face in broadcast
interaction. The contraining walls on mediated activities that are erected
by the power of broadcast rapidly disintegrate as a form of electronic
communication is made available which is adequate in speed, form and
complexity to encompass the abstractness of the social forms involved.
In Figure 3.1, the individual is subject to one-way communication from
the ‘elite’ producers of messages. The horizontal connection with other
consumers of the same messages is generally only possible via the fetish
of the image or the celebrity, in whom (as Durkheim once argued in relation to religion) concrete consciousnesses are concentrated.10 Conversely,
with the Internet, the message producers are bypassed, as the walls that
are erected at the horizontal level effectively disappear.
Theories of Cybersociety
53
Media producers
Media consumers as indeterminate undifferentiated ‘mass’
Figure 3.1
Transmission model: high integration/low reciprocity
These ‘media’ walls are the result of the architecture of broadcast
itself. As we saw with Debord in the previous chapter, the more the individual looks to the media so as to acquire a cultural identity, the less he
or she looks ‘sideways’ for interaction. Conversely, the less the individual
looks sideways for social solidarity and reciprocity, the more this mode of
association becomes weak and de-normalized, and so the alternative
dependence on a centralized apparatus of cultural production becomes
imperative.
In the second media age, however, the walls separating individuals
at a horizontal level are overcome, as the individual looks directly to others
for a sense of milieu and association. As Poster (1995) explains:
Subject constitution in the second media age occurs through the mechanism of interactivity. … interactivity has become, by dint of the advertising
campaigns of telecommunication corporations, desirable as an end in itself,
so that its usage can float and be applied in countless contexts having
little to do with telecommunications. Yet the phenomena of communicating
at a distance through one’s computer, of sending and receiving digitally
encoded messages, of being ‘interactive’, has been the most popular application of the Internet. Far more than making purchases or obtaining information electronically, communicating by computer claims the intense interest
of countless thousands. (33)
The Internet lifts individuals out of the isolation created by media
walls – particularly as these walls are reinforced in urban contexts. In
information societies, individuals increasingly interact with computer
54
COMMUNICATION THEORY
screens, developing face-to-screen relations rather than face-to-face
relations, but this opposition is no longer significant, argues Sherry
Turkle, when the larger cultural contexts of post-industrial societies are
eroding the boundaries between the real and the virtual. It is not possible
to think of the individual as alone with his or her computer, as Sherry
Turkle explored in her 1984 text The Second Self; rather, as she more
recently suggests: ‘This is no longer the case. A rapidly expanding system
of networks, collectively known as the Internet, links millions of people in
new spaces that are changing the way we think, the nature of our sexuality,
the form of our communities, our very identities’ (Turkle, 1995: 9). What
Turkle describes as the ‘Age of the Internet’ is synonymous with the
opportunity to build virtual communities ‘in which we participate with
people from all over the world, people with whom we converse daily,
people with whom we may have fairly intimate relationships but whom
we may never physically meet’ (10).
The extent to which the Internet is hailed as an overcoming of fragmentation and individualism is quite remarkable in recent literature. In
some cases it is attributed with an integrative function which is able to
correct a tendency that is over two hundred years old.
As Dave Healy argues, ‘the networked citizen . .. is never alone’. To
the degree that the Internet represents a ‘culture of coherence’, he argues,
it serves as ‘a corrective to the dangers of individualism’ which Alexis de
Tocqueville spoke of in his visit to America in the 1830s (Healy, 1997: 60).
The message of redemption which is promoted in the second media
age thesis, be this for public or private, is a resounding one, a message
whose dreams of unity have theological undertones, to which I shall
return in Chapter 6. But for the most part, the second media age thesis is
derivative of a neo-liberalist broader faith in the emancipatory potential
of new means of communication, regardless of the actual exchanges that
are encouraged by such means. As Armand Mattelart (2000) has suggested, an ‘ideology of limitless communication – but without social
actors’ has taken over from an ‘ideology of limitless progress’ (120).
The computer-mediated communication (CMC) perspective
There is an alternative account of electronically extended interactivity that
significantly predates the second media age thesis, namely the computermediated communication (CMC) perspective.
The CMC perspective overlaps with the second media age perspective but is distinctively concerned with the way in which computer communication extends and mediates face-to-face models of communication.
In this perspective the computer is as much a tool as a window onto
cyberspace. What it is that gets mediated in this perspective is face-to-face
interaction, whether this be between two people or many as in a chat
Theories of Cybersociety
55
group. A symptom of this is the fact that CMC literature is often concerned
with how individuals try to develop ways of substituting the absence of
face-to-face relations on the Internet: for example, by observing netiquette11 (the idea that cyberspace demands forms of polite protocol one
would expect in embodied life), or by the growth of emoticons – the
symbols used in email denoting facial expressions.12
There are four major ways in which CMC literature differs from the
second media age thesis. Firstly, it is focused on the uniqueness of the
communication event in cyberspace. Secondly, it is concerned much more
with interaction than with integration, that is, the myriad of individual
interactions rather than the overall social contexts and rituals by which
these interactions become meaningful. Thirdly, unlike ‘media studies’,
some CMC frameworks are interested in how ‘external factors’ influence
a communication event. With broadcast analysis, very little exploration
occurs of how outer contexts influence media content; rather, media content is assessed according to how it might reflect or express non-media
realities. Finally, whilst not concerned with the kinds of social integration
which might underpin CMC, it is concerned with information integration,
the way in which communicating by way of computers is based in information processes that can be found in a burgeoning number of interactions mediated by computer. This latter point opens out the domains of
cybernetics and the information society, fields of analysis which can be
broadly collected together under the umbrella of information theory.
Information theory The CMC perspective is a continuation of conduit models
of communication first discussed in the 1950s. So before looking at the
contemporary features of CMC it is worth sketching the main contours of
information theory. Oddly, these theories were less relevant to broadcast
than they are to dyadic reciprocity – be it face-to-face or electronically
extended. The fact that they achieved some considerable influence in the
United States during the height of broadcast defies the fact that they were
never able to accommodate the phenomena of performativity, of spectacle, and reification examined in the previous chapter. Dyadic models
of communication are not very helpful in explaining what happens when
a few centres of cultural production send messages to an indeterminate
mass.
The main elements of this outlook, some of which have been
mentioned in the Introduction, are reducible to a process-driven ‘positivist’ model in which intersubjectivity, the communication event between
two entities, becomes the ultimate yardstick with which to measure other
communication processes. The embryo for this view is most commonly
located in Shannon and Weaver’s monograph The Mathematical Theory of
Communication (1949).
As Chris Chesher (1997) appraises this text for its relevance to the
Internet:
56
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Shannon and Weaver separated information content from the means of
its carriage. … While Shannon and Weaver’s information theory was strictly
technical and not concerned with the meaning of messages, it was applied
far more broadly in describing and analysing communications processes.
Information was imagined as a centre of social actions – the ‘information
revolution’, and the ‘information society’. The computer as information transferer and processor applied the epistemological model of ‘information’ in
this tradition. Treating communications as largely a problem of ‘getting the
message across’, and information as autonomous and central, has become
a dominant and often uncriticised premise of contemporary info-culture.
The operation relies on a belief that the informational sign unproblematically
stands in for the actual. (88)
Shannon and Weaver’s theory, a result of research conducted for
the AT&T telecommunications company, aimed to account for how a unit
of information which is produced by a sender at one end of a communication channel is able to be faithfully reproduced at the other end by a
receiver. The source may be speech on the telephone, writing in a book, or
beeps on a telegraph wire, which is conducted on a channel (a wire, a
magazine or book) and received by another person with or without the aid
of a ‘decoding’ device.13 Such a sensibility about information has entered
into everyday popular conceptions. The very nomenclature ‘hi-fidelity’
is erected on this model – that somehow an original performance of a
musical piece can be faithfully reproduced on an electronic music system
in one’s living room. George Lakoff (1995: 116) points out that such a model
also pervades the epistemology of education. The idea that teachers
‘impart’ knowledge to the minds of students which must then be ‘regurgitated in an exam’ presupposes that all knowledge is comprised of stable
quanta of information, and that such information is understood by sender
and receiver in exact duplication.
Shannon and Weaver’s theory is pure medium theory: they were
interested in neither the content of messages, their meaning, the possibility of intentionality behind them, nor the social and psychological condition of their reception. Yet their theory became a standard departure point
for ‘information theory’ as it was appropriated by other disciplines and
perspectives, including structural linguistics (particularly Roman
Jakobson) and media effects theory. The distinction of this theory is that it
rapidly claimed for itself a universal applicability, whether the kind of
communication being examined was between machines, biological entities or human institutions.
It is not surprising that Shannon and Weaver’s physics of communication could easily synchronize with the co-emerging field of cybernetics
(Shannon was a student of Norbert Wiener – the heralded founder of this
discipline). Wiener’s Cybernetics: or Control and Communication in the
Animal and Machine ([1948] 1961) appeared the year before Shannon and
Weaver’s text. In this text, perhaps one of the first formalized understandings of ‘information’ as an ontological force in social life was presented.
Theories of Cybersociety
57
The combination of utopianism and anxiety which is expressed there
seemed futuristic in the 1940s and indeed is in many ways typical of cyberspace literature today. For example, the current fascination with chaos and
complexity theory is anticipated in Wiener’s discussion of entropy as the
tendency for system-based organization to deteriorate without constant
management by ever greater quantities of information.
For the latter condition to prevail, a state of perfect knowledge and
perfect exchange should exist in communication infrastructures. Wiener
would probably be very satisfied with the open and unconstrained character of computer-mediated communication on the Internet and Usenets.
Together with the anthropologist Gregory Bateson, he promoted the
circular realization of information flows containing feedback mechanisms,
which for them was a necessary condition for communicative solidarity.
Their critique of the mathematical theory was not a rejection of its positivism as much as the fact that, as a model designed by and for communications engineers, its unilinearity was unable to accommodate the social
characteristics of communication processes.
Implicitly, of course, the schools influenced by cybernetics were at the
same time critical of broadcast as an antisocial communication apparatus,
consisting of unequal relations between senders and receivers, and a distortion of information that resulted directly from broadcast’s technical
sub-structure rather than from class or ideological biases.
However, whilst the cybernetic schools may have rejected unidirectional modelling, the idea of feedback does not necessarily make the
unilinear model of communication redundant, as John Fiske (1982) has
pointed out:
Feedback … has one main function. It helps the communicator adjust his
message to the needs and responses of the receiver. … Though feedback
inserts a return loop from destination to source, it does not destroy the
linearity of the model. It is there to make the process of transmitting
messages more efficient. (23)
So, by Fiske’s account, the early cybernetic models added the fact that
receivers were more actively a part of the communication process, but
their role remained confined to a transmission model typical of the
‘process schools’.14
It was not until George Gerbner’s (1956) attempt at a general model
of communication that the process school was able to break out of some
of its more positivist underpinnings (i.e. that a medium is a transparent
carrier of messages, and that the content of messages is objectively given,
waiting to be faithfully reproduced).
In his model, the meaning of any given message is culturally relative
as individual perceptions will order and make sense of a communication
event in different ways according to the most familiar cultural frameworks available. The other major departure from the hypodermic model
58
COMMUNICATION THEORY
of communication is in postulating what ‘a message’ actually is. For Gerbner,
a message never exists in some kind of raw state waiting to be coded, sent,
then decoded. Rather, the practice of coding is itself part of what a message is. The revelation that accompanies this, however, is that the medium
in which a message is sent is itself a part of the coding and therefore
of the message – the means and control dimension of communication. The
innovation which Gerbner makes therefore is in critiquing the idea that
the medium or form of communication merely conveys, transports or
transmits the message. Instead, the message is always already a part of
the form.
In also making the listener, viewer or receiver more active in the
process of communication, Gerbner introduces two new concepts: access
and availability. The first refers to the social and technical conditions for
access to a communication medium. In the second media age, not everyone can afford Internet access. First World ownership of television is high,
but access to the transmission of messages is extremely low for most people.
With the concept of availability, Gerbner points towards the closure of
communication at the point of the production of a message. Before the age
of mass media, the availability of ‘information’ was confined to relatively
privileged or cloistered groups of intellectuals who had the literacy skills
denied to the majority. In totalitarian political regimes, the population
may be entirely literate but the central organization of power is based
around the dissemination of selective publications, which has earned the
title of propaganda. Here the selectivity and lack of availability of alternative literature, rather than what it says, is what makes it propaganda.
Critics of propaganda seldom appreciate this fact, putting the influence of
the material down to its ‘highly charged’ ideological character. Paradoxically,
the same publication, when disseminated in democracies offering free
speech, can be heralded as positive proof of this speech rather than derided,
as it might be elsewhere.
Gerbner’s insights, in taking the hypodermic model to extended
lengths, offer some revelations about media ‘form’ to which we can return
later. Nevertheless it should be pointed out that Gerbner still did not depart
from the dyadic positions of the transmission models of communication.
The problem with positivist transmission models of communication
is that they assume that all communication occurs in a vacuum without
appreciation of the social and cultural contexts involved. For example,
largely absent from transmission accounts is an appreciation that the
‘success’ of any particular communication depends on the degree to which
interlocutors might share a common culture.
There are some limited exceptions to this in the models of Lasswell
(1948) and Newcomb (1953). With Lasswell, the addressee is widened to
include mass communication. Because of this fact, Lasswell’s model has
been a popular foundation paper for traditions in media studies, particularly the ‘effects’ tradition and audience studies. The fact that Lasswell
Theories of Cybersociety
59
insisted that mass communication needed a different methodological
approach from personal communication makes his work useful for
analysing broadcast. Lasswell was interested in the influence of communication structures on society as a whole. His most general and famous
adage was: Who says what, in which channel, to whom and with what effect?
Lasswell’s framing of communication theory in this way proliferated into
an array of sub-branches looking at content, control, audience and impact.
But his guiding principles came from functionalist sociology, which
recognized communication institutions as important in the regulation of
social relations, and therefore in need of monitoring, improvement and
policy so as to avoid ‘dysfunction’. These principles address the role that
communication processes can play in social reproduction. Mass communication, in particular, provides an inventory of public messages which
allow social values to be monitored. In large-scale settings of social integration a media-generated consensus around social values enables better
integration between society’s institutions as well as maintenance of traditions and respect for the past.
Lasswell’s work might be seen as articulating Durkheim’s reference
to communication, in the nineteenth century, as a material social fact
which provides one of the ingredients of social solidarity and dynamic
density: ‘... the number and nature of the elementary parts of which society is composed, the way they are arranged, the degree of coalescence
they have attained, the distribution of population over the surface of the
territory, the number and nature of channels of communication, the form
of dwelling etc.’ (Durkheim, 1982: 58). Like Durkheim, Lasswell also continued the nineteenth-century sociological dichotomy of society versus
the individual in which communication is treated entirely as a social fact,
that is, ‘a category of fact with distinctive characteristics: it consists of
ways of acting, thinking, and feeling, external to the individual, and
endowed with a power of coercion, by reason of which they control him’
(Durkheim, 1982: 52).
This dualism of society or ‘system’ versus the individual as the basic
unit of the functionalist paradigm is successful to the degree to which
‘media’ are considered a continuation of social forms by technical means
(see previous chapter), but it runs into difficulties when particular media
are seen to be constitutive of new social forms (see the discussion of
McLuhan below).
Whatever Lasswell’s political aspirations as a reformer, his work has
the merit of offering a general theory of communication that spans broadcast and network. Today the legacy of the Lasswellian approach, combined with the information thinkers, can be seen in the various discourses
that try to grapple with CMC in the vast assortment of perspectives which
are all nevertheless framed by process models: the user perspective,
the content perspective, economic and political perspectives and control
perspectives.
60
COMMUNICATION THEORY
CMC as cyberspace The benefit of the process models for studying the second
media age is that they provide a departure from exclusively content- and
linguistically based models of media analysis. In doing so, they begin to
explore the ‘ends of the chains’ of communication events, taking into
account the significance of who is speaking, the nature of the medium in
which this speech occurs, and the effects of communication events for the
listener.
However, the early information theorists are unable to address two
important questions in CMC: the precise techno-social nature of the medium
that ‘mediates’ in CMC, and the kind of identities that exist on-line.
To illustrate this, consider Gerbner’s model. Gerbner’s advance was
to show how a sender’s or receiver’s appreciation of a medium could
actually alter the content of an individual message to the point where, he
argues, it is imperative that the medium-contexts of communication must
always be taken into account. Of course, this insight is valuable if the
medium that is implicit in the communication process is capable of reproducing the structure or appearance of an object or external reality (analogue communication). With digital communication, however, where
there is no analogy entailed in the communication process, the ability
of a communicant (who is virtually immersed) to make sense of what
the digital substructure signifies socially is almost entirely lost. A prominent
example is that of HTML, the mark-up language used for putting pages
on the World Wide Web. When the pages are finished they can be analogically and graphically hyperlinked with other pages and interactively
interfaced on screen. However, the mathematical code that underpins it
plays little or no part in cognitive communication.
Interestingly, it is only when the complex binary code that underpins
so much of what we actually see on the screen becomes rendered as an
analogue interface that it begins to make sense – not as language, but as
‘space’.
One of the central tenets of computer-mediated communication theory
is that CMC enables a form of ‘socially produced space’ (Jones, 1995: 17),
namely cyberspace. This is said to be comparable to a kind of electronic
agora.15 The agora, dating from post-Homeric Greece, refers to an open
space in which goods and information are exchanged. In the agora, information is typically relayed by word of mouth or by messages posted on
walls, a process which even became institutionalized in European life in
the form of the cosmopolitan coffee house.
The café, which is frequently attributed with the status of bedrock
of ‘civil’ society,16 has of course become an extensive carrier of the proselytization of cyberspace with the large number of cyber-cafés that have
sprung up in cities all over the world. These (embodied) cafés are places
in which the rituals of the old world – coffee consumption – and of the
new – logging on to an ICQ, MUD, MOO or email service – become
entirely blended.
Theories of Cybersociety
61
Paradoxically, these cafés, which are frequented by those interested
in tapping into the civics of cyberspace, at the same time annul the
embodied kind of civics for which cafés were originally invented. The café
table is replaced by benches and rows of terminals appended to coffeestained keyboards.
The other kind of café that is also intertwined with the advancement
of CMC is the on-line virtual café, where, in a MUD or a MOO, participants meet in an analogue representation of a café, present themselves to
other café revellers, and engage in hours of chat.
According to Marc Smith (1995), there are four aspects of virtual
interaction that shape the communication behaviours that go on within
them.
• Virtual interaction is aspatial, whereby increasing distance does not
affect the kind of interactions possible. Because of this, the economies
of co-presence are superseded to the point where mutual presence
becomes redundant in cases where it was once a functional imperative.
Smith cites, for example, the growing trend for companies to relocate
to rural areas.
• Virtual interaction via systems like the WELL is predominantly asynchronous. With the exceptions of Internet Relay Chat, MUDs and ICQs,
CMC (e.g. conferencing systems and email) operates by the flexibility of
posting messages which can be replied to according to the convenience
of users’ own time zone or work schedule.
• As with communities of scholars whose connection is mediated by
print, CMC is acorporeal because it is primarily a text-only medium.
The dual effect of the asynchronous and acorporeal features of CMC is
its facilitation of interaction between quite large groups of people, well
beyond, for example, what telephone conferencing could enable.
• CMC is astigmatic; that is, social differentiation based on stigma tends
to be absent as there are few visible cues and markings or behaviours
which locate an individual with a particular social status.
The last point here is one which Tim Jordan employs in his book
Cyberpower (1999). For Jordan, CMC is inherently anti-hierarchical. He argues
that because identity in cyberspace is seldom identified with the off-line
hierarchies, differentiation based on status is very difficult (81). Secondly,
the many-to-many capacity of the Internet creates a much more inclusive
and participatory environment in which the culture of exclusion which
occurs in off-line life is difficult to sustain.17
CMC and the problem of identity Smith (1995) contends that the four characteristics of
interaction that he advances combine to make virtual interaction reasonably
anonymous. This, he claims, leads directly to issues of identity in a virtual
space.
62
COMMUNICATION THEORY
In many virtual spaces anonymity is complete. Participants may change
their names at will and no record is kept connecting names with real-world
identities. Such anonymity has been sought out by some participants in
virtual interactions because of its potential to liberate one from existing or
enforced identities. However, many systems, including the WELL, have found
that complete anonymity leads to a lack of accountability. As a result, while
all members of the WELL may alter a pseudonym that accompanies each
contribution they make, their user id remains a constant and unambiguous
link to their identity. However, even this fairly rigorous identification system has
limitations. There is no guarantee that a person acting under a particular
user id is in fact that person or is the kind of person they present themselves as. The ambiguity of identity has led some people to gender-switching,
or to giving vent to aspects of their personality they would otherwise keep
under wraps. Virtual sociopathy seems to strike a small but stable percentage of participants in virtual interaction. Nonetheless, identity does remain
in a virtual space. Since the user id remains a constant in all interactions,
people often come to invest certain expectations and evaluations in the
user of that id. It is possible to develop status in a virtual community that
works to prevent the participant from acting in disruptive ways lest their
status be revoked. (www.netscan.sscuet.ucla.edu/csoc/)
This particular kind of anonymity which Smith describes as operating in CMC Jordan sees as a result of the fluidity of identity which operates in cyberspace. This fluidity, which is much more open than is possible
in institutional, embodied life, necessitates individuals’ creation of a stable
self-identity. For this reason, CMC interlocutors tend to spend much more
time than in other forms of communication revealing information about
themselves, their status, place, and other contexts for why they are communicating. Jordan (1999) refers to such an identity as an ‘avatar’.
An avatar is a stable identity that someone using Barlovian cyberspace has
created. The existence of an avatar means someone has used some of
cyberspace’s resources in ways that result in other avatars recognising a
stable online personality. Someone’s avatar may be constructed from
the style of their online writing, from the repeated use of a name or selfdescription, or from any number of other virtual possibilities. (59)
However, no avatar is ever stable for long, and its potential, if not
actual, transiency is always working against its stability. Another feature
of CMC which undermines this stability is the sheer mobility that it offers
communicants. As Steven Jones (1995) has suggested:
The importance of CMC and its attendant social structures lies not only in
interpretation and narrative, acts that can fix and structure, but in the
sense of mobility with which one can move (narratively and otherwise)
through the social space. Mobility has two meanings in this case. First it is
clearly an ability to ‘move’ from place to place without having physically
travelled. But second, it is also a mobility of status, class, social role and
character. (17)
Theories of Cybersociety
63
This mobility is highly evident in the phenomenon of the widening
generation gap between adults and adolescents (see Holmes and Russell,
1999). The empowerment which adolescents experience by way of CMC
immersion is intensified by the fact that it dramatically exaggerates the
generation gap between them and pre-CMC generations. This gap rests
on both the widening differentials in technical competence and the fact that
many parents and teachers find CMC alien in the ways in which it promotes individual forms of adolescent self-construction. In addition, broadband interface technologies such as the Internet lead to rapid identifications
with global concepts of citizenship. The cultural mores which emerge
from the interface of adolescent and technology subsume the narrow
rigidity which previously characterized family norms and conventional
forms of discipline and pedagogy which exist within the classroom.
The new sense of the personal which emerges through CMC immersion establishes itself in differing ways. On the one hand, the investment
of an adolescent’s identity in avatars attenuates embodied or face-to-face
relationships, whilst, on the other, it enhances the personal qualities of
being an autonomous information consumer. Here the status of adolescents as by far the strongest take-up group of CITs becomes particularly
heightened in the age of virtual communities.
Taking some cues off-line – contexts of CMC The generation gap phenomenon that has
been a feature of the take-up of CMC and CITs in general highlights an
aspect of this perspective which has so far been overlooked. Whilst it is
interesting to examine how the technical mediums of CMC may, to varying
degrees, directly affect the forms of community and identity which operate
within them, the outer contexts of CMC also need to be assessed. A prominent exponent of this view is Nancy Baym, who argues in her essay ‘The
Emergence of Community in Computer-Mediated Communication’ (1995)
that ‘[t]oo much work on CMC assumes that the computer is the sole influence of communicative outcomes’ (139). This assumption is exemplified by
what is called the ‘cues filtered-out approach’, which, she says, has come to
dominate the understanding of computer-mediated communication:
Because computer-mediated interactants are unable to see, hear, and feel
one another they cannot use the usual contextualization cues conveyed by
the appearance, nonverbal signals, and features of the physical context.
With these cues to social context removed, the discourse is left in a social
vacuum quite different from face-to-face interaction. (139–40)
Baym identifies five different sources of impact on CMC: external contexts in which the use of CMC is set; the temporal structure of the group;
the infrastructure of the computer system; the purposes for which the
CMC is used; and the characteristics of the group and its members (141).
With regard to the first source, Baym argues that ‘[a]ll interaction, including CMC, is simultaneously situated in multiple external
64
COMMUNICATION THEORY
contexts’ (141). In other words, communication in CMC depends on the
sharing of a common culture which antedates interlocutors exchanging
meaning on the Internet. Secondly, like Marc Smith, Baym points out that
interactions may be synchronous or asynchronous. The time-world of the
exchange is in turn influenced by the sub-variables of the computer system
infrastructure, the speed, number and adaptability of computer interfaces.
Finally the number of interlocutors forming a group and the intensity of
purpose of their interaction will significantly determine what is communicated and how. Baym’s analysis is an important advance in overcoming
the legacy of much information theory, which takes as its ideal-type dyadic
reciprocity as well as transport notions of communication. These departure
points are instructive up to a point, but have difficulty accommodating
the complexity of CMC.
The convergence perspective
An important sub-variant of the second media age thesis, and one more
encompassing than the relatively narrow concerns of on-line CMC perspectives, is found in the literature on media convergence (see Fidler,
1997; Flew, 2002; Van Dijk, 1999). The convergence paradigm can rest on
an architectural distinction between broadcast and network, but sometimes also on an historical (second media age) distinction, as in the case of
Van Dijk.18
Convergence perspectives range from looking at ‘industry convergence’, to medium convergence, to convergence of individual media
technologies.
Technological convergence is the usual starting point for this perspective, and can take place at the level of infrastructure (transmission
links – optical fibre, microwave, satellite) or transportation (content
being transported in a new way such as Internet on TV, or webcasting).
Services such as weather on phones, entertainment on the Internet, but
also types of data, and the way sound, text, data and images can be
combined, are all included under the umbrella of convergence. What
underlies such convergence are various forms of the integration of
telecommunications, data communications and mass communications
(Van Dijk, 1999: 9).
There is also the ‘functional convergence’ that occurs in individual
media products, such as mobile phones converging with digital cameras.
This sense of convergence is perhaps the most commonplace, and mostly
takes the form of pointing out how older ‘analogue technologies’ have
been re-created in the image of digital technologies. There are also
very crude attempts to suggest that television and the Internet exhibit
some kind of essential process of merging because TV can be viewed
on computers, and CMC is readily advertised on television (see Seiter,
1999: 115).
Theories of Cybersociety
65
But these technological levels of convergence are only made possible by
industry convergence, resulting from collaboration between corporations
in telecommunications, media and IT, or by takeovers and mergers
between them. The relationship between corporate and technological convergence is dynamic and two-way. Corporate convergence gives rise to
new combinations of mediums, technological innovation and content
delivery, whilst technological innovation creates the compulsion for new
kinds of corporate convergence.19
But finally, we can speak of the convergence between broadcast and
networking as mediums, which Van Dijk (1999) calls ‘the second communications revolution’. This revolution is one in which older mediums are
redetermined, in two key ways – as interactive and as digital. It is digitalization which, according to Flew (2002: 10–11), is significant for the way
in which it makes platforms and their media inter-operable, and networkable. Moreover, digitalization delivers the cybernetic dream of separating a channel of communication from content. Digital media can be
broken down to a common base of bits, which are universally transferable
and manipulable across media.
So what converges then, in terms of mediums, is not digital and analogue technologies, but new digital technologies, with digitally remediated analogue technology, as Table 3.1 outlines.
Under the broadcast column, television, radio and newsprint are
each available in a digital form, as are many of the consumer items associated with them, such as DVDs and personal computer portals for viewing
or listening to such media. Notable is a return to a wired infrastructure as
providing a wider bandwidth for broadcast media, and the decline of
electromagnetic transmission, which otherwise require an analogue-todigital conversion process for use by the end consumer in digital form.
In the network column, there are also older analogue network
technologies, most obviously the telephone, which was one of the first to
be digitalized, in landline exchanges, but also older analogue mobile networks. However, unlike the broadcast column, there is also an array of
‘born digital’ technologies, which have been made possible entirely
within a network infrastructure context. The Internet is at the frontier of
these technologies, but the digital telephone network is also the hub for
a proliferation of new P2P (person-to-person) networked bandwidth.
On the policy front, broadcasters are interested in the ‘free speech’
implications of a second media age, and exploit the way in which its historicism has become an orthodoxy by lobbying government regulators to
slacken ownership concentration laws. Meanwhile key players in network media who facilitate the de-commodification of broadcast products,
software, music and film-downloading web portals, are attacked by the
owners of such media products via civic-legal means or by relayed pressure through telecommunications authorities. In this case, however, the
arguments are not political, concerned with freedom of speech, but exclusively economic.
66
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Digitalization as the basis of convergence, wider
bandwidth and multi-media (the ability to combine image, sound
and text)
Table 3.1
Technology
Broadcast (wireless
and wired)
Network (wireless
and wired)
Digital TV, radio on-line,
news text on-line, DVDs
Older network technology:
‘digital-enabled’ ISDN,
mobile telephony, from
analogue to digital
Altogether newly ‘born
digital’ technologies: the
Internet, mobile text, mobile
fax, mobile data, mobile
video text, networked PDAs
(Personal Digital
Assistants). Providing new
services: home shopping,
banking, gambling,
searchable databases
Medium-channels
Electromagnetic waves,
satellite, microwave,
copper and optical fibre
cable
Satellite, microwave,
copper and optical fibre
cable
Policy
Broadcasters pressure
governments to relax
policies, because
‘everyone’ can be a
broadcaster
Networking makes
possible the provision of
more information and
entertainment that is
otherwise commodified by
broadcasters and telcos
(telecommunications
corporations) and now
provided for free. MP3,
movies, news – dilutes
the user-pays dimension
of media
Advertising not as powerful,
but its promise has caused
losses for broadcasters
For convergence theorists, technologies, media and policies have
each become more interdependent across both broadcast and network
architectures of communication:
No medium today, and certainly no single media event, seems to do its cultural work in isolation from other media, any more than it works in isolation
from other social and economic forces. What is new about new media
comes from the particular ways they refashion older media and the ways in
which older media refashion themselves to answer the challenges of new
media. (Bolter and Grusin, 1999: 15)
Theories of Cybersociety
67
The virtual urbanization perspective
To confine the discussion of convergence to technology and industry can
overlook the ways in which very profound convergences are happening
between electronic and physical spaces. Compared to the research on
media convergence, there is much more literature dealing with the
convergence between technology and urban life.
Whereas both convergence and the CMC perspective have largely
neglected the influence of external realities, as Baym (1995) has pointed
out, there is certainly a growing body of literature which can be and
which is distinctively concerned with the urban contexts of media cultures, both new and old (see, e.g., Boyer, 1996; Crang et al., 1998; Droege,
1997; Graham, 2000; Graham and Marvin, 1996; Hall and Brotchi, 1991;
Hepworth and Ducatel, 1992; Holmes, 1997; Mitchell, 1996; Ostwald,
1997; Soja, 1996; Swyngedouw, 1993; Turow and Kavanaugh, 2003). This
literature, which is oriented towards a ‘virtual urbanization’ perspective,
is beginning to explore the multiple interrelations between computermediated space and contemporary urban space. As I have argued elsewhere (Holmes, 1997), virtual realities are already embodied in particular
everyday technologies such as freeways, television and the shopping mall
(41–2). The most instructive feature of these technological forms is that they
can already be considered as proto-virtual realities, displaying features
that characterize virtual spaces: they tend to homogenize ‘culture’ according to a logic which makes experience over in its own image; and they
presuppose and are major contributors to the production of cosmopolitan
world-spaces.
Implicitly, virtual urbanization is a perspective which sees life on the
screen not so much as a new or additional development but as an internal
development of the logic of modernity and of the kind of urbanization
that accompanies it.
Whereas, with conceptualizations of the first media age, broadcast
is viewed as a neutral kind of service to urbanization and city life, it can
now, with the Internet, be seen much more as a precondition of this urbanization. Globally, urban populations are increasing much more rapidly
than the rate of increase of overall world population. According to UN
estimates, urban dwelling worldwide was 39% in 1975, 50% in 2000, and
will be 63% in 2025.
The central features of urbanization that are relevant to the rise of the
second media age are:
• the increased scales of spatial separation of workplace from
household;
• the atomization of an urban population into units of consumption;
• the standardization of the built environment;
• the privatization and duplication of access to property and resources.
68
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Urbanization, but also suburbanization, is enhanced by an increase
in transportation and communication technologies which have traditionally enabled the maintenance of geographic association. As I have argued
elsewhere (Holmes, 2001: 31), ‘... as cities grow in their scale and abstractness, the older technologies of urban connection, the motor car, the television, the telephone, can become inadequate for the maintenance of a daily
cycle of connection’. Because of this, new forms of communicative networks such as the Internet and mobile telephony are lauded for their
perceived speed and efficiency in being able to replace the relatively cumbersome networks of old. Alternatively, there is also a tendency to abandon
urban networks altogether, as they become replaced by the security village,
the gated community, within which the home becomes the ultimate refuge.
The retreat to ever-shrinking spaces of urban privacy – the home, the graphics of the personal computer, the intimacy of the SMS keypad – leads to ever
greater ‘personalization’. This in turn opens up markets for the commodification of the means to ever greater control over immediate environments –
be this with the car, the home cinema or electronic assistance that is carried
on the body.
The more individuals find connection to an ‘outside’ on the basis of
personalized domestic electronic refuges, the less need there is for the
main street or the agora, and for public space in general. What public space
remains tends to itself be characterized by very enclosed and privately
controlled environments.
Both the physical and the electronic urban architectures converge
around the principle of continuous subdivision. Such subdivision is
endless in its scale, as the connectivity that these network spaces make
possible enables ever-expanding forms of urbanization – cities on ever
greater scales. Within these scales, each domestic or individual unit is separated and united at the same time. The relationship is dialectical: the
more the individual cell is able to be integrated via a centralized, decentralized or distributed network, the less dependence there is on proximity
to or physical immediacy with others. Conversely, the less individuals
get to know their neighbours, the more important it is to be tuned in or
logged on to one of these networks.
These relations of synthesis through segregation are already anticipated in Debord’s account of the social bond via the image and of Adorno
and Horkheimer’s depiction of the culture industry, which is further discussed in the next chapter. However, what they do not analyse is the way
in which media forms coalesce with other urban means of connection.
For example, an important dominating virtual space is the contemporary freeway. The technical as well as metaphorical links between the
motor vehicle superhighway and the so-called information superhighway
are quite profound (see Jones, 1995: 10–11). Freeways and electronic media
are deeply embedded in the suburbanization process as well as making
possible ever greater separation between workplace and home and leisure
zones – such as the mega shopping malls.
Theories of Cybersociety
69
As I have argued elsewhere (Holmes, 2004), the path-dependence on
motorized transport and the path-dependence on telecommunication
are mutually constitutive. When our social world becomes geographically
fragmented, we privately come to rely on the agents of separation that
have aggregately produced this condition. Wherever freeways have driven
corridors of speed and efficiency through a city, it creates a culture of
avoiding accidental contact with strangers. Emphasis is placed on the
control which individuals have over their use of urban space. As we
become more monadic in retreating to spaces from which we can exercise
this control, such virtualization has the added ‘benefit’ of removing us
from physical danger from embodied others, at the same time as it
encourages us to fear others. As soon as we leave our car we become a
delinquent, as Baudrillard quips about the LA freeway system. The motor
car is as much an agent of protection as it is of transport. Our fleeting
association with others travelling at high speed is unfulfilling in any
physical sense of exchange as other drivers become our objects of ‘road
rage’ just as anonymous interlocutors on the Internet can subject each
other to ‘flaming’.
The return of McLuhan
Having addressed recent literature on the urban and technical dynamics
of cybersociety, it is instructive to return to the work of Marshall
McLuhan as a case example of a thinker who provides a very early
account of network media culture.
What we can nominate as McLuhan’s ‘second media age’, which he
calls the age of ‘automation’ or cybernation, is contrasted with the mechanical age of mass reproduction, which is the first media age. However, in
McLuhan’s texts we can identify two prior forms of media-tagged societies
in relation to which the mechanical/electric distinction operates. These are
‘tribal’ social conditions based on speech and scribal society based on
alphabetic writing. Together, the four kinds of society – tribal, scribal,
mechanical and electric – do not evolve in a linear progression, but rather
each kind of society can encompass a number of qualities which are found
in others. Moreover, McLuhan does not posit an over-arching process to
the development of these revolutions. It is only in the electric age that what
he calls the sense ratio and sensory balance that individuals have with
their environments becomes stable once again. This results in what he
views as a ‘re-tribalization’ of culture, a return to days of audile sensory
stability, before the distorted technological mediums of writing and print.
The mechanical age is characterized by fragmentation but uniformity,
repetition and centralism corresponding to the first media age, whilst the
electric age is one of integration via decentralization, which creates
‘extreme interdependence on a global scale’. To a large degree, individuals
in information societies are still catching up with the new possibilities of
70
COMMUNICATION THEORY
technically constituted worlds because they are caught off guard by the
biases of print culture. Certain adjustments in psycho-social life are
necessary before we can face ‘electromagnetic technology’.
For McLuhan, information, rather than vision, becomes the basis of
the electric age. In a passage very similar to Jean-François Lyotard’s claims
in The Postmodern Condition (1984: 194), he argues that the era of cybernation is one in which prior forms of technological extension will not be
allowed to exist except by being translated into information systems
(McLuhan, 1967: 68; see also Innis, 1972).
A well-known distinction that McLuhan makes which roughly corresponds to a first versus second media age thesis is that between ‘hot’ and
‘cool’ medium. Hot mediums include radio, movies, photographs. Cool
mediums include the telephone and TV.
A hot medium is one that extends one single sense in ‘high definition’. High
definition is the state of being well filled with data. A photograph is, visually, ‘high definition’. A cartoon is ‘low definition’, simply because very little
visual information is provided. Telephone is a cool medium, or one of low
definition, because the ear is given a meager amount of information. And
speech is a cool medium of low definition, because so little is given and so
much has to be filled in by the listener. On the other hand, hot media do
not leave much to be filled in or completed by the audience. Hot media, are,
therefore, low in participation, and cool media are high in participation or
completion by the audience. (McLuhan, 1964: 31)
These relationships can be represented as in Table 3.2. From this table it
can be observed that McLuhan partially subscribed to an ‘informational’
view of communication, in which senders and receivers become connected by a message. The receiver of hot messages may have quite a bit of
work to do – depending on the medium. Notably also, McLuhan does not
distinguish between technologies of broadcast (like TV) and point-topoint network technologies (like the telephone).
There are a number of difficulties with McLuhan’s explication of hot
and cool mediums, however – like his rather strained distinction between
cinema and television. Firstly, it is true that cinema is able to provide
‘more information’ than television, especially if a sense-impression view
is taken20 – it has a wider screen – but the ability of television to convey
complexity is quite outstanding compared to other forms of media.
Secondly, McLuhan claims that hot mediums tend to extend only one
sense in high definition. His classification of cinema as ‘hot’ is glaringly
out of place in this regard. Thirdly, McLuhan claims that a cinema or radio
audience is passive whilst a television one is more active. During his own
time of writing and to date, no empirical audience studies have shown
this to be true. Fourthly, McLuhan contradicts himself where he says that hot
mediums tend to overtake cool mediums, but that, historically, it is ‘past
mechanical times’ that can be designated as hot’ whilst the ‘contemporary
Theories of Cybersociety
Table 3.2
71
Features and types of hot and cool mediums
Features (McLuhan,
1964: 31–3)
Hot mediums
Cool mediums
Low participation
Extends one single
sense
High definition
A large amount of
information
High participation
Tend to ovetake cool
mediums
Tend to be mechanical,
repetitive, uniform
Examples (McLuhan,
1964: 31–2)
Radio
Cinema
Photograph
Phonetic alphabet
Telephone
Television
Cartoon
Speech
Hieroglyphic and
ideogrammatic written
characters
Paper
Lecture
Book
Monastic and clerical
script
Stone
Seminar
Dialogue
Past mechanical times
Developed countries
The contemporary TV age
Underdeveloped countries
Print
Examples (McLuhan,
1964: 36)
Low definition
Small amount of
information
Need to be completed by
the audience
Tend to be supplanted and
remade by hot mediums
TV’ age is cool (36). Finally, McLuhan describes how cool mediums ‘need
to be completed by an audience’. However, the actual instances of cool
mediums he specifies – telephone, cartoon, speech (if taken as face-to-face),
the interactive seminar and dialogue – don’t actually have an ‘audience’,
whereas the hot mediums of radio, cinema, print and lectures do.
For McLuhan’s schema to have coherence, television should be
placed in the category of a hot medium. If this were done, his account would
make sense in terms of the first and second media age – corresponding to
what he calls the mechanical age versus cybernation. I point this out, not
in order to fit everything into the dualism that this distinction purveys,
but because McLuhan himself is inconsistent.
A final problem is the way the hot/cool distinction is over-extended
to include all manner of objects, past and present societies, stone and
paper, phonetics and writing, so much so that it dilutes itself by way of
a generalized and generalizing dualistic vitalism.
However, in differentiating between hot and cool media according
to definition and information, different technologies are clustered in a
72
COMMUNICATION THEORY
parallelism around like mediums according to broadcast and network
integration. That is, the telephone (cool), even though it is interactive,
allowing for significant ‘participation’ in a communicative event, is merely
a conduit for speech, but lacks the (hot) range of cues and information
involved in the face-to-face. Television, one would think is, in itself pretty
‘hot’, but compared to its ‘counterpart‘, cinema, with its imposing highquality screen and sound, television is actually quite cool. Christopher
Horrocks (2001) claims that the Internet has problematized the status of
television as a cool medium. Cool mediums demand high participation,
and wide bandwidth interactivity is a heightened form of participation
otherwise denied to television. Horrocks suggests that because the Internet
acts like a kind of meta-medium in combining a range of media, of which
television becomes part of its content, it renders television not so ‘cool’
anymore and the latter can be considered ‘hot’ in relation to the Internet, if
we allow it to be considered as a distinct medium.
McLuhan’s distinction between hot and cold media places the capacity for a medium to convey complexity at a premium – in the volume of
information (what the cyberspace theorists would see as bandwidth), the
level of definition (e.g. the continuums that McLuhan never really wrote
about – analogue to digital) and the number of senses that it works upon.
Notably, McLuhan’s observations on hot and cool media are a remarkable
anticipation of the theoretical analysis of ‘virtual reality’.
As Nguyen and Alexander (1996) point out, for McLuhan, ‘every new
technology changes how our sense organs operate to perceive reality, and
it may be that computer technology changes not only our perception of
reality but also our very selves’ (112–13).
Media, by altering the environment, evoke in us unique ratios of sense perceptions. The extension of any one sense alters the way we think and act –
the way we perceive the world. When these ratios change, [individuals]
change. (McLuhan and Fiore, 1967: 41)
However, notably, we are never aware of the hold which a medium has
over us when it is effective and operating. As soon as we notice a medium,
it becomes ‘old’. This is arguably why it is possible to speak of a ‘second
media age’ now that the Internet and network-interactive technologies are
more prominent – the older mediums of broadcast are rendered more
object-like, rather than invisible.
Social implications
Cyberspace as a new public sphere
One of the most prominent implications of the purported ‘re-tribalization’
of the consequences of the second media age is the way in which it is said
Theories of Cybersociety
73
to allow a renewal of the public sphere. During the 1970s a number of
thinkers heralded the decline of the public individual and of the public
sphere (see Gouldner, 1976; Habermas, [1962] 1989, and, later, 1974;
Sennett, 1978). Post-broadcast accounts of the public sphere lay claim to
new kinds of politics, new kinds of ‘electronic assembly’, and even a return
of participatory democracy by way of CMC. In the 1990s the most enthusiastic promoters of electronic democracy came from the editors of Wired
magazine. Jon Katz prophesied the emergence of a ‘digital nation’ in which
on-line culture would offer the means for individuals to have a genuine
say in the decisions that affect their lives, whereas Kevin Kelly saw in the
Internet a revival of ‘Thomas Jefferson’s 200-year-old dream of thinking
individuals self-actualizing a democracy’ (cited in Lax, 2000: 160).
In a key text addressing the role of the Internet in transforming the
nature of the public sphere, Mark Poster (1997) claims that ‘contemporary
social relations seem to be devoid of a basic level of interactive practice’
(217). For Poster, the physical forums for ‘interactive practice . .. such as
the agora, the New England town hall, the village church, the coffee
house, the tavern, the public square, a convenient barn, a union hall, a
park, a factory lunchroom, and even a street corner’ (217), are in decline.
The central factor behind such a demise of embodied assembly is, according to Poster, the concomitant rise of broadcast media which ‘isolate
citizens from one another and substitute themselves for older spaces of
politics’ (217).
Poster takes up John Hartley’s argument that, for all intents and purposes, broadcast media are the public sphere: ‘Television, popular newspapers, magazines and photography, the popular media of the modern
period, are the public domain, the place where and the means by which
the public is created and has its being’ (Hartley, 1992b: 1). In Hartley’s view,
the media provide a specular space which, although it lacks the possibility
of direct interaction, allows participants to express public opinion through
the act of consuming media as well as to relate to a common culture of discourses. If it is true that, as Hartley would suggest, the electronic media
have eclipsed and displaced the public sphere, then a great deal of pressure is placed on understanding what kind of public sphere electronic
media produce.
The specular space of the media, where all participants can relate to
message producers and the messages that are produced, is one which, up
to a point, sits well with Jürgen Habermas’s idea of an homogeneous
universal public sphere. In a central work, The Structural Transformation of
the Public Sphere ([1962] 1989), Habermas defines the public sphere as a
domain of uncoerced conversation directed exclusively towards pragmatic
agreement. For Habermas (1989), such a development of a democratic
public sphere was possible in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
but has been diluted in the current period by the fact that the apparatus of
media is controlled by interests which systematically distort the content of
public discourse.21
74
COMMUNICATION THEORY
However, what is also stressed in Habermas’s earlier work is the
importance of ‘literacy’ in the formation of discursive publics. For him,
the press was at the centre of a rational project towards democracy. Taking
Britain as a model, Habermas argues that capitalist entrepreneurs promoted the ‘world of letters’: ‘The public sphere in the political realm
evolved from the public sphere in the world of letters’ (1989: 30–1).
Through the salon, theatre, and the coffee house, ‘Conversation turned
criticism and bon mots into arguments’ (31) as public discourse became
autonomous from church and court. Looking for emancipation from
church and state, the rising bourgeoisie appealed to enlightenment
values of ‘free speech’ and debate in the same stride as they sought to
remove the obstacles to a free market.22 Such values enabled educated
and propertied classes to maintain ideological power, but nevertheless
upheld the ethos of freedom of opportunity and the sense of citizenship
that accompanies this.
The extent to which the Internet and new ‘interactive’ technologies
facilitate and maintain the literacy necessary for Habermas’s rational project is pivotal here in deciding what contribution they can make to any
form of democratic deliberation. Certainly, studies of how Internet submedia are used show that they are highly text-based, but to what extent is
such textual communication merely a reproduction of off-line communication? And to what extent do personal computers using graphic user
interface share with TV and video games the privileging of ‘emotion and
empathy instead of reason and judgement’? (Kaplan, 2000: 208).
In a volume looking at the idea of global literacy on the Web,
Hawisher and Selfe (2000) ask: ‘How does the ordered space of the Web
affect the literacy practices of individuals from different cultures – and the
constitution of their identities – personal, national, cultural, ethnic – through
language? What literacy values characterize communications practices in
this ordered space?’ (1)
They critique the claims of Net ideologists such as MIT Media Lab
director Nicholas Negroponte and former US Vice-President Al Gore
that the Web is a culturally neutral literacy environment. Such a claim is
derivative of an imperializing, ‘global village’ narrative which ‘is shaped
by American and Western cultural interests at the level of ideological
production’ (1).
The ethnocentric ideology of the global village heroically imagines
the information networks which the West supplies to ‘the world’ as some
kind of paternalistic gift-of-community. Or, as Hawisher and Selfe put it
rather more cynically:
According to this utopian and ethnocentric narrative, sophisticated computer
networks – manufactured by far-sighted scientists and engineers educated
within democratic and highly technological cultures – will serve to connect
the world’s peoples in a vast global community that transcends current
geopolitical borders. Linked through this electronic community the peoples
Theories of Cybersociety
75
of the world will discover and communicate about their common concerns,
needs and interests using the culturally neutral medium of computer-based
communication. When individuals within the global community discover –
through increased communication – their shared interests and commonweal, they will resolve their differences and identify ways of solving global
problems that extend beyond the confining boundaries of nation states. (2)
What makes a lie of such a narrative is the fact that the greater majority of
the world’s population does not have access to the Net or World Wide
Web. Rather, ‘the culturally specific nature of literacy practices clearly
influences the use of the Web and the use of the internet in fundamental
ways’ (2), especially when we consider what Selfe calls the ‘ideologically
interested nature of the global-village narrative as constructed specifically
within the framework of American and western politics and economics,
and culture’ (2).
The fragmentation of the bourgeois public sphere
If we take Hawisher’s, Selfe’s and Habermas’s observation that the bourgeois public sphere is very much confined to the educated and literate
classes, and, globally, their concentration is in powerful Western nations,
it becomes difficult to conflate an Internet-mediated public sphere with
anything like a ‘global village’. Whilst every nation and every population
is part of the globe, not everyone partakes of this idyllic public arena.
However, not even the bourgeois public sphere, in its limited form, is
as unitary as cyber-utopians claim it to be. Since Habermas put forward
his thesis of a unitary public sphere, many theorists have suggested alternative models, such as Negt and Kluge’s (1993) idea of an ‘oppositional’
working-class public sphere, Rita Felski’s concept of a feminist public
sphere, and Nancy Fraser’s (1990) notion of a ‘post-bourgeois’ public
sphere.
What is distinctive about these last mentioned models is that they
each define themselves against a unified public sphere as pervaded by
some version or other of a ‘dominant ideology’ – be it patriarchal or bourgeois or perhaps ‘logocentric’, and based too much on decision-making
and questions of ‘consciousness’. More recently, newer understandings
of a public sphere have emerged which can be viewed as qualitatively
different from traditional civic and media-extended accounts of ‘publicness’.
These newer theses take account of interactive media and ‘interactivity’
as considerations in the delimitation of alternative possibilities of civic
integration.
Todd Gitlin (1998) has advanced the idea of ‘public sphericules’, segmented spheres of assimilation which have their own dynamics and
forms of constitution. Gitlin argues that ‘a single public sphere is unnecessary as long as segments constitute their own deliberative assemblies’ (173).
76
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Gitlin suggests that the segmented assemblies constituted by computermediated communities do loosely interrelate, in a parallel sphere of
liberal-pluralist diversity. It is akin to the state-generated public sphere
implied by ‘multi-culturalism’, in which a citizen in, say, Australia or
America might adopt a national identity by embracing a much more
unitary principle of publicness – liberal or communitarian pluralism.
Finally, the segmentation of the public sphere comes to bear down on
the question of democracy itself:
Does democracy require a public or publics? A public sphere or separate
public sphericules? Does the proliferation of the latter, the comfort in which
they can be cultivated, damage the prospects for the former? Does it not
look as though the public sphere, in falling, had shattered into a scatter of
globules, like mercury? The diffusion of interactive technology surely
enriches the possibilities for a plurality of publics – for the development of
distinct groups organized around affinity and interest. What is not clear is
that the proliferation and lubrication of publics contributes to the creation
of a public – an active democratic encounter of citizens who reach across
their social and ideological differences to establish a common agenda of
concern and to debate rival approaches. (173)
Gitlin does not address the role of CMC in traditional kinds of
decision-making activities like voting, which characterize participatory
kinds of democracy (see Sobchack, 1996), but, rather, suggests that the
electronic public sphere, what John B. Thompson (1995) calls ‘mediated
publicness’, facilitates a ‘deliberative’ model of democratic engagement.
Gitlin’s view accords with the thesis of Barbara Becker and Josef
Wehner (1998), who argue that interactive media support the formation of
‘partial publics’ – ‘discourses characterised by context-specific argumentation strategies and special themes’ (1).
Becker and Wehner still subscribe to the idea that traditional mass
media have the central role of mobilizing and institutionalizing public
opinion, but argue that interactive media are growing in significance as a
space for the formation of ‘pre-institutional’ forms of public opinion.
Interactive media enable alternative kinds of public opinion, but this
‘alternativeness’ does not come out of ideological reaction to dominant
values in the media, but from the structure of interactive mediums themselves. Thus, Becker and Wehner follow Neidhardt and Gerhards in arguing that different forums of public opinion – based on direct or extended
interaction, on assemblies, or on the mass media – correspond to different
ways of ‘selecting, clustering and spreading information’ (Becker and
Wehner, 1998: 2).
Technologically extended interactive environments are distinguished
from mass media by the fact that they are unable to constitute a ‘mass’ in
which individuals are related together as ‘citizens’. Rather, the Internet
promotes differentiation instead of homogenization by ‘generating polycontextual communication structures’ in which there ‘is no citizen who is
Theories of Cybersociety
77
discussing with other citizens on the net. Rather, there are simply
individuals – such as experts, old people, homosexuals, women, men,
children, youngsters – who debate their particular interests on the net’
(Becker and Wehner, 1998: 2). Becker and Wehner echo many of the
advances made by the second media age theorists. However, they add
two important observations which challenge the characterization of the
Internet as a free de-centralized structure by firstly pointing out that the
numerous sub-media of the Internet are characterized by ‘thematically
restricted domains’ – a point to which I will return. Secondly, less and less
information on the Net can be regarded as ‘public’ and universally accessible as, increasingly, the bulk of Internet content becomes colonized by
contextless, fragmented information (advertising, spam, unverified messages) whilst a significant volume of ‘bandwidth’ is accessible only by
institutional and private elites.
Public/private
What both the models of ‘unified’ and ‘partial’ politics discussed above
are committed to is some notion of the separation of the public from the
private, which rests on the Greek distinction between polis (the place of
demos – democracy) and the oikos (household.) The public/private distinction is a complex one, which in modern capitalism is so often confused by
the extension of private control (private property, private interests) into
the ‘public sphere’ as market place. The traditional pre-capitalist market
place is not a place of private interests negotiating but of the public good
of exchange. Today the private exists in the public sphere, as can, to take
Hartley’s argument, the ‘public’ exist in the private. Privacy might be
commonly thought of as being confined to the spaces of the home, but
this is also, increasingly, the place where, paradoxically, individuals gain
access to the public sphere.
This is mutually generated; the less individuals engage in practices
of interaction in ‘public spaces’, the more they are likely to be engaged in
interactive practices in private spaces, and vice versa. Under these conditions the household unit becomes a primary cell of modern social relations, the basic unit and building block from which social interaction
occurs. When the public sphere has withdrawn to the home, where a
‘dialogic’ or two-way open interaction becomes impossible, interaction
becomes more and more ‘confined’ to the family, the household and one’s
workplace.
These conditions certainly did not obtain in pre-media society, in
which the frequency and intensity of embodied interaction were of
an entirely different order. The origins of European modernity since the
eighteenth century, for example, are founded on the café as the bedrock of
the emergence of a public sphere (Habermas, 1989). In the year 1700, for
example, the city of London boasted 3,000 coffee houses.
78
COMMUNICATION THEORY
However, in media societies, where the geographic and kinship ties
of the parish, local neighbourhood or industrial slum have virtually
disappeared, individuals have historically become very heavily dependent
on media of many kinds to acquire a sense of belonging and attachment
to others. The situation is one of separation and unity. Individuals are separated at a geographic level, locked away in their housing-allotment
or -unit fortresses, but united on scales of city or nation in their attachment
to forms of media. Ironically, the marketing calls for consumers to ‘get
connected’ and ‘travel on the Internet’ instead of being ‘stuck at home’ are
an exact reproduction of the social and urban consequences of broadcast
technologies. Individuals are told they can interact to overcome the
tyranny and restraints of broadcast, but they do so only by reinforcing the
domestic conditions of their atomized existence.
The question of whether interaction, once it is reduced to the electronically mediated and technologically extended kinds of access to communication which are enabled from the home, constitutes participation in a
public sphere is a pivotal one to ask in relation to CMC. Certainly the
private/public question becomes extremely vexed on the Internet. As Poster
(1997) suggests:
If ‘public’ discourse exists as pixels on screens generated at remote locations by individuals one has never met and probably will never meet, as it
is in the case of the Internet with its ‘virtual communities’, ‘electronic
cafés’, bulletin boards, e-mail, computer conferencing and even video conferencing, then how is it to be distinguished from ‘private’ letters, printface
and so forth? (219–20)
We could add to Poster’s observation the fact that virtual meeting places
are replicated in physical form in cybercafés and video-cafés. Symbolically
as well as functionally, the cybercafé is extremely interesting. It strongly
re-affirms the idea that the cellular network basis of gaining access to the
public sphere predominates, where even one of the strongest institutions
of embodied public life can be remade in terms of CMC. Nobody meets
face-to-face at a cybercafé, as the face-to-screen interaction precludes dialogic
contact in any form other than the electronic.
Problems with the public cybersphere thesis
The success of any argument claiming a special role for the Internet in
the constitution of a new public sphere rests on its ability to establish a
practical/imaginary unity in which all participants have equal opportunity
for ‘observation’ and communication. This postulated imaginary unity, best
known in the phrase ‘virtual community’, seldom reconciles itself with the
fact that the Internet is not at all technically homogeneous and is segmented
into quite a range of properties and capabilities which each carry different
sociological and communicative potentials and effects.
Theories of Cybersociety
79
It is true that, unlike television, the Internet is a network23 as well as
‘dialogical’, capable of a two-way dialogue. But its network properties are
rarely realized in communication directly, and seldom do they become
meaningful qua network, because, as Becker and Wehner (1998) point out,
individuals only ever ‘use’ the Internet within well-defined sub-mediums.
Trevor Barr (2000) usefully breaks down the different kinds of interaction on the Internet into six categories:
1
2
3
4
5
6
one-to-one messaging (such as email);
one-to-many messaging (such as ‘listserv’);
distributed message databases (such as USENET news groups);
real-time communication (such as ‘Internet Relay Chat’);
real-time remote computer utilization (such as ‘telnet’); and
remote information retrieval (such as ‘ftp’, ‘gopher’ and the World
Wide Web’). (118)
It can be seen from this list that the Internet provides a generic environment for a number of different modes of interaction which can vary
according to real time/stored time, symmetrical versus asymmetrical
dialogue, broadcast sending and receiving, and information posting and
retrieval.
But each of these modes of interaction relates very differently to the
possible constitution of an ‘electronic public sphere’. Moreover, the information and communication possibilities of the Internet are more often
than not parasitic of broadcast-mediated communication. The growth of
companion websites which accompany media organizations, newspapers, consumer products, sporting events, etc., has provided an astonishing impetus to the use of information retrieval, listserv and interactive
databases available on the Internet.
When CMC is broken down into specific sub-media rather than
reduced to the indeterminacy of the Internet as a communication environment, a more sophisticated appreciation of the technological transformations of the public sphere is enabled, and the advancement of new
accounts of context-specific partial publics is one outcome.
However, at the same time, the global reach and mobility of all forms
of Internet communication, regardless of the specificities of their submedia, also need to be accounted for. The reason for this, I argue, is that it
is impossible to separate the significance of contemporary CMC from its
antecedent and wider context of broadcast communication culture.
Why this is significant is that, whereas broadcast generates an instant
‘international context’ of social connection, there are few ways in which
individuals can achieve meaningful interaction to make tangible these
global connections. There are telephones and other ‘narrow-band’ ways of
communicating, but none of these is quite able to provide a multi-media
context for any given interaction. The Internet, it is argued by its promoters,
changes all of that.
80
COMMUNICATION THEORY
In accounting for the growth of computer-mediated communication
via the Internet, both national and global statistics become significant.
But given that the experience of community on the Internet is not limited
to national boundaries, it is also important to consider the shape and structure of this virtual community.
Besides being hailed as a technology which can deliver the ‘global
village’, the Internet is also promoted as a singular medium which allows
for democratized processes which were not previously possible in the era
of broadcast. But what kinds of democracy are being postulated here?
Traditionally, and more than ever now, democracy is heavily aligned
with the nation-state (see Hirst and Thompson, 1996). Because of this, a
nonsense is made of the claim that the Internet enables universal participation in the democratic process. The point here is that practices of communication afforded by CMC may be able to substitute some of the
functions of the mass media – for example, in the formation of preinstitutional public opinion – but do not necessarily exert pressure on the
institutional apparatuses of politics. Of course the mass media themselves, as a means of electronically mediated communication, can never
replace the institutional apparatuses of politics, and, as numerous studies
have shown, have been just as much used by politicians as they have
influenced them.
The Internet can properly be classified as a ‘global’ technology, which
enables connections with individuals and institutions overseas just as
easily as it does nationally, regionally or locally. If there is an imagined
community (see Anderson, 1983) on the Internet, it is definitely not the
nation-state. State-bounded kinds of citizenship cannot be considered
coterminous with the kinds of citizenship which are achieved on the
Internet. However, this is not to argue that a global sense of citizenship,
even if it too is an ‘imagined one’, cannot exist. Recent protests against
international financial institutions such as the World Bank were organized
almost entirely through Internet media – a case of not so visible electronic
assemblies producing very visible embodied assemblies.
Democracy and interaction
To privilege either ‘broadcast’ or interactive mediums like CMC as
domains which can deliver a universal public sphere is fraught with
methodological problems. Perspectives on media epochs – ‘the video age’,
the ‘age of the Internet’ (Turkle) or the ‘second media age’ (Poster) – are
too simplistic and read as much too technologically determinist insofar as
they neglect the sub-media and subcultures which are internal to apparatuses of electronic media, both broadcast and interactive. Such models
tend to be one-dimensional in that they view forms of public association,
be they by images and broadcast or by information and interactivity, as
mutually exclusive.
Theories of Cybersociety
81
At the same time, however, the ‘public sphericules’ or ‘partial publics’
thesis of Gitlin, and of Becker and Wehner, purveys another kind of technological determinism, which moves from the grand historical grounding
of social life on one or other over-arching technology, to differentiating
forms of association in specialized ‘spheres’ on the basis of more particular technological mediums as the context for particular civic subdivisions.
It is true that certain mediums, particularly ones like CMC which
enable global reach, provide the individual with mobilities of communication which enable associations beyond what persists in modern life as
the most powerful sense of a pre-given public frame – the nation-state.
And moving beyond the nation-state in a global rather than ‘international’ sense also expands the numbers of those with whom we would
want to participate in a public sphere. However, it is also true that individuals are mobile across communicative mediums and continuously
participate not in a pre-given public sphere, but in the process of constructing publicness across a range of mediums. But it is less accurate to
say that the contemporary public sphere is breaking down and becoming
fragmented than it is to say that it is sustained across increasingly more
complex, dynamic and global kinds of communication environments.
Notes
Parts of the discussion of the public sphere in this chapter, were presented in Holmes, D.
(2000) ‘Technological Transformations of the Public sphere: The Role of CMC’, 2nd international conference on cultural attitudes towards technology and communication, Perth,
July.
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
The mission statement, which is published at NetAid’s website (http://www.netaid.org/
netaid/mission.htm), is revealing in its appeals to a humanistic universalism.
For an analysis of the significance of the Walkman from a cultural studies perspective,
see Du Gay et al. (1997).
Because of this, personalized information technologies are sometimes described as primitive or proto-virtual realities (Holmes, 1997). They are kinds of virtual realities, but ones
which only seal off a restricted number of senses.
As Heilig points out, the human eye has a vertical span of 15 degrees as well as a horizontal one of 180 degrees (quoted in Shields, 1996: 76).
For a useful, pithy chronology of the development of the Internet, see Hobbes Internet
Timeline at http://www.isoc.org/guest/zakon/Internet/History/HIT.html.
I will not rehearse here the numerous accounts of the military origins of the Internet’s technical scope – that is, as an unintended consequence of the US military-industrial complex’s
need to decentralize information to avoid possible loss or capture of command and control
information during projected nuclear exchanges (see Rheingold, 1994: 774).
The face-to-face is re-created metaphorically, by way of the promise of more comprehensive technical means to represent human gestures and communication. This at least is the
promise that it offers to a mythologized dyadic relationship. An enhancement of intersubjective presence supplies its motivating ideology whilst, in its actual operation as a
system of interchange, material displacement of such a relation is its outcome.
The ‘guarantee’ of reciprocity which once found its conditions in bodily present interchange and agency-extended reciprocity (reciprocity that does not pretend to be re-creating
82
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
COMMUNICATION THEORY
the face-to-face but recognizes its instrumental, tool-using extension) becomes more
and more displaced as social ties are more intensely recast in terms of dependency on
technologically mediated simulations.
See also Robin Nelson’s (1999) comparison of a TV drama from the 1980s and one from
the 1990s, ‘Boys from the Blackstuff ‘and’ Twin Peaks’, respectively, as a case study in
the way ‘TV space has begun to depart from a (humanist) depiction of characters and
events grounded in a historical world in which actions have consequences to a (postmodern) collage of attractive but dislocated images and sounds’ (17).
It could be argued that the sums paid to celebrity sports and film stars are an accurate
reflection of the commodification of the value of interactivity that is extracted from the
media-constituted ‘masses’.
A useful guide to decorum on the Internet can be found at http://www.dtcc.edu/cs/rfc1855.
html; see also Shea (1994).
For a site which explores emoticons, see http://www.randomhouse.com/features/davebarry/
emoticon.html
Shannon and Weaver’s theory was actually motivated by the perceived need to enable
cost-effective communication which minimized random noise and so allowed transparent and successful communication.
The codification of communication theory into process schools and semiotic schools is
implicit in the work of John Fiske. This clustering of schools is potentially useful for the
first and second media age distinction. However, semiotics is barely of interest for
analysing the Internet, which is arguably all process and not much in the way of content.
To the extent that it is content, there is no particular reason why it is any more instructive
for the purposes of study than the ‘wider’ bandwidth semiotic mediums of broadcast.
For an argument for the case that cyberspace cannot be said to constitute a space in any
socially meaningful sense, see Chesher (1997).
Indeed the German coffee house of the eighteenth century is heralded as no less than
the place in which the communicative culture of modernity began in Europe.
For an argument which is strongly opposed to Jordan’s and Smith’s position, see Spears
and Lea (1994).
Van Dijk (1999) restates the archetypal second media age thesis: ‘The interrelationship
of processes and the growing role of media networks gives rise to a new type of society.
The best name for this new type is “network society”. In the course of the twentieth
century it has replaced another type of society that has been called “mass society”’ (23).
A salient example is the marriage of digital photography and mobile telephony, leading
to mergers between corporations who specialize in these technologies (e.g. Sony Ericsson),
which in turn lead to innovations in the micronization of photographic technologies
and the way images can be sent wirelessly.
Mark Poster (1990) claims that McLuhan’s ‘mediumization’ of media studies is restricted
to a sense-centred empiricist conception of media effects.
Electronic media become arms of the interests of capital rather than information
providers which abide by a public service ethos. This ethos only remains in other institutions like public libraries, museums and government statistical services which are
involved in impartial and neutral presentation of information.
Similarly, Hawisher and Selfe argue (see discussion below) that in the USA the popular
imagination about computers is that they are the ‘latest technological invention in a
long line of discoveries that will contribute to making the world a better place by
extending the reach and the control of humankind, most specifically the reach of
America and its related system of free market capitalism and democracy’ (Hawisher
and Selfe, 2000: 6).
Television can be a network, but only for the content producers.
FOUR
THE INTERRELATION BETWEEN BROADCAST
AND NETWORK COMMUNICATION
Thus far, we have looked at broadcast media and network media as
distinct fields of enquiry for contemporary communication theory. As
foreshadowed in Chapter 1, there are two principal ways in which this
can be done: by taking up the ‘media age’ thesis, or by seeing broadcast
and network forms of communication and association as making possible
distinct forms of social integration.
In this chapter we will attempt to theorize the interrelation between
these two forms, both in terms of the ‘first and second media age’ and in
terms of ‘social architectures’ of media form. In both models, the way in
which individuals find connection with the different media forms can be
shown to be interdependent – network communication becomes meaningful because of broadcast, and broadcast becomes meaningful in the
context of network. But the oscillation between these forms is not an
entirely new phenomenon, and, as we shall see, predated the arrival of a
‘second media age’ by many years. It is just that in contemporary times
this dynamic has visibly attained much more of a ‘technological’ and
commodified separation.
As suggested in Chapter 1, my critique of cyber-utopianism is whether
an historical distinction between the first and second media age can be
made at all. I am strongly in agreement with the idea that broadcast and
network communication mediums offer different possibilities of connectedness in information societies and that to contrast them is highly instructive, but to say that the latter has eclipsed the former is extravagant.
Rather, I am going to argue, when other social contexts, such as the urban
realities of their consumption, are considered, the two are mutually constitutive, and the mutuality of these dynamics was evident long before the
Internet, as we shall see.
The first and second media age as mutually constitutive
As previously argued, the historical distinction between the first and
second media age is the primary foundation upon which utopian claims
84
COMMUNICATION THEORY
about New Media have been made. This distinction underpins the second
media age thesis itself and much of the cyberculture literature which now
defines itself in opposition to, or as having succeeded, ‘media studies’.
Part, if not most, of the difficulty in making this historical distinction
between these two forms of media association is that it is based on a
misconceived ‘parallelism’ between communication mediums and the
technical mediums they are said to relate to as if in a one-to-one correspondence. Broadcast can be interactive as much as interactivity can be
facilitated within broadcast. In fact almost all technically constituted
forms of communication, from print to television, to cyberspace, contain
elements of broadcast and interactivity; it is just that these are realized
differently, and at different levels of embodiment in different techno-social
relations.
In the historical model, broadcast media are characterized by oneway communication. Typically, this entails a sender of messages transmitting information to an indeterminate mass or audience, without that
audience having recourse to also ‘transmit’ information, at least not to the
extent that the broadcaster does. Post-broadcast mediums of communication, on the other hand, are said to provide for two-way interaction and a
‘restoration’ of the specificity of both interlocutors. In this way, the second
media age is viewed as redemptive and emancipatory. The centrist tyranny
that is seen to be carried by the apparatus of broadcast media is said to be
annulled by a supposed democratization of broadcast, where everyone
can be a broadcaster or datacaster, thereby flattening out the otherwise
concentrated (performative) power of broadcast.
The overriding evidence for this argument is to point to the massive
take-up of new media in developed nations. Statistics on the rate of
growth of web traffic, the take-up of PCs in the home, as well as connections to the Internet, mobile telephony and short messaging services
(SMS) or texting are all a part of this evidence. Regardless of what individuals actually do with the technology, or what it might mean to use it,
the fact of its take-up is said to be proof of the need individuals have to
‘find connection in a computerized world’ (Rheingold, 1994).
It is empirically true that, from 1990 onwards, the take-up of interactive media technology in information societies increased far more dramatically than did the adoption of new broadcast technologies. However,
if such a trend is posited as the basis of the second media age thesis, there
are a number of problems.
One such problem involves the question of historical determination.
The early second media age advocates like Gilder, Negroponte, Kapor
and Poster suggested that the need for interactive technology has been
historically created by broadcast. The very development of New Media
which provide such interactivity is, in a sense, seen to be driven by this
need. Second media age advocates suggest that the new interactive media
are able to overcome the hard-wired asymmetry of broadcast and allow
everyone to be a broadcaster and audience member simultaneously.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
85
Moreover, culturally, the ‘control society’ age of broadcast is said to be fast
disappearing. Audiences will not tolerate such subjection when they can
be producers. According to the theory, they will rapidly abandon broadcast as a source of information and entertainment. Or if they remain loyal
to broadcast, they choose reality TV, where they can see themselves in the
production, rather than obey the mass-produced artifices of the culture
industry.
However, from the historical vantage point of over a decade of the
Internet, we can see how, empirically, this has not proved to be overwhelmingly true. Internet use in many of the most information-rich
countries with high media densities began to slow in 1999. At the same
time, as various studies indicate, attachment to broadcast forms of media
did not show any significant decline (see, e.g., Castells, 2001; Schultz,
2000: 208). Furthermore, it is empirically the case that, when websites
begin to charge fees for information that is otherwise free to air, net users
rapidly abandon them.
The fact that the Internet as a communicative technology has not
signalled a demise of radio, TV, newspapers or other broadcast media in
information societies is tied to the fact that broadcast and network technologies are, as we shall see, mutually constitutive. Moreover, it reveals the
fallacy of the technological determinism inherent in the first and second
media age distinction and the way in which the heralding of a second
media age is often represented as a linear eclipse of the broadcast era.
At the core of the distinction between first and second media age is the
idea that an historical era, defined by its media, can so closely correspond
to a small number of technological forms. In the context of the current distinction, the fallacy inheres in reducing ‘interactivity’ and ‘broadcast’ to a
function of technology itself.
As was argued in Chapter 1, neither broadcast nor interactivity needs
to be technologically extended in order for its distinctive political, social
and economic properties to be realized. For example, reciprocal communication is inherent to a range of technological forms, from face-to-face, to
telephone and writing. From different perspectives, numerous surveys of
the history of communications show how broadcast has had a systemic
form which is as old as human society itself (see Feather, 2000; Innis,
1972; Jowett, 1981; Thompson, 1995; Williams, 1974, 1981). For Raymond
Williams (1974), the social basis of broadcasting long preceded its
mechanical and electronic forms:
The true basis of this system had preceded the developments in technology.
Then as now there was a major, indeed dominant, area of social communication, by word of mouth, within every kind of social group. In addition, then
as now, there were specific institutions of that kind of communication which
involves or is predicated on social teaching and control: churches, school,
assemblies and proclamations, direction in places of work. All these interacted with forms of communication within the family. (21)
86
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Garth Jowett (1981) has charted how, long before the development of
writing, personal seals, portraits on coins and printed illustrations provided a system of broadcasting symbolic imagery to denote political,
financial or intellectual authority.
For Williams (1981), the only difference between modern and
pre-modern systems of broadcasting is that, today, audiences assemble in
numerous combinations, in contrast to the ‘massing’ of previous kinds of
audiences:
… we have at once to notice that there are radical differences between, for
example, the very large television audience – millions of people watching
a single programme, but mainly in small unconnected groups in family
homes; the very large cinema public – but in audiences of varying sizes, in
public places, on a string of occasions; and the very large actual crowds,
at certain kinds of event, who are indeed (but only in this case) physically
massed. (15)1
Broadcast and network interactivity as forms of communicative solidarity
Whilst the historical basis for making a distinction between broadcast and
interactivity is weak, the sociological basis for making this distinction is
strong. The repeated observation made by second media age theorists
that the take-up of interactive technology is a way of overcoming broadcast is, I argue, an important one. It suggests that, in media societies, the
horizontal integration of direct two-way interaction provides aspects of
social integration, and a sense of belonging that cannot be provided by the
‘vertical’ kinds of integration of broadcast media.
However, the second media age theorists offer few answers as to why
this yearning for interaction is a yearning for technologically extended interaction, and cannot be satisfied by face-to-face interaction.
Since the formation of publics mediated by broadcast apparatuses,
face-to-face interaction, and its extended forms, which may be synchronous (in low bandwidth tele-mediated interaction such as telephone) or
asynchronous (such as letter writing), have provided horizontal interaction in ways that complement broadcast interaction. This fact can be
seen in numerous studies over the years which demonstrate how vertical
and horizontal kinds of interaction have historically been co-extensive.2
The fact that broadcast and interactivity operate mutually is most
visible at the level of content:
• The programming material of broadcast media – the soap narratives,
the sporting events, the personality of media presenters, the content
of the news – provides the content of countless conversations, be they
face-to-face, on the Internet, or as other kinds of interaction. The fact that
the Internet is parasitic on broadcast can be found in what is actually
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
87
discussed in computer-mediated communication environments. For
example, in the mid-1990s the largest subscriber list of all on Usenet
(over 3 million users) was r.a.t.s, which stands for rec.arts.tv.soaps
(Baym, 1995: 138). Baym (1995) claims that ‘[t]he idea of soap opera
fans using computers to gossip about their favorite (and least favorite)
soap characters challenges conventional images of both soap opera
fans and computer users’ (138).3 Mathew Hills (2001) argues that on-line
fan clubs function as a community of imagination that is always
‘available’ to fans:
As an affective space in which caring for, and about, the object of fandom
constitutes the most significant communal claim, the fan newsgroup resembles an ongoing and never-ending fan convention. … It is thus a ‘space’ in
which common sentiment can migrate from a fixed or ritualistic point, moving out into the fan’s practice of everyday life via the newsgroup’s constant
availability. (157)
• Equally, however, the content of broadcast media is overwhelmingly
composed of simulations of, or references to, face-to-face interaction.
Consider the soap opera, the most popular TV genre: it is made of up
of thousands upon thousands of face-to-face interactions, or images of
people on the telephone, and, more recently, the Internet. But mostly
they indulge in never-ending close-up shots of dyads and triads of
faces interacting. We watch the TV, ‘hooked’ on our programme, as if
the faces, gestures and expressions which stream past the screen give
us a simulated dose of the exact same kinds of interaction we are
avoiding ourselves – as long as we remain a viewer. Similarly, radio
genres engage all of the metaphorics of face-to-face company which
listeners are suspending as a condition of that engagement. The radio
announcer thanks us for ‘joining the programme’, or declares it is
‘good to be with you’. All of these statements are to suggest the
announcer is in the room with you. But it need not be the face-to-face
that is substituted in this way. It is not insignificant that advertisers use
telephone rings, or doorbell or alarm clock sounds, with increasing
frequency to also get the listener’s attention.
Each of these examples shows how broadcast media are a central
reference for face-to-face interaction, and extended forms of interaction,
as much as this interaction itself becomes the content of broadcast genres.
However, in the context of the second media age thesis, this co-dependent
relationship has become obscured. Instead the second media age thinkers
only emphasize one side of this relationship, that of the need for individuals to renew interactive forms of communication in relation to the way
broadcast media displace geographic forms of interaction.
Broadcast and interactive communication also operate mutually
because they have central characteristics common to them, which are each
88
COMMUNICATION THEORY
aspects of the commodification of communication. This manifests itself in
four ways: (1) as technologies of urbanization, (2) as technologies of mobile
privatization, (3) by enabling forms of the extension of social relationships, and (4) as agents of interrelated economic processes. When these
continuities are recognized, many of the social and political claims of the
second media age perspective are shaken.
Communication and urbanization
Both broadcast and interactive forms of communication structure, and are
structured by, one common operation – the partitioning of a mass into
atomized units. In this a number of observations of the second media age
theorists about the first media age are most noteworthy. What they
describe as the first media age is charged with the characteristic of interpellation and individuation.
Adorno and Horkheimer (1993) were among the first to provide an
insightful description of this effect of media in their discussion of the ‘culture industry’. For them, the culture industry corrodes the horizontal networks of associations which make up urban self-formation, channelling
populations into individual units, who, once isolated, must reconnect
through what vertical means is offered to them via the mass media. ‘City
housing projects designed to perpetuate the individual as a supposedly
independent unit in a small hygienic dwelling make him all the more subservient to his adversary’ (30), which for Adorno and Horkheimer is the
power of capitalism to remove individuals from networked means of
cultural production.
For them this process is circular: the more individuals become reliant
on media, the less they are dependent on horizontal networks. The more
abandoned are these networks, the more mass media become their only
source of cultural production. Thus, the entire edifice of mass media
becomes an environment of what has more recently been called ‘path
dependence’. In turn, the need for people to form local attachments to
place is removed, as place is redefined as anywhere within a common
mediascape. The ‘need’ for everyone to stake out their own self-enclosed
unit, preferably on a greenfield site on the fringes of suburban expansion,
rather than adjacent to dwindling inner-urban horizontal networks, is a
frontier expression of media-driven urbanization.
However, this kind of urbanization is usually explained, first, in terms
of redefining individuals as consumers and, secondly, by assigning them
‘identical needs, in innumerable places to be satisfied with identical goods’.
The organizers of media industries declare such a culture system to be
‘based in the first place on consumer’s needs, and for that reason ... the
technical contrast between the few production centres and the large number
of widely dispersed consumption points ... [is, they claim] accepted with so
little resistance’ (Adorno and Horkheimer, 1993: 31).
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
89
Adorno and Horkheimer’s point is that mass media both produce
media products to satisfy consumer needs as well as produce these needs
to satisfy the culture system of the media. In other words, there is a sense
in which media audiences themselves are turned into commodities – as
consumers who have a use-value for the growth of the culture industry
itself: ‘The result is the circle of manipulation and retroactive need in
which the unity of the system grows ever stronger’ (31).
Thus, media-driven urbanization, which requires the duplication of
innumerable, individual units wherever it operates, breaks up networks
at the same time as it installs a more over-arching form of assimilation
around a ‘few production centres’ of culture. In doing so it even menaces
the extended network possibilities of the telephone. ‘The step from the
telephone to the radio has clearly distinguished roles. The former still
allowed the subject to play the role of subject. . .. The latter . .. turns all
participants into listeners and authoritatively subjects them to broadcast
programmes’ (31).
Given their predilection for the role function that is offered by the
telephone over radiated media, Adorno and Horkheimer might be
expected to welcome the liberal qualities of the Internet, and the ability of
consumers to interact with previously one-way forms of programming.
However, from an economic and social point of view, the introduction of
a more powerful interactive apparatus in the context of the dominance of
mass media is of an entirely different order than the transition from telephone to radio and television.
Once the social path-dependence on the architectures of radiated media
is in place, interactivity, no matter what form, must be conducted on the
basis of such architecture, and indeed contributes to the daily replication of
such an architecture. This is something which second media age advocates
fail to point out in their claims of the redemptiveness of cyberspace: horizontal unity overcomes the vertical segregation, but also reproduces this
segregation.4 Moreover, also neglected by the second media age theorists is
that the first media age is characterized by a form of separation and unity.
As we saw in Chapter 2, there are many agents through which this occurs,
the image being primary among them – the society of the spectacle.
With Debord (1977), spectacle is a form of reification, a realm in
which direct social relationships are expressed through a totemic system
of images. To the extent that the spectacle ‘concentrates all gazes and all
consciousnesses’ (aphorism 3), the individual only ‘recognizes himself in
the dominant images of need’ (30). The channelling of attention towards
a singular medium is the very basis for segregated individualism. There
is no competing need for horizontal gazes and dialogue, which the spectacle accommodates entirely. Within Debord’s terms, however, it is not
essential that the image becomes the agent of separation/unity; it is just
that in the most intense period of high capitalism’s self-promotion it is a
‘technique’ which serves such a role. The important point is that in late
capitalism social needs require abstract ‘mediation’ in some form:
90
COMMUNICATION THEORY
If the spectacle, taken in the limited sense of ‘mass media’ which are its
most glaring superficial manifestation, seems to invade society as mere
equipment, this equipment is in no way neutral but is the very means suited
to its total self-movement. If the social needs of the epoch in which such
techniques are developed can only be satisfied by their mediation, if the
administration of this society and all contact among men can no longer take
place except through the intermediary of this power of instantaneous communication, it is because this communication is essentially unilateral.
(Debord, 1977: 24)
To the extent that the Internet can be considered a medium that is at
once instantaneous and an invocation of the gaze (the World Wide Wait),
it signals little change in the ‘individuating’ aspect of the technological
mediation of embodied presence. In other words, if an ‘audience’ is constituted only in an atomized form by mass media, then the difference
between the phenomenological world of a broadcast audience member
and that of an individual immersed in a so-called ‘interactive technology’
begins to flatten out.
Some empirically driven research on Internet use confirms the acceleration of individualization which typifies CMC. The Stanford ‘Internet
and Society Study’ conducted by the Institute for the Quantitative Study
of Society (Nie and Erdring, 2000) found that Internet users spend more
hours at the office and keep working when they get home, and the longer
people have used the Internet, the more hours they spend on it per week.
As the director of the Stanford study, Norman Nie, explains:
We’re moving from a world in which you know all your neighbors, see all your
friends, interact with lots of different people every day, to a functional
world, where interaction takes place at a distance … the more hours people
use the Internet, the less time they spend with real human beings. (Nie and
Erding, 2000: 1)
The use of Internet sub-media brings individuals together at the level
of electronic assembly but it also renews the physical atomization of
media operators. In doing so it materially creates the very conditions
which ideologically it proposes to overcome.
To this degree, network communication is actually parasitic of one of
the conditions that have been produced by broadcast whilst continuing
this condition. The need for extended network communication is proportionately related to the degree of geographic atomization which exists
within a communicative field.
Broadcast can be considered a first media age in relation to the fact
that its atomistic qualities seem to be more tangibly overcome by the
Internet. But in truth, they are also ‘virtually’ overcome by the medium of
broadcast also. The concept of a first media age begins, therefore, to look
more like a theoretical invention integral to the postulation of a second
media age.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
91
Communication and mobile privatization
The role of communication in urban cultures cannot simply be reduced to
the multiplication of urban units but relates to the way the communicative mediums which they make possible allow for ever greater mobilities
from within these units. This tendency is accentuated by the diffusion of
new media, as the virtual urban futures thesis maintains (see Chapter 3),
but in truth it is characteristic of all electronic media, not just those of a
second media age. As I have argued elsewhere (Holmes, 2001), electronic
media do not have to be portable to provide mobility, as it is possible to
‘travel’ with audio-visual and interface media, even when the body is in
stasis.
The products of information capitalism are themselves commodities,
but their most significant quality is that they commodify subjective and
intersubjective experience. In the context of urban cultures, the endgame
of such a process culminates in private bubbles of communication and
commuting.
The definition of ‘private’ is here extended from its typical use in
economics and politics. As Margaret Morse (1998) uses it in a spatial
sense, privatization refers to the way in which certain urban spaces, like
privately owned and controlled shopping malls and the home, become
refuges which de-realize their ‘outside’ environments. For example, the
historical separation of workplace and household becomes exaggerated
by broadcast media, where the shrinking public realm only has enough
room in it for work itself, whilst the pursuit of leisure is expected to take
place in the home. ‘The process of distancing the worker from the workplace and the enclosure of domestic life in the home, separated from its
social surroundings, allowed a compensatory realm of fantasy to flourish’
(109). For Morse, the home physically disconnects itself from an
outside, virtualizing itself on scales that expand as the public realm
contracts.
Such privacy, described in the information technology industry as
‘personalization’, was advanced by Raymond Williams (1983) in his concept of mobile privatization: ‘At most active social levels people are
increasingly living as private small-family units or, disrupting even that,
as private and deliberately self-enclosed individuals, while at the same
time there is an unprecedented mobility of such restricted privacies’ (188).
Williams argues that the private ‘shells’ of the motor car, office and home
unit gradually become extended by new media in ways in which it
becomes possible to travel without physical movement. The paradox of
MTV or the World Wide Web is that thousands of images can stream past
us every hour, where we can be transported around the world at lightning
speed, sampling countless other places, styles and impressions, whilst we
are stationed in absolute stasis, our only motion being with a mouse or
remote control. New media give us a mobility which exempts the consumer from having to leave the comfort of his or her shell, even his or her
92
COMMUNICATION THEORY
armchair. Such shells do not have to be physical; indeed, the space in front
of a computer screen is one that is intensely personalized, designed for a
single user with the right password, and with icons, characters and images
which demand a face-to-screen association.
Mobile privatization is not merely a trend in domestic and civic
life; it also mediates the modern workplace (see Greenfield, 1999) and
post-workplace trends evident in telework (see Morelli, 2001). The most
important feature of Williams’ concept for the present discussion is that
media-based mobility can be interactive or derived from broadcast. In
Television, Technology and Cultural Form (1974) Williams describes how the
increasingly private refuge of home and family generates the need for ‘new
kinds of contact’ and ‘news from “outside”, from otherwise inaccessible
sources’ (27). Such a need generated from the fact of urbanization may be
met just as much by letters and telephone as it is by Internet connections,
mobile telephones and texting. However, the more mobile and portable
such means of connection are, the more we can translate the private refuge
of the home into the electronically generated recluse of communication
bubbles which de-realize our relation to physical public space. The more
such bubbles are occupied, the less likely are face-to-face forms of recognition. What face-to-face relations do exist in the public sphere are jeopardized, or made more schizophrenic, by the always open possibility that
a mobile phone will ring or a message device will beep.
The endgame of mobile privatization is, according to Arthur and
Marilouise Kroker (1996), a radically divided self – a self which is at war
with itself – split between an embodied self and an electronic identity.
Because of this, there is a demand on each individual to find protective
shells in which to co-exist. The Walkman and the mobile phone are powerful examples of the micro-personalization of the self in public life – what
the Krokers call the ‘electronic self’:
… the electronic self is torn between contradictory impulses towards
privacy and the public, the natural self and the social self, private imagination and electronic fantasy. The price for reconciling the divided self by
sacrificing one side of the electronic personality is severe. If it abandons
private identity and actually becomes media (Cineplex mind, IMAX imagination, MTV chat, CNN nerves), the electronic self will suffer terminal
repression. However, if it seals itself off from public life by retreating to an
electronic cell in the suburbs or a computer condo in the city, it quickly
falls into an irreal world of electronic MOO-room fun within the armoured
windows. (74)
The electronic self seeks to ‘immunize itself against the worst effects of
public life’ by ‘bunkering in’.
Bunkering in is the epochal consciousness of technological society in its
most mature phase. McLuhan called it the ‘cool personality’ typical of the
TV age, others have spoken of ‘cocooning’ away the 90s, but we would say
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
93
that bunkering in is about something really simple: being sick of others and
trying to shelter the beleaguered self in a techno-bubble. (75)
According to the Krokers, such an electronic self becomes incapable of
negotiating a pre-virtual public world and becomes politically tuned out
and socially awkward:
Suffering electronic amnesia on the public and its multiple viewpoints,
going private means that the electronic self will not be in a position to maximize its interests by struggling in an increasingly competitive economic
field. (74)
Denied a political conduit, the electronic self is reactive only – often swaying between fear and anger:
Frightened by the accelerating speed of technological change, distressed by
the loss of disposable income, worried about a future without jobs, and
angry at the government, the electronic self oscillates between fear and
rage. Rather than objectify its anger in a critical analysis of the public situation, diagnosing, for example, the deep relationship between the rise of
the technological class and the loss of jobs, the electronic self is taught by
the media elite to turn the ‘self’ into a form of self-contempt. (76)
Bunkering in, which becomes a kind of survival strategy, tends to narrow
the electronic self’s world of control to ‘whining about the petty inconveniences’ rather than broad scales of social and political issues. ‘Bunkering
in knows no ethics other than immediate self-gratification’ because its
outerworldly contact has been de-realized. This disengagement created by
the architecture of the processed digital world makes it ‘hip to be dumb,
and smart to be turned off and tuned out’ (76).
The psychological war zone of bunkering in and dumbing down is the actual
cultural context out of which emerges technological euphoria. Digital reality
is perfect. It provides the bunker self with immediate, universal access to
a global community without people: electronic communication without
social contact, being digital without being human, going on-line without leaving the safety of the electronic bunker. The bunker self takes to the Internet
like a pixel to a screen because the information superhighway is the biggest
theme park in the world: more than 170 countries. And it’s perfect too for
dumbing down. Privileging information while exterminating meaning, surfing
without engagement, digital reality provides a new virtual playing-field for
tuning out and turning off. (77)
In the Krokers’ depiction, those features that are attributed to the TV age –
cocooning, the bunker ego, the passive couch potato, etc. – find themselves multiplied in the context of the greater array of electronic bunkers
which provide a new platform of engagement/disengagement in social
life.
94
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Technological extension
Rapidly, we approach the final phase of the extensions of man – the
technological simulation of consciousness, when the creative process of
knowing will be collectively and corporeally extended to the whole of
human society, much as we have already extended our senses and our
nerves by the various media. (McLuhan, 1964: 11)
Any form of interaction which exceeds embodied mutual presence
requires the extension of one or more communicative faculties. A number
of the thinkers examined in the previous chapter view media in terms of
an overdevelopment of one or more aspects of sensorial culture – print,
the image, oral culture – so much so that, in the case of McLuhan, it is
proposed that an entire epoch can be based on it.
However, the property of extension, which may enable the continuation of face-to-face kinds of cognitive communication across time and
space, also introduces entirely new qualities which are not possible within
face-to-face communication. And it is this property of extension that is
common to both broadcast and interactive technology.5 Any medium
which enables such extension will necessarily transform the content, form
and possibility of what can be communicated. As Meyrowitz (1995) suggests, analyses of mediums are significant because they suggest that
‘media are not simply channels for conveying information between two
or more environments, but rather shapers of new environments themselves’ (51). For this reason, writing and print can also be included as technologies of extension. Both are able to dispense with presence insofar as
they can reach across both space and time (see also Sharp, 1993: 232).
Technological extension, which can never reproduce the fact of
embodiment (despite the ideological project of virtual reality), nonetheless
facilitates a great number of possibilities which mutual presence cannot
fulfil. Two of its broadest features are that technological extension can
transform:
• the symmetry of a communication process (as with broadcast);
• the temporal mode of presence of a communication process (as with
delayed interactivity versus real-time communication and storage
retrieval – synchronous or asynchronous).
When it is technologically extended, broadcast, which is possible
within Internet sub-media like email and bulletin boards as well as traditionally regulated apparatuses, typically involves a temporal separation
between the point of production of communication and the point of consumption. For example, television has been described as ‘a vast relay and
retrieval system for audiovisual material of uncertain origin and date which
can be served up instantaneously by satellite and cable as well as broadcast transmission and videocassette’ (Morse, 1998: 107). The production
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
95
and consumption of information are typically separated in context and in
time, a separation which can be unlimited in its degree of abstractness. On
the Internet, the six kinds of interaction described by Barr (2000) in the
previous chapter (see p. 79) nearly all involve asynchronous forms of
mediated connection.
However, the Internet is unique in its ability to combine possibilities
of synchronous and asynchronous engagement – by extending the properties of speech, writing and the image in combination. The Internet is
itself a storage network as well as an interactive environment. Electronic
mail may be dyadic and reciprocal, circular within discussion groups, of
a broadcast nature broadcasting information, with any particular user
transmitting to the many. Powerful search processes are able to retrieve
information stored and collated in databanks. The only difference between
television and the Internet on these points is that the ‘retrieval’ of content
from their respective archives is performed by different people: by media
workers on behalf of an audience (in the case of television), or directly by
the consumer (in the case of the Internet).
The economic interrelationship
A fourth continuity between the broadcast and network architectures is
the way their economic logics presuppose each other. Economically, network media are accompanied by a form of commodification which, as we
shall see, constitutes a parasitic reversal of the kind of commodification
which typifies broadcast. The form of commodification which is peculiar
to a first media age is intertwined with the ever-expanding dimensions of
advertising.6 As Smythe (1981) shows, television, and any kind of broadcast media, do not so much sell products as sell the concentration spans
of audiences to advertisers. In this relationship the circulation of the sign
becomes fused with the circulation of commodities:
1
2
3
4
5
Advertisers sell material commodities to the consumer.
Broadcasters sell audiences (consumer consciousness) to advertisers
(measured by ratings).
Television programming is marketed by broadcasters to consumers.
Consumers are also workers who sell their labour-power to corporations in return for the means to purchase commodities.
The cost of advertising is reflected in the price of the commodity.
For step 2 to occur, broadcasters have to be able to offer high numbers
of media consumers and high-quality ‘concentration’, which is achieved
during ‘prime time’ when higher prices for advertisements are charged.7
This simply cannot be achieved in any medium other than broadcast,
which is why, as I have outlined elsewhere (Holmes, 1997), advertising
will never be successful, in a ‘stand-alone’ way, on the Internet as it is in
96
COMMUNICATION THEORY
mass media. One of the reasons for the crash in dot.com stocks in 1999
was the failure of advertising on the Net as a revenue-generating exercise
(see Cassidy, 2002; Kuo, 2001). On the Internet, there is no mass, because
a mass is entirely constituted by broadcast media. Broadcast audiences
are built up over time, but they need to be reasonably synchronous with
regular visibility for advertisers to have any success.8
The interactive sub-media of the Internet, like the World Wide Web,
cannot deliver a ready-made ‘mass’ to advertisers, and even when websites are used in a companion role, their effectiveness is questionable.
Gauntlett (2000) points out that ‘modestly sized but inescapable adverts’
still appear on the World Wide Web and these ads can be personalized to
particular sites, but the solvency of web directories is overwhelmingly
derived from the promise of stock values, not from advertising revenue (7).
Chan-Olmsted (2000) observes that ‘the Internet is the most cluttered
medium in the world. To succeed in marketing an online brand, a marketer
most likely will need distribution of communication messages via mass
media to create broad awareness of the product or service’ (98). Direct
marketing ads are nearly always duplications of advertising ‘that has
come from channels outside the Internet, such as TV spots and infomercials’ (98). Internet sub-media that allow consumers to personalize information they want will only ever be a ‘valuable extension’ of traditional
media’ (100).
Thus, broadcast advertisements often include a World Wide Web
address, so that ‘the consumer can continue a brand relationship initiated
in an ad in an established medium and extend it to a closer relationship
on the Net’ (100). The fact that such sites might get a large number of
visits is already driven by mass marketing. However, web proprietors
(portal providers and search engine companies) have vigorously tried to
aggregate web advertising in terms of portal loyalty strategies. In what
has been called a game of ‘portalopoly’, ‘Internet companies are racing to
build sites (known as portals) that serve as hubs or gateways to the larger
internet’ (Buzzard, 2003: 205). Portals function like the mass circulation
magazines or TV networks: ‘They are sites that meta-aggregate content
and offer a range of services in order to be the home page for as many
users as possible, thereby attracting more advertising revenue’ (Buzzard,
2003: 205). However, as we shall see below, contra Buzzard (2003: 206),
these hubs, lacking liveness, performativity and specular visibility, fail to
provide a mechanism for audience constitution.
On the Internet, the technical nature of its sub-media means it is not
possible to be a broadcaster in the same way as it is with mass media. Yet,
it is on the basis of a deception, or at least a sociologically uninformed
view, that broadcasters in the USA are lobbying to have ownership and
control laws relaxed in the wake of the Internet (cf. McChesney, 2000).
Because anyone can publish content on the World Wide Web, they argue
that media monopolies have been rendered ineffectual and so restrictions
on owning television, radio and print outlets should be lifted.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
97
Media of interactive communication, however, tend to be scarce in
advertising and rest on the time-charging of a communicative event, renting of telephone lines, renting of computer servers and storage space.
Conversely, the more broadcast media are provided ‘free-to-air’, the more
they feature advertising. Viewers are relatively tolerant of such advertising, but the same does not obtain for forms of broadcast that require payper-view, such as cable TV and cinema. Consumers of pay-television and
time-charged pay-per-view media resent advertising in these contexts.
Cinema-goers arrive late at films in order to avoid lead advertisements,
whilst cable TV must promote itself as advertisement-free.9 An example of
the indignation at receiving advertisements via a pay-per-use service
surfaced in Australia in August 2001, when the largest phone company,
Telstra, was investigated over charging customers for ‘spam’ messages.
The Australian Consumers Association demanded that all customers
should get a refund. A spokesperson for the Association, Charles Britain,
said: ‘I think it’s a bit rich. It’s a characteristic of spam and email that
people have to pay to receive what are essentially advertisements. We
don’t approve of that in the electronic mail domain and I don’t think it’s
a good idea with message bank or SMS [texting].’
However, as long as the commodity circuits of the two kinds of
medium are kept separate, consumers are generally content to participate
in both forms of commodification. In the context of the metro-nucleation
wrought by the culture industry, it is easy for Internet Service Providers
(ISP) to appeal to consumers concerning their interest in exploring an
expanded range of horizontal communication mediums. For a timecharged fee, the ISP will electronically remove the cellular architecture
which divides individuals from others locked into the same system of
‘widely dispersed consumption points’. And of course the promise is that
it will do so more comprehensively than a telephone company can and
with much greater bandwidth. It is this feature which prompted Howard
Rheingold (1994) to speculate as to whether the Internet would be the
‘next technology commodity’ (60–1). Certainly, an inspection of those
dot.com stocks before the crash in the late 1990s would have had most of
us being readily convinced by Mr Rheingold.
Understanding network communication in the context of
broadcast communication
As has been argued, the distinction between first and second media age is
a useful one to the extent that it suggests that ‘broadcast’ and ‘interactivity’ carry ontologically distinct forms of social tie, differences which are to
a limited measure clarified by the epochal distinction. Sometimes, postbroadcast theorists glimpse the fact that this distinction need not be
historical (see Baym, 2000; Wark, 1999). McKenzie Wark (1999) suggests,
98
COMMUNICATION THEORY
deferring to Innis as the classic exponent of this view, that ‘[t]elevision
makes it possible to generate vast publics, attuned simultaneously to the
same message; the telephone makes it possible to coordinate personal
connections, exchanging particular and self-generated messages’ (23).
Wark sees these two technologies as providing a basis for different kinds
of ‘culture’, which for him inhere in the messages rather than the mediums
they allow: ‘Through the television and telephone, quite different kinds of
culture coalesce; one based on normative and majoritarian messages; the
other at least potentially enabling the formation of marginal and minority
culture’ (23–4). In Wark’s analysis, it is the dynamic between ‘mainstream’
and minority that is reproduced in these two technologies, a dualism that
is in fact at the heart of second media age politics, from the visions of
Apple users in the 1960s to the current utopian hopes of using the Net for
peace and global protest against ‘the system’ (see Terranova, 2001).
Wark’s discussion is a useful departure from succession models of
media. He argues that there are at least two kinds of cultural productions
arising from different media forms, and that these can co-exist in tension.
He is clearly not arguing that television’s ‘mainstream’ is progressively
undermined by increased telephony or any other medium which makes it
possible to coordinate personal connections, exchanging particular and
self-generated messages.
What Wark avoids, in this discussion at least, is choosing technologies which are marked by considerable historical separation: TV versus
Internet, cinema versus interactive television, etc. By appreciating a
co-presence of communicative technologies and the social or cultural
dynamics they produce, the historical distinction is weakened. Instead, it
becomes necessary to appreciate the way in which ‘interactive’ and
‘broadcast’ forms of communication carry different kinds of social bond.
These two kinds of social bond are mutually co-dependent as well as, in
the current era, carried much more heavily by technological extension. It
is this increased degree of extension which, it might be argued, could
qualify as a second media age, much more than the predominance of
interactivity over broadcast. If anything, technologically extended interactivity has not eclipsed broadcast; it has merely provided everyday
forms of interaction with increased alternatives.
As carriers of integration, broadcast and the Internet can broadly be
described in terms of the predominance of mediated forms of either
recognition or reciprocity. Both processes, collective recognition and
extended reciprocity, carry with them modes of integration of persons
which, as our discussion of mobile privatization suggests, prioritize the
relationship of individuals to an ‘outside’ on the basis of commoditized
social relationships.
In this, it can be argued, it is impossible to adequately understand the
extended reciprocity of network communication without understanding the social dynamics of broadcast communication. As we have seen,
mediums of broadcast integration provide the socio-spatial as well as the
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
99
ideological preconditions of virtual communities. Broadcast communication,
in establishing, as Adorno and Horkheimer show, a horizontal cellular
architecture which can only be integrated via mass media, has heightened
the dependence individuals have on those media, or on whatever horizontal means of communication that can break down the tele-mediated
fields which divide each adjacent unit from the next.
In this connection, the notable decline in extended families and faceto-face neighbourhood kinds of networks corresponds inversely to the
rise of ‘metro-nucleation’. As Geoff Sharp points out, many years ago, in
Family and Social Network, Elizabeth Bott (1971) clearly demonstrated
the transition to a later modern mode of integration in which the reconstruction of the material habitat contributed to the increased segregation
of the institutional settings of everyday life (Sharp, 1993: 236). To quote
McLuhan and Fiore: ‘The family circle has widened. The worldpool of
information fathered by electric media – movies, Telstar, flight – far surpasses any possible influence mom and dad can now bring to bear.
Character no longer is shaped by only two earnest, fumbling experts.
Now all the world’s a sage’ (in McLuhan and Fiore, 1967: 14). Indeed the
family circle has widened, but not before it has also shrunk – a contraction
of embodied wide-kinship networks which then find substitution in the
global openness of electronic media of all kinds.
However, whilst this dual operation of expansion and contraction
wrought by broadcast media has increased the ability to identify with far
greater numbers of other persons than was possible in pre-media societies, it has also dramatically reduced the daily physical interaction with
such others. Such re-territorialization of social architectures of identification creates heightened, almost religious, attachment to extended media
(see Martin-Barbero, 1997), which is inversely related to widespread
breakdown of families as a basis for social capital in media societies (see
Fukuyama, 1999). As face-to-face familial and ‘local’ associations with others
become overpassed, in the manner of an inter-suburban freeway, interaction increasingly becomes confined to a level of association which has an
abstractness which is somehow adequate to the technically mediated
bond which abolished its local expressions – broadcast. As the embodied
public sphere is replaced by an electronic public sphere, to ‘go out’, as
McLuhan once remarked, is to be alone (cited in Levinson, 1999: 134). And
when we are out, he noted, our interactions become more violent, insofar
as we have been stripped of readily available roles. Road rage (Lupton,
1999), street rage, telephone rage, even air rage, become more common.
Insofar as, McLuhan argues, the medium is our identity, when we turn off
the Internet we lose the role it assigns to us as a netizen, and we are forced
to take responsibility for our identity.
When we are immersed in the comfort of electronic media, on the
other hand, we are able to foster new types of shared experience, resulting in ‘greater personal involvement with those who would otherwise be
strangers’ (Meyrowitz, 1995: 58). However, the mobile privatization side
100
COMMUNICATION THEORY
of this connection, when we try to confront the disjunction between two
kinds of interaction – face-to-face and disembodied – can also lead to Net
flaming (see Dery, 1994; Springer, 2000).
In the modern era, the trends towards increased densities in, and
increased use of, telephonic and Internet-based forms of communication
are an outcome of the fact that the ‘virtual community’ of broadcast
extends the sphere of recognition, but excludes interactivity as an ingredient of such a community. One of the most instructive signs of the inadequacy of broadcast in this regard can be found in recent changes to its
genre. On television, it is no surprise that it is precisely since the availability of the Internet that ‘reality’ TV has became an established genre,
still clinging to the last remnants of simulacra, the semblance of undirected,
authentic, spontaneous and intimate personality, which other genres so
comprehensively lack in the context of network. Changes to how we are
able to control the viewing of television with digital video are also an
example of new kinds of expectations about media brought about by the
increased availability and normalization of interactive technology.
A recent advertisement for DVD in Australia boasted the virtues of
being able to view films as you have never been able to before. DVD
‘puts you in the director’s chair’. It allows you to ‘get behind the scene’
and pass through that wall which separates the producers and consumers
of media, meaning, in some removed, imaginary sense, that we are
able to ‘interact’ with the producers by being able to direct proceedings as
they are.
But by far the most visible indication of the way in which individuals seek to overcome exclusion from interactivity in a public domain is in
the extraordinary production of personal websites. Net enthusiasts of all
kinds see the Net as a way of gaining visibility in a world where they are
otherwise rendered as anonymous consumers. It provides an extended
‘mediaplace’ in the world which they don’t otherwise have. A typical
page conveys a level of intimacy via pictures and personal life which can’t
be achieved in institutional life, such as where you work or where you
study. It seems appropriate to put your photo on the Web because others
rarely appreciate you in the context you would prefer them to see you in.
People from your working institutional life seldom appreciate who you
are – the fact that you might be a good sportsperson, or a fine cook. To the
extent that personal web-page authors believe they have a visibility comparable with broadcast on the WWW, they can deliver themselves from a
feeling of anonymity.
However, the experience of visibility is inevitably limited by the very
architecture of Internet communication. As Schultz (2000) points out:
Bulletin boards and Internet discussion groups can balance the power and
biases of traditional mass media and play an important role in controlling
and criticizing journalism as well as in establishing mobilizing types of
communication … . As Friedland … has suggested, the Internet gives people
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
101
a fine tool for an ‘electronic public journalism’ that is independent from
professional media organizations. However, these new opportunities
involve problems that former media critics really did not face. How attractive is the content of such a Web page compared to the highly produced
content of broadcast? Communication and participation alone do not mean
much in terms of quality and value of content. Also, communication can
remain without any significant effects as long as it is not transformed into
communicative power and effective decisions … . Eventually, there is a
seemingly trivial but most important consideration: the greater the number
of communicators, the less time everyone has to listen to others; the
smaller the size of interacting groups, the smaller their significance for
society as a whole. This is one of the reasons why one must doubt whether
Internet enthusiasts are right in their belief that the end of traditional institutions of politics and media has come. They suggest that a new elite of
‘netizens’ is going to take over society … . But on what integrational foundations is the alleged net community grounded? There seem to be few
apart from an individualistic rhetoric of free information and a euphoria
about thousands of subcommunities to which no one can belong at the
same time anyway, not even in bodiless cyberspace. After all, attention is
one of the most valuable resources in the new era … . Economists would
call it a very scarce commodity. With a growing number of information and
communication forums, some central sources may become more important. They can reduce complexity, help users make judgements about what
is important, and build shared beliefs. (207)
Understanding broadcast communication in the context of network
communication
By far the greatest contribution of the second media age thesis is that it
acts as a powerful lens for analysts of media to understand something
about broadcast which has, up until now, been difficult to see – its character as a medium. The mere fact that ‘television’ as the standout technocultural form of broadcasting has recently become formalized as a distinct
domain of analysis is significant in this regard (see Casey, 2002; Corner
and Harvey, 1996; Geraghty and Lusted, 1998; McNeill, 1996; Newcomb,
2000).10 Television studies, as a sub-discipline of media studies, has
acquired a new positivity. Television has come to mirror the way in which
the Internet either has become a distinct technology of communication, or
is posited as a stand-in for broadcast-in-general, just as the Internet
emblematizes the rise of the network society.
Throughout most of the period in which media studies thrived in its
analysis of broadcast, by looking at ownership and control, media institutions, media content (from semiotics to ideology and hegemony) and,
latterly, audience studies, the one area that was left the most neglected
was that of broadcast as medium. With the exception of a small burst of
medium theory in the 1960s and 1970s, linguistic and semiotically based
102
COMMUNICATION THEORY
accounts of media dominated all of the different schools, from conservative
‘effects’ analysis to radical Marxist accounts of ideology.
The value of the second media age thesis is that it makes the study of
broadcast as a medium all the more distinct. On the other hand, what is
obfuscated by the second media age argument is the fact that this distinction cannot be so easily periodized. But, inevitably, attempts are made to
do this by claiming that New Media are signalling the demise of old
media, or at least changing the way in which the old media are related to.
Indeed television and the Internet are most commonly posited as offering
the sharpest contrast by which this periodization can be established. In
this scenario, all media are reduced to two standout forms. Either the
Internet is seen to overtake television, or it has changed the culture of
television. In the latter case, for example, Bruce Owen, in The Internet
Challenge to Television (1999), argues that television is beginning to change
at the same pace as computer networks. Television viewers, he claims,
now accept the far higher level of freneticness which is commonplace in
nearly every rapid-cycle television advertisement we watch.
But some have attempted such temporalization without taking
on a second media age position. In his essay ‘What Was Broadcasting?’,
David Marc (2000) argues that, in the US context, ‘[t]he Broadcast Era,
a period roughly stretching from the establishment of network radio in
the 1920s to the achievement of 50 percent cable penetration in the
1980s, becomes more historically distinct every time another half dozen
channels are added to the cable mix’ (631). Marc’s argument is that with
the introduction of cable television in the USA, the niching of broadcast
leads to its de-massification, and the collapse of its transdemographic
possibilities, which will consign it to a ‘biblical era of mass communications’ in which great events and famous people will have become
entombed (631).
Marc’s argument, based solely on the US experience, that ‘mass
broadcast’ constitutes large publics and pluralized forms of broadcast
constitute multiple public spheres is significant from the point of view of
reinforcing the argument that broadcast is a constitutive medium.
Regardless of how large or ‘transdemographic’ it is, broadcast constitutes
audiences within particular fields.11 The changes in television broadcasting by the mid-1980s in the USA were indeed significant to the reconfiguration and distribution of audiences, but did not in themselves cause
any major rethinking of what broadcast, as a communicative form,
actually is.
What is significant in the period of the inception of the Internet,
therefore, is the sudden return of interest in medium theory as a legitimate
perspective in media studies (see Chapter 2). From the early 1990s onwards,
when the Internet began its exponential growth, the theoretical necessity
of analysing the social implications of communication mediums had
become paramount, if not unavoidable.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
103
A key reason why medium theory has rebounded is to do with the
fact that the Internet and CMC are so much more visibly seen to be a
social medium than is broadcast. From a McLuhanist perspective, this is
paradoxical insofar as he argues that new medium environments remain
unperceived ‘during the period of their innovation’ (McLuhan and Fiore,
2001: 17). However, it is precisely because, in an everyday sense, the
Internet is seen as a tool, or as a vessel/conduit ‘highway’ (see the discussion below of Meyrowitz’s three metaphors of media), rather than an
environment, that it is seen as a medium much more so than is broadcast.
An appreciation of how the Internet might be a medium-as-environment
is less common in an everyday sense. Most studies of the Internet examine how it is a means of connection, a superhighway for virtual travel, or
a mode of association that makes possible virtual community defined
through connecting individuals who have similar interests.
In terms of the foregoing discussion of the different qualities of technological extension that are manifest in different communication mediums, it is useful to outline some of the qualities of broadcast which are not
possible on the Internet – all of which have to do with the communication
event.
Broadcasting and ‘datacasting’
We have already suggested that broadcast needs to be considered as a
form of socio-communicative bond rather than a technical medium. In
this way, it is necessary to appreciate the fact that broadcast may or may
not be technologically extended. However, across the technologically
extended spectrum of broadcast, it is possible to distinguish different
types of broadcast event according to its visibility and the synchronicity
of its audience. In doing so, we can see how datacasting via digital broadcasting services and on the Internet is not quite the same as conventional
broadcast.
• Datacasting is a service that has long been offered by digital television
providers, but in this context its range of qualities is more variable:
multiple kinds of audiences can be constituted within such a transmission platform. However, the fact that the ‘live’ forms of the transmission have subscribers, unlike ‘datacasting’ on the Internet, means
that the digital television version of datacasting retains a ‘mass
constitutive’ function.12
• There are also more recent forms of ‘interactive’ datacasting which
enable the streaming and caching of video and audio services that
have found their most attractive application in ‘video-on-demand’.
These services are ‘invocational’: the consumer chooses the time to call
up the content, but not as part of an audience.
104
COMMUNICATION THEORY
• It is also possible to use broadband Internet for interactive datacasting
of televisual content, but as its only proven value is in delivering
video-on-demand, this value is limited by much smaller screens.
• Other categories of Internet datacast, such as a simple broadcast email,
webcasting or bulletin board posting, are asynchronous as they are
mediated by the storage of media which are retrieved at indeterminate
and undirected times by the eventual audience. Nor do social expectations about Internet datacasting conform to any kind of appointed
regulation, unlike broadcast events.
Only when an Internet datacast is parasitic on already existing broadcast events does it have this quality. For example, when the Olympics
are being beamed around the world, mirror-sites on the World Wide Web
will assume a high visibility also. However, where Internet datacasts are
not paralleling media events, they will only ever have an irregular visibility. It is only when a datacast is itself reported in a broadcast that it will
acquire a visibility comparable to the form of media in which it becomes
known.13
For example, as remarked above, it is impossible to become famous
on the Internet in any of its sub-media. The only persons who have
become famous were ones reported by the mass media as being popular
Net personalities. In truth, however, the reason why their web-pages have
received such attention is precisely the exposure they have had in broadcast. Fame on the Internet can only be ‘second-order’ fame which parallels
an audience that has already been constituted by a synchronous, highly
visible media event of some kind.
Gauntlett (2000) draws on an argument from Michael Goldhaber
that visibility on the Internet is reduced to an ‘attention economy’.
Attention is a scarce resource (Gauntlett, 2000: 9). If a website does not
have ‘interesting content’, other websites will not link to it. However,
Gauntlett fails to explore what determines a site’s content as ‘interesting’.
He correctly points out that the amount of money backing a site is irrelevant to its popularity, but ignores the power of broadcast media in making
this determination. Thus he gives examples of ‘penniless’, ‘ordinary’ people
who are supposed to have accumulated large amounts of attention on the
Internet:
To take a real-life example, Harry Knowles – an ordinary, hairy, twenty-something guy from Austin, Texas – has received much attention with his Aint it
Cool News (www.aint-it-cool-news.com), a website providing daily Hollywood
gossip and movie previews from a network of ‘spies’ (industry insiders and
people who infiltrate test screenings). … Knowles is now very well known
and much in demand. (11)
There are numerous layers of Gauntlett’s discourse that can be unpacked
here to show that Knowles’ fame has nothing to do with the medium of
the Internet, but everything to do with broadcast.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
Table 4.1
105
The broadcast event
Synchronous audience
Asynchronous audience
Regular-visibility broadcast
Public speech
Television
Radio
Daily newspaper
Irregular-visibility broadcast
Media stunt
Newsflash
Baudrillard’s ‘obscene’
(see p. 107)
Magazine
Novel
Billboards
Datacasting
Computer virus
• The characterization of Knowles as ‘ordinary’ already reaffirms a basic
binary upon which the symbolic inequality of broadcast operates,
between high and low visibility.
• It is a real-life example supposedly because it did not occur via ‘the
image’, but in fact Knowles’ attention was achieved entirely by trading
in images, and the system of images, for which he became an agent.
• Knowles’ ‘fame’ is entirely parasitic on the Hollywood personality
system, which is the basis of his site being ‘interesting’. It is not because
Knowles is hairy, twenty-something or parodying another dominant
genre – news.
• In turn, Gauntlett publishes Knowles’ URL, which may receive more
visits as a result of people reading Gauntlett’s mass-produced book.
Moreover, a website’s popularity will vary over time depending on
its synchronicity with events managed by the mass media, and made
visible by mass media, for which it can only ever be a mirror, or an antisite (a site which reaffirms the power of a broadcast text in its efforts to
parody or criticize it).
Table 4.1 classifies forms of broadcast by their synchronicity and visibility. A broadcast event may be asynchronous but have high visibility,
such as magazines and billboards. They tend to have a regular but not
very immediate visibility. The impact of the content of such forms tends
to build up over time. A broadcast event might also be synchronous but
have irregular visibility, such as a media stunt. Such stunts, sometimes
attempted by social movements, tend to be highly irregular, but, just for
that reason, acquire high visibility and a synchronous audience when
they do appear. Some broadcast ‘mega-events’ exhibit a dramatic concentration of both visibility and synchronicity (see Garofalo, 1991; Real, 1984).
No event collapses more of the positive features described above than do
the Olympic Games – the most ‘widely shared regular event in human
history’ (Real, 1984: 222).
Whilst there are these variations in kinds of broadcast media, the way
broadcast differs from interactive media is far more significant in understanding contemporary media. By such a contrast, a host of qualities of
broadcast media come into view which were previously difficult to see.
106
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Broadcast is the only medium that is capable of being ‘live’
The medium alone makes the event – and does this whatever the contents,
whether conformist or subversive. Serious problem for all counterinformation, pirate radios, anti-media, etc. (Baudrillard, 1983: 101)
In the section above on technological extension we discussed how, in
enabling the continuation of face-to-face kinds of cognitive communication across time and space, electronic and broadcast media also introduce
entirely new qualities of interaction which are not possible within face-toface communication.
Datacasting on the Internet lacks one paramount quality that television and radio and newspapers possess – that of being ‘live’. When we
say an image is ‘live’, it usually refers to the fact of there being no separation between the time of production of a message and the time of its
reception, such as the coverage of a sporting fixture. This is known as
‘real-time’ and may exist in broadcast or interactive contexts. However,
there is a sense in which only electronic broadcasts are always ‘live’.
Whatever the temporal origin of the content of a media broadcast, what
makes it live is the fact that it is simultaneously being experienced by
a mass audience whose very quality as a mass is constituted by the
broadcast itself.14 The intensity of the ‘liveness’ operating in a broadcast
event is also related to the size of the audience, and its capability of
immediacy – the fact that it may be showing real-time footage or that
such footage might be able to intercede at any moment. Much has been
made of the difference between cinema and television precisely around
the liveness differential. Flitterman-Lewis (1992) suggests that television
succeeds in the production of ‘presentness’ in a way that film cannot. It
offers a ‘here and now’ in opposition to cinemas’s ‘there and then’ (218).
Television’s ‘peculiar form of presentness’ founds its triumphal claims
to immediacy:
You should think of television performing its most distinctive function, the
live transmission of events. … Unlike cinema the sequence of the actual
event cannot be reversed when shown on television. … The now of the television event is equal to the now of the actual event in terms of objective
time, that is, the instantaneous perception by the observer of the actual
event and by the television viewer. (Zettl, 1973: 263)
Zettl’s specification of this distinctive function, however, goes only
part of the way towards understanding broadcast. In casting a television
broadcast in terms of a representation of a live event, questions of realism,
and bandwidth (i.e. TV versus radio) also necessarily come up. The point
is successfully made that only in such a transmission do the time-world
of the represented event and the time-world of the viewership coincide.
However, the ‘nowness’ view of ‘liveness’ falls short of understanding
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
107
the role of the audience in media events, and the fact that television
programming also provides a context for ‘liveness’. In her essay ‘TV Time
and Catastrophe, or Beyond the Pleasure Principle of Television’, Patricia
Mellencamp (1991) argues that the distinctive quality of TV time is not that
it is capable of simultaneity with live events, but that, in a Baudrillardian
sense, it is simultaneous with itself, and other programmes that happen
at the same time. For Mellencamp, when coverage of a catastrophe interrupts the regulated half-hour viewing of daily transmission, the thrill of
interruption produces the very liveness of the event. Instead, the regularity of the scene is menaced by what Baudrillard calls the obscene, which
is the co-product of the graphic, the sensational, which shocks audiences
into the hyperreal.15
This idea is also found in Dayan and Katz’s analysis of media events
as ‘high holidays’ away from the routine of programming. These events
have a special place themselves in the history of broadcast media in that
their importance has coincided with the globalization of media. What
once captured the attention of a nationwide audience can quickly
progress to worldwide status. But for Dayan and Katz (1992), this need
not be the televising of catastrophe, but such events typically include contests, conquests and coronations – ‘epic contests of politics and sports,
charismatic missions, and the rites of passage of the great’ (401).
What is distinctive in Mellencamp’s analysis is not the relationship
between a media message and an individual viewer, listener or reader, but
the fact that each member of a media audience is aware of the reach and
cross-contextuality of the broadcast, and as such the media event takes on
a power beyond the meaning of the individual messages.16 Marshall
McLuhan was perhaps one of the most powerful exponents of this quality
of broadcast, which, in his case, was a characteristic of what he viewed to
be auditory culture. It is when information becomes instantaneous and
comes from all directions that it impacts in tribalizing ways. For this
reason the assemblages and information that are possible within even
visual electronic media and genres like newspapers are in fact ‘aural’, in
McLuhan’s terms. Newspapers, which graphically arrange information in
a non-linear fashion, are in fact, in McLuhan’s sensorial ontology, based on
the medium of the ear and its sensitivity to media which surround their
audiences with a presence and range of extension not equalled by visual
media (see McLuhan, 1964).17
The duration of a broadcast itself constitutes an event that is quite
independent of the fact that its content may not have been produced at
the same time. Electronic broadcast immediately qualifies for this effect,
whereas newspapers qualify in a more limited sense. For the day of a
newspaper’s production it remains an event; indeed, Hegel once
described it as the ‘morning prayer’ of modernity: ‘The newspaper,
Benedict Anderson says, is a “one day bestseller”. Nobody reads last
week’s newspaper, unless they find it wrapped round potatoes in the
kitchen. But everyday it sells out in millions’ (Inglis, 1993: 29).
108
COMMUNICATION THEORY
The predictions in the early 1990s that, as a result of making newspapers
available on-line, print versions would become redundant within ten
years have not materialized. For the same reason, the capacities of digital
television (themed content, pay-per-view, video-on-demand) will never
usurp the sociological appeal of broadcast, despite claims that this
can happen simply through regulatory practices (see Steemers, 2000).
Newpapers, like television and radio, make possible an aspect of communicative solidarity which Net mediums cannot, and will never be able
to fulfil – the fact that they are able to be performative.
Broadcast is the only medium that can be performative
The performative quality of broadcast is an extension of one quality of
speech, which the language philosopher J.L. Austin labelled the ‘speech
act’. In everyday speech, an utterance may be considered an ‘act’ when it
refers to an immediate situation. The utterance does not have to be ‘true’
or ‘false’; rather, it becomes a form of action which has mutual consequences in a setting of ‘live’ interaction. In speech act theory this situation
is usually part of a face-to-face interaction, where utterances refer to the
present-at-hand in the form of ‘here’ and ‘this’. Anyone outside the range
of a speech act will not be able to interpret its meaning. Conversely, those
within the range of the speech act will potentially feel part of an exclusive
speech community. Such a speech community of mutual presence will be
able to realize its distinctive group dynamic the more speech acts are
made. Actions such as promising (‘we will do that later on’), naming (‘this
is the best ...’), warning (‘watch out for . ..’), requesting, insulting, and
greeting have a different meaning in relations of mutual presence than,
say, in writing or in Internet interaction.
The important thing to stress here is the degree of mutuality, or how
many other people are simultaneously being acknowledged as hearing a speech
act. When speech acts are formalized into speech events, like lectures, public
talks or indeed speeches at formal gatherings, the boundaries are also
formally defined and generally known. In such circumstances, the extent to
which the audience will know something of the speaker will itself add to
the meaning of the speech. However, whilst there are occasions when little
may be known of the speaker, one characteristic is common to all speech
events – the fact that a given speech act is constitutive, regardless of the content, of an audience. It is the constitutive function of extended speech acts
across time and space which makes possible public opinion also. Public
opinion is entirely an outcome of the performativity of communicative
fields. Such opinion does not issue from the mass, except by and for
the institution of radial communication. Public opinion is merely a reflex of
the mobilized or formulated forms of organized discourse endemic to the
structure of a performative apparatus. Outside of this, public opinion, as
Pierre Bourdieu (1993) once famously suggested, ‘does not exist’.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
109
This latter quality is central to understanding broadcast. The
performativity of broadcast derives not merely from its ‘live’ quality but
also from the fact that it can technically extend speech events to an almost
unlimited audience. When the news presenter says that ‘the world is in
shock’ because of the death of a member of the British royal family, there
is a sense in which this utterance is the event, more so than the actual
death. Of course, the utterance may rest on the truth of a state of affairs,
but what is never in dispute is that, at a certain hour, such a statement was
made to the world. When we are told the world is in shock, we, as audience members, are immediately enveloped by such an utterance, regardless of our attachment to the deceased royal. We may as well be in shock
in the sense of consummating what is likely to be the common state of all
audience members. The outpouring of mourning for Princess Diana was
almost entirely an effect of the powerful performativity of media.18
Similarly, recall from Chapter 2 the widespread panic over a Martian
invasion as a result of Orson Welles’ radio broadcast of The War of the
Worlds. As a novel, H.G. Wells’ book could never have the same effect
precisely because it lacked the synchronous audience which electronic
broadcast and newspapers provide. Similarly, extended-interactive
communication can never constitute an event as broadcast does. Indeed
broadcast can be the event. This is particularly salient with broadcasted
mega-news, which takes on an historical status far more powerful than
any pre-broadcast events would ever allow.
The audio-visually documented assassination of John F. Kennedy levitated
him and his presidency into an historiographical mythosphere once occupied
only by the likes of Washington, Jefferson, and Lincoln. By contrast, William
McKinley never had a chance. The O.J. Simpson trial is assured a place in
the popular history of the twentieth-century American jurisprudence that few,
if any, Supreme Court rulings might hope to occupy; Judge Ito has already
eclipsed Oilver Wendell Holmes in recognition factor. Father Coughlin will
have generated far more usable material than Pope John XXIII, and Billy
Graham more than both. Who is likely to be a more dominant presence in
the digital archives? Albert Einstein or Carl Sagan? Dr Freud or Dr Ruth?
Charles Darwin or Pat Robertson? Mother Teresa already has a higher
F-Score than Albert Schweitzer. In the future the past will belong to the audiovisually reproducible. The giants of the arts and sciences who, for whatever
reason, failed to climb the transmission towers of the twentieth century can
expect to be remaindered to the specialists’ bin. (Marc, 2000: 630)
Marc argues that it was the culture of broadcasting that made Elvis and
the Beatles possible: ‘They emerged from the night spots of Memphis and
Hamburg to appear on The Ed Sullivan Show. In the cable environment,
however, The Ed Sullivan Show is no longer possible’ (630).
The foregoing examples serve to show that broadcast and network
communication are ontologically distinct – a distinction which has numerous consequences for the kind of telecommunities that technologically
110
COMMUNICATION THEORY
extended communication makes available. This is a topic which we shall
return to in Chapter 6.
Only broadcast is constitutive of a media ‘mass’
Another difference between the first and second media age, or, as this
book proffers, broadcast and network architectures, is that whilst both
produce individuation, only broadcast enables a mass conscience collective.
As has been argued elsewhere, while the Internet facilitates reciprocity
with little or no recognition, broadcast facilitates mass recognition (in the
form of meaning integration) with little reciprocity. Moreover, the mass is
constituted as an effect of the broadcast apparatus itself.19 There is no
mass without broadcast, in the sense that it is a social body entirely
derived from extended speech events. Such a mass has little opportunity
for horizontal interaction between each of its members, nor is there much
opportunity for interaction between a mass and the few centres of media
production, but the mass itself retains its basic form and solidarity,
Althusser has argued, as long as it accepts its interpellation via such a
centre (see Chapter 2). Broadcast so homogenizes a centre and makes possible the so-called ‘mainstream’, that it creates within itself a tension
between the impulse for collective totemization of an image, a message,
a narrative (the synthesization of a conscience collective), at the same time
as it reinforces the cult of individualism from which the need for such
synthesis is drawn. Broadcast effects a dual movement of separating and
uniting a given audience, which divides the reciprocal cohesion of subjects (based on direct interaction) and reconstitutes this cohesion on a
more abstract basis of association.
As per Table 4.1, the solidarity of a media mass depends on the kind
of broadcast. The more performative the broadcast, the more cohesive is
the conscience collective of the mass formed by such an event. It is also evident that this is not simply an effect of such broadcast but is itself ‘popular’.20 It is the performative feature of broadcast which can give it a bardic
function, as discussed by Fiske and Hartley (1978) in relation to television.21 Individuals wanting to find out about a spectacle event that they
have heard about (from a friend or a fragment of news) will inevitably
tune in to a big network channel. From the standpoint of the broadcasters,
Marc (2000) also points out the sermonic features of modern broadcast:
‘Broadcasting by its nature is an evangelical activity, whether it is used to
preach the gospel of consumerism (commercial television) or the gospel
of ethnical culture (PBS [Public Broadcasting Service]). A broadcast typically
invites everyone who can receive its messages to sympathize, empathize,
learn the creed, buy the products, and join the fold’ (640).
However, Marc, who adopts a technologically centred understanding
of broadcast, views cable television as not capable of such bardic functions, and suggests that the decline of over-the-air transmission can be
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
111
blamed for the ‘severe social dislocations and polarizations that have
taken place in American society’ (640). The ‘nation-as-audience’ is seen to
be overcome by a ‘nation-of-audiences’. It is true that cable television, or
narrowcasting, does not, by definition, have such large mass audiences,
but they are just as capable of constituting a mass, just as free-to-air television is. This can happen over time, or by the fact that narrowcasting
content is seldom produced just for a particular channel, but is generally
reproduced and reproducible on potentially global scales, in duplicate
narrowcasts or broader broadcasts. ‘Indiscrimination’, Marc (2000) insists,
is the characteristic which distinguishes broadcast from cable (640).
However, as more recent paradigms in audience studies demonstrate, discrimination is the preserve not of the broadcaster, but of the audience.
Whether audiences discriminate between spatial locations on the cable
dial, or between temporal slots in broadcasting programming, is not nearly
as significant as the fact that, in each case, a mass is constituted by radial
transmission. Structurally, whatever the mix of broad versus narrow
transmission, the nation-of-audiences will always prevail, and whatever
the mix, the nation-as-audience will always be possible should a spectacle
arise that is presupposed by such a form. A day in September 2001 made
this plain . .. and not just for a nation.
Broadcasts that have regular and stable visibility can become points
of ritual attachment, be this a weekly soap opera, the nightly news, or a
once-a-year fix on a sporting tournament. Where the performativity of a
broadcast event is at its highest intensity, it is even possible for the mediagenerated fields which atomize audiences at a face-to-face level to
momentarily disappear.
When Princess Diana’s death was announced in 1997, numerous
reports were made of persons who never even followed the life of the
Princess but were overcome by spontaneous grief, whatever they were
doing and wherever they were. At the moment the news was received
of the death of the most photographed person in the world, the local contexts of association which would otherwise occupy them were rapidly
dissolved, as the most binding field of recognition became the calling of
global media.
However, typically, the synthesis produced by broadcast media
rarely produces such affective horizontal attachments, as audiences need
only look to ongoing media narratives to consummate a sense of belonging to a telecommunity.
Audiences without texts
There is no audience outside of broadcast. The performativity of a broadcast event – whether it is synchronous or asynchronous – and its instantaneity are much more important factors in the formation of an audience
112
COMMUNICATION THEORY
than the kind of text which it communicates. Genres and texts may be
organized in repetitious ways that facilitate strong identification with a
common language of meaning, but a large part of an audience will be
drawn to a broadcast event simply out of its performativity. In fact, it is
possible for some audiences to form only out of the performativity of a
broadcast. In such cases, the idea that everyone is consuming the same
message is more important to audience members than are the affect and
meaning of the text. This is especially true if the media event is synchronous. This adds a dimension of simultaneity to media consumption, or, as
Hills (2001) argues, in applying Benedict Anderson’s (1983) concept of
‘imagined community’ to fan communities: ‘The kind of imagining characteristic of a nation is therefore one of pseudo-simultaneity, the assumption that thousands of anonymous, unseen and unknown individuals are
watching the same television programme at the same time’ (Hills, 2001:
152). This simultaneity effect is particularly true of spectacle events and
breaking news, but it is also true of channel surfers, who are immersing
themselves in the medium much more than in any narrative content.
The fact that the formation of a given audience rests, in whole or in
part, on the performativity which a broadcast medium supplies to the
texts which are communicated in them problematizes developments in
audience studies which advance the oxymoronic notion of the ‘active
audience’ (see Nightingale, 1996: 7–8). In this assignation audiences are
active users of mass media insofar as broadcast messages are useful.
Paradoxically, the postmodern thesis on the active audience rests largely
on the behaviourist premises of the uses and gratifications approach to
audience research (see Katz et al., 1974).
The account of the active audience is ultimately tautological insofar
as audiences do not antedate broadcast events, but are internal to them.
The active audience argument conflates the audience of a particular technical medium like radio or print with patronage of the texts and genres of
these media. To say, for example, that radio audiences are ‘diversified’ is
to misconceive an audience as abstractly belonging to a technical medium,
rather than to a particular media event (which may happen to be made
possible by radio, television or print). This can be seen from the realities
of actual audience measurement. Few audience survey instruments are
ever conducted in relation to a technical medium, only in relation to actual
media events, such as an edition of a newspaper or magazine, or the
screening of an electronic media programme.
In UK audience research, such as Dave Morley’s study of the UK
current affairs programme ‘Nationwide’ (1980), the active audience was
defined in relation to interaction with texts rather than mediums. Morley’s
analysis drew on Hall’s encoding/decoding schema, which allowed for
negotiated and oppositional readings, rather than just the usual dominant
reading that in implied in processual models of communication. Virginia
Nightingale (1996: 16) suggests that Morley’s ‘audience’ might best be
described as a constituency – a group defined by its common use of the
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
113
same signs and codes (be this critical, negotiated or passive). In this case, for
Morley, the audience, as Nightingale explains, has a kind of ‘dual existence’ –
‘it is part of the mass audience and also part either of subcultural or communal relations with others’ (Nightingale, 1996: 15). Interestingly, Morley
turned away from the audience–text interaction research of ‘Nationwide’,
to look again at audience–medium interaction in later work (see Morley, 1992).
Paralleling such a shift was the attempt to locate the audience. Is the
audience the same as ‘the mass’, or can it only be found in texts? The mass
argument is criticized by theorists like Ang (1996) who argue that the
audience-as-object is an invention of media institutions and corporations.
The entire superstructure of marketing exercises that audiences need to be
‘reached’ is founded on this myth. Audiences are not ready-formed receptacles awaiting to be discovered but are constituted in the same operation
as the audience–text interaction.
Another sense in which audiences are possible without texts is
related to the way the growth of network communication has been accompanied by heightened levels of ‘audience participation’. This is especially
evident in the spectacular rise of ‘reality TV’ programmes and spectacle
features – these are examples of unscripted content (see Couldry, 2003:
Chapter 6). Of course they are still social texts in the formulaic way in
which they unfold, but they work much more on the principle of imaginary substitution – the suggestion to audience members that they are seeing (a representative of) themselves on the other side of the screen, or at
least can imagine themselves doing whatever is being screened. Once
again we can see how a new genre allows us to reflect on old mediums
that have become acquainted with their ontological power.
The return of medium theory
Man, [McLuhan] understood the internet in the sixties. He was the internet in the sixties. The world’s just finally caught up to him. He was the
internet in the sense he was in touch with the entire globe. … He was
wired long before the editors of Wired magazine were born. This man was
truly wired. (Robert Logan in Benedetti and Dehard, 1997: 171)
In the previous chapter, we discussed the return of McLuhan, who, in
being the most prominent first-generation medium theorist of electronic
broadcast, has enigmatically become the subject of his own prediction –
that theoretically we can view old mediums from the vantage point of the
new, but that at the same time we attach ourselves to new media through
the objects of old media – what he called rear-view mirrorism.
In this chapter, I have suggested that both network and broadcast can
be viewed from the standpoint of each other. This is a corollary of the fact
that I have sought to reject a linear succession model of media forms. In
doing so, broadcast and network communication can be looked at from
114
COMMUNICATION THEORY
the perspective of medium, and each of them can become the basis for
revealing the limitations of the content views of both forms of media.
One of the obstacles to fruitfully comparing and contrasting the two
kinds of social medium that are carried by network and broadcast is the
fact that the discourses around ‘medium’ are, typically, technologically
reductive. Certainly, it is commonplace to think of the Internet as a
medium in a way which is contrasted with television as a medium.22
Similarly, distinguishing between technologies within the same sociological medium has the same effect (for example, see Marc’s [2000] discussion of radio and television as separate mediums).23 To contrast television
with the Internet sharpens a period distinction between media forms, but
softens and obscures the analysis of broadcast and network as distinctive
integrative ‘shapes’, as discussed above. However, this relationship is
seldom adequately theorized. For example, even though McLuhan is
heralded as having ‘understood the Internet’ in the 1960s, the Internet in
itself is not a medium in the sense in which medium is explored by
McLuhan. For McLuhan, as we have seen in the previous chapter, mediums are much more tied to how they extend individual bodily senses.
Some technologies extend just one sense (telephone – the ear; print – the
eye) while others extend numerous senses at once (cinema, television and
the computer, in which a variety of hot and cool ‘effects’ are produced).
Moreover, McLuhan’s paradigm has the (perhaps accidental) virtue of
grouping broadcast technologies according to the personal-social experiences they produce. Thus TV is considered to be an acoustic medium like
radio, in which sound represents the privately experienced equivalent of
a social world characterized by ‘information from all directions’.
However, the Internet as a form of ‘cyberspace’ increasingly comes to
be termed a ‘medium’ in itself. For example, Christopher Horrocks (2001)
argues that McLuhan’s insights ‘now seem appropriate for a medium
that arrived just after his message faded’ (5). Although Horrocks’ essay
‘explores the encounter of Marshall McLuhan’s major insights into media
and technology with the present world of information networks,
e-commerce, digital technology and the age of virtual reality’ (4), the project of defining the Internet as a medium is left unaccomplished.24 If anything, Horrocks is able to stress the continuities between broadcast and
interactive communication through his exploration of the meaning of virtuality. For McLuhan, interactivity does not have to be defined as interaction between individuals through a medium, but can be defined as
interaction with a medium itself. We might recall McLuhan’s discussion
of hot mediums as rich in information intensity (approximating virtual
reality) but low in interactivity. Cool mediums require higher scales of
interactivity from listeners/viewers/users. Thus, to follow McLuhan’s definition, interactivity is common to both the first and second media age, but
contention remains as to whether, with New Media, individuals desire to
simulate a face-to-face environment or are content to interact only with
the medium itself.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
115
In Arthur Kroker’s view, interactivity is not important; rather, what
is significant is that we live in a processed world in which all individuals
are essentially x-rayed by media:
For McLuhan, it’s a processed world now. As we enter the electronic age
with its instantaneous and global movement of information, we are the first
human beings to live completely within the mediated environment of the
technostructure. The ‘content’ of the technostructure is largely irrelevant
(the ‘content’ of a new technology is always the technique which has just
been superseded: movies are the content of television; novels are the content of movies) or, in fact, a red herring distracting our attention from the
essential secret of technology as the medium, or environment, within which
human experience is programmed. It was McLuhan’s special genius to
grasp at once that the content (metonymy) of new technologies serves as
a ‘screen’, obscuring from view the disenchanted locus of the technological
experience in its purely ‘formal’ or ‘spatial’ properties. McLuhan wished to
escape the ‘flat earth approach’ to technology, to invent a ‘new metaphor’
by which we might ‘restructure our thoughts and feelings’ about the subliminal, imperceptible environments of media effects. (Kroker, 2001: 56–7)
But what of the distinction between broadcast and interactive solidarity? If broadcast is also a medium of interactivity, what is the standing
of these two forms as ‘mediums’. From McLuhan the Wired magazine
editors have taken up the idea of the Internet as an extension of consciousness itself. Horrocks (2001) quotes McLuhan: ‘The next medium,
whatever it is – it may be the extension of consciousness – will include
television as its content, not as its environment . ..’ (pp. 52–53). Here
McLuhan suggests television is itself a medium, and that whatever supersedes it will interiorize it. Certainly, cyber-utopians celebrate the idea that
the World Wide Web is a place where every netizen can broadcast their
own moving video or digital images. Paul Levinson (1999) suggests that
the Internet is a ‘meta-medium’ which includes ‘the written word in
forms ranging from love letters to newspapers, plus telephone, radio
(“RealAudio” on the Web), and moving images with sound which can be
considered a version of television’ (37–8).
This problem of medium is fruitfully explored by Joshua Meyrowitz
in his essay ‘Understandings of Media’ (1999). Meyrowitz argues that three
key metaphors have prevailed in the thinking of medium: medium-asvessel/conduit, medium-as-language and medium-as-environment (44).
The first kind of metaphor, medium-as-vessel/conduit, is the most
common. It is a metaphor in which a medium is regarded as a container
for sending or storing content. It leads people to ask: ‘What is the content?
How did the content get there? How accurately does the media content
reflect “reality”? How do people interpret the content? What effects does
the content have?’ (45). For Meyrowitz, this metaphor is so prevalent
because it appears to transcend both mediated and unmediated interaction. It provides for intentionality across different media: ‘We all have a
116
COMMUNICATION THEORY
sense that a message that someone loves us has power and meaning apart
from whether we receive it in face-to-face interaction, by letter, by phone,
by e-mail, or by videotape’ (45). The message seems to be much more
important than differences between the media. Using this metaphor,
people believe that a movie can be made of a book, or that an interview
can be transcribed into a journal article which has the same meaning.
When we relate a television programme to a friend who hasn’t seen it, we
recount the content, the plot, the actors, etc. Meyrowitz points out that the
greater part of media studies have adopted this metaphor with its focus
on content and thereby overlooked medium directly.
The next two kinds of metaphors are only found in mediated interaction.
Medium as language treats a medium like a language with its own grammar. This is a grammar of production variables such as font type, camera
angle, sound reverberation, which are peculiar to mediated interaction,
or, as Meyrowitz proffers, ‘it is impossible for us to “cut to a close-up” or
“dissolve to the beach” in everyday interactions’ (47). Conversely, we
consciously associate the meaning of a word, image or sound with its
grammar or presentation. In a war movie, for example, ‘we rarely see
prolonged close-ups of “the enemy” but see numerous of “our soldiers”,
who, regardless of their actions, we sympathize with, as does the lingering
camera’ (48).
The last metaphoric perspective which Meyrowitz discusses is of
medium-as-environment.25 This is different from a media ‘container’ or
conduit which carries or transmits a message. Rather a medium-asenvironment comprises the fixed characteristics peculiar to a medium that
make it unique, ‘regardless of content and grammar choices’ (48). These
relate to (1) the type of sensory information the medium can transmit,
(2) the speed and immediacy that is allowed a communicative event,
(3) whether it is uni-directional, bi-directional or multi-directional,
(4) whether the interaction is sequential or simultaneous, (5) the physical
requirements for using the medium, (6) the ease of learning to use the
medium.26
Like McLuhan, Meyrowitz maintains that individuals are generally
not aware of extended mediums and the way they shape experience and
perception. It is possible to be conscious of medium grammars, and when
they are pointed out, they can be seen easily. Medium-as-environment is
a different matter, however. Meyrowitz would agree with McLuhan that
‘[e]nvironments are not passive wrappings, but active processes which
work us over completely, massaging the ratio of the senses and imposing
their silent assumptions. But environments are invisible. Their groundrules, pervasive structure, and overall patterns elude easy perception’
(McLuhan, 1967: 68). However, unlike McLuhan, Meyrowitz stresses that
to understand an individual communicative event, all three kinds of
medium metaphors need to be considered together, but that they are
typically considered in isolation, by distinct research communities.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
117
Elsewhere, Meyrowitz suggests that the second and third kinds of
metaphor began to inform a whole second generation of medium theorists
in the 1990s including their thoughts on cyberculture. In 1994 Meyrowitz
suggested that ‘second generation medium theory’ began in the late 1980s
with a diverse range of analyses of media technologies. He pointed to the
fact that a diverse range of communication forms was beginning to be
looked at afresh from medium standpoints. Re-appraisals of photography,
computer networks, ‘smart machines’ electronic text, TV versus print, and
the relationship between communication technology, public space and
social change are listed as fields of second wave medium studies
(Meyrowitz, 1994: 69).
This second wave has consolidated itself in the renewed interest in the
work of McLuhan, Innis, Carey, Katz and others. Perspectives explored in
the previous chapter – on virtual community, virtual space and the renovations of CMC analysis – can be counted as part of this wave. More recently,
the writings of Michel de Certeau, Margaret Morse and Karen Knorr-Certina
suggest new and important directions in medium theory. But the explosion
of literature on the interrelationship between New Media and the sociology
of time and space is also central here. Concepts of time-space compression
and ‘technological space-time’ (Harvey, 1989; Virilio, 1997), including ‘cyberspace time’ (Lee and Liebenau, 2000; Nguyen and Alexander, 1996), are part
of this trend. The turn also to visual culture (see Evans and Hall, 1999) is a
departure but also a renewal of a regard for the image which had enabled
cultural studies to significantly redefine media studies.
Medium theory also has a number of recent theorists who take an
extreme view of medium-as-environment. Arthur Kroker (2001) exemplifies an excessive position in which ‘new media ... are seen to be “new
nature”’, but is confused as to whether it is a metaphor or an environment. The take on McLuhan is that ‘technology is an “extension” of biology: the expansion of the electronic media as the “metaphor” or
“environment” of twentieth-century experience implies that, for the first
time, the central nervous system itself has been exteriorized. It is our
plight to be processed through the technological simulacrum; to participate intensively and integrally in a “technostructure” which is nothing
but a vast simulation and “amplification” of the bodily senses’ (57).
Similarly, Paul Virilio is well known for his exaggeration of a version
of medium theory in recent writings on communication. In his case ‘new
nature’ does not compete with the old, but substitutes it.
I think the infosphere – the sphere of information – is going to impose itself
on the geosphere. We are going to be living in a reduced world. The capacity
of interactivity is going to reduce the world, real space to nearly nothing.
Therefore, in the near future, people will have a feeling of being enclosed in a
small, confined, environment. In fact, there is already a speed pollution
which reduces the world to nothing. (Virilio, 1998: 21)
118
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Recasting broadcast in terms of medium theory
By far the strongest case for medium theory is the way in which we can
reappraise broadcast media in a consolidated fashion. Just as, McLuhan
argues, old media become the content of a new medium, so too the mediums that are made possible by old media can be viewed in a new way.
Human-made environments remain unperceived by individuals ‘during
the period of their innovation. When they have been superseded by other
environments, they tend to become visible’ (McLuhan and Fiore, 2001: 17).
From the vantage point of second-generation medium theory, we can
also look at some of the older media theorists and recast their work as
‘medium theories’ of broadcast media. This is what I attempted in
Chapter 3 in explaining Althusser’s theory of ideology, Debord’s account
of the media spectacle, Baudrillard’s account of the simulacrum and the
later accounts of audience studies each as versions of medium theory.
However, as we shall see in the next chapter, second-generation
media theory needs to be distinguished from the fact that ‘transmission’
and content views of New Media have also been renewed in contemporary analysis. The study of language on the Internet, of cues-filtered-out
approaches and of interaction views of CMC are each examples of such
perspectives (see Table 4.2). Similarly, audience studies continues to grow
as a field of media studies, but now with a renewed emphasis on the fragmented audience as well as the populist but flawed notion that the
Internet commands an ‘audience’.
Both broadcast and network forms of communicative action can be
studied from the point of view of their content or their medium quality. In
the next chapter we will see how what is common to all content (transmission) views is that they take as their building block face-to-face interaction and assess all communication, no matter how abstract, according to
how successfully it reproduces the features of such interaction.27
Transmission theories are, as suggested in the earlier discussion of
extension, only interested in how a medium may enable the continuation
of face-to-face kinds of cognitive communication across time and space.
They are not interested in how such extension introduces entirely new qualities which are not possible within face-to-face communication, a property
that is common to both broadcast and interactive technology. The latter is
the specialization of medium theory.
This basic distinction between the two methodologies is also related to
divergent perceptions of the function of communication in social life. For the
content theorists, it is cognitive interaction, but for the medium theorists,
it is increasingly a matter of social integration by way of media rituals. The
turn to ritual communication is central to second-generation medium
theory. As we shall see, in media societies, attachment to mediums can be
much more powerful that attachment to other people. Indeed, as a basis for
community, these mediums will always be there, from cradle to grave,
whilst other relationships may appear and disappear many times over.
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
119
Medium theory as applied to network and
(retrospectively) to broadcast communication
Table 4.2
Broadcast
(media studies)
Content theory
Transmission views
(Interaction)
Medium theory
Ritual views
(Integration)
Network (cyberstudies)
Information theory 1
(user, content, control,
effects tradition)
Shannon, Gerbner,
Lasswell, Katz
Audience studies 1
Mass–elite frameworks
Frankfurt School –
culture industry 1
Orthodox Marxist
theories of ideology 1
Semiotic accounts of
communication
CMC perspectives
(communicative
efficiency, CMC and
‘perfect knowledge’)
Cues-filtered-out
approaches
Information theory
Frankfurt School –
culture industry 2
Neo-Marxist theories of
ideology 2
Society of the spectacle
The theory of simulacra
‘Medium’ theory 1
Post-Saussurian
perspectives
The mediumization of
audience studies –
‘soap communities’
Virtuals community
perspectives
Virtual space
perspectives
CMC as cyberspace
Broadcast also facilitates
a ‘virtual community’
Sociality with objects
Medium theory 2
Communication theory cannot confine itself to the study of the interaction between media producers and media audiences, between message
producers and message receivers. Understanding the nature of communication mediums requires an understanding of communicative integration –
the phenomenon explored in the following chapter. Even when we are not
interacting with others ‘through’ these mediums, the mediums themselves
still frame our lives.
Notes
1
2
Similarly, the significance of vaudeville as an entertainment form which developed a
very large pre-electronic mass should be noted here, particularly for the formation of
highly visible national stars (see Snyder, 1994).
Which typically point to a marked decline in face-to-face networks (see Guest and
Wierzbiki, 1999).
120
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Another example is the large number of people who participate in reader-to-reader
newspaper forums (see Schultz, 2000: 214–17).
On this count in particular, the claims of the cyber-utopians that cyberspace can restore
community and the public sphere are exaggerated. Graham and Aurigi (1998) have
argued that the claims that public space has disappeared in cities are exaggerated for
the purposes of this narrative of redemption. ‘Not all urban trends everywhere can be
generalized from Los Angeles, or other supposedly “paradigmatic” examples’ (59).
As Geoff Sharp (1993) argues, ‘technologically extended forms also stand on their own
feet . . . they have positive characteristics of their own’ (233).
The scale of advertising, its budgets, the enlargement of the places in which it can occur.
The contrast I am drawing here is between the dominance of the commercial dynamics
of broadcasting in the first media age and the post-advertising world of user-pays communication. The contrast does not cohere in relation to public service broadcasting institutions, which, as Williams (1974) argues, rest on a paternalistic basis ‘an authoritarian
system with a conscience . . . with values and purposes beyond the maintenance of its
own power’ (131).
In Culture Jam Lasn (2000) provides a summary rate card for 30-second advertisements
on US TV circa 2000. On a national scale the Superbowl is priced at US $1,500,000 for
30 seconds; CBS news, $55,000; MTV, $4,100, $3,000. On local networks, late evening news
attracts $750; Saturday morning cartoons, $450; and late night movies, $100.
For the greater difficulty of the Internet than radio or television as an advertising
medium, see Black (2001: 402).
As Ien Ang (1996) documents, in early 1990 Walt Disney Studies began prohibiting
cinema theatres in the USA from showing advertisements before Disney-produced
movies were screened. ‘The decision was made because the company had received a great
number of complaints from spectators who did not want to be bothered by advertising
after having paid $7.50 for seeing a film, leading the company to conclude that commercials “are an unwelcome intrusion” into the filmgoing experience’ (53).
Studies of television have steadily emerged into a sub-discipline since their inception.
Newcomb’s critical readers have carried five editions since the 1970s. John Fiske and
John Hartley made numerous attempts at developing a distinct television ‘theory’ in the
late 1970s and 1980s (see Fiske, 1987; Fiske and Hartley, 1978), but by the 1990s (e.g.
Hartley, 1992a) it had attained a high formalism.
In fact Marc argues that broadcasting as an industry, rather than a mode of integration,
is returning to whence it came: ‘.. . it is easy to forget that radio emerged from the
laboratory as a wholesaler’s market-specific product. First known as the wireless telegraph or radiotelegraph, it was primarily sold as a wholesale military-industrial tool
that extended the capabilities of telegraphy to ocean-going vessels’ (632).
Television forms of datacasting may include: live data mining – the consumer interacts
with the data synchronously with their transmission; off-line data mining – the consumer interacts with the set-top box or receiver that stores and/or updates data which
have been previously transmitted; return path interactivity – the provision of a return
path (e.g. a modem) which allows the consumer to interact beyond the data provided,
which may include email services or on-line shopping.
For example, the followers of JennyCam underwent its largest growth when television
programmes reporting it began to proliferate. The same is true of all privately generated
sites which have become well known.
However, see Caldwell (1995) on the ‘myth of liveness’.
Baudrillard’s appreciation of this quality of broadcast is invaluable in pointing out the
limitations of cyberactivism and the pirates of ‘counter-information’. Anti-media that
do not have access to the dominant forms of broadcasting are generally subject to them,
and are consigned to limited expressions of ‘culture-jamming’.
In the case of a spectacle or a catastrophe, this awareness intensifies (see Couldry, 2003: 7).
The modern instantaneous quality of ‘news’ itself is, it should be pointed out, already
based on electrical technology (see Marc, 2000: 630).
The Interrelation between Broadcast and Network Communication
18
19
121
But of course, this performativity was also only made possible because of the historical
accumulation of the image of Princess Diana, the most photographed woman in world
history, which had transformed her into an icon.
According to Robert Nisbet (1970):
The mass is a large aggregate of people, which may or may not be in physical
union, in which the unifying force is some single, usually simple, interest or idea.
The television public is a mass, the crowd at a football game is a mass; the
people brought together in part of a city by an incident, or report of an incident,
are a mass. … It is the essence of the mass, as Simmel observed, that it is built
around a single interest or aim, one involving but a part of the individual’s whole
nature, and that it is animated or guided by only simple ideas. (94)
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
On the continued popularity of the regular networks in the USA, see Buzzard (2003: 207)
and Dizard (2000: 82). According to Meyrowitz, in 1990, when cable TV was experiencing a crest in the USA, ‘cable households spent more than half their viewing time watching “regular” network programming and ... the most frequent use of VCR’s is for time
shifting of programs broadcast for network-affiliated stations’ (Meyrowitz, 1990: 467).
However, in their discussion of this function, they fail to point out how this characteristic is also endemic to radio and newsprint.
See the collection by Newcomb (2000) for a sample of the everyday use of TV as
medium.
Marc claims that ‘broadcasting’ as an industry in the USA can be divided into radio
(c. 1925–55) and television (c. 1955–85) in which ‘[e]ach survived the brief golden age by
reconditioning its programming to supplement, complement, and otherwise accommodate the new medium that was eclipsing it’ (637).
The closest Horrocks gets to this is in suggesting that the Internet meets all of the criteria for McLuhan’s posthumously published account of the tetrad, whereby the transition from one medium to another can be measured according to a limited number of
questions (see Horrocks, 2001: 60, 61, 79).
McLuhan, as Meyrowitz acknowledges, is the principal exponent of media as environment (see McLuhan and Fiore, 1967: 26).
These markers for defining a medium-as-environment discussed by Meyrowitz bear a
remarkable likeness to some of the indicators of social solidarity discussed by
Durkheim in The Division of Labour in Society (1984). Intensity, rigidity, Elements 1 and 3,
underlie two dominant bases for how community tends to be discussed, by either
recognition or reciprocity.
Even medium views are sometimes accused of this. For example, Horrocks (2001) claims
that:
Arguably, in McLuhan’s paradigm, even the medium of television relies on this
same metaphysical ghost of presence. Indeed, to go further, we could say with
Derrida that the virtual reality environment is itself crucially dependent on maintaining presence and the immediacy of speech (the virtual discourse insists on
the claim “you are really there”). (30)
FIVE
INTERACTION VERSUS INTEGRATION
In this chapter I will explore the difference between modern, extended
forms of communication as forms of ‘social interaction’ and as forms of
‘social integration’. To do this it is necessary to also distinguish between
‘transport’ views of communication, whose interest is in interaction, and
‘ritual’ views of communication, which are interested in communication
as the basis of a form of community or social integration such as a virtual
(Internet) or audience (broadcast) community.
The philosophy of communication which underwrites the transport
view will be assessed and the range of kinds of interaction which this
view conjectures will be surveyed. Thereafter, the idea of ‘mediation’ –
that media are distinguishable by the fact that they are said to mediate
interaction – is investigated. This view, which is a sophisticated extension
of the ‘transport’ view, is finally shown to be limited in that it does not
account for the fact that, as argued, some functions of communication do
not require ‘interaction’ in the transport sense, but have the function,
which defines them, of maintaining some or other level of social integration without interaction in any form.
The important sociological difference between interaction and integration is, at this point, delineated by showing that in media/information societies there are levels of integration in which ‘interaction’ does not always
presuppose the mutual engagement of social actors, such as ‘interaction’
with communication technologies themselves, or ‘interaction’ with mediums. The abstract forms of such levels of social integration are then related
to the foundational distinction between broadcast and interactivity as
forms of integration which enable two distinct kinds of telecommunity, one
based on community as practice, and another on community as recognition.
The strength of the integration model of understanding communication will be tested through a critique of some recent discourses surrounding cyberspace and virtual community.
Transmission versus ritual views of communication
The renewed interest in medium theory since the inception of Internet communication has come to challenge predominant transmission or ‘transport’
models of communication as applied to communication relationships
Interaction versus Integration
123
(one-to-one, one-to-many, many-to-many) as well as individual
communication technologies, from print to radio and TV and the burgeoning proliferation of New Media.
Medium theory’s recovery has also been accompanied by a growing
adoption of ritual accounts of communication. Ritual views of communication contend that individuals exchange understandings not out of selfinterest nor for the accumulation of information but from a need for
communion, commonality and fraternity. Ritual views may be micro or
macro. The micro-view looks at individual attachments to objects, and the
rituals people have with them, whereas the macro-view examines attachment to the mediums which these objects provide access to. As we will see
in Chapter 6, in media societies, the micro-level attachment to media technologies is of an intensity which far exceeds other kinds of attachment,
including with other human beings. However, at the macro level, attachment to social life and community becomes realized through these
mediums – as virtual communities or broadcast/audience communities.
What is common to all ritual views, is that they suggest that mediums are not ‘used’ for the purposes of social interaction, but are, instead,
forms of social integration. Each medium, conceived either as a technical
environment or as a form of social connection, is able to facilitate a sense
of belonging, security and community, even if individuals are not actually
directly interacting in them. When we leave a television on in the background even when we are not watching it, or download our electronic mail
when at work before engaging in face-to-face contact, we are immersing
ourselves in forms of media integration.1
However, as pointed out in the previous chapter, the overwhelming
view of the communication medium is as a conduit or vessel for the transmission of sense, of content. This is overwhelming both in the everyday
common-sense understanding of communication as either ‘information’
or ‘entertainment’, and in research models into media, both old and new
(see Table 4.1).
In Chapter 3, we saw how audience effects analysis, hypodermic
needle models, media impact theories and computer-mediated communication approaches are each based on a transport view of communication.
But what is common to all transport views of communication is a predominant set of assumptions about the nature of ‘subjectivity’ or identity
that is involved in a communication process, and the nature of the ‘messages’ and meaning that are said to circulate between them. The pervasive
commitment to these assumptions, as it has evolved in Western traditions
of philosophy and in communication theory, is described by the philosopher Jacques Derrida as ‘logocentrism’.
Logocentric communication
‘Logocentrism’ is a designation that has been developed by Derrida to characterize how communication in the Western world has always been marked
124
COMMUNICATION THEORY
by an over-powering desire for self-presence, the here and the now. This
usually involves a quest for lost origins – a master word or signified thought,
a logos which would transcend the uncertainties which may unsettle ordinary language. Logocentrism involves an ‘exigent, powerful, systematic
and irrepressible desire for a transcendental signified’ (Derrida, 1976: 49).
A transcendental signified functions like a primordial self-presence, which
is somehow independent of the play of signs, and which would bring an
end to that infinite regress for a final meaning in the certitude of a ground.
It lies at a point where representation withdraws into a transparent unity
with what it represents, where subject and object are joined at last in presence in a privileged connection to truth and meaning.
For Derrida, logocentrism is inscribed in a range of features of
Western thought and culture, including an imperative to decide quickly,
to define who is foe and who is friend, anxiety over having to have certainty
and truth, the desire for instantaneous and perpetual contact – a supernormative impulse for self-presence and certitude. For the purposes of
this book I am primarily going to detail the implications of logocentrism
for communication.
In an early collection of his most accessible interviews, Positions,
Derrida (1981) outlines the main features of logocentric communication as
the communication of consciousnesses. The logocentric concept of communication involves ‘a transmission charged with making pass, from one subject to another, the identity of a signified object’ (23).
This conception also borrows from the value of presence involved in
auto-affection or ‘phonocentrism’, where the temporal and spatial are
united in a way which provides an increased measure of guarantee that a
message will reach its destination: a situation in which the speaker hears
him- or herself speak at the same moment as the hearer does. In this
model of communication, subjects are posited as the self-present symmetrical poles of an intersubjective process. The other value which is
central to logocentrism, as we have seen, is the view that there exists an
inventory of fixed signifieds which precede and are anterior to the speaking subject and which are merely drawn upon in order to communicate
meaning and make present a common reality. Against the logocentric concept of communication, Derrida argues, as we shall see, that language is
constituted in the very difference and distance that communication in its semiolinguistic sense is supposed to overcome.
The metaphysics of the sign
Derrida’s critique of the logocentric concept of communication is at its
clearest in his account of Saussure.2 Saussure was one of the first thinkers
to explore the stability of the relationship between signifiers (marks on a
page, sounds in the air) and signifieds (thought concepts). When these
two elements are associated, they become a sign. Saussure showed that it
Interaction versus Integration
125
is the relationship not between signifier and signified but between systems
of signifiers which determines the kinds of thought concepts that are associated with any one signifier.
Because of this, the relationship between signifier and signified is not
‘fixed for all time’ but is in fact arbitrary, even if it may be fixed by social
convention. The consequences of this claim are far-reaching.
To begin with, it means that language is a system without positive
terms. There are no self-present terms with which one can anchor other
terms.3 Saussure (1922) proposed that ‘whatever distinguishes one element
from another constitutes it’ (118–21). To repeat a signifier it is not necessarily true that a signified associated with it in a former signification will
also be repeated. In this, Saussure, as Derrida would be the first to tell us,
contributed powerfully in overturning the metaphysical notions of language as a nomenclature or a naming system.
However, Derrida’s criticism of Saussure is directed first at the notion
that there is such a thing as a stable sign ‘system’ as a kind of general context and, secondly, at the notion that the signs which constitute the system
are full enough in their identity in order that we may discern differences
between them. Thirdly, there is a problem of agency insofar as Saussure
seems to be assuming that subjects do actually discern differences
between signs in a more or less uncomplicated way. What is problematic in
Saussure is that he regarded the relation between a signifier and a signified
to be in a cosy one-to-one correspondence, as in a parallelism, as if all
signs were constituted by symmetrical values (that could be measurable)
of the signifier and signified.
Derrida’s critique is that there is no such thing as a ‘closed’, or what
he calls ‘saturable’, context of meaning, and that signs somehow ‘possess’
a fullness of meaning (a plenitude) by which they are differentiated from
other ‘full’ signs.
Communication and dissemination
This critique is well set out in an important article which formalizes
Derrida’s thoughts on the topic of communication: ‘Signature, Event,
Context’ (hereafter SEC, Derrida, 1986). In this article, a sustained analysis
is developed.4 In particular, Derrida addresses the question of ‘contexts’ of
communication. He proposes to demonstrate that there is no such thing
as completely saturated or homogeneous contexts, which would have two
consequences:
• ‘a marking of the theoretical insufficiency of the usual concept of context
[the linguistic or non-linguistic]’ (310);
• ‘a rendering necessary of a certain generalization and a certain displacement of the concept of writing . . . which could no longer . . . be
included in the category of communication . . . understood in the
126
COMMUNICATION THEORY
restricted sense of the transmission of meaning. Conversely, it is
within the general field of writing thus defined that the effects of
semantic communication will be able to be determined as particular,
secondary, inscribed, supplementary effects’ (SEC: 310–11). Derrida
says that a new concept of writing is bound to intervene which will
transform itself and the problematic, i.e. transform the problematic of
thinking communication on the basis of the semantic and the nonsemantic and the system of interpretation which is hermeneutics (see
SEC: 309–10).
In SEC and in other texts, Derrida advances a new concept of writing
whose purpose is to overturn ‘a definition of language as communication,
in the sense of the communication of a content‘ (1988: 79). Derrida attempts
to demonstrate that the effects of semantic communication are subordinate
(both de facto and de jure) to the effects of writing – defined as the impossibility of an homogeneous context – which can simply be enhanced to varying
degrees by technically more powerful degrees of mediation (such as the
vulgar ‘classical’ concept of writing). This force of writing throws into confusion the non-semiolinguistic concept of communication, which carries
with it the sense of bridging a gap or opening an aperture.5
Derrida redeploys ‘writing’ in a special way not simply as a label for
words on a page (i.e. a technical medium) but as a term which he opposes
to the way in which speech is thought of as carrying the logos. Rather than
suggest that writing is merely an extension of speech, he reverses this
claim by showing that speech, the ability to produce meaning, is governed
by certain properties that have been historically recognized in the conventional notion of writing. In particular, there is a force in writing that he
calls dissemination, or the way in which meaning is never self-present or
‘full’ but is always escaping to numerous other contexts, as well as being
borrowed from other contexts over time and in space.
Derrida reduces the effects of language to two – polysemia and dissemination. In SEC Derrida speaks of ‘the necessity of, in a way, separating the concept of polysemia from the concept I have elsewhere named
dissemination, which is also the concept of writing’ (SEC: 316).
The semantic horizon which habitually governs the notion of communication
is exceeded or punctured by the intervention of writing, that is, of a dissemination which cannot be reduced to a polysemia. Writing is read, and
‘in the last analysis’ does not give rise to a hermeneutic deciphering, to the
decoding of a meaning or truth. (SEC: 329)
Dissemination is a force of rupture which is not reducible to ‘the horizon
of a dialectics’, to ‘the work of the negative in the service of meaning’
(SEC: 317).
Dissemination is defined as one of the sides (or effects) of the iterability (repeatability) of the signifier (a word on a page, a sound in the air,
Interaction versus Integration
127
which Derrida also calls a ‘mark’), the side in which the mark fails to
reproduce a signified content. The ability of a mark to reproduce a signified content can be reduced to polysemia, the production of a range of
possible meaning-effects which are the result of the contextual chains in
which the mark can be associated in a horizontal fashion.
For Derrida, polysemia is a rather modest aspect of signification, a
‘narrowly semiotic aspect’ of his concept of writing (1981: 29). Signs are
able to signify things, but what is neglected is that they do so in the face
of the alterity of the sign, the fact that it plays a role elsewhere, in other
contexts at other times.
The difference between polysemia and dissemination has nothing to
do with the size of contexts; rather, they are two opposing forces implicit
to all contexts, and scale is irrelevant. Nor does dissemination have anything to do with the relation between unmediated and mediated communication. The nature of mediation is that it implicitly presupposes that
there is some substance that is being mediated. It cuts in always before
(always-already before) the effects of representation and a semantic field.
Its effects are precisely those of a structural indifference towards performative communication and the impossibility of saturation. The more information that one has about a context, the less successful will be the possibility
of totalizing the interpretation of utterances.
For this reason, there can be no neat narrative about what individuals think with regard to the failure or otherwise of the sign to signify.
Dissemination does not make its effects felt in the service of meaning;
rather, the phenomenal level of meaning is materially foreclosed by
the way that an audience, a viewer, a listener, a reader, is caught up in
dissemination.
The effects of dissemination ensure that ‘there can never be an experience of pure presence, but only chains of differential marks ... because
the iterability which constitutes their identity never permits them to be a
unity of self-identity‘ (SEC: 318). The consequence of this is not to say that
‘the mark is valid outside its context, but on the contrary that there are
only contexts without any centre of absolute anchoring’ (SEC: 320). When
the statement is made, ‘we need to put a matter “in context” or “in perspective”’, a logocentric promotion to the idea of a stable context is being
reinstated.
The difference between dissemination and polysemia, then, inheres
in the latter’s being determined by, and functioning within, the ‘imaginary’
experience of an homogeneous context, even if this context is as abstract
as that which receives its definition from an arche (a starting point) or
eschaton (an end point) – as in the philosophy of Hegel. Within this context the task of interpretation is still to recapture the possible meanings
within the text – by means of a totalizing dialectics, for example. Derrida’s
critique of polysemic interpretation is precisely to deal with the desire for
totalization (the fallacy that contexts are finite and totally knowable) and
self-presence (the dream of a sign which would refer to nothing but itself).
128
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Transcendentally, totalization and self-presence are both impossible,
then, because all contexts are inhabited by radical alterity or dissemination.
Moreover, Derrida argues that today, in the era of telecommunication, we
have become more attuned to these realities of language-as-writing. The
ideology of telecommunication is that, in a non-semiolinguistic sense, it
aims to ‘bring subjects together’. But, argues Derrida, the purposive rationale of telecommunication conceived as the transport of semantic communication is de jure undermined at its very origin. Yet, on the other hand,
the fact of telecommunication as a non-semiolinguistic phenomenon, as
that which enables the citational grafting and lifting of marks out of local
contexts, that is, as the material basis of that always open possibility,
establishes de facto a form of subjectivity which is constitutively more
abstract than social forms which relied on the illusion of closed contexts.
That is, the techno-utopia of global-village discourses proposes a return to
the immediacy of social relations whilst in fact it dissolves those relations
in its very production.
Writing and telecommunication
What writing and telecommunication do in relation to ‘the transparency
and immediacy of social relations’ is to introduce the always open potential for a meaning to be abstracted from its ‘original’ context, in the way
that it is experienced as original. In other words, this is to say that the distinction between the original and the repeated becomes entirely open and
indeterminable; this is how writing extends and abstracts individuals
from closed contexts (see SEC: 320). What Derrida celebrates in the modern
period is the more transparent move towards social relations assuming
a form in which discourses refer to nothing except themselves (as in a
simulacrum); to no grand narrative or originating discourse, even though
there may be a nostalgia for such things. As such a condition, which
reveals the disseminative side of writing, begins to prevail, the more ‘local
contexts come into contact owing to more powerful and universal means
of communication that can be found in the era of telecommunication
and the Internet. These developments in the means of communication
de-parochialize contexts by bringing them into contact with others. That is,
the possibility of reproducing a meaning (what Derrida calls the ‘internal
context’ in the semiolinguistic sense: SEC: 317) is undermined by the very
practice of its reproduction the more a mark is mass-reproduced (but not
in the sense of permanence). The efforts to intensify mass communications
can only create greater abstraction. So writing, which, de jure is normally
thought of as a technology for the reproduction of meaning, when considered logocentrically (the semiolinguistic sense) is also the medium which
de facto destroys this very ideal as lived wherever it operates.
In theorizing the rise of telecommunication, Derrida argues against
the idea of a ‘global village’, as popularly conceived as a universal
Interaction versus Integration
129
community. The ‘network society’ is marked not by a change in
semiolinguistic extension (an ability to extend meaning) which works the
same for both speech and writing, but by the phenomenon of language-aswriting as a technological power in itself changing and producing more
and more non-saturable and open contexts.
The notion that ‘writing’overcomes the problem of immediacy is as
ideological as the notion that this already occurs in relations of mutual
presence or of performative, event-like statements. And yet Derrida is
enthusiastic about telecommunication not because it creates a global
village but because it undermines the ideological notion of an homogeneous context by installing the material power of writing as a nonsaturable context. The kind of threat which only writing makes possible
to logocentrism is now made more universal than ever following the rise
of telecommunication.
As writing, communication, if one insists upon maintaining the word, is not
the means of transport of sense, the exchange of intentions and meanings,
the discourse and ‘communication of consciousnesses’. We are not witnessing an end of writing which, to follow McLuhan’s ideological representation, would restore a transparency or immediacy of social relations; but
indeed a more and more powerful historical unfolding of a general writing
of which the system of speech, consciousness, meaning, presence, truth,
etc., would only be an effect. (SEC: 329)
Derrida is here critical of how McLuhan singles out writing (in the
narrow sense as defined by Derrida) as the one technology of communication which threatens the, by his account, sensory richness of an oral culture by means of an over-dependence on vision. The emergence and
predominance of exclusively electric technologies are posited to facilitate
the restoration of sensory balance (especially the liberation of the said
improvisory, gestural and synaesthetic qualities of speech), counterbalancing the linear and mechanical culture of what McLuhan (1967) calls
Gutenberg or typographic man.
For Derrida, the effect of privileging the narrow definition of writing
is that it reinstates a dichotomy between speech and writing which in turn
reinstates the phonocentric metaphysics of presence: ‘It is this questioned
effect that I have elsewhere called logocentrism’ (SEC: 329). The ‘powerful
historical unfolding of a general writing’ arrives to release the radical
potential of the ‘essential predicates’ of the general, disseminative status of
writing which have always been repressed and denied by logocentrism:
… writing, as a classical concept, carries with it predicates … whose force
of generality, generalization, and generativity find themselves liberated, grafted
onto a ‘new’ concept of writing which also corresponds to whatever always
has resisted the former organization of forces, which has always constituted
the remainder irreducible to the dominant force which organized the – to
say it quickly – logocentric hierarchy. (SEC 329–30)
130
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Experiencing mediums the logocentric way
The logocentric metaphysic of communication is one that permeates most
of the Western experience of all of the mediums that are discussed in this
book – whether in terms of individual communicative technologies or of
communicative architectures.
In much communication theory too, many of the various assumptions which underpin logocentrism can be seen to operate. These are: a
philosophy of the medium as vessel, of individuals as ‘users’ of this kind
of medium, and of meaning as the product of intentionality. Two mediums are postulated within logocentrism: firstly, natural language as a conduit; and, secondly, a technical means of conveying language, such as print,
television or on-line communication networks.
It follows that, within the logocentric tradition, some technical mediums are viewed as ‘conveying’ messages more powerfully than others, and
are able to provide an immediacy that others are not. The ideology of such
a state of communication is virtual reality itself, in which the process of representation withdraws to the point where only the represented remains.
The yearning for such a condition of unmediated transparency is, as Bolter
and Grusin (1999) argue, especially pronounced in the context of digital
technology. They claim that, from the early 1990s, new digital media,
together with the way older media have remediated to take on the form of
the new, ‘fulfill our apparently insatiable desire for immediacy’ (5).
Live ‘point-of-view’ television programs show viewers what it is like to
accompany a police officer on a dangerous raid or to be a skydiver or a race
car driver hurtling through space. Filmmakers routinely spend tens of millions of dollars to film on location or to recreate period costumes and place
in order to make their viewers feel as if they were ‘really’ there. … In all
these cases, the logic of immediacy dictates that the medium itself should
disappear and leave us in the presence of the thing represented: sitting in
the race car or standing on a mountain top. (5–6)
Bolter and Grusin argue that immediacy depends on what they call
‘hypermediacy’ – a fixation with the medium itself (6). Where ‘one
medium seems to have convinced viewers of its immediacy, other media
try to appropriate that conviction’ (9). They point out that increasingly
during the 1990s televised newscasts, with their multiple panels of text,
image and logos, ‘came to resemble web pages in their hypermediacy’ (9).
These examples of multi-media enhancement of the television medium
are driven not simply by demands for rich formats of information, but by
a metaphysical commitment to expressivism, and the transmission model
of communication.
As suggested by Derrida, the experience of medium in logocentric culture is predominantly an instrumental affair. A medium is lived as just a
tool for expressing meaning, just as language is viewed as a transparent
Interaction versus Integration
131
medium for transporting sense. Such a medium is conceived as having
authors who are autonomous, unified meaning-creators, who must draw
upon the stock of meanings available to them to produce symbolic forms.
The meanings which can be conveyed in a given medium are regarded as
stable, and antedate the actual communication event. Communication is
the transport of these stable intended meanings: the communication of consciousnesses. The task of readers, listeners or viewers of texts is to understand what the author intended to say – what Derrida calls ‘hermeneutic
deciphering’.
In pre-Saussurian accounts of communication this meant that to
repeat a signifier is to repeat the meaning or the concept that supposedly
accompanies it. The task of the author is to select the appropriate signifiers: ‘I am searching for the word to convey what I mean.’ For the reader
or audience, meanwhile, communication is completed by identifying the
signifieds which the author is seen to have attached to the chosen signifiers. This notion of correspondence also implies that it might be possible
for a signifier to fail to carry the signified that should accompany it. This
logocentric system implies that it is somehow possible to re-create
the ‘original context’ in which a signifier had meaning for an author, or
producer of symbolic forms.
However, for Derrida, as we have seen, the meaning of a signifier at
the point in which it is consumed will always be different from its meaning at the point of production. The so-called ‘original context’ can never
be reproduced.6 Moreover, signifiers do not even exhibit stability within
the same context, and may be read by different audiences in a diverse
number of ways.
The open-endedness of writing-as-language ensures that there is no
such thing as understanding an author ‘out of context’, because there is
never an ‘original’ context which can be captured by a logocentric reading; rather, the context is the reading, the translation, etc.
For Derrida, we would be searching in vain to find an original context or an original author, just as we would be to yearn for an original
‘meaning’ or, perhaps, as positivist philosophers do, search for the ‘meaning of meaning’. It is radical alterity which ensures that the one-to-one
correspondence between a signifier and a signified, intentionality and the
‘original context’, is a myth, a theological idea.
Nevertheless, Derrida would be one of the first to acknowledge that
the logocentric mode of experiencing communication is a pervasive one in
Western societies, and one that looks set to survive the de-parochialization
that accompanies new means of global communication.
Experiencing mediums as sites of ritual
In keeping with the logocentric metaphysics of communication, transmission accounts take dyadic interaction as their building block of analysis,
132
COMMUNICATION THEORY
and then examine more and more complex forms of mediation that alter
this building block. Transmission accounts do not ignore the kinds of
mediation that are in play in a communication process; indeed, they are
interested in how these mediations distort or inhibit the continuation of
dyadic interaction as a way of appreciating what they are.
However, as Meyrowitz points out, the idea of intentionality, which
is the most dominant metaphoric framework by which mediums are
‘lived’, cuts across all kinds of communication. We saw in the previous
chapter that the metaphysics of intentionality suggests that the message is
the medium. And, within this metaphysics, the more extended across
time and space are the mediums by which we can express intentionality,
the more convincing it is to live by the instrumental metaphor of
communication. The greater the distance that is covered in a communicative event, the more assured we can be of the validity of logocentric
communication.
We have already seen how the ‘metaphysics of presence’ which characterizes the Western experience of communication is premised on the
phonocentric analogue of face-to-face exchange. This does not mean that
the act of face-to-face communication is preferred over other kinds of communicative acts; rather, all forms of communication tend to be metaphorically lived and evaluated in terms of face-to-face communication.
For example, the vast critical literature bent on discrediting the social
utility of television, which had its origins well before the Internet, is
largely aimed at its inadequacy for face-to-face-like interaction.7 Likewise,
the Internet itself is also assessed for what qualities of face-to-face communication it can redeem by simulation. Where a medium is deemed to
offer more opportunities for such simulation, those interacting with mediums are typically described as ‘users’. Thus, for example, consumers of
broadcast technologies are seldom called ‘users’, whereas those who
interact with email, the World Wide Web or interactive TV frequently
receive such a designation.
To think of technological mediums in this way is to follow a familiar
fallacy that equates communication, transportation and exchange systems
as ‘service functions’ of culture, as supplements to social reproduction. By
this view, individuals are regarded as tool-using actors who are placed at
either end of intersubjective processes. In such a view, the message is the
medium and the medium is ‘used’ as a tool.
In contrast to this model, the advent of Internet communication has
coincided with a renewed interest in theories of ritual communication.
What theorists of the Internet have taught us is the importance of looking
at the ritual aspects of technologically extended communication, which
also means looking at the distinction between interaction and the way in
which communicative forms carry social integration. Sometimes, this connection is only intuitively observed, as when, for example, Howard
Rheingold (1994) describes communication on his own Internet network,
the WELL, as a ‘bloodless technological ritual’.
Interaction versus Integration
133
Part of the reason why ritual views have become popular is that
cyberspace is so much more visibly a medium than is broadcast. Both the
medium and the content of cyberspace can be analysed, but the content is
not as socially visible as is the content of broadcast. I will return to this
contrast in the sections below on the nature of ‘interaction’ in broadcast
and network architectures.
As the medium of broadcast is less visible, media studies analysis has
always tended to gravitate to messages and genres, ownership and control. But an important counter-tradition to this can be found in the work
of James Carey and Elihu Katz.
Carey’s work has attained considerable popularity as a kind of
modern-day foundational expositor of the ritual approach, his key text being
Communication as Culture (1989). For Carey, social reality is partly produced
in communication, not simply reflected by it. Quoting from John Dewey,
Carey argues, ‘Society exists not only by transmission, by communication,
but it may fairly be said to exist in transmission, in communication’ (14).
Media might reflect the world, but they also produce the world. And
when individuals interact with media, they are, as Durkheim would suggest, worshipping the way ‘society substitutes for the world revealed to
our senses a different world that is a projection of the ideals created by the
community’ (Carey, 1989: 19). However, such a ceremony need not be
driven by the desire for a ‘metaphysic of presence’, since typically the
medium that is interacted with is invisible.
Carey’s view of media is, in a way, remarkably similar to that of
Derrida and Baudrillard, in elevating the importance of the performative
role of texts, whether these be media texts or written texts. As Carey conjectures, ‘The particular miracle we perform daily and hourly – the miracle
of producing reality and then living within and under the fact of our own
production – rests upon a particular quality of symbols: their ability to be
both representations “of” and “for” reality’ (29).
Carey’s formula can be seen to parallel Derrida’s claim about the
double dimension of the sign: one aspect of it concerns the reproducibility of meaning, whilst the other is about the fact that texts themselves
constitute their own reality, which refer not to a beyond, but to each
other, to intertextuality, which we can only gain access to via specific
mediums.
In mounting the argument for communication as ritual, news is a
central focus for Carey because it is so typically thought of in terms of
information alone:
If one examines a newspaper under a transmission view of communication,
one sees the medium as an instrument for disseminating news and knowledge, sometimes divertissement, in larger and larger packages over
greater distances. Questions arise as to the effects of this on audiences,
news as enlightening or obscuring reality, as changing or hardening attitudes, as breeding credibility or doubt. …
134
COMMUNICATION THEORY
A ritual view of communication will focus on a different range of problems
in examining a newspaper less as sending or gaining information and more
as attending a mass, a situation in which nothing new is learned but in
which a particular view of the world is portrayed and confirmed. (20)
Under a ritual view, ‘news is not information but drama’ (see Carey,
1989: 21; Morse, 1998: 36–67). But this drama need not be simply about
communion but can be based on anxiety. News is a premier genre for
invoking such anxieties, and the addiction of audiences to tune in to a
daily update can be to ritually satisfy Dionysian needs (See Alexander,
1986)8. However, from a transport point of view, individuals are viewed
as simply ‘using’ the media to overcome their anxieties, rather than
the media having produced the behaviour which is supposed to be
overcome.
The transmission model of communication, on the other hand, promotes the illusion that messages comprise ‘information’ that is simply
learned and that they externally influence otherwise unmediated behaviour. Such a view takes no account of our attraction to such media in
the first place, and the way in which a ‘media event’ can come to mean
as much, in terms of attachment, or more, to individuals as non-media
events.
Carey is also critical of prevailing views of the power of media: ‘We
are (mistakenly) coerced into thinking of communication only as a “network of power” which needs to be “balanced” at the level of content in
order to legitimately represent the pluralist interests of liberal democratic
societies’ (34). Such power derives not from media influence over consciousness as hegemonic networks, but from a form of remapping and
displacement of primary environments of recognition and identification.
