The Complete Works of Boole George
By Boole George
()
About this ebook
The Complete Works of Boole George
George Boole was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in Ireland.
This collection includes the following:
An Investigation of the Laws of Thought
The
Related to The Complete Works of Boole George
Related ebooks
Science and Method Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5An Investigation of the Laws of Thought (Barnes & Noble Digital Library) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Investigation of the Laws of Thought Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsScience and Method (Barnes & Noble Digital Library) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Universe a Vast Electric Organism Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFaith across the Multiverse: Parables from Modern Science Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Scientist: A Short Essay and Two Stories Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe philosophy of B*rtr*nd R*ss*ll Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsUnified Field Theory: The Psychology of Relativity Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSymbolic Logic and the Game of Logic Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGravity Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Electric Meme: A New Theory of How We Think Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5God=mc2?: Getting Spirituality Down to a Science! Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Origin of Consciousness and the Mind-Body Problem Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSuper Logic Modern Mathematics: Classical Mathematics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFifty Economic Fallacies Exposed (Revised) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Opticks Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGravity's Century: From Einstein's Eclipse to Images of Black Holes Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Such is Life Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEmergence 2: An In-Depth Look at the Psychology of AI Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsStable State Universe Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Improbability Principle: Why Coincidences, Miracles, and Rare Events Happen Every Day Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Our Universe and How It Works: Quantum Gravitation and Fifth Dimension Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Critique of Pure Reason Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Kant's Critiques Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Critique of Pure Reason: Bestsellers and famous Books Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Critique of Practical Reason Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Shadows of Thought Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Critique of Practical Reason: The Theory of Moral Reasoning (Kant's Second Critique) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, and on the Will in Nature - Two Essays Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
General Fiction For You
Remarkably Bright Creatures: Curl up with 'that octopus book' everyone is talking about Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Prophet Song: WINNER OF THE BOOKER PRIZE 2023 Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Priory of the Orange Tree: THE NUMBER ONE BESTSELLER Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5French Short Stories for Intermediate Level + AUDIO: Easy Stories for Intermediate French, #1 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Little Life: The Million-Copy Bestseller Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Before the Coffee Gets Cold: The heart-warming million-copy sensation from Japan Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Drive your Plow over the Bones of the Dead Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Learn French for Beginners & Dummies Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Poor Things: Read the extraordinary book behind the award-winning film Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5100 French Short Stories for Beginners and Intermediate Learners: Learn French with Stories + Audiobook Rating: 1 out of 5 stars1/5Welcome to the Hyunam-dong Bookshop: The heart-warming Korean sensation Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5French Short Stories for Beginners: Easy French Beginner Stories, #1 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Little Friend Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Seven Moons of Maali Almeida: Winner of the Booker Prize 2022 Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Bunny: TikTok made me buy it! Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Life of Pi: A Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Galatea: The instant Sunday Times bestseller Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Winners: From the New York Times bestselling author of TikTok phenomenon Anxious People Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tales from the Cafe: Book 2 in the million-copy bestselling Before the Coffee Gets cold series Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5PANENKA Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Alchemist Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tenth of December Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Cold Enough for Snow Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Spinning Silver: A rich and enchanting fairytale retelling Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5First French Reader: A Beginner's Dual-Language Book Rating: 1 out of 5 stars1/5The Seven Deaths of Evelyn Hardcastle: the global million-copy bestseller Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related categories
Reviews for The Complete Works of Boole George
0 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
The Complete Works of Boole George - Boole George
The Complete Works of Boole George
Boole George
Shrine of Knowledge
© Shrine of Knowledge 2020
A publishing centre dectated to publishing of human treasures.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means without the prior written consent of the succession or as expressly permitted by law or under the conditions agreed with the person concerned. copy rights organization. Requests for reproduction outside the above scope must be sent to the Rights Department, Shrine of Knowledge, at the address above.
ISBN 10: 599894598
ISBN 13: 9780599894594
The Complete Works of Boole George
This collection includes the following:
An Investigation of the Laws of Thought
The Mathematical Analysis of Logic Being an Essay Towards a Calculus of Deductive Reasoning
Accordingly, since by the logical reduction the solution of all questions in
the theory of probabilities is brought to a form in which, from the probabilities
of simple events, $s$, $t$, \&c. under a given condition, $V$, it is required to determine
the probability of some combination, $A$, of those events under the same condition,
the principle of the demonstration in Prop. IV. is really the following:--``The
probability of such combination $A$ under the condition $V$ must be calculated
as if the events $s$, $t$, \&c. were independent, and possessed of such probabilities
as would cause the derived probabilities of the said events under the same
condition $V$ to be such as are assigned to them in the data.'' This principle I
regard as axiomatic. At the same time it admits of indefinite verification, as
well directly as through the results of the method of which it forms the basis.
I think it right to add, that it was in the above form that the principle first presented
itself to my mind, and that it is thus that I have always understood it,
the error in the particular problem referred to having arisen from inadvertence
in the choice of a material illustration.
\mainmatter
\chapter[NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK]{\large NATURE AND DESIGN OF THIS WORK.}
1. The design of the following treatise is to investigate the
fundamental laws of those operations of the mind by which
reasoning is performed; to give expression to them in the symbolical
language of a Calculus, and upon this foundation to establish the
science of Logic and construct its method; to make that method
itself the basis of a general method for the application of the mathematical
doctrine of Probabilities; and, finally, to collect from
the various elements of truth brought to view in the course of
these inquiries some probable intimations concerning the nature
and constitution of the human mind.
2. That this design is not altogether a novel one it is almost
needless to remark, and it is well known that to its two main
practical divisions of Logic and Probabilities a very considerable
share of the attention of philosophers has been directed. In its
ancient and scholastic form, indeed, the subject of Logic stands
almost exclusively associated with the great name of Aristotle.
As it was presented to ancient Greece in the partly technical,
partly metaphysical disquisitions of the Organon, such, with
scarcely any essential change, it has continued to the present
day. The stream of original inquiry has rather been directed
towards questions of general philosophy, which, though they
have arisen among the disputes of the logicians, have outgrown
their origin, and given to successive ages of speculation their peculiar
bent and character. The eras of Porphyry and Proclus,
of Anselm and Abelard, of Ramus, and of Descartes, together
with the final protests of Bacon and Locke, rise up before the
mind as examples of the remoter influences of the study upon the
course of human thought, partly in suggesting topics fertile of
discussion, partly in provoking remonstrance against its own undue
pretensions. The history of the theory of Probabilities, on
the other hand, has presented far more of that character of steady
growth which belongs to science. In its origin the early genius
of Pascal,--in its maturer stages of development the most recondite
of all the mathematical speculations of Laplace,--were directed
to its improvement; to omit here the mention of other names
scarcely less distinguished than these. As the study of Logic has
been remarkable for the kindred questions of Metaphysics to
which it has given occasion, so that of Probabilities also has been
remarkable for the impulse which it has bestowed upon the
higher departments of mathematical science. Each of these subjects
has, moreover, been justly regarded as having relation to a
speculative as well as to a practical end. To enable us to deduce
correct inferences from given premises is not the only object of
Logic; nor is it the sole claim of the theory of Probabilities that
it teaches us how to establish the business of life assurance on a
secure basis; and how to condense whatever is valuable in the
records of innumerable observations in astronomy, in physics, or
in that field of social inquiry which is fast assuming a character
of great importance. Both these studies have also an interest
of another kind, derived from the light which they shed upon
the intellectual powers. They instruct us concerning the mode
in which language and number serve as instrumental aids to the
processes of reasoning; they reveal to us in some degree the
connexion between different powers of our common intellect;
they set before us what, in the two domains of demonstrative and
of probable knowledge, are the essential standards of truth and
correctness,--standards not derived from without, but deeply
founded in the constitution of the human faculties. These ends
of speculation yield neither in interest nor in dignity, nor yet, it
may be added, in importance, to the practical objects, with the
pursuit of which they have been historically associated. To unfold
the secret laws and relations of those high faculties of
thought by which all beyond the merely perceptive knowledge
of the world and of ourselves is attained or matured, is an object
which does not stand in need of commendation to a rational
mind.
3. But although certain parts of the design of this work have
been entertained by others, its general conception, its method,
and, to a considerable extent, its results, are believed to be original.
For this reason I shall offer, in the present chapter, some
preparatory statements and explanations, in order that the real
aim of this treatise may be understood, and the treatment of its
subject facilitated.
It is designed, in the first place, to investigate the fundamental
laws of those operations of the mind by which reasoning is
performed. It is unnecessary to enter here into any argument to
prove that the operations of the mind are in a certain real sense
subject to laws, and that a science of the mind is therefore {\it possible}.
If these are questions which admit of doubt, that doubt is not
to be met by an endeavour to settle the point of dispute \textit{\`{a} priori},
but by directing the attention of the objector to the evidence of
actual laws, by referring him to an actual science. And thus the
solution of that doubt would belong not to the introduction to
this treatise, but to the treatise itself. Let the assumption be
granted, that a science of the intellectual powers is possible, and
let us for a moment consider how the knowledge of it is to be
obtained.
4. Like all other sciences, that of the intellectual operations
must primarily rest upon observation,--the subject of such observation
being the very operations and processes of which we
desire to determine the laws. But while the necessity of a foundation
in experience is thus a condition common to all sciences,
there are some special differences between the modes in which
this principle becomes available for the determination of general
truths when the subject of inquiry is the mind, and when the
subject is external nature. To these it is necessary to direct
attention.
The general laws of Nature are not, for the most part, immediate
objects of perception. They are either inductive inferences
from a large body of facts, the common truth in which they express,
or, in their origin at least, physical hypotheses of a causal
nature serving to explain ph{\ae}nomena with undeviating precision,
and to enable us to predict new combinations of them. They
are in all cases, and in the strictest sense of the term, \textit{probable}
conclusions, approaching, indeed, ever and ever nearer to certainty,
as they receive more and more of the confirmation of experience.
