Plato Politicl Thoughts
Plato Politicl Thoughts
Plato Politicl Thoughts
For other uses, see Plato (disambiguation) and Platon rigorous and systematic examination of ethical, political,
(disambiguation).
metaphysical, and epistemological issues, armed with a
distinctive methodcan be called his invention. Few
[1]
Plato (/pleto/; Greek: Pltn pronounced other authors in the history of Western philosophy approximate him in depth and range: perhaps only Aristotle
[pl.tn] in Classical Attic; 428/427 or 424/423
would be gen348/347 BC) was a philosopher and mathematician in (who studied with him), Aquinas and Kant
[10]
erally
agreed
to
be
of
the
same
rank.
Classical Greece, and the founder of the Academy in
Athens, the rst institution of higher learning in the
Western world. He is widely considered the most pivotal
gure in the development of philosophy, especially the 1
Western tradition.[2] Unlike nearly all of his philosophical
contemporaries, Platos entire uvre is believed to have
1.1
survived intact for over 2,400 years.[3][4]
Along with his teacher, Socrates, and his most famous
student, Aristotle, Plato laid the very foundations of
Western philosophy and science.[5] Alfred North Whitehead once noted: the safest general characterization
of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.[6] In addition
to being a foundational gure for Western science, philosophy, and mathematics, Plato has also often been
cited as one of the founders of Western religion and
spirituality,[7] particularly Christianity, which Friedrich
Nietzsche, amongst other scholars, called Platonism for
the people.[8] Platos inuence on Christian thought is
often thought to be mediated by his major inuence on
Saint Augustine of Hippo, one of the most important
philosophers and theologians in the history of Christianity. Plato was the innovator of the dialogue and dialectic
forms in philosophy, which originate with him. Plato
appears to have been the founder of Western political
philosophy, with his Republic, and Laws among other
dialogues, providing some of the earliest extant treatments of political questions from a philosophical perspective. Platos own most decisive philosophical inuences
are usually thought to have been Socrates, Parmenides,
Heraclitus and Pythagoras, although few of his predecessors works remain extant and much of what we know
about these gures today derives from Plato himself.[9]
Biography
Early life
1 BIOGRAPHY
Republic as sons of Ariston,[14] and presumably brothers of Plato, but some have argued they were uncles.[15]
But in a scenario in the Memorabilia, Xenophon confused the issue by presenting a Glaucon much younger
than Plato.[16]
The sources of Diogenes account for this fact by claiming that his wrestling coach, Ariston of Argos, dubbed
him Platon, meaning broad, on account of his robust gure[28] or that Plato derived his name from the
breadth (, platyts) of his eloquence, or else
because he was very wide (, plats) across the
forehead.[29] Recently a scholar has argued that even the
name Aristocles for Plato was a much later invention.[30]
Although Platon was a fairly common name (31 instances
are known from Athens alone[31] ), the name does not occur in Platos known family line. The fact that the philosopher in his maturity called himself Platon is indisputable,
but the origin of this naming must remain moot unless
the record is made to yield more information.
According to some accounts, Ariston tried to force his attentions on Perictione, but failed in his purpose; then the
god Apollo appeared to him in a vision, and as a result,
Ariston left Perictione unmolested.[19] Another legend related that, when Plato was an infant, bees settled on his
lips while he was sleeping: an augury of the sweetness of
style in which he would discourse about philosophy.[20]
Ariston appears to have died in Platos childhood, although the precise dating of his death is dicult.[21] Perictione then married Pyrilampes, her mothers brother,[22]
who had served many times as an ambassador to the
Persian court and was a friend of Pericles, the leader of
the democratic faction in Athens.[23] Pyrilampes had a
son from a previous marriage, Demus, who was famous
for his beauty.[24] Perictione gave birth to Pyrilampes
second son, Antiphon, the half-brother of Plato, who appears in Parmenides.[25]
In contrast to reticence about himself, Plato often introduced his distinguished relatives into his dialogues,
or referred to them with some precision: Charmides
has a dialogue named after him; Critias speaks in both
Charmides and Protagoras; and Adeimantus and Glaucon
take prominent parts in the Republic.[26] These and other
references suggest a considerable amount of family pride
and enable us to reconstruct Platos family tree. According to Burnet, the opening scene of the Charmides is a
glorication of the whole [family] connection ... Platos
dialogues are not only a memorial to Socrates, but also
the happier days of his own family.[27]
1.1.2
Name
1.1.3 Education
Apuleius informs us that Speusippus praised Platos
quickness of mind and modesty as a boy, and the rst
fruits of his youth infused with hard work and love of
study.[32] Plato must have been instructed in grammar,
music, and gymnastics by the most distinguished teachers of his time.[33] Dicaearchus went so far as to say that
Plato wrestled at the Isthmian games.[34] Plato had also
attended courses of philosophy; before meeting Socrates,
he rst became acquainted with Cratylus (a disciple of
Heraclitus, a prominent pre-Socratic Greek philosopher)
and the Heraclitean doctrines.[35] W. A. Borody argues
that an Athenian openness towards a wider range of sexuality may have contributed to the Athenian philosophers openness towards a wider range of thought, a
cultural situation Borody describes as polymorphously
discursive.[36]
1.4
Later life
1.3
PHILOSOPHY
stroyed by Lucius Cornelius Sulla in 84 BCE. Neoplatonists revived the Academy in the early 5th century, and
it operated until AD 529, when it was closed by Justinian
I of Byzantium, who saw it as a threat to the propagation
of Christianity. Many intellectuals were schooled in the
Academy, the most prominent one being Aristotle.[45][46]
Throughout his later life, Plato became entangled with the
politics of the city of Syracuse. According to Diogenes
Laertius, Plato initially visited Syracuse while it was under the rule of Dionysius.[47] During this rst trip Dionysiuss brother-in-law, Dion of Syracuse, became one of
Platos disciples, but the tyrant himself turned against
Plato. Plato almost faced death, but he was sold into
slavery. Then Anniceris[48] bought Platos freedom for
twenty minas,[49] and sent him home. After Dionysiuss
death, according to Platos Seventh Letter, Dion requested
Plato return to Syracuse to tutor Dionysius II and guide
him to become a philosopher king. Dionysius II seemed
to accept Platos teachings, but he became suspicious of
Dion, his uncle. Dionysius expelled Dion and kept Plato
against his will. Eventually Plato left Syracuse. Dion
would return to overthrow Dionysius and ruled Syracuse
for a short time before being usurped by Calippus, a fellow disciple of Plato.
