The document discusses Euclid's axioms for geometry and their flaws. It provides Euclid's original five axioms, then discusses how they are insufficient to prove key theorems like the existence of points on a line. The document introduces Hilbert's reformulation of geometry axioms in the late 19th century to address issues with Euclid's system. It also discusses how axiom systems can be modeled using abstract concepts like points represented by tables and lines by chairs to demonstrate properties without relying on visual diagrams.
The document discusses Euclid's axioms for geometry and their flaws. It provides Euclid's original five axioms, then discusses how they are insufficient to prove key theorems like the existence of points on a line. The document introduces Hilbert's reformulation of geometry axioms in the late 19th century to address issues with Euclid's system. It also discusses how axiom systems can be modeled using abstract concepts like points represented by tables and lines by chairs to demonstrate properties without relying on visual diagrams.
The document discusses Euclid's axioms for geometry and their flaws. It provides Euclid's original five axioms, then discusses how they are insufficient to prove key theorems like the existence of points on a line. The document introduces Hilbert's reformulation of geometry axioms in the late 19th century to address issues with Euclid's system. It also discusