This lecture discusses the future of studying Classical Antiquity. It argues that such studies are still progressing through asking new questions of old sources, influenced by modern intellectual developments. As an example, it will analyze the interpretation of a Greek play, showing how new insights can still be gained, without relying on new evidence.
This lecture discusses the future of studying Classical Antiquity. It argues that such studies are still progressing through asking new questions of old sources, influenced by modern intellectual developments. As an example, it will analyze the interpretation of a Greek play, showing how new insights can still be gained, without relying on new evidence.
Original Description:
E. R. Dodds, The Ancient Concept of Progress and Other Essays (Oxford 1973), 26-44
This lecture discusses the future of studying Classical Antiquity. It argues that such studies are still progressing through asking new questions of old sources, influenced by modern intellectual developments. As an example, it will analyze the interpretation of a Greek play, showing how new insights can still be gained, without relying on new evidence.
This lecture discusses the future of studying Classical Antiquity. It argues that such studies are still progressing through asking new questions of old sources, influenced by modern intellectual developments. As an example, it will analyze the interpretation of a Greek play, showing how new insights can still be gained, without relying on new evidence.
Copyright:
Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 19
11
The Prometheus Vinctus and the
Progress of Scholarship W HEN the Trustees of the Dill Memorial Fund did me the honour of inviting me to give the Dill Memorial Lecture for 1946, 1 I was moved to accept their invitation not only by my natural feeling of pietas towards the land which bred me but by a sense of what I owe to my fellow countryman, Sir Samuel Dill. I never, alas, knew him as a person, though I believe I once in boyhood heard him speak; but his book on Roman Sociery from Nero .to Marcus Aurelius, received as a prize at school, opened a door for me into a fascinating world in which I have since spent a good deal of time, the world of later Greco- Roman culture where Greek rationalism fought its long losing battle against the revelations that came from the East, and under the shadow of the pax Romana the patterns of thought that were to rule men's minds for a millennium were slowly taking shape. I am grateful to Dill for this initiation and glad to have the opportunity today of expressing my gratitude. More than forty years have passed since the publication of that book. They have been years of swift growth and even swifter destruction. The old Chinese curse, 'May you live in interesting times!' has descended on us with a vengeance. And at this moment as we emerge, still a little breathless, from our second World War it is inevitable that we should ask ourselves what future there is for those studies of Classical Antiquity to which Dill gave his life. Ought they indeed to have any future? Can we afford it? Beset as we are with the pressing problems of this new Age of Violence, feeling as many of us do that nothing less 1 Since this lecture is firmly tied to its situation in time, has circulated in manuscript, and has been utilized by some later writers on the subject (Lloyd- Jones, Rose, Fitton-Brown), I have not attempted to bring it up to date but re- produce it here virtually as it stands in my original draft. I have, however, added a few notes in square brackets where it seemed desirable to supplement my argu- ment or to call the reader's attention to important later publications. The Prometheus Vinctus and Scholarship 27 than the future of civilization itself is at stake, can we afford to keep so much of our intellectual manpower employed in working the old mines-mines whose best ore, they tell us, has long since been minted and passed into common currency, mines which are certainly encumbered by mountainous slagheaps, the dis- carded leavings of past generations of workers? To these ques- tions I shall attempt no direct answer: for Dill's studies are my studies, and I hold that no man can be a judge in his own cause. But there are two things which I should like to say, very briefly, for they are very simple. The first is, that if we are concerned, as I think we should be, to repair the torn fabric of western European culture, to re- affirm the essential moral and intellectual values by which Western Man has lived for so many centuries, then we cannot afford to lose all contact with that ancient world within which those values were created; we cannot afford to let slip that tradi- tion which is the common cultural inheritance of all the western lands and lies at the root of whatever cultural unity they still possess. My second point is this. A cultural tradition cannot be trans- mitted passively. Unless new minds are always at work on it, so that it is continuously reinterpreted and revalued by and for the new generations, it becomes a dead thing, an encumbrance, a pedant's burden. If we aim merely at disseminating in pre- digested form, through translations and popular handbooks, so much of the results of the labours of former scholars as our chil- dren can swallow in their spare time, then I am sure the tradition will die on us. The condition of life is growth : a study which has ceased to progress ceases to attract enterprising minds, and there- fore ceases to live. Now I have sometimes heard it suggested that the study of Classical Antiquity has reached, or will soon reach, this stage : that all the work of major importance has long ago been done and the mine is approaching exhaustion, what remains being at best low-grade ore. Were I satisfied that this was true, I think I should give up teaching Greek and try to find a new profession. But the statement seems to me to be false, and I shall endeavour to illus- trate its falsity. What is true, and what the outside critic does not always sufficiently realize, is that the questions which are central for the classical scholar today are for the most part materially The Prometheus Vinctus and different, and nearly always differently formulated, from those on which attention was focused a hundred or even fifty years ago. The public is apt to picture the classical scholar eternally chewing the cud of some stale problem which defeated the best efforts of Bentley and Porson, but such a picture bears very little relation to the facts. It is true that such perennial unsolved problems do exist and that we do from time to time return to them. But when we do so it is usually for one of two reasons: either because some fresh piece of evidence-a new papyrus or a new inscription or a new vase-painting-has put into our hands a critical weapon which Bentley and Porson lacked, or else because the new ex- perience of a new generation of men has suggested a fresh angle of attack. In that way old problems are from time to time either solved or brought a stage nearer to solution. But in classical scholarship, as in all the historical sciences, the more usual and more important type of progress consists in the statement and solution of problems which are themselves entirely or partly new. That may happen through new discoveries which raise new questions. An obvious example is the complete restatement of the Homeric problem, partly in the light of Aegean archaeology, partly through the comparative study of oral poetry, which enables us to see not so much that Wolf and his successors gave the wrong answers as that they asked the wrong questions. But it can also happen without the stimulus of sensational discoveries, through a change in the focus of the scholar's eye. What we find in any document depends on what we are looking for, and what we look for depends on our own interests, which in turn are determined, at least in part, by the intellectual climate of our own age. This kind of growth could be illustrated from many different fields, among them that in which Dill was a pioneer-the field ofGreco-Roman social history. It would be easy to show how the broadening of modern historical interests to include social and economic, cultural and religious institutions, and the con- sequent shift of focus from the great figures on the public stage to the anonymous army of common men, has led to ever more systematic study of the scattered material to be found in inscrip- tions and papyri, with the result that today we know the mind and heart, the daily hopes and cares, of the ordinary citizen of the Roman Empire far better than our grandfathers could dream the Progress of Scholarship 29 of doing. Or one could show how the modern analysis of logical concepts is at present giving new life to a part of ancient philo- sophy which in my youth appeared to be stone dead-the study of Aristotelian and Stoic formal logic. Or again, it would be possible to show how recent developments in social anthropology and social psychology open the way to a fuller understanding of Greek religion as an element in the complex pattern of Greek culture. In all these cases new insights have been achieved by putting fresh questions to old witnesses. I propose in the remainder of this lecture to examine another and prima facie a much less favourable case-the interpretation of a Greek play. The masterpieces of the Attic dramatists have been studied intensively through many generations and have exercised the minds of the very greatest Greek scholars, men like Scaliger and Casaubon, Porson and Elmsley, Hermann and Wilamowitz. Is any further progress really possible here? Let me say at once that in so far as the questions we ask are the same as theirs we are most unlikely to do better than they, save where fortune has put into our hands new evidence or a new critical instrument. That has happened to some extent, especially with Euripides, 1 thanks to the publication of numerous papyrus frag- ments both of lost plays and of extant ones. The former have widened our knowledge of the poet's mind and style; the value of the latter has lain not so much in the new readings they offered, which have in general been disappointing, as in the light they threw on the history of the text and the nature and origin of the corruptions to which it has been exposed. We may reasonably hope for more such gifts of fortune in the future. But for the play about which I have chosen to talk today we have at present no such adventitious aids : there are as yet no papyri of the Prometheus Vinctus. And unless really good papyri do turn up I doubt ifwe shall ever have a text of this play substan- tially better than the one which Wilamowitz edited just before the first World War. No fewer than five scholars of distinction have in fact edited the Prometheus since that date-Mazon, Smyth, Groeneboom, Thomson, Murray. But if my arithmetic is right the total number of new readings introduced into the text of the 1 [Since this was written Menander has become for the first time a living figure and there have also been significant additions to our knowledge of Aeschylus and Sophocles.] The Prometheus Vinctus and play by these five distinguished editors adds up to just six, or rather more than one new reading apiece. 1 And what is more significant than the number, not one of these five editors has accepted a single emendation proposed by any of the other four. Surely this suggests that the law of diminishing returns has begun to operate and that in restoring the text of the Prometheus we have got about as far as we are likely to get in the absence of fresh evidence. And while there are plays which offer more scope for conjectural emendation than the Prometheus, I think the conclu- sion is broadly true of Greek tragedy in general. This is also the lesson of the papyri. When a new papyrus of the Bacchae was pub- lished not long ago, it proved to support no fewer than thirteen corrections made by modern critics. That sounds like a pleasing testimony to our acumen. But before congratulating ourselves we should observe that most of these corrections were glaringly obvious and had been made before the end of the eighteenth century, and that the most recent critic of whose labours the papyrus takes any notice is Paley. On this sort of evidence my advice to those ambitious of immortalizing their names in an apparatus criticus would be that they should seek newer pastures: there is still plenty of work of this kind to be done on later texts, including for example such major authors as Strabo, Plutarch, and Plotinus. This does not mean, however, that in the field of Greek tragedy scholars have no more to do than sit and wait for another papyrus to fall from Heaven. What it points to is a shift in the focus of attention from textual questions to the study of dramatic technique on the one hand, and on the other to the problem of relating the individual work of art to the social and cultural back- ground out of which it grew. That shift has already taken place. It is exemplified on the one hand by books like Kranz's Stasimon and Professor Kitto's Greek Tragedy, on the other by Pohlenz's excellent book on tragedy (which ought to be translated) and in a more controversial way by Professor George Thomson's Aeschylus and Athens. In the case of the Prometheus Vinctus a lively discussion has in our day been focused on three interconnected problems. These concern respectively its date and authenticity; the structure of 1 [Murray's revised text (1955) incorporates in this play one additional new conjecture; Untersteiner's (1948), none.] the Progress of Scholarship 31 the trilogy (the Prometheia) of which it is presumed to have formed part; and the meaning of the work as a whole. I propose to offer some account of this controversy, because it illustrates so well the way in which contemporary issues are mirrored in the world of learning, and also the way in which the human weaknesses of scholars pervert their judgement and yet sometimes in the end contribute to the progress of scholarship. Of the three questions I have mentioned it is historically con- venient to start from the last-the question of the meaning of the work. Logically, we should not attempt to answer it until we have answered the other two; but in practice the views which scholars have held on this question have largely determined their opinion on the others. The discussion has its roots in the nineteenth century. Until then, readers of the Prometheus Vinctus had usually been content to interpret the play in the light of their immediate emotional response to it. And the nature of that response was never in doubt. To the imagination of the Christian Fathers the picture of the ancient Titan who suffers for his love of humanity had appeared as a prefigurement of the Christian Redeemer on the cross. To the imagination of the poets-of Goethe, Shelley, Byron-it had appeared as a symbol of the revolt of human intelligence against 'a world it never made', since, as a Greek poet put it, 'the Promethean part of man is his intellect'. 1 But nineteenth-century scholars would have none of that. Was not Prometheus the enemy of Zeus? And was not Zeus for Aeschylus the holiest of all names? Do not the Danaids in his Supplices pray to Zeus as 'King of Kings, most blessed of the blessed, among the perfect Power most perfect' ? 2 Do not the old men in the Agamemnon cry out in a bewildered time that 'Only in the thought of Zeus can the heart be free from its vain burden of distress' ?J Hermann indeed declared stoutly that such contradictions did not matter : Aeschylus was a dramatist, not a theologian, and his attitude to Zeus just varied with the myths he handled. But the majority of nineteenth-century scholars thought otherwise, and concluded, with Schoemann, 4 that since Prometheus is a rebel against the supreme and holy God, our nai:ve sympathy with him cannot correspond to the poet's intention. Prometheus, said r Plato comicus, frag. 136 Kock. [See above, pp. 6f.] 2 Suppl. 524ff. 3 Ag. 163 tf. Gefesseltes Prometheus (1844). 32 The Prometheus Vinctus and Schoemann, was quite mistaken in supposing that he had done a service to mankind by creating the arts of civilization; all he had invented was technology, a nasty thing which does people harm by making them rich and materialistic. Whether astronomy and medicine actually have this effect, whether this was really the view of 'technology' held by Aeschylus, whether it was even a possible view in the earlier part of the fifth century, Schoemann did not pause to inquire; but his argument was very gratifYing to professors of Greek, resentful as they were against the growing claims of the upstart natural scientists, and they have often re- peated it since.I Correspondingly great efforts were made to whitewash the Zeus of the Prometlzeus Vinctus. Sikes and Willson express the accepted judgement of their time when they observe in their preface to the play: 'Prometheus had sinned, and was further sinning; Zeus was acting within his rights in punishing the sinner at the commencement of the play, and in adding to his punish- ment at the end ... The Judge had been stern, but not unjust.' Professor J. A. K. Thomson in a paper published in 1920 found it possible to go even further. 'The design of Zeus', he thought, 'may honestly be regarded as something higher and in the long run more beneficial to man himself than the hasty generosity ofPrometheus.' 2 This seems to me a dark saying. The only design of Zeus for mankind about which the poet has told us was a de- sign to liquidate the lot. 'Zeus', we are told, 'paid no regard to suffering humanity; he intended to wipe out the entire breed and replace it by another.'J To quote this design as an example of the higher beneficence one must be a pessimist indeed. But there is no trace of any other. The first advance resulting from the modern discussion has been the fairly general abandonment of such attempts to distort 1 Cf. the works of Schmid and Vandvik referred to below. George Thomson, from the opposite standpoint, praises Aeschylus for his 'bold materialism' (Aeschylus and Athens (1941), 327). But in fact the main stress in the great anthropological speech (44I-506) is laid on intellectual achievements-astronomy, arithmetic, medicine, divination. The potter's wheel, which we might expect to find mentioned, is left out: apparently it was too f3avavuos, too 'technological', for Aeschylus. It would be easier (though for other reasons still wrong) to find 'bold materialism' in the Ode to Man in the Antigone. [See above, pp. 5 f.] 2 'The Religious Background of the Prometheus Vinctus', Harv. Stud. in Class. Philol. 3 I (I 920)' s6. 3 P.V. 231 ff. the Progress of Scholarship 33 the evidence, attempts which in origin seem to reflect the extremely conservative and monarchist tendencies of nineteenth- century universities, especially in Germany. They are not, how- ever, wholly dead even now. As recently as 1943 a Norwegian scholar named Vandvik published a curious essay 1 in which he maintained that the account of the situation given by Prometheus is completely false and that the audience is meant to perceive its falsity. Since Zeus is just, it is impossible that he should have meant to destroy mankind; since he is all-powerful, it is im- possible that Prometheus should have saved them; since he is omniscient, it is impossible that Prometheus should possess a secret which Zeus does not know. These are merely the delusions of the insane Titan, and both we and the Chorus are very silly to sympathize with him. The people with whom we ought to sympathize are Oceanus, who is a 'noble' character, and Cratos and Hermes, who represent 'the Olympian wisdom'. I mention this theory, not on account of its merits-for it seems to me to have none-but because it constitutes a logical reductio ad absur- dum of the nineteenth-century interpretation. For the objection to that interpretation is simply that it does not fit the facts as the poet has chosen to represent them. Far from attempting to whitewash Zeus, Aeschylus appears, as various critics have shown, 2 to have gone out of his way to exhibit him in the most unfavourable light. All that he has added to the Hesiodic tradition-Prometheus' new status as son of Themis, the goddess of Justice, and as inventor of all arts and sciences, his services to Zeus in the war against the Titans, and his frustration of the plan to destroy mankind, not to mention the Io scene-all this tends to exalt the character of Prometheus and to blacken that of his divine adversary. Had Aeschylus meant us to think ofZeus as 'stern but just', ofPrometheus as (in the words of a German textbook) 'an impertinent reformer', he could and presumably would have written the play otherwise. He could, for example, have given Zeus more sympathetic ad- vocates than the ugly brute Cratos, whose tongue, we are told, matches his appearance,J and the still nastier Hermes, who is, 1 'The Prometheus of Hesiod and Aeschylus', Norske Videnskaps-Akademi, Hist.- Filos. Klasse 1942 (Oslo, 1943). 2 Cf. S. H. Butcher, Harvard Lectures on Greek Subjects (I 904), I 7 ff.; L. E. Mat- thaei, Studies in Greek Tragedy (1918), 10 ff.; 0. J. Todd, C.Q. 19 (1925), 61 ff.; L. R. Farnell, J.H.S. 53 (1933), 40 ff. 3 P. V. 78. 34 The Prometheus Vinctus and and is surely meant to be, the worst sort of 'gentleman's gentle- man'. If these are the employees, what, asks the audience, must the employer be? But except these two no one in the play perceives the divine justice which was so obvious to Victorian editors. Hephaestus does his work with a disgusted reluctance, and even the time-serving Oceanus calls Zeus 'a harsh and irre- sponsible ruler'. 1 As for Io, her sufferings could well have been attributed solely to Hera's malice, as in fact they are in the Supplices; but in the P. V. she names Zeus as their author and therefore longs for his dethronement. 2 There remains only the Chorus. The Chorus wobble, as Choruses do, torn between sym- pathy for Prometheus and alarm at his dangerous utterances : as Farnell put it, 'to sit on the fence and recommend prudence is the bourgeois function of Choruses'. But at the end they come off their fence and choose to sink into Tartarus with Prometheus rather than play the coward at the command of Hermes.J This is surely decisive evidence of the side on which our sympathies are meant to lie. And we cannot evade it by supposing, as certain scholars have done, that at the last moment they change their mind and run away: such a change would have to be indicated in the text. Vandvik, perceiving that the Chorus's decision is fatal to his whole view of the play, is driven to assume that the lines in which they announce it are an interpolation. Short of such lame subterfuges there seems to be no escape from the conclusion that the P. V. as it stands is what the Russians would call an 'anti-God play'. For those who still hold that the devout Aeschylus cannot have written such a play there is only one road out of the dilemma-by proving that the P. V. is not his work. Once the nineteenth-century interpretation had col- lapsed, it was logical that this desperate attempt should be made; and it was made, as we should expect on social and political grounds, in Germany. The campaign was opened by Gercke, who in I 9 I I suggested that the play was composed in the early years of the Peloponnesian War by an admirer of Euripides. But a much weightier attack was launched in I929 by a well- known scholar, Wilhelm Schmid of Ttibingen, in his Unter- suchungen zum geftsselten Prometheus. Schmid dates the play about 450-445, and claims it as 'our oldest evidence for the existence I P.V. 324 2 P. V. 757-60; contrast Suppl. 2g6. 3 P. V. 1063-70. the Progress of Scholarship 35 of the sophistic movement and its radicalism about the middle of the fifth century at Athens'. Its purpose was to glorify the idea of progress and thus exalt Man in general, and technical educa- tion in particular, at the expense of God. It was intended as a counterblast to the Prometheus Lyomenos, which was a genuine work of Aeschylus. Owing to the bad taste of later generations the two plays got confused, and the Vinctus was preserved among the works of Aeschylus while the Lyomenos was lost. We do not know who composed the Vinctus, but he can hardly have been an Athenian gentleman, for it is evident that he sympathized with the industrial classes. Schmid would prefer to attribute the play to a metic, 'a business man with a colonial point of view', or to some alien like Ion of Chios. Schmid supported these opinions with impressive batteries of learning. Yet he appears to have made very few converts, even in Germany. Nor is that surprising, for the difficulties of his theory are many and, I think, insuperable. I shall not spend time on listing them all. Perhaps it is enough to say that, apart from the unlikelihood of the sort of confusion Schmid postulates, the Vinctus was clearly meant to have a sequel (as its numerous loose ends and unfulfilled prophecies show) and trilogies were out of fashion in the 'forties; that the supposed links with the sophistic movement vanish on closer inspection ; 1 and finally, that Oceanus and Danaus, Io's madness and Cassandra's, the geographical lecture in the Vinctus and the geographical digressions in the Supplices and the Agamemnon, are unmistakably creations of the same mind. One may wonder why Schmid, an able and learned man, did not see all this for himself. The answer, I suppose, must be that the play appeared to him so dangerous, so subversive of all that a conservative German believed in, that it was essential to find reasons for excluding it from the Aeschylean canon. On that view his book affords what Housman called in another connec- tion 'fresh and superfluous proof of the weakness of man's reason and the strength of his passions'. Yet scholarship sometimes draws 1 The word aoifnan}s is older than the movement it has come to denote for us. It occurs not only in the P. V. (62, 944) but in an undisputed fragment of Aeschylus (frag. 314 Nauck), where it describes an 'expert' musician; Herodotus applies it to Solon (I. 29) and Pythagoras (4. 95). [Cf. now Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, iii. 27-34.] The typical concepts of sophistic anthropology, 'need' and 'utility', are significantly missing from the P. V. The Prometheus Vinctus and unexpected profit from the human frailties of scholars. In the course of failing to prove that the P. V. was the work of an un- known atheist, Schmid did an important service to learning: he brought together a very substantial body of evidence tending to show that in metre, diction, style, and structure the P. V. stands apart from the rest of Aeschylus' work, and by doing this he set a new problem. Not indeed entirely new: Wackernagel 1 had already called attention to certain linguistic peculiarities, Ernest Harrison 2 to the presence of 'Sophoclean' rhythms in the tri- meters, and as far back as I 86g the metrical singularity of some of the choral odes had led W estphal3 to suggest that the play had been worked over by a later hand. But by his full statement of the evidence Schmid focused attention on the problem of ac- counting for it. Some of his points are easily disposed of. That the P. V. should be 'the poorest in action of all Greek plays' need surprise no one : a person chained to a rock has little opportunity for action. Nor need we wonder that such words as 'a gulley', 7TAav7J, 'wandering', xplEtv, 'to sting', occur repeatedly in the P. V. but nowhere else in Aeschylus : they would not have occurred here were it not that the scene is laid among mountains and that one character is a wanderer tormented by a gadfly. There remains, however, a good deal which cannot be so lightly dismissed. In particular, Schmid's investigations into the build of the iambic trimeters, since supplemented by the work ofDenniston,4 Yorke,s and others, prove that in a number of respects the P. V. shows a closer approximation to Sophoclean technique than any other play of Aeschylus, representing in several cases a more advanced development of tendencies which are observable in the Oresteia. Again, the P. V. has certain common words which Aeschylus elsewhere avoids but the other tragedians do not-notably Atav, TE, KalTot, and the interjection Other features which seem to call for explanation are the brevity of the choral odes, compensated by Io's long monodies, and the prevalence of dactylo-epitrite metre; the very curious changes of metre in Prometheus' opening speech; and, perhaps most striking of all, 1 'Sprachgeschichtliches zu Aischylos, Prometheus', Verhandlungen der Versammlung der Philologen (1902), 65f. 2 Proc. Camb. Philol. Soc., 1921. 3 Prolegomena zu Aeschylus' Tragodien (186g). 4 C.Q. 30 (1936), 73 ff., 192. 5 Ibid. 116ff., 153f. the Progress of Scholarship 37 the relative simplicity and clarity of the style as compared with any other play of Aeschylus. I Since the publication of Schmid's book discussion has been largely centred on trying to account for these peculiarities. Some of them suggest the possible influence of Sophocles, whose first play was acted in 468, thirteen years before Aeschylus' death. That in a rapidly changing poetic climate a great poet can sharply modify his style late in life, partly under the influence of his juniors, has been shown in our own day by the example of W. B. Yeats; we may recall also how Propertius learned from Ovid. The dating of the P. V. soon after 4 70, which was accepted in the nineteenth century on not very conclusive grounds, has accordingly been called in question: George Thomson and others would put it at the very end of Aeschylus' life, between the Oresteia in 458 and his death in 456/5. 2 Among other advantages, such a date would enable us to assume that Aeschylus used three actors here, as he did in the Oresteia, and thus get rid of the grotesque and (as I think) unworkable hypothesis that Prome- theus was represented by a wooden dummy.3 Further, tradition says that after the production of the Oresteia Aeschylus retired to Sicily; and if the play was written for production at Syracuse, this may account for some of its distinctive peculiarities. If he had in mind an audience unused to the high and elaborate style of Attic tragedy, Aeschylus may well have deemed it prudent to keep his diction simple and his choral odes short ;4 he may also have purposely introduced one or two local Sicilian words, as the scholiasts tell us he did. These suggestions seem to me plausible as far as they go. Whether they go far enough is perhaps still open to dispute. Observing that so good a judge as Kranzs cannot believe all the choral odes to be the work of Aeschylus, Professor D. S. Robert- son6 put forward shortly before the war a hypothesis which I find tempting on several grounds. According to the Suda, a number of 1 [I have quoted only a sample of the evidence. For the most complete state- ment and discussion of it see now C. J. Herington's indispensable book, The Author of the 'Prometheus Bouna' (I 970).] 2 [In my judgement this dating has now been put on a firm foundation by Herington's work.] 3 [This hypothesis still has its defenders, but see the objections of P. Arnott, Greek Scenic Conventions (I962), 96 ff., and Herington, 88f.] + Cf. F. Focke, Hermes, 65 (I93o), 259 ff. s Stasimon, I 26 ff. 6 Proc. Camb. Philol. Soc. I 938. 1 The Prometheus Vinctus and Aeschylus' plays were not performed in his lifetime but were staged posthumously by his son Euphorion (who also wrote plays of his own). Robertson suggested that the P. V. may have been among these posthumously staged plays, that it was unfinished, and that Euphorion supplied some of the odes as stopgaps. I find this hypothesis seductive because it can be used to explain a number of difficulties besides those which its author had in mind. Ancient editors were notoriously conservative, even to the point of preserving obvious doublets; and I think we can reason- ably assume that if Euphorion found a number of unfinished and unplaced passages among his father's drafts for the P. V., he would probably do his best to work them in rather than let them be lost to posterity. Now there is one passage in the play which most scholars, since Badham pointed it out, have judged to be misplaced if not spurious, namely the lines about Atlas which so strangely interrupt the splendid ode on the universal mourning for Prometheus. 1 It cannot, I think, have been designed for this place; yet it is convincingly Aeschylean in style, there is nowhere else in the play where it could go, and it seems too long for a marginal adscript. On Robertson's hypothesis I should be dis- posed to guess that it was a fragment of an earlier draft, either for the P. V. itself or for some other uncompleted part of the tetralogy, which Euphorion inserted here because he did not want to waste it and the metrical context was more or less suitable. On the same principle one might also suspect that the odd patch- work of metres in the Titan's opening speech had its source in Euphorion's editorial activities. Robertson's hypothesis would also relieve us of some embar- rassing questions concerning the other plays of the tetralogy. We know that the Vinctus was followed by the Lyomenos (The Unbinding of Prometheus), and we have sufficient fragments of the latter to reconstruct a good part of its action in rough outline. But on the remaining plays of the set Antiquity is strangely silent. The satyr-play is nowhere mentioned; the only known satyr-play of Aeschylus dealing with Prometheus is the Pyrkaeus, and this, we know, was staged along with the Persae in 4 72. As for the remaining tragedy, it has been identified since Welcker with the play called Prometheus Pyrphoros in the Medicean list. But the Pyrphoros is a tantalizing ghost. Scholars have been unable to I P. V. 425-30 the Progress of Scholarship 39 agree as to its subject or the position it occupied in the trilogy. The solitary line which is quoted as coming from itl tells us nothing, and appears in almost the same form in the Choephoroe. Nor does the opinion made fashionable by Westphal, which de- rives its name from the institution of a torchlight procession in honour of Prometheus, really help us very much : a procession does not make a play. Since we cannot decide what it was about, and since the Medicean table of dramatis personae for the trilogy appears to take account only of the Vinctus and the Lyomenos, I feel tempted to return to Hermann's view that the Pyrphoros of the list is merely an alternative title for the satyr-play Pyrkaeusz_ which the list omits, though it certainly once existed. That would leave us with only two Prometheus tragedies, the Vinctus and the Lyomenos, which has generally been thought impossible, since we do not hear of Aeschylus or anybody else presenting 'dilogies'. If indeed the plays were intended solely for production at Syracuse, the objection is perhaps not decisive: we do not know the rules, if there were any, which governed Sicilian dramatic festivals.l But Robertson's hypothesis suggests another possible explana- tion: the reason why we hear so little of the two remaining plays of the tetralogy may be simply that Aeschylus died before he had written them. He may have planned to prefix to the Vinctus a tragedy dealing with earlier events such as the theft of fire and Zeus' threat to destroy mankind, which are mentioned only briefly in the Vinctus; this would have made clear among other things the part played in these events by Ocean, to which there is an unexplained and puzzling allusion in our play.4 As it was, 1 Frag. 208 Nauck, cf. Cho. 582. [I agree with Fraenkel and Snell that P. Oxy. 2245 (frag. 278 in Lloyd-Jones's appendix to the Loeb Aeschylus) cannot be attributed to the Pyrphoros; such indications as we have point to a satyr-play, presumably the Pyrkaeus.] 2 [An objection to identifying the Pyrphoros with the Pyrkaeus (which dealt with the theft of fire) has often been based on the tense of l>oea8at in schol. P. V. 94: ~ V yap Tc'p llvpcp6pcp y' f.Wpuioas cp1JO'L 00ea8at avT6v. But the tense of the scholiast's paraphrase need not be that used by Aeschylus (cf. the similarly loose use of cp1Jal. oel>ea8at in the Hypothesis to our play, line 10). And in fact the figure of 30,000 years is incompatible, if literally meant, with the assumptions of the Prometheia (a space of 13 generations, P. V. 774). See Pohlenz, Die griechische Tragodie (1930), i. 70, and now A. D. Fitton-Brown, j.H.S. 79 (1959), 53.] 3 Cf. Focke, loc. cit. [A similar view has since been put forward, partly at my suggestion, by the late Professor H. J. Rose in his Commentary on the Surviving Plays of Aeschylus (1957-8), i. 9 f.] 4 P.V. 331. The Prometheus Vinctus and Aeschylus died, the tetralogy remained a dilogy, and the so-called Pyrphoros is the ghost not of a lost play but of an unborn one. All this, however, is sheer speculation, and likely, perhaps, always to remain speculation: I mention it only to show that even in so hackneyed a field of discussion there is still room for fresh ideas. We must now return to the question from which we started -the question what Aeschylus made of the Prometheus story as a whole and what significance he saw in it. We know from the fragments of the Lyomenos and from the mythographical tradition that the conflict between Zeus and the Titan ended at last in a reconciliation. Heracles shot the tor- turing eagle; Prometheus yielded up his secret, perhaps on the advice of his mother Themis who is also Mother Earth; he was released from bondage and restored to a place of honour. What the terms of the reconciliation were we are, alas, not told. But I think it would now be fairly widely agreed that it cannot have been brought about simply by a one-sided surrender on the part of Prometheus. After the magnificent crescendo of defiance which we have witnessed in the Vinctus such an unmotived transition from pride to humility must have produced a painful and de- pressing effect of anticlimax. When the poet has used all his art to make his audience share the Titan's resentment against the divine tyrant, to thrill them with the spectacle of a moral and intellectual will unconquerable in its resistance to arbitrary might, if he then proceeded to exhibit the defeat and abject surrender of that will, what lesson could they draw save that the world is in the grip of an irresponsible and unscrupulous power against which all resistance is in vain? Besides being 1uap6v, morally shocking to Greek ideas, such a conclusion would indeed contradict all that Aeschylus has implied elsewhere about the relations between God and Man. And it would also make nonsense of certain passages in the Vinctus. Consider the predic- tion put into Prometheus' mouth at line 190: T ~ V D' UTEpap.vov UTOpEaas o p y ~ v ELS ap8p.ov p.o'i Kat cfnAOTYJTU a7TEVDWV U7TEvDovTl 7To8' ijgE, 'Subduing his stubborn temper, Zeus shall come at last to a pact of friendship with me, and the will shall be his and mine.' In a Greek play such a prophecy is virtually an undertaking given the Progress of Scholarship by the poet to the audience, an undertaking which he is expected to honour. And its fulfilment clearly requires more than a mere surrender on Prometheus' part. The pact is to be a voluntary treaty of peace, and one of its conditions is a change in the temper of Zeus. Such a change is again predicted at line g81. Prometheus has uttered a groan, Wf.Lot, and Hermes has observed tauntingly that in the bright vocabulary of Zeus there is no such word as Wf.Lot. 'Ah,' says Prometheus, 'but Time as he grows older teaches every lesson.' He plainly implies that Zeus will one day learn to say Wf.Lot. That is again an undertaking which commits the poet. We must suppose, therefore, as many scholars now do, that in the Lyomenos Aeschylus presented not only a changed Prome- theus but a changed Zeus. And there is in fact some direct evidence of this : for in the interval between the two plays Zeus had decided to liberate Prometheus' fellow Titans, who formed the Chorus of the Lyomenos. That seems to mean that Zeus has already, before the Lyomenos opens, begun to 'subdue his stubborn temper'. In the Vinctus he is a raw, untried sovereign: with an emphasis which must be deliberate, and which surely has a bearing on the sequel, the insulting term v'os is applied to him no less than nine times in the course of the play. Among Greeks to call a ruler 'new' is an insult: it implies that his sovereignty lacks proper sanction. But it is also an excuse, for it implies in- experience. Wilamowitz 1 justifiably compared the man who ex- cused the peculiar behaviour of J ehovah in the early books of the Old Testament; 'Ah, but the Lord God was young himself in those days.' The Zeus of the Prometheia visibly begins as the savage, unmoralized god of legend; we must believe that he ended as the god whom Aeschylus worshipped. The moral gulf to be bridged is wide, but so is the time-scale of the Prometheia: between the beginning of the action and its end thirteen human generations must intervene. 2 That slow but decisive change may in fact reflect the evolution of morals and religion in the mind of man; but to Aeschylus and his audience it neces- sarily appears as an objective evolution in Heaven) 1 Aischylos: Interpretationen (1914), 150. [That gods, like men, gain in experience with age is already assumed by Homer, Iliaa 21. 440.] 2 P. V. 774 3 [It has sometimes been suggested that the change in Zeus should be read as a conscious symbol of the gradual change in men's religious ideas. But as G. Grossman has recently remarked (Promethie und Orestie (1970), 85), Aeschylus was 42 The Prometheus Vinctus and This notion of a 'progressive' Zeus seems strange to us, who are accustomed to associate progress not with God but with our beliefs about him. First suggested by Dissen as far back as I 824, it was rejected by the great W elcker, and among nineteenth-century scholars only a very few (most notably Lewis Campbell and Henri Weil) had the temerity to adopt it. In the present century it has won much wider acceptance ; 1 but there is still an impor- tant minority who assert flatly that such a notion is 'un-Hellenic' . 2 Is not that because our idea of what is 'Hellenic' is still too much coloured by Plato and Aristotle? The doctrine of a changeless and eternal God took root in Greek thought only when Plato (following a hint in Parmenides) had expounded the conception of aion as a timeless mode of being, of which time is the 'moving image'. Later this doctrine was to be grafted on to Christianity through the influence of Platonizing thinkers like Saint Augus- tine. But the gods of earlier Greek belief are no more changeless than the early Jewish J ehovah. They are not timeless beings external to the cosmos; they are part of its furniture (cf. Hesiod, Works and Days, 108). And being within the cosmos they are within time and have each of them a personal history in time: Zeus, for example, had once been a child, and you could even visit his birthplace. In the conception of such beings there was nothing to exclude the assumption of a moral development. And if belief in the old not a modern 'Religionshistoriker' : the change he depicts is an objective one and is situated in the mythical past before the Trojan War.] 1 [To the long list of scholars who (with individual variations) have adopted this view, quoted by H. Lloyd-Jones, 'Zeus in Aeschylus', J.H.S. 76 (1956), n. 2I, we may now add the names of N. Terzaghi, Renaiconti Accad. Lincei (I 955) ; A. D. Fitton-Brown, J.H.S. 79 (I 959), 52 ff.; G. Meautis, L' Authenticite et la elate du Promethte Enchazne (I96o); and G. Grossman, op. cit.] z [So Farnell, J.H.S. 53 (I933), 47; Lloyd-Jones, op. cit.; Rose, Commentary, i. I I; L. Golden, In Praise if Prometheus (I962), I03 ff. But the most eloquent and influential proponent of this opinion has been Karl Reinhardt (Aischylos als Regisseur und Theologe (I 949); 'Prometheus', Eranos-Jahrbuch 25 (I 957)). Reinhardt's conception, however, of the Aeschylean Zeus as a mysterious two-faced coincidentia oppositorum, simultaneously tyrant and saviour, seems to me a good deal more anachronistic than the view here defended. And it gets little support from the text of Aeschylus, where, as P. V. g8 I indicates, the element of time is all-important. In the Vinctus only the tyrant face is visible; in the Lyomenos, to judge from the fragments, only the saviour face appeared (cf. Grossman's criticism, op. cit. 102 ff.). Nor has Golden convinced me that the Zeus of the P. V. is just a symbol for 'the destructive forces of nature', totally distinct from the Zeus of the Supplices: what audience could read this riddle?] the Progress of Scholarship 43 legends was to be reconciled with belief in divine justice, that assumption may well have appeared to certain thoughtful minds as not only possible but necessary. Stobaeus has preserved a long and interesting passage from a later tragedian, Moschion, in which someone speaks of a bygone time when 'Law took a humble seat and Violence [ Bia] shared the throne of Zeus' . 1 Since the speaker mentions Prometheus a few lines lower down, it is not unlikely that Moschion had in mind Aeschylus' play, where Kratos and Bia are the agents of Zeus. That to Aeschylus himself the idea of a possible change in the attitude of gods was not foreign, the Eumenides sufficiently testifies. There too we are shown a conflict between divine beings, which is brought to an end by an act of free generosity and by the conversion before the spectators' eyes of the spirits of vengeance into ministers of blessing. Nor is this all. In the course of that conflict one party to it points out that Zeus himself has sinned against the moral law which he now professes to uphold; he has imprisoned his own father. In reply the spokesman of Zeus neither denies the act nor seeks to justify it, but merely remarks that such deeds are not irrevocable: 'Fetters he can strike off.' 2 If this means anything it means that Zeus has not always been 'the most perfect of the perfect' : he has done wrong in his time, but the wrong he did can be, and presumably has been, righted. Surely this is highly relevant to the Prometheus problem, especially when we remember that the Zeus of the Vinctus is still under his father's curse, as we learn from lines 910 ff. And relevant too, if I interpret them rightly, are the famous closing words of the trilogy, ZEvs o 7Tav67T-ras / ov-rw Mo'ipa -re avyKa-r[3a, 'Thus Zeus the all-seeing and Fate's assignment have made their peace together.'3 The Oresteia, starting from an old tale of crime and punish- ment, celebrates the beginning of the reign of justice on earth. I think the Prometheia, starting from another such tale, celebrated 1 Frag. 6. 15 Nauck. Cf. Thomson, Aeschylus anrl Athens, 339 [The word Ad in this passage may be a scribal conjecture, but it makes sense; the only suggested alternative, Canter's AlK!J, makes none-'Justice' has no place in a regime of cannibalism. But more direct evidence is now available in a new Aeschylean papyrus, P. Oxy. 2256, frag. ga (= frag. 282 Lloyd-Jones), where Dike describes the origin of her partnership with Zeus-'Since that day Zeus has honoured me'- which implies that they have not always been partners.] 2 Eum. 64o-6. 3 Eum. 1045-6. Cf. Cornford, Plato's Cosmology (1937), 361 ff. 44 The Prometheus Vinctus its beginning in Heaven. 1 Aeschylus, like us, had lived through an Age of Violence among men, and tradition told him that there had once been a like Age of Violence among the gods. But his faith is that both on earth and in Heaven the rule of Violence is over. He can believe that Power in the person of Zeus is now at last reconciled with the Intelligence of which Prometheus is the mythical embodiment, and both of them with the supreme principle of Justice whose guardians are the Moirai and the Erinyes. 2 Such optimism was possible only for a generation like that of Aeschylus, a generation which had seen in the Persian Wars the victory, beyond all hope, of justice over brute force, and at Athens, in the years that followed, the swift blossoming of a civilization whose like had never been known before. It was a supreme moment in the history of Western Man. But it did not, it could not, last. Within the lifetime of the next generation the Peloponnesian War was to prove to all men that Power, Intelligence, and Justice were still at odds. With that realiza- tion the belief in human progress faded, and with it the mirror- image of a progressive Zeus. The Vinctus was still admired, as a symbol of Man's protest against the injustice of life. The Lyomenos was half forgotten, and eventually lost, because its lesson was no longer understood. 1 Cf. F. Vian, R.E.G. 55 (1942), 216: 'Dans l'Olympe aussi, il faut que s'etablis- sent les reformes de Clisthene.' [The parallel holds good so far, but I am wholly unconvinced by any of the recent attempts to discover political allegory in the P. V. (discussed by A. J. Podlecki, The Political Backgrouna of Aeschylean Tragerly (1966), eh. vi).] 2 P. V. 5II-I6.
The Crest-Wave of Evolution
A Course of Lectures in History, Given to the Graduates' Class in the Raja-Yoga College, Point Loma, in the College-Year 1918-19
The Crest-Wave of Evolution A Course of Lectures in History, Given To The Graduates' Class in The Raja-Yoga College, Point Loma, in The College-Year 1918-19 by Morris, Kenneth, 1879-1937