1.5
Death
2
2.1
Philosophy
Recurrent themes
tionship of the older man and his boy lover to the fatherson relationship (Lysis 213a, Republic 3.403b), and in the
Phaedo, Socrates disciples, towards whom he displays
more concern than his biological sons, say they will feel
fatherless when he is gone.
In several of Platos dialogues, Socrates promulgates the
idea that knowledge is a matter of recollection, and not of
learning, observation, or study.[53] He maintains this view
somewhat at his own expense, because in many dialogues,
Socrates complains of his forgetfulness. Socrates is often
found arguing that knowledge is not empirical, and that
it comes from divine insight. In many middle period dialogues, such as the Phaedo, Republic and Phaedrus Plato
advocates a belief in the immortality of the soul, and
several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the
afterlife. More than one dialogue contrasts knowledge
and opinion, perception and reality, nature and custom,
and body and soul.
Several dialogues tackle questions about art: Socrates
says that poetry is inspired by the muses, and is not rational. He speaks approvingly of this, and other forms of divine madness (drunkenness, eroticism, and dreaming) in
the Phaedrus (265ac), and yet in the Republic wants to
outlaw Homers great poetry, and laughter as well. In Ion,
Socrates gives no hint of the disapproval of Homer that
he expresses in the Republic. The dialogue Ion suggests
2.3
Theory of Forms
2.2
Metaphysics
5
that perfect justice exists (although it is not clear where)
and his own trial would be a cheap copy of it.
The allegory of the cave (often said by scholars to represent Platos own epistemology and metaphysics) is intimately connected to his political ideology (often said to
also be Platos own), that only people who have climbed
out of the cave and cast their eyes on a vision of goodness
are t to rule. Socrates claims that the enlightened men
of society must be forced from their divine contemplations and be compelled to run the city according to their
lofty insights. Thus is born the idea of the "philosopherking", the wise person who accepts the power thrust upon
him by the people who are wise enough to choose a good
master. This is the main thesis of Socrates in the Republic, that the most wisdom the masses can muster is the
wise choice of a ruler.
PHILOSOPHY
edge which Gettier addresses is equivalent to Platos is accepted by some scholars but rejected by others.[56] Plato
himself also identied problems with the justied true belief denition in the Theaetetus, concluding that justication (or an account) would require knowledge of differentness, meaning that the denition of knowledge is
circular (Theaetetus 210ab).[57]
Later in the Meno, Socrates uses a geometrical example to
expound Platos view that knowledge in this latter sense
is acquired by recollection. Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy, who
could not have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave
boys lack of education). The knowledge must be present,
Socrates concludes, in an eternal, non-experiential form.
In other dialogues, the Sophist, Statesman, Republic, and
the Parmenides, Plato himself associates knowledge with
the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to one another (which he calls expertise in
Dialectic), including through the processes of collection
and division.[58] More explicitly, Plato himself argues in Papirus Oxyrhynchus, with fragment of Platos Republic
the Timaeus that knowledge is always proportionate to the
realm from which it is gained. In other words, if one deetc. These correspond to the appetite part of the
rives ones account of something experientially, because
soul.
the world of sense is in ux, the views therein attained
Protective (Warriors or Guardians) those who are
will be mere opinions. And opinions are characterized
adventurous, strong and brave; in the armed forces.
by a lack of necessity and stability. On the other hand,
These correspond to the spirit part of the soul.
if one derives ones account of something by way of the
non-sensible forms, because these forms are unchanging,
Governing (Rulers or Philosopher Kings) those
so too is the account derived from them. That apprehenwho are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love
sion of forms is required for knowledge may be taken to
with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the
[59]
cohere with Platos theory in the Theaetetus and Meno.
community. These correspond to the reason part
Indeed, the apprehension of Forms may be at the base of
of the soul and are very few.
the account required for justication, in that it oers
foundational knowledge which itself needs no account,
In the Timaeus, Plato locates the parts of the soul within
thereby avoiding an innite regression.[60]
the human body: Reason is located in the head, spirit in
the top third of the torso, and the appetite in the middle
third of the torso, down to the navel.[62][63]
2.5 The state
Main article: The Republic (Plato)
Platos philosophical views had many societal implications, especially on the idea of an ideal state or government. There is some discrepancy between his early and
later views. Some of the most famous doctrines are contained in the Republic during his middle period, as well
as in the Laws and the Statesman. However, because
Plato wrote dialogues, it is assumed that Socrates is often
speaking for Plato. This assumption may not be true in
all cases.
Plato, through the words of Socrates, asserts that societies have a tripartite class structure corresponding to
the appetite/spirit/reason structure of the individual soul.
The appetite/spirit/reason are analogous to the castes of
society.[61]
2.6
Unwritten doctrines
7
responsible for such actions, rather than one individual
committing many bad deeds.) This is emphasised within
the Republic as Plato describes the event of mutiny on
board a ship.[64] Plato suggests the ships crew to be in
line with the democratic rule of many and the captain,
although inhibited through ailments, the tyrant. Platos
description of this event is parallel to that of democracy
within the state and the inherent problems that arise.
THE DIALOGUES
and the good and beautiful ... will not, when in earnest,
write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words,
which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth eectually. The same argument is
repeated in Platos Seventh Letter (344 c): every serious man in dealing with really serious subjects carefully
avoids writing. In the same letter he writes (341 c): I
can certainly declare concerning all these writers who
claim to know the subjects that I seriously study ... there
does not exist, nor will there ever exist, any treatise of
mine dealing therewith. Such secrecy is necessary in order not to expose them to unseemly and degrading treatment (344 d).
It is, however, said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good (
), in which the Good ( ) is identied
with the One (the Unity, ), the fundamental ontological principle. The content of this lecture has been
transmitted by several witnesses. Aristoxenus describes
the event in the following words: Each came expecting
to learn something about the things that are generally considered good for men, such as wealth, good health, physical strength, and altogether a kind of wonderful happiness. But when the mathematical demonstrations came,
including numbers, geometrical gures and astronomy,
and nally the statement Good is One seemed to them, I
imagine, utterly unexpected and strange; hence some belittled the matter, while others rejected it.[74] Simplicius
quotes Alexander of Aphrodisias, who states that according to Plato, the rst principles of everything, including the Forms themselves are One and Indenite Duality ( ), which he called Large and Small
( )", and Simplicius reports as
well that one might also learn this from Speusippus and
Xenocrates and the others who were present at Platos lecture on the Good.[30]
2.7 Dialectic
3.2
genes Laertius to an ancient scholar and court astrologer scholars such as E.R. Dodds and has been summarized
to Tiberius named Thrasyllus.
by Harold Bloom in his book titled Agon: E.R. Dodds is
The works are usually grouped into Early, (sometimes by the classical scholar whose writings most illuminated the
some into Transitional), Middle, and Late period.[83][84] Hellenic descent (in) The Greeks and the Irrational [...]