Both the ritual and the power dimensions of media have been in
Carcy’s view obscured by ‘uses and gratifications analysis’ (32). The ‘uses’
model reaffirms the notion that media are an instrumental extension of
processes of moral development (18). From telegraph to computer, communication is seen to be about moral improvement. This is usually
expressed as new technologies being used to carry older forms of social
relationships in a new, more ‘helpful’ medium. This latter view is one
which can be characterized as a purely informational view of communication, in which communication becomes either a means of control or a
means of expressing individuality.
Table 5.1 summarizes the major differences between transmission
and ritual approaches.
Now that we have examined the difference between transmission
and ritual accounts of communication, I want to investigate the difference
between interaction and integration in terms of various typologies which
have been put forward in communication theory. We shall begin with
typologies of interaction.
Interaction versus Integration
Table 5.1 Transmission
Transmission view
135
and ritual perspectives compared
Concerned with content
News is information (Carey, 1989: 21)
Individuals interact with each other
Logocentric – individuals restore presence
Symbols are representations ‘of’ (Carey, 1989: 29)
The media ‘mediate’ reality
Interaction
Face-to-face is privileged
Fleeting
Ritual view
Concerned with medium
News is drama and performance
Individuals interact with a medium
Simulacra – the act of communication
does not refer beyond itself
Symbols are representations ‘for’
The media produce reality
Integration
Face-to-face is marginalized
Constant
Types of interaction
As has been suggested, the metaphoric framework of logocentrism is one
which privileges interaction-as-event. Because of this, ‘phonocentric’ and
auto-effective forms of communication are privileged over others.
Phonocentric interaction exhibits a number of features which are differentially given continuation by different mediums.
These are the qualities of being ‘live’, and of mutual presence
between two or more interactants, who each have an opportunity for
speech. What these qualities provide, which can be ‘lost’ in extended communication, is a rich range of contextual information. Regardless of what
is known of each interactant in such a setting, the fact of their presence;
their body language, gestures and symbolic expressions; the way that
they acknowledge other interactants with glances and expressions; brings
with it a ready-made environment of meaning.
When we look at extended media, however, these two qualities, of
synchronicity and mutual presence, are, by definition, no longer co-present.
No extended media can reproduce all of these qualities of phonocentric
communication at once. The project of virtual reality is one which dreams
of such an achievement, but, paradoxically this requires making the body
redundant.9
However, extended media are certainly capable of singling out one or
two of these qualities in a typically enhanced fashion. Thus broadcast
can be viewed as an exaggeration of the auto-affective features of phonocentric communication events – it isn’t live merely for two people, but
potentially for billions of people. However, from the standpoint of the
same model, it does not measure up in allowing all participants an equal
opportunity for speech. Conversely, interactive telecommunication is a
very powerful means of two-way or multiple-way communication, but is
seldom live, or in real time. And even when it is real time, the absence of
mutual presence attenuates the deictic gestures possible in phonocentric
communication events.
136
COMMUNICATION THEORY
These basic differences between kinds of extended media, and the
fact that they typically extend some aspects of phonocentric communication whilst they annul others, is well outlined by John B. Thompson in his
book The Media and Modernity (1995).
In a sophisticated typology of interaction, Thompson distinguishes
between three types of interaction: face-to-face interaction, mediated interaction and mediated quasi-interaction. ‘Face-to-face interaction occurs in a
context of co-presence; the participants in the interaction are immediately
present to one another and share a common spatial-temporal reference
system’ (82). In the face-to-face, participants can ‘use deictic expressions
(“here”, “now”, “this”, “that”, etc.) and assume that they will be understood’ (82). Face-to-face communication is, like some extended modes, dialogic, or two-way. However, Thompson claims it is a special dialogic,
because it is the only communicative event in which participants ‘are constantly and routinely engaged in comparing the various symbolic cues
employed by speakers, using them to reduce ambiguity and to refine their
understanding of the message’ (83, italics mine). It is the multiplicity of
symbolic queues that are seen to be available to face-to-face situations that
guarantees a form of presencing which Derrida names ‘phonocentrism’.
Thompson’s next form of interaction is ‘mediated interaction’, which
includes letter-writing and telephone conversations. It presupposes a
technical medium (paper, electromagnetic waves, etc.) which enables
messages to be transmitted to persons remote ‘in space, in time, or both’.
The most important feature, however, is that ‘[w]hereas face-to-face interaction takes place in a context of co-presence, the participants in mediated interaction are located in contexts which are spatially and/or temporally distinct. ... The
participants do not share the same spatial-temporal reference system and
cannot assume that others will understand the deictic expressions they
use’ (83). Because of this, communicants must decide how much contextual information to add, such as signatures, letterhead information, or
identification at the start of a phone conversation.
The third form of interaction is ‘mediated quasi-interaction’. This
form is peculiar to the media of mass communication – books, newspapers, radio and television – and its defining feature is that ‘symbolic forms
are produced for an indefinite range of potential recipients’ (84). This
level of interaction is one which engages individuals ‘impersonally’, but
does not exclude them from more horizontal forms of personal association. Of course, the early days of ‘mass communication’ and effects analysis assumed that something equivalent to this level of interaction was the
dominant form of interaction of mass society – so much so that the
primary group of ‘face-to-face’ relations had to be ‘rediscovered’ in this
tradition (see Lowery and De Fleur, 1983: 180).
For Thompson however, it is because the addressees of this form of
communication do not have specificity, to the extent that this form engages
them, that individuals look also to primary forms of association.
Nevertheless, quasi-interaction, even if it is largely ‘one-way’, is still a
Interaction versus Integration
Table 5.2
137
John B. Thompson’s instrumental/mediation
paradigm
Types of interaction
Qualities
Face-to-face interaction (mutually embodied
presence)
Dialogic
Mutual presence
A high degree of contextual infomation
(body language, gestures, symbolic
cues, deictic expressions: ‘here’, ‘this’)
Reciprocal
Interpersonal specificity
Mediated interaction (technical mediums
like writing, telephoning)
Dialogic
Extended/not mutual
Restricted degree of contextual
information (letterhead, signature,
date placed on communication)
Reciprocal
Interpersonal specificity
Mediated quasi-interaction (books,
newspapers, radio, TV)
Monological
Extended
Produced for an indefinite range of
recipients by a small number of media
producers
Senders and receivers of messages
nevertheless form bonds
form of interaction, according to Thompson, because it ‘links people’
together (84).
As per the summary of Thompson in Table 5.2, the two forms of
extended interaction are significant in the way they correspond to interactive versus broadcast communication. The quasi-interactive quality of
broadcast is precisely the feature that second media age thinkers are critical of. Second media age thinkers are critical of the fact that there are
agents who stand between a sender and receiver of messages. The now
fashionable concept of ‘disintermediation’ that has emerged in recent
literature is entirely circumscribed by this rejection of mediation-by-agents
(see Dominick, 2001; Flew, 2002). This concept is primarily confined to
describing the economic functions of media in connecting buyers and sellers
(the removal of the ‘middleperson’), but has also broadened out to the cultural functions of media. Somehow, the heightened dependence on CMC
which replaces such mediation-by-agents isn’t also seen to be a form of
mediation (as Thompson’s model proffers). Disintermediation only refers
to the removal of human agents in the media process.
Oddly, machine-assisted or electronic means of communication are
somehow exempt from the mediation process, as if they are transparently
a means of rescuing the face-to-face from the way it suffers at the hands
of mass media. However, what can be noted in Thompson’s typology is
138
COMMUNICATION THEORY
that whilst these interactive forms differ, they have in common the fact
that they are both viewed as a mediation of face-to-face interaction and that
from this standpoint the term ‘disintermediation’ is flawed. There is no
reason why, within the logocentric framework of ‘mediation’ theory,
using submedia of the Internet, for example, is any less ‘mediated’ than
watching television.
However, as we shall see, whilst it is erroneous to classify either
network or broadcast dynamics as either more or less ‘mediated’, the conceptualization of mediation itself must be emancipated from the transmission
model. Thompson’s model also sits firmly within the communication-astransport paradigm of communication – a transmission-based model in
which the face-to-face is the base and is mediated by an architecture that
extends it in some way.
The problem with ‘mediation’
Thompson’s model is useful in the way it summarizes the background
theoretical architecture that is drawn on by many of those attempting to
theorize old and new media. For example, the ‘cues-filtered-out’ approach
is easier to understand in this comparative typology of media forms.
Nearly all of the cyberspace literature is framed by a social interaction
model – i.e. that face-to-face interaction is being supplanted by extended
forms of communication – and this is seen to be derived from technology
somehow intervening and separating us from some ‘natural state’ of interaction which is the face-to-face.
More useful still in Thompson’s typology is the way in which it takes
the interaction model to its outer limit. And the limit of this model is precisely the question of communicative context. We can recall Thompson’s
claim that ‘the participants in mediated interaction are located in contexts which
are spatially and/or temporally distinct’. A number of observations can be
made here:
• What is assumed in this statement is that the communicative context
which is to be privileged over all others is the ‘local’, ‘embodied’ context capable of mutual presence, which is separated from other such
‘local’ contexts.
• The task of communication is to overcome such separation by the
transmission of symbolic forms.
• Interactants have some measure of control in overcoming this separation of contexts by actively adding specific cues that are otherwise
structurally absent.
Mediation theory is a variant of instrumental theory, discussed above.
Instead of an interactant simply using a medium to convey a message, the
Interaction versus Integration
139
meaning of the message will be affected by a range of factors that come to
mediate its successful transmission. However, intentionality may be preserved insofar as the interactant understands the medium and is able to
make allowances for such mediation in crafting a particular message.
Thus, for example, journalists learn how to ‘write across’ different media.
In this way, interactants are seen to ‘metaphorically’ extend what they
may be accustomed to in face-to-face interaction. This is because they
inevitably project the qualities of face-to-face communication onto the
extended forms.
However, this description of mediated interaction assumes either
that the ‘local context’ of interlocutors in technologically extended communication is already known (be this mutually or otherwise) or at least
that it is in part disclosed in the communication process. The interlocutors
are deemed not to have an identity outside of what is known of their local
context. The local context gives them their identity. They may venture out
of it and communicate with others across time and space, but they do
so anchored in their context of origin, and are said to be identified in
this way.
To return to Table 5.2 once more, we can see how mediated and
quasi-mediated forms of interaction are seen to be continuations of the
face-to-face by other means. The qualities listed beside these forms are in
terms of what is replicated from the face-to-face, of what is absent.
Thompson does not, however, add what is unique to technologically
extended media which are absent in the face-to-face. Thus, for example,
under mediated interaction, he could add the fact that print is capable of
information storage, or, in the quasi-mediated interaction list, the fact that
broadcast communication is synchronous between large audiences, something unachievable in mutual presence.
However, technologically extended communication, whilst annulling
some of the features of phonocentric communication, also adds qualities
which are not possible within such communicative events. The technical
apparatuses of communication mediums can produce sounds not generated by the human voice, text too difficult to produce in the course of ordinary dialogue, as well as images beyond merely the image of the person
engaged in interaction. These qualities, which Meyrowitz identifies (see
previous chapter), can be thought of as providing the resources of an
entirely different register of communication ‘language’ – the arrangement
of images, camera angles, fades, echoes, sound-mixing genres, textual
conventions and styles, etc. The way that producers and consumers of
such images, music and text relate to them will vary considerably.
However, despite this, all interlocutors appreciate that the meaning of
messages in these mediums is to some degree shaped by the medium.
In such cases, the idea that the face-to-face is simply mediated begins
to collapse as it is realized that technologically constituted mediums bring
about new contexts of a substantially different order than can contexts capable of mutual presence. To insist that there exists a separation of contexts
140
COMMUNICATION THEORY
can only be upheld in an instrumental model of communication. In ritual
views, however, there is no separation; the medium is the context.
But the mediation view is very entrenched. It is even built in to
nomenclatures of communication like ‘computer-mediated-communication’.
The problem with the mediation view is that it replicates, in the field
of communication studies, what is endemic to common-sense views of
technology-in-general – an instrumental perspective. It does not see communication technology as substantively capable of its own context and
the dependence that individuals might have on this context.
The difference between instrumental and substantive views of
technology is well explored by Feenberg (1991). In Feenberg’s account,
the instrumental perspective ‘treats technology as subservient to values
established in other social spheres (e.g. politics and culture)’, while substantive theory ‘attributes an autonomous cultural force to technology
that overrides all traditional or competing values’ (5). Substantive theory
sees technology as embedded in circuits of interaction, and ‘argues that
technology constitutes a new type of cultural system that restructures the
entire world as an object of control’ (5). The more technology comes to
mediate the kinds of engagement and interaction individuals have with
the world, the more it takes on the character of an environment rather
than a tool. Moreover, technology has the power to encourage individuals to view environments in particular ways that are shaped by the means
they have of relating to them.
Raymond Williams’ distinction between technical invention and
technology-as-socially-configured is valuable here (Williams, 1974). He
suggests that in fact even in the first media age ‘technology’ cannot be
empiricized (i.e. technology-as-object) but, in a more Heideggerian way,
is always-already located as a medium (e.g. broadcasting).
This blind spot of second media age thinkers for not seeing technology in this wider sense allows them, in my view, to conflate their own
critique of first media age theory with their projection of first media age
‘technologies’ as fundamentally tool-like. For this reason, so much is
invested in the term ’cyberspace’, whereas, if Williams’ distinction is
adopted (with the addition of a list of qualifiers about the nature of interaction in broadcast technology), first media age technology might also be
considered a kind of cyberspace, serving to level further the distinction
between first and second media age.
Medium theory and individuality
Like transmission accounts, medium theory typically looks at how the
position of the communicants and the information communicated is determined by different media. But it also suggests something quite radical and
different from transmission accounts – the possibility that individuality
Interaction versus Integration
141
itself is (at least partially) an effect of a medium. In this view there are no
pre-given subjects with an experience of the real. There are no transcendental contexts which pre-exist other contexts and determine how they
are experienced.
In Thompson’s case it is embodied, mutual contexts which are seen
to pre-exist the extended contexts, and these former contexts structure
how we engage with the latter contexts. Moreover, the extended contexts
mediate our attempts at re-creating local contexts, even when they may be
separated in space and time.
The position of the individual in these settings is very much conceived logocentrically. Intentionality, the idea of being a language-user,
and even the idea of being a subject at all, is tied to this essentialism.
In contrast to this, medium theory suggests that individuality is an
effect of the medium itself. Such an idea was really first glimpsed by
Adorno and Horkheimer’s account of the culture industry, which they
describe as ‘a circle of manipulation and retroactive need’ (see Chapter 2
for a discussion).
Althusser’s model of ideology-in-general is also interesting in this
regard. Whilst, ostensibly, he was interested in the formation of identity
in ideology as an unconscious structure, his account purveys a ‘constitutive’ account of subject formation. There are no pre-given subjects with an
experience of social reality; rather, they are constituted by an apparatus of
integration. Althusser named the mechanism of this apparatus ‘ideologyin-general’. Ideology-in-particular is the name given to the content of
ideology, a question of consciousness, whereas ideology-in-general describes
the very operation of ‘calling’ or hailing individuals as subjects of a
system of broadcast.
For Althusser, therefore, a particular mass media kind of identity is
peculiar to the structure of broadcast, but not of interactive networks of
communication. Althusser does not theorize the forms of reciprocity and
identity formation produced by extended telephony or letter-writing. The
Internet, too, had only become fully operational in the year that Althusser
died. But network integration in general was for him an inadequate
terrain for examples of interpellation. Interpellation only occurs within
‘one-to-many’ apparatuses.
It is only recently, in the development of the theory of the avatar, that
accounts of subjectivity constituted in extended interactive mediums
have also come to the fore. In this view, the medium-as-environment does
not simply hijack a former kind of identity, but constitutes a new kind of
identity which lives a kind of virtual life. The TV channel surfer, the Internet
avatar, the writer and reader immersed in the text, etc., are each an example of this relationship. Implicitly, therefore, medium theory espouses an
account of the subject, rather than the individual.
The concept of the subject is one which has emerged in poststructuralist studies of power, language and ideology, but has recently
been incorporated into accounts of on-line identity. Sherry Turkle (1995)
142
COMMUNICATION THEORY
complains that, throughout the 1970s and 1980s, the idea that the self is
decentred and made up of multiple identities was a marginal one – ‘a time
when it was hard to accept any challenge to the idea of an autonomous
ego’ (15). Turkle suggests that ‘the normal requirements of everyday life
exert strong pressure on people to take responsibility for their actions and
to see themselves as intentional and unitary actors’ (15). But, and with
some cause for celebration, the Internet has changed this situation.
Turkle argues that the Internet ‘is [an] element of computer culture
that has contributed to thinking about identity as multiplicity. On it people
are able to build a self by cycling through many selves‘ (178) – so much so
that ‘[n]ow, in postmodern times, multiple identities are no longer so
much at the margins of things. Many more people can experience identity
as a set of roles which can be mixed and matched, whose diverse
demands need to be negotiated‘ (180). In this account of identity-assubject, Turkle overcomes the widespread essentialist views of on-line
identity as some kind of deceptive or fictive representation of another
level of a ‘real’ identity.10
Subject theory is a model of individuality which shares some similarities with ‘role theory’ in that individuals are capable of taking on
many different kinds of roles. However, it departs from role theory in
proposing that there is no subjectivity outside of these roles. In medium
theory, therefore, comparing the behaviour of an Internet avatar with a
‘corresponding’ off-line identity, does not make sense. Conversely, an offline subject does not simply ‘use’ a medium to further communication
objectives.
Because a medium already presupposes subjects who are its conduits
just as much as the technological medium (print, wires, electromagnetic
waves) is, medium theory does not speak of ‘users’ of a medium. Indeed
McLuhan abandoned the reference to media participants as ‘users’ in his
later writings.
From the point of view of the medium itself, to seek to understand
the avatar’s behaviour by establishing a link between that avatar and an
off-line identity will tell us very little compared to understanding the way
identity is formed within the medium itself.
Demonstrating the link between different kinds of subjectivities and
different mediums helps clarify the nature of the mediums themselves.
We can recall McLuhan’s claim that the technical aspects of mediums
produced certain personality types: bookish, tribal, etc.
If we apply this idea to broadcast and network forms as mediums, it
produces valuable insights into the modern dynamics of communication.
The media audience is well known as a mass (mass media). In both cases
the individual is constituted by the medium itself. The Internet avatar is,
by definition, constituted in a contextless space from which the very sense
of knowledge and power is internal to the medium. However, it is also
possible to use the Net as a mirror site for relationships which simultaneously exist off-line.
Interaction versus Integration
143
Medium theory insists on the need to look first at the architecture of
each medium, to assess the ‘subject position’ of actors within that medium.
For example, within broadcast, the viewer, listener or reader is constituted
in a ‘passive’ role as message creator, but a very active one in terms of the
need to interpret messages. In horizontal ‘network’ forms of communication, the avatar is constituted as a much more active kind of subject position with respect to the medium. However, where it seems that individuals
have an active role in regard to a medium, the dependence and attachment
they have to that medium are often disguised. This attachment can sometimes be revealed when flows of communication are interrupted. When a
connection is broken, the resulting anxiety can be a measure of the attachment, but also the way in which individuals relate to CITs which allow for
multiple connection, such as call-waiting on the telephone, multiple applications running at once on a computer, and channel-hopping on the TV,
can be a measure of the power of medium. The greater the urge to check
an incoming call or email, to roam channels, websites and stations, and the
more fragmented are the communication events, the more the individual
becomes a subject enveloped by the medium. When the linearity of
communication events is removed, the medium becomes more visible.
Over the past thirty years, the fact that mediums are about practice
and form, rather than content, has been the subject of numerous attempted
theorizations. These include glance theory (see Ellis, 1982), liveness theory,
audience theory and medium theory itself. However, when it comes to
understanding an individual’s relation to a medium, individual identity
often becomes obscured or one-dimensional – an effect of the medium
rather than an agent of it. The individual is no longer seen as an autonomous
monad with an experience of the real, but as nomadic, fleeting and contingent. However, whilst the individual is no longer positivized, there is a
tendency for the impact of mediums to be exaggerated, which is a charge
often levelled at McLuhan, Baudrillard and the Krokers.
Christopher Horrocks (2001) claims that one of the shifts in
McLuhan’s thought is, in the early years, seeing media participants as
communicating through mediums, and, in the later writings, seeing them
as being the subject of the medium (57). By the time McLuhan first begins
to discuss the computer, he abandons the early discourse of viewers,
listeners and audiences in which ‘the medium is the message’ to a later
discourse about media users: ‘in all media the user is the content’ (58).
However, this quote from McLuhan (in McLuhan and Zingrone, 1997:
280–1) is closer to Baudrillard’s understanding of the mass as the conduit
of media than it is to user perspectives. But Horrocks interprets
McLuhan’s shift as accommodating a user perspective suited to wideband Internet: ‘With Virtuality, in its widest sense, the use of e-mail,
e-conferencing and other tools demonstrates the shift from McLuhan’s
definition of the user as participant through a medium to manipulator
of that medium’ (57). Horrocks argues that the telephone could not
be manipulated as a medium, however the personal computer is more
144
COMMUNICATION THEORY
‘plastic in its interactive possibilities: A typical personal computer might
have e-mail, Web chat, RealAudio, word-processing and a news ticker
functioning at the same time’ (57) where users may vary their attitude in
how they construct their own media environment.
There are two problems here. Firstly, the sense in which McLuhan
suggests that users become the content does not permit the agency of
manipulators or of agents who have an attitude to the medium in which
they are immersed. Secondly, as Turkle and others have well shown, identity in virtual space is infinitely substitutable, and can itself be manipulated.
Reciprocity without interaction – broadcast
We have seen, with Thompson, the description of broadcast as a form of
mediated quasi-interaction. The concept of quasi-interaction Thompson
adapts from Horton and Wohl’s concept of ‘para-social interaction’ (Horton
and Wohl, 1956). In an article written in the mid-1950s, when the metapsychology of media consumption had barely been analysed, Horton and
Wohl explore the idea of intimacy at a distance, and the way in which
audiences identify with performers as face-to-face events. ‘The new mass
media are obviously distinguished by their ability to confront a member
of the audience with an apparently intimate, face-to-face association with
a performer’ (228). This intimacy, however, is not necessarily governed by
a ‘sense of obligation, effort, or responsibility on the part of the spectator,
and indeed lies in a lack of effective reciprocity. ... The interaction, characteristically, is one-sided, nondialectical, controlled by the performer, and
not susceptible of mutual development’ (215). Similarly, in Thompson’s
typology, the mediated quasi-interaction of books, newspapers, radio and
television does not have ‘the degree of reciprocity’ or ‘personal specificity
of other forms of interaction’ (Thompson, 1995: 84). Nevertheless, it establishes a structured ‘social situation’ of symbolic exchange in which audiences are able to ‘form bonds of friendship, affection or loyalty’. In other
words, because it is monological, it lacks mutual interaction but enables
strong forms of identification which carry a form of reciprocity.
This latter function of mass broadcast media has been emphasized by
the systems theorist Niklas Luhmann. In Luhmann, all forms of communication contribute to the construction of reality, but mass media are peculiar in producing a continual ‘self-description of society and its cognitive
world horizons’ (Luhmann, 2000: 103).
As with Thompson, mass media are characterized by widespread
dissemination, and ‘anonymous and thus unpredictable uptake’ (Luhmann,
2000: 103). This leads to a paradox: ‘the reproduction of non-transparency
in transparency’. Mass media are self-referential; they may not actually
reflect a reality outside themselves. However, what is transparent is that
Interaction versus Integration
145
they operate as a reserve for processing information. The individual
consumption of media may be unpredictable and anonymous, but as a
system, everyone can relate to it with ease.
Whereas mass media provide definite forms of solidarity, however,
they do so with little or no interaction. Thompson describes broadcast
media as ‘mediated quasi-interaction’ because they are only semi-interactive.
In Thompson’s view, only direct interaction, be it face-to-face or electronic
(‘real-time’), can qualify as a form of reciprocity. Clearly, Thompson feels
obliged to include broadcast as a form of interaction, but does not specify
why this term needs to be retained when no reciprocity is alleged to be
occurring.
What becomes the distinguishing feature of quasi-interaction is not
its ‘interactivity’ in a conventional sense, but that it is able to act as a
mechanism of communicative solidarity for social actors. Identification
and recognition make up for the lack of reciprocity in such a situation. In
this, Thompson redresses the way second media age theorists dismiss or
overlook the fact that broadcast, even if it is unequal at the level of interaction, still facilitates a powerful form of social integration – one which
even colonizes electronic interactivity itself – in, for example, the way in
which Internet participants aspire to broadcasting their own personal
web-page. Thompson also overcomes the unnecessary historicization of
media ages that is widespread in contemporary literature.
In order to restore the social aspects of the different types of interaction specified, Thompson also proposes that mediated interaction and
quasi-interaction have their own systems of social organization. He conceives of these systems as being built out of the basic building blocks of
‘local contexts’, which he calls ‘interactive frameworks of production’.
However, for mediated quasi-interaction, only the producers of symbolic
forms are immersed in a ‘local’ interactive framework of production,
whereas for the recipients, who are indeterminate, another framework is
added, ‘interactive frameworks of reception’.
In the social organization of face-to-face interaction, there is no separation between the context of production and of reception.
In the social organization of mediated interaction, the context of
production and that of reception are separated, but the settings of the production of messages are also available for face-to-face kinds of interaction.
We may be writing a letter or an email and be able to engage in embodied
conversation.
The social organization of mediated quasi-interaction is also a setting
for face-to-face and mediated interaction. Whilst watching television we
can be on the phone or engaged in conversation with others who are
also watching the television. This confluence of media events becomes a
form of ‘social organization’ when ‘[t]he conversational content of the
face-to-face interaction may be determined largely by the activity of reception, as when individuals are involved in commenting on the messages or
146
COMMUNICATION THEORY
images received’ (Thompson, 1995: 89–90). Thus, many face-to-face
conversations have a reference to TV as their content.
However, in the above models of intersecting forms of communication, face-to-face interaction continues to be privileged. Thompson’s
primary aim is to show the complex ways in which extended forms of
interaction mediate the face-to-face.
Thompson’s model does not view the extended forms of interaction as
themselves social ontologies except insofar as they mediate all of those
‘local contexts’ of production. Moreover, it can be argued that an oversight
of Thompson’s analysis is that the very idea of ‘local’ contexts of communication is made possible by communication that is stretched across space
and time. The very experience of the local qua local, in its contemporary
form, is made possible by more universal and extended forms of symbolic
exchange. To appreciate the fact that extended contexts should be regarded
just as important as ‘local’ contexts would also address the problem of
describing quasi-interaction as a form of interaction.
Remember that the second media age theorists see the problem of
broadcast as being one-way, whereas networked, horizontal forms are
two-way. But this holds true only from a logocentric conception of interaction. With the aid of Thompson, we can reveal a sense in which broadcast contains forms of reciprocity.
To return to Figure 3.1 (p. 53) regarding the architecture of broadcast,
we can note that at the level of interaction it is a largely one-way form of
communication. Thompson notes, in relation to television, that there can be
various kinds of ‘right of reply’ and interviews with audience members,11
but the overwhelming volume of ‘transmitted’ messages is one-way.
However, there is another way to view this architecture which reinstates its interactive quality. To appreciate this view, we must abandon the
idea that interaction must take place directly between agents, and view it
instead as something that can occur within a circuit of symbolic exchange
which may involve both human and technical agents.
In the architecture of broadcast that is illustrated in Figure 5.1, the
arrows have been located in both directions to suggest a dialogical relationship. The idea that embedded within broadcast is a form of reciprocity is not easy to see. It usually means establishing that the one-way
communication that is said to exist within broadcast is actually two-way
after all. This means establishing how the audience is a producer of a
media form as much as a destination for it.
Broadcast is a communication architecture in which a number of
forms of reciprocity are embodied.
• Broadcast isn’t entirely monological. There is the reciprocity which
occurs when media consumers also become producers. Thompson
gives examples with television, but it needs to be appreciated that it is
common to all forms of broadcast: ‘letters’ to the editor, opinion pages,
talkback radio and street interviews; and also on television, non-acting
Interaction versus Integration
147
Media producers as agents of cultural consensus
Media consumers as divided and unified
Figure 5.1
Ritual model: high integration/high reciprocity
persons appearing on documentaries, reality TV programmes, and the
high visibility of members of a ‘live’ audience.
• Broadcast is indirectly dialogical via the ratings system. Media producers may shape audience tastes, but, equally, audiences react to
trends in broadcast as a whole and may withdraw their patronage,
leading to changes in programming.
• At an individual level, media consumers do not simply comprise ‘an
indefinite range of recipients’. Audiences are specific to definite genres
and times, and constitute a remarkably high degree of solidarity. This
solidarity is channelled totemically and ritually through ‘media
agents’ – the characters, the presenters, the hosts and the media workers
who facilitate the structural architecture of broadcast. It is through these
agents that individual members of a given audience indirectly ‘interact’ with each other.12 Instead of having a directly horizontal communicative relationship with others, a detour is taken via these media
agents. It enables a form of the many speaking to the many via the
performative quality of the apparatus proving itself in every act of
broadcast.13
• As Thompson points out, the peculiar form of quasi-interaction consummates itself directly between audience members when they find
themselves in a face-to-face interaction. In fact the reason they may
associate is because of the common bond they feel with media agents
who have already brought them together. They may otherwise routinely
associate face-to-face, but make of broadcast media a primary basis for
mutual conversation.
148
COMMUNICATION THEORY
However, to continue to view this architecture in terms of ‘interaction’
becomes problematic, a matter which even Thompson has reservations
about, in his ad hoc remark that what he calls quasi-interaction should
really be called quasi-participation, which nevertheless sustains reciprocity as per the above. What is missing from Thompson’s account is the way
these agents of media (the media workers, the culture industry) carry a
form of social integration, what James and Carkeek (1997) have called
‘agency-extended’ integration, which we shall return to below in the section
on ‘levels of integration’.
It is insofar as broadcast can be regarded as a form of reciprocity or
‘quasi-social’ or ‘para-social’ interaction that the second media age thesis
becomes unsustainable. Broadcast can only be considered a one-way form
of communication to the extent that the metaphor of the media as channel, rather than environment, is adhered to. Broadcast media enable a
form of reciprocity without interaction in which many individuals are
‘metaphorically’ interacting with each other constantly.14 The broadcast
medium becomes the agent through which each audience member is able
to ‘reflexively monitor’ what it is that other audience members are consuming. Of course, if a broadcast programme is consumed in the mutual
presence of others, this reflexive monitoring will bring in their reactions.
In Figure 5.1, therefore, broadcast, like network forms of interactivity,
is characterized as a form of the many speaking to the many. This can be
appreciated only if broadcast is viewed as a medium of social integration.
The main relationship that is active for the audience is with other audience members, not with performers and celebrities. The latter are merely
the conduit by which solidarity is achieved with other viewers, listeners
and readers. Here, we can take issue with Meyrowitz’s No Sense of Place
(1985) for characterizing para-social interaction as illusory. Certainly individual members of audiences may come to feel they ‘“know” the people
they “meet” on television in the same way as they know their friends and
associates’ (119), but the intimacy being established is really with other
members of the audience, most of whom they will never meet.
Broadcast, like network activity, when conceived either as a technical
environment or as a form of social connection, is able to facilitate a sense
of belonging, security and community, even if individuals are not actually
directly interacting. Both these mediums, in different ways, enable forms
of social integration rather than extensions of face-to-face interaction.
They offer modes of relating which can determine the form of general
interaction in a given media society (see Table 5.3).
Broadcast integration also brings about a high level of recognition
between audiences and media producers, but, as we have seen, low levels of actual interaction. In such a mode of integration, audiences come to
identify strongly with media presenters, news teams, and film and soap
stars (see especially Langer, 1997). Some actors can readily acquire a cult
status whilst many news programme presenters may be endowed with
authority. All are bestowed with charisma as a reflex of the concentration
Interaction versus Integration
149
Broadcast and network as forms of communicative
integration
Table 5.3
Broadcast integration
Network integration
The many interact with the many by way of
the agent of message procedures (‘media
workers’, the culture industry, etc.)
The many interact with the many by way
of computer simulations of presence
High level of recognition/identification
Low level of recognition/identification
Very low level of interaction
Very high level of interaction
Individual experiences strong identity/
identification with figures of authority,
charisma or cult movements
Individual experiences weak
identification with others as figures of
authority or charisma
Concentration spans of audiences are sold
to advertisers
The need to communicate in highly
urbanized settings is sold to
individuals
Source: from Holmes, 1997: 31.
of consciousnesses in their person. The intensity of such concentration can
have substantial consequences for the distribution of recognition relations
within the specular field of a given broadcast medium. As discussed in
the next chapter, celebrities may become over-exposed, whilst audiences
can be too dispersed for cult fixation to gather momentum. These kinds
of changes will have an effect on the kind of virtual community that is
constituted by media events as much as entire mediums.
But there is also the question of the number of broadcast channels
that are available in a given national frame. The ‘nationwide’ audience
which Morley (1980) first theorized can only occur in settings where there
are a relatively small number of channels and broadcast conduits. In
Australia, commercial networks have recently staunchly opposed the
introduction of multi-channelling, ‘which would reduce their capacity to
offer advertisers a mass market on a single channel, while bringing in no
extra revenue’ (Tingle, 2002: 1). In order for advertisers to have an effective mass audience, the number of broadcasters either has to be very small
or very specialized, as in the case of cable TV.
Interaction without reciprocity – the Internet
To turn now to the second column of Table 5.3, just as there can be reciprocity without interaction, there can also be interaction without reciprocity. This is exemplified by any form of interaction between strangers at a
distance, as in much of the communication on the Internet. Such forms of
interaction are possible in fleeting, transient, face-to-face contexts in
abstract settings like a large metropolis where there is little likelihood of
such communication being repeated. But on the Internet it becomes a
150
COMMUNICATION THEORY
systemic reality. Most Internet identities are avatars for whom reciprocity
is not possible. For reciprocity to be successful there has to be some sense
of obligation to communicate which has a socially organized basis. Except
for mirror sites on the Web, and Internet email use, none of the sub-media
of the Internet provide a stable environment for relations of trust to
develop between users, or between users and information. For example,
on the World Wide Web, the phenomenon of bit-rot has even deterred
authors and analysts of cyberspace from print-publishing URLS from
websites (see Lunenfeld, 1999: 237). In CMC Net sub-media, avatars are
not accountable or responsible to each other except insofar as they apply
pre-given norms from the off-line world. But to do this is precisely contrary
to what an avatar is.
To appreciate this we need to distinguish between communication on
the Internet between interlocutors who have a prior face-to-face or institutional association and those who are anonymous to each other. In the
former circumstance, Internet communication is largely an affair of the
conduit and vessel. It may be simply a more efficient or instrumental
means of sending messages to those who are already known.
However, a large part of Internet use is between individuals who do
not know each other from other contexts, even institutional contexts.
A great deal of interaction takes place mediated by a computer-generated
infrastructure, but the obligation of reciprocity does not exist. Reciprocity
requires an identification of interactants in order for an exchange to be
rendered mutually. The proof of the distinctive consequences of anonymous communication on the Internet can be seen in the fact that it is considered necessary to have ‘policies’ to deal with such problems (Kling
et al., 2000). Such policies are not required in broadcast mediums. As Kling
et al. argue: ‘While many people believe that anonymous communication
on the Internet is not only acceptable but has positive value, others see
risk in it because anonymous users are not accountable for their behaviour.
Consequently, anonymity can mask or even encourage criminal or antisocial behaviour’15 (98). To remedy this perceived problem, the American
Association for the Advancement of Science’s (AAAS) Program in
Scientific Freedom, Responsibility and Law held a conference in 1997 to
‘better understand the nuances of anonymous communication on the
internet and develop ideas that could guide policy development in this
area’ (Kling et al., 2000: 98). Four major principles were advanced as
providing a guiding role in policy development:
• Anonymous communication on-line is morally neutral.
• Anonymous communication should be regarded as a strong human
right; in the United States it is also a constitutional right.
• On-line communities should be allowed to set their own policies
regarding the use of anonymous communication.
• Individuals should be informed about the extent to which their identity is disclosed on-line (Kling et al., 2000: 99–101).
Interaction versus Integration
151
As demonstrated by the AAAS exercise, the idea that the ‘rights’ of
avatars need to be protected is again a function of their low visibility, and
the fact that no kind of ‘other’, be it a person or an authority, has a commitment to an avatar. Very weak identification with others is experienced
between Internet avatars. There is a very low level of recognition between
them as they lack ‘off-line’ contexts of recognition which can provide
wider bases of identification. Often recognition is limited to text-based
interaction, in which the identity of an other is confined to what he or she
can construct with text.
However, it need not be the case that Internet avatars are deprived of
reciprocity. They could associate at another level of interaction, by being
members of the same institution, or by revealing a social world in which
they could relocate their identities, their character, and their reputation;
or, finally, they could meet each other. Any of these other contexts would
enable a triangulation of each interactant’s identity. Nonetheless, the
sheer volume of traffic within sub-media of the Internet ensures that most
interaction is between avatars.
In cases where, from the point of view of a given interactant, interaction is entirely internal to CMC, the kind of identity which is formed
may be described as constituted at a merely ‘intellectual’ level of abstraction which promotes a certain kind of solipsistic ego formation. Insofar
as an interactant can discontinue a relationship at any time without
its having repercussions in any kind of socially constituted field of recognition, CMC is well suited to the generalization of an autonomous
individualism which has long been characteristic of intellectual culture.
Instrumental control and liberation from the flesh is at the core of such
individualism (see Sharp, 1985). Interactants who do not like the
responses they get from interlocutors do not have to confront them at all.
They can control the kinds of interaction they have by minimizing random contact and only continue those relationships in which their
ideational reflection shines the brightest. Ultimately, such means of control result in avatars having conversations with no one but themselves,
particularly given that their identity is a self-contructed-for-others which
engages with a myriad of other ‘selves-constructed-for-others’. This is
not to say that such selves are not ‘real’; on the contrary, they are constituted ‘cybernetically’, as it were, and willingly participate in a system
which mutually reinforces the maximization of each interlocutor’s own
reflection.
The levels of integration argument
Thompson (1995) points out that for most of human history communication has been face-to-face. Most human institutions have evolved
within the scope of face-to-face relations. The emergence of new types of
152
COMMUNICATION THEORY
interaction which Thompson specifies has brought about new social fields
and changes to the nature of work, public/private divisions and leisure
time.
But it has, most significantly, brought about new modes of social integration. In order to explain this we need to formalize the distinction
between interaction and integration. Whereas interaction involves the
empirical act of engaging in a speech act, either extended or in mutual
presence, social integration is made possible by some or other form of
reciprocity, via interdependence, long-term continuity of association and
strong identification with an other – even an abstract other.
The claim here is that reciprocity can still occur without direct interaction. In fact it is possible to see how most reciprocity involves little direct
interaction at all, but rather is embedded in numerous kinds of rituals
which solidarize certain kinds of communion which may not be empirically obvious.16 From a sociological point of view, these rituals need not
involve restoring co-presence at all; rather, they may be oriented towards
quite abstract forms of association – but association nevertheless.
Social integration through ritual
A recent important book which can help us see how reciprocity in media
sociality can and does occur without any form of interaction is Nick
Couldry’s Media Rituals: A Critical Approach (2003). I am in complete
agreement with Couldry’s claim that ‘[w]e cannot analyse the social
impacts of contemporary media without taking a position on broader
social theory’ (3). And Couldry takes as the indispensable starting point
for such a position a radicalized reassessment of Durkheimian thought on
social integration.
As Durkheim allows us to ask: ‘how, if at all, do societies cohere, how
is it that they are experienced by their members as societies?’ (Couldry,
2003: 6).17 Couldry follows Durkheim in suggesting that even modern,
complex media societies exhibit principles of coherence that can be understood through the study of rituals. Three senses of ritual are distinguished: ritual as habitual action, ritual as formalized action, and ritual
as action that is associated with transcendental values. It is this latter form
of ritual which has the most bearing on the role of media in social integration. For Couldry, media represent a ‘wider space of ritualization’
which has a range of transcendental functions beyond individual habits
of media consumption. Moreover, the portrayal of ‘already existing ritual
action’ such as the televising of a religious event fails completely to illustrate what he wants to capture in the notion of media ritual.18
For Couldry, media rituals occur within psychological and spatial
boundaries in which it is possible for strangers to interact in symbolically
unequal yet naturalized ways in which they experience a shared set
of values. For example, in a description similar to Horton and Wohl’s
Interaction versus Integration
153
‘para-social’ interaction, Couldry discusses the ritualized meeting between
the ‘media person’ (celebrity) and the ‘ordinary person’ (media consumer)
in which audiences live their world of values through the celebrity at the
same time as the celebrity somehow comes to stand in for, and provide a
pivotal window into, social life (26–7).
This concentration of symbolic power is, for Couldry, more pronounced
in the modern media than in any other social institution (like church and
education). He favours ‘[a] strong concept of symbolic power ... [which] ...
would insist that some concentrations of symbolic power (for example, the
concentration from which contemporary media institutions benefit) are so
great that they dominate the whole social landscape’ (39).
Couldry sees media as supplying a late-modern ‘myth of the centre’.19
He describes a condition in which every member of modern societies
believes that the media are our ‘access point to society’s centre’. This is,
of course mythical, yet, to the extent that it is universally accepted, also
very powerful. The media themselves also enjoy a virtual monopoly over
the power of naming (43),20 and ‘defining-the-situation’. However, this
power is not a kind of hegemony in the Gramscian sense, or even the kind
of ‘will to truth’ which Foucault formulates; instead it is much more a
relation to the media’s status as an institution in the neo-Durkheimian
sense, rather than in the political spirit.
Because society’s symbolic resources are very unequally distributed (with
media institutions being the main beneficiaries of that inequality), these
ongoing conflicts of definition are marked by symbolic violence: certain definitions have enough weight and authority to close off most other alternatives from view, although such closure can never be total and is always, in
principle, open to challenge. (43)
The rest of Couldry’s book looks at genres of media where this authority
can stamp itself the heaviest: the ‘liveness’ of the media event, the ‘reality’
TV show, and the way in which fan clubs, in defining themselves purely
in terms of media, ritually reproduce the ‘myth of the centre’.
The distinction between ‘levels’ of integration
Couldry’s book is very useful for affirming and renewing the significance
of the concept of social integration and how it is related to ritual in media
societies. However, in a given society, ‘social integration’ need not be seen
to occur in a singular homogeneous space that changes over time.21
Rather, we can also point to perspectives which propose that individuals
can source their sense of integration from a range of levels of association,
which primarily differ in their degree of ‘abstraction’ in space and time,
from embodied forms of intimacy to the generalization of ‘action at a distance’ which characterizes contemporary global culture.
154
COMMUNICATION THEORY
The particular social integration perspective which is to be introduced
here has a number of exponents, who, from varying and quite separate
moments in sociological theory, can all be written into the development of
a distinctive tradition. This framework can be vicariously observed in a
number of different intellectual movements: situational/interactionist
(Goffman; Thompson/Meyrowitz), phenomenological (C.H. Cooley/
G.H. Mead; Calhoun), and abstraction arguments (Durkheim/Sohn-Rethel;
Giddens/Sharp/Slevin).
Situational/interactionist perspectives
The work of Joshua Meyrowitz provides an invaluable resource for problematizing the significance of New Media. Meyrowitz’s writings are distinctive in the way they synthesize the media writings of McLuhan and
the sociological work of Erving Goffman. In his pre-Internet work No
Sense of Place, Meyrowitz (1985) was beginning to integrate communication theory and sociological accounts of everyday life in useful ways.
Meyrowitz’s use of Goffman is in taking up social role theory to
explain different levels of association. McLuhan’s notion of sense ratios is
abandoned in favour of ‘face-to-face’, ‘back region’ and ‘front region’. In this
view, there are many kinds of selves distributed across levels of public
and private ‘regions’.
In adopting this approach, Meyrowitz (1985) explores ‘a common
denominator that links the study of face-to-face interactions with the
study of media: the structure of “social situations”’ (4). The key premise
from which he conducts the analysis is that media have architectures
which shape social situations in profound ways. Media create environments and various forms of electronic assembly which can either cut
through spatial segregation or replace it with electronic versions.
Focusing mainly on the case of television broadcasting, Meyrowitz
primarily wants to show how electronic media can break down the
‘traditional association between physical setting and social situation’ and
teleport individuals into an electronic public sphere (7).
Imagine that many of the walls that separate rooms, offices, and houses in
our society were moved or removed and that many once distinct situations
were suddenly combined. Under such situations, the distinctions between
our private and public selves and between the different selves we project
in different situations might not entirely disappear, but they would certainly
change. We might still manage to act differently with different people, but
our ability to segregate encounters would be greatly diminished. We could
not play very different roles in different situations because the clear spatial
segregation of situations would no longer exist. (6)
All of the ‘backstage’ behaviours that are carried on in the cloistered
architecture of interaction would now be visible by larger audiences with
Interaction versus Integration
155
better visibility. ‘Media, like walls and windows, can hide and they can
reveal. Media can create a sense of sharing and belonging or a feeling of
exclusion and isolation. Media can reinforce a “them versus us” feeling or
they can undermine it’ (7).
Importantly, however, Meyrowitz resists the temptation, commonplace in much Internet literature, to see New Media as having abolished
face-to-face interaction. Rather, for him, New Media expand the range of
possibilities of how individuals might interact, which can sometimes
present conflicting senses of the normative context in which actors are able
to take on roles. This may include confusion about which medium to undertake interaction in, and the nature of expectations individuals feel about
having to speak, to reply or to listen. Thus the title of Meyrowitz’s book
No Sense of Place alludes not to the disappearance of a sense of place, but
to the saturation of the self by a clash of ontological ‘levels’ of association.
In a communicative culture dominated by television, individuals are
typically able to hide behind the medium of broadcast when they are
actually interacting with a television itself. Without the comfort of the
television on, even in the background, a kind of role-vacuum is created, in
which responsibility shifts to the individual to be self-active.
Meyrowitz’s analysis is well complemented in Thompson, but with
many of the conceptual shortcomings we identified above. Nevertheless,
Thompson also makes a thoroughgoing case for a ‘levels’ argument, even
though it does not carry a sense of integration. He claims that entire systems of social organization are based on these levels, but it is as though
such organization is functional to dynamics of techno-social systems rather
than fulfilling different kinds of needs that emerge out of changes in the
infrastructures of communication.
Calhoun’s phenomenological levels of socialization
Working from what can broadly be described as a phenomenological
approach, the American public sphere theorist Craig Calhoun has made
some progress with developing a levels approach which is an advance on
those of Meyrowitz and Thompson. In three important articles on computermediated social relations, Calhoun (1986, 1992, 1998) innovatively develops the idea of indirect social relationships. Following C.H. Cooley’s
work in Social Organization (1909), Calhoun works up a typology-driven
model of communicative levels of social integration. Where Calhoun differs
from Thompson and Meyrowitz is in placing social integration rather
than interaction as the traversing agency across these levels. To explain
this we need to revisit Cooley for a moment. In Social Organization,
Cooley proposes the need to distinguish between primary and secondary
social relationships. ‘A primary relationship must be both directly interpersonal and involve the whole person.’ A secondary relationship, by
contrast, ‘need meet only the criteria of directness’, but not in a way
156
COMMUNICATION THEORY
which permits any kind of intimacy or many-sided recognition (Calhoun,
1986: 332).
Calhoun wishes to add tertiary and quaternary ‘indirect’ relationships: ‘Noting the impacts of modern communications technology, we
may go further and identify as indirect those relationships that require the
mediation of a complex communications system’ (332).22
For Calhoun, tertiary relationships are ones that individuals are
‘aware of’ and active in, for which he lists bureaucracy as an archetypal
form. ‘We have “tertiary” relationships with those to whom we write to
complain about errors in our bank statements, with our political representatives (most of the time), and, often, with the senior managers of the
companies for which we work’ (332). Quaternary relationships are ones
which we are not aware of such as surveillance infrastructures, and we are
exposed to techno-social systems in which we find ourselves unwilling
participants (333).23
Both tertiary and quaternary relationships allow for what Calhoun calls
large-scale social integration, the definitive locus of which is the modern
‘mega-urban’ city. Cooley’s secondary direct, but unfulfilling, relationships
are, in some measure, a part of the large-scale urban picture because they
offer ‘serendipitous contact across socio-cultural boundaries’ (335).
But secondary relationships are also cause for the experience of
widespread anomie, precisely because of their practical difference from
primary relationships. Calhoun argues that this difference is ontological,
not simply a matter of perception. Secondary relationships are generally
held in low esteem by city dwellers, as advanced by Cooley himself at the
beginning of the twentieth century. Primary relationships, found in family
and face-to-face networks, provide spontaneous settings of integration
even when they involve conflict.24
The frustration of secondary relationships, in workplaces, in the
market place, in the public sphere, is that they take up so much of our
time, and are emotionally involving but unfulfilling. Whilst it is true that
primary relationships may also be unsatisfying, at least they are capable
of generating enduring loyalty and satisfaction, which secondary ones
can’t. Secondary relationships foster a destructive notion of freedom in
which ‘strangers often seem to exist only to annoy us’ (as Sartre once suggested, ‘Hell . .. is other people’), and such ‘relationships are simply the
choices of the moment rather than commitments’ (335, my insertion).
They are purely functional, such that when even their functionality fails,
it reverberates as an even more intense condemnation of the hopelessness
of the emotional or other value of such levels of association.
Under such conditions we seek to avoid emotional involvement in
our dealings with strangers and ‘deal with problems by trying to escape’,
as narrated in Philip Slater’s (1971) account of the ‘pursuit of loneliness’.
Such a condition has also become the subject of films like Falling Down.
The ontological impasse between primary and secondary relationships, which is in some sense ‘proven’ by the everyday tension between
Interaction versus Integration
157
them, is, argues Calhoun, eased by the widespread development of
tertiary relationships. Whilst some may see technologically mediated
relationships as just a disembodied extension of estranged secondary relations25 (particularly when tertiary relationships are only a rudimentary or
modest feature of social relations generally), for the most part, he argues,
such a level of relationship can be experienced as emancipatory. Remember
that Calhoun was advancing this thesis well before the utopian discourses
which heralded the Internet as relieving everyone from the impersonal
aspects of trying to maintain large-scale integration in an embodied form
by way of networks of agents.
The ‘proliferation of tertiary relationships cuts down on secondary,
but not primary, relationships’ (336). Calhoun argues that in substituting
for the unwieldiness of large-scale social integration occurring at an embodied level, a tertiary relationship can actually free up individuals to spend
more time in primary modes. ‘We might focus time and energy on community building, friendships and family life, though this is only a possibility, not an automatic result’ (336).
For Calhoun, this possibility is a feature of all technologically
extended and mediated relationships, not simply communicative ones.
He gives the example of the automatic teller machine. ‘Direct interpersonal contact is reduced, as the customer no longer deals with a teller. But
the customer also spends less time standing in lines and has greater flexibility as to when to use banking services.’ The customer does not have to
endure the
rebuff of non-recognition. … There is often a disappointment on the
customer’s side at not being recognized (and apparently not trusted) by a
person with whom he or she may interact on a regular basis. … It is not
obvious that we are losing much of value in giving up this sort of ‘personal’
interaction. (336)
Conversely, argues Calhoun, the flexibility we have with interfacing
with the much more numerous machines frees up time which can be used
more productively elsewhere, as well as being ‘redeployed into primary
relationships’ (336).
However, Calhoun’s caveat is that while computers might greatly
assist in large-scale integration,
there is as much (or more) reason to think that computerization and new communications technologies will lead to or accompany further deterioration of
interpersonal relationships. A drift toward relationships of convenience might
be accelerated; passive enjoyments from the mass media might predominate
over active social participation. A few people might even wind up preferring
relationships based on single common interests and mediated through
computer networks – or worse (from the point of view of social integration),
preferring the company of computers themselves, which are dependable,
don’t talk back, and don’t make silly mistakes (very often). (337)
158
COMMUNICATION THEORY
In other words, Calhoun perceives a tension between the capacity of
tertiary relationships to enhance and regenerate primary ones and their
tendency to replace them altogether.
Constitutive abstraction
A position known as ‘constitutive abstraction’ has been advanced for
many years by an Australian group associated with the journal Arena
who have developed a social theory which looks at social relations as an
intersection of ‘levels of integration’. It is an account which has emerged
largely in isolation from other approaches to ‘levels’ theory but is one
which nevertheless contains invaluable points of innovation.
The Arena thesis takes up the work of Alfred Sohn-Rethel, who poses
the question in his Intellectual and Manual Labour (1979): can there be
abstraction other than by thought? By this, Sohn-Rethel suggests that
abstraction is not merely a property of the mind, but can occur in social
relationships also. When it does so, these relationships are no less ‘real’
than less abstracted ones; however, they do possess distinctive features.
The constitutive abstraction argument shares the departure point of
Thompson that most human culture has been framed by face-to-face relationships and only recently have we seen the emergence of new forms of
social relations. The newer forms are shaped by the rise of postmodern
technoscience of all kinds, not just communication. Postmodern technoscience differs from the science of the Enlightenment or modernity in that
it is seen to reconstitute the natural and social worlds rather than simply
harness such worlds in the name of progress. Thus, IVF fundamentally
intervenes in the process of human reproduction, to the point of making
many of its qualities redundant. Nuclear power, in sub-atomically
rivalling processes which occur on the sun, makes possible the 24-hour
society, in a different way than did coal.
The main agents of these changes are the intellectually related groupings. The results of their practice of reconstituting the world creates
settings of ‘new nature’ which abstract all persons into an orbit of interchange and exchange that can be seen to be derived from intellectuals and
their practices.
In this view, therefore, print, the dominant medium of intellectuals, is
seen as a precursor to modern technologically extended forms of communication. The newer forms of communication bring about practices which
abstract the individual from more embodied forms of social relations and
de-link those individuals from the kinds of roles that they once had, giving
them the appearance of autonomy.
As Sharp (1985) suggests:
The first point to make about this sort of practice is that in order to be
engaged in it the person must be abstracted from the settings which make
Interaction versus Integration
159
up the structure of what we still take to be the mainstream life of society. Of
course such members of the intellectually related groupings go to work, get
paid, have families and go to the supermarket and the pub; but none of
these settings accounts for or defines the specificity of the relations within
which they carry on their distinctive practice. The second point relates to the
social form of which this abstracted practice is constitutive. Basically it
would seem that for the intellectuals we can say that interchange is mediated by print which serves as one abstracted way of symbolizing the linguistic element of face-to-face interaction. This technological medium allows the
social tie to be extended in space and in time. It creates a setting whereby
the participant is ‘lifted out’ of the relationships of everyday life and where
at least subjectively persons experience themselves as the authors of their
own creations. In other words, they begin to experience themselves as postindividual or, as the contemporary pop term would have it, as ‘autonomous
persons’ acting in a setting where the boundaries or constraints visible in
ordinary life might seem to have dropped away. (62–3)
However, the emergence of the autonomous individual who no longer
has the roles which once seemed to be easily ascribed is not merely a
matter of changes in interaction. For social relations generally to take on
the mode of interchange which has characterized intellectuals for many
centuries,
different modes of the extension of the social relations must emerge – in
transport, in communication generally. To illustrate this process for the polity,
the extended process of commodity exchange and the reconstruction of the
practices of ideological integration, it is scarcely necessary to look beyond
the role played by television as a form of extended social relationship. But
the ways in which the population at large is drawn within the field of extended
interaction all require separate treatments in their own right. (63)
It is these ‘separate treatments’ which are quite underdeveloped in the
Arena thesis. However, Paul James and Freya Carkeek (1997) have proposed levels of integration in a way in which New Media can be more
readily contextualized. Drawing on the Arena framework, they explore
‘levels of social integration’, ‘understood as intersecting forms of structured practices of association between people’ (110). The levels do not
exist as pure forms but are analytically distinguishable. Nominally, they
distinguish three levels: face-to-face integration, agency-extended integration and disembodied integration.
Face-to-face integration is defined as the level where the modalities of being
in the ‘presence’ of others constitute the dominant ontological meaning of
interrelations, communications and exchanges, even when the self and the
other are not always engaged in immediate face-to-face interaction. Under
such forms of interrelation, the absence of a significant other, even through
death, does not annul his/her presence to us. Agency-extended integration
involves the extension of possibilities of interrelation through persons acting
in the capacity of representatives, intermediaries or agents of others. (111)
160
COMMUNICATION THEORY
This level corresponds to what Cooley and Calhoun call ‘secondary
relationships’.
‘Disembodied integration is the level at which the constraints of
embodiment, for example being in one place at one time, can be overcome
by means of technological extension – broadcasting, networking or telephoning, to name only a few’ (111). This level corresponds to Thompson’s
mediated interaction and mediated quasi-interaction.
James and Carkeek go on to clarify that ‘each of these levels is more
abstract than the level “prior” to it, and each is implicated quite differently
in the ways we live the relationship between nature and culture, and the
ways we live our bodies and the “presence” of others’ (111).
As posited by the Arena perspective, levels of integration are not
empirical forms, however, but are ‘ideal-type’ social forms, which are also
capable of co-presence within a given societal form.26 In tribal societies it is
face-to-face meetings which are the most important, whilst abstraction at
the level of religion is very much in terms of the totemization of the body
and of the land. In agency-extended society, the greatest importance is
attributed to manual craft and networks of actors consolidated in institutions. In more abstract, information societies, on the other hand, it is the
intellect which is ritualized in the fetish of high-technology and ultimately
the use of technologies which presuppose the analytic dismembering or
displacement of the natural world.
However, ‘less abstract’ is not equated with underdeveloped, nor is
‘abstract’ equated with developed. Most literature is framed by such a
linear model of the succession of forms of mediation, but in the Arena model,
even though new levels of abstraction keep emerging on an historical basis,
they do so in tension with established forms, which they intersect with
rather than simply supersede. Thus, Arena authors claim not to argue for
a return to close-knit parochial communities which rest on face-to-face
relations but, rather, that the tension between levels is enriching ‘as long
as any one level does not come to constitute the dominating mode of livingin-the-world, and so does not thin out prior levels of human interrelation’
(James and Carkeek, 1997: 111).
For James and Carkeek, these different levels intersect in complex
ways. Each level may ‘contradict, qualify, dominate or be “thinned out”
by other levels of integration’ (111). In particular circumstances, one of
these levels may become dominant throughout a societal form. However,
it is older forms of integration which are vulnerable to annulment by
newer forms, rather than the reverse. In tribal societies, face-to-face integration is generally dominant, but seldom comes into tension with agencyextended or disembodied integration. What is of interest in this situation
is the way in which a tribal, status-bound culture might take up disembodied forms of communication. In this circumstance what is important is
that persons are bound to each other even when the self and the other are
not engaged in immediate and embodied interaction. Therefore the point of
Interaction versus Integration
161
‘finding connection’ by means of tele-mediation may seem anachronistic
for persons formed in this way.
When agency-extended integration predominates, it is the expectation of embodied networks of intermediates which becomes the dominant
centre of ‘ontological security’ within a societal form. In such a setting,
word of mouth, recommendations, networks of knowledge and activity
offer far more of a guarantee of bonding to the social form than can be
achieved via an abstract market, telecommunications, etc. The dominant
form of this level of integration is the institution: church and state, guild
and corporation, media and the culture industry – and their various
constituencies, which each become trusted anchors.
Like agency-constituted integration, the interactive events of disembodied integration usually refer back to the face-to-face (e.g. emoticons,
cybersex) whilst annulling the face-to-face by extension. Disembodied integration is the most paradoxical because it typically creates the very conditions which it nostalgically attempts to overcome.
Extension of communication by agent
An important level of communicative integration which the abstraction
thesis points to, but which is too often overlooked in current-day accounts
of ‘community’ and ‘interaction’, is that of extension by agent. For example,
almost always, analyses of technologically extended social relations limit
themselves to a comparison with ‘face-to-face’ communication, from which
follow familiar binaries of embodied/disembodied, virtual/real, etc.
What is overlooked is the way in which a communication process
which also forms part of the ‘reciprocity without interaction’, which we discussed above, is mediated by other actors, and is not simply a technical
means of transmission. This is more visible in broadcast than with the agents
who are at work in CMC – the software designers and programmers. In the
broadcast situation, Raymond Williams (1961) discusses an important
distinction between source and agent. A source is someone who offers an
‘opinion, a proposal, a feeling’ and ‘normally desires that other persons will
accept this and act or feel in the ways that he defines’ (293), whereas an agent
is someone whose ‘expression is subordinated to an undeclared intention’
(293), such as attracting audiences, editing a text to satisfy certain tastes, etc.
‘In social terms, the agent will normally in fact be a subordinate – of a government, a commercial firm, a newspaper proprietor’ (293), necessary to any
complex administration.
But agency is always dangerous unless its function and intention are not
only openly declared but commonly approved and controlled. If this is so,
the agent becomes a collective source, and he will observe the standards
of such expression if what he is required to transmit is such that he can
wholly acknowledge and accept it – recreate it in his own person. (293)
162
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Thus, for Williams, agents have a moral obligation to give carriage to
what is commonly approved and controlled, and where the agent unreflexively assists in the process of transmission, without regard for the
standards of expression, he or she is acting in a way that is ‘inferior to the
poorest kind of source’ (293).
To follow Williams’ argument, agents are a necessary part of any kind
of mass communication, but they are also significant actors in the ‘mediation’ of culture itself. They figure deeply in the way that reception and
response depend on factors other than the ‘techniques’ and means of
transmission. But they are so often overlooked as mediators of communication because of the fact that dominant and popular conceptions of the
communication process make too sharp a distinction between source and
technique, an author-message and conduit (cf. Meyrowitz), not leaving
much room in between for the idea of agent.
Abstraction and the Internet
A much more recent abstraction argument which provides an account of
the Internet from a social theory point of view is that of James Slevin, in
his useful volume The Internet and Society (2000). Slevin draws together
theoretical analyses from Anthony Giddens, John Thompson and a theorist
of postmodernity, Zygmunt Bauman.
Giddens prefigures the constitutive abstraction argument discussed
above, but in a less developed way. Nevertheless, Giddens’ more familiar
concept of ‘space-time distanciation’ is one suited to developing a contextual analysis of the Internet.
Giddens argues that traditional forms of institutional socialization
have declined as our occupation of social space is today less tied to a sense
of physical place (see Giddens, 1990; this is also integral to Thompson,
1995). In Giddens’ account it is not merely new communication practices
which contribute to such de-physicalization, but also monetary exchange,
travel, chronological time-keeping and old communications technologies
such as print. The distanciation characteristic of these techno-social
arrangements produces a ‘“lifting out” of social relations from local contexts of interaction and their restructuring across indefinite spans of timespace’ (Giddens, 1990: 21). The ‘disembedding’ of close-knit social relations
results in more abstract forms of social tie, in which time-space relations
are no longer experienced as restraints on actors (Giddens, 1987). The former characterize band societies and agricultural communalism, whereas
civilizational (pre-industrial) societies and industrialized societies are
characterized by successive forms of disembedding (cf. Giddens, 1987:
93–6). Giddens (1987) argues, ‘The level of time-space distanciation characteristic of band societies is low. The mobile character of the society does
not involve a mediated transcendence of space: that is to say, it does not,
as in large societies, involve regularized transactions with others who are
Interaction versus Integration
163
physically absent’ (93–4). For Giddens, these regularized transactions
become system-like within time-space envelopes that have their own distinct set of time-space conditions that are tied to technology, institutions
and social organization.
James Slevin (2000) adopts the ontological contours of Giddens’
account of time-space distanciation by way of its influence on Thompson’s
theory of communication and cultural transmission. Slevin’s particular
contribution is to rework the disembedding thesis by arguing that the
Internet combines three aspects of cultural transmission in a unique way:
as a technical medium, as an institutional apparatus, and as a form of spacetime distanciation.27
A technical medium (e.g. print, analogue or digital communication)
is distinguished by its capacity to store information and reproduce it (as
in ‘mass reproduction’, for example), as well as its availability for participation. The Internet, Slevin argues, is a powerful super-medium which is
capable of strongly realizing all of these attributes. However, we cannot
understand the significance of this without also understanding institutional contexts which govern the technical medium. For example, it is
very easy to eulogize the Internet’s capabilities for interaction, but it would
be naïve to do so without also pointing out its potential for surveillance.
The ways in which the Internet is used lie outside its material/technical
substratum, and have more to do with the modern state and its institutions, which have their own culture. Thus, surveillance, for example,
could be said to have always been practised by the modern state, but the
technical means of carrying it out have changed.
There is yet one other form of change, however, which Slevin adopts
from Giddens and Thompson, which is the ‘degree of temporal and spatial
distancing involved in the circulation of information and other symbolic
content’ (Slevin, 2000: 69). Slevin argues that technical and institutional
apparatuses of the transmission of culture not only produce time-space
relations, but also respond to them. For example, disembedding may facilitate greater numbers of persons who will never meet each other to virtually interact, but it can also contribute to conditions, like globalization,
which require more complex and powerful technical and institutional
means of connection. ‘The pressure and opportunities for mobilizing
time-space during the exchange of information constitute the “grounding”
for the way in which such exchanges are organized and sustained’ (69).
For Slevin, the Internet provides a ‘grounding’ for a new level of disembeddedness, which he contrasts with mass communication, but in a
way in which Thompson’s interaction-based comparison is revised. Four
key aspects of mass communication are challenged by the Internet as
super-medium. Firstly, the Internet is a relatively ‘open communication
system’ which does not require ‘large scales of expert systems for the production of content’. Second, the Internet does not just ‘equalize’ the relation
between sender and receiver, but blurs the dichotomy between the two,
although this ‘may vary from encounter to encounter, from application to
164
COMMUNICATION THEORY
application’ (74). Thirdly, to the degree that institutional arrangements
allow, availability in time-space is enhanced. ‘Organizations can now store
masses of information on their websites and achieve around-the-clock
availability’ (75); in comparison, news in mass media will only be broadcast if it is televisable, newsworthy, etc. Finally, traditional mass media are
compelled to circulate symbolic forms in ways which parallel Internet
communication. Slevin points to the digitalization of broadcast and the
proliferation of channels and their specialization in programming and
audiences (76).
In each of these cases, the Internet is seen to recast the distinct timespace conditions of electronic media in general. Ultimately, Slevin does
not oppose the Internet to broadcast; rather, the two forms must be considered in relation to institutional forces, as comprising a complex level of
extended integration that is distinguishable from face-to-face and agencyderived modes.
Conclusion
The different levels arguments that we have explored differ from interaction perspectives in that they suggests that media of communication can
act as bases of association which reach well beyond the communication
events they make possible. Meyrowitz’s understanding of media ‘architectures’ provides one kind of model for thinking about the hierarchies
of structured communication. It is a decisive advance on Thompson’s
model, which rests on an empirical reduction of ‘interaction’ (rather than
integration) whose basic analogue is the face-to-face; as such, it treats all
other interactions as ‘mediated’. ‘Mediation’ theory is a variant of the
reproductive view of communication: that mediated or extended communication is a continuation of dialogical interaction by other means. The
integration argument insists that these ontological levels are constitutive
of distinct orders of the distribution of recognition relations, rather than
the mediation of some kind of ‘building-block’ form of interaction: the
face-to-face. In contrast, approaches like Calhoun’s and the Arena thesis
are concerned to show that the division between face-to-face, extended
and technically constituted is an ontological one, and that social integration via specific levels is more than simply the aggregation of communicative events within each of these levels.
Unlike interaction theory, which is derived from ‘transmission’
accounts of communication, and the idea that development in the means
of communication is about moral improvement, the integration theorists
view human culture as being engaged across a range of levels of communication. The sociological basis of the integration perspective resists the
tendency of interaction approaches to view the telos of communication as
providing a transcendental unity, a virtual community or global village.
Interaction versus Integration
165
Rather, what is true of all of the integration perspectives is that in each of
the ‘levels’ of social integration, individuals are separated and united at
the same time. It is the architecture of this separation and unity and the
tension that exists between levels which will determine the kinds of community and association that are possible within given social formations. It
is to the question of community that we shall now turn.
Notes
Some of the passages discussing the work of Derrida in this chapter are derived from
Holmes, D. (1989), ‘Deconstruction: A Politics Without a Subject’, Arena, No. 188: 73–116.
1 This, of course, becomes metaphysical in the cases of the discourses of cyberculture –
discussion of being ‘jacked-in’ to the matrix, etc., plugged in to the medium.
2 In his treatment of Saussure, Derrida merely repeats the much earlier development that
is offered by Jacques Lacan (1985).
3 This would imply a mode of ideality in which, for example, a sign could be infinitely
repeated and withstand modification of its meaning, a project which occupied the
philosopher Edmund Husserl.
4 For an extended review of Derrida’s writings see Holmes (1989) and Norris (1982).
5 This is implicit throughout Derrida’s work and is explicit in the opening of SEC with a
distinction between non-semiolinguistic and semiolinguistic communication, between
communication in the sense of bridging a gap, making close what was afar, and the
sense of communication as the transmission of meaning.
6 Except that the medium actually provides such a context when engaged with ritually. It
is precisely because the original context cannot be reproduced that we look to the
medium itself.
7 But also its inadequacy compared to the civic virtues of print (see Marc, 2000: 637).
Telephones have seldom met with the same kind of critique.
8 Alexander argues that news operates in a paradigm of truth-telling, but that when it
addresses an issue concerned with crisis, this function gives way to being a forum for
what he calls ‘a certain ritualized value experience’. In a case study of the reporting of
Watergate in the US media in 1973, Alexander argues that the media had become more
concerned with ‘“values” that define the meaning of nation, the nature of citizenship,
the duties of office, or the meaning of life itself. When truth is broadcast on such a generalized level, there is media ritual’ (245).
9 See Regis (1990) for a discussion of how postmodern technoscience rejoices in exceeding and abjuring the body.
10 For an exemplary instance of this treatment of identity, see Donath (1999).
11 Using the example of television, Thompson illustrates this point (Thompson, 1995: 96).
12 Thus, as Thompson (1995) points out, it is possible to ‘communicate through television’ (92).
13 In a rare articulation of this form of integration that is conceptualized in the interests of
the promotion of talk shows, Couldry cites a television producer from Dominique
Mehl’s analysis of intimacy and television, who explains the attractions of TV for
self-disclosure. ‘It’s as if, in order to speak to those close to them, it’s necessary [for them]
to pass through TV. One could say that, in order that these people are reintroduced into
the social circuit, they must pass through television. .. . Which is their home’ (quotation
translated in Couldry, 2003: 124).
14 Thus reciprocity does not require the ‘logocentric’ here and now of interaction, but is
made possible by the anticipation that it is at least possible to be in the position of an
interlocutor (as in the case of ‘para-social interaction’). Or as Walter Ong (1982) says: ‘In
real human communication, the sender has to be not only in the sender position but also
166
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
COMMUNICATION THEORY
in the receiver position before he or she can send anything. .. . Human communication
is never one-way. Always, it not only calls for response but is shaped in its very form
and content by anticipated response’ (176).
On the positive side are: investigative journalism, whistle-blowing, law enforcement,
self-help, personal privacy protection, avoiding persecution (113–14). The negative
includes: spamming, deception, hate mail, impersonation and misrepresentation,
on-line financial fraud, numerous illegal activities (115–16).
These forms of communion may have positive and negative functions: they might
enable a shared sense of belonging whilst also masking inequalities and conflicts within
the social order.
‘To the extent that “everything works as if” there were a functioning social whole, media and
media rituals are central to that construction – which is why we need to study them’ (10).
Thus Couldry wishes to reject theorists who argue in a limited or general sense that
media rituals are extensions of other forms of everyday ritual. For an instance of the
latter, and a comparative analysis of rites, ceremonies and media ritual, see Rothenbuhler
(1998).
However, Couldry’s book makes little attempt to theorize the relationship between
mass media rituals and New Media rituals.
Couldry enlists the work of Italian political
theorist Albert Melucci for this notion, but he
∨ ∨
could just as easily employ Slavoj Zizek’s work in The Sublime Object of Ideology (1989).
For Couldry, the ‘ritual’ is not an activity, but marks an entire sphere of integration (2).
Significantly, Calhoun says, such tertiary relationships might involve ordinary written
communication; they ‘need not involve electronic technology, though such technology
now greatly enhances the reach and the efficacy of such systems’ (332).
Calhoun’s tertiary and quaternary levels are dealt with in most CMC literature in terms
of use/abuse, ‘impact analysis’ or within the sociology of technology in terms of a
positive and negative effects debate (see, e.g., Spears and Lea, 1994).
A major work which configures such primary relations as a level of sociation is Bott
(1971).
‘Certainly, they think, a world dominated by relationships conducted over the phone,
by correspondence, or with the assistance of computer would be much worse’ (Calhoun,
1986: 335).
Sharp distinguishes between social form and societal form. Social forms are modes of
integration that feature identifiable bases of community, virtual, extended, face-to-face,
whereas a societal form refers to an actually existing historical ‘configuration’ of the
different levels and components of social integration and their institutions (see Sharp,
1993: 225).
Slevin’s caveat is as follows:
It must be remembered, however, that the internet cannot be approached as a
single communication entity. … It consists of an array of different technical applications. A more detailed study would involve the examination of various internet
applications, for example WWW, e-mail, IRC etc. and the unique way in which they
combine Thompson’s ‘attributed of technical media’. (62–3)
SIX
TELECOMMUNITY
Rethinking community
For a term that is so over-used in media publics, it is remarkable how
under-theorized ‘community’ is today. Since the nineteenth century, when
Ferdinand Tönnies formulated what has become the most widely referenced understanding of community, in his Community and Association
(1995), little formal analysis of community has been undertaken. And yet
a certain regard for community has constantly endured throughout the
discourses of modernity as a key term of reference and as a legitimating
narrative for the human sciences and civic discourse.
For example, in the documentation of modern field research, ‘community’ is a key identifier for research into ‘impact assessment’. The destination of such ‘impacts’, whether they are of electronic media, urban
developments or just about any governmental policy it is possible to
name, is invariably ‘community’. And yet, oddly, few of these documents
feel compelled to define ‘community’ at all. At best, they tend to defer to
‘community’ as a legitimating narrative which is safe to deploy precisely
because of its ambiguity.
In the nineteenth century, the principal theorists of community were
Tönnies and Émile Durkheim. Durkheim’s concept of the conscience collective can be added to Tönnies’ distinction between community and association, as foundational theories which have been little explored in terms
of their relevance today. At the same time, new conceptions of community
have co-emerged in relation to globalization and telecommunication
which either reinforce mythological conceptions of community, by arguing that such a fiction is being ‘lost’, or advance new bases of human association that did not exist previously.
In this chapter, the relevance of the old and the new accounts of
community to studying media and communications will be thoroughly
examined. In particular, we will be looking at whether broadcast and networked mediums of communication can, in themselves, provide contexts
for community as defined by these accounts. The different characteristics
of these types of community will be outlined and their interrelationship
will also be explored. But first, we will examine classical theories of community as well as some recent claims about the resurgence of community.
168
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Classical theories of community
Until recently, conventional usages of the term ‘community’ in the human
sciences had tended to render it as a formalization or deviation from what
Émile Durkheim described as the conscience collective, which he defines
as ‘the set of beliefs and sentiments common to the average members of a
single society [which] forms a determinate system that has its own life’
(cited in Lukes, 1973: 4). This ‘life of its own’ is one which earns it the
status of a ‘social fact’, having an effectivity and role to play in social integration. Conscience collectives are typically based on organized core values
such as those exhibited by a religion. In such a case, a social group, or
even entire societal forms, can be enveloped by a system of belief which
becomes an overarching organizing mechanism of association.
Such an overwhelming centralized means of association, which
Durkheim associated with traditional or ‘mechanical’ societies, was becoming attenuated by the advance of modern societies. Religion itself comes
into crisis as the institution of the church becomes just one of a plurality
of institutional sub-systems.
The move to what Durkheim called ‘organic soldarity’ is also marked
by an increasing division of labour that becomes the organizing agent for
social integration. The individualism inherent in specializing in a job
becomes a basis for differentiation, which is itself elevated to a belief and
a basis for a new kind of solidarity. Thus, for Durkheim, there is less stress
on the conscience collective as being based on ideas, and more on the recognition of the importance of institutions, from family, to education, to workplace, and, at the same time, a recognition of the necessity of the division
of labour.
A much neglected aspect of Durkheim’s account of the conscience
collective is his emphasis on the importance of material social facts: the
institutions of society, population density, but also ‘the number and
nature of channels of communication’. The material, structural features of
a society radically shape the forms of association which they can facilitate
(Durkheim, 1982: 58).
As populations increase, and the urban architecture which they cohabit becomes more and more private, the so-called ‘dynamic density’ of
society begins to change. In such conditions, the means of communication
and transportation become vital to maintaining anything like the kind of
community found in pre-industrial, pre-media kinds of societies. The forms
associated with this kind of society – what Tönnies called Gemeinschaft –
have, in media societies, all but hollowed out. Besides Gemeinschaften of religion, Tönnies lists Gemeinschaften of language, and of place, as the most
important basis for such forms of solidarity (Tönnies, 1955). In the modern
era of globalization, these forms are rapidly breaking down.
Gemeinschaft is a form of ‘unity in plurality’, it is close-knit: ‘the intimate, private, exclusive living together – like a family’. This, Tönnies contrasts with Gesellschaft, which is a form of plurality in unity. Gesellschaft is
Telecommunity
169
public life – it is the world itself. ‘One goes into Gesellschaft (society) as one
goes into a strange country’ (38).
In contrast to Gemeinschaft, Gesellschaft (society) is transitory and
superficial. Whilst Gemeinschaft, should be understood as a living organism, Gesellschaft (society) [is] a mechanical aggregate and artifact’ (39).
Gesellschaft (association) is always by way of contractual arrangement, or
cooperation towards a specific aim. Gesellschaft is well suited to
Durkheim’s principle of individualism. ‘In Gesellschaft every person
strives for that which is to his own advantage and affirms the actions of
others only in so far as and as long as they can further his interest’ (88).
For Durkheim, the onset of what Tönnies calls Gesellschaft created a
weak overall sense of a conscience collective for any given society as a
whole, and for him, the division of labour was not a sufficient unifying
force to overcome the loss of an ideational bond. Instead, the conscience
collective contracts to institutions, in which solidaristic attachments can
become feverishly strong. It is as though, as compensation for the absence
of any kind of overall integration into society, that ‘strange country’ which
has now become the world itself, individuals seek refuge in the private
and closed environments of institution and family. This ‘miniaturization’
of community can also realize itself in the workplace, subcultures and, as
we shall see, television and the Internet (Fukuyama, 1999).
The change from traditional to modern societies is therefore a transformation in the architecture of community. In Durkheimian terms it does
not mean that individuals in modern societies are more weakly integrated
than they were in traditional societies; it is just that such integration is
concentrated into sub-systems of the social order.
It is, however, true to say that in modern societies individuals do not
look to the ‘social whole’ for a sense of integration, and generally feel a
sense of anomie in relation to such an entity. But such a general condition
of anomie is not a prescription for a romantic return to close-kit community, which communitarian movements espouse, a movement which was
at its most salient in the nineteenth century, precisely when the bourgeois
and industrial revolutions of Europe were experienced most bluntly and
starkly.
Rather, unlike Tönnies, Durkheim saw the kind of solidarity exhibited by traditional societies as having its own particular problems, to do
with over-integration and over-regulation. The close-knit community
might well be intimate and highly connected, but it can also be suffocating, oppressive and imprisoning.
These problems of over-integration have today been transferred to
those institutions which have miniaturized community – the workplace
and the family being obvious ones. To take the workplace, the rise of workaholism, and the phenomenon of people living to work, rather than the
other way around, can create enormous pressures, leading to permanent
stress, depression, even suicide. Similarly, the modern nuclear family is
experienced by many teenagers as too suffocating. They look to ways of
170
COMMUNICATION THEORY
escape, and when they do escape, they typically take all kinds of risks, as
a means of rebellion and compensation for a life course of over-regulation.
Paradoxically, the over-regulation that is found in institutionalized forms
of community stands in an inverse relationship to the very weak kinds of
tie that are found outside these protected bubbles of community. Whilst
they may become suffocating, the cost of leaving them may be to accept a
condition where contract and law must perpetually rule over mistrust
and individual interest.
The contrast between the micro-community and the outside world
grows ever more pronounced in modern/postmodern societies, to the
point at which integration into the larger contexts of what Cooley called
secondary relationships as well as tertiary, indirect mediated relationships
becomes difficult for many people.
Another major aspect of this contrast is around the question of belief.
As community miniaturizes, the number of settings in which individuals
are enveloped by different belief systems also multiplies. Thus the discourses within the family will be different from those in the school yard
and different again in the workplace. In most cases, these differences
come into conflict with one another, and for an individual to cope with
this fact s/he will invariably adopt different and contradictory subject
positions. The fact that the theory of the subject emerged at the zenith of
the period of modernity needs to be related to this question of the pluralization of settings of integration.
Such pluralization need not be seen as a dilution of community from
the point of view of a given individual. Bell and Newby (1976) argue that
community is only possible when the connection between individuals
can be characterized as multi-stranded. These strands could be based in
repetition of meeting in the street, kinship, membership of a group. Like
Tönnies, Bell and Newby distinguish between three different forms of
community: there are geographically based communities of propinquity,
which do not necessarily require a strong conscience collective; there are
communities of a localized social sub-system, such as in institutions; and,
lastly, there is the populist sense of community as belonging and goodwill, which is described as communion. Communion need not depend only
on parochial assembly and may well occur at a distance.
But for Bell and Newby, neither an extended nor a local sense of community is necessarily sufficient on its own. What is lacking in a technologically extended communication event might be supplemented by
embodied travel. Conversely, the more that people travel in an embodied
manner, the more they might feel the calling to ‘stay connected’ via electronic or other means to the places that have been visited. But, for the most
part, in environments of virtual electronic community, we are permanently
exposed to a propinquity with strangers: on the screens we immerse ourselves in; in gazing from our car at high speed; or in halls of large volumes
of flânerie – the airport, the shopping mall, the tourist bubble. In the midst of
such a maelstrom and proximity of strangers beating out familiar pathways
Telecommunity
171
of movement, to ‘travel’ weightlessly, whether corporeally or in the
imagination, is to establish networks of communication in which communities have their life.
The ‘end of the social’ and the new discourse of community
The rise of the ‘network society’, together with the contentions that social
ties and practices are of a much more capillary nature in modern society,
and that anything like a ‘social whole’ can be effective in the integration
of persons, has informed recent proclamations concerning the ‘end of the
social’.
In a 1996 article on ‘The Death of the Social’, Nikolas Rose argues
that, with the assistance of postmodern theory, ‘the object “society”, in the
sense that began to be accorded to it in the nineteenth century (the sum of
the bonds of relations between individuals and events – economic, moral,
political – within a more or less bounded territory governed by its own
laws) has begun to lose its self-evidence’ (Rose, 1996: 328). For Rose, ‘“The
social” ... within a limited geographical and temporal field, set the terms
for the way in which human intellectual, political and moral authorities,
in certain places and contexts, thought about and acted on their collective
experience’ (329) – which is, for Rose – the nation-state.1
Similarly, Alain Touraine (1998), in a account of the ‘end of Homo
Sociologicus’, proclaims:
We have learned to do without the idea of society as it was defined by rationalist thought from the 16th to the 18th century, and as it was renovated
and reinforced by the theorists of modernity, of industrial society, of the welfare state and also of national development policies. We have come to
the end of the road to which the founding fathers of sociology led the way
a century ago. (127)
For Touraine, society is neither a ‘state of nature’ nor a progressive
framework of human development; rather, it has become a technology of
managing populations which has recently exhausted itself. Since the
1970s, in texts like The Self-Producing Society, The Voice and the Eye and The
Return of the Actor, Touraine has promoted the idea of a ‘programmed
society’, namely that advanced industrial societies have developed ‘the
capacity to choose their organization, their values, and their processes
of change without having to legitimate these choices by making them
conform to natural or historical laws’ (Touraine, 1988: 40).
The problem with such a society is that it produces a setting in which
norms are rapidly changing because they are constantly being redefined,
generating a crisis for how individuals are integrated. Individuals whose
roles were once highly defined, what Touraine calls ‘actors’, must increasingly become more self-forming and self-active, without the programmed
172
COMMUNICATION THEORY
and governmental contexts which might give either ‘instrumental’ or
‘value-rational’ kinds of action any kind of solid meaning. Without roles
to protect them, individuals are much more vulnerable when they go out
into society (Gesellschaft), as the links between actor and system become
diluted.
Like Touraine, Rose (1996) contends that ‘“[t]he Social” ... no longer
represents an external existential sphere of human sociality’ (329). Rather,
within the modern nation-state, ‘the social’, as a project, is said to be
replaced by what he calls a ‘government of individuation’, a form of subjection and control in which individuals are encouraged to be responsible
for themselves and police their own behaviour and that of others.
For Rose, the development of social ontologies in the present age has
been enveloped by discourses, ways of speaking and thinking which
manage the experience of social reality. This is sometimes called, following Michel Foucault, ‘governmentality’. The social only has a unity insofar as it is ‘in the name of the social’ that various political pressures are said
to be exerted on populations for the purposes of national governance.
Many of these tendencies have become necessary, according to Rose, precisely because of the erosion of traditional state power by globalization,
requiring a ‘new spatialization of government’ to manage politics and
economics. This has brought about new kinds of discourses of control, in
which abstract economic processes are mischievously spoken about in
terms of communities of interest.
Such a language reterritorializes populations as groups of specialized
markets within economic relations that ‘do not respect national political
boundaries’ (Rose, 1996: 330). Rose asks: by what terminology are economic relations now understood, and how is economic governance posed,
in the era of globalization? ‘Consider the prominence of the language of
community’ (331).
Rose (1996) contends that the language of community has become a
burgeoning terminology of political life and that it has replaced ‘the
social’ as the centre of governmentality (see also Touraine, 1998). The
most notable of these is the globalization of community, in which nationally constituted ‘imagined communities’ co-exist in narrative form. At the
same time, nationalism itself is attenuated as the number of narrative
identifications with community proliferates ad nauseum: terms as wideranging as, for example, ‘the business community’, ‘the sporting community’, ‘gambling communities’ – in fact the kind and range of divisions are
almost limitless. The very discursive prominence of community is posited
as proof enough of the reterritorialization of older (mostly geographic
and ethnic) frames of belonging based on what Rose (1996) calls ‘other
spatializations: blood and territory; race and religion; town, region and
nation’ (329).
In the same way as populations are coming to be discursively divided
into smaller and smaller distinct communities, they are also, in the opposite direction, ‘called up’ to communion with quite abstract kinds of
Telecommunity
173
global communities – virtual communities, the Olympic community, the
‘international community’.2
Globalization and social context
For Rose, ‘society’ and community are viewed as discursive constructs
that have changed roles. ‘The formation of the notion of a national economy was a key condition for the separation out of a distinct social
domain’ (Rose, 1996: 337). Whereas, for Rose (1996), ‘the social’ once acted
as a discursive agent for the integration of persons on the basis of ‘social
protection, social justice, social rights and social solidarity’ (329), for
Touraine (1998), the decline of national communities derives from
the ‘decomposition ... of society’ by way of the ‘growing autonomy of the
economic sphere from institutional controls’ which ‘exist in general at the
national level’ (129). Touraine acknowledges, contra the extreme globalists, that the events that are said to have produced globalization – ‘the
increase in international trade; the more rapid intensification of financial
flows; the rise of new industrial countries; the birth of the information
society ... the end of the Cold War and the fall of the Soviet empire’ – are
not systemically linked, but rather are phenomena ‘largely independent
of one another, and are of different natures’ (129–30).
Nevertheless, taken together, these discrete events are said to have
social and political consequences, the first being the ‘breakdown of social
and political constraints on economic activity’, producing ‘the most radical rupture ever observed between actor and system’, whilst the second is
the weakening of the nation-state (130–1). For Touraine, the most significant change is in the decomposition of the institutionalization of norms in
the social world: ‘the main fact is that we no longer recognize the presence
of norms in many realms of life’ (131). Instead, as larger and larger spheres
of behaviour are no longer said to be subject to nation-state/society-framed
norms, ‘[t]he system is no longer a social one, but becomes a global market,
self-regulated by law firms, rating agencies and international financial
institutions and the financial markets themselves ... the social actor disappears, and the remaining actors are no longer social’ (130).
In the contemporary context, therefore, Touraine poses the main task
for sociology today as having to discover ‘a new principle, capable of
replacing the idea of society and more specifically of national society,
which for so long played this role of mediation and integration’ (133).
This leaves him with the question: ‘how can we be actors and create space
for autonomy between the globalized economy and communal cultures,
neither one of which leaves room for the actor?’ (135).
Touraine’s own answer to this question is that ‘there are no longer
transcendent universal values that might unite all of humanity’ (136), as
in the case of the grand narratives of modernity; rather, capitalism, in its
174
COMMUNICATION THEORY
contemporary form, promotes individuation and difference, and it is this
right to individuation and difference which is left over as the last viable
universal value that is able to provide a normativity in contemporary life.
Promoting Foucault’s return to the question of the subject in his later
work, Touraine turns attention away from a sociology of system and actor
to that of the subject: ‘The recognition of each person’s right and capacity
to become a subject is a universalistic value; as is the right to combine a
commonly shared scientific or technological rationality and a particular
cultural identity’ (136).
Touraine’s turn to a social theory of the subject through individuation,
which he claims is necessitated by the global market’s decomposition of
social norms, shares much ground with the work of Jean-Luc Nancy in
The Inoperative Community (1991) and Georgio Agamben in The Coming
Community (1993). In these texts a philosophical rethinking of community
is attempted in ways which are more suited to the fragmentations of
modernity that are evident today. According to Agamben and Nancy, we
can no longer speak of a transcendent principle or context of community
other than the fact that subjects must be self-active in attributing any kind
of global significance to their experience. To impose and presuppose community in the name of the transcendent is to disregard it since, as Nancy
(1991: xxxviii) puts it, community cannot be presupposed and the thinking of community as essence is the closing off of the political. Community
is realized in the very retreat from an organizing principle, the refusal of
a universalizing essence.
Like Nancy and Agamben, Touraine (1998) does not appeal to a universalist discourse: ‘while dominated groups used to refer to a metasocial principle – God, reason, history or the nation – in order to challenge
the dominant group’s power, today the defence of the subject invokes no
higher principle and does not seek to obtain power’ (138). Instead, for
Touraine, the subject only struggles against the (now global) economic
forces which are constantly threatening a reduction of being ‘to a series of
life experiences, resembling the television programmes one sees when
one zaps from channel to channel’ (136), while ‘community’ no longer has
internal conditions but is formed and acts through strategies akin to
Rose’s account of governmentality.
The rise of global communities of practice
The governmentality perspective, which proposes that discursive strategies become increasingly important for the maintenance of nation-state
forms of society, identifies globalization as the basis of the breakdown
between system and actor. Globalization is seen to erode the middle-level
agencies of social integration which were once provided by technocratic
society.3
Telecommunity
175
In the wake of such erosion, community, on the one hand, retreats to
micro-communities, and, on the other hand, reaches out to more and
more global forms of cosmopolitan integration. Such a re-spatialization of
community makes it very difficult for Tönnies’ Gemeinschaft or even the
imagined community of the nation-state (Anderson, 1983) to persist.4
In a review of the different definitions of community that have
appeared over the last fifty years, Ken Dempsey (1998) points to two characteristics which keep returning: first, having the social ties in common
that produce a high degree of social solidarity (a structural characteristic);
and, second, the experience of belonging together. As Dempsey points
out, problems begin when we insist that both characteristics have to be
present in order for community to exist:
… it is possible for the objective (or structural) characteristics of community
to be present and the subjective characteristics to be absent. People may
be linked by social ties of interdependence and yet have no sense of
belonging together. It is also possible for the opposite to be true: for people
who do not know one another, to have a sense of belonging together. (141)
The fact that the objective and subjective components of community
are rarely in alignment, in a globalized world in which the relationship
between language, religion and place is becoming increasingly arbitrary
and cosmopolitan, suggests that other bases for community can come to
the fore. From a Durkheimian point of view, all individuals need to be
socially integrated in some way or another. How this occurs may vary
enormously between individuals and according to the place in which they
live, including the new ‘places’ that are able to come into existence, such
as cyberspace.
However, it is increasingly clear in media societies that tradition and
belief, or a conscience collective, are no longer an organizing basis for community. Through mediums and rituals, it has become quite orthodox for
people who do not know one another to have a sense of belonging
together in a mediated ceremony. In addition, the advent of cyberspace
introduces the prospect that communities of place are not just geographical, and it also facilitates the possibility of meeting nearly everyone who
has the same interest as you and is also connected to the Internet, wherever they are located.
However, the content of beliefs and interests is only one component
of Durkheim’s original description of the conscience collective. He also
specified intensity – the intimacy of interactions, volume, the number of
people enveloped by the interactions – and rigidity – the regularity and
adherence of these interactions. This also means that social integration is
very much based on the practice of interaction, not just on what it signifies. When we routinize our interaction with others and with the mediums
through which we conduct such interactions, we create a world around us
which becomes very familiar to us, regardless of what the content of our
176
COMMUNICATION THEORY
interactions is. Rituals are concerned more with this routinization than
they are with trying to identify with the same ideas or aesthetic effect.
We can draw from Durkheim the observation that community is as
much about practice as it is about belief, a distinction also recently made
by Nancy Baym (2000) in her innovative analysis of the difference
between ‘audience community and network community’.
Audience communities and online communities co-opt mass media for interpersonal uses. Grappling with the social nature of these new types of community requires understanding them not just as online communities (organized
through a network) or as audience communities (organized around a text)
but also as communities of practice organized, like all communities, through
habitualized ways of acting. (4)
Whilst audience communities might be organized around image, music
and text, both on-line communities and audience involve regularized
forms of practice.
Drawing on formulations from Hanks (1996) and Lave and Wenger
(1991), the communities-as-practice approach provides an instructive
means of steering our way through the complex differences between
broadcast and network forms of community, and without the sentimentalism so often ascribed to the term.
At the center of the practice approach is the assumption that a community’s structures are instantiated and recreated in habitual and recurrent
ways of acting or practices. When people engage in the ordinary activities
that constitute their daily lives, they are participating ‘in an activity system
about which participants share understandings concerning what they’re
doing and what that means in their lives and for their communities’ (Lave
and Wenger, 1991, p. 98). In short, if one wants to understand a community, then one should look to the ordinary activities of its participants. This
is a fairly minimalist definition of community, without the warm and fuzzy
connotations that many link to the term, but it is a definition that provides
a workable core. Without shared engagement in a project, there can be no
warmth and fuzziness. (Baym, 2000: 22)
Of the different indices of community, place, religion, language and
ethnicity can be associated with communities of belief, whereas it is space
and place which stand out as a site of practice.
As communities of belief become disassociated from particular
places, owing to global movements of culture, modern communication
becomes all the more important in order to sustain them, as they regularly
occur over ever-greater distances.
However, at the same time, such means of communication make possible new kinds of spaces that are available to be practised. In this connection, the implications of Michel de Certeau’s formulation that ‘space is
a practiced place’ (de Certeau, 1988: 117) are far-reaching in their
Telecommunity
177
consequences. In practising places, it makes no difference whether they are
global or local senses of place, corporeal or electronic spaces. Indeed
‘cyberspace’ is a place that we can become just as attached to by way of our
routines of navigation as we can by the repetition of meeting people when
we go into the street.
As I have argued in Virtual Globalization (Holmes, 2001), de Certeau’s
formulation is a very useful one for thinking across physical and virtual
spaces. In The Practice of Everyday Life (1988), de Certeau explores how we
can relate to our physical environment by practising routines of traversal
in our daily existence and observation which can equally be applied to
how individuals navigate media spaces.5 Any medium which can extend
experience necessarily brings together local and global kinds of settings,
to the extent that it is globally accessible or extant. Indeed, as local worlds
become subject to accelerating flows of messages, bodies, styles and
commodities which course through them, attachment to electronic global
spaces can become more attractive, to the extent that they offer a stable
uniformity that can no longer be found on a local basis.6
Sociality with mediums/sociality with objects
The centrality of ‘communities of practice’ for understanding the interrelation between local and global community also requires a differentiation between the corporeal and virtual means of engaging with such
spaces. When we turn to the question of media spaces, there are two
dimensions of interaction involved in all media: interaction with mediums; and sociality with the media technologies which give us gateways to
such mediums.
As we saw in the previous chapter, interacting with mediums is
explored by ritual perspectives of communication, whereas intersubjective communication is explored by transmission accounts.
The argument that, in information societies, individuals increasingly
interact with a medium rather than with other interlocutors is one which
is well supported not only by ritual communication views but also by
neo-McLuhanist and abstraction views. Moreover, the fact of interacting
with mediums is apparent whether we are discussing broadcast or network
integration.
Whether we choose to single out television or the Internet, interacting with mediums tends to have two consequences: ritual forms of attachment to an electronic assembly are usually accompanied by a parallel
tendency to fetishize the personalization of media technologies. In the
case of mediums, it is not that they ‘mediate’ our relationship to others;
rather, it is the medium itself which is worshipped. In the case of the personal media technologies, the relationship to objects with which communication is enabled can become more intense than to other persons.
178
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Sociality with media
As identified in the previous chapter, medium theory has a habit of
differentiating social forms according to regimes of communication.
Further, it tends to inflate the technical importance of mediums to the point
where a given era is defined by the technology itself. In this it does not
consider the question of social dependence on mediums, and the question
of social determination, which structures the way in which some mediums become dominant over others. Moreover, medium theory tends to
argue that one rather than another medium is dominant because more
people are physically interacting with it. Integration theory, on the other
hand, argues that in any given communicative situation there is always a
co-presence of levels of mediatized integration involved – face-to-face,
agency-extended, etc. – but that one of these levels can come to recast how
all other levels are experienced. Thus, for example, in modern society it is
possible for those immersed in technologically extended communication
cultures to engage in face-to-face relationships in a disembodied register.
This is not to point to the fact that the modern ‘computer nerd’ engages
little in the way of eye contact. It is rather that such subjects necessarily
adopt CMC as a frame of reference, even when they are not engaged in
such communication. Conversely, persons formed in cultural settings
where the face-to-face relationship is dominant will tend to attribute
everything with a face-to-face character, even when they are not actually
engaged in mutual presence.
The integration approach to media is distinguishable from interaction approaches which confine themselves to intersubjectivity. As we saw
in the previous chapter, integration occurs not by interacting with others,
but by interacting at the level of an indirect social relationship (Calhoun,
1992), one that is extended by another agent, be it another person or a
communication technology.
Moreover, following Meyrowitz, communication mediums possess the
quality that they can extend experience in ways that exceed the kinds of
behaviour found in local environments: media are not merely ‘channels for
conveying information between two or more environments, but rather
shapers of new environments themselves’ (Meyrowitz, 1994: 51). In a more
recent account, ‘The Shifting Worlds of Strangers’, Meyrowitz (1997) argues
that such re-territorialization changes the relationship between ‘them’ and
‘us’. The balance between oral, print and electronic environments profoundly changes the relationship between strangers and ‘familiars’.
In regarding media as environments of sociability, traditional charges
of ‘technological determinism’ are no longer pertinent in the way they
were in the earlier years of media studies. One of the most cogent and persistent accounts of technological determinism is that of Raymond
Williams in his Towards 2000 (1983) and Television: Technology and Cultural
Form (1974). In these texts Williams is very critical of the way in which one
Telecommunity
179
particular technology could be said to carry a spirit or Geist which defines
an age. Secondly, he rightly points out that few analyses relate the causes
of the development of individual technologies to a range of locatable
political and economic interests, rather than simply technical progress.
For him, technological determinism is an outcome of some or other
‘expressive totality’ view of technology as inevitable, and he wants to
restore a sense of agency and policy to media technology.
However, Williams does not address the fact that when media
become apparatus and networks which people live with and work with
in an everyday sense, they have meta-psychological and social dynamics
which are quite independent from how they have emerged. Of course the
tendency to place the meaning of these networks and apparatuses within
some kind of expressive Geist theory is a simplifying temptation – a
simplification which Williams is justifiably annoyed with.
The kind of sociality which emerges in media environments is typically ‘embedded’ in networks or groupings of techno-social mobility.
These networks, which always involve actions that are embedded within
technical means of communication or transportation, become meaningfulin-themselves, not as means to extend face-to-face relationships.
John Urry (2002) argues that in most contemporary literature on mobility an appreciation of the embeddedness of forms of sociality in a network/medium is precluded by the pervasive dichotomies within which
technologically extended mobility is thought. The dichotomies of ‘[r]eal/
unreal, face-to-face/life on the screen, immobile/mobile, community/virtual
and presence/absence’ (7) are each premised on the former term providing
some pre-virtual knowable other which is in some way threatened or transformed by new forms of mobile ‘at-a-distance’ connections.
Normally, this knowable other is characterised as ‘real’, as opposed to the
airy, fragile, and virtual relationships of the electronic. And the real is normally
taken to involve the concept of ‘community’. Real life is seen to comprise
enduring, face-to-face, communitarian connection, while the virtual world is
made up of fragile, mobile, airy and inchoate connections. (2002: 1)
In opposition to such a limit-paradigm, Urry argues that all societies
have exhibited and continue to exhibit diverse ‘at-a-distance’ connections,
‘more or less intense, more or less mobile, and more or less machinic. ...
All social relationships involve complex patterns of immediate presence
and intermittent absence at-a-distance’ (1).
By arguing that extended forms of connection are just as ‘real’ as
propinquitous ones, or that, in a sense, all forms of community are
‘telecommunities’, and vice versa, we avoid one-dimensional, utopian or
dystopian accounts of community.
That persons may become attached and embedded in techno-social
networks across vast dimensions of metropolises and the globe does not
mean that such networks have abolished less technologically mediated
180
COMMUNICATION THEORY
networks; indeed, they are typically mutually constitutive. Where technical
embeddedness becomes more and more normative, other forms of connection like the face-to-face often become revalued. And with this form of
connection, direct interaction with another person can become substituted
by interaction with media objects.
Sociality with objects
Dependence on techno-social networks may exhibit different kinds of
intensity depending on what other kinds of connections and circulations
co-exist with them. The more embedded are technologies in such networks, the more it is possible to engage with these technologies as ends in
themselves. To the extent that such embeddedness creates a techno-social
way of life, ‘transport’ models of understanding communicative events
become redundant, as is the social type said to be at the centre of this
model‚ the media technology ‘user’. User perspectives (see, e.g.,
Silverstone, 1991; Silverstone et al., 1991, 1992) are typically interested in
which technologies are taken up by particular individuals and the purposes for which they are used, but do not examine the interaction between
individuals and objects, nor how such interaction can actually alter the
identity of the person interacting. What the user perspective also ignores
is that objects of interaction are means of maintaining the connection to
mediums/networks.7
The television, the Walkman, the mobile phone, the motor car, the
keyboard – people become very attached to these commodities, and begin
to relate to objects rather than to other people. The greatest fetishism of
commodities is of these means of connection. Relations to other persons
become refracted through these objects, or they may become confused
with our own narcissistic relationship to the technology itself.
In a longitudinal study (1991–6) of over 400 TV audience diarists in
the UK, Gauntlett and Hill (1999) document the companionship which the
TV set provided for viewers of all age demographics. ‘When respondents
wrote about what television meant to them, they often listed the information and entertainment aspects of television, but mentioned as well the
company and even “friendship” that it offers’ (115). Two kinds of attachment were reported: the TV set itself as ‘friend’ or a member of the
family; and TV as bringing ‘friends’ from outside the home (115–19).
Many of the diarists who reported strong emotional affections toward
their set lived alone. But equally, many reported some degree of guilt
about issues such as daytime TV viewing being a waste of time, or being
selfish in watching a programme which the viewer knew that few family
members, friends or visitors would be interested in.
Arguably, the more personalized a communication technology,
the greater the human–technical interface. McLuhan, in a chapter in
Understanding Media (1994) entitled ‘The Gadget Lover’, argues that in
Telecommunity
181
media societies, individuals everywhere encounter themselves in a world
which becomes closed and virtualized, which, as the story of Narcissus
tells us, requires a fascination with media which extend this closed bubble
in which others become resolved into our own image.
The youth Narcissus [from the Greek word narcosis or numbing] mistook his
own reflection in the water for another person. This extension of himself by
mirror numbed his perceptions until he became the servomechanism of his
own extended or repeated image. The nymph Echo tried to win his love with
fragments of his own speech, but in vain. He was numb. He had adapted
to his extension of himself and had become a closed system.
Now the point of this myth is the fact that men at once become fascinated by any extension of themselves in any material other than themselves. (1994: 51)
Medium theory argues that once technologies are integrated into a
‘way of life’, it may be difficult to be without them. Indeed, an individual’s intolerance at having a connection broken gives a precise measure of
how attached he or she is to that medium. It also changes our very conception of what a medium is. McLuhan, for example, claimed that electric
light and the motor car are both mediums. It is certainly true that if either
stopped working in our immediate environment most of us would seek to
rectify this problem very quickly to the extent that we are very dependent
on them. In the case of transport, the centrality of travel in sustaining
community networks is never more visible than when it breaks down, be
this a public or private instance. Typically, a train strike or a flat battery is
thought of purely in terms of inconvenience. However, the propensity for
individuals to treat such events as moral crises suggests that they are significant in ways much more to do with community.
In circumstances where our everyday actions become embedded in
technological networks, technology itself becomes transparent. The
philosopher Martin Heidegger pointed this out in his analysis of the way
in which technology destines the world to be revealed as a reserve of
utility (see Heidegger, 1997). When technology as ‘equipment’ is routinely
used to achieve given ends, the power that it holds can become taken for
granted as the technology itself becomes invisible. As Knorr-Cetina (1997)
explains of Heidegger: ‘Equipment becomes problematic only when it is
unavailable, when it malfunctions or when it temporarily breaks down.
Only then do we go from “absorbed coping” to “envisaging”, “deliberate
coping” and to the scientific stance of theoretical reflection of the properties
of entities’ (10).
The implications of Heidegger’s insight into the conditions of the
visiblity/invisibility of technology in everyday life are integrated by
Knorr-Cetina into an extremely novel account of the social bonds which
individuals form with technological objects.
Given that individuals must develop a certain ‘technical intelligence’
in order to cope with technological change, with switching between the
182
COMMUNICATION THEORY
use of different technologies, or to overcome the malfunction or dysfunction
of technology, Heidegger argues that technological society presupposes a
more ‘theoretical attitude’ oriented towards objects of knowledge, rather
than ‘practical reason’, which is concerned only with instruments. Thus,
what was once the specialization of science and experts becomes an ‘attitude’
throughout the population.
Such a change prompts Knorr-Cetina to examine the relation that
scientists and experts have to objects in developing an extended account
of what she calls ‘objectualization’. Objectualization describes the way
that ‘objects displace human beings as relationship partners and embedding environments, or that they increasingly mediate human relationships,
making the latter dependent on the other former’ (1).
For Knorr-Cetina, there are two principal driving forces of objectualization: ‘The first is the spread of expert contexts and knowledge cultures
throughout society that discharge these cultures into society as a possible
driving force behind the rise of an object-centred sociality’ (23). The second
are the ‘relationship risks’ that many find inherent in contemporary human
relationships.
Where human relationships fail, individuals turn to objectual relationships as compensation. Knorr-Cetina describes this as a post-social
development, where ‘social’ is reserved for forms of societies based upon
solidarity in the Durkheimian sense (18), the unity of something shared, the
unity of a moral field or a unity of meaning.
Like Touraine and Rose, Knorr-Cetina argues that information societies are undergoing a post-social transition. But post-social transitions
imply that social forms as we knew them have become flattened, narrowed and thinned out; they imply that the social is retracting. KnorrCetina points out that this is usually explained in Durkheimian terms as
a further boost to individualization and the loss of a common culture (6).
. . . as common values are no longer at the award growth of shared
traditions and cannot just be imposed by some authority, integration via
norms and values appears to be less and less effective. In fact, this sort
of integration is imaginable today only as a socio-culturally engineered
consensus. (24)
But the shift away from such value consensus and the rise of individualization need not be read as the ‘death of the social’: ‘postsocial relations are not a-social or non-social’ (7). Rather, Knorr-Cetina argues that it is
an error to characterize individualization in terms of ‘human relationships’ in the present period. If we take into account the ways in which
human beings tie themselves to object-worlds, then the ordinary concept
of individualization is problematized. In that case, ‘objects may simply be
the race winners of human relationship risks and failures, and of the
larger postsocial developments’ (23) In other words, for Knorr-Cetina,
‘Individualization intertwines with objectualization – with an increasing of
Telecommunity
183
our orientation toward objects as sources of the self, of relational intimacy,
of shared subjectivity and of social integration’ (9).
However, for Knorr-Cetina, the relationship of individuals to technology isn’t just a matter of ritual, although this is strong, but of turning
everyday objects like commodities and instruments into knowledge
objects in ways that become meaningful as such. Where the propensity of
a particular individual to do this (which may vary according to gender
and age) is either resisted or too intense, it attracts a label – technophobia
or addiction (see Brosnan, 1998).
In Knorr-Cetina’s work, where the notion of solidarity is brought into
the scenario of an object-centred sociality, it also needs to be epistemically
grounded and not only ritually derived (19). In other words, having an
epistemic intimacy with the object is important, not just the routine ritual
of ‘using’ it as a means to some end. And indeed, in post-social societies,
Knorr-Cetina claims that such an intimacy is beginning to eclipse intimacy
with other human beings.
Consider the following statement from William Mitchell (1996) about
his personal use of the Internet:
The keyboard is my café. Each morning I turn to some nearby machine – my
modest personal computer at home, a more powerful workstation in one of
the offices or laboratories that I frequent, or a laptop in a hotel room – to
log into electronic mail. I click on an icon to open an ‘inbox’ filled with
messages from round the world – replies to technical questions, queries for
me to answer, drafts of papers, submissions of student work, appointments, travel and meeting arrangements, bits of business, greetings,
reminders, chitchat, gossip, complaints, tips, jokes, flirtation. I type replies
immediately, then drop them into an ‘outbox,’ from which they are forwarded automatically to the appropriate destinations. If I have time before
I finish gulping my coffee, I also check the wire services and a couple of
specialized news services to which I subscribe, then glance at the latest
weather report. This ritual is repeated whenever I have a spare moment
during the day. (7)
What emerges here is that, whilst the meetings, the travel, the ‘content’,
the business of institutional life vary from day to day, the technological
ritual of clicking on is constant, enduring and cathartic.
Digital intimacy
Theories of object-relations are not entirely new, and have had a longstanding tradition in psychoanalytic theory. But few have related such
theories to a transition from one kind of social form to another, or to the
significance of media as relationship partners. One such theorist, referred
to by Knorr-Cetina, is Sherry Turkle, who manages to combine both a
concern for social change and an attachment to digital technology.
184
COMMUNICATION THEORY
In The Second Self (1984) and Life on the Screen (1995) Turkle is centrally
concerned with the self–other relations in New Media environments. In her
earlier work, Turkle (1984) explores the way in which many computer users
relate to computers as though they have a mind and conversely view themselves as machines. For Turkle it is the very opacity of digital technologies,
the fact that, if you were to open one up you would not see tangible moving parts, gears, levers or wheels, but rather, simply, ‘wires and one black
chip’ (22), that encourages us to speak of them in psychological terms. The
computer is an evocative object with which we can develop an almost spiritual relationship (306): ‘For adults as well as children, computers, reactive
and interactive, offer companionship. They seduce because they provide a
chance to be in complete control, but they can trap people into an infatuation with control, with building one’s own private world’ (19).
For Turkle, making the computer into a second self, finding a soul in
the machine, can substitute for human relationships, a path dependence
which can come to be both cause and effect of a new kind of hysteria:
Terrified of being alone, yet afraid of intimacy, we experience widespread
feelings of emptiness, of disconnection, of the unreality of self. And here
the computer, a companion without emotional demands, offers a compromise. You can be a loner, but never alone. You can interact, but need never
feel vulnerable to another person. (307)
In her later work, Turkle (1995) turns away from the object-narcissism
of the PC to the decentred and multiple identities of the Internet. In cyberspatial worlds, rather than the virtual world of face-to-screen, it is possible to reveal ourselves in new ways. The Internet has achieved in practice
what psychoanalysts have long been trying to achieve in theory: the realization that the autonomous ego is a fiction (see Turkle, 1995: 15). With
much relief, Turkle revisits the insights of psychoanalysts whom she studied
many decades earlier, simply by ‘tinkering’ with the Net:
In my computer-mediated worlds, the self is multiple, fluid, and constituted
in interaction with machine connections, it is made and transformed by language; sexual congress is an exchange of signifiers; and an understanding
follows from navigation and tinkering rather than analysis. And in the
machine-generated world of MUDs I meet characters who put me in a new
relationship with my own identity. (15)
Media equations
From an entirely different direction, and without recourse to psychoanalytic theory, it is significant that media–object relationships are also being
researched by computer corporations. Microsoft commissioned one such
study, ‘Social Responses to Communication Technologies’, written by Reeves
Telecommunity
185
and Nass (1996). In their The Media Equation: How People Treat Computers,
Television, and New Media Like Real People and Places, they declare, triumphantly
but simplistically, that media equal real life (!): ‘We have found that individuals’
interactions with computers, television, and new media are fundamentally
social and natural, just like interactions in real life’ (5).
The simplistic import of their ‘equation’ is that ‘the social’ is defined
in the narrow, everyday sense of ‘politeness’. Nevertheless, their observations concerning interaction bear some attention despite the fact that they
lack contextualization in any recognizable social analysis. The social
responses study indicates that people are polite to well-designed computers, that screen motion draws similar responses to real motion, and
that, psychologically, object-relations to TV screens are not so different
from those to PC screens.
Mostly, these relationships are of a passive order; they ‘do not apply
to the rare occasions when people yell at a television or plead with a computer’ (253). Interactions between persons and media technology lead
individuals to ‘allocate attention, assess competence’ and organize information in ways which aren’t just about efficiency or entertainment (253).
Such research, which is also the subject of numerous studies on
mobile phone use in Katz and Aakhus’s collection Perpetual Contact
(2001), can sometimes lead to New Age kinds of spiritualism represented
in attempts to suggest a new kind of community technospirit which
emerges within a particular medium.
Katz and Aakhus, in their sixteen-page review of the essays in
Perpetual Contact, feel compelled to invent a new term for such a spirit
which emerges out of mobile phone use, which they call ‘Apparatgeist’
(2001). In advancing this term, the authors rapidly slide from a concern
with (as the essay title suggests) ‘The Meaning of Mobile Phones’ to universal claims about history, society and the human spirit! The tendency
for New Media theorists to coin neologisms to define a new epoch, as we
saw with the second media age thesis, or to make such grand universal
claims, a matter to which I will return, is interesting in itself. For Katz and
Aakhus, the term Apparatgeist achieves no less than to ‘tie together the
individual and collective aspects of societal behaviour’ (307). Having
defined Apparat as a term that can be found in numerous dictionaries and
then defined Geist as a handy word derived from Hegelian philosophy,
they see their new term as suitable for referring to ‘the common set of
strategies or principles of reasoning about technology evident in the identifiable, consistent and generalized patterns of technological advancement throughout history’ (307).
Apparatgeist is the ‘master concept which is informed by a ‘logic’ which
is called ‘perpetual contact’. In turn ‘perpetual contact is a socio-logic’ of
‘personal communication technology’ or PCT (307). From there, Katz
and Aakhus run through a series of random but no less grand theoretical
consequences of how ‘PCTs’ make up the Apparatgeist:
186
COMMUNICATION THEORY
• They have a Geist which can be likened to the expansion of freedom.
• They have their own logic that informs the judgements people make
about the utility or value of the technologies in their environment.
• They inform the predictions that scientists and technology producers
might make about personal technologies.
• They also have a socio-logic that results from ‘communities of people
“thinking and acting together over time”’ (307).
• In making possible Apparatgeist PCTs, ‘the compelling image of perpetual
contact is the image of pure communication . .. which is an idealization
of communication committed to the prospect of sharing one’s mind
with another, like the talk of angels that occurs without the contraints
of the body’ (307).
Moreover, perpetual contact has a univeral historical status, parallel
with the ‘the image of perpetual motion that has driven the machinery of
the past two millennia’ (307). ‘Whereas the idea of perpetual motion concerns the means of production, perpetual contact concerns the means to
communicate and interact socially, which is fundamental to humans’ (308).
Whilst Katz and Aakhus want to stress that their term does not
require technological determinism, because it is about constraint of possibilities (307), their account is technological determinism at its worst,
as well as tautological. The essay is subtitled ‘A Theory of Apparatgeist’, a
theory of something that is predicated on their own theory. Their inability to even imagine that any of the phenomena in the list above, even the
more credible amongst them, are attributable to any agents other than
PCTs and their Geist is worrying, but unfortunately typical of a growing
methodological essentialism around New Media impacts.
Post-social society and the generational divide
Youth instinctively understands the present environment – the electric
drama. It lives it mythically and in depth. This is the reason for the great
alienation between generations. Wars, revolutions, civil uprisings are
interfaces within the new environments created by electric informational
media. (McLuhan and Fiore, 1967: 9–10)
A key consequence of the transition to an information or knowledge society that has received a lot of attention is the widening of the differences
between generations accompanied by a contraction of the time in which
this gap appears. Moreover, New Media environments such as ‘cyberspace’ are said to have their own ‘time-worlds’ which operate at far greater
cycles than other forms of time.8 In shorter and shorter cycles, the way
in which persons are formed by media is quickly outdated. Computer
companies employ adolescent ‘geniuses’ who seemingly have a natural
Telecommunity
187
aptitude for computers, and form their own networks of association which
older generations cannot understand.
Some writers, such as Mark Dery, suggest that this is the basis of an
epochal change, the decisive process which justifies something approximating a second media age thesis. Increasingly, computer culture, or
cyberculture, seems as if it is on the verge of attaining escape velocity in
the philosophical as well as the technological sense’ (Dery, 1996: 3). For
those immersed in it, cyberculture ‘resounds with transcendentalist fantasies of breaking free from limits of any sort, metaphysical as well as
physical’ (p 8). This, it is argued, leads to a breakdown of cultural transmission and a separation of world-views.
It is certainly true that youth lead the way in their take-up and consumption of New Media, with older age groups perpetually catching up.
In Finland, for example, which has the highest density of mobile phone
use in the world – 64% at the beginning of 2000 – figures clearly suggest
that take-up of the technology has been highest among the two youngest
groups, and it steadily declines in proportion to age group. As at 2000,
personal ownership statistics are revealing for the following age groups
15–19 (77%), 20–9 (86%), 30–9 (77%), 40–9 (67%), 50–9 (59%) and over 60
(29%) (see Puro, 2001: 21).
In Finland and in Norway, which has the second highest mobile
phone density, teenagers stand out spectacularly as the highest usergroup of SMS (short messaging services, or ‘texting’). For teens, it is associated with extensive subcultures. As Skog (2001) has remarked of the
Norwegian experience, ‘SMS has spurred teens to create an anglicized
clique-based abbreviated language’ (262). According to Skog’s statistics,
75% of girls and 62% of boys regard SMS as an essential feature of their
phone (262).
The fact that a technologically mobile network of youth are able to
develop a highly specialized and defined communication culture that
excludes nearly all other age groups illustrates the potential rigidities of
the digital divide.
The ease with which armies of ‘cyberbrats’ are able to take up New
Media stands in stark contrast to the ‘technophobia’ with which older generations are often tinged. Technophobia is not an opposition to technologyin-general, but a fear of the technologically very new and of the pace in
which this newness colonizes the life world.
The youth-biased take-up of New Media does not, in itself, demonstrate resistance among older age groups. Rather, it is more likely that
younger people will find New Media intuitive because they do not have
to adapt from a prior regime of working with media apparatuses. When
young people learn computers, for example, their complexity rapidly
becomes transparent. In Heideggerian terms, children already have a
theoretical attitude in working with computers, for which practical reason
is naturalized. However, for those without this attitude, significant anxieties
may be aroused in using any kind of technology.
188
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Brosnan (1998), in his positivist psychology of technophobia, suggests
that ‘until technology becomes invisible, it will be found to create feelings
of anxiety within certain individuals’ (2). In the interests of novelty,
Brosnan tries to suggest that young people may suffer from technophobia
on account of greater expectation over their proficiency. However, this
argument is not supported by the studies. What is important, though, is
that older people who live alone tend not to be so ‘technophobic’, possibly
because they may welcome object-centred relationships as substitutes for
human relationship partners who have been lost. Studies in Germany of
older age group television audiences display a similar trend (see Grajczyk
and Zollner, 1996).
Despite several 1980s studies that otherwise show a clear correlation
between technophobia and age, Brosnan is reluctant to link the two,
except to say what is clear is that the earlier individuals have their first
experience with computers, the less anxiety they will experience with
them. His account interchanges ‘technology’ with ‘computers’ at the peril
of much confusion. ‘As the diffusion of technology throughout many
aspects of life has exposed virtually everyone to computerization, the
relationship between anxiety, age and experience has become less clear’
(21). The problem with this statement is that Brosnan amalgamates all
technologies into one experiential maelstrom, for which he takes PCs to
be a metonym. As we saw with mobile phones and SMS, the basis for generational differentiation can have a very short history and be concentrated
in extremely narrow sub-media of New Media.
Network communities
The foregoing perspectives on types of bonding with both personal communication technologies and media objects deals with the more visible
kinds of rituals that people have with media, via the embodied interface
that they have with actual physical media. In large measure the concrete
subject–object nature of this relationship provides ready evidence for
ritual cases to be put concerning media. However, it may do so whilst
hiding the less tangible relationship individuals may have to mediums.
Nevertheless, as we shall see, the problem with studying network
communities, or ‘virtual communities’, as they are often called, is that they
can easily be rendered as metaphysical and abstract as the ‘personalized’
relationships are concrete. Moreover, the various theories of virtual community, what Rheingold (1994) has called a ‘bloodless technological ritual’,
can attain truly theological meanings as various theorists revel in the
power, the totality and the unity of the universal condition which it is said
to promise.
I am not therefore arguing that communication studies should
not examine interaction with mediums, which is surely of paramount
Telecommunity
189
importance in ‘post-social’ society, but something of the metaphysics of
such communities and of the theories about them needs to be examined.
The imagined ‘universal’ community
The world is getting smaller, and [people] travel faster, countries are
being brought within hours of each other instead of days, the people of
those countries are getting more and more like one great family, and
whether they like it or not one day they have to learn to live like one great
family. (From the British wartime film For Freedom, 1940)
The humanist universalism that is typified in the above statement, as much
as the mistaken way in which McLuhan’s maxim of the global village
is taken up, is one which persists today in all manner of ‘computopia’ narratives. It is not simply that the means of communication have speeded
up, but they have a density which reduces the ‘degrees of separation’
between persons. As Watts (2000) claims, with the Internet, ‘within a significant chunk of the www every site could be reached from every other
site through about four hotlinks’ (4). Thus, in Durkheimian terms, the
‘dynamic density’ produced by such an increase in communication infrastructure brings greater and greater numbers of persons into its orbit.
Certainly McLuhan, in his populist interpretation, has been taken up
as the patron saint of such a concept of community. As Arthur Kroker
(1995) says of McLuhan, he never deviated from the classical Catholic project of seeking to recover the basis for a ‘new universal community’ in the
culture of technology: ‘The Christian concept of the mystical body – all
men as members of the body of Christ – this becomes technologically a
fact under electronic conditions’ (McLuhan in Stearn, 1968: 302). The
body, both mystical and sensual, is integral to McLuhan’s media cosmology, which has undoubtedly had enduring appeal among those who continue to deify the electronic village (esp. Wired magazine).
McLuhan’s earlier advances of a techno-spiritualism find continuity
in the cyber-soul or the cyber-mind in which individuality itself is resolved
into a unified identity. Mark Slouka in War of the Worlds (1996) says:
… in the very near future, human beings will succeed in wiring themselves
together to such an extent that individualism as we know it today … will
cease to exist. What will take its place? The great truth of our collective identity, made clear and apprehensible through the offices of that ‘global mind’,
the Net. (96)
Such a cyber-mind is close to Gibsonian renditions of cyberspace as an outof-body consensual hallucination which is available to be shared. A variant of this is the cybernetic unification of souls on an almost ineffable astral
level whose eternal object of desire is ‘community’. In her analysis of narratives of cyberspace as a gateway for spiritual redemption, Margaret
190
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Wertheim (1999) quotes from a 1997 virtual reality conference paper by the
developer of VRML (Virtual Reality Modelling Language), Mark Pesce. In
opening his paper Pesce claims that those who fully appreciate what
cyberspace is are those touched by revelation, sangrail, the Holy Grail – a
revelation that was once the privilege of witches and mystics, which hackers have a special understanding of, and which is available to all in the
modern era: ‘The revelation of the Graal is always a personal and unique
experience. ... I know – because I have heard it countless times from many
people across the world – that this moment of revelation is the common
element in our experience as a community’ (253).
In Pesce’s account, the ecstasy of cyberspace is that it is, at once, the final
paradise available to all, whilst offering all a unique, irreplaceable moment
of revelation – a place of both redemption and solipsism. The excessively
individualistic form of this revelation paradoxically embraces some order of
a generalized other whilst failing to identify with any particular others.
Foster (1997) argues that ‘[s]olipsism, or the extreme pre-occupation with
and indulgence of one’s own inclination, is potentially engendered in the
technology [of the Internet]’ (26). As the private basis from which each netizen realizes his or her own very personal Grail becomes more convincing,
sources of self-identity become tenuous: ‘as the private becomes more allencompassing and the image of one’s own world view becomes more convincing, one can lose sight of the other altogether’ (26).
In the absence of the other, avatars everywhere encounter only themselves, and extend themselves in the image of the medium itself, which
acts back on them as an externalized spirit to be worshipped. Wertheim
(1999) remarks that, ‘[i]n one form or another, a “religious” attitude has
been voiced by almost all the leading champions of cyberspace’ (255, see
also Robins, 1995: 151). Regardless of whether the champions of cyberspace are ‘formal religious believers’ like Wired magazine’s Kevin Kelly,
‘again and again we find in their discussions of the digital domain a “religious valorization” of this realm’ (256).
In order that such a place is reserved for cyberspace, it is frequently
associated with Judaeo-Christian narratives of which it is seen to be part
of an eternal return. For example, Michael Benedikt (1991) describes it as
a New Jerusalem, which, like the Garden of Eden, ‘stands for our state of
innocence’ and is a ‘Heavenly City which stands for our state of Wisdom
and Knowledge’ (15). In the Book of Revelations, the Heavenly City
exhibits a beauty and a geometry tantamount to a ‘religious vision of
cyberspace itself’ (Wertheim, 1999: 258).
However, the genesis myths which are commonplace are not at all
restricted to Christianity.9 As Wertheim points out, they can just as easily
be based in Greek mythology: ‘From both our Greek and our JudeoChristian heritage Western culture has within it a deep current of dualism
that has always associated immateriality with spirituality’ (256).
The ineffable and the sublime feature strongly in Greek mythology,
and indeed the very idea of utopia comes from the Greek, meaning
Telecommunity
191
‘nowhere’, a beyond which cannot be found in the mundane materiality
of everyday life.10
Of course, technology has always figured in attaining such a beyond,
for which cyberspace is the latest enlistee. Because of this, the Greek
legends used to explain technologically mediated community are always
about the emancipation as well as the imprisonment which technology is
capable of delivering. In Technopoly (1993), Postman narrates the
Judgement of Thamus as being able to teach us that ‘every culture must
negotiate with technology‘, and that always ‘a bargain is struck in which
technology giveth and technology taketh away’ (5). The realization by
human beings of some form of community is said to be dependent on the
correct negotiation of the perils and ecstasies of technology.11
These relationships to technology invariably harbour dreams of
unity, in the form of democracy, community and a metaphysical common
weal or common interest. In nearly all cases the status of modern communication technology is cast within the above configuration of a ‘use or
abuse’ framework of technology. Technology can be a source of great
enlightenment, hope and belongingness, but it is assumed that it can also
foreclose relationships in which it has a lesser mediating role.
Such is the tenor of Darin Barney’s Prometheus Wired: The Hope of
Democracy in the Age of Network Technology (2000). Barney takes a rather
more in-depth look at the history of both technology and the meanings of
political utopia, employing the writings of Plato, Aristotle, Marx, Heidegger
and George Grant for this purpose.
In doing so, Barney revisits the myth of Prometheus, who concealed
the earthly possession of fire from Zeus. Zeus’s response was to deny the
blessing of hope to mortal beings. The technology of fire is granted. It may
provide light and warmth, but Zeus knew it would also lead transient
beings to extend themselves beyond their mortal limits, leading to apocalyptic situations. ‘When beings who are mortal by nature no longer foresee their own death, they begin to regard themselves as immortal: as
having no natural limits, like gods, which they are not. Hope thus seduces
human beings into overestimating and overreaching themselves, with
tragic consequences’ (5). Barney’s corrective to Enlightenment doctrine is
that ‘[h]ope enlightens, but it also blinds’ (5). Nowhere are the stakes of
this insight so high as they are in the virtual dreams that are held out for
the role of network technology in political organization.
The immateriality of cyberspace, the fact that it is so ‘clean’ and free
from mortal struggle, coincides with another metaphysical theme of the
cyber-utopians – that of ‘liberation from the flesh’. As Wertheim (1999)
has commented, ‘Among many champions of cyberspace we also find a
yearning for transcendence over the limitations of the body’ (259). In the
sentiments of cyber-enthusiasts like Jaron Lanier and Nicole Stenger, it is
possible to ‘transcend the body’ or at least be ‘re-sourced’ sparkling juveniles who will never age (259). ‘Dreaming of a day when we will be able
to download ourselves into computers, Stenger has imagined that in
192
COMMUNICATION THEORY
cyberspace, we will create virtual doppelgangers who will remain youthful
and gorgeous forever’ (259).
Given that the virtual community can never be ‘lived’ in embodied
form, but only imaginatively by extension, it is not surprising that the
imagined universal community is also realized in a secular quest for
liberation from the flesh itself. The intellect, rather than the body, lies at
the centre of the life world of the virtual community, where ‘the secular
and scientific myth of the conquest of nature could be fused with the logic
of commodity production’ (Sharp, 1985: 65).
Abstraction from the flesh (solipsism) and spiritual unity (universal
humanism) are at the base of a bewildering array of attempts to define a
kind of ‘cybergeist’ in some form of conceptual singularity. Solipsistic tendencies to define-it-ism are a telling indication of this. Typically this entails
inventing neologisms which have the minimal reference to comparable
terms whilst claiming the maximal reference to a universal condition. The
authors of these neologisms stand out as ideologists of this solipsism,
which can attain rapturous proportions. Numerous, zine-like publications
flourished in the mid-1990s advancing home-grown concepts of cyberspace which made little attempt to engage with concepts which already
addressed their ‘investigations’.
We have already discussed the Apparatgeist, but numerous other
examples can be given. Sometimes terms might be referring to the same
thing but talk past each other as they each rush in to claim a universal
descriptor that is oblivious to the rush of neologisms found elsewhere.
Apparatgeist, digitopia, cyberutopia, cyberia (Rushkoff), technopoly
(Postman), infomedia (Koelsch): lexical fragmentation prevails at the precise juncture where an homogeneous speech community is supposed to
find renewal.
One even finds completely needless attempts to redefine those few
terms which have established themselves – such as ‘cyberspace’. An indulgent case of this can be found in Darren Tofts’ Memory Trade: A Prehistory
of Cyberculture (1997), an illustrated essay which feels compelled to redefine cyberspace as ‘cspace’. It is worth quoting at length:
To come to terms with the historicity of cyberculture we need a concept that
identifies both the ur-foundation of technologized consciousness, as well as
its extension in the current preoccupation with the creation of digital worlds.
The concept I propose is called ‘cspace’.
The concept of ‘cspace’ first announced itself as a means of abbreviating cyberspace, a nonce invention that served the purpose of expedience. I first used the term when I was thinking through the connections
between poststructuralism, cybernetics and writing. Within that context, it
took on a new, aleatoric meaning, embodying many of the ideas I was
working with at the time. Pronounced in exactly the same way as ‘space’,
cspace is beautifully ambivalent, for as a form of shorthand it accommodates two different meanings (cyberspace/space), yet they cannot co-exist
Telecommunity
193
at one and the same time. A particular kind of reading must choose
between them … no spoken reading of cspace can elide cyberspace with
space. Furthermore, a silent reading of the text on the page must unpack
and mentally vocalize cyberspace, codify the visual sign with acoustic
value, in order to hear it. (51)12
For Tofts, ‘cspace’, which is initially announced as a concept, rapidly
progresses to an ontology which has ‘manifestations’ such as the everyday
division between ‘inside’ and ‘outside’ (51) of technological worlds,
whether this be ‘jacking into the matrix’ or ‘speaking on the telephone’.
Cspace is heralded as a kind of ancestral trope, the inside and outside of
alphabetic writing, which is said to invoke Socratic fears about language
having spatial architectures that cannot be controlled by the subject. For this
reason ‘cspace’, it is repeated, is no less than the ‘ur-concept of technologized consciousness, as well as the grammacentrism of cyberculture’ (51).
A very different but equally inflated conflation of a nomenclature
with an ontology is that of ‘cyberpower’, put forward by Tim Jordan
(1999). Writing at the end of the 1990s, Jordan felt confident enough to
proclaim:
The patterns of a virtual life are clear enough to be mapped. The virtual
world and its social order can be traced now in its entirety, from pole to
pole. This does not mean all areas are perfectly known. Sometime in the
future we will probably look back at this map and see where it has equivalents to the dragons and the sea monsters faithfully represented on early
maps of the world. (3)
This nevertheless does not prevent a self-assured vision of cyberspace as
a totality:
However, we can produce an overview of all of cyberspace’s multifarious
life, the first globe of cyberspace. This book is such a globe. It is a cartography of the powers that circulate through virtual lives, a chart of the forces
that pattern the politics, technology and culture of virtual societies. These
powers set the basic conditions of virtual lives. They are the powers of
cyberspace and together they constitute cyberpower. (3)
As the book proceeds, cyberpower turns from being a map of power
relationships on the Internet, to being indistinguishable itself from the
form of this relationship: ‘Cyberpower is the form of power that structures
culture and politics in cyberspace and on the Internet’ (208). The merit of
Jordan’s book is that it does break down the forms of recognizable power
relationship that operate in cyberspace in useful ways: individual, social
and imaginary. But as with Tofts’ fixation with his own solipsistically
invented ‘monster concept’ of cspace, Jordan valorizes cyberpower into a
theoretical dragon too indeterminable to have any analytic value.
194
COMMUNICATION THEORY
The virtual Internet community
It can be seen from the foregoing discussion that speculation on network
communities can attain quite theological dimensions. At precisely the
time that Alain Touraine made his sociological claim that social systems,
as systems, no longer exhibited transcendent ‘universal unifying values’,
some cyber-utopians wanted to point to the Internet as providing just
such values. However, this is not true of a growing body of empirical and
analytic research which has been conducted from the mid-1990s onwards
and which has sought to unravel the specific forms of connection and
bond which the Internet makes possible. Such research can be divided
into two clear methodologies and premises. One body of research merely
extends demographic sociology to include questions about Internet use
(Anderson and Tracey, 2001; Di Maggio et al., 2001, Howard et al., 2001;
Nie and Erdring, 2000; Wellman, 1999), whereas the other form of
research focuses exclusively on Net communities in their various forms
(e.g. Baym, 1998, 2000; Rafaeli and Sudweeks, 1997; Smith, 1997). The
demographic researchers proceed much more from a behaviourist
‘impacts’ paradigm, asking questions like ‘are on-line identities consistent with off-line identities?’, whereas the virtual community studies are
interested in the sui generis qualities of the new medium, exploring
whether a new medium allows for new ways of behaving and new identities which bear no relation to, or cannot be meaningfully compared to,
off-line identity.
For these latter researchers, ‘virtual’ does not mean immaterial and
spiritual. Virtual communication might be disembodied, but it has a definite
architecture and technical infrastructure which is material – a network
rather than a matrix.
Rather than run headlong into announcing a mythical universalism,
the empirical research on Net communities has taken the Internet as a
model for specifying a set of social dynamics which can be distinguished
from either ‘broadcast’ (as the first media age) or face-to-face communities.
Certainly, it is easy to differentiate ‘virtual Internet communities’
from face-to-face communities. They are, as in Dempsey’s second type of
community discussed above, made up of persons who do not necessarily
know one another but have a sense of belonging together (Foster, 1997:
24). And the fact that such communities are entirely disembodied in no
way lessens the solidarity of such a community in the Durkheimian sense.
Despite the fact that audience communities are able to constitute a
mediated ceremony, as we shall see, the term ‘virtual community’ has
only attached itself to the Internet. Clearly, audience communities qualify
as ‘disembodied communities’ in which persons still feel a sense of ‘belonging together’. We saw, however, in Table 5.3 in the previous chapter how
this feeling of ‘belonging together’ is mediated by different agents (technical infrastructure: Internet; and technical plus human infrastructures:
broadcast). Both Internet and broadcast also exhibit some of the qualities of
Telecommunity
195
face-to-face communication, but in inverse relationship: interaction without
reciprocity (Internet) and reciprocity without interaction (broadcast).
What is valorized in Internet communities is that they are ‘interactive’ (Willson, 1997: 146). Interactivity becomes foundational for the speculation of virtual community and, as particularly the second media age
theorists argue, for community in general. We are reminded by Rheingold
(1994) that virtual communities are a compensation for the loss of traditional communities around the world. The loss of these communities
has been postulated by Stone (1991) as a ‘drive for sociality’ – ‘a drive that
can be frequently thwarted by the geographical and cultural reality of
cities’ (111).
What is denied in the metropolis is communities of a ‘face-to-face’
nature, and their attenuation is seen to be compensated for by the electropolis, which, whilst distinguishable from these communities, is largely
thought within their terms: ‘More and more commercial, political, media,
and social interaction occurs in cyberspace every day, supplementing and
enhancing face-to-face meetings. A new class of acquaintance has emerged:
virtual friends and associates – those we feel we know well but have never
met’ (Whittle, 1996: 230).
Because ‘virtual Internet communities’ are delineated within the
face-to-face paradigm, they work to emphasize every quality of on-line
communication which is intrinsic to face-to-face communication whilst
explaining those qualities that are absent either as a loss, or as compensated for in other ways. What is retained by the utopian theorists of virtual
Internet communities is an homogeneous sense of an agora in which interaction can take place, and, of course, interactivity itself, which is raised to
an ideology of the modern period.13
Rheingold (1994) is an early paradigm example of this view. For him,
cyberspace has the potential to be a place which ‘can rebuild the aspects of
community that were lost when the malt shop became the mall’ (24–6),
named variously as the new ‘social commons’ or the ‘electronic agorae’. The
fact that an agora that is global in proportion can replace the malt shop does
not present problems for Rheingold. This is because an agora is only limited
by its exclusion of interactivity. If the virtual community can facilitate the
latter, then, no matter how many participants, it still qualifies as an agora.
Of course, for second media age figures like Rheingold, the actual
agorae of pre-media society are scantily theorized. What are projected and
idealized are those geographical communities, antedating broadcast and
the culture industry, that managed to thrive in urban life and rural centres
in various forms of ‘third places’ – the market, the promenade, the street
and the arcade. But the confluence of mass media with the ‘automobilecentric, suburban, fast-food, shopping mall way of life eliminated many
of these “third places” from traditional towns and cities around the
world’ (Rheingold, 1994: 25).
For other second media age theorists, like Mark Poster, the agora, a
foundation of ancient Athenian civic life, is deemed distinctive in its
196
COMMUNICATION THEORY
openness, unregulated by the state or church, and an arena for unfettered
political expression. With the growth of cosmopolitan cities in early
European modernity, the agora typically contracted to institutions which
became normative for embodied interaction – the cosmopolitan coffee
house predominates as the most significant continuation of a public agora.
But also, as Poster (1997) points out, ‘the New England town hall, the public
square, a convenient barn, a union hall, a park, factory lunchroom, and
even a street corner’ may perform agora-like functions (217).
Roseanne Stone (1991) takes up the virtual-community-as-agora
thesis so sweepingly that she constructs an entire genealogy of virtual
community, including its mythologies, that dates from well before the
Internet itself.
As Ostwald (1997) outlines it, Stone’s ‘phenomenological view of
the spatial and the experiential’ is divided into four epochs of virtual
communities.
The first epoch brings together intellectual interchange, which survives
today in the university: ‘the academic community of the journal has, like
any other community, strict laws and customs. Communications between
members of the community may be rigidly ordered to meet accepted
forms of language, referencing and format’ (131).
The next epoch of virtual communities derives from mass media: ‘In
this epoch, the virtual spatiality of radio and television connect people
together through perceived experiences and the illusion of participation.
Like the academic community spatialized within the journal or paper, the
tele-visual community creates its own particular variations of language
and presentation’ (131).
The founding moment for the third epoch was when the intranet network, Communitree, went on-line in May 1978. An asynchronous bulletin
board capable of facilitating CMC, ‘Communitree was a rudimentary precursor to the global news-nets where hundreds of thousands converse
daily and exchange data in a free-flowing system’ (131).
Epoch four in Stone’s virtual community is based on Gibson’s
‘Matrix’, a form of cyberspace in which the communion of selves attains
its fullest expression. The mere existence of multiple selves in cyberspace
(the socialization of virtual reality) guarantees an interactive freedom
unparalleled in the other epochs.
Stone’s epochs provide a somewhat more nuanced way of thinking
about modes of communicative association. But what is common to all of
these epochs is that agorae of interactivity are their recurring basis.
Whilst Stone distinguishes between different agorae, and describes
the kinds of community they make possible, the nature of interaction
which takes place within them is left untheorized. As in the case of second
media age thinkers, it is often supposed that interaction is a matter of
speech, or, at least in the Gibsonian Matrix, an exchange of consciousness.
But does community always require a reciprocity and the exchange
of consciousness? This view is certainly a pervasive one, for which the
Telecommunity
197
agora provides a gathering-as-communion, in which interactivity is
always modelled on face-to-face exchange.
The sense of community made possible by flânerie
The practice of flânerie – a form of pedestrianism which sought the sensation of crowds for its own sake – is, as it has appeared at different times
in the development of cities, I argue, indispensable for understanding
virtual Internet communities, which can be viewed as a continuation of
flânerie by other means.
We have seen already the difference between Gemeinschaft and
Gesellschaft inherited from classical sociology. As narrated by Tönnies, this
difference is borne out by the contrast between city and village. The village
is itself an agora replete throughout its entire aspect, whereas in the city
certain places are set aside especially for the conduct of interaction. As is
prevalent in much of the literature, the virtual community takes the village,
or the ‘global village’, as its analogue, with a selective interpretation of
McLuhan providing a ready-made justification. In the next two sections,
I am going to argue that cyberspace does not signal the return of the communitarian agora, but is in fact a continuation of the cosmopolitan agora.
Such an agora is not distinctly European but can be found in all cultures
which undergo rapid urbanization. It has more to do with the culture of
cities than with culture ethnically defined; indeed, this is what makes the
flâneur such a precursor of a global form of cosmopolitan identity.
But to understand this, we must understand the changing practices
of flânerie which emerged in European modernity. Up until the midnineteenth century in Europe and Russia the public promenades of the
great cities drew massive crowds, where individuals began a practice that
is scarcely visible today, but which has been heralded as a defining practice of modernity – that of the pedestrian who seeks out the crowd. Two
principal savants of flânerie are Charles Baudelaire (1972) and Walter
Benjamin (1977), who describe how, at the height of the period of flânerie,
flâneurs revelled in their anonymity. Published in 1863, Baudelaire’s
benchmark essay ‘The Painter of Modern Life’ declares of the flâneur: ‘The
crowd is his domain, just as the air is the bird’s, and water that of the fish.
His passion and his profession is to merge with the crowd’ (Baudelaire,
1972: 399). In the rapidly populating cities, in the tumult of the revolutionary world, the individual becomes at once an outsider and singular,
but, as Featherstone (1998) notes, there is a recognizable social type: ‘the
flaneur moved through the crowds with a high sense of invisibility – he
was in effect masked and enjoyed the masquerade of being incognito’
(913).14 The kind of space which the cosmopolitan agora offered to the
flâneur was not one which redeemed Gemeinschaft in the midst of the multitudes. Nor did it produce anomie either (Tester, 1996: 7). Rather, for the
bourgeois stroller, it was a place of intense fervour and passion.15
198
COMMUNICATION THEORY
The promenades of the great cities of modernity were places of
high-volume interaction, but very impersonal interaction. The main feature of such ‘face-to-face’ interaction was that it was visual.16 It was either
to see or be seen that the flâneur sought out the crowd. With such purpose
the flâneur would overcome unfeeling isolation through enjoying the multiplication of selves. The metropolitan person is also addicted to the heightened tempo of the large city – and would form an attachment to the street
as if it were a home.17
For Benjamin (1977):
The street becomes a dwelling for the flâneur; he is as much at home
among the façades of houses as a citizen is in his four walls. To him the
shiny, enameled signs of businesses are at least as good a wall ornament
as an oil painting is to the bourgeois in his salon. The walls are the desk
against which he presses his notebooks; news-stands are his libraries and
the terraces of cafés are the balconies from which he looks down on his
household after his work is done. (37)
As Keith Tester (1996: 5) explains, the flâneur has a calling, which is
doing, not simply being. For Baudelaire (1972), the man who lives in a box,
or the man who lives like a mollusc (the man who simply is), is actually
incomplete; the struggle for existential completion and satisfaction requires
relentless bathing in the multitude (it requires doing over and over again).
The flâneur, then, ‘the man of the crowd’, works at his identity, and
does not actually lose it in the crowd, as the badaud, or simple ‘man in the
crowd’, does. His observation of the street is specialized and intellectual.
The aestheticization of such a gaze provides the flâneur with a sense of differentiation; it is what makes him special, and individual, even where in
fact he may be repressing the images of decay which can also be observed
around the city.
For this reason, the flâneur lives heroically as a foreigner in his own
city18 – the complete reverse of the situation of the village or small town
person. For the latter, strangers only come from outside and must be
assimilated – as Shields (1994) suggests: ‘the stranger is a foreigner who
becomes like a native, whereas the flaneur is a native who becomes like a
foreigner’ (68).
If there was community in the town square and the cafés of midmodernity it was in the display of proto-cosmopolitanism. But in both forms
of the flâneur it was interacting with a mass of strangers which became
life’s prime goal: to be outside, to be with others for the sake of it, not to
anticipate an individual interaction. As we shall see, the form of individual
that arose from flânerie, the person who swung between being seen and
being invisible, is very important for understanding the Internet avatar,
whose community is also to mix with those who are strangers. Like the
flâneur, the avatar is invisible, but mixes with the broadest kind of ‘public’
ever envisaged, that of the virtual community.
Telecommunity
199
From street to virtual flâneur – the transformation of flânerie
Click, click, through cyberspace, this is the new architectural promenade.
(Mitchell, 1996: 24)
For Walter Benjamin, flânerie was a peculiarly nineteenth-century
European phenomenon, whose fall from public life resulted from the
withdrawal of spaces in which it could be practised. The street itself was
undergoing massive changes. Pedestrianism of any kind had become
hazardous as the tramcars, the trolleys and locomotion drove corridors of
speed throught the cities. As Benjamin narrated it, this is why the great
arcades had become so important, as they turned the street inward and
quarantined an exclusive zone in which the flâneur could thrive (Benjamin,
1977: 36). But when the arcades began to be demolished to make way for
department stores, it was the beginning of the end of this kind of flâneur.
If the arcade is the classical form of the intérieur, which is how the flâneur
sees the street, the department store is the form of the intérieur’s decay.
The bazaar is the last hangout of the flâneur. … if in the beginning the
street had become an intérieur for him, now this intérieur turned into a
street, and he roamed through the labyrinth of merchandise as he had once
roamed through the labyrinth of the city … (Benjamin, 1977: 54)
The story of the disappearance of the flâneur coincides with the story
of the disappearance of public space. The street becomes the arcade, the
arcade becomes the department store, the department store is absorbed
by vast privately owned zones that are shopping malls.
For Mike Featherstone (1998: 910), in the modern period this means
that urban spaces where the occupants of different residential areas could
meet face-to-face, engage in casual encounters, accost and challenge one
another, talk, quarrel, argue or agree, lifting their private problems to the
level of public issues and making public issues into matters of private
concern – those ‘private/public’ agorae of Cornelius Castoriadis are fast
shrinking in size and number.
For Benjamin, this process corresponds to a change in the flâneur also,
who is redefined as a consumer, a private, possessive individual who
attempts to re-create his own sense of a world-of-the-whole through the
market. The final phantasmagoria is the private dwelling itself, which, as
Ann Friedberg (1993) describes it, simulates a dioramic display of goods
and commodities, and, together with media, provides for every need.
As we saw in the previous chapter on mobile privatization, the private home itself becomes the basis for a virtual agora. Electronic assemblies and electronic interaction take precedence over interaction with our
neighbours, or geographic community. Indeed, as McLuhan says of the
United States at least: ‘to go outside is to be alone’ (quoted from an interview with Tom Wolfe, ‘McLuhan: The Man and His Message’. Staying
200
COMMUNICATION THEORY
inside becomes the basis for connection. There is no longer any calling to
physically associate as a goal in itself.
In exploring this de-physicalization of flânerie, Featherstone (1998)
asks, ‘How far can the new forms of electronic communication such as the
Internet and multimedia also facilitate flânerie?’ (919). A number of commentators (including Featherstone, 1998; Jones, 1995; Mitchell, 1996;
Smith, 1999) have insisted that cyberspace is a unique replacement for the
geographic agora. As Steven Jones has suggested of CMC,
Like the boulevardiers or the denizens of Nevsky Prospect described by
Berman (1982), the citizens of cyberspace (or the ‘net’ as it is commonly
called by its evanescent residents) come here to see and be seen, and to
communicate their visions to one another, not for any ulterior purpose, without greed or competition, but as an end in itself. (Berman, 1982: 196, cited
in Jones, 1995: 17)
For them, broadcast cannot offer a meeting place of this kind. Instead, it
gathers audiences together but leaves them with little to discuss save for
what is offered as spectacle. Indeed, the sub-media of the Internet are able
to offer the same kinds of opportunity for interaction as did the spaces of
flânerie which featured in the early period of modernity.
For Featherstone (1998), the most important characteristic of Internet
sub-media in this regard is that they are non-linear – they move away from
‘the linear physical construction of the book with its sequence of pages, or
the film with its one-way movement through time’ (9). Such forms of association were not possible with television until the development of video
cassette recorders/players. But the database, whether it is a CD-ROM or
the Internet’s ‘Library of Babel’, enables instantaneous information association, which, according to Featherstone, encourages electronic flânerie.
But unlike the deliberate ambling of the traditional flâneur, hypertext
allows the virtual traveller to jump to other places in texts or in the Web
of pages. Such flânerie presupposes the ontology of the disembodiedextended, discussed in the previous chapter, the individual who is ‘lifted
out’ of the constraints of embodiment, or, as Featherstone puts it, does not
have to ‘wait to reach the street-corner to change direction’.
Indeed, the jump, to continue the metaphor, can be to another city. Not only
is the flâneur’s city a world, but the world has become his/her city: with
everything potentially accessible, potentially visible. Hence, hypertexting
brings to the fore the problem of navigation, of movement within text or
work. There no longer is a correct sequential way of reading or proceeding;
the work has become directly activated by the particular purposes, or
whims, of the user. This is one of the defining characteristics of the new
electronic media: interactivity. It encourages engagement and two-way interaction on the part of the user which contrasts to the one-way mode of communication, which encouraged passive reception, which we find in the
traditional age of mass media. (921)
Telecommunity
201
So, once again, we find a central characteristic of the second media
age being introduced here as an agent of the return of flânerie. Electronic
flânerie is also an improvement, in speed, mobility and reach, on the urban
flâneur.
The urban flâneur typically sauntered around, letting the impressions of
the city soak into his subconscious. The electronic flâneur is capable of
great mobility; his pace is not limited to the human body’s capacity for
locomotion – rather, with the electronic media of a networked world, instantaneous connections are possible which render physical spatial differences
irrelevant. (921)19
Featherstone does, however, tend to reduce such non-linearity to ‘the
Internet’ as an exclusive environment for such mobilities. For example, he
argues that ‘with the Internet there has been a massive speed up of the
rate at which new perceptions are brought in front of the eye’ (921–2),
whereas, as we know from Simmel (1971), the ‘mental life’ of the metropolitan person is before all else distinguished by ‘information overload’.
The second media age thesis dilutes also when we compare the largely
textual experience of the ‘World Wide Wait’ with the frenetic culture of
music television, which institutionalizes channel surfing, or image surfing, into a genre, as Featherstone himself observes: ‘we can recall the
much-vaunted postmodern channel hopper, MTV, or music video viewer,
who is bombarded with fragments of images and information removed
from their context so that he is incapable of chaining together the signifiers into a meaningful message’ (922). This quote would insinuate that
the mass media do not generate such passive participants as Featherstone
earlier suggests.
An added counterpoint of Featherstone’s second media age argument
is his assertion that virtual forms of association preceded the Internet by
many years. The difference between today’s ‘city of bits’ and the industrial
city is one of degree only. The industrial city was always ‘an information
city in the sense that the urban landscape was continually inscribed and
reinscribed with information, with cultural meanings in the aestheticised
façades of buildings, advertisements, neon signs, billboards’ (922). And
we could add to this observation the fact that nineteenth-century technologies of simulation were already providing alternatives to the mutual
agora. The panorama, the diorama and cinema prefigure television and
the Internet by providing virtual spaces to ‘travel’ which give the illusion
of being part of worlds that do not require physical involvement.
Problems with dominant definitions of virtual community
The fact that cyberspace may provide a milieu for electronic flânerie conflicts with two very prevalent views of virtual Internet community. The
202
COMMUNICATION THEORY
first rests on its touted efficiency in being able to connect people with
common interests,20 and the second is that it is able to reduce serendipitous
interaction between strangers.21 Both of these views fall within an instrumental conception of the Internet.
In the first case, virtual community is cast in terms of interest-based
relationships.22 In the community-of-interest view, individuals, or avatars,
are bonded together solely in the pursuit of common interests. See Marc
A. Smith for a comparison of virtual communities with the committees of
correspondence of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. The appeal of
CMC or the Internet is that it is seen to deliver the satisfaction of these interests much more efficiently than can life off-line. However, the needs that are
met to satisfy these interests tend to be less material than they are psychological. And indeed the appreciation of shared interest in a particular movement, style or object, be it the environment, fashion or tropical fish, is viewed
to be sufficient in most cases for a sense of bond to emerge with other people. Of course, this particular view, heavily promoted by Wired magazine in
the 1990s, is founded in a consumerist approach to community. J. Macgregor
Wise (1997) argues that it didn’t take long for the Internet to become a frontier for commodification, not in what it sells, but in the way individuals
relate to it: ‘Community based on special interests (hobbies) is already on its
way towards a consumerist-centered (rather than community based on
community interests) organization, where the dominant communities (e.g.
newsgroups) are communities centered around leisure activities (e.g. Star
Trek)’ (154).
Another dominant instrumental view of the virtual community is celebratory of on-line cultures where there is ‘no sense of place’. In these definitions, computerization removes dependence on physical ‘place’ and
minimizes accidental contact amongst strangers. This in turn provides an
architecture for the community-of-interest to flourish, as individual interactions are unlikely to be cluttered by colliding with unwanted forms of
association. Thus, it enhances the efficiency of communication among
those who already need to communicate more efficiently (see, e.g., Calhoun,
1986). However, this latter view differs substantially from the practice of
flânerie, which encourages a community of strangers bathing in each
other’s company.
In both of these views, the idea of community is a Gemeinschaft-by-othermeans, and not association as an end in itself. In both views, traditional ‘nostalgic’, real-life senses of community can benefit, but they can also be
threatened. Wellman and Gulia (1999) see the utopian versus the dystopian
versions of virtual community arguments as the central binary which organizes the debate.23 But the binary between the reinvigoration of real-life community and its attenuation conceals the fact that what is reaffirmed by both
positions is a commitment to a one-dimensional sense of real-life community,
which can be either ‘helped’ or eroded by technological mediation.
One glaring problem with such a commitment is that, as we have
identified, it is historically possible to uncover senses of community not
Telecommunity
203
anchored in communicative interaction, but which also do not involve
technological mediation – a fact which problematizes too simple a reallife/virtual community distinction.24 The merit of the flânerie perspective,
for example, is that it points to long-held practices of association which
have very different bases than that of functional connections between
rational, autonomous subjects. It allows that the visual, aesthetic and
mutual sensoria of public life are also strong sources of community feeling. By contrast, the widely heralded instrumental functions of cyberspace are only a part of the spectrum of human interaction. Moreover, the
hailing of the Internet as a redemption of interactivity accentuates the
way CMC dramatically extends dialogic communication as an instrumental aspect of face-to-face communication, but at the expense of other
qualities of mutual presence.
The more reliant individuals are on CMC to meet communication
needs, the less they engage with embodied interaction. No empirical studies
are necessary to demonstrate this relationship.25 This, in itself, is not a
dystopian situation; it is just that it precludes the possibility of more
rounded (multi-levelled) expressions of everyday life. This is usually
expressed by critics of on-line communication via a broader critique of computerization cast within a humanist narrative. George Lakoff (1995) laments:
One of the sad things is that the increase in computer technology does not get
you out into the world more, into nature, into the community, dancing, singing,
and so on. In fact, as the technology expands, there is more expectation that
you will spend more of your life on a screen. That is not, for my money, the way
one should live one’s life. The more that the use of computers is demanded
of us, the more we shall be taken away from truly deep human experiences.
That does not mean you spend time at a computer, you will never have any
deep human experiences. It just means that current developments tend to put
pressure on people to live less humane lives. (124)
Once again, the entrenched dichotomy which opposes a ‘deep’
human essence to technology appears here. Rather than on-line interaction being merely a new kind of human experience which may or may not
result in a loss of other levels of human experience, it is seen to result in a
decline in ‘human experience’ in general.
Lakoff’s othering of technology is also evident in his claim that
experience on-line is fictive:
Online ‘interactivity’ is an illusion. What passes as interactive is pretty uninteractive! It has to do with some fixed menu, not with being able to probe
as you would a person or to judge or be moved as you would in a live interaction. There have to be canned answers and canned possibilities. (Lakoff,
1995: 24)
We have also seen that community has many possible sources, and
that cosmopolitan settings also make a form of community possible via
204
COMMUNICATION THEORY
the image and the effervescence of large populations. Echoing Lakoff’s
charge that the interactivity of on-line communities is not genuine is the
concept of ‘pseudo-communities’ (see Beninger, 1987; Jones, 1995; Slouka,
1996; Stoll, 1995).26
What is missing in the critique of virtual community as ‘pseudocommunity’ is a basic but important understanding of the fact that ‘virtual
community’ can seldom be separated from physical community. Too
often, attempts are made to conduct isolated analyses of Net interaction
in isolation from other interactions without considering that ‘[t]he Net is
only one of many ways in which the same people may interact’ (Wellman
and Gulia, 1999: 170). The empirical research of Wellman and Gulia and
the analyses of Castells (2001) are particularly concerned to dispel the
dichotomy between an idealized past of parochial community and the
narcissistic future of physical isolation overcome by virtual association.
Castells wants to show that uses of the Internet are ‘overwhelmingly
instrumental’ and ‘closely connected to the work, family and everyday
life of Internet users’ (118). He is at pains to demonstrate that on-line
activity does not detract from off-line life, and selectively reviews surveys
which show ‘that internet users have larger social networks than nonusers’ (121). Of course, what Castells reinstates is precisely the dichotomy
between real/virtual that he says he wants to overcome. In repeating
what is a commonplace habit in conceptualizing virtual communication,
Castells does not consider use of the Internet to itself be already part of
‘everyday life’ or already ‘social’; rather, it is seen to be simply compatible with, or to enhance, such life and not be a threat to it. In arguing that
email, for example, is predominantly used for ‘work purposes, to [do]
specific tasks, and to keep in touch with family and friends in real life’ (118),
Castells’ actual object is not virtual community or the Internet, but institutional and face-to-face ‘real life’, defined as ‘real’, in relation to which
communication technology provides a service. Such an approach is incapable of anticipating precisely what is sui generis about virtual community, or that new forms of electronic assembly may exist which enable
forms of interaction not previously practised. To focus on such novelties
of interaction is not to inflate them to the status of a Zeitgeist, but to establish methodologies to analyse the nature of a new kind of social bond.
Overcoming this recurring dualism between real and virtual,
Kumiko Aoki makes a useful but regularly overlooked distinction
between three domains of virtual community:
1 those which totally overlap with physical communities
2 those that overlap with these ‘real-life’ communities to some degree
3 those that are totally separated from physical communities (cited in Foster,
1997: 24).
In his review of empirical research discussed above, Castells (2001)
claims that most Net interactions fall into category 1 or 2. Based on this
Telecommunity
205
research, he concludes that most accounts of virtual community are
over-inflated, and that this has led to a simplistic stereotyping of most Net
users as isolated nerds and geeks who live out a withdrawn and isolated
existence. As I have argued above, Castells’ claims are based on the collapsing of demographic surveys which set out from an institutional
framework with research into CMC. This does not leave him with any
room for a considered analysis of category 3. Either such a category is
reserved for a tiny minority of persons with identity problems who seek
the Net as some sort of fantasy or refuge from real life, or else Castells is
anxious to show that such persons also have a life off-line where they lead
quite normal existences, and are ‘civically engaged’; i.e. that there is no
withdrawal from other forms of sociability. This again shows that, for
Castells, the ‘social’ is a decisively off-line condition and that life on-line
either enhances or annuls such sociability.
It is true that, where there is total overlap between the two kinds
of communities, we typically think of on-line communication as an augmentation or supplementation of face-to-face community rather than the other
way around. In the case of partial overlap, the moment of identification
between two communicants is often more ambiguous and difficult to
negotiate. For virtual communities which have no reference to physical
communities, identification is not burdened with ‘verification’ in that
identity formation is purely internal to the speech events.
Because of this, there is a sense in which, in the third situation, part
of every communication event consists, in part, of interlocutors’ conversations with themselves. Taylor argues that in CMC, ‘The striving subject
enters into conversation in order to build itself up through the search for
truth. Thus the person who converses relates to herself/himself even
when s/he seems to be relating to an other’ (cited in Foster, 1997: 26). The
computer terminal is less a window onto other worlds than it is a halfreflective mirror. Psychoanalysts would tell us that this is true of all
communication, but in cases where such communication becomes technologically embedded, it also gains a different kind of visibility. Where
there are low levels of identification, the case of Aoki’s third form of community, the validation of truth, morality and aesthetics, the three normative domains inherited from modernity cannot be satisfied dialogically,
except in an imaginary sense, an illusion that is proportional to the
accountability of each communicant.
But the low accountability of on-line communicants, what I have called
‘interaction without reciprocity’, isn’t merely related to the absence of
identification between interlocutors but also to their high virtual motility –
the potential for mobility, including the mobility to ‘switch off’ and escape
from any communication event. This feature is accentuated by the high
number of possible connections which can be made on-line, and the fact
that such connections are part of a web or a network.
Rafaeli and Sudweeks (1997) have argued that on-line interactivity
needs to be thought of across an entire network, not simply between
206
COMMUNICATION THEORY
two given interlocutors. For them, connectivity is more important than
interactivity, and the degree to which a given interaction transcends simple
reaction is decisive here.
As Tanjev Schultz (2000) summarizes their view:
Eventually, in two-way, or reactive, communication one side responds to the
other, but such communication remains reactive unless ‘later messages in
any sequence take into account not just messages preceded [sic] them, but
also the manner in which previous messages were reactive’ (Rafaeli and
Sudweeks, 1997). But Rafaeli also draws a very fine line between two-way
and reactive communication: ‘Two-way communication is present as soon
as messages flow bilaterally. Reactive settings require, in addition, that
later messages refer to (or cohere with) earlier ones’ (Rafaeli, 1988: 119).
Rafaeli’s model suggests that a lot of use of the new technologies is far
from interactive. (210)
As Schultz suggests, two-way communication does not, in itself,
guarantee interactivity. And to extend Taylor’s point, if an exchange does
not develop into a relationship where one utterance becomes a context for
another, the discourse becomes egological. Conversely, reactive communication is not just typical of broadcast communication, but is possible
within networks.
As we shall see in the next section, it is fanciful to see ‘interactivity’
as a precondition of virtual kinds of community. This is related to a final
problem that is endemic to dominant definitions of virtual community,
which is that it is confined to network forms of community. When instrumental views of virtual community are critiqued, it becomes clear that broadcast architectures also enable such communities. This further dilutes the
historical distinction between first and second media age, although, as we
shall see, the two forms of virtual community have their own specific
dynamics.
Broadcast communities
Virtual community is people all over the world gathered around television
sets to watch the Super Bowl or a world cup match. (Wilbur, 1997: 14)
A primary implication of the contrast between broadcast and network
communication discussed in the previous two chapters is the way in
which the study of communication architectures allows us to reconsider
broadcast as a technical medium of social integration just as computerconstituted communication networks are today viewed as a medium of
identity and community. As we saw in Chapter 2, broadcast mediums are
not simply conduits for messages, but facilitate institutionalized spectacle
as well as constituting enclosed worlds of representation which may
Telecommunity
207
become self-referential. These two aspects – the spectacle and simulacrum
properties of broadcast media – are active in constituting worlds of representation which attain ritual status for media audiences, and indeed
become sources by which audiences acquire the symbolic and semiotic
materials with which to construct a meaningful identity and a worldspace of personal object meanings. As Silverstone (1999: 99) observes, the
role of ritual community is confined to broadcast.
In a capitalist society these ritual processes are largely of benefit to
the culture industry. But spectacle and simulacrum also generate apparently resistant rituals, which, on the surface, seem to be a reaction to the
very structure of broadcast itself, but which the culture industry continuously re-appropriates.
As we saw in Chapter 3, this system of cultural production where the
few produce culture for the many is widely condemned by the different
celebrants of the Internet. For them, the major feature of the Internet is
that it enables democratized participation in the public sphere, which in
the era of broadcast and ‘systematically distorted communication’ is otherwise undermined. These debates about democracy, the public sphere and
techno-social conditions of communication are increasingly being subsumed within a theory of community.
The levels argument explored in the previous chapter suggests that
abstract communities have just as much intensity as face-to-face-based
senses of community. Even the most abstract and disembodied levels have
rituals and ceremonies capable of integrating ‘strangers’ – indeed ordinarily they transform strangers into natives. These rituals may be symbolic,
such as voting, watching sport, etc., but they can also be very practical, such
as annual tourism pilgrimages, downloading email or watching the same
programme, such as the evening news, every day of the year.
However, what distinguishes broadcast forms of ritual from media
ritual in general is publicity, an element of display and of spectatorship.
Publicity and public spectacle are, of course, an aspect of flânerie which
cannot be achieved on the Internet. Remember that flânerie involves a
dialectic of seeing and being seen. Display, rather than an exchange of
sign-values and texts, is at its core. Broadcast institutionalizes such practices of spectacle display and spectatorship, which may or may not be
technologically extended, by creating specular spaces of association.
This function of broadcast is posited by some sociologists as contributing to the maintenance of social order itself, as Bob Mullan has
pointed out. Quoting from Shils and Young’s well-known discussion of
the coronation of Elizabeth II (1953), Mullan shows the continuity
between the embodied and extended rituals of coronation, both of which
sustain social order and power:
For Shils and Young: ‘the central authority of an orderly society, whether it be
secular or ecclesiastical, is acknowledged to be the avenue of communication
with the realm of the sacred values. Within its society, popular constitutional
208
COMMUNICATION THEORY
monarchy enjoys almost universal recognition in this capacity, and it is
therefore enabled to heighten the moral and civic sensibility of the society
and to permeate it with symbols of those values to which the sensitivity
responds. Intermittent rituals bring the society or varying sectors of it repeatedly into contact with this vessel of the sacred values. The Coronation provided, at one time and for practically the entire society, such an intensive
contact with the sacred that we believe we are justified in interpreting it as …
a great act of national communion.’ (cited in Mullan, 1997: 4)
Television, and, we could add, the press and radio are able to extend this
communion to so many more than is possible in mutual spectatorship:
On 2 June 1953 much of Britain came to a standstill as millions watched
the regal ceremony from Westminster Abbey. In the weeks before the event
500,000 sets were sold as ‘Coronation fever’ swept the land. Despite the
fact that there were only two million or so sets in existence somehow 20
million managed actually to watch the occasion. At the time the Coronation
became the ‘biggest event in television history’ and was broadcast in
France, Holland, Germany. It is estimated that ultimately the world audience
measured some 277 million. (5–6)
But, as we saw with Carey’s discussion of ritual in the previous chapter, celebrative communion is only one variant of ritual display. Carey
(1998) also discusses rituals of shame, degradation and excommunication.
In media past and present there are a plethora of examples to demonstrate how the depiction of ‘acts of cruelty can promote, however distastefully, states of social integration’ (43). Drawing on Dayan and Katz
(1992), he lists the McCarthy, Watergate and Iran–Contra hearings, and his
own case study of the Robert Bork Senate hearing as a ‘media event’. To
these political rituals must be added the confessional forms of TV talk
shows, and the tribal cruelty of excommunication that occurs on reality
survivor shows.
Like the ceremonial appropriation of ritual, the ritual of shaming and
exclusion also has historical antecedents that operated prior to electronic
media. However, unlike the restitutive and deliberative ‘ordeals’ of modern
democracy, the older regimes of ritual were punitive and violent. The most
common occasion for display in pre-media societies was for torture,
execution and ‘punishment’. As John B. Thompson (1995) demonstrates
(see also Chapter 2), in societies of the ancient world, the organization of
power was based on the visibility of the few by the many. This could take
the form of the visibility of nobility via the royal progression, the coronation or funeral, but also the careful management of public punishment in
towns and cities throughout a nation.27
However, there are three major differences which Thompson outlines
between the mediation of visibility by broadcasting technology, and the
spectacle of old. Firstly, there is the range and scope, which we have
already illustrated with the coronation example. Secondly, there is the
Telecommunity
209
‘field of vision’, which enables individuals to see things that are ‘far
removed from the locales of their day-to-day lives’ (130). Finally, there is
the ‘directionality’: ‘In the case of television . .. the direction of vision is
essentially one-way. … The kind of publicness created by television is thus
characterized by a fundamental contrast between producers and recipients in terms of their visibility and invisibility, their capacity to see and to
be seen’ (130).
Thompson’s chronicle of broadcasting links mass media to a new
form of publicness based on visibility. He suggests that such a publicness
does not require speech in the Habermasian sense, but rather allows individuals to assume degrees of visibility and invisibility. Even if they are
part of an agora in which they are invisible and have no speech, they can
at least feel integrated with those who share their situation, and who are
metaphorically represented in the serial world of the screen. In the latter
sense, all audiences of mass media have visibility, in the very liveness of
the medium. On the Internet, however, everyone has speech, but, in
Akio’s third register, no visibility at all.
Tanjev Schultz (2000) is one writer who wishes to reclaim the function of mass media as an agent of integration and as ‘providers of a shared
lifeworld’. He sees ‘a future for this very function’.
Criticism of mass media power and centralization does not necessarily deny
their immense achievements. Jürgen Habermas, for instance, continued the
cited tradition of worry about lack of interaction in mass media …. But he
also viewed their integrational role as a benefit of modernism and as a
necessary condition for a vivid public sphere in complex societies. (Schultz,
2000: 208)
For Habermas, however, visibility in itself is an insufficient basis for
the public sphere if it does not include speech. At the same time, the power
of speech is attenuated if little is known of the speaker, as Habermas also
points out in The Theory of Communicative Action (1984). However, the ritual function of media is absent from Habermas’s theory. Regardless of
what kinds of texts circulate within mass media, they provide a place in
which people construct meaning in their lives. Martin-Barbero (1997) suggests that we should look for ‘the processes of re-enchantment in the continuing experience of ritual in communitarian celebration and in the other
ways that the media bring people together’ (108).
Not only does television provide such ritual opportunity, but it also
has an enduring constancy. Ruth Rosen (1986) refers to a study by Agnes
Nixon which found that most viewers (of soap opera in particular)
regarded TV as the only ‘constant’ in their lives. The world outside may
be in chaos and flux but TV provides an anchor. ‘All potential viewers
are members of a society that has been in constant transformation
through geographic mobility and the loss of extended families’ (Rosen,
1986: 46) find solace in tuning in to characters who, regardless of the
210
COMMUNICATION THEORY
convulsions in their life, are always with you Monday to Friday. Thus
the ritual involves a constancy of participation, not just the consumption
of texts.
As Baym (2000) suggests, ‘Being a member of an audience community is not just about reading a text in a particular way; rather, it is about
having a group of friends, a set of activities one does with those friends,
and a world of relationships and feelings that grow from those friendships’ (207). Such friendship may be with the characters as much as with
other ‘audience friends’ who are enveloped by the same form of virtual
participation.
This densely textured world of participation provides a standing
reserve of sign-values, a reserve which is at its richest in the wider bandwidth of broadcast, which is, ultimately, television. Television is able to
convey complexity but with a remarkable uniformity across a population.28 Never have so may complex meanings – whether these be readerly
or writerly in the Barthesian sense, hot or cool in the McLuhanist sense –
been available to such large audiences.
Following our earlier discussion, the definition of the flâneur,
whether embodied or electronic, as one who bathes in the crowd can be
satisfied within both audience and network environments. However, it
can be observed that audience–medium interactions offer much more to
virtual flâneurs than do network–medium interactions.
As we saw with the rise of the flâneur, the excitement of flânerie was
not a return to Gemeinschaft and community organized around interaction
between members of a speech community. Rather, it was about interaction
with a crowd of some form. Few physical forms of mutual association
outside of broadcast assemblies offer this effect today save for the spectacle of the large sporting event.
The media offer the opportunity for people to come together to
understand the central questions of life, from the meaning of art to the
meaning of death, of sickness, of youth, of beauty, of happiness and of
pain (see Martin-Barbero, 1997).
But audience communities which are organized around texts do not
fully account for the kinds of social integration that are possible within
broadcast. We have seen already how practices of media usage are common to network and broadcast dynamics alike. Broadcast, which may be
said to ‘influence consciousness’, is also an environment for practices and
rituals which are not simply semiotic.
Symbolic inequality in broadcast communities
The constancy that is provided by media genres to provide a common culture over time points to media as a mythological ‘centre’ of social life in
modern societies, to use Couldry’s (2003) phrase, but it is a constancy
Telecommunity
211
which is uneven in its broader social expressions. Whilst, as a general
rule, the production of visibility is the foundation of audience communities, the genre and content of a media product can produce differing
affects, divisions and identifications that stratify audience communities.
As argued, broadcast may be a form of reciprocity without interaction, where the many speak to the many, but they do so by way of agents
of communication, media presenters, hosts, celebrities and ‘personalities’
who become intermediaries enabling such reciprocity to occur. This is
expressed in a very weak level of reciprocity versus a strong degree of
identification with those celebrities. These persons become ‘media
friends’ (Meyrowitz, 1994). Such a world of virtual friendship is usually
totally separate from the kind of friendships we might have in face-to-face
or CMC forms. Only rarely do these worlds meet, as when we actually
meet a celebrity, and there is a very dramatic collapsing of these worlds
into each other. But the places that become famous in broadcast media can
also become physically sacred, to the point where fans and audiences go
on pilgrimage to them (see Couldry, 2003: Ch. 5). Alternatively, there are
cases of those who already live in a location made famous by a television
series wanting to redefine the name of their place to match the fictional
name featured in the programme.29
In a demonstration of the power that such agents have in social integration, Nick Couldry (2003) provides a list that is well suited to understanding this symbolic inequality:
•
•
•
•
•
people calling out as their presence ‘on air’ is acknowledged (the
studio chat show host turns to them and asks them to clap, ‘show what
they feel’)
people either holding back, or rushing forward, at the sight of a celebrity
people holding back before they enter a place connected with the
media, so as to emphasise the boundary they cross by entering it
performances of media people that acknowledge their own specialness
before a crowd of non-media people
performances by non-media people in certain types of formalised media
context, such as a talk show. (52)
These kinds of events indicate the extreme symbolic differentials between
celebrities and so-called ‘ordinary’ individuals. Here the relationship
between a ‘larger-than-life’ Big Subject and the infinity of small subjects is
easily expressed in the idea that a person could become a ‘household name’.
But equally, it might be expressed in the practice of ‘name-dropping’, of an
‘ordinary’ person claiming to know a celebrity in some way. By finding a
way to share in the persona of persons in whom mass recognition is concentrated, an ordinary person can claim some of this recognition by way of
the celebrity as agent.
For the celebrity, on the other hand, name-dropping is impossible. To
name-drop would be to place oneself lower on the hierarchy of recognition.
212
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Instead celebrities refer to each other as though they make up the entire
population. The familiar statement of the media celebrity concerning parties
that ‘everyone will be there’ or ‘everyone is here’ implies that the celebrity
class posits itself as standing in for all classes.
Those who are locked outside this celebrity class must find ways of
sharing in it at-a-distance in ways discussed above, or accept their exclusion
by participation in ritual attention to the anomic condition. The contemporary talk show is an example of this, fixated with unhappy and unsatisfied
guests who, staged or otherwise, confess their loneliness, or feelings of rejection at losing a partner (see below for an extended discussion).
Horton and Wohl (1956) argue, based on the American experience,
that insofar as the production of anomie is, in part, internal to media, the
anomic class is recognized by the mass media themselves, and ‘from timeto-time specially designed offerings have been addressed to this minority’
(223). They give the example from 1951 of a very popular radio programme in the USA – ‘The Lonesome Gal’. As they describe the programme, it sounds very much like a forerunner of reality television,
which is, ‘in fact, nothing but the reciprocal of the spectator’s own parasocial role’ (224). What they mean by this is that instead of being a managed or self-contained drama, ‘The Lonesome Gal’ presented a character
who could potentially be any person in the audience, anyone ‘ordinary’
from the street. ‘Her entire performance consisted of an unbroken monologue, unembarrassed by plot, climax or denouement. The Lonesome Gal
simply spoke in a throaty, unctuous voice whose suggestive sexiness
belied the seeming modesty of her words’ (224). But most importantly the
Lonesome Gal appealed to her audience as being ‘only one of millions of
lonely girls, seeking love and companionship’, and in doing so,
empathized with the low visibility that ‘lonely heart’ audience members
might feel on a daily basis, but which the programme was actually
helping reproduce. This basic structure of interchangeability between an
audience member’s aspirations to be recognized, and a non-celebrity rolemodel who occupies precisely such a place of recognition, is manifest in
all forms of reality genres, which are discussed further below.
But the dominant fields of recognition from which all forms of broadcast recognition spring are based on a division between high and low
visibility of personalities. Fame is, by definition, concentrated among a
few, and the gap between the famous and the ordinary can be measured
in economic terms by the endorsements, appearance and advertising fees
actually paid to celebrities. More recently, it is also possible to measure the
fame of a celebrity by websites, such as Fametracker, devoted to auditing,
summarizing and documenting their fan support, covering the volume of
and loyalty to numerous sites devoted to celebrity deification. There are
also celebrity exchanges such as Celebdaq (UK) and Hollywood SX (USA)
where imaginary currency is used to buy and sell celebrity stock. And
celebrities themselves are using the World Wide Web to extend the
market that they establish on the screen. Upon the pretext of revealing an
Telecommunity
213
inner personality, screen stars parasitize their own image to sell themselves
in another medium for economic gain. Sites like WorldLive.Com host
on-line diaries of megastars such as Melanie Griffiths, who receives hitmoney from each of the millions of fans who log on to her diary. But also
they might be enticed into buying jewellery from her ‘Goddess’ range of
products. Such marketing is more powerful than an advertising campaign
featuring the celebrity, as it proposes to overcome the symbolic inequality
between fan and star by the star divulging common everyday feelings,
but also by emulating a non-celebrity’s only avenue for achieving fame –
the personal web-page.
Lonely at the top Because of the fact that celebrities belong to a very restricted
visibility class, it is frequently difficult for them to associate with persons
of low visibility. They relate to each other, in the form of a kind of ‘status
closure’ that is bound up in image-making; many of them report the difficulty of having ‘real relationships’. There is even a genre which provides
for this fact, films where a member of the media elite (or high-visibility
elite) wants to experience being a ‘real person’: for example, Notting Hill,
Coming to America, and Love Actually.30 Two strong themes emerge in these
narratives. Firstly, there is the idea that a famous person needs to masquerade as an ‘ordinary’ (perhaps anonymous) person, or at least downplay their fame, in order to see whether people appreciate them for reasons
other than just being ‘famous’. Secondly the celebrity finds the affections
of others superficial and suspicious, and seeks some way in which they
can view the ‘true’ behaviour of others.
But the ‘true’ behaviour of ordinary people must be experienced
candidly, without their being aware of celebrities, cameras and microphones – a realm which is itself constructed by the culture industry and
formalized in ‘candid camera’ genres of television. Opposite the celebrity, the
ordinary media consumer cannot have access to an intimate or empathic
connection with their media hero either. To do so would be to transgress
a boundary that cannot be crossed in any open sense. According to
Meyrowitz (1994), however, there is a restricted sense in which this
becomes realized – where a fan accumulates a very private obsession with
a celebrity, to the point that they become ‘media friends’. In a culture
where electronic relationships can become as real as physical ones, some
categories of fans may come to confuse the two in strange ways, and live
their physical life in relation to the screen identification. Fans become so
obsessed with being like them that they take on their appearance, surround themselves with their iconic memorabilia, or may even stalk the
same person, or, in the most extreme case of not being able to reconcile the
virtual with the physical, threaten to kill them, or actually succeed in their
murder (see Meyrowitz, 1994: 63–4).
Of course, when fans act out such behaviour ‘fanatically’ (which is
the root of the term applied to them), they become not friends but others,
as ‘strangers’ whose strangeness is inversely measurable alongside the
214
COMMUNICATION THEORY
fame of the star. This affirms not only the privacy of the celebrity, but also
the boundary division between media and ordinary.
This division traps the star as much as the fan, shrinking the field of
legitimate relationships to celebrity circles as their personality is so
overdetermined by the image. As such, the celebrity must not only act on
the set, but also act out a role as an heroic individual among other heroes.
They are the last flâneurs, bathing themselves in the crowd.
Moreover, media influence the behaviour of non-celebrities who
might appear in it. Individuals modify their behaviour on TV in terms of
narratives of expectation.31 This is as binding on the celebrity as it might
be on a viewer. Paradoxically, the over-exposure of a celebrity via the
image can become suffocating to the point that they feel they do not get
any attention outside of playing the glamorous roles that are expected of
them. On occasions this may result in being attracted to scandal for its
own sake, or, in some recent cases, petty shoplifting – Jennifer Capriati
and Winona Ryder.
Ultimately, the position of the celebrity can be quite fatalistic, their
immersion in their own image leaving little room for escape, an index of
which is the high rate of suicide among celebrities. Such suicide may also
affect the behaviour of fans, who may become deeply melancholic or even
commit suicide themselves insofar as they are enveloped by the pathos of
their object-fixation.32 A study by Wasserman (1984) showed that reported
celebrity deaths by suicide are more likely to be imitated than are noncelebrity suicides. Alternatively, obsessive object relations with celebrities
may result in some order of resentment towards the inequality of the culture industry. Celebrities hire security guards for their protection, and
some of those who want to walk the streets and be like everyone else
might end up paying the price, as John Lennon did.33
Rituals of audience community – metonymous identification
Whilst the celebrity might swing between the heroic and the melancholic,
audiences have recourse to several forms of narrative through which
to ‘live’ their relationship to broadcast culture. After all, they do have
choice over the programming and genres of media events in which they
participate.
In the following discussion, focusing on television audiences, I will
describe some of these genres in terms of the way they bring about variations of audience community, but also some ways in which these mediumcommunities become consummated through behaviour on the Internet. In
nearly all of the formats and genres I examine, the main ritual being
enacted by television audiences is to identify with what is happening in a
television studio metonymously. That is, it is as though what happens in
the studio is somehow able to substitute for a larger reality beyond the
screen. A field of recognition is established by which the activity in the
Telecommunity
215
studio metonymically stands in for, is substituted for, a reality which
cannot be otherwise represented, such as the audience itself.
Television news is an important starting point for understanding the
temporal life of audience communities. Whether on free-to-air or cable,
television news functions as a hub around which other kinds of programming are organized. The major evening bulletin provides a time-mark for
the end of the working day and the beginning of a sense of private control of one’s pleasure. This time-mark is itself heavily promoted by the
networks in the expectation that news service loyalty will lead to channel
loyalty for the rest of the evening. Freeway billboards and internal promotion aggressively market news programming for its comprehensiveness, its parochial expertise, or simply because the presenters appeal to
the image of a surrogate family who will look after the viewer’s needs.
The format of news itself provides comfort to audiences in the very
regularity of its structure. On commercial media this format usually
involves some variation of a proven sequence, beginning with stories that
have photo opportunities, car crashes, local politicians, national then
international sound bites, followed by a three-minute world news roundup, sport, weather and the mandatory human interest story in conclusion.
The predictability of such programming, and the fact that its affective
pattern shows little variation, from violence-rage, to public figures offering a voice of reason, to the closure of a cat rescued from a tree, offers a
constancy in viewers’ lives that may compensate for the disorder of the
working day. Thus, the performativity of the news is carried by both its
formulaic sequencing and its serialization from day to day.
No other television genre quite has this constancy and availability,
which is why news is invariably a flagship for channel loyalty. The point
here is that this quality of constancy is evident independently of the actual
content of news texts. That narrative details change each day reaffirms the
durability of the genre itself. Thus the ritual of television news is not
related to any kind of bardic ‘textual’ function of representation (see Fiske
and Hartley, 1978), but to the fact of its performance and the authority of
this performance.
The metaphysical grounding of such authority is a doctrine of representation as vision, in which language is a ‘system of representation’
rather than a form of activity (see Carey, 1989: 80). But also, news is
invested with an authority by which its producers are bestowed with the
power to metonymically manage, codify and organize the representation
of the world for us. The world is substituted by a referential format that
‘stands in’ for some larger, unknown reality.
As a visual, ephemeral medium, television news elevates the doctrine
of expressive realism to a high point that is expressed in the fetish of the
‘photo opportunity’. The ephemeral dimension which distinguishes TV
news from the press is its preoccupation with ‘live’ footage. The expectations of ‘liveness’, which are in conflict with the regulated timetabling of
television news, is accommodated by the continuous obsession with
216
COMMUNICATION THEORY
updates of news, sport and weather. But what is concealed in the
announcement of ‘breaking news’ is the way in which all broadcasted
news is live, in a way that news based on information retrieval is not.
Almost all broadcast news services all over the world have a mirror site on
the World Wide Web, but none of these sites have a specular status, except
insofar as they are consumed as a substitute for a centre of broadcast.