But of the character of probability, in the strict and
proper sense of that term, they are never wholly divested. On the
other hand, the knowledge of the laws of the mind does not require
as its basis any extensive collection of observations. The general
truth is seen in the particular instance, and it is not confirmed
by the repetition of instances. We may illustrate this position
by an obvious example. It may be a question whether that formula
of reasoning, which is called the \textit{dictum} of Aristotle, \textit{de omni et nullo},
expresses a primary law of human reasoning or not; but
it is no question that it expresses a general truth in Logic. Now
that truth is made manifest in all its generality by reflection
upon a single instance of its application. And this is both an
evidence that the particular principle or formula in question is
founded upon some general law or laws of the mind, and an illustration
of the doctrine that the perception of such general truths
is not derived from an induction from many instances, but is involved
in the clear apprehension of a single instance. In connexion
with this truth is seen the not less important one that
our knowledge of the laws upon which the science of the intellectual
powers rests, whatever may be its extent or its deficiency, is
not probable knowledge. For we not only see in the particular
example the general truth, but we see it also as a certain truth,--a
truth, our confidence in which will not continue to increase
with increasing experience of its practical verifications.
5. But if the general truths of Logic are of such a nature that
when presented to the mind they at once command assent,
wherein consists the difficulty of constructing the Science of
Logic? Not, it may be answered, in collecting the materials of
knowledge, but in discriminating their nature, and determining
their mutual place and relation. All sciences consist of general
truths, but of those truths some only are primary and fundamental,
others are secondary and derived. The laws of elliptic motion,
discovered by Kepler, are general truths in astronomy, but
they are not its fundamental truths. And it is so also in the
purely mathematical sciences. An almost boundless diversity of
theorems, which are known, and an infinite possibility of others,
as yet unknown, rest together upon the foundation of a few simple
axioms; and yet these are all \textit{general} truths. It may be
added, that they are truths which to an intelligence sufficiently
refined would shine forth in their own unborrowed light, without
the need of those connecting links of thought, those steps
of wearisome and often painful deduction, by which the knowledge
of them is actually acquired. Let us define as fundamental
those laws and principles from which all other general truths of
science may be deduced, and into which they may all be again
resolved. Shall we then err in regarding that as the true science
of Logic which, laying down certain elementary laws, confirmed
by the very testimony of the mind, permits us thence to deduce,
by uniform processes, the entire chain of its secondary consequences,
and furnishes, for its practical applications, methods of
perfect generality? Let it be considered whether in any science,
viewed either as a system of truth or as the foundation of a practical
art, there can properly be any other test of the completeness
and the fundamental character of its laws, than the completeness
of its system of derived truths, and the generality of the methods
which it serves to establish. Other questions may indeed present
themselves. Convenience, prescription, individual preference,
may urge their claims and deserve attention. But as
respects the question of what constitutes science in its abstract
integrity, I apprehend that no other considerations than the
above are properly of any value.
6. It is designed, in the next place, to give expression in this
treatise to the fundamental laws of reasoning in the symbolical
language of a Calculus. Upon this head it will suffice to say, that
those laws are such as to suggest this mode of expression, and
to give to it a peculiar and exclusive fitness for the ends in view.
There is not only a close analogy between the operations of the
mind in general reasoning and its operations in the particular
science of Algebra, but there is to a considerable extent an exact
agreement in the laws by which the two classes of operations are
conducted. Of course the laws must in both cases be determined
independently; any formal agreement between them can only be
established \textit{\`{a} posteriori} by actual comparison. To borrow the
notation of the science of Number, and then assume that in its
new application the laws by which its use is governed will remain
unchanged, would be mere hypothesis. There exist, indeed,
certain general principles founded in the very nature of language,
by which the use of symbols, which are but the elements of
scientific language, is determined. To a certain extent these
elements are arbitrary. Their interpretation is purely conventional:
we are permitted to employ them in whatever sense we
please. But this permission is limited by two indispensable conditions,--first,
that from the sense once conventionally established
we never, in the same process of reasoning, depart; secondly,
that the laws by which the process is conducted be founded exclusively
upon the above fixed sense or meaning of the symbols
employed. In accordance with these principles, any agreement
which may be established between the laws of the symbols of
Logic and those of Algebra can but issue in an agreement of processes.
The two provinces of interpretation remain apart and
independent, each subject to its own laws and conditions.
Now the actual investigations of the following pages exhibit
Logic, in its practical aspect, as a system of processes carried on
by the aid of symbols having a definite interpretation, and subject
to laws founded upon that interpretation alone. But at the
same time they exhibit those laws as identical in form with the
laws of the general symbols of algebra, with this single addition,
viz., that the symbols of Logic are further subject to a special
law (Chap, II.), to which the symbols of quantity, as such, are
not subject. Upon the nature and the evidence of this law it is not
purposed here to dwell. These questions will be fully discussed
in a future page. But as constituting the essential ground of
difference between those forms of inference with which Logic is
conversant, and those which present themselves in the particular
science of Number, the law in question is deserving of more
than a passing notice. It may be said that it lies at the very
foundation of general reasoning,--that it governs those intellectual
acts of conception or of imagination which are preliminary to
the processes of logical deduction, and that it gives to the processes
themselves much of their actual form and expression. It
may hence be affirmed that this law constitutes the germ or seminal
principle, of which every approximation to a general method
in Logic is the more or less perfect development.
7. The principle has already been laid down (5) that the
sufficiency and truly fundamental character of any assumed system
of laws in the science of Logic must partly be seen in the
perfection of the methods to which they conduct us. It remains,
then, to consider what the requirements of a general method in
Logic are, and how far they are fulfilled in the system of the present
work.
Logic is conversant with two kinds of relations,--relations
among things, and relations among facts. But as facts are expressed
by propositions, the latter species of relation may, at
least for the purposes of Logic, be resolved into a relation among
propositions. The assertion that the fact or event $A$ is an invariable
consequent of the fact or event $B$ may, to this extent at
least, be regarded as equivalent to the assertion, that the truth
of the proposition affirming the occurrence of the event $B$ always
implies the truth of the proposition affirming the occurrence of
the event $A$. Instead, then, of saying that Logic is conversant
with relations among things and relations among facts, we are
permitted to say that it is concerned with relations among things
and relations among propositions. Of the former kind of relations
we have an example in the proposition--``All men are mortal;''
of the latter kind in the proposition--``If the sun is totally
eclipsed, the stars will become visible.'' The one expresses a relation
between ``men'' and ``mortal beings,'' the other between
the elementary propositions--``The sun is totally eclipsed;''
``The stars will become visible.'' Among such relations I suppose
to be included those which affirm or deny existence with
respect to things, and those which affirm or deny truth with respect
to propositions. Now let those things or those propositions
among which relation is expressed be termed the elements of
the propositions by which such relation is expressed. Proceeding
from this definition, we may then say that the \textit{premises} of any
logical argument express \textit{given} relations among certain elements,
and that the conclusion must express an \textit{implied} relation among
those elements, or among a part of them, i.e. a relation implied
by or inferentially involved in the premises.
8. Now this being premised, the requirements of a general
method in Logic seem to be the following:--
1st. As the conclusion must express a relation among the
whole or among a part of the elements involved in the premises,
it is requisite that we should possess the means of eliminating
those elements which we desire not to appear in the conclusion,
and of determining the whole amount of relation implied by the
premises among the elements which we wish to retain. Those
elements which do not present themselves in the conclusion are,
in the language of the common Logic, called middle terms; and
the species of elimination exemplified in treatises on Logic consists
in deducing from two propositions, containing a common element
or middle term, a conclusion connecting the two remaining terms.
But the problem of elimination, as contemplated in this work,
possesses a much wider scope. It proposes not merely the elimination
of one middle term from two propositions, but the elimination
generally of middle terms from propositions, without
regard to the number of either of them, or to the nature of their
connexion. To this object neither the processes of Logic nor
those of Algebra, in their actual state, present any strict parallel.
In the latter science the problem of elimination is known to be
limited in the following manner:--From two equations we can
eliminate one symbol of quantity; from three equations two
symbols; and, generally, from $n$ equations $n-1$ symbols. But
though this condition, necessary in Algebra, seems to prevail in
the existing Logic also, it has no essential place in Logic as a
science. There, no relation whatever can be proved to prevail
between the number of terms to be eliminated and the number
of propositions from which the elimination is to be effected.
From the equation representing a single proposition, any number
of symbols representing terms or elements in Logic may be
eliminated; and from any number of equations representing propositions,
one or any other number of symbols of this kind may
be eliminated in a similar manner. For such elimination there
exists one general process applicable to all cases. This is one of
the many remarkable consequences of that distinguishing law of
the symbols of Logic, to which attention has been already
directed.
2ndly. It should be within the province of a general method
in Logic to express the final relation among the elements of the
conclusion by any admissible \textit{kind} of proposition, or in any selected
\textit{order} of terms. Among varieties of kind we may reckon
those which logicians have designated by the terms categorical,
hypothetical, disjunctive, \&c. To a choice or selection in the
order of the terms, we may refer whatsoever is dependent upon
the appearance of particular elements in the subject or in the
predicate, in the antecedent or in the consequent, of that proposition
which forms the ``conclusion.'' But waiving the language
of the schools, let us consider what really distinct species of
problems may present themselves to our notice. We have seen
that the elements of the final or inferred relation may either be
\textit{things} or \textit{propositions}. Suppose the former case; then it might
be required to deduce from the premises a definition or description
of some one thing, or class of things, constituting an element of
the conclusion in terms of the other things involved in it. Or
we might form the conception of some thing or class of things,
involving more than one of the elements of the conclusion, and
require its expression in terms of the other elements. Again,
suppose the elements retained in the conclusion to be propositions,
we might desire to ascertain such points as the following,
viz., Whether, in virtue of the premises, any of those propositions,
taken singly, are true or false?--Whether particular
combinations of them are true or false?--Whether, assuming a
particular proposition to be true, any consequences will follow,
and if so, what consequences, with respect to the other
propositions?--Whether any particular condition being assumed with
reference to certain of the propositions, any consequences, and
what consequences, will follow with respect to the others? and
so on. I say that these are general questions, which it should
fall within the scope or province of a general method in Logic to
solve. Perhaps we might include them all under this one statement
of the final problem of practical Logic. Given a set of
premises expressing relations among certain elements, whether
things or propositions: required explicitly the whole relation
consequent among \textit{any} of those elements under any proposed
conditions, and in any proposed form. That this problem, under
all its aspects, is resolvable, will hereafter appear. But it is not
for the sake of noticing this fact, that the above inquiry into the
nature and the functions of a general method in Logic has been
introduced. It is necessary that the reader should apprehend
what are the specific ends of the investigation upon which we
are entering, as well as the principles which are to guide us to
the attainment of them.
9. Possibly it may here be said that the Logic of Aristotle,
in its rules of syllogism and conversion, sets forth the elementary
processes of which all reasoning consists, and that beyond these
there is neither scope nor occasion for a general method. I have
no desire to point out the defects of the common Logic, nor do I
wish to refer to it any further than is necessary, in order to place
in its true light the nature of the present treatise. With this
end alone in view, I would remark:--1st. That syllogism, conversion,
\&c., are not the ultimate processes of Logic. It will
be shown in this treatise that they are founded upon, and are resolvable
into, ulterior and more simple processes which constitute
the real elements of method in Logic. Nor is it true in fact that
all inference is reducible to the particular forms of syllogism and
conversion.--\textit{Vide} Chap. xv. 2ndly. If all inference were reducible
to these two processes (and it has been maintained that
it is reducible to syllogism alone), there would still exist the
same necessity for a general method. For it would still be requisite
to determine in what order the processes should succeed
each other, as well as their particular nature, in order that the
desired relation should be obtained. By the desired relation I
mean that full relation which, in virtue of the premises, connects
any elements selected out of the premises at will, and which,
moreover, expresses that relation in any desired form and order.
If we may judge from the mathematical sciences, which are the
most perfect examples of method known, this \textit{directive} function
of Method constitutes its chief office and distinction. The fundamental
processes of arithmetic, for instance, are in themselves
but the elements of a possible science. To assign their nature is
the first business of its method, but to arrange their succession
is its subsequent and higher function. In the more complex
examples of logical deduction, and especially in those which form
a basis for the solution of difficult questions in the theory of
Probabilities, the aid of a directive method, such as a Calculus
alone can supply, is indispensable.
10. Whence it is that the ultimate laws of Logic are mathematical
in their form; why they are, except in a single point,
identical with the general laws of Number; and why in that particular
point they differ;--are questions upon which it might not
be very remote from presumption to endeavour to pronounce a
positive judgment. Probably they lie beyond the reach of our
limited faculties. It may, perhaps, be permitted to the mind to
attain a knowledge of the laws to which it is itself subject, without
its being also given to it to understand their ground and
origin, or even, except in a very limited degree, to comprehend
their fitness for their end, as compared with other and conceivable
systems of law. Such knowledge is, indeed, unnecessary for the
ends of science, which properly concerns itself with what is, and
seeks not for grounds of preference or reasons of appointment.
These considerations furnish a sufficient answer to all protests
against the exhibition of Logic in the form of a Calculus. It is
not because we choose to assign to it such a mode of manifestation,
but because the ultimate laws of thought render that mode
possible, and prescribe its character, and forbid, as it would
seem, the perfect manifestation of the science in any other form,
that such a mode demands adoption. It is to be remembered
that it is the business of science not to create laws, but to discover
them. We do not originate the constitution of our own minds,
greatly as it may be in our power to modify their character.
And as the laws of the human intellect do not depend upon our
will, so the forms of the science, of which they constitute the basis,
are in all essential regards independent of individual choice.
11. Beside the general statement of the principles of the
above method, this treatise will exhibit its application to the
analysis of a considerable variety of propositions, and of trains of
propositions constituting the premises of demonstrative arguments.
These examples have been selected from various writers,
they differ greatly in complexity, and they embrace a wide range
of subjects. Though in this particular respect it may appear to
some that too great a latitude of choice has been exercised, I do
not deem it necessary to offer any apology upon this account.
That Logic, as a science, is susceptible of very wide applications
is admitted; but it is equally certain that its ultimate forms and
processes are mathematical. Any objection \textit{\`{a} priori} which may
therefore be supposed to lie against the adoption of such forms
and processes in the discussion of a problem of morals or of general
philosophy must be founded upon misapprehension or false
analogy. It is not of the essence of mathematics to be conversant
with the ideas of number and quantity. Whether as a general
habit of mind it would be desirable to apply symbolical processes
to moral argument, is another question. Possibly, as I have
elsewhere observed,\footnote{Mathematical Analysis of Logic. London : G. Bell. 1847.}
the perfection of the method of Logic may
be chiefly valuable as an evidence of the speculative truth of its
principles. To supersede the employment of common reasoning,
or to subject it to the rigour of technical forms, would be the last
desire of one who knows the value of that intellectual toil and
warfare which imparts to the mind an athletic vigour, and teaches
it to contend with difficulties, and to rely upon itself in emergencies.
Nevertheless, cases may arise in which the value of a
scientific procedure, even in those things which fall confessedly
under the ordinary dominion of the reason, may be felt and acknowledged.
Some examples of this kind will be found in the
present work.
12. The general doctrine and method of Logic above explained
form also the basis of a theory and corresponding method
of Probabilities. Accordingly, the development of such a theory
and method, upon the above principles, will constitute a distinct
object of the present treatise. Of the nature of this application
it may be desirable to give here some account, more especially as
regards the character of the solutions to which it leads. In connexion
with this object some further detail will be requisite concerning
the forms in which the results of the logical analysis are
presented.
The ground of this necessity of a prior method in Logic, as
the basis of a theory of Probabilities, may be stated in a few
words. Before we can determine the mode in which the expected
frequency of occurrence of a particular event is dependent upon
the known frequency of occurrence of any other events, we must be
acquainted with the mutual dependence of the events themselves.
Speaking technically, we must be able to express the event
whose probability is sought, as a function of the events whose
probabilities are given. Now this explicit determination belongs
in all instances to the department of Logic. Probability, however,
in its mathematical acceptation, admits of numerical measurement.
Hence the subject of Probabilities belongs equally to
the science of Number and to that of Logic. In recognising the
co-ordinate existence of both these elements, the present treatise
differs from all previous ones; and as this difference not only
affects the question of the possibility of the solution of problems
in a large number of instances, but also introduces new and important
elements into the solutions obtained, I deem it necessary
to state here, at some length, the peculiar consequences of the
theory developed in the following pages.
13. The measure of the probability of an event is usually
defined as a fraction, of which the numerator represents the number
of cases favourable to the event, and the denominator the
whole number of cases favourable and unfavourable; all cases
being supposed equally likely to happen. That definition is
adopted in the present work. At the same time it is shown that
there is another aspect of the subject (shortly to be referred to)
which might equally be regarded as fundamental, and which
would actually lead to the same system of methods and conclusions.
It may be added, that so far as the received conclusions
of the theory of Probabilities extend, and so far as they are consequences
of its fundamental definitions, they do not differ from
the results (supposed to be equally correct in inference) of the
method of this work.
Again, although questions in the theory of Probabilities
present themselves under various aspects, and may be variously
modified by algebraical and other conditions, there seems to be
one general type to which all such questions, or so much of each
of them as truly belongs to the theory of Probabilities, may be
referred. Considered with reference to the \textit{data} and the \textit{qu\ae{}situm},
that type may be described as follows:---1st. The data are
the probabilities of one or more given events, each probability
being either that of the absolute fulfilment of the event to which
it relates, or the probability of its fulfilment under given supposed
conditions. 2ndly. The \textit{qu\ae{}situm}, or object sought, is the
probability of the fulfilment, absolutely or conditionally, of some
other event differing in expression from those in the data, but
more or less involving the same elements. As concerns the data,
they are either \textit{causally given},---as when the probability of a particular
throw of a die is deduced from a knowledge of the constitution
of the piece,---or they are derived from observation of
repeated instances of the success or failure of events. In the
latter case the probability of an event may be defined as the
limit toward which the ratio of the favourable to the whole number
of observed cases approaches (the uniformity of nature being
presupposed) as the observations are indefinitely continued.
Lastly, as concerns the nature or relation of the events in question,
an important distinction remains. Those events are either
\textit{simple} or \textit{compound}. By a compound event is meant one of
which the expression in language, or the conception in thought,
depends upon the expression or the conception of other events,
which, in relation to it, may be regarded as \textit{simple} events. To
say ``it rains,'' or to say ``it thunders,'' is to express the occurrence
of a simple event; but to say ``it rains and thunders,'' or
to say ``it either rains or thunders,'' is to express that of a compound
event. For the expression of that event depends upon
the elementary expressions, ``it rains,'' ``it thunders.'' The criterion
of simple events is not, therefore, any supposed simplicity
in their nature. It is founded solely on the mode of their expression
in language or conception in thought.
14. Now one general problem, which the existing theory of
Probabilities enables us to solve, is the following, viz.:---Given
the probabilities of any simple events: required the probability of
a given compound event, i.e. of an event compounded in a given
manner out of the given simple events. The problem can also
be solved when the compound event, whose probability is required,
is subjected to given conditions, i.e. to conditions dependent
also in a given manner on the given simple events.
Beside this general problem, there exist also particular problems
of which the principle of solution is known. Various questions
relating to \textit{causes} and \textit{effects} can be solved by known methods
under the particular hypothesis that the causes are mutually exclusive,
but apparently not otherwise. Beyond this it is not
clear that any advance has been made toward the solution of
what may be regarded as the general problem of the science, viz.:
Given the probabilities of any events, simple or compound, conditioned
or unconditioned: required the probability of any other
event equally arbitrary in expression and conception. In the
statement of this question it is not even postulated that the
events whose probabilities are given, and the one whose probability
is sought, should involve some common elements, because
it is the office of a method to determine whether the data of a
problem are sufficient for the end in view, and to indicate, when
they are not so, wherein the deficiency consists.
This problem, in the most unrestricted form of its statement,
is resolvable by the method of the present treatise; or, to speak
more precisely, its theoretical solution is completely given, and
its practical solution is brought to depend only upon processes
purely mathematical, such as the resolution and analysis of equations.
The order and character of the general solution may be
thus described.
15. In the first place it is always possible, by the preliminary
method of the Calculus of Logic, to express the event whose
probability is sought as a logical function of the events whose
probabilities are given. The result is of the following character:
Suppose that $X$ represents the event whose probability is sought,
$A$, $B$, $C$, \&c. the events whose probabilities are given, those
events being either simple or compound. Then the \textit{whole} relation
of the event $X$ to the events $A$, $B$, $C$, \&c. is deduced in the
form of what mathematicians term a \textit{development}, consisting, in
the most general case, of four distinct classes of terms. By the
first class are expressed those combinations of the events $A$, $B$, $C$,
which both necessarily accompany and necessarily indicate the
occurrence of the event $X$; by the second class, those combinations
which necessarily accompany, but do not necessarily imply,
the occurrence of the event $X$; by the third class, those combinations
whose occurrence in connexion with the event $X$ is impossible,
but not otherwise impossible; by the fourth class,
those combinations whose occurrence is impossible under any circumstances.
I shall not dwell upon this statement of the result
of the logical analysis of the problem, further than to remark
that the elements which it presents are precisely those by which
the expectation of the event $X$, as dependent upon our knowledge
of the events $A$, $B$, $C$, is, or alone can be, affected. General
reasoning would verify this conclusion; but general reasoning
would not usually avail to disentangle the complicated web
events and circumstances from which the solution above described
must be evolved. The attainment of this object constitutes
the first step towards the complete solution of the question I
proposed. It is to be noted that thus far the process of solution
is logical, i. e. conducted by symbols of logical significance, and
resulting in an equation interpretable into a \textit{proposition}. Let this
result be termed the \textit{final logical equation}.
The second step of the process deserves attentive remark.
From the final logical equation to which the previous step has
conducted us, are deduced, by inspection, a series of algebraic
equations implicitly involving the complete solution of the problem
proposed. Of the mode in which this transition is effected
let it suffice to say, that there exists a definite relation between
the laws by which the probabilities of events are expressed as
algebraic functions of the probabilities of other events upon which
they depend, and the laws by which the logical connexion of
the events is itself expressed. This relation, like the other coincidences
of formal law which have been referred to, is not
founded upon hypothesis, but is made known to us by observation
(I.4), and reflection. If, however, its reality were assumed \textit{\`{a} priori}
as the basis of the very definition of Probability, strict deduction
would thence lead us to the received numerical definition as a
necessary consequence. The Theory of Probabilities stands, as
it has already been remarked (I.12), in equally close relation to
Logic and to Arithmetic; and it is indifferent, so far as results
are concerned, whether we regard it as springing out of the latter
of these sciences, or as founded in the mutual relations which
connect the two together.
16. There are some circumstances, interesting perhaps to the
mathematician, attending the general solutions deduced by the
above method, which it may be desirable to notice.
1st. As the method is independent of the number and the
nature of the data, it continues to be applicable when the latter
are insufficient to render determinate the value sought. When
such is the case, the final expression of the solution will contain
terms with arbitrary constant coefficients. To such terms there
will correspond terms in the final logical equation (I. 15), the
interpretation of which will inform us what new data are requisite
in order to determine the values of those constants, and
thus render the numerical solution complete. If such data are
not to be obtained, we can still, by giving to the constants their
limiting values $0$ and $1$, determine the limits within which the
probability sought must lie independently of all further experience.
When the event whose probability is sought is \textit{quite} independent
of those whose probabilities are given, the limits thus
obtained for its value will be $0$ and $1$, as it is evident that they
ought to be, and the interpretation of the constants will only
lead to a re-statement of the original problem.
2ndly. The expression of the final solution will in all cases
involve a particular element of quantity, determinable by the solution
of an algebraic equation. Now when that equation is of
an elevated degree, a difficulty may seem to arise as to the selection
of the proper root. There are, indeed, cases in which
both the elements given and the element sought are so obviously
restricted by necessary conditions that no choice remains. But
in complex instances the discovery of such conditions, by unassisted
force of reasoning, would be hopeless. A distinct method
is requisite for this end,---a method which might not
appropriately be termed the Calculus of Statistical Conditions,
into the nature of this method I shall not here further enter
than to say, that, like the previous method, it is based upon the
employment of the ``final logical equation,'' and that it definitely
assigns, 1st, the conditions which must be fulfilled among the
numerical elements of the data, in order that the problem may
be real, i.e. derived from a \textit{possible experience}; 2ndly, the numerical
limits, within which the probability sought must have
been confined, if, instead of being determined by theory, it had
been deduced directly by observation from the same system of
ph{\ae}nomena from which the data were derived. It is clear that
these limits will be actual limits of the probability sought.
Now, on supposing the data subject to the conditions above assigned
to them, it appears in every instance which I have examined
that there exists one root, and only one root, of the final
algebraic equation which is subject to the required limitations.
Every source of ambiguity is thus removed. It would even seem
that new truths relating to the theory of algebraic equations
are thus incidentally brought to light. It is remarkable that
the special element of quantity, to which the previous discussion
relates, depends only upon the \textit{data}, and not at all upon the
\textit{qu\ae{}situm} of the problem proposed. Hence the solution of each
particular problem unties the knot of difficulty for a system of
problems, viz., for that system of problems which is marked by
the possession of common data, independently of the nature of
their \textit{qu\ae{}sita}. This circumstance is important whenever from a
particular system of data it is required to deduce a series of connected
conclusions. And it further gives to the solutions of
particular problems that character of relationship, derived from
their dependence upon a central and fundamental unity, which
not unfrequently marks the application of general methods.
17. But though the above considerations, with others of a
like nature, justify the assertion that the method of this treatise,
for the solution of questions in the theory of Probabilities, is a
general method, it does not thence follow that we are relieved in
all cases from the necessity of recourse to hypothetical grounds.
It has been observed that a solution may consist entirely of terms
affected by arbitrary constant coefficients,---may, in fact, be
wholly indefinite. The application of the method of this work to
some of the most important questions within its range would--were
the data of experience alone employed--present results of
this character. To obtain a \textit{definite} solution it is necessary, in
such cases, to have recourse to hypotheses possessing more or less
of independent probability, but incapable of exact verification.
Generally speaking, such hypotheses will differ from the immediate
results of experience in partaking of a logical rather than of a
numerical character; in prescribing the conditions under which
ph{\ae}nomena occur, rather than assigning the relative frequency
of their occurrence. This circumstance is, however, unimportant.
Whatever their nature may be, the hypotheses assumed must
thenceforth be regarded as belonging to the actual data, although
tending, as is obvious, to give to the solution itself somewhat of
a hypothetical character. With this understanding as to the
possible sources of the data actually employed, the method is
perfectly general, but for the correctness of the hypothetical elements
introduced it is of course no more responsible than for the
correctness of the numerical data derived from experience.
In illustration of these remarks we may observe that the
theory of the reduction of astronomical observations\footnote{
The author designs to treat this subject either in a separate work or in a
future Appendix. In the present treatise he avoids the use of the integral
calculus.}
rests, in
part, upon hypothetical grounds. It assumes certain positions
as to the nature of error, the equal probabilities of its occurrence
in the form of excess or defect, \&c., without which it would be
impossible to obtain any \textit{definite} conclusions from a system of
conflicting observations. But granting such positions as the
above, the residue of the investigation falls strictly within the
province of the theory of Probabilities. Similar observations
apply to the important problem which proposes to deduce from
the records of the majorities of a deliberative assembly the mean
probability of correct judgment in one of its members. If the
method of this treatise be applied to the mere numerical data,
the solution obtained is of that wholly indefinite kind above described.
And to show in a more eminent degree the insufficiency
of those data by themselves, the interpretation of the arbitrary
constants (I. 16) which appear in the solution, merely produces
a re-statement of the original problem. Admitting, however,
the hypothesis of the independent formation of opinion in the
individual mind, either absolutely, as in the speculations of
Laplace and Poisson, or under limitations imposed by the actual
data, as will be seen in this treatise, Chap. XXI., the problem assumes
a far more definite character. It will be manifest that the
ulterior value of the theory of Probabilities must depend very
much upon the correct formation of such mediate hypotheses,
where the purely experimental data are insufficient for \textit{definite}
solution, and where that further experience indicated by the interpretation
of the final logical equation is unattainable. Upon
the other hand, an undue readiness to form hypotheses in subjects
which from their very nature are placed beyond human
ken, must re-act upon the credit of the theory of Probabilities,
and tend to throw doubt in the general mind over its most legitimate
conclusions.
18. It would, perhaps, be premature to speculate here upon
the question whether the methods of abstract science are likely at
any future day to render service in the investigation of social
problems at all commensurate with those which they have rendered
in various departments of physical inquiry. An attempt
to resolve this question upon pure \textit{\`{a} priori} grounds of reasoning
would be very likely to mislead us. For example, the consideration
of human free-agency would seem at first sight to preclude
the idea that the movements of the social system should ever manifest
that character of orderly evolution which we are prepared
to expect under the reign of a physical necessity. Yet already
do the researches of the statist reveal to us facts at variance with
such an anticipation. Thus the records of crime and pauperism
present a degree of regularity unknown in regions in which the
disturbing influence of human wants and passions is unfelt. On
the other hand, the distemperature of seasons, the eruption of
volcanoes, the spread of blight in the vegetable, or of epidemic
maladies in the animal kingdom, things apparently or chiefly the
product of natural causes, refuse to be submitted to regular and
apprehensible laws. ``Fickle as the wind,'' is a proverbial expression.
Reflection upon these points teaches us in some degree
to correct our earlier judgments. We learn that we are not to
expect, under the dominion of necessity, an order perceptible to
human observation, unless the play of its producing causes is
sufficiently simple; nor, on the other hand, to deem that free
agency in the individual is inconsistent with regularity in the
motions of the system of which he forms a component unit.
Human freedom stands out as an apparent fact of our consciousness,
while it is also, I conceive, a highly probable deduction of
analogy (Chap, XXII.) from the nature of that portion of the
mind whose scientific constitution we are able to investigate.
But whether accepted as a fact reposing on consciousness, or as
a conclusion sanctioned by the reason, it must be so interpreted
as not to conflict with an established result of observation, viz.:
that ph\ae{}nomena, in the production of which large masses of men
are concerned, do actually exhibit a very remarkable degree of
regularity, enabling us to collect in each succeeding age the elements
upon which the estimate of its state and progress, so far
as manifested in outward results, must depend. There is thus no
sound objection \textit{\`{a} priori} against the possibility of that species of
data which is requisite for the experimental foundation of a
science of social statistics. Again, whatever other object this
treatise may accomplish, it is presumed that it will leave no
doubt as to the existence of a system of abstract principles and of
methods founded upon those principles, by which any collective
body of social data may be made to yield, in an explicit form,
whatever information they implicitly involve. There may, where
the data are exceedingly complex, be very great difficulty in obtaining
this information,---difficulty due not to any imperfection
of the theory, but to the laborious character of the analytical
processes to which it points. It is quite conceivable that in many
instances that difficulty may be such as only united effort could