This choice to group chronologically is thought worthy of In his chapter on Plato and the Irrational Soul [...] Dodds
criticism by some (Cooper et al),[85] given that its recog- traces Platos spiritual evolution from the pure rationalnised that there is no absolute agreement as to the true ist of the Protagoras to the transcendental psychologist,
Orphics, of the later
chronologicity, since the facts of the temporal order of inuenced by the Pythagoreans and
works culminating in the Laws.[90]
[86]
writing are not condently ascertained.
[91]
to make exhaustive
Early : Apology (of Socrates), Charmides, Crito, Lewis Campbell was the rst
use
of
stylometry
to
prove
objectively
that the Critias,
Euthyphro, Gorgias, (Lesser) Hippias (minor), (Greater)
Timaeus,
Laws,
Philebus,
Sophist,
and
Statesman were
Hippias (major), Ion, Laches, Lysis, Protagoras
all clustered together as a group, while the Parmenides,
Middle/Transitional : Cratylus, Euthydemus, Meno, Phaedrus, Republic, and Theaetetus belong to a separate
Parmenides, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Republic, Symposium,
group, which must be earlier (given Aristotles statement
in his Politics[92] that the Laws was written after the ReMiddle/Late : Theaetetus
public; cf. Diogenes Laertius Lives 3.37). What is reLate : Critias, Sophist, Statesman / Politicus, Timaeus , markable about Campbells conclusions is that, in spite
Philebus, Laws
of all the stylometric studies that have been conducted
Chronologicity was not a consideration in ancient times, since his time, perhaps the only chronological fact about
in that grouping of this nature are virtually absent (Tar- Platos works that can now be said to be proven by stylometry is the fact that Critias, Timaeus, Laws, Philebus,
rant) in the extant writings of ancient Platonists.[87]
Sophist, and Statesman are the latest of Platos dialogues,
the others earlier.[93]
3.1
Increasingly in the most recent Plato scholarship, writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Platos
writings can be established with any precision,[94] though
Platos works are still often characterized as falling at least
roughly into three groups.[95] The following represents
one relatively common such division.[96] It should, however, be kept in mind that many of the positions in the
ordering are still highly disputed, and also that the very
notion that Platos dialogues can or should be ordered
is by no means universally accepted.
First Alcibiades (*), Second Alcibiades (), Clitophon (*), Among those who classify the dialogues into periods of
Epinomis (), Epistles (*), Hipparchus (), Menexenus(*), composition, Socrates gures in all of the early dialogues and they are considered the most faithful repreMinos () (Rival) Lovers (), Theages ()
sentations of the historical Socrates.[97] They include The
Apology of Socrates, Charmides, Crito, Euthyphro, Ion,
Laches, Lesser Hippias, Lysis, Menexenus, and Protago3.1.1 Spurious writings
ras (often considered one of the last of the early diaThe following works were transmitted under Platos logues). Three dialogues are often considered transiname, most of them already considered spurious in an- tional or pre-middle": Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Meno.
tiquity, and so were not included by Thrasyllus in his Whereas those classied as early dialogues often contetralogical arrangement. These works are labelled as clude in aporia, the so-called middle dialogues provide
Notheuomenoi (spurious) or Apocrypha.
more clearly stated positive teachings that are often ascribed to Plato such as the theory of Forms. These di Axiochus, Denitions, Demodocus, Epigrams, alogues include Cratylus, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Republic,
Eryxias, Halcyon, On Justice, On Virtue, Sisyphus.
Symposium, Parmenides, and Theaetetus. Proponents of
dividing the dialogues into periods often consider the
Parmenides and Theaetetus to come late in this period
3.2 Composition of the dialogues
and be transitional to the next, as they seem to treat the
theory of Forms critically (Parmenides) or only indirectly
No one knows the exact order Platos dialogues were writ- (Theaetetus).[98] Ritters stylometric analysis places Phaeten in, nor the extent to which some might have been drus as probably after Theaetetus and Parmenides,[99] allater revised and rewritten. A signicant distinction of though it does not relate to the theory of Forms in the
the early Plato and the later Plato has been oered by
10
same way. The rst book of the Republic is often thought
to have been written signicantly earlier than the rest of
the work, although possibly having undergone revisions
when the later books were attached to it.[98]
THE DIALOGUES
3.6
Platonic scholarship
11
bad reputation, and ultimately, his death. In the Symposium, the two of them are drinking together with other
friends. The character Phaedrus is linked to the main
story line by character (Phaedrus is also a participant in
the Symposium and the Protagoras) and by theme (the
philosopher as divine emissary, etc.) The Protagoras is
also strongly linked to the Symposium by characters: all
of the formal speakers at the Symposium (with the exception of Aristophanes) are present at the home of Callias
in that dialogue. Charmides and his guardian Critias are
present for the discussion in the Protagoras. Examples
of characters crossing between dialogues can be further
multiplied. The Protagoras contains the largest gathering
of Socratic associates.
In the dialogues Plato is most celebrated and admired for,
Socrates is concerned with human and political virtue,
has a distinctive personality, and friends and enemies who
travel with him from dialogue to dialogue. This is not
to say that Socrates is consistent: a man who is his friend
in one dialogue may be an adversary or subject of his
mockery in another. For example, Socrates praises the
wisdom of Euthyphro many times in the Cratylus, but
makes him look like a fool in the Euthyphro. He disparages sophists generally, and Prodicus specically in
the Apology, whom he also slyly jabs in the Cratylus for
charging the hefty fee of fty drachmas for a course on
language and grammar. However, Socrates tells Theaetetus in his namesake dialogue that he admires Prodicus and
has directed many pupils to him. Socrates ideas are also
The safest general characterisation of the European philosophnot consistent within or between or among dialogues.
ical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato.
(Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality, 1929).
3.6
Platonic scholarship
totles and other Platonist philosophers works (see AlFarabi, Avicenna, Averroes, Hunayn ibn Ishaq). Many
of these comments on Plato were translated from Arabic into Latin and as such inuenced Medieval scholastic
philosophers.[106]
During the Renaissance, with the general resurgence of
interest in classical civilization, knowledge of Platos philosophy would become widespread again in the West.
Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists
who broke with Scholasticism and fostered the owering of the Renaissance, with the support of the Platoinspired Lorenzo (grandson of Cosimo), saw Platos philosophy as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences.
His political views, too, were well-received: the vision
of wise philosopher-kings of the Republic matched the
views set out in works such as Machiavelli's The Prince.
More problematic was Platos belief in metempsychosis,
transmigration of the soul, as well as his ethical views
(on polyamory and euthanasia in particular), which did
not match those of Christianity. It was Plethons student
Bessarion who reconciled Plato with Christian theology,
arguing that Platos views were only ideals, unattainable
due to the fall of man.[107]
12
THE DIALOGUES
at least on par with Aristotles. Notable Western philosophers have continued to draw upon Platos work since
that time. Platos inuence has been especially strong
in mathematics and the sciences. He helped to distinguish between pure and applied mathematics by widening
the gap between arithmetic, now called number theory
and logistic, now called arithmetic. He regarded logistic as appropriate for business men and men of war
who must learn the art of numbers or he will not know
how to array his troops, while arithmetic was appropriate for philosophers because he has to arise out of
the sea of change and lay hold of true being.[108] Platos
resurgence further inspired some of the greatest advances
in logic since Aristotle, primarily through Gottlob Frege
and his followers Kurt Gdel, Alonzo Church, and Alfred
Tarski. Albert Einstein suggested that the scientist who
takes philosophy seriously would have to avoid systematization and take on many dierent roles, and possibly
appear as a Platonist or Pythagorean, in that such a one
would have the viewpoint of logical simplicity as an indispensable and eective tool of his research.[109]
Many recent philosophers have diverged from what some
would describe as the ontological models and moral ideals characteristic of traditional Platonism. A number of
these postmodern philosophers have thus appeared to disparage Platonism from more or less informed perspectives. Friedrich Nietzsche notoriously attacked Platos
idea of the good itself along with many fundamentals
of Christian morality, which he interpreted as Platonism for the masses in one of his most important works,
Beyond Good and Evil (1886). Martin Heidegger argued against Platos alleged obfuscation of Being in his incomplete tome, Being and Time (1927), and the philosopher of science Karl Popper argued in The Open Society
and Its Enemies (1945) that Platos alleged proposal for
a utopian political regime in the Republic was prototypically totalitarian. The political philosopher and professor
Leo Strauss is considered by some as the prime thinker involved in the recovery of Platonic thought in its more political, and less metaphysical, form. Strauss political approach was in part inspired by the appropriation of Plato
and Aristotle by medieval Jewish and Islamic political
philosophers, especially Maimonides and Al-Farabi, as
opposed to the Christian metaphysical tradition that developed from Neoplatonism. Deeply inuenced by Nietzsche and Heidegger, Strauss nonetheless rejects their
condemnation of Plato and looks to the dialogues for a
solution to what all three latter day thinkers acknowledge
as 'the crisis of the West.'
3.7
First page of the Euthyphro, from the Clarke Plato (Codex Oxoniensis Clarkianus 39), 895 AD. The text is Greek minuscule.
13
by Oxford University in 1809.[114] The Clarke is given
the siglum B in modern editions. B contains the rst six
tetralogies and is described internally as being written by
John the Calligrapher on behalf of Arethas of Caesarea.
It appears to have undergone corrections by Arethas
himself.[115] For the last two tetralogies and the apocrypha, the oldest surviving complete manuscript is Codex
Parisinus graecus 1807, designated A, which was written nearly contemporaneously to B, circa 900 AD.[116]
A must be a copy of the edition edited by the patriarch,
Photios, teacher of Arethas.[117][118][119] A probably had
an initial volume containing the rst 7 tetralogies which
is now lost, but of which a copy was made, Codex Venetus
append. class. 4, 1, which has the siglum T. The oldest
manuscript for the seventh tetralogy is Codex Vindobonensis 54. suppl. phil. Gr. 7, with siglum W, with a
supposed date in the twelfth century.[120] In total there
are fty-one such Byzantine manuscripts known, while
others may yet be found.[121]
To help establish the text, the older evidence of papyri
and the independent evidence of the testimony of commentators and other authors (i.e., those who quote and
refer to an old text of Plato which is no longer extant)
are also used. Many papyri which contain fragments of
Platos texts are among the Oxyrhynchus Papyri. The
2003 Oxford Classical Texts edition by Slings even cites
the Coptic translation of a fragment of the Republic in
the Nag Hammadi library as evidence.[122] Important authors for testimony include Olympiodorus the Younger,
Plutarch, Proclus, Iamblichus, Eusebius, and Stobaeus.
During the early Renaissance, the Greek language and,
along with it, Platos texts were reintroduced to Western
Europe by Byzantine scholars. In September or October of 1484 Filippo Valori and Francesco Berlinghieri
printed 1025 copies of Ficinos translation, using the
printing press at the Dominican convent S.Jacopo di
Ripoli.[123][124] Cosimo had been inuenced toward
studying Plato by the many Byzantine Platonists in Florence during his day, including George Gemistus Plethon.
Henri Estiennes edition, including parallel Greek and
Latin, was published in 1578. It was this edition which
established Stephanus pagination, still in use today.[125]
3.8
Modern editions
4 See also
Cambridge Platonists
List of speakers in Platos dialogues
Methexis
Platos tripartite theory of soul
Platonic Academy
Platonic love
Platonic solid
Platonic realism
Proclus
Seventh Letter
Theia mania
Ellen Francis Mason, translator of Plato
5 Notes
a. ^ Plato is a nickname from the adjective
plats broad. Diogenes Laertius mentions three possible meanings of the nickname:[136]
' ,
[],
.
,
.
And he learnt gymnastics under Ariston, the
Argive wrestler. And from him he received
14
6 FOOTNOTES
the name of Plato on account of his robust gure, in place of his original name which was
Aristocles, after his grandfather, as Alexander informs us in his Successions of Philosophers. But others arm that he got the name
Plato from the breadth of his style, or from the
breadth of his forehead, as suggested by Neanthes.
6 Footnotes
[1] Jones 2006.
[2] quote="...the subject of philosophy, as it is often
conceiveda rigorous and systematic examination of ethical, political, metaphysical, and epistemological issues,
armed with a distinctive methodcan be called his invention http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/
[3] See introduction. https://books.google.com/books?id=
eSKTvJDrr5kC&printsec=frontcover&source=gbs_ge_
summary_r&cad=0#v=onepage&q&f=false
[4] quote= " one of the most dazzling writers in the Western
literary tradition and one of the most penetrating, wideranging, and inuential authors in the history of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/
[5] Plato. Encyclopaedia Britannica. 2002.