The fact that television news cultivates a synchronous relation with
audiences makes possible the determination of every news announcement
as an event. The event is the activity of the broadcast itself, not the representation of something anterior to the broadcast. This is something that
news shares with all ‘events’ in the media.
However, an everyday appreciation of this is often obscured by the
fact that the routine quality of media is ‘programmed’ ahead of time on
the part of producers, and within a representational ontology. It is, by definition, without spontaneity and instantaneity. Insofar as audiences live
their relation to programming within a process model, such an aesthetics
of reception governs their experience of television events.
The live event But television programming becomes ordinary and routine,
except in relation to the possibility that it may be interrupted. In such a
case the extraordinary media event itself can become a genre which
claims a double status of ‘liveness’, live in relation to a non-media reality,
and live in relation to a surprising departure from programming. As
Dayan and Katz (1992) theorize this media form:
The most obvious difference between media events and other formulas of
genres of broadcasting is that they are, by definition, not routine. In fact,
they are interruptions of routine; they intervene in the normal flow of broadcasting in our lives. Like the holidays that contrast with daily everyday
routines, television events propose exceptional things to think about, to witness, and to do. Regular broadcasting is suspended and preempted as we
are guided by a series of special announcements and preludes that transform daily life into something special and, upon the conclusion of the event,
are guided back again. In the most characteristic event, the interruption is
monopolistic, in that all channels switch away from their regularly scheduled programming in order to turn to the great event, perhaps leaving a
handful of independent stations outside the consensus. Broadcasting can
hardly make a more dramatic announcement of the importance of what is
about to happen. (403–4)
The authority of the broadcast medium is never more heightened
than in the interruptive live event, yet it is also more involving of audiences who may feel a special connection precisely in the singularity and
distinctiveness of the event. The event, which can be as banal as a breakdown in transmission followed by an announcement of the ‘return of normal
programming’, provides a time-stamp that stands out from the ‘pounding’
of regular programming.
Telecommunity
217
The talk show The genre of the television talk show with a studio audience
introduces another source of ‘liveness’ which adds a layer of ritual that
reinforces a depth of feeling in audience communities. Talk shows like
those of Jerry Springer which involve the audience, or Trisha, stand at the
intersection of two forms of association: namely a physical assembly
which acts as the content of an electronic assembly.34 Both forms of assembly are asymmetrical, with most participants having little opportunity to
speak compared to hosts and select guests. The two audiences become
overlaid in interesting ways. The embodied audience is live at the point
of production and consumption, whereas the electronic audience is usually only live at the point of consumption. However, by way of identification with the embodied audience, the electronic audience is able to feel as
though they are there, involved with the proceedings as much as the
studio audience they are identifying with. As McLaughlin (1993) suggests
in her review of the work of Carpignano:
The presence of the public on television ‘produces a short circuit in the
dichotomy’ between textual production and reception. The studio audience
participates in both the viewing of the text and its scripting, while the home
viewer ‘monitors a space where a negotiation of textual meanings is in
progress much in the same way as his [sic] personal negotiation with
the screen’. ‘The act of viewing a text becomes an act of viewing an act of
viewing’. (45)
Whilst the television audience clearly identifies with the studio audience and both audiences identify with the talk show host, the host typically lacks the spatial authority that is bestowed on film stars, news
presenters, pop stars or any figure who occupies a form of stage. As
McLaughin observes, the talk show host mingles with the audience, and
has the role of an intermediary rather than an expert (45). The genre is one
of reversing the power relations between stage and audience via a
metaphoric displacement of the studio audience by the TV audience. The
studio audience is ‘literally’ on centre stage. The show is constructed
around the audience and defined by their involvement. The studio audience is supposed to exhibit forms of folk knowledge and home truths
which are privileged over any expertise on the part of the host or guest
commentators.
Thus, the talk show is a prominent example of the way in which
broadcast enables forms of reciprocity without interaction between a large
number of persons who are nevertheless profoundly involved with the
affective identifications between the audiences, guests, hosts and companions in the viewing or studio experience. These identifications are,
I argue, largely metonymic.
At the individual level, the field of recognition of the talk show provides for the possibility of intimacy with very large audiences as well as
a sense that an ordinary person may become a ‘representative’ performer
218
COMMUNICATION THEORY
on behalf of those millions of viewers who will never get that chance:
‘Talk shows make sense for many performers, as means of dealing with
their normal “invisibility”. They are, following Thompson, “struggles of
visibility” – a matter of “being seen before the social gaze, before a representative sample of the social body”’ (Couldry, 2003: 118). The appearance
of people on talk shows individually overcomes the problem of ‘ordinariness’ that television audiences suffer whilst more generally reinforcing
the division between ordinary and media culture. For the individual
involved, it is ‘less a comment on how trashy they are and more a comment on the exclusiveness of television and the limited access of ordinary
people to media representation’ (Gamson, cited in Couldry, 2003: 118).
But talk shows also provide for, indeed excel in, the spectacle of
shaming – the modern-day confessional box. Couldry (2003) argues that
‘whatever the artificiality and indeed cruelty of such shows and their
attendant ethical problems, part of their significance for performers derives
from the opportunity they represent, against the odds, to be seen before a
public audience, to emerge from invisibility’ (118). Given how much the
modern individual is atomized and physically sequestered from others,
Couldry argues that we become very accepting of ‘action at a distance’
with, or on behalf of, others. But, he suggests, ‘the price of the expansion
of the boundaries of private experience, if indeed that is what is occurring, is to submit that experience to the power dimensions of the mediation process’ (116). These power dimensions are shaped by the theme of
the talk show (shaming, celebratory, etc.), the field of recognition that the
host encourages between the guests and the two audiences, the spatial
authority that the guests are given on the stage, and numerous other factors
which the guests have no control over. This careful stage-management in
turn limits the ‘reality effect’ of the show, in relation to which guests are
encouraged to break out of the boundaries of their ‘visibility trap’ (125).
When the guests do this, their actions are not just ‘real’ but are part of the
‘really real’. The ‘really real’, Couldry explains, ‘is the moment when something “genuinely” uncontrolled happens in the highly controlled setting
of the studio’ (125). Thus, it is the display of emotion, in the form of tears
or violence between confessional subjects of a talk show, that receives its
impact precisely because it is the opposite of the controlled, linear, composed production values of nearly all television formats.
Paradoxically, the communication of ‘emotion’ in this way, as something that television is otherwise incapable of conveying in its scripted
genres, also appeals to being able to ‘represent’ the emotions of viewers,
whose participation is displaced and metaphoric. But their identification
is potentially far more powerful than that which they may have with a
celebrity. For a start it may be cathartic that, finally, an ‘ordinary person’ is
able to make their feelings known on air. There may be a sense of justice
for the viewer also. Now ‘we can hear our side’ of the story rather than the
envy-sponsored preoccupations of the rich and famous. Then there is
the amplification of the reality effect that results from the fact that, whilst
Telecommunity
219
the non-celebrity is expected to perform, they are perceived to have no
special agenda to do with some image they are trying to cultivate, which
is the skill of celebrity. Instead, a field of identification is established
where we ‘really get to know them for who they really are’.
Reality television The talk show is an important forerunner of reality TV,
which institutionalizes a cluster of practices by which the symbolic
inequalities between media and ‘ordinary’ culture can be redressed. But
this again is only from the standpoint of guests, who feel they are able to
act as representatives of their ‘ordinary’ colleagues, and for individual
viewers, who might identify a guest as ‘standing in’ for them in some
way. Nevertheless, reality TV provides for forms of reciprocity, again by
metonymous identification, which operate without the need for direct
interaction.
It ought to be pointed out that the enormous popularity of reality
television formats since the mid-1990s coincides with the rise of the
Internet as a medium which, in McLuhanist terms, has reworked the
dominant medium of television. Simply put, reality TV is a genre in which
the audience appears interchangeable with the producer. In a media landscape where individuals might expect greater visibility by dint of the
possibilities of self-publishing on the Internet, so too this ‘struggle for
visibility’ demands greater audience participation in traditional broadcast
media.
Of course, the appearance of interchangeability is all it is. It is not
possible for the whole of the audience to be so exchanged, only a random
selection of that audience. But if the majority of an audience identify with
persons who are seen to be legitimate representatives, the exchange takes
on a convincing, even exciting, quality. This is because, as James Carey
(1989) suggests:
In our time reality is scarce because of access: so few command the machinery for its determination. Some get to speak and some to listen, some to
write and some to read, some to film and some to view … there is not only
class conflict in communication but status conflict as well. (87–8)
What is also illusory is the idea that a reality TV show such as
Endemol Corporation’s thirty-seven-country formula Big Brother is somehow ‘raw’ and ‘unscripted’, whereas its narrative is so one-dimensionally
determined by the gaze of the camera, architecture and editing.
Whichever version one turns to – Dutch, Australian, French – the same
kinds of cloistered interactions are developed, along with the same
processes of othering – shaming, heroic adulation, sympathy.
These three elements – camera gaze, architecture and editing – combine
to produce a peculiar effect in television convention, the inauguration of
surveillance as a mediated spectacle (Andrejevic, 2004: 2). A distinct field
of recognition is established in such programming by which audiences,
220
COMMUNICATION THEORY
via metonymous identification, watch themselves being watched in a
form which is a potential mis-en-abyme. It is possible for a spectator to
become a participant and vice versa – such that being in front of a camera
and being in front of a screen become interchangeable.
In his book Reality TV: The Work of Being Watched (2004), Andrejevic
cites an example of being both participant and spectator at once. He introduces the case of a web-cam artist, Anna Voog, who once placed on-line
video of herself watching ‘Big Brother’ on a lazy Saturday. In this instance,
Andrejevic argues, Voog is
caught between her television and her camera. … On the one hand is the
promise of interactivity – that access to the means of media production will
be thrown open to the public at large, so that ‘everyone can have their own
TV show’. … On the other hand is the reality represented by reality TV – that
interactivity functions increasingly as a form of productive surveillance
allowing for the commodification of the products generated by what I call
the work of being watched. (2)
For Andrejevic, the surveillance culture possible in reality TV works
‘neatly as an advertisement for the benefits of submission to comprehensive surveillance in an era in which such submission is increasingly productive’ (2). For Andrejevic, reality TV is not a democratization of
television because it only permits the gates of participation to be opened
once its subjects, including the viewers, have submitted to the authority
of surveillence. This authority stamps itself on the legitimacy of other telemediated practices such as the web-cam. Voog’s web-page itself highlights the way in which ‘viewers themselves were increasingly being
watched in the age of interactive media that have ostensibly ushered in an
era of the end of privacy’ (2).
The personal web-page Andrejevic argues that personal web-cams and webpages double as a home-grown version of reality TV. However, the control that we have over such images is seen to be emancipatory, unlike the
highly regulated images that are wrought by the televisual medium.
Thus, he ultimately endorses a second media age view that ‘[t]he internet
allows people like [Voog] to become content producers, rather than
remaining merely media consumers’ and offers them ‘the ability to control the product of their creative labour’ (5).
Thus, in the face of mass-mediated symbolic inequality, the personal
web-page breaks up the monopoly of the culture industry. This in turn is
said to explain the very fashionability of private web-pages and webcams. Cheung (2000), another theorist of this trend, argues for its emancipatory status as it ‘allows ordinary people to present their “selves” to the
net public’. Such emancipation is achieved by three means. Firstly, there
is the size of the ‘audience’ that it can reach, which, whilst not on the same
scale as that experienced by media celebrities, goes some way towards
Telecommunity
221
redressing the imbalance between the poles of broadcast circulation.
Secondly, the bandwidth and ability to convey complexity in image,
music and text allows for richer forms of ‘impression management’ than
are achieved in face-to-face interaction. Thirdly, it is emancipatory
because it ‘insulates’ the author from any embarrassment, and avoids the
possibility of rejection that is experienced in mutual presence (Cheung,
2000: 49).
But Cheung does not explore the nature of web-page audiences, or
deconstruct the idea that their authors are ‘ordinary’ and ‘amateur’ (43).
The fact that such characterization is assigned already indicates the
necessarily ‘reactive’ nature of such a practice. Which is to say, personal
home-pages are not a derivative of Internet communication, but are in fact
yet another ritual of audience communities.
To go back to Anna Voog, who manages in practice to make of her
own person a viewer and a producer, such a convergence, which Andrejevic
makes into a vignette of old and new media convergence, can be argued
to have already been attained within the dynamics of broadcast architecture itself. Voog merely has recourse to the technological means of displacing the aura of the image onto the apparatus or means of
communication. It is the apparatus which becomes reified, as the image
becomes a metonymic condensation of the audience. The television audience can see themselves in such images, without making this the reflexive
subject of a further broadcast on web-cam.
Telecommunity
Electronically mediated communication to some degree supplements
existing forms of sociability but to another extent substitutes for them.
New and unrecognizable modes of community are in the process of formation and it is difficult to discern exactly how these will contribute to or
detract from postmodern politics. (Poster, 1990: 154)
The term ‘telecommunity’ can be found in the text of Alvin Toffler’s The
Third Wave (1980). Without endorsing the historicism of this text, we can
say that Toffler’s description of technologically extended community as a
social form is one that is useful in a general way.
Long before the Internet, Toffler points out that technological extension is a general feature of late-capitalist societies, but that the distinctive
form of community which it makes possible is by way of the ‘selective substitution of communication for transportation’ (382). For Toffler, the dispersal of populations across cities, and between home and work, creates
unnecessary anomie. When communications begin to replace commuting,
he argues, it can actually revitalize face-to-face relationships insofar as it
enables work-from-home (a prophecy of modern telework) where family
bonds and time for neighbourhood bonds are enhanced.35 At the same
222
COMMUNICATION THEORY
time, people who are shy or invalid can pursue community on the basis of
interests – again a prophecy of how the Internet is actually used.
Of course, Toffler, like the second media age theorists of more than a
decade later, saw the limitations of television in its lack of interactivity.36
In line with the second media age thesis, he held great optimism for the
ability of extended interaction to help create community, but was opposed
to the idea of the ‘electronic cottage’ simply replacing other levels of community such as the face-to-face.
Toffler’s enthusiasm for community being made across a range of
intersecting levels can be better appreciated if we incorporate the insights
of the ritual views of communication. To do so is to immediately recognize the value of both broadcast and Internet community as levels of community which can be negotiated with face-to-face levels of integration.
As we have seen in this chapter, virtual or telemediated community is
possible within both broadcast and network architectures of communication. The rituals involved in each kind of community differ, as do the fields
of identification that they produce. What they have in common, however,
is the character of enabling participation at a distance, in a movement of
expansion and contraction. Increasingly, the basis of consuming media
retreats to private media spaces, and from this privacy, individuals are able
to reach out to more global forms of connection, where those older intermediate forms of community have all but disappeared.
This double movement of media ritual, the expansion of public forms
of display and visibility, but only from the interface of privately controlled
spaces, marks a general change in the nature of ‘interaction’. Between
these forces, to interact with others is to interact with media. Such media
receive their power from the fact they have a constancy that endures
beyond any particular individual communication event. This is expressed
in everything from the techno-spiritualism which worships divine communion in cyberspace, to the everyday micro-rituals of media consumption explored in this book.
Whether electronic mediated communication extends or substitutes
for intermediate forms of community, this book has also argued that it can
strongly be identified as a driver of urban and global culture which, whilst
uneven in the way it is connected to the transmission of local cultures, nevertheless establishes quite distinct forms of culture itself, which have their
own rituals. Studying these rituals in the coming decades and how they
are related to social integration will be a task central to the social sciences.
Notes
Parts of this chapter are derived from reviews and conference presentations or proceedings
which I have presented or published. These are: a review of Barney, Darin, Prometheus
Wired: The Hope for Democracy in the Age of Network Technology, The Australian Journal of
Political Science, 2001, 36 (3): 618–619, and Holmes, D. (1998) ‘Sociology without the
Telecommunity
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
223
Social? Governmentality and Globalisation’, in Refashioning Sociology: Responses to a New
World Order. Brisbane: QUT Publications, pp. 167–173.
Where the social exists outside the nation-state, it does so in ‘supra-national’ bodies
(WHO, UN, etc.).
Of course, all of these nominated contenders for community can be considered ‘imagined communities’ in the Andersonian sense (Anderson, 1983). However, insofar as
they are made possible by mediated publicness, and it is only though this kind of publicness that individuals gain access to these imagined communities, they are also lived
as the really real.
The discursive formation of community, as a kind of ‘intermediate’ level of social integration, would, within a levels argument, fit well within the secondary, agency-extended
levels of integration outlined in Chapter 5.
Anderson in Imagined Communities (1983) conjectures that one of the reasons for
the stability of the nation-state is the ‘remarkable confidence of community in
anonymity’ (40).
Whether it is about tuning in to the same radio or television time slot, or adopting the
newspaper as our ‘morning prayer’, as Hegel once suggested, or visiting the same bookmarks on our web-browser, the interface of which itself has a familiar and reassuring pixilated architecture, or whether we are at home at the cybercafé, all of these places are
practised to the point of a uniformity which can be monumental in character. One can
relate to the standardization of media architectures like a web-browser or a news performance in the same way as monuments might become references for a traveller.
For an analysis of the physical and architectural qualities of these spaces, see Holmes
(2001).
An alternative to the user perspective in self/technology relations is provided by Steven
Johnson in his idea of ‘interface culture’, which is measured by the degree that aesthetic
values are a part of a technological environment. It is not simply a matter of computers
and other hardware/software configurations being ‘user-friendly’. Rather, the ‘computer
must also represent itself to the user, in a language the user understands’ (Johnson,
1997: 14).
For example, educationalists are interested in whether classroom environments can
keep up with ‘cyberspace’. Moursund (1996) posed the question of the rate of change in
cyberspace to a sample of fifty administrators, who thought that changes in the dynamics and modes of possibility in cyberspace were about eighteen times faster than in
embodied space (4).
Computer companies certainly are interested in developing their own historical
mythology and aura around their products. For example, every piece of software from
Microsoft Corporation is accompanied by a certificate of authenticity which is printed
on cloth that has the image of ‘Augusta Ada Byron, collaborator of Charles Babbage in
the nineteenth century’. Ada is also trademarked by the US Department of Defense.
Ada is the name of its Proprietary Programming Language (see Plant, 1998: 14–22).
From Plato’s Republic, to Saint-Simon, Thomas More and William Morris, this tradition
has been a powerful one in the West.
The grand discourse of the perils of the Internet is that of the super-panopticon, which
itself has a genesis myth – that of the Library of Babel – ‘of the universe as a repository
of information’ (Whitaker, 2000: 48) The use of the Internet as an encyclopedic basis for
surveillance presents ever greater risks to privacy the more information comes to mediate all categories of activity. The accumulation of information also makes possible an
enlightenment in reverse.
Whilst he does not acknowledge the fact, Tofts is here replicating the point which the
philosopher Jacques Derrida makes about difference in language as constituted in the
last instance by language-as-writing, in which the mark or the gram within a signifier is
the minimal basis of conceptuality. Thus his invention of différance as a replacement of
the French différence, where the ‘a’ is silent when spoken and is noticeable only in its
written form. See Derrida (1986).
224
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
COMMUNICATION THEORY
‘Interactivity has almost turned into a dull buzzword. The term is so inflated now that
one begins to suspect that there is much less to it than some people want to make it
appear’ (Schultz, 2000: 205; see also Silverstone, 1999: 95).
The bourgeois flâneur is also a mythic hero of cultural studies (see Wark, 1999). The hero
stays up late, lives in the inner city, can identify with those in poverty, but never has to
suffer it. As we shall see soon, the electronic flâneurs of the Internet display the same
characteristics: they aestheticize their sessions of surfing, they want to save everyone
else, and substitute the Internet for the world, oblivious to the fact that 90% of the world
does not use the Internet, and for most of them, it would not be of any assistance if they
did. There is even a dandy form of such electronic flâneurs, who put up their own
web-page with elaborate image, music and text.
It is worth noting Nikolai Gogol’s introduction to his love story ‘Nevsky Prospect’, set
in St Petersburg circa 1835. Here the street itself becomes the hero (cited in Berman,
1992: 195–6).
As with virtual flânerie, embodied flânerie was an interaction based on a contained information set. Whereas, on the Internet, what you know about others might be confined to
images or texts, with the traditional flâneur it was the image.
Recall here numerous appraisals of the Internet as home to the avatar.
‘The hero of modern life is he who lives in the public spaces of the city’ (Tester, 1996: 5).
According to Paul Virilio (2001), the ‘immediacy and instantaneity’ of modern information present ‘serious problems for contemporary society’ (23–4).
This view is very common among Internet utopians. See, especially, Gauntlett (2000: 13),
Rheingold (1994), Whittle (1996: 241ff).
Exemplary is Negroponte (1995), who argues that the real benefits of Internet sub-media
are that they routinize asynchronous communication, making it possible to communicate with whom you want to when you want to, and you do not have to respond spontaneously to other human beings. The more one spends one’s life on-line, the more this
becomes a way of life (see 167ff).
A definition which echoes many of the terms found in microeconomic theory.
This binary they describe as Manichaean, ‘duelling dualists who feed off each other,
using the unequivocal assertions of the other side as foils for their arguments’ (167).
One way of overcoming this ontological binary is to suggest, as Roger Silverstone (1999)
does, that ‘all communities are virtual communities’. He explains: ‘The symbolic expression
and definition of community, both with or without electronic media, has been established as a sine qua non of our sociability. Communities are imagined and we participate
in them both with and without the face-to-face, both with and without touch’ (104).
But for an empirical study that does, see the Stanford ‘Internet and Society Study’ (Nie
and Erdring, 2000), discussed in Chapter 4.
For Stoll, network interactions are ‘superficial’ (23).
The punitive function of visibility is not as common today, with the exception of ‘public humiliation’ TV shows. See below the discussion of talk shows.
‘Television significantly constitutes a domain in which people ordinarily share experiences of the same complex social messages’ (Livingstone, 1990: 1).
Here note the case of ‘Northern Exposure’ in Canada and ‘Seachange’ in Australia.
‘Seachange’ was an extremely popular public broadcast series about a small seaside
community known as ‘Pearl Bay’, which was filmed at the town of Barwin Heads in
southern Victoria. After the series had attracted a cult following in 1999, the residents of
the town met at the town hall to discuss whether they should change the town’s name
to ‘Pearl Bay’. An analysis was made of how beneficial such a change would be for
tourism, which was already picking up. However, the series came to an end, and
Barwin Heads has retained its name. Nevertheless, some of the sets in the film have
been repurposed for media pilgrimages, such as ‘Diver Dan’s Shed’, now a restaurant.
This genre is the obverse of a format in which the ‘ordinary’ person masquerades as
part of an elite (Sunset Boulevard, Dave and Desperately Seeking Susan).
Telecommunity
31
225
Langer (1997: 167) advances that TV and cinema have different personality systems,
with the star system of cinema maintaining spectacle-at-a-distance and television
providing an idiom of intimacy.
32 Or the reporting of celebrity assassinations. ‘Following John Lennon’s murder, a
teenage girl in Florida and a 30-year-old man in Utah killed themselves. Their suicide
notes spoke of depression over Lennon’s death’ (Meyrowitz, 1994: 64).
33 As Meyrowitz notes, for Mark David Chapman, the murderer of John Lennon, the
killing unravelled a tragic negotiation with his alter ego. Chapman believed he was
Lennon, and emulated him in every way. ‘John Lennon Killed by Stranger’ was the
headline in December 1980, but Meyrowitz points out he was a close media ‘friend’.
‘In a sense, John Lennon was killed by the sinister side of the same force that makes
millions still mourn him and other dead media heroes, a new sense of connection to
selected strangers created by those modern media that simulate the sights and sounds
of real-life interactions’ (Meyrowitz, 1994: 63).
34 When exploring talk shows, it is necessary to acknowledge the variety of formats, including therapeutic, confessional, the studio debate between lay people or a panel of experts,
and programmes that draw out conflict between friends and lovers. As Couldry (2003:
120) observes, however, whatever their content, all talk shows have an underlying ritual
form, which is about legitimately entering a television space, to engage in a form of intimacy with a broad public which is not possible in any other forum.
35 Certainly this is true of some Net groups, as Willson (1997) narrates. It is worth noting
that virtual community participants often feel the need to reinforce/complement their
disembodied relations by simulating, at the level of ritual, more embodied or sensorial
contacts. For example, participants on the WELL, a virtual community on the Internet,
have regular face-to-face picnics and social gatherings. The participants develop a more
complete understanding of each other at such gatherings (Rheingold, 1994: 21).
36 ‘The emerging info-sphere will make possible interactive electronic contact with others
who share similar interest ... such relationships can provide a far better antidote to loneliness than television as we know it today, in which the messages all flow one way and
the passive receiver is powerless to interact with the flickering image on the screen’ (383).
REFERENCES
Adilkno (The Foundation for the Advancement of Illegal Knowledge) (1998).
‘Probing McLuhan’, in Media Archive, New York: Autonomedia.
Adorno, T. (1954). ‘Television and the Patterns of Mass Culture’, Quarterly of Film,
Radio, and Television, Vol. 8.
Adorno, T. and Horkheimer, M. (1993). ‘The Culture Industry: Enlightenment as
Mass Deception’, in S. During (ed.), The Cultural Studies Reader, London:
Routledge.
Agamben, G. (1993). The Coming Community, trans. M. Hardt, Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Alexander, J. (1986). ‘The “Form” of Substance: The Senate Watergate Hearings as
Ritual’, in S.J. Ball-Rokeach and M.G. Cantor (eds), Media, Audience and Social
Structure, London: Sage.
Alford, J. (1983). ‘The Myth of False Consciousness’, Australian Left Review, No. 84,
Winter, pp. 6–9.
Althusser, L. (1971). Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, trans. Ben Brewster,
New York: Monthly Review Press.
Anderson, B. (1983). Imagined Communities, London: Verso.
Anderson, B. and Tracey, K. (2001). ‘Digital Living: The Impact (or Otherwise) of
the Internet on Everyday Life’, unpublished research, Suffolk, UK, Btax CT
Research.
Andrejevic, M. (2004). Reality TV: The Work of Being Watched, Lanham, MD:
Rowman and Littlefield.
Ang, I. (1991). Desperately Seeking the Audience, London: Routledge.
Ang, I. (1996). Living Room Wars: Rethinking Media Audiences for a Postmodern
World, New York: Routledge.
Austin, J.L. (1962). How to Do Things with Words, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Barney, D. (2000). Prometheus Wired: The Hope of Democracy in the Age of Network
Technology, Sydney: University of New South Wales Press.
Barr, T. (2000). Newsmedia.Com.Au: The Changing Face of Australia’s Media and
Communications, St Leonards: Allen and Unwin.
Baudelaire, C. (1972). ‘The Painter of Modern Life’, in Baudelaire: Selected
Writings on Art and Literature, trans. P.E. Charvet. Harmondsworth: Penguin,
pp. 395–422.
Baudrillard, J. (1982). Simulations, New York: Semiotext(e).
Baudrillard, J. (1983). ‘The Implosion of Meaning in the Media’, in In the Shadow of
the Silent Majorities, trans. P. Foss, J. Johnston and P. Patton, New York:
Semiotext(e).
References
227
Baudrillard, J. (1988). ‘Los Angeles Freeways’, in America, trans. C. Turner, London:
Verso.
Baym, N. (1995). ‘The Emergence of Community in Computer-Mediated
Communication’, in S. Jones (ed.), Cybersociety: Computer-Mediated Communication
and Community, London: Sage.
Baym, N. (1998). ‘The Emergence of On-line Community’, in S. Jones (ed.),
Cybersociety 2.0: Revisiting Computer-Mediated Communication and Community,
London: Sage.
Baym, N. (2000). Tune In, Log On: Soaps, Fandom, and Online Community, London: Sage.
Becker, B. and Wehner, J. (1998). ‘Electronic Media and Civil Society’, in
Proceedings of Cultural Attitudes Towards Technology and Communication, 1st
Conference, available at http://www.it.murdoch.edu.au/~sudweeks/catac98/
Bell, C. and Newby, H. (1976). ‘Communion, Communalism, Class and Community
Action: The Sources of New Urban Politics’, in D. Herbert and R. Johnston (eds),
Social Areas in Cities, Vol. 2. Chichester: Wiley.
Bell, C. and Newby, H. (1974). The Sociology of Community: A Selection of Readings,
London: Cass & Co.
Bell, D. (1962). ’America as a Mass Society: A Critique’, in The End of Ideology: On
the Exhaustion of Political Ideas in the Fifties, New York: Free Press.
Bell, D. (1980). ‘A Reply to Weizenbaum’, in T. Forrester (ed.), The Microelectronics
Revolution: The Complete Guide to the New Technology and Its Impact on Society,
Oxford: Blackwell.
Bell, D. and Kennedy, B. (2000). The Cybercultures Reader, London: Routledge.
Belsey, C. (1982). Critical Practice, London: Methuen.
Benedetti, P. and Dehard, N. (eds) (1997). Forward Through the Rearview Mirror:
Reflections on and by Marshall McLuhan, Ontario: Prentice-Hall Canada Inc.
Benedikt, M. (ed.) (1991). Cyberspace: First Steps, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Beniger, J.R. (1987). ‘Personalization of Mass Media and the Growth of Pseudocommunities’, Communication Research, Vol. 14, No. 30, 352–71.
Benjamin, W. (1977). ‘The Paris of the Second Empire in Baudelaire’, in Charles
Baudelaire: A Lyric Poet in the Era of High Capital, trans. Harry Zohn, London:
New Left Books.
Bennett, T. (1982). ‘Theories of the Media, Theories of Society’, in M. Gurevitch,
T. Bennett, J. Curran and J. Woollacott, Culture, Society and the Media, London:
Methuen.
Berman, M. (1982). All That Is Solid Melts into Air, New York: Simon and Schuster.
Bianculli, D. (1996). Dictionary of Teleliteracy: Television’s 500 Biggest Hits, Misses,
and Events, New York: Continuum.
Bishop, B. (1999). Global Marketing for the Digital Age, Lincolnwood IL: NTC
Business Books.
Black, D. (2001). ‘Internet Radio: A Case Study in Medium Specificity’, Media,
Culture & Society, Vol. 23: 397–408.
Bolter, J.D. and Grusin, R. (1999). Remediation: Understanding New Media,
Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press.
Boorstin, Daniel J. ([1961] 1962). The Image: Or, What Happened to the American
Dream, New York: Atheneum.
228
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Bott, E. (1971). Family and Social Network: Roles, Norms, and External Relationships in
Ordinary Urban Families, New York: Free Press.
Bourdieu, P. (1993). ‘Public Opinion Does Not Exist’, in Sociology in Question, trans.
R. Nice, London: Sage.
Boyer, C.M. (1996). Cybercities: Visual Perception in the Age of Electronic Communication,
New York: Princeton Architectural.
Brecht, B. (2003). ‘The Radio as an Apparatus of Communication’, in A. Everett
and J.T. Caldwell (eds), New Media: Theories and Practices of Digitextuality,
New York: Routledge.
Brosnan, M. (1998). Technophobia: The Psychological Impact of Information Technology,
London: Routledge.
Buchstein, H. (1997). ‘Bytes That Bite: The Internet and Deliberative Democracy’,
Constellations, Vol. 4, No. 2: 248–63.
Buzzard, K.S.F. (2003). ‘Net Ratings: Defining a New Medium by the Old:
Measuring Internet Audiences’, in A. Everett and J.T. Caldwell (eds), New Media:
Theories and Practices of Digitextuality, New York: Routledge.
Caldwell, J. (1995). ‘Excessive Style: The Crisis of Network Television’, in
Televisuality: Style, Crisis and Authority in American Television, New Brunswick,
NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Calhoun, C. (1986). ’Computer Technology, Large-scale Social Integration and the
Local Community’, in Urban Affairs Quarterly, Vol. 22, No. 2: 329–49.
Calhoun, C. (1992). ‘The Infrastructure of Modernity: Indirect Social Relationships,
Information Technology, and Social Integration’, in H. Haferkampf and
N. Smelser (eds), Social Change and Modernity, Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Calhoun, C. (1998). ‘Community Without Propinquity Revisited: Communications
Technology and the Transformation of the Urban Public Sphere’, Sociological
Inquiry, Vol. 68, No. 3: 373–97.
Cantril, H., Gaudet, H. and Herzog, H. (1940). The Invasion from Mars, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press.
Carey, J.W. (1969). ‘The Communications Revolution and the Professional
Communicator’, in P. Halmos (ed.), The Sociology of Mass Media Communicators,
Sociological Review Monograph 13, University of Keele.
Carey, J. (1972). ‘Harold Innis and Marshall McLuhan’, in R. Rosenthal (ed.),
McLuhan: Pro & Con, London: Pelican.
Carey, J. (1989). Communication as Culture: Essays on Media and Society, Boston:
Unwin Hyman.
Carey, J. (1995). ‘Time, Space and the Telegraph’, in D. Crowley and P. Heyer (eds),
Communication in History, White Plains, NY: Longman USA.
Carey, J. (1998). ‘Political Ritual on Television: Episodes in the History of Shame,
Degradation and Excommunication’, in T. Liebes and J. Curran (eds), Media,
Ritual, Identity, London: Routledge.
Casey, B. (2002). Television Studies: The Key Concepts, London: Routledge.
Cassidy, J. (2002). Dot.Con: The Greatest Story Ever Sold, New York: HarperCollins.
Castells, M. (1996). The Information Age: Economy, Society and Culture, Vol. 1: The
Rise of the Network Society, Malden, MA and Oxford: Blackwell.
References
229
Castells, M. (2001). The Internet Galaxy, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chakhotin, S. (1939). The Rape of the Masses: The Psychology of Political Propaganda,
trans. E.W. Dickes, New York: Alliance Book Corporation.
Chan-Olmsted, S. (2000). ‘Marketing-Mass Media on the World Wide Web:
The Building of Media Brands in an Integrated and Interactive World’, in
A.B. Albarran and D.H. Goff (eds), Understanding the Web: Social, Political and
Economic Dimensions of the Internet, Ames: Iowa State University Press.
Chesher, C. (1997). ‘An Ontology of Digital Domains’, in D. Holmes (ed.), Virtual
Politics: Identity and Community in Cyberspace, London: Sage.
Cheung, C. (2000). ‘A Home on the Web: Presentations of Self on Personal
Homepages’, in D. Gauntlett (ed.), Web.Studies: Rewiring Media Studies for the
Digital Age, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cooley, C.H. (1909). Social Organization: Study of the Larger Mind, New York:
C. Scribner’s Sons.
Corner, J. (1997). ‘Media Studies and the “Knowledge Problem”’, in T. O’Sullivan
and Y. Jewkes (eds), The Media Studies Reader, London: Arnold.
Corner, J. and Harvey, S. (1996). Television Times: A Reader, London: Arnold.
Couldry, N. (2003). Media Rituals: A Critical Approach, London: Routledge.
Crang, M., Crang, P. and May, J. (1998). Virtual Geographies: Bodies, Space and
Relations, London: Routledge.
Crowley, D. and Mitchell, D. (1995). ‘Communication in a Post-Mass Media
World’, in D. Crowley and D. Mitchell (eds), Communication Theory Today,
Cambridge: Polity.
Davis, E. (1998). Techgnosis: Myth, Magic, Mysticism in the Age of Information,
New York: Harmony.
Dayan, D. and Katz, E. (1992). Media Events: The Live Broadcasting of History,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Debord, G. (1977). The Society of the Spectacle, trans. F. Perlman and J. Supak,
Detroit: Black and Red Publications.
de Certeau, M. (1988). The Practice of Everyday Life, Los Angeles: University of
California Press.
Dempsey, K. (1998). ‘Community, Experiences and Explanations’, in A. Kellehear
(ed.), Social Self, Global Culture, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Derrida, J. (1976). Of Grammatology, trans. G.C. Spivak, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press.
Derrida, J. (1978). Writing and Difference, trans. A. Bass, London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul.
Derrida, J. (1981). Positions, trans. A. Bass, London: Athlone Press.
Derrida, J. (1986). Margins of Philosophy, trans. A. Bass, Brighton: Harvester Press.
Derrida, J. (1988). Limited Inc. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Dery, M. (ed.) (1994). Flamewars: The Discourse of Cyberculture. London: Duke
University Press.
Dery, M. (1995). ‘The Medium’s Messenger’, 21.C. Previews of a Changing World,
Vol. 2: 8–12.
Dery, M. (1996). Escape Velocity: Cyberculture at the End of the Twentieth Century,
New York: Grove Press.
230
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Di Maggio, P., Hargittai, E., Neuman, W.R. and Robinson, J. (2001). ‘The Internet’s
Effects on Society’, in Annual Reviews of Sociology, Vol. 27, 307–336.
Dizard, W. (2000). Old Media New Media: Mass Communications in the Information
Age (3rd edn), New York: Addison-Wesley Longman.
Dominick, J.R. (2001). The Dynamics of Mass Communication: Media in the Digital Age
(7th edn), Boston: McGraw-Hill.
Donath, J. (1999). ‘Identity and Deception in the Virtual Community’, in M. Smith
and P. Kollock (eds), Communities in Cyberspace, London: Routledge.
Downes, T. and Fatouros, C. (1995). Learning in an Electronic World: Computers in
the Classroom, Newtown: Primary English Teaching Association.
Droege, P. (ed.) (1997). Intelligent Environments: Spatial Aspect of the Information
Revolution. Amsterdam, New York: Elsevier.
Du Gay, P., Hall, S., James, L., Mackay, H. and Negus, K. (1997). Doing Cultural
Studies: The Story of the Sony Walkman, London: Sage in association with the
Open University.
Durkheim, E. (1982). The Rules of Sociological Method, ed. S. Lukes; trans. W.D.
Halls, New York: Free Press.
Durkheim, E. (1984). The Division of Labour in Society, Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Eade, J. (ed.) (1997). Living the Global City: Globalization as a Local Process, London:
Routledge.
Eagleton, T. (1991). Ideology, London: Verso.
Edge, D. (1988). The Social Shaping of Technology, Edinburgh: PICT Working Papers
No. 1.
Ellis, J. (1982). Visible Fictions: Cinema, Television, Video, London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Elsaesser, T. and Hoffmann, K. (eds) (1998). Cinema Futures: Cain, Abel or Cable? The
Screen Arts in the Digital Age, Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.
Escobar, A. (1994). ‘Welcome to Cyberia’, Current Anthropology, Vol. 5, No. 3, 211–31.
Ettema, J.S. and Whitney, D.C. (eds) (1994). Audiencemaking: How the Media Create
the Audience, London: Sage.
Evans, J. and Hall, S. (eds) (1999). Visual Culture: The Reader, London: Sage.
Feather, J. (2000). The Information Society: A Study of Continuity and Change
(3rd edn), London: Library Association Publications.
Featherstone, M. (1998). ‘The Flâneur, the City and Virtual Public Life’, Urban
Studies, Vol. 35, Nos. 5–6: 910–18.
Featherstone, M. and Burrows, R. (eds) (1995). Cyberspace, Cyberbodies, Cyberpunk:
Cultures of Technological Embodiment, London: Sage.
Feenberg, A. (1991). Critical Theory of Technology, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fidler, R. (1997). Mediamorphosis: Understanding New Media, Thousand Oaks, CA:
Pine Forge Press.
Finnegan, R. (2002). Communicating: The Multiple Modes of Human Communication,
London: Routledge.
Fiske, J. (1982). Introduction to Communication Studies, London: Methuen.
Fiske, J. (1987). Television Culture, London: Methuen.
Fiske, J. and Hartley, J. (1978). ‘Bardic Television’, in Reading Television, London:
Methuen.
References
231
Flew, T. (2002). New Media: An Introduction, Melbourne: Oxford University Press.
Flitterman-Lewis, S. (1992). ‘Psychoanalysis, Film and Television’ in R.C. Allen
(ed.), Channels of Discourse, Reassembled: Television and Contemporary Criticism,
Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press.
Foster, D. (1997). ‘Community and Identity in the Electronic Village’, in D. Porter
(ed.), Internet Culture, London: Routledge.
Fraser, N. (1990). ‘Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of
Actually Existing Democracy’, Social Text, Vol. 25/26: 56–80.
Friedberg, A. (1993). Window Shopping: Cinema and the Postmodern, Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Fukuyama, F. (1995). Trust: The Social Virtues and the Creation of Prosperity, New York:
Free Press.
Fukuyama, F. (1999). The Great Disruption: Human Nature and the Reconstitution of
Social Order, New York: Free Press.
Garofalo, R. (1991). ‘Understanding Mega-events: If We Are the World, Then How
Do We Change It?’, in C. Penley and A. Ross (eds), Technoculture, Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Gates, B. (1996). The Road Ahead, London: Penguin.
Gauntlett, D. (ed.) (2000). Web.Studies: Rewiring Media Studies for the Digital Age,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Gauntlett, D. and Hill, A. (1999). TV Living: Television Culture and Everyday Life,
London: Routledge.
Geraghty, C. and Lusted, D. (1998). The Television Studies Book, London: Arnold.
Gerbner, G. (1956). ‘Toward a General Model of Communication’, Audio Visual
Communication Review, Vol. IV, No. 3: 171–99.
Gergen, K.J. (1991). The Saturated Self: Dilemmas of Identity in Contemporary Life,
New York: Basic Books.
Giddens, A. (1986). Sociology: A Brief but Critical Introduction, London: Macmillan.
Giddens, A. (1987). A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism, Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Giddens, A. (1990). The Consequences of Modernity, Cambridge: Polity.
Gilder, G. (1993). ‘The Death of Telephony: Why the Telephone and TV Will Not Be
the Stars of a Communications Revolution’, The Economist, 11–17 September 1993.
Gilder, G. (1994). Life After Television, New York: Norton.
Gitlin, T. (1998). ‘Public Sphere or Public Sphericules?’, in T. Liebes and J. Curran
(eds), Media, Ritual, Identity, London: Routledge.
Gitlin, T. (2002). Media Unlimited: How the Torrent of Images and Sounds Overwhelms
Our Lives, New York: Henry Holt and Co.
Goffman, E. (1973). The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life, Woodstock, NY:
Overlook Press.
Goodheart, E. (2000). ‘Marshall McLuhan Revisited’, Partisan Review, Vol. 67: 90–100.
Gouldner, A. (1976). The Dialectic of Ideology and Technology, London: Macmillan.
Graber, D.A. (2001). Processing Politics: Learning from Television in the Internet Age,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Graham, S. (2000). Splintering Urbanism: Networked Infrastructures, Technological
Mobilities and the Urban Condition, London: Routledge.
232
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Graham, S. and Aurigi, A. (1998). ‘The “Crisis” in the Urban Public Realm’, in
B. Loader (ed.), Cyberspace Divide: Equality, Agency and Policy in the Information
Society, London: Routledge.
Graham, S. and Marvin, S. (1996). Telecommunication and the City: Electronic Spaces,
Urban Places, London: Routledge.
Grajczyk, A. and Zollner, O. (1996). ‘How Older People Watch Television: Telemetric
Data on the TV Use in Germany in 1996’, Gerontology, Vol. 44, No. 3: 176–81.
Green, B. and Bigum, C. (1993). ‘Aliens in the Classroom’, Australian Journal of
Education, Vol. 37, No. 2: 119–41.
Greenfield, C. (1999). ‘Home Alone? Mobile Privatization and the Transformation
of Work’, in J. Lee, B. Probert and R. Watts (eds), Work in the New Economy:
Policies, Programs, Populations, Melbourne: Centre for Applied Social Research,
RMIT University.
Guattari, F. (1986). ’The Postmodern Dead End’, Flash Art, No. 128: 40–1.
Guest, A.M. and Wierzbiki, S.K. (1999). ‘Social Ties at the Neighbourhood Level:
Two Decades of GSS Evidence’, Urban Affairs Review, Vol. 35, No. 1: 92–111.
Gumbrecht, H.U. and Marrinan, M. (eds) (2003). Mapping Benjamin: The Work of
Art in the Digital Age, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Habermas, J. (1974). ‘The Public Sphere: An Encyclopedia Article’, in E. Bronner
and D. Kellner (eds), Critical Theory and Society: A Reader, London: Routledge.
Habermas, J. (1984). The Theory of Communicative Action (Vol. 1), London:
Heinemann.
Habermas, J. ([1962] 1989). The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An
Inquiry into Bourgeois Society, trans. T. Burger and F. Lawrence, Cambridge: Polity.
Habermas, J. (1992). ‘Further Reflections on the Public Sphere’, in C. Calhoun
(ed.), Habermas and the Public Sphere, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hall, P. and Brotchi, J. (eds) (1991). Cities of the 21st Century: New Technologies and
Spatial Systems, Melbourne: Longman Cheshire.
Hall S. (1977). ‘Culture, the Media and the “Ideological Effect’’’, in J. Curram,
M. Gurevitch and J. Woollacott (eds), Mass Communication and Society, London:
Arnold.
Hall, S. (1980). ‘Encoding/Decoding’, in S. Hall, D. Hobson, A. Lowe and P. Wills
(eds), Culture, Media, Language: Working Papers in Cultural Studies, 1972–79,
London: Hutchinson.
Hall, S. (1982). ‘The Rediscovery of “Ideology”: Return of the Repressed in Media
Studies’, in M. Gurevitch, T. Bennett, J. Curram and J. Woollacott (eds), Culture,
Society and the Media, London: Methuen.
Hall, S., Cruz, J. and Lewis, J. (1994). ‘Reflections upon the Encoding/Decoding
Model: An Interview with Stuart Hall’, in J. Cruz and J. Lewis (eds), Viewing,
Reading, Listening: Audiences and Cultural Reception, Boulder, Co: Westview.
Hanks, W.F. (1996). Language and Communicative Practices, Boulder, Co: Westview.
Haraway, D.J. (1991). ‘A Manifesto for Cyborgs’, in Simians, Cyborgs and Women:
The Reinvention of Nature, New York: Routledge.
Hartley, J. (1992a). Tele-ology: Studies in Television, London: Routledge.
Hartley, J. (1992b). The Politics of Pictures: The Creation of the Public in the Age of
Popular Media, New York: Routledge.
References
233
Hartley, J. (1998). ‘This Way Lies Habermadness’, Media International Australia,
No. 88: 125–35.
Harvey, D. (1989). The Condition of Postmodernity, Oxford: Blackwell.
Hawisher, G.E. and Selfe, C.L. (2000). ‘Introduction: Testing the Claims’, in Global
Literacies and the World Wide Web, London: Routledge.
Healy, D. (1997). ‘Cyberspace and Place’, in D. Porter (ed.), Internet Culture,
London: Routledge.
Heidegger, M. (1997). ‘The Question Concerning Technology’, in The Question
Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. W. Lovitt, New York: Harper
Torchbooks.
Heller, S. and Anderson, G. (1994). Typeplay, Dusseldorf: Nippan Shuppan Hanbai.
Hepworth, M. and Ducatel, K. (1992). Transport in the Information Age: Wheels and
Wires, London: Belhaven Press.
Herbert, T.E. and Proctor, W.S. (1932). Telephony, Vol. 1. 2nd edn, London: New Era.
Hills, M. (2001). ‘Virtually Out There: On-line Fandom’, in S. Munt (ed.),
Technospaces: Inside the New Media, London: Continuum.
Hirst, P. (1976). ‘Althusser and the Theory of Ideology’, Capital and Class, Vol. 5,
No. 4: 385–412.
Hirst, P. and Thompson, G. (1996). Globalization in Question: The International
Economy and the Possibilities of Governance, Cambridge: Polity.
Holloran, J. (1970). The Effects of Television, London: Pantheon Books.
Holmes, D. (1989). ‘Deconstruction: A Politics without a Subject, That Is’, Arena,
No. 88: 73–116.
Holmes, D. (ed.) (1997). Virtual Politics: Identity and Community in Cyberspace,
London: Sage.
Holmes, D. (ed.) (2001). Virtual Globalization: Virtual Spaces/Tourist Spaces, London:
Routledge.
Holmes, D. (2004). ‘The Electronic Superhighway: Melbourne’s CityLink Project’,
in S. Graham (ed.), The Cybercities Reader, London: Routledge.
Holmes, D. and Russell, G. (1999). ‘Adolescent CIT Use: Paradigm Shifts for
Educational and Cultural Practices?’, British Journal of Sociology of Education,
Vol. 20, No. 1: 73–82.
Horrocks, C. (2001). Marshall McLuhan and Virtuality, Lanham, MD: Totem Books.
Horton, D. and Wohl, R. (1956). ‘Mass Communication and Para-social Interaction:
Observation on Intimacy at a Distance’, Psychiatry, Vol. 19: 215–29.
Howard, P.E.N., Rainie, L. and Jones, S. (2001). ‘Days and Nights in the Internet: The
Impact of Diffusing Technology’, American Behavioral Scientist, Vol. 45: 383–404.
Huyssen, A. (1995). ‘In the Shadow of McLuhan: Baudrillard’s Theory of Simulation’,
in Twilight Memories, New York: Routledge.
Inglis, F. (1993). Media Theory: An Introduction, Oxford: Blackwell.
Innis, H. (1964). The Bias of Communication, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Innis, H. (1972). Empire and Communications, Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
James, P. and Carkeek, F. (1997). ‘This Abstract Body’, in D. Holmes (ed.), Virtual
Politics: Identity and Community in Cyberspace, London: Sage.
Jameson, F. (1991). Postmodernism, or The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, London:
Verso.
234
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Johnson, S. (1997). Interface Culture: How Technology Transforms the Way We Create
and Communicate, New York: HarperCollins.
Jones, P. (2000). ‘McLuhanist Societal Projections and Social Theory: Some
Reflections’, Media International Australia, No. 94: 39–56.
Jones, S. (ed.) (1995). Cybersociety: Computer-Mediated Communication and Community,
London: Sage.
Jordan, T. (1999). Cyberpower: The Culture and Politics of Cyberspace and the Internet,
London: Routledge.
Jowett, G. (1981). ‘Extended Images’, in R. Williams (ed.), Contact: Human
Communication and Its History, London: Thames and Hudson.
Kaplan, N. (2000). ‘Literacy Beyond Books’, in A. Herman and T. Swiss (eds), The
World Wide Web and Contemporary Cultural Theory, London: Routledge.
Katz, E. Blumler, J. and Gurevitch, M. (1974). ‘Utilization of Mass Communication
by the Individual’, in J. Blumler and E. Katz (eds), The Uses of Mass
Communications: Current Perspectives on Gratifications Research, Beverly Hills and
London: Sage.
Katz, J.E. and Aakhus, M.A. (eds) (2001). Perpetual Contact: Mobile Communication,
Private Talk, Public Performance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kearney, R. (1984). Dialogues with Contemporary Continental Thinkers: The
Phenomenological Heritage, Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Kirby, V. (1997). Telling Flesh, London: Routledge.
Kling, R. et al. (2000). ‘Anonymous Communication Policies for the Internet:
Results and Recommendations of the AAAS Conference’, in R.M. Baird,
R. Ramsower and S.E. Rosenbaum (eds), Cyberethics: Social and Moral Issues in
the Computer Age, New York: Prometheus Books.
Knorr-Cetina, K. (1997). ‘Sociality with Objects: Social Relations in Postsocial
Knowledge Societies’, Theory, Culture, Society, Vol. 14, No. 4: 1–30.
Kornhauser, W. (1960). The Politics of the Masses, London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Krause, L. and Petro, P. (eds) (2003). Global Cities: Cinema, Architecture, and
Urbanism in a Digital Age, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Kress, G.R. (2003). Literacy in the New Media Age, London and New York: Routledge.
Kroker, A. (1995). Digital Humanism: The Processed World of Marshall McLuhan,
Montreal: CTheory.
Kroker, A. (2001). Technology and the Canadian Mind: Innis/McLuhan/Grant,
Montreal: CTheory.
Kroker, A. and Kroker, M. (1996). Hacking the Future: Stories for the Flesh-Eating 90s,
Montreal: CTheory.
Kroker, A. and Weinstein, M. (1994). Data Trash: The Theory of the Virtual Class, New
York: St Martin’s Press.
Kuo, D. (2001). Dot.bomb: My Days and Nights at an Internet Goliath, London: Little,
Brown.
Lacan, J. (1985). ‘The Agency of the Letter in the Unconscious: Or Reason since
Freud’, in Ecrits: A Selection, trans. A. Sheridan, London: Tavistock.
Lakoff, G. (1995). ‘Body, Brain and Communication’, an interview with I.A. Boal,
in J. Brook and I. Boal (eds), Resisting the Virtual Life: The Culture and Politics of
Information, San Francisco: City Lights.
References
235
Langer, J. (1997). ‘Television’s Personality System’, in T. O’Sullivan and Y. Jewkes
(eds), The Media Studies Reader, London: Arnold.
Lapham, L. (1994). ‘Introduction to the MIT Press Edition: The Eternal Now’, in
M. McLuhan, Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Larrain, J. (1983). Marxism and Ideology, London: Macmillan.
Lasn, K. (2000). Culture Jam, New York: Quill.
Lasswell, H. (1948). ‘The Structure and Function of Communication in Society’, in
L. Bryson (ed.), The Communication of Ideas, New York: Harper.
Lave, J. and Wenger, E. (1991). Situated Learning: Legitimate Peripheral Participation,
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Lax, S. (2000). ‘The Internet and Democracy’, in D. Gauntlett (ed.), Web.Studies:
Rewiring Media Studies for the Digital Age, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lazarsfeld, P.F. and Kendall, P.L. (1949). ‘The Communications Behavior of the
Average American’, in W. Schramm (ed.), Mass Communications, Urbana:
University of Illinois Press.
Lealand, G. (1999). Paper presented to the Australian Key Centre for Media and
Cultural Policy, ‘Regulation – what Regulation? Cultural Diversity and Local
Content in New Zealand Television in the 1990s’, September.
Leavis, F.R. (1930). Mass Civilisation and Minority Culture, Cambridge: Minority Press.
Lee, H. and Liebenau, J. (2000). ‘Time and the Internet at the Turn of the
Millennium’, Time & Society, Vol. 9, No. 1: 43–56.
Lefebvre, H. (1991). The Production of Space, trans. D. Nickolson-Smith, Oxford:
Blackwell.
Le Grice, M. (2001). Experimental Cinema in the Digital Age, London: British Film
Institute.
Lemaire, A. (1970). Jacques Lacan, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Levinson, P. (1999). Digital McLuhan: A Guide to the Information Millennium,
New York: Fordham University/Routledge.
Lévy, P. (2001). Cyberculture, trans. Robert Brononno, Minnesota: University of
Minnesota Press.
Liebes, T. and Curran, J. (1998). Media, Ritual, Identity, London: Routledge.
Lievrouw, L. and Livingstone, S. (2002). Handbook of New Media: Social Shaping and
Consequences of ICTs, London: Sage.
Lipset, S. (1963). Political Man, London: Heinemann.
Livingstone, S. (1990). Making Sense of Television, London: Routledge.
Lowery, S. and De Fleur, M. (1983). Milestones in Mass Communication Research,
New York: Longman.
Lukács, G. (1971). History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics,
trans. R. Livingstone, London: Merlin Press.
Lukes, S. (1973). Émile Durkheim: His Life and Work: A Historical and Critical Study,
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Lull, J. (1995). Media, Communication, Culture: A Global Approach, Cambridge: Polity.
Lunenfeld, P. (1999). The Digital Dialectic: New Essays on New Media, Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Lupton, D. (1999). ‘Monsters in Metal Cocoons: Road Rage and Cyborg Bodies’,
Body and Society, Vol. 5, No. 1: 57–92.
236
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Lyotard, J.-F. (1984). The Postmodern Condition, trans. G. Bennington and B. Massumi,
Manchester: Manchester University Press.
McCarthy, A. (2001). Ambient Television: Visual Culture and Public Space, Durham,
NC: Duke University Press.
McChesney, R. (2000). ‘So Much for the Magic of Technology and the Free Market: The
World Wide Web and the Corporate Media System’, in A. Herman and T. Swiss
(eds), The World Wide Web and Contemporary Cultural Theory, London: Routledge.
McLaughlin, L. (1993). ‘Chastity Criminals in the Age of Electronic Reproduction:
Re-viewing Talk Television and the Public Sphere’, Journal of Communication
Inquiry, Vol. 17, No. 1: 41–55.
McLuhan, E. and Zingrone, F. (eds) (1997). The Essential McLuhan, London: Routledge.
McLuhan, M. (1964). ‘Introduction’ to H. Innis, The Bias of Communication, Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, reprinted in E. McLuhan and F. Zingrone (eds), The
Essential McLuhan, London: Routledge, 1997.
McLuhan, M. (1967). The Gutenberg Galaxy: The Making of Typographic Man,
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
McLuhan, M. (1994). Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
McLuhan, M. and Fiore, Q. (1967). The Medium is the Massage: An Inventory of
Effects, London: Penguin.
McLuhan, M. and Fiore, Q. (produced by Jerome Agel) (2001). War and Peace in the
Global Village, Corte Madera: Ginko Press.
McNeill, A. (1996). Total Television, London: Penguin.
McNeill, L. (1997). Travel in the Digital Age, London: Bowerdean Publishing.
McQuail, D. (1983). Mass Communication Theory: A Reader, London: Sage.
McQuire, S. (1995). ‘The Go-for Broke Game of History’, Arena Journal (New Series),
No. 4: 201–27.
Marc, D. (2000). ‘What Was Broadcasting?’, in H. Newcomb (ed.), Television: A Critical
View, New York: Oxford University Press.
Martin-Barbero, J. (1997). ‘Mass Media as a Site of Resacralization of Contemporary
Cultures’, in S. Hoover and K. Lindby (eds), Rethinking Media, Religion and Culture,
London: Sage.
Marx, K. (1973). Grundrisse, London: Penguin.
Marx, K. (1977). Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844, Moscow: Progress
Publishers.
Marx, K. (1976). Capital, Vol. I, London: Penguin.
Marx, K. and Engels, F. (1970). The German Ideology, New York: International
Publishers.
Mattelart, A. (2000). Networking the World, 1794–2000, trans. L. Carey-Libbrecht and
J.A. Cohen, Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota Press.
Mattelart, A. and Mattelart, M. (1992). Rethinking Media Theory: Signposts and New
Directions, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Mellencamp, P. (ed.) (1991). ‘TV Time and Catastrophe, or Beyond the Pleasure
Principle of Television’, in P. Mellencamp (ed.), Logics of Television: Essays in
Cultural Criticism, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Meyrowitz, J. (1985). No Sense of Place: The Impact of Electronic Media on Social
Behavior, New York: Oxford University Press.
References
237
Meyrowitz, J. (1990). ‘Television: The Shared Arena’, The World and I, Vol. 5, No. 7:
464–81.
Meyrowitz, J. (1994). ‘The Life and Death of Media Friends: New Genres of
Intimacy and Mourning’, in R. Cathcart and S. Druckers (eds), American Heroes
a Media Age, Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press.
Meyrowitz, J. (1995). ‘Medium Theory’, in D. Crowley and D. Mitchell (eds),
Communication Theory Today, Cambridge: Polity.
Meyrowitz, J. (1997). ‘Shifting Worlds of Strangers: Medium Theory and Changes
in “Them versus Us,”’ Sociological Inquiry, Vol. 67, No. 1: 59–71.
Meyrowitz, J. (1999). ‘Understandings of Media’, ETC: A Review of General
Semantics, Vol. 56, No. 1: 44–53.
Mitchell, W.J. (1996). City of Bits: Space, Place and the Infobahn, Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Morelli, N. (2001). ‘The Space of Telework: Physical and Virtual Configurations for
Remote Work’, in D. Holmes (ed.), Virtual Globalization: Virtual Spaces/Tourist
Spaces, London: Routledge.
Morley, D. (1980). The ‘Nationwide’ Audience: Structure and Decoding, London:
British Film Institute.
Morley, D. (1986). Family Television: Cultural Power and Domestic Leisure, London:
Comedia.
Morley, D. (1992). Television Audiences and Cultural Studies, London: Routledge.
Morse, M. (1998). Virtualities: Television, Media Art, and Cyberculture, Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
Morris, M. and Ogan, C. (1996). ‘The Internet as Mass Medium’, Journal of
Communication, Vol. 46, No. 1: 39–50.
Moursund, D. (1996). ‘How Long Is a Cyberspace Year?’, Leading and Learning with
Technology, Vol. 24, No. 1: 4–5.
Mullan, B. (1997). Consuming Television: Television and Its Audience, Oxford: Blackwell.
Nancy, J.-L. (1991). The Inoperative Community, trans. P. Conor et al., Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Negroponte, N. (1995). Being Digital, New York: Knopf.
Negt, O. and Kluge, A. (1993). Public Sphere and Experience: Toward an Analysis
of the Bourgeois and Proletarian Public Sphere, trans. P. Labanyi, J.O. Daniel and
A. Oksiloff, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Nelson, R. (1997). TV Drama in Transition: Forms, Values and Cultural Change,
Houndmills: Macmillan.
Newcomb, H. (ed.) (2000). Television: The Critical View (6th edn), New York: Oxford
University Press.
Newcomb, T. (1953). ‘An Approach to the Study of Communication Acts’,
Psychological Review, 60, 393–340.
Nguyen, D.T. and Alexander, J. (1996). ‘The Coming of Cyberspacetime and the
End of the Polity’, in R. Shields (ed.), Cultures of the Internet: Virtual Spaces, Real
Histories, Living Bodies, London: Sage.
Nie, N. and Erdring, R. (2000). ‘The Internet and Society Study’ conducted by the
Institute for the Quantitative Study of Society, available at http://www.stanford.edu/
group/siqss/
Nightingale, V. (1996). Studying Audiences: The Shock of the Real, London: Routledge.
238
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Nisbet, R. (1970). The Social Bond, New York: Knopf.
Noble, D. (1997). The Religion of Technology: The Divinity of Man and the Spirit of
Invention, New York: Knopf.
Norris, C. (1982). Deconstruction: Theory and Practice, London: Methuen.
Ong, W. (1982). Orality and Literacy: The Technologization of the World, London:
Methuen.
Ostwald, M. (1997). ‘Virtual Urban Futures’, in D. Holmes (ed.), Virtual Politics:
Identity and Community in Cyberspace, London: Sage.
O’Sullivan, T., Hartley, J., Saunders, D., Montgomery, M. and Fiske, J. (1994). Key
Concepts in Communication and Cultural Studies (2nd edn), London: Routledge.
Owen, B.M. (1999). The Internet Challenge to Television, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Plant, S. (1998). Zeros and Ones: Digital Women and the New Technoculture, London:
Fourth Estate.
Porter, D. (ed.) (1997). Internet Culture, London: Routledge.
Poster, M. (1990). The Mode of Information: Post-structuralism and Social Context,
Cambridge: Polity.