[6] Whitehead 1978, p. 39.
[7] http://rebels-library.org/files/foucault_hermeneutics.pdf
[8] http://www.gutenberg.org/files/4363/4363-h/4363-h.
htm
15
16
6 FOOTNOTES
[79] For a brief description of the problem see for example [97] Dodds 2004.
Gaiser 1980. A more detailed analysis is given by Krmer [98] Brandwood 1990, p. 251.
1990. Another description is by Reale 1997 and Reale
1990. A thorough analysis of the consequences of such an [99] Brandwood 1990, p. 77.
approach is given by Szlezak 1999. Another supporter of
this interpretation is the German philosopher Karl Albert, [100] Meinwald 1991.
cf. Albert 1980 or Albert 1996. Hans-Georg Gadamer
[101] The time is not long after the death of Socrates; for the
is also sympathetic towards it, cf. Grondin 2010 and
Pythagoreans [Echecrates & co.] have not heard any deGadamer 1980. Gadamers nal position on the subject
tails yet (Burnet 1911, p. 5).
is stated in Gadamer 1997.
[80] Blackburn 1996, p. 104.
17
of numbers or he will not know how to array his troops. [133] Complete Works - Philosophy
The philosopher, on the other hand, must be an arithmetician because he has to arise out of the sea of change and [134] Clarendon Plato Series - Philosophy Series - Series - Academic, Professional, & General - Oxford University Press
lay hold of true being."'
[109] Einstein 1949, pp. 683684.
[111] Irwin 2011, pp. 64 & 74. See also Slings 1987, p. 34:
"... primary MSS. together oer a text of tolerably good [137] Seneca, Epistulae, VI 58:29-30; translation by Robert
Mott Gummere
quality (this is without the further corrections of other
sources).
[138] Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, II
[112] Slings 1987, p. 31.
Browne 1672.
Nails 2006, p. 1.
Wilamowitz-Moellendor 2005, p. 46.
Plato. Encyclopaedia Britannica. 2002.
Plato. Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume V
(in Greek). 1952.
Seneca, Epistulae, VI, 58, 31: natali suo decessit et annum
umum atque octogensimum.
[118] RS Brumbaugh - Plato for the Modern Age (p.199) Uni- [146] Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, III
versity Press of America, 1 Jan 1991 ISBN 0819183563
[147] Nails 2002, p. 54.
[Retrieved 2015-3-20]
[119] J Duy - The lonely mission of Michael Psellos (in) [148] Thucydides, 5.18
Thucydides, 8.92
Byzantine Philosophy and Its Ancient Sources edited by
K Ierodiakonou (Oxford University Press, 2004) ISBN
0199269718 [Retrieved 2015-3-20]
[120] Dodds 1959, p. 39.
[121] Irwin 2011, p. 71.
[122] Slings 2003, p. xxiii.
[123] J Hankins - (p.301) ISBN 9004091610 [Retrieved 20153-20]
[124] Allen 1975, p. 12.
[125] Suzanne 2009.
[126] Cooper 1997, pp. xii & xxvii.
[127] Oxford Classical Texts - Classical Studies & Ancient History Series - Series - Academic, Professional, & General Oxford University Press
[128] Cambridge Greek and Latin Classics - Series - Academic
and Professional Books - Cambridge University Press
[129] Cambridge Classical Texts and Commentaries - Series Academic and Professional Books - Cambridge University
Press
[130] Irwin 1979, pp. vi & 11.
[131] Dodds 1959.
[132] Fine 1999a, p. 482.
7 References
7.1 Primary sources (Greek and Roman)
Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, I. See original text
in Latin Library.
Aristophanes, The Wasps.
Perseus program.
Plato.
Charmides. Translated by Benjamin
Jowett. Wikisource. See original text in Perseus
program.
Plato.
Gorgias. Translated by Benjamin Jowett.
Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program.
Plato, Parmenides. See original text in Perseus program.
18
Plato.
The Republic. Translated by Benjamin
Jowett. Wikisource. See original text in Perseus
program.
Plutarch (1683) [written in the late 1st century].
" Pericles". Lives. Translated by John Dryden.
Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program.
REFERENCES
Thucydides.
History of the Peloponnesian War.
Translated by Richard Crawley. Wikisource., V,
VIII. See original text in Perseus program.
Xenophon, Memorabilia.
Perseus program.
7.2
Secondary sources
Albert, Karl (1980). Griechische Religion und platonische Philosophie. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.
Albert, Karl (1996). Einfhrung in die philosophische Mystik. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Allen, Michael J. B. (1975). Introduction. Marsilio Ficino: The Philebus Commentary. University
of California Press. pp. 158.
Baird, Forrest E.; Kaufmann, Walter, eds. (2008).
Philosophic Classics: From Plato to Derrida (Fifth
ed.). Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson
Prentice Hall. ISBN 0-13-158591-6.
Blackburn, Simon (1996). The Oxford Dictionary
of Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
Bloom, Harold (1982). Agon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Blssner, Norbert (2007). The City-Soul Analogy. In Ferrari, G. R. F. The Cambridge Companion to Platos Republic. Translated from the German
by G. R. F. Ferrari. Cambridge University Press.
Borody, W. A. (1998). Figuring the Phallogocentric Argument with Respect to the Classical Greek
Philosophical Tradition. Nebula, A Netzine of the
Arts and Science 13: 127.
Boyer, Carl B. (1991). Merzbach, Uta C., ed. A
History of Mathematics (Second ed.). John Wiley &
Sons. ISBN 0-471-54397-7.
Brandwood, Leonard (1990). The Chronology of
Platos Dialogues. Cambridge University Press.
7.2
Secondary sources
19
Fine, Gail (2003). Introduction. Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays. Oxford University
Press.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1980) [1968]. Platos Unwritten Dialectic. Dialogue and Dialectic. Yale
University Press. pp. 124155.
Guthrie, W.K.C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy: Volume 4, Plato: The Man and His Dialogues:
Earlier Period. Cambridge University Press. ISBN
0-521-31101-2.
Hasse, Dag Nikolaus (2002). Plato arabicolatinus. In Gersh; Hoenen. The Platonic Tradition
in the Middle Ages: A Doxographic Approach. De
Gruyter. pp. 3366.
Irwin, T. H. (1979). Plato: Gorgias. Oxford University Press.
Irwin, T. H. (2011). The Platonic Corpus. In
Fine, G. The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford
University Press.
Jones, Daniel (2006). Roach, Peter; Hartman,
James; Setter, Jane, eds. Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary (17 ed.). Cambridge University Press.
Kahn, Charles H. (1996). Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form.
Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-64830-0.
Nails, Debra (2002). The People of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 0-87220-564-9.
Nails, Debra (2006). The Life of Plato of Athens.
In Benson, Hugh H. A Companion to Plato. Blackwell Publishing. ISBN 1-4051-1521-1.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm (1967).
Vorlesungsaufzeichnungen. Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (in German). Walter de Gruyter. ISBN
3-11-013912-X.
Notopoulos, A. (April 1939). The Name of Plato.
Classical Philology (The University of Chicago
Press) 34 (2): 135145. doi:10.1086/362227.
Penner, Terry (1992). Socrates and the Early Dialogues. In Kraut, Richard. The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. pp.
121169.
20
Plato. Encyclopaedia Britannica. 2002.
Plato. Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume XVI (in Greek). 1952.
Plato. Suda. 10th century.
8 FURTHER READING
Szlezak, Thomas A. (1999). Reading Plato. Routledge. ISBN 0-415-18984-5.
Tarn, Leonardo (1981).
Brill Publishers.
Speusippus of Athens.
8 Further reading
Alican, Necip Fikri (2012). Rethinking Plato: A
Cartesian Quest for the Real Plato. Amsterdam and
New York: Editions Rodopi B.V. ISBN 978-90420-3537-9.
Allen, R. E. (1965). Studies in Platos Metaphysics
II. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 0710036264
Ambuel, David (2007). Image and Paradigm in
Platos Sophist. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 9781-930972-04-9
Arieti, James A. Interpreting Plato: The Dialogues
as Drama, Rowman & Littleeld Publishers, Inc.
ISBN 0-8476-7662-5
Bakalis, Nikolaos (2005). Handbook of Greek
Philosophy: From Thales to the Stoics Analysis
and Fragments, Traord Publishing ISBN 1-41204843-5
Barrow, Robin (2007). Plato: Continuum Library of
Educational Thought. Continuum. ISBN 0-82648408-5.
Cadame, Claude (1999). Indigenous and Modern Perspectives on Tribal Initiation Rites: Education According to Plato, pp. 278312, in Padilla,
Mark William (editor), Rites of Passage in Ancient
Greece: Literature, Religion, Society, Bucknell
University Press, 1999. ISBN 0-8387-5418-X
21
Cooper, John M. & Hutchinson, D. S. (Eds.)
(1997). Plato: Complete Works. Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. ISBN 0-87220-349-2.
Corlett, J. Angelo (2005). Interpreting Platos Dialogues. Parmenides Publishing. ISBN 978-1930972-02-5
Durant, Will (1926). The Story of Philosophy. Simon & Schuster. ISBN 0-671-69500-2.
Derrida, Jacques (1972). La dissmination, Paris:
Seuil. (esp. cap.: La Pharmacie de Platon, 69-199)
ISBN 2-02-001958-2
Field, G.C. (Guy Cromwell) (1969). The Philosophy
of Plato (2nd ed. with an appendix by R. C. Cross.
ed.). London: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19888040-5.
Irwin, Terence (1995). Platos Ethics, Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19-508645-7
Jackson, Roy (2001). Plato: A Beginners Guide.
London: Hoder & Stroughton. ISBN 0-340-803851.
Jowett, Benjamin (1892). [The Dialogues of Plato.
Translated into English with analyses and introductions by B. Jowett.], Oxford Clarendon Press, UK,
UIN:BLL01002931898
Kochin, Michael S. (2002). Gender and Rhetoric in
Platos Political Thought. Cambridge Univ. Press.
ISBN 0-521-80852-9.
Kraut, Richard (Ed.) (1993). The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. ISBN
0-521-43610-9.
Fine, Gail (2000). Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology Oxford University Press, USA, ISBN 0-19875206-7
Finley, M. I. (1969). Aspects of antiquity: Discoveries and Controversies The Viking Press, Inc., USA
22
Nightingale, Andrea Wilson. (1995). Genres in
Dialogue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy,
Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-48264-X
EXTERNAL LINKS
9 External links
Works available on-line:
Plato
Platos Academy
Platos Organicism
Platos Phaedo
Platos Republic
Platos Theaetetus
Middle Platonism
Neoplatonism
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
Plato
Platos Ethics
Friendship and Eros
Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology
Plato on Utopia
Rhetoric and Poetry
Other resources:
Plato at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology
Project
Plato at PhilPapers
"Plato and Platonism". Catholic Encyclopedia.
New York: Robert Appleton Company. 1913.
Website on Plato and his works: Plato and his
dialogues by Bernard Suzanne
Approaching Plato: A Guide to the Early and
Middle Dialogues
23
10
10.1
24
10
Arjun01, Goldsmitharmy, Mtevfrog, Tholly, Dgfdgf, Wild Pansy, Uriel8, Mschel, Pallasathena~enwiki, R'n'B, Kane2742, CommonsDelinker, Nwhitehair, Hairchrm, Dionysiaca, FlyingWookieeofDoom, Iamryan365, J.delanoy, Nev1, Slideshow Bob, Cyborg Ninja, Shas,
HistoryOne, Brenda maverick, Alex2706, OddMNilsen, LordAnubisBOT, Cursorial, Austin512, Samtheboy, Sirfrosties, AdamBMorgan,
KowDude, Stevenw988, Rcnet, AntiSpamBot, (jarbarf), 97198, Chiswick Chap, Flyingricepaddy, Allreet, NewEnglandYankee, Urzadek,
Touch Of Light, 83d40m, Malerin, Brian Pearson, Mufka, Jay ryann, Milogardner, Zoso101, Madhava 1947, MetsFan76, Juliancolton,
WJBscribe, Rich182, SBKT, U.S.A.U.S.A.U.S.A., AppleCinamon, Sarregouset, Freepunk, Don Brillante, Inwind, Barak181, Dorftrottel,
Ttias, Celebrei, Eddiedog, Xcountry99, Center4499, Lights, Vranak, X!, PeaceNT, Bandaidboy, Deor, C.lettingaAV, VolkovBot, Macedonian, ArqMage, Je G., Indubitably, NikolaiLobachevsky, Ph8l, Kaiilaiqualyn, Dominics Fire, Mcewan, Philip Trueman, Dchmelik,
StellarDude, TXiKiBoT, Templovesbryan, Vryk, NatT941, Python182, Kriak, Technopat, Stephen jonathan morris, Balorio, Thmazing,
Miranda, Rei-bot, Anonymous Dissident, Greentriangle86, Qxz, Retiono Virginian, Koranjem, Lradrama, Ontoraul, Afp2258, Martin451,
Gsimlote, Abdullais4u, LeaveSleaves, Icelord1125, Cremepu222, Ilyushka88, Arpan123, Maxim, Redpijka, Syncrosh, Eric9876, Blacksheetofpaper, Eldredo, Frankenngers, Taurenrulz, Verbist, Finngall, SQL, Aweihgiwurhg, Fleurstigter, Burntsauce, Sylent, Mallerd,
Bunty234, Thanatos666, BraveLittleToaster, Nsau101449, Insanity Incarnate, Mattieo9123, Dessymona, Klapper, Doc James, AlleborgoBot, Quantpole, Logan, ZBrannigan, Legoktm, Cowlinator, Oiophron~enwiki, EmxBot, Austriacus, Joseph Jervis, Blcckl, Himan12345,
Cosprings, SieBot, StAnselm, Tresiden, Fixer1234, YonaBot, M0ib, Letterhead, Nihil novi, Moonriddengirl, Euryalus, BotMultichill,
Jauerback, Winchelsea, Gerakibot, Jsc83, Dawn Bard, Caltas, Yintan, Platoboy, Drknow2000, Rubbersoul20, Stratman07, Mr Justice
mk5, JohnLauritsen, Elakhna, Devbhargava, Lightmouse, Techman224, Sparklefaceness, Macy, Mitya1, Spartan-James, Vanished user ewsn2348tui2f8n2o2utjfeoi210r39jf, Cyfal, Dcattell, Pinkadelica, Felixfelis, Denisarona, Ipsumesse, Vonones, Troy 07, Gr8opinionater,
WikipedianMarlith, RegentsPark, Schipbob, Ricardo Frantz, ClueBot, Editor at work, Phoenix-wiki, PipepBot, WinedAndDined, Kotniski, Wikievil666, The Thing That Should Not Be, P0mbal, Mild Bill Hiccup, Ashmedai 119, Singinglemon~enwiki, Puchiko, Privatemusings, MindstormsKid, DragonBot, Alexbot, Jusdafax, Cowgirl92, Ludwigs2, Bchaosf, Sun Creator, Juiced Up Chaos, Noosentaal,
Muro Bot, Gennarous, Catalographer, Practical321, Camboxer, Oskar71, Chronicler~enwiki, Jerryofaiken, Pichpich, Dawillia, Stickee,
Rror, WikHead, SilvonenBot, Badgernet, NCDane, Kbdankbot, Mdbertram, Addbot, Wran, Yousou, DOI bot, Atethnekos, Theleftorium,
DaughterofSun, LightSpectra, Nz26, Wingspeed, Fieldday-sunday, Ironholds, Startstop123, CanadianLinuxUser, Leszek Jaczuk, Fluernutter, La Vern De Wilde, Download, BepBot, Bassbonerocks, Debresser, Favonian, SamatBot, LinkFA-Bot, AgadaUrbanit, Tassedethe,
Roaryk, NMHSchool, DubaiTerminator, VASANTH S.N., Erutuon, Tide rolls, Lightbot, , Gail, Alain08, Lilweezyfbaby, JEN9841,
Shippower77, LuK3, Gaberdine2, Luckas-bot, Yobot, Pink!Teen, Fraggle81, Opcn, USA12345, IW.HG, Magog the Ogre, AnomieBOT,
Thuvan Dihn, 1exec1, Jim1138, Galoubet, JackieBot, Keithbob, Mikroth, Christiangamer7, Materialscientist, ImperatorExercitus, Tintero, Citation bot, OllieFury, Gemtpm, LilHelpa, MauritsBot, Xqbot, Timir2, Trap The Drum Wonder, Tad Lincoln, Amore Mio, Grim23,
Trut-h-urts man, Gap9551, Anonymous from the 21st century, GrouchoBot, Omnipaedista, Gott wisst, Cresix, PauAmma, GhalyBot, Sewblon, Lexy-lou, Dougofborg, Spongefrog, Green Cardamom, , FreeKnowledgeCreator, FrescoBot, Anna Roy, T of Locri,
Fludds, MathFacts, HJ Mitchell, Paulhendrickson1245, 09dphelps, Android1961, Becckyairdd, Jaxon8969, Beforepluto, U Knee Verse 1,
Citation bot 1, Allstrak, Shiki2, Cheezy Bergy 2, SmithS1968, JIK1975, WQUlrich, Pinethicket, Eameece, Ency456, Snow0160, Pikiwyn,
SpaceFlight89, Thesevenseas, Crescent66, Saayiit, Maricon0wnz, Darivative, Cnwilliams, Volcry, Tamiicash, Tim1357, Abc518, Kgrad,
FoxBot, Double sharp, TobeBot, Pollinosisss, Georgiamusic, Jskhatter, Mono, Lotje, Loyalprecision, TurkeyStuers, Vera.tetrix, Clrbear430, Lkjhgfdsa 0, Straightthugtom, Satdeep Gill, Tbhotch, Gtziavelis, Fghsfghsfghs, Tat3rt0t1234, Waschwartz, DARTH SIDIOUS 2,
TjBot, Ripchip Bot, Saruha, Brandaray, Mandolinface, DASHBot, DiogenesTCP, EmausBot, John of Reading, WikitanvirBot, Marecheth
Ho'eElohuth, Syncategoremata, Mychele Trempetich, J. Clef, Tommy2010, Aur, Evanh2008, Kkm010, HiW-Bot, ZroBot, Soturix,
DelianDiver, Bilbo571, H3llBot, Wiooiw, AndrewOne, Zap Rowsdower, Ocaasi, JCGTU, Aidarzver, Coasterlover1994, DRMAR777,
L Kensington, MonoAV, Chewings72, Eastern Emperor, ChuispastonBot, Tziemer991, Jordibuma, Neil P. Quinn, GaleCarrLV, Petrb,
Helpsome, ClueBot NG, Hannaharendt, GoetheFromm, ReecyBoy42, Movses-bot, Alis9, Ashrzr, Frietjes, Polyesterthought, Oxford73,
Patrycja Z., Helpful Pixie Bot, Clandarkre, Lowercase sigmabot, Vagobot, TCN7JM, Odarcan, Graham11, TheGeneralUser, AvocatoBot, Davidiad, Snow Rise, Cncmaster, TROPtastic, CitationCleanerBot, Chmarkine, Dobrich, Asauers, Corey833, David12345, BattyBot,
Pendragon5, Zaxnaaog, Pratyya Ghosh, Zen Light, Arr4, Cyberbot II, Maxronnersjo, Khazar2, Ducknish, Vanished user sdij4rtltkjasdk3,
Asisman, Archer47, Pirhayati, Dexbot, Belisariusgroup, Webclient101, Prohairesius, TwoTwoHello, Lugia2453, VIAFbot, Graphium,
EntroDipintaGabbia, DanielTom, Juc123, Nicereddy, PinkAmpersand, Godot13, Link2077, I am One of Many, JPaestpreornJeolhlna,
Sosthenes12, Ketxus, Rakomwolvesbane, 7532665a, Jakec, Clover-bergamot, Elard09, Amb941, Navindukaru, X2sherman, Zenibus, Ginsuloft, Gavelboy, Inanygivenhole, Marcbcarlson, Jackmcbarn, Fredmond4, Aubreybardo, LittleIPEditor, Vancouver Socrates, Bojo1498,
Reinerda, Nizolan, 1234timewar, FelixRosch, Monkbot, , Gunduu, Statelaw1944, Crazynyancat, Good afternoon, Zeiimer, House of
Mogh, Seshata, Jordanjlatimer, Tetra quark, Hujt, Whalestate, Mj thenovelatre, KasparBot, Kingshowman and Anonymous: 1359
10.2
Images
File:Anselm_Feuerbach_-_Das_Gastmahl._Nach_Platon_(zweite_Fassung)_-_Google_Art_Project.jpg
Source:
https:
//upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/7/75/Anselm_Feuerbach_-_Das_Gastmahl._Nach_Platon_%28zweite_Fassung%29_
-_Google_Art_Project.jpg License: Public domain Contributors: sQGa34z2sZaRmg at Google Cultural Institute, zoom level maximum
Original artist: Anselm Feuerbach
File:Clarke_Plato_page_1_recto.jpg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/7/75/Clarke_Plato_page_1_recto.jpg
License: Public domain Contributors: Bodleian Library http://bodley30.bodley.ox.ac.uk:8180/luna/servlet/view/all/who/Plato/what/MS.
%20E.%20D.%20Clarke%2039/ Original artist: John the Calligrapher, Clarke, Plato
File:Commons-logo.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/en/4/4a/Commons-logo.svg License: ? Contributors: ? Original
artist: ?
File:Folder_Hexagonal_Icon.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/en/4/48/Folder_Hexagonal_Icon.svg License: Cc-bysa-3.0 Contributors: ? Original artist: ?
File:Herma_of_Plato_-_0042MC.jpg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/3/3b/Herma_of_Plato_-_0042MC.
jpg License: CC BY-SA 3.0 Contributors: taken by Ricardo Andr Frantz Original artist: Ricardo Andr Frantz (User:Tetraktys)
File:Nuremberg_chronicles_f_61v_2.png Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/b/b0/Nuremberg_chronicles_f_
61v_2.png License: Public domain Contributors: Own work (scan from original book) Original artist: Michel Wolgemut, Wilhelm Pleydenwur (Text: Hartmann Schedel)
File:POxy3679_Parts_Plato_Republic.jpg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/3/3d/P._Oxy._LII_3679.jpg License: Public domain Contributors: http://www.papyrology.ox.ac.uk/POxy/ Original artist: Platon
10.3
Content license
25
File:People_icon.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/3/37/People_icon.svg License: CC0 Contributors: OpenClipart Original artist: OpenClipart
File:Plato-raphael.jpg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/4/4a/Plato-raphael.jpg License: Public domain Contributors: Unknown Original artist: Raphael
File:Plato_i_sin_akademi,_av_Carl_Johan_Wahlbom_(ur_Svenska_Familj-Journalen).png Source: https://upload.wikimedia.
org/wikipedia/commons/5/5e/Plato_i_sin_akademi%2C_av_Carl_Johan_Wahlbom_%28ur_Svenska_Familj-Journalen%29.png
License: Public domain Contributors: http://runeberg.org/famijour/1879/0077.html Original artist: After Carl Wahlbom
File:Portal-puzzle.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/en/f/fd/Portal-puzzle.svg License: Public domain Contributors: ?
Original artist: ?
File:Sanzio_01_Plato_Aristotle.jpg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/9/98/Sanzio_01_Plato_Aristotle.jpg
License: Public domain Contributors: Web Gallery of Art: <a href='http://www.wga.hu/art/r/raphael/4stanze/1segnatu/1/athens1.jpg'
data-x-rel='nofollow'><img
alt='Inkscape.svg'
src='https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/6f/Inkscape.svg/
20px-Inkscape.svg.png' width='20' height='20' srcset='https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/6f/Inkscape.svg/
30px-Inkscape.svg.png 1.5x, https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/6/6f/Inkscape.svg/40px-Inkscape.svg.png 2x'
data-le-width='60' data-le-height='60' /></a> Image <a href='http://www.wga.hu/html/r/raphael/4stanze/1segnatu/1/athens1.html'
data-x-rel='nofollow'><img alt='Information icon.svg' src='https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/3/35/Information_
icon.svg/20px-Information_icon.svg.png' width='20' height='20' srcset='https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/3/35/
Information_icon.svg/30px-Information_icon.svg.png 1.5x, https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/thumb/3/35/Information_
icon.svg/40px-Information_icon.svg.png 2x' data-le-width='620' data-le-height='620' /></a> Info about artwork Original artist: Raphael
File:Socrates.png Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/c/cd/Socrates.png License: Public domain Contributors:
Transferred from en.wikipedia to Commons. Original artist: The original uploader was Magnus Manske at English Wikipedia Later versions
were uploaded by Optimager at en.wikipedia.
File:Socrates_and_Plato.jpg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/9/90/Socrates_and_Plato.jpg License: Public
domain Contributors: ? Original artist: ?
File:Speaker_Icon.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/2/21/Speaker_Icon.svg License: Public domain Contributors: ? Original artist: ?
File:Wikibooks-logo-en-noslogan.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/d/df/Wikibooks-logo-en-noslogan.
svg License: CC BY-SA 3.0 Contributors: Own work Original artist: User:Bastique, User:Ramac et al.
File:Wikiquote-logo.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/f/fa/Wikiquote-logo.svg License: Public domain
Contributors: ? Original artist: ?
File:Wikisource-logo.svg Source: https://upload.wikimedia.org/wikipedia/commons/4/4c/Wikisource-logo.svg License: CC BY-SA 3.0
Contributors: Rei-artur Original artist: Nicholas Moreau
10.3
Content license