Poster, M. (1995). The Second Media Age, Cambridge: Polity.
Poster, M. (1997). ‘Cyberdemocracy: Internet and Public Sphere’, in D. Holmes
(ed.), Virtual Politics: Identity and Community in Cyberspace, London: Sage.
Poster, M. (2000). What’s the Matter with the Internet? Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Postman, N. (1993). Technopoly: The Surrender of Culture to Technology, New York:
Knopf.
Puro, J.-P. (2001). ‘Finland: A Mobile Culture’, in J.E. Katz and M.A. Aakhus (eds),
Perpetual Contact: Mobile Communication, Private Talk, Public Performance,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rafaeli, S. (1988). ‘Interactivity: From Media to Communication’, in R.P. Hawkins,
J.M. Wiemann and S. Pingree (eds), Annual Reviews of Communication Research,
Vol. 16: Advancing Communication Science: Merging Mass and Interpersonal Process,
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage.
Rafaeli, S. and Sudweeks, F. (1997). ‘Networked Interactivity’, Journal of ComputerMediated Communication, Vol. 2, No. 4. Available at: http://www.ascusc.org/
jcmc/vol2/issue4/rafaeli.sudweeks.html
Real, M. (1984). Supermedia, London: Sage.
Reeves, B. and Nass, C. (1996). The Media Equation: How People Treat Computers,
Television, and New Media Like Real People and Places, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Regis, E. (1990). Great Mambo Chicken and the Transhuman Condition: Science Slightly
over the Edge, London: Viking Press.
Rheingold, H. (1994). The Virtual Community: Finding Connection in a Computerized
World, London: Secker and Warburg.
Robins, K. (1995). ‘Cyberspace and the World We Live in’, in M. Featherstone and
R. Burrows (eds), Cyberspace, Cyberbodies, Cyberpunk: Cultures of Technological
Embodiment, London: Sage.
Robins, K. and Webster, F. (1999). Times of the Technoculture: From the Information
Society to the Virtual Life, London: Routledge.
References
239
Rose, N. (1996). ‘The Death of the Social? Re-figuring the Territory of
Government’, Economy and Society, Vol. 25, No. 3: 327–56.
Rosen, R. (1986). ‘Search for Yesterday’, in T. Gitlin (ed.), Watching Television:
A Pantheon Guide to Popular Culture, New York: Pantheon.
Rosenberg, M.J. (2001). E-learning: Strategies for Delivering Knowledge in the Digital
Age, New York: McGraw-Hill.
Rothenbuhler, E.W. (1998). Ritual Communication: From Everyday Conversation to
Mediated Ceremony, London: Sage.
Russell, G. and Holmes, D. (1996). ‘Electronic Nomads? Implications of Trends in
Adolescents’ Use of Communication and Information Technology’, Australian
Journal of Educational Technology, Vol. 12, No. 2: 130–44.
Saussure, F. de (1992). Course in General Linguistics, trans. R. Harris, La Salle, IL:
Open Court Classics.
Schultz, T. (2000). ‘Mass Media and the Concept of Interactivity: An Exploratory
Study of Online Forums and Reader Email’, Media, Culture & Society, Vol. 22:
205–21.
Schwoch J. and White, M. (1992). ‘Learning the Electronic Life’, in J. Schwoch,
M. White and S. Reilly, Media Knowledge: Readings in Popular Culture, Albany:
State University of New York Press.
Seiter, E. (1999). Television and New Media Audiences, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Selby, K. and Cowdery, R. (1995). How to Study Television, Houndmills: Macmillan.
Sennett, R. (1978). The Fall of Public Man, New York: Knopf.
Shannon, C. and Weaver, W. (1949). The Mathematical Theory of Communication,
Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.
Sharp, G. (1983). ‘Intellectuals in Transition’, Arena Journal (New Series), No. 65: 84–95.
Sharp, G. (1985). ‘Constitutive Abstraction and Social Practice’, Arena, 70: 48–82.
Sharp, G. (1993). ‘Extended Forms of the Social: Technological Mediation and SelfFormation’, Arena Journal (New Series), No. 1: 221–37.
Shea, V. (1994). Netiquette, San Francisco: Albion Books.
Shields, R. (1994). ‘Fancy Footwork: Walter Benjamin’s Notes on Flânerie’, in Keith
Tester (ed.), The Flâneur, London: Routledge.
Shields, S. (ed.) (1996). Cultures of the Internet: Virtual Spaces, Real Histories, Living
Bodies, London: Sage.
Shils, E. (1957). ‘Daydreams and Nightmares: Reflections on the Criticism of Mass
Culture’, The Sewanee Review, Vol. 65, No. 4.
Shils, E. and Young, M. (1953). ‘The Meaning of the Coronation’, Sociological
Review, December: 63–81.
Silver, D. (2000). ‘Looking Backwards, Looking Forward: Cyberculture Studies,
1990–2000’, in D. Gauntlett (ed.), Web.Studies: Rewiring Media Studies for the
Digital Age, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Silverstone, R. (1999). Why Study the Media? London: Sage.
Simmel, G. (1971). ‘The Metropolis and Mental Life’, in D.N. Levine (ed.), On
Individuality and Social Forms, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Skinner, D. (2000). ‘McLuhan’s World and Ours’, The Public Interest, Winter: 52–64.
Skog, B. (2001). ‘Mobiles and the Norwegian Teen: Identity, Gender and Class’, in
J.E. Katz and M.A. Aakhus (eds), Perpetual Contact: Mobile Communication,
Private Talk, Public Performance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
240
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Slater, P. (1971). The Pursuit of Loneliness: American Culture at the Breaking Point,
London: Allen Lane.
Slevin, J. (2000). The Internet and Society, Cambridge: Polity.
Slouka, M. (1996). War of the Worlds: The Assault on Reality, London: Abacus.
Smart, B. (1992). Modern Conditions: Postmodern Controversies, London: Routledge.
Smith, C. (1997). ‘Casting the Net: Surveying an Internet Population’, Journal of
Computer-Mediated Communication, Vol. 3, No. 1, available at http://www.ascusc.
org/jcmc/Vol3/issue1/smith.html
Smith, M. (1995). ‘Voices from the Well: The Logic of the Virtual Commons’, Ph.D.
dissertation, University of California, available at http://www.netscan.sscnet.
ucla.edu/soc/csoc/papers/voices/Voices.htm
Smith, M. (1999). ‘Invisible Crowds in Cyberspace: Mapping the Social Structure
of Usenet’, in M.A. Smith and P. Kollock (eds), Communities in Cyberspace,
London: Routledge.
Smith, M. and Kollock, P. (eds) (1999). Communities in Cyberspace, London: Routledge.
Smythe, D.W. (1981). ‘On the Audience Commodity and Its Work’, in Dependency
Road: Communications, Capitalism, Consciousness and Canada, Norwood, NJ: Ablex.
Snyder, R.W. (1994). ‘The Vaudeville Circuit: A Prehistory of the Mass Audience’,
in J.S. Ettema and D.C. Whitney (eds), Audiencemaking: How the Media Create the
Audience, London: Sage.
Sobchack, V. (1996). ‘Democratic Franchise and the Electronic Frontier’, in
Z. Sardar and J. Ravetz (eds), Cyberfutures: Culture and Politics on the Information
Superhighway, London: Pluto Press.
Sohn-Rethel, A. (1979). Intellectual and Manual Labour: A Critique of Epistemology,
London: Macmillan.
Soja, E. (1996). Thirdspace: Journeys into Los Angeles and Other Real and Imagined
Places, Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.
Spears, R. and Lea, M. (1994). ‘Panacea or Panopticon? The Hidden Power of
Computer-Mediated Communication’, in Communication Research, Vol. 21,
No. 4: 427–59.
Springer, C. (2000). ‘Digital Rage’, in D. Bell and B. Kennedy (eds), The
Cybercultures Reader, London: Routledge.
Sprinker, M. (1987). Imaginary Relations: Aesthetics and Ideology in the Theory of
Historical Materialism, London: Verso.
Stearn, G. (ed.) (1968). McLuhan: Hot and Cool, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Steemers, J. (2001). ‘Broadcasting is Dead. Long Live Digital Choice’, in H. Mackay
and T. O’Sullivan (eds), The Media Reader: Continuity and Transformation, London:
Sage.
Stevenson, N. (1995). Understanding Media Cultures: Social Theory and Mass
Communication, London: Sage Publications.
Stoll, C. (1995). Silicon Snake Oil, London: Pan.
Stone, A.R. (1991). ‘Will the Real Body Please Stand Up?: Boundary Stories about
Virtual Cultures’, in M. Benedikt (ed.), Cyberspace: First Steps, Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Stratton, J. (1997). ‘Cyberspace and the Globalization of Culture’, in D. Porter,
(ed.), Internet Culture, London: Routledge.
References
241
Swyngedouw, E. (1993). ‘Communication, Mobility and the Struggle for Power
over Space’, in G. Giannopoulos and A. Gillespie (eds), Transport and
Communications in the New Europe, London: Belhaven.
Taylor, T. and Ward, I. (eds) (1998). Literacy Theory in the Age of the Internet,
New York: Columbia University Press.
Terranova, T. (2001). ‘Demonstrating the Globe: Virtual and Real Action in the
Network Society’, in D. Holmes (ed.), Virtual Globalization: Virtual Spaces/Tourist
Spaces, London: Routledge.
Tester, K. (1996). The Flâneur, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Thompson, J.B. (1994). ‘Social Theory and the Media’, in D. Crowley and
D. Mitchell (eds), Communication Theory Today, Cambridge: Polity.
Thompson, J.B. (1995). The Media and Modernity: A Social Theory of the Media,
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Thompson, J.B. (1995). The Media and Modernity, Cambridge: Polity.
Tingle, L. (2002) ‘TV Revolution to Create more Free Channels’, in the Sydney
Moving Hearald, 23 April, p. 1.
Tocqueville, A. de (1990). Democracy in America, Vol. 2, ed. P. Bradley, New York:
Vintage Books.
Toffler, A. (1980). The Third Wave, London: Pan.
Tofts, D. (1997). Memory Trade: A Prehistory of Cyberculture, North Ryde: 21C
Publications.
Tönnies, F. (1955). Community and Association, London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Touraine, A. (1988). The Return of the Actor, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Touraine, A. (1998). ‘Sociology without Society’, Current Sociology, Vol. 46, No. 2:
119–45.
Turkle, S. (1984). The Second Self, New York: Simon and Schuster.
Turkle, S. (1995). Life on the Screen: Identity in the Age of the Internet, New York:
Simon and Schuster.
Turow, J. and Kavanaugh, A. (eds) (2003). The Wired Homestead, Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Urry, J. (2002). ‘Global Complexities’, Paper presented at the International
Sociological Association World Congress of Sociology, Brisbane, Australia, 7–13
July 2002.
Urry, J. (2003). Global Complexity, Malden, MA: Polity.
Urry, J. and Rojek, C. (eds) (1997). Touring Cultures: Transformations of Travel and
Theory, London: Routledge.
Van Dijk, J. (1999). The Network Society: Social Aspects of New Media, London: Sage.
Vidich, A.J. and Bensman, J. (1960). Small Town in Mass Society, New York: Anchor
Books.
Virilio, P. (1997). ‘The Overexposed City’, in N. Leach (ed.), Rethinking Architecture,
London: Routledge.
Virilio, P. (1998). ‘Is the Author Dead? An Interview with Paul Virilio’, in J. Der
Derian (ed.), The Virilio Reader, Oxford: Blackwell.
Virilio, P. (2000). The Information Bomb, London: Verso.
242
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Virilio, P. (2001). ‘Speed and Information: Cyberspace Alarm!’, in D. Trend (ed.),
Reading Digital Culture, Oxford: Blackwell.
Wardrip-Fruin, N. and Montfort, N. (eds) (2003). The New Media Reader, Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Wark, M. (1994). Virtual Geography, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Wark, M. (1999). Celebrities, Culture and Cyberspace: The Light on the Hill in a
Postmodern World, Sydney: Pluto Press.
Wark, M. (2000). ‘Whatcha Doin’, Marshall McLuhan?’, Media International
Australia, No. 94: 89–96.
Wasserman, I.M. (1984). ‘Imitation and Suicide: A Re-examination of the Werther
Effect’, American Sociological Review, No. 49: 427–36.
Watts, D. (2000). ‘The Internet, the Small World, and the Nature of Distance’, Santa
Fe Institute, available at http: aries.mos.org/internet/essay.html
Weigel, Van B. (2002). Deep Learning for a Digital Age: Technology’s Untapped
Potential to Enrich Higher Education, San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Wellman, B. (ed.) (1999). Networks in the Global Village: Life in Contemporary
Communities, Boulder, CO: Westview.
Wellman, B and Gulia, M. (1999). ‘Virtual Communities as Communities: Net
Surfers Don’t Ride Alone’, in M. Smith and P. Kollock (eds), Communities in
Cyberspace, London: Routledge.
Wertheim, M. (1999). The Pearly Gates of Cyberspace: A History of Space from Dante to
the Internet, Sydney: Doubleday.
Whitaker, R. (2000). The End of Privacy: How Total Surveillance Is Becoming a Reality,
Melbourne: Scribe Publications.
Whittle, D. (1996). Cyberspace: The Human Dimension, New York: W.H. Freeman.
Wiener, N. ([1948] 1961). ‘Introduction’, in Cybernetics: or Control and
Communication in the Animal and the Machine (2nd edn), Cambridge, MA; MIT
Press.
Wilbur, S. (1997). ‘An Archaeology of Cyberspaces: Virtuality, Community,
Identity’, in D. Porter (ed.), Internet Culture, London: Routledge.
Wilhelm, A.G. (2000). Democracy in the Digital Age: Challenges to Political Life in
Cyberspace, New York: Routledge.
Williams, R. (1961). Culture and Society: 1780–1950, Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Williams, R. (1974). Television: Technology and Cultural Form, London: Fontana.
Williams, R. (ed.) (1981) Contact: Human Communication and Its History, London:
Thames and Hudson.
Williams, R. (1983). Towards 2000, London: Chatto and Windus/Hogarth.
Williams, R. and Edge, D. (1992). Social Shaping Reviewed – Research Concepts,
Findings, Programmers and Centres in the UK, Edinburgh: PICT Working Papers
No. 41.
Willson, M. (1997). ‘Community in the Abstract’, in D. Holmes (ed.), Virtual
Politics: Identity and Community in Cyberspace, London: Sage.
Winston, B. (1998). Media, Technology and Society: A History from the Telegraph to the
Internet, London: Routledge.
References
243
Wise, J.M. (1997). Exploring Technology and Social Space, London: Sage.
Wolf, M.J.P. (2000). Abstracting Reality: Art, Communication, and Cognition in the
Digital Age, Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Zettl, H. (1973). Sight, Sound and Motion: Applied Media Aesthetics, Belmont, CA:
Wadsworth.
Z iz ek, S. (1989). The Sublime Object of Ideology, London: Verso.
INDEX
Aakhus, M.A., 185–6
‘Apparatgeist’ and perpetual contact,
185–6, 192
abstraction, v, 18n, 32, 128, 151, 153–4,
177, 192
constitutive, 158–61
and the Internet, 162–4
Adorno, Theodor, 34
culture industry, 23–5, 34, 39, 68,
88–9, 119, 141
Frankfurt School, 25, 119
and Max Horkheimer, 24–5, 33, 68,
88–9, 99, 141
advertising, xii, 34, 37, 43n, 44, 50, 66,
77, 87, 95–7, 100, 102, 120n, 149, 201,
212–13
billboards, 105, 201, 215
Agamben, Giorgio, 174
agora, 60, 68, 73, 195–7, 199, 201, 209
cosmopolitan-agora, 196
cyberspace as electronic agora, 60,
195, 199–200
of potential assembly, 17
Alexander, J., 72, 117, 134, 165n
Alford, J., 28
Althusser, Louis, xi, 28–31, 34, 110, 118, 141
Ideological State Apparatus, 28
ideology-in-general, xi, 30, 31, 141
ideology-in-particular, 30, 141
interpellation, xi, 29–30, 34, 88,
110, 141
American Association for the
Advancement of Science’s Program
in Scientific Freedom, Responsibility
and Law (AAAS), 150–1
Anderson, Benedict, 107, 194
imagined communities, 80, 112,
175, 222–3n
Andrejevic, Mark, 219
Anna Voog, 220–1
personal web pages, 220–1
‘the work of being watched’, 220
Ang, Ien, 42n, 112, 120n
Aoki, Kumiko, 204–5
three domains of virtual community, 204
Apple, 98
architectures, 138, 143
broadcast, ix, 9, 13, 20, 53, 66, 95, 99, 110,
133, 146–8, 206, 220, 222
communication, 18n, 130, 206
media, 164, 223n
‘media’ walls, 53
network, ix, 9, 13, 20, 48, 66, 93, 95, 97,
100, 110, 133, 194, 202, 222
social, 83, 89, 99, 154, 165, 169
urban, 168
Arena, 158–60, 164
ARPANET, 47
AT&T, 56
‘attention economy’, 104
audience communities, 123, 176,
194, 210–11
metonymous identification, 214–21
rituals of, 214–21
audience, 8, 21, 23, 25, 34, 36, 40, 43n, 50,
58, 59, 84–6, 89–90, 95, 103, 107–13,
118–19, 122–4, 127, 131, 133–4, 139,
142–4, 146–7, 149, 154, 161, 164, 176,
188, 200, 207, 209, 212, 221
activity, 30, 40, 42n, 50, 58, 70, 112, 143,
145, 148, 155, 156, 171, 174
audience studies, 42n, 58, 101, 111–12,
118–19, 143
friends, 144, 148, 210
hot and cool media, 70–1
para-social interaction, 144, 148, 153
passive, 9, 18n, 22, 40–1, 70, 93, 143, 200,
201, 225n
synchronous and asynchronous, 96,
103–6, 109, 139
see also McLuhan, hot and cool mediums
Aurigi, Alex, 120n
Austin, J.L., 108
Australian Consumers Association, 97
Automatic Teller Machine (ATM), 1, 157
avatar, 62–3, 141–3, 150–1, 190, 198,
202, 224n
bandwidth, 13, 45, 46, 48, 65, 72, 77, 86, 97,
106, 210, 221
Barlow, John Perry, 47, 48
Barlovian cyberspace, 47, 62
Index
Barney, Darin, 191
Barr, Trevor, 8, 79, 95
Baudelaire, Charles, flânerie, 197–8
Baudrillard, Jean, xi, 5, 10, 27, 31, 36–8, 39,
43n, 51, 69, 106, 107, 118, 120n, 133, 143
hyperreal, 31, 38, 43n, 107
obscene, 105, 107
simulacrum, 36, 38, 39, 43n, 100, 118,
119, 128, 135, 207
Baym, Nancy, 87, 97
audience community and network
community, 176, 194, 210
contexts of CMC, 63–4, 67
Becker, Barbara, 76–7, 79, 81
‘partial publics’, 76, 79, 81
behaviourism, x, 5, 18n, 23, 42, 112, 194
Bell, Daniel, 7, 22, 170
‘end of ideology’, 22
multi-stranded community, 170–1
Benedikt, M., Judeo-Christian narratives
of cyberspace, 190
Benjamin, Walter, flânerie, 197–9
Bennett, Tony, 21–2, 42n
Big Brother, 219–20
Bolter, J.D., and Grusin, R., 19n, 38, 43n,
66, 130
hypermediacy, 130
remediation, 19n, 43n
Boorstin, Daniel J., 31–3, 43n
‘homogenisation of experience’, 33
Bott, Elizabeth, 99, 166n
Bourdieu, Pierre, 108
Brecht, Bertolt, 19n
broadcast, 11–14, 17, 20–43, 44–5, 49–53, 55,
57, 59, 64–7, 70, 72–3, 78–80, 82n,
83–121, 122–3, 132–3, 135, 137–41, 142,
143, 144–9, 150, 154, 155, 161, 164, 167,
176, 177, 194, 195, 200, 206–21
architecture, ix, 9, 13, 20, 53, 66, 95, 99,
110, 133, 146–8, 206, 220, 222
authority of, 215, 216
‘The Broadcast Era’, 85, 102
broadcast event, 103–6, 109, 111–12
as constitutive of media ‘mass’, 102
convergence thesis, xi
dependence on, 3
interactivity, ix, xi, 10, 12, 50, 84–6, 97–8,
100, 115, 122, 148
maintenance of social order, 207
mediation of visibility, 208–9
mutually constitutive with network
integration, 83–6
network mediums parasitic on
broadcast, xi, 12, 52, 79, 86–7, 90,
95, 104, 105
245
broadcast, cont.
public sphere, 80, 102
reciprocity without interaction, 144–9,
161, 195, 211, 217
rethinking of, 101–19
sociological approach to, ix-x
broadcast communities, x, xiii, 122,
206–21, 222
in news, 215–16
reality TV, 219–20
rituals of, 214–20
symbolic inequality of, 34, 105, 210–14
talk shows, 217–19
Brosnan, M., technophobia, 183, 188
Buzzard, K.S.F., 18n, 96, 121n
cable, 1, 8, 66, 94, 97, 102, 109, 110, 111,
121n, 149, 215
Caldwell, J., 120n
Calhoun, Craig, xii, 43n, 154, 160, 164,
166n, 178
efficiency of communication, 202
phenomenological levels of
socialization, 155–8
capitalism, 4, 6, 9, 24–8, 31, 32, 34, 74, 77,
82n, 88, 89, 91, 173–4, 207, 221
Carey, James, xii, 6, 15, 39, 46, 117, 215, 219
anthropological or ritual approach, xii,
133–135, 208
divertissement, 133
status conflict in communication, 219
uses and gratification model, 134
Carkeek, Freya, 148, 159, 160
cartoon, 70, 71, 120n
Castells, Manuel, 8, 43n, 48, 85, 204–5
interactive society, 8
CBS, 21, 120n
celebrity, 24, 35, 52, 82n, 212–14, 218–19
as the last flâneur, 214
Celebdaq and Hollywood SX, 212
deaths of, 109, 111, 214, 224n
and non-celebrity, 34–5, 105, 153, 211,
212–13, 217–18, 219, 220–1, 224n
and scandal, 214
and symbolic inequalities, 34,
105, 210–14
WorldLive.com, 213
Centre for Contemporary Cultural
Studies (CCCS), 17n
Certeau, Michel de, 117,
176, 177
‘space is a practiced place’, 176
Chan-Olmsted, S., 96
Chapman, Mark David, 225n
Chesher, Chris, 55, 82n
246
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Cheung, C., 220–1
cinema, 13, 21, 22, 32, 40, 45, 68, 70–2, 86,
97, 98, 106, 114, 120n, 201, 224n
citizenship, 10, 22, 63, 74, 80, 165n
city, 16, 67, 69, 78, 88, 92, 121n, 156,
197–201, 223n, 224n
coffee houses, 60–1, 73–4, 77, 82n, 196
communication and information
technologies (CITs), 2–3, 11–12, 14,
41, 63
producing ‘new’ social relationships,
19n, 143
‘communication as culture’, xii
communication environments, x, 12,
13, 81, 87
community, xii–xiii, 5, 6, 10, 16, 20, 23, 46,
52, 63, 74, 108, 118, 121n, 123, 133, 148,
157, 161, 165, 166n, 167–222, 222n,
223n, 224n
as a legitimating narrative, 167
of belief, 176
citizenship, 10, 22, 63, 74,
80, 165n
classical theories of, 167–71
community as practice, 122, 174–7
community as recognition, 122
electronic, 74
global communities, 172–3, 174–7
and ‘imagined communities’, 80, 112,
175, 222–23n
imagined universal community,
129, 189–93
and ‘impact assessment’
research, 167
‘international’ community, 173
media-constituted, x
micro-communities, 170, 175
‘miniaturization’ of, 169
network, 176, 188–9, 194, 196
nostalgia of, 16, 202
Olympic community, 173
on-line communities, 87, 101, 150,
176, 204
over-integration and over-regulation,
169–70
pseudo-communities, 204
renewal of, xii, 120n, 192
telecommunity, xii, 17n, 111,
122, 167–222
virtual communities, x, xii–xiii, 9, 48,
54, 62, 63, 68, 78, 80, 99, 100, 103,
117, 119, 122, 123, 149, 164, 170, 173,
188, 192, 194–7, 198, 201–6, 222,
224n, 225n
‘complexity theory’, 19n, 57
computer-mediated communication
(CMC), ix–xi, 17n, 47, 54–5, 57, 59,
67, 87, 90, 103, 117, 118, 119, 123, 137,
150, 151, 161, 166n, 178, 196, 200, 202,
205, 211
as anti-hierarchical, 61
contexts of, 63–4
as cyberspace, 60–1, 119
electronic democracy, 9–10, 73, 76, 80–1
extends face-to-face communication, 203
form of ‘socially produced space’, 60
and identity, 62–3
and the public sphere, 78–9
Constitutive Abstraction, 158–62
content (of communication), 25, 55, 57, 60,
82n, 86–7, 101, 103–6, 107–8, 111,
113–16, 118, 126, 133, 134, 135, 145,
163, 166n, 175–6, 211, 215
content analysis, 6, 59, 119
focus of media studies, ix, 4–5
and ideology, 26, 29–30, 34, 141
and the medium, 36, 39–40, 43n, 49,
94, 106, 112, 116, 123
and the user, 143–4, 220
versus form, ix–xi, xiii, 5–6, 8, 20, 27,
43n, 51, 56, 118, 143
convergence perspective, xi–xii, 13, 64–6
corporate, 65;
functional, 64
industry, 64
medium, 64–5
of space, 67
technological, xi, 3–4, 41, 50, 64
telecommunications, xi, 64
Cooley, C.H., 154–6, 160, 170
Corner, John, 18n, 101
Couldry, Nick, 113, 120n, 165–6n, 225n
media as mythological ‘centre’ of social
life, 210–11
symbolic inequality of media
friends, 152–3
talk shows and the ‘really real’, 218
talk shows as ritual, 218
Crowley, David, 41, 42
cultural capital, 34
cultural studies, concerns of, 4, 5, 42n, 43n
concern for passive audience, 22
influence on media studies, 4, 117
culture industry, xii, 9, 31, 39, 50, 52, 68,
85, 88–9, 97, 119, 141, 148–9, 161, 195,
207, 213–14
mass media as, 23–5
and the personal web page, 220
cybercafé, 78, 223n
cybergeist, 192
Index
cybernetics, 55–7, 192
cybersex, 161
cybersociety, xi, 44–82
cyberspace, xiii, 1, 2, 4, 9, 11, 18n, 42, 44–7,
49, 51–2, 54–5, 57, 60–2, 72, 82n, 84, 89,
101, 117, 119, 133, 138, 140, 150, 175,
177, 186, 189–93, 195, 196, 203, 222, 223n
as electronic agora, 60, 195, 197, 199–200
as new public sphere, 72–5, 120n
as routine, 177
as revelation, 190
and ‘cyberbrats’, 187
and global telecommunications, 46
and the Internet, 4, 46–7, 48, 50, 114
Judaeo-Christian narratives of, 190
and virtual flânerie, 199–201
and virtual reality, ix, 44–6, 49, 122, 201
cyber-terrorism, 11
cyber-utopia, 52, 75, 83, 115, 120n, 191, 194
Dallas Smythe, 43n
datacasting, 84, 103–5, 106, 120n
Dayan, D., 107, 208, 216
Debord, Guy, 5, 27, 53, 68, 90
spectacle, 31–4, 89, 118
deconstruction, 5, 6
Deleuze, Gilles, rhizome, 10
democracy, 23, 43n, 73, 76, 77, 82n, 134,
207, 208
and cyberspace, 24, 72–5, 80, 191
and interaction, 80–1
democratization, 9–11, 23, 84, 207, 220
Dempsey, Ken, 175, 194
Derrida, Jacques, 6, 20, 51, 121n, 129, 131,
133, 165n, 223n
dissemination, 126–8
‘hermeneutic deciphering’, 126, 131
logocentrism, 6, 11, 75, 123–4, 127–9,
130–2, 135, 138, 141, 146, 166n
phonocentrism, 6, 124, 129, 132,
135–6, 139
polysemia, 126–8
writing-as-language, 131
Dery, Mark, 100
‘escape velocity’, 187
dialogicity, 40, 77–9, 136, 137, 146–7, 164,
203, 205
digital, ‘digital age’, 10
digital divide, 58, 187
‘digital nation’, 73
technology, 2, 7, 8, 19n, 45, 49, 60, 64,
65–6, 82n, 100, 103, 108, 114, 115,
130, 183–184
digitalization, 65–6, 164
disembedding, 162–3
247
disembodiment, 36, 100, 157, 159–161, 178,
200, 207
disembodied communities, 194, 225n
‘disintermediation’, 137–8
dot.com stocks, 96–7
Durkheim, Emile, 52, 59, 121n, 133, 152–3,
154, 189
community, 167–9, 175–6, 182, 194
conscience collective, 110, 167–70, 175
cult of the individual, 29, 110
‘organic solidarity’, 168
DVD, 65–6, 100
e-commerce, 114
economy, 173
effects analysis, 4, 21, 42n, 56, 58, 82n, 102,
115, 119, 123, 133, 136, 166n
electrical-analogue time-worlds, 49
electronically based communications, 8
electronically extended relations, 3, 39,
49, 54, 55
email, 3, 17n, 47, 50, 55, 60, 61, 78, 79, 94,
97, 104, 116, 120n, 132, 143–4, 145,
150, 166n, 204, 207
embodiment, xiii, 2, 12, 14, 16, 36, 42, 47,
55, 60–3, 67, 69, 73, 78, 80, 84, 90, 92,
94, 99, 137, 138, 141, 145–146, 154,
157–8, 160–1, 170, 188, 192, 196, 200,
203, 207, 210, 217, 223n, 224n, 225n
emoticons, 16, 55, 82n, 161
Endemol Corporation, 219
Erdring, R., 90, 194, 224n
European traditions in media studies, 4
face-to-face interactions, x, xii, 2, 8, 11–12,
14, 15–17, 17n, 49, 54, 63, 71–2, 78, 81n,
85, 87, 92, 94, 99–100, 108, 111, 114,
116, 118, 119n, 123n, 132, 135, 136–9,
144–6, 148–51, 154–6, 158–9, 161, 164,
166n, 178–80, 194–5, 197–9, 204–5, 207,
211, 221–2, 224n, 225n
extended by CMC, 54–5, 63, 106, 118, 203
fandom, 87, 112, 153, 211, 212–13, 214
on-line fan clubs, 87
Featherstone, Mike, the flâneur, 197, 199–201
MTV, 201
Feenberg, A., 140
Felski, Rita, 75
Fidonet, 47
Fiore, Quentin and Marshall McLuhan,
41, 72, 99, 103, 118, 121n,186
first media age, 6, 34, 95, 120n, 140
and the second media age, ix, 4, 7–11,
12, 17, 43n, 44, 50, 52, 67, 69, 71,
82n, 83–91, 97, 110, 114, 140, 194, 204
248
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Fiske, John, 57, 82n, 120n
‘bardic’ function of news, 110, 121n, 215
the flâneur, 197–198, 210, 223–4n
and celebrity, 214
defined as consumer, 199
virtual, 199–201, 210, 223–4n
flânerie, 170, 197–203, 207, 210, 224n
Flew, Terry, 64, 65, 137
Flitterman-Lewis, S., 106
form, versus content, ix–xi, xiii, 5–6, 8, 20,
27, 43n, 51, 56, 118, 143
Forrest Gump, 34–5
Foster, Derek, 190, 194, 204, 205
Foucault, Michel, 31–3, 43n, 153
disciplinary society, 33
‘governmentality’, 172, 174
Frankfurt School, 25, 119
Fraser, Nancy, 75
freeway, xii, 67, 68–9, 99
Friedberg, Ann, 199
ftp, 79
Fukuyama, Francis, 99, 169
Gates, Bill, 7
Gauntlett, D., 7, 18n, 96, 104, 105, 180, 224n
generation gap, 19n, 63
genre, 14, 24, 34–5, 36, 37, 49, 87, 100, 105,
107, 112, 113, 133, 134, 139, 147, 153,
201, 210, 211, 212, 213, 214–19, 224n
Gerbner, George, 57–8, 60, 119
access, and availability, 58
vertical dimension of communication, 58
Gibson, William, 45, 47, 189, 196
Giddens, Anthony, xii, 21, 154, 162–3
time-space distanciation, 162–3
Gilder, George, 7, 9, 10, 14, 52, 84
Gitlin, Todd, 17n, 42n, 76
‘public sphericules’, 75–6, 81
global communities, 129, 172–3, 189–93
global citizenship, 63, 80
of practice, 174–7
globalization, 107, 163, 167, 168,
172, 173–4
Goffman, Erving, 154
gopher, 79
Gore, Al, 7, 18n, 74
Graham, S., 43n, 67, 120n
Gramsci, Antonio, 28
hegemony, 28, 40, 43n, 52, 101, 153
Grusin, R. and Bolter, J.D., 19n, 38, 43n,
66, 130
hypermediacy, 130
remediation, 19n, 43n
Guattari, Félix, 16
Gulia, M., 17n, 202, 204
Habermas, Jurgen, 209
public sphere, 42n, 72–81
Hall, Stuart, 17, 26, 117
‘American Dream Sociology’, 22–3
encoding/decoding, 17n, 112
Hanks, W.F., 176
Hartley, John, 18n, 22, 42n, 73, 77, 120n
‘bardic’ function of news, 110, 121n, 215
Hawisher, G.E., 74, 75, 82n
Healy, Dave, 54
Hegel, G.W.F., 107, 127, 185, 223n
Heidegger, Martin, 140, 181–2, 187, 191
Heilig, Morton, 81n
Herbert, T.E., 46
Hill, A., 180
Hills, Mathew, 87, 112
Hirst, P., 30, 31, 80
historicism, ix, xi, xii, 7–11, 39, 64, 65, 81,
83–6, 97, 129, 145, 192, 206, 221
problems with historical typology, 11–15
Hobbes Internet Timeline, 81
Hollywood, 24, 104, 105, 213
Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor Adorno,
24–5, 33, 68, 88–9, 99, 141
Horrocks, Christopher, 72, 114, 115,
121n, 143
Horton and Wohl, The Lonesome Gal, 212
para-social interaction, 144, 148, 152–3,
166n, 212
HTML, 60
hypodermic model, 58
IBM, 47
ICQ, 50, 60, 61
identity, 5, 8, 36, 76, 92, 123, 127, 139,
141–4, 149, 150, 165n, 174
constituted by media environments,
15, 21, 48, 53, 61–3, 99, 151, 180,
184, 189, 190, 194, 205–7
see also avatar
ideology, ix, xi, 4, 5, 18n, 22, 34, 37–9, 43n,
54, 74, 75, 81n, 101–2, 118–19, 128, 130,
141, 195n
‘end of ideology’, 22
of interactivity, 18–19n
media as apparatus of, 25–9
as a structure of broadcast, 29–31
see also Althusser
IMAX, 92
‘Information Revolution’, 19n, 56
information society, 2, 7, 55–6, 173
information theory, x, 55–9, 64, 119
Shannon, C. and Weaver, W.,
56, 82n
Inglis, F., 107
Index
Innis, Harold, 5, 38, 41–2, 43n, 51, 70, 85,
98, 117
Institute for the Quantitative Study of
Society, 90
institutionally extended relations, 49
instrumental views of communication, xii,
18n, 20, 81n, 130, 132, 137, 138, 139–40,
202–3, 206
Integration, x–xiii, 12, 13, 15–17, 29, 35, 53,
55, 69, 75, 99, 119, 120n
broadcast, 3, 34, 35, 72, 86, 98, 148–9,
177, 206–10
community as practice and community
as recognition, 122, 174–7
levels of, x, 122, 148, 151–3, 153–60, 165,
166n, 222, 223n
network, 3, 8, 72, 98, 141, 149, 177
and ritual view of communication,
119, 122–3, 133–5, 140
social integration, 3–4, 6, 16, 21–2, 24–5,
31, 50, 52, 55, 83, 86, 118, 122–3, 132,
145, 148, 152–7, 159, 164, 168,
169–71, 173, 175, 182, 183, 206,
208, 210–11, 222
and sociality with mediums, 178–80
versus interaction, 15–17, 55, 122–66
Interaction, x–xiii, 8, 12, 14, 40, 49, 52, 76,
77–9, 84, 86, 90, 99, 114–16, 118, 175–6,
177, 178, 180, 185, 188, 195–9, 202–4,
206, 209–10, 219, 222, 224n, 225n
approach to media culture, xi, 164, 178
and broadcast, 52, 53, 73, 86–8, 106,
108, 110, 112–13
and democracy, 80–1
face-to-face, see face-to-face interactions
world divided between the ‘interacting’
and ‘interacted’, 8
mediated, 15, 86, 115–16, 136–9, 145, 160
mediated quasi-, 136–7, 144–8, 160
para-social, 144, 148, 153, 166n
practice of, 77, 175
without reciprocity, 144–9, 161, 195,
211, 217
technologically extended, 76, 86, 94–5,
98, 137, 159, 222
and transmission view of
communication, xii, 15, 119, 164, 177
virtual interaction, 61–4, 79, 108,
200, 224n
without reciprocity, 149–51, 195, 205
interactivity, 9, 10, 12–13, 18n, 40,
53–54, 72, 75, 80, 82, 89, 94, 100,
114–15, 117, 195–7, 200, 203–6,
220, 222, 223n
activity versus passivity, 14, 15
249
interactivity, cont.
and broadcast, ix, xi, 10, 12, 50, 84–6,
97–8, 100, 115, 122, 148
interactive society, 8
versus connectivity, 206
interface, 14, 60, 63, 64, 91, 187, 188, 223n
human-technical interface, 2, 180
Interface Culture, 223n
‘Internet and Society’ study, 90, 224n
Internet, ix–xiii, 2, 3–5, 7–17, 17n, 18n, 19n,
31, 36, 40, 42, 44–5, 55–7, 61, 63–4,
66–7, 72–3, 76–80, 81n, 82n, 83–90,
92–3, 95–104, 106, 108, 110, 113–15,
118, 120n, 121n, 122, 128, 132, 141–3,
145, 155, 157, 166n, 169, 175, 177, 183,
189, 190, 193, 201–4, 207, 209, 214, 219,
220–2, 223n, 224n
abstraction and, see abstraction
anarchy of, 8
ARPANET, 47
attraction of Internet communication,
48–50
bulletin board, 17n, 47, 78, 94, 100–1,
104, 196
and cyberspace, 4, 46–7, 48, 50, 114
digital divide, 58, 187
electronic frontier, 9, 48, 65, 202
email, see email
emancipation from broadcast media,
9, 44, 48, 50–4, 84
emoticons, 16, 55, 82n, 161
Fidonet, 47
ICQ, 50, 60, 61
interaction without reciprocity, see
Interaction without reciprocity
‘Internet’ age, 10, 49, 54, 80
Internet community, 194–7, 201, 222
Internet datacasting, 84, 103–5, 106, 120n
Internet Relay Chat (IRC), 17n, 61,
79, 166n
‘Internet Revolution’, 1, 51
Internet Service Provider (ISP), 97
MOOs, 17n, 48, 60–1, 93
MUDs, 17n, 48, 50, 60–1, 184
Net flaming, 69, 100
netiquette, 16, 55, 82n
netizen, 99, 101, 115, 190
newsgroup, 17n, 47, 87, 202
reconstitution of public sphere,
72–5, 120n
redemptive of interactivity, 9, 10, 44,
54, 84, 89, 120n, 189–90, 203
sub-media, 12, 47, 48–50, 77, 79, 80,
90, 94, 96, 104, 150–1, 188, 200, 224n
Usenet, 47, 57, 79, 87
250
COMMUNICATION THEORY
Internet, cont.
and the virtual flâneur, 197, 199–201,
210, 223–4n
the WELL, 47, 61–2, 132, 225n
World Wide Web, see World Wide
Web (WWW)
intranet, 47, 196
ISDN, 80
IVF, 158
Jakobson, Roman, 56
James, Paul, 148, 159–60
Jameson, Frederic, 32
JennyCam, 120
Johnson, Steven, 223n
Jones, Steven, 7, 14, 18n, 60, 62, 68, 194,
200, 204
Jordan, Tim, 38, 47, 50, 61–2, 82n
avatar, 62
CMC as anti-hierarchical, 61
cyberpower, 193
Jowett, Garth, 85–6
Kaplan, N., 74
Kapor, Mitch, 48, 84
Katz, Elihu, 107, 112, 117,119, 133, 208, 216
Katz, Jon, ‘Apparatgeist’ and perpetual
contact, 185–6, 192
‘digital nation’, 73
Kelly, Kevin, 73, 190
Kling, Rob, 150
Kluge, Alexander, 75
Knorr Cetina, Karin, 17n,
117, 181–3
on Heidegger, 181
objectualization, 182
post-social, 182
Knowles, Harry, 104–5
Kroker, Arthur, 19n, 92–3, 115,
117, 143
on McLuhan and the ‘new universal
community’, 189
Kroker, Marilouise, 92–3, 143
Lacan, Jacques, 6, 165n
Lakoff, George, 56, 203–4
Langer, J., 148, 224n
Lanier, Jaron, 191
Lasn, K., 120n
Lasswell, H., 58–9, 119
Lave, J., 176
Lea, M., 82n, 166n
Lealand, Geoff, 19n
Lennon, John, 214, 224n, 225n
Levinson, Paul, 99, 115
Lévy, Pierre, 7, 9
linguistic perspective on media, x,
4–6, 18n, 23, 51, 56, 60, 101–2,
126, 159
semiolinguistics, 124, 128–9, 165n
Lipset, Seymour, 22–3
‘liveness’, 96, 106, 107, 120n, 143, 153, 209,
215, 216–17
Livingstone, S., 7, 224n
local context, 111, 128, 138–9, 141,
145–6, 162
logos, 11, 124, 126, 130
Los Angeles, 120n
Luhmann, Niklas, v., 144
Lukács, Georg, 27
‘reification’, 26, 27, 31, 32, 36, 55, 89
Lyotard, Jean-François, 6, 70
grand narratives, 11, 128, 173
magazines, 24, 25, 36, 56, 73, 96, 105, 112
malls, xii, 37, 67, 68, 195
and flânerie, 170, 199
privatization of public space, 3, 91
Marc, David, 4, 102, 109–11, 114, 120n,
121n, 165n
Martin-Barbero, J., 99, 209, 210
Marvin, S., 43n, 67
Marx, Karl, 26–27, 37, 43n, 191
commodity fetishism, 26, 37
mass media, 5, 7, 9–10, 13, 20, 21–3, 32,
34–8, 40, 42n, 51, 58, 76, 80, 88–90, 96,
99–100, 104–5, 112, 137, 141–2, 144–5,
157, 164, 166n, 176, 195, 196, 200–1,
209, 212
as agent of integration, see Integration,
broadcast
as apparatus of ideology, 25–9, 29–31
as a culture industry, see culture
industry, mass media as ‘path
dependence’
mass society, 21–25, 42n, 82n, 136
‘age of the masses’, 22
‘massification’ of society, 21
mass/elite framework, 21–2, 38
Mattelart, Armand, 54
McCarthy, Anna, 37, 208
McLaughlin, L., 217
McLuhan, Marshall, xi, 5, 8, 38–42, 43n, 51,
69–72, 82n, 94, 99, 103, 107, 113,
114–17, 118, 121n, 129, 142, 143–4, 154,
177, 189, 199, 210, 219
automation, 40, 69
cybernation, 40, 69–71
global village, 39, 74–5, 80, 128–9, 164,
189, 197
Index
McLuhan, Marshall, cont.
Gutenberg or typographic man, 129
hot and cool mediums, 40–1, 70–2,
114, 210
McLuhan Galaxy, 8
media and narcissism, 180–1
‘new universal community’, 189
rear-view mirrorism, 113, 121n
‘re-tribalization’, 69, 72
sociality with objects, 180–1
‘the medium is the message’, 38–42, 143
‘the medium is the massage’, 38, 41
‘to go outside is to be alone’, 199
virtuality, 114, 143
youth and the ‘electric drama’, 186
McQuail, Denis, 39
media effects theory, 4, 42n, 56, 82n, 115
see also effects analysis
media environments, xi, 14, 144, 179,
184, 186
media event, 45, 66, 104, 107, 112, 134, 149,
153, 208, 214, 216
as interruption of routine, 107, 216
‘contest, conquests, and coronations’, 107
Coronation, 107, 207–8
Olympics, 104
Princess Diana, 109, 111, 121n
media friends, 211, 213
media studies, ix–xi, 4–7, 18n, 42n,
43n, 55, 58, 82n, 84, 101, 102, 116–19,
133, 178
focus on content and representation,
ix, 4–5
media stunt, 105
mediation, x, xii, 17n, 42, 52, 89–90, 122,
126, 127, 132, 137–8, 160–2, 164, 173,
202–3, 208, 218
‘disintermediation’, 137–8
mediation-by-agents, 137
problems with, 138–40
remediation, 19n, 43n
media users, 143
‘mediaplace’, 100
mediascape, 222;
and sociality, 177
medium theory, 38, 41–2, 51, 56, 101–3,
113–9, 122–3, 178, 181
and individuality, 140–4
Shannon, C. and Weaver, W., 56, 82n
Mehl, Dominique, 165–6n
Mellencamp, Patricia, 107
Meyrowitz, Joshua, xii, 1, 15, 38–42, 43n,
45, 51, 94, 99, 103, 115–17, 121n, 132,
139, 148, 154–5, 162, 164, 178, 211, 213
death of John Lennon, 224n, 225n
251
Meyrowitz, Joshua, cont.
intentionality, 56, 115, 130–2, 139, 141
media friends, 211, 213
medium-as-environment, 103, 115–17,
121n, 141
medium-as-language, 115
medium-as-vessel/conduit, 103,
115–16, 123, 130, 206
‘second generation medium
theory’, 117–18
sociality with mediums, 178
Microsoft, 184, 223n
MIT Media Lab, 74
Mitchell, David, 41, 42
Mitchell, William J., 67, 183, 199, 200
Morley, Dave, 112–13, 149
Morse, Margaret, 43n, 91, 94, 117, 134
MP3, 66
MTV, 49, 91, 92, 120n, 201
Mullan, Bob, 207–8
broadcast as maintenance of social
order, 207
multi-culturalism, 76
multimedia, 8, 49, 66, 200
Nancy, Jean-Luc, 174
narcissism, 180–1, 184, 204
‘narrow-band’, 79
narrowcasting, 111
‘nation-as-audience’, 111
‘nation-of-audiences’, 111
nation-state, 21, 43n, 75, 80, 81, 171–5,
222n, 223n
Nationwide, 112–13
Negroponte, Nicholas, 7, 9, 10, 18n,
74, 224n
Negt, Oskar, 75
Nelson, Robin, 81–2n
‘Netaid’, 44, 81n
network, ix–xii, 1–5, 8, 10–15, 16–17, 17n,
20, 34, 38, 42, 44, 46–51, 52, 54, 59,
64–6, 68–9, 70, 72, 74, 78–9, 82n, 83, 85,
89, 90, 95–6, 97–103, 109, 110, 113–14,
117–19, 119n, 121n, 130, 132–4, 138,
141–3, 146, 148–9, 156–7, 160–1, 167,
171, 176, 179–81, 192, 194, 196, 201,
205–6, 210, 224n
community, 176, 188–89, see also
virtual community
and democracy, see democracy
dependence on, 3, 143, 178, 180
integration, see integration, network
as normative medium, 14
parasitic of broadcast medium, xi, 12,
52, 79, 83, 86–7, 90, 104–5
252
COMMUNICATION THEORY
network, cont.
sociality with, see dependence
‘network society’, 82n, 101, 129, 171
telecommunity, 188–9
New Criticism, 5
New Media, xii, 8, 13, 17n, 19n, 50, 84, 102,
114, 117–18, 123, 154–5, 159, 166n,
185–188
and digitization, 13
and ideology, 18n
‘new media age’, 7
New Media historicism, 13
youth consumption of, 19, 186–7
Newby, H., 170
Newcomb, H., 101, 120n, 121n
Newcomb, T., 58
news, 23, 34, 40, 66, 86, 105, 109, 111,
112, 120n, 133, 148, 164, 165n, 207,
215–6, 223n
as drama, 134–5
bardic function of, 110
newsflash, 105
newstext on-line, 66
Nguyen, D.T., 72, 117
Nie, Norman, 90, 194, 224n
Nightingale, Virginia, 112–13
Nisbet, Robert, 121n
novel, 24, 105, 115
nuclear power, 158
oikos, 77
Olympics, 104
Ong, Walter, 166n
ontology, 15, 36, 39, 193, 200, 216
optical fibre, 2, 49, 64, 66
Ostwald, Michael, 45–6, 67, 196
otherness, 2, 35
Owen, Bruce, 102
packet-switching, 2, 10
pay-per-view media, 97, 108
PBS, 110
PDA, 66
performativity, 38, 55, 96, 108, 109, 111–2,
121n, 215
‘speech act’, 108, 152
‘speech community’, 108, 192, 210
personal web-page, 100, 145, 213, 220–1
personalization, 13, 68, 91, 92, 177
person-to-person (P2P), 65
phonetic alphabet, 71
photography, 19n, 70, 71, 73, 82n, 117
Plato, 191, 223n
pluralism, 21, 23, 76, 134, 168
polis, 68, 77
positivism, 5, 18n, 23, 33, 42n, 55, 57–8,
131, 188
Poster, Mark, 7, 8–9, 11, 15, 51–3, 73, 78, 80,
82n, 84, 195–6, 221
Postman, N., 17n, 191, 192
post-social, 182–3, 186–8
post-structuralism, 23, 29
presence, 6, 12, 13, 31, 36, 40–1, 61, 81n, 90,
94, 98, 107, 108, 121n, 124, 127–30,
132–3, 135–9, 148–9, 152, 159–60, 165n,
178–9, 203, 221
self-presence, 124, 127–8, 165n
prime-time, 50
process schools, 57, 82n
Proctor, W.S., 46
propaganda, 21, 58
proto-virtual reality, 67, 81n
public space, 3, 68, 77, 92, 117, 120n,
199, 224n
public sphere, 9–11, 42n, 72–81, 92, 99, 102,
154–6, 207, 209
and CMC, 78–9
decline of, 73
democracy and, 23, 72–5, 207
feminist, 75
‘oppositional’ working class, 75
‘post-bourgeois’, 75
reconstitution by Internet, 72–5, 120n
transformation of, 79
‘public-sphericules’, 75–6, 81
radio, 1, 4, 9, 11–13, 17, 19n, 21–2, 25, 34,
40, 45, 51, 65, 70–1, 85, 87, 89, 96, 102,
105–6, 108–9, 112, 114–15, 120n, 121n,
123, 136–7, 144, 147, 196, 208, 212, 223n
radio on-line, 66
Rafaeli, S., 194, 205–6
rage, 93
air-, 99
road-, 69, 99
street-, 99
telephone-, 99
RAND Corporation, 10
RealAudio, 115, 144
‘real time’, 49, 79, 94, 106,
135, 145
Real, M., 105
reality TV, 14, 37, 100, 153, 212, 219–20
and the audience, 85, 113, 147
reciprocity, 10, 20, 49, 53, 55, 64, 81n, 85,
95, 98, 121n, 137, 141, 152, 161, 166n,
196, 212
and broadcast, 110, 144–9, 195, 211,
217, 219
and Internet, 110, 149–51, 195, 205
Index
recognition, 30, 33–4, 100, 110, 121n, 134,
145, 148–9, 151, 156–7, 164, 208, 211–12
community and, 98, 122, 168, 174
face-to-face, 92
field of, 19n, 22, 36, 111, 151, 214,
217, 218, 219
representation, 31–2, 36–7, 43n, 106, 124,
127, 130, 133, 135, 206–7, 215–16, see
also ‘the image’
focus in media studies, ix, 4–5
and identity, 142
Rheingold, Howard, 7, 9, 10, 81n, 84, 97,
132, 188, 195, 224n, 225n
as a nostalgic communitarian, 16
ritual, xii, 14–15, 17, 20, 55, 60, 87, 111, 118,
131–5, 152–3, 165n, 166n, 177, 183, 188,
207–10, 212, 225n
audience communities, 214–15, 217,
221–2, 225n
broadcast communities, 207–10
versus transmission view, 6, 20,
119, 122–35
view of communication, x, 6, 17, 119,
140, 147, 177, 222
Rose, Nikolas, 171–4, 182
Rosen, Ruth, 209
Russell, G., 19n, 63
satellite based communications, 2, 13–14,
51, 64, 66, 94
global positioning system (GPS), 2
‘saturation’ thesis, 2, 127
‘saturated self’, 17n, 155
Saussure, Ferdinand de, 5, 124–5, 165n
‘Copernican revolution’ in
humanities, 5
Schultz, Tanjev, 12–13, 85, 100–1, 120n, 206,
209, 223n
Schwoch, James, 1–3, 17n
second media age, ix–xi, 1–17, 20, 39, 43n,
44–5, 50, 54–5, 58, 60, 64–5, 67, 69, 72,
77, 80, 83–91, 97, 101, 102, 137, 140,
145–6, 195–6, 201, 220, 222
as agent of return of flânerie, 199–201
and first media age, ix, 4, 7–11, 12, 17,
43n, 44, 50, 52, 67, 69, 71, 82n, 83–91,
97, 110, 114, 140, 194, 204
historicism, see historicism
Internet as emancipation from broadcast
media, see Internet, emancipation
as orthodoxy, ix, xi, 8, 19n, 20, 50, 65
‘re-tribalization’, 69, 72
thesis, ix, xi, 4, 8, 12, 20, 50–4, 55, 64, 70,
82n, 84, 87, 101, 102, 148, 185, 187,
201, 222
253
second media age, cont.
utopianism, 7, 18–19n, 52, 57, 74–5, 83,
98, 115, 120n, 128, 157, 179, 189,
191–2, 194–5, 202, 224n
Selfe, C.L., 74–75, 82n
semiotics, ix, 5, 11, 23, 51, 82n, 101, 127,
207, 210
analysis of media, x, xi, 82n, 119
Shannon, C., 55–56, 82n, 119
Sharp, Geoff, 3, 94, 99, 120n, 151, 154,
158–9, 166n, 192
Shields, R., 198
Shils, Edward, 22–3, 207
silicon century, 2
Silverstone, Roger, 3, 18–19n, 180, 207,
223n, 224n
Simmel, G., 121n, 201
Situational/Interactionist perspective, 154–5
Skog, B., 187
Slater, P., 156
Slevin, James, 154, 162–4, 166n
Slouka, Mark, 189, 204
Smith, Marc, 61–2, 64, 82n, 200, 202
SMS, 84, 97, 187, 188
soap opera, 16, 86–7, 111, 119, 148, 209
social architectures, see architectures, social
sociality, 152, 172
‘drive for sociality’, 195
with mediums, 177–80
with objects, 119, 177, 180–3
sociological approach, ix–x, 4, 18n, 22, 25,
42n, 59, 78, 86, 96, 108, 122, 152, 154,
164, 194
Sohn-Rethel, Alfred, 154, 158
Sony Ericsson, 82n
Walkman, 45
spam, 77, 97, 166n
Spears, R., 82n, 166n
spectacle, xii, 6, 12, 24, 27, 31–6, 38, 43n, 55,
89–90, 110–13, 118–19, 120n, 200,
207–8, 210, 218, 219, 224n
spectatorship, 32, 144, 207–8, 212, 220
speech, 5, 10, 11, 23, 39–40, 43n, 47, 49, 56,
58, 60, 65, 69–72, 74, 95, 105, 108–9,
110, 121n, 126, 129, 135, 152, 181, 192,
196, 205, 209–10
Stenger, Nicole, 191–2
‘stimulus’ and ‘response’, 21
Stoll, C., 204, 224n
Stone, A.R., 195–6
Stratton, Jon, 46
subcultures, 8, 43n, 80, 169, 187
subject, 5, 6, 11, 14, 26, 29–30, 33, 34, 42n,
53, 89, 113, 124, 141–3, 170, 174, 178,
188, 193, 205, 211, 221
254
COMMUNICATION THEORY
subject, cont.
as a fiction, 16
‘subject position’, 30, 143, 170
suburbanization, 68, 88, 92, 99, 195
see also city, urbanization, freeway, malls
Sudweeks, F., 194, 205, 206
surveillance, 11, 33, 156, 163, 219–20, 223n
talk show, 24, 165n, 208, 211, 212,
224n, 225n
as ritual, 225n
and audience community, 217–19
host as intermediary, 217
and metonymous identification, 217–19
and the ‘really real’, 218, 222–3n
Taylor, T., 205–206
technological determinism, 12, 17n, 81, 85,
178–9, 186
‘techno-social’ relations, xi, xiii, 12, 60, 84,
155, 156, 162, 179–80, 207
‘technostructure’, 115, 117
telecommunications, 2, 13, 14, 52, 56, 65,
69, 128–9, 135, 161, 167
and cyberspace, 46
convergence, xi, 64
telecommunity, xii, 17n, 111, 122, 167–222
telegraph, 13, 39, 40, 46, 56, 120n, 134
telephone, 1, 2, 12–13, 16–17, 46–7, 48, 51,
56, 61, 65, 68, 70–2, 79, 85–7, 89, 92,
97–9, 114–15, 136, 143–4, 165n, 193
television, 1, 2, 4, 8, 9, 11–15, 17, 18n, 19n,
22, 24, 32–3, 34, 37, 40, 45, 49–52, 58,
64–8, 70–4, 79, 81n, 82n, 84–7, 89, 92–8,
100–3, 105–8, 110–12, 114–17, 120n,
121n, 123, 130, 132, 136–8, 141, 143–8,
153–5, 159, 165n, 166n, 169, 174, 177,
180, 185, 188, 196, 200–1, 206, 208–22,
223n, 224n, 225n
‘TV age’, 71, 92, 93
television studios, 211, 214–15,
217–18, 225n
telnet, 79
Telstra, 97
Terranova, T., 98
terrorism, 43n
see also cyber-terrorism
Tester, Keith, 197
the flâneur, 198, 224n
The Ed Sullivan Show, 109
‘the image’, 5, 15, 31–5, 36–8, 52, 64, 68, 89,
94–5, 105, 117, 214, 221
Thompson, John B., xii, 21, 33, 85, 136–9,
141, 144–8, 151–2, 154, 155, 158, 160,
162, 163–4, 165n, 166n, 208–9, 218
instrumental/mediation paradigm, 137
Thompson, John B., cont.
‘mediated publicness’, 34, 76, 223n
time-space, 163–164
compression, 117
distanciation, 162–3
relations, 162–3
Toffler, Alvin, 221–2
Tofts, Darren, 192–3, 223n
cspace, 192–3
Tönnies, Ferdinand, 167–170
Gemeinschaft, 168–9, 175, 197, 202, 210
Gesellschaft, 168–9, 172, 197
totalization, 127–8
Touraine, Alain, 171–4, 182, 194
‘end of Homo Sociologicus’, 171
decomposition of social norms, 173–4
‘programmed society’, 171–2
society as a technology of managing
populations, 171
tourism, 24, 170, 207, 224n
transmission view, 6, 42n, 53, 58, 118,
130–4, 138, 140
and interaction, xii, 15, 119, 164, 177
and ‘process schools’, 57
versus ritual view, 6, 20, 119, 122–35
‘transport’ model of communication, see
transmission view
Turkle, Sherry, 2, 7, 49, 52, 54, 80, 141–142,
144, 183–4
‘age of the Internet’, 10, 49, 54, 80
computer screen as ‘second self’,
2, 54, 184
digital intimacy, 183–4
United Nations (UN), 44, 67, 222n
urbanization, xi, 12, 21, 32, 67–69, 88, 90,
92, 197
micro-urbanization, 68
urban life, x, 3, 53, 54, 67, 68–9, 78, 83,
91, 120n, 149, 156, 167, 182, 196,
199, 201, 222
see also city, freeway, suburbanization,
malls
Urry, John, 179
Usenet, 47, 57, 79, 87
user perspective, 18n, 59, 143, 180, 223n
‘uses and gratification’ model, 112, 134
van Dijk, J., 64, 65, 82n
Vaudeville, 119n
video, 49, 50, 66, 78, 100, 103, 115, 200
games, 74
video age, 80
video-cafés, 78
video-on-demand, 8, 103–4, 108
Index
Virilio, Paul, 17n, 117, 224n
virtual community, x, xii–xiii, 9, 48, 54, 62,
63, 68, 78, 80, 99, 100, 103, 117, 119,
122, 123, 149, 164, 173, 188, 192, 194–7,
198, 201–6, 224n, 225n
dichotomies of, 179, 203–4
and physical communities, xii, 204–5
three domains of, 204–5
utopian and dystopian versions of,
7, 18–19n, 52, 57, 74–5, 83, 98, 115,
120n, 128, 157, 179, 189, 191–2,
194–5, 202, 203, 224n
and virtual flânerie, 199–201, 210, 223–4n
virtual reality, 16, 72, 94, 114, 121n, 130,
135, 190, 196
and cyberspace, ix, 44–6, 49, 122, 201
‘virtual urbanization’ perspective, 67–9, 91
‘virtuvoltage’, 46
virus, 105
Voog, Anna, 220–1
Walt Disney Studios, 120
Wark, McKenzie, 38, 97–8, 223n
Wasserman, I.M., 214
Watergate, 165n, 208
Watts, Duncan, 189
Weaver, W., 55–6, 82n
Wehner, Joseph, 76–77, 79, 81
the WELL, 47, 61–2, 132, 225n
255
Wellman, Barry, 17n, 194, 202, 204
Wenger, E., 176
Wertheim, Margaret, 190–1
Whitaker, R., 223n
White, Mimi, 1–3, 17n
Whittle, D., 195, 224n
Wiener, Norbert, 56–57
Williams, Christopher, 18n
Williams, Raymond, 85–6, 91–2, 120n, 140,
161–2, 178–9
mobile privatization, xii, 88, 91–3, 98,
99–100, 199
source and agent, 161–2
technical invention, 140
technology-as-socially-configured, 140
Willson, Michelle, 195, 225n
Winston, Brian, 13–14, 19n
Wired, 43n, 73, 113, 115, 189, 190, 202
Wise, J. Macgregor, 202
World Bank, protests, 80
World Health Organization (WHO), 222n
World Wide Web (WWW), 47, 50, 60, 75,
79, 91, 96, 100, 104, 115, 132, 150, 166n,
189, 212, 216
World-Wide-Wait, 90, 201
Y2K bug, 2
Zettl, H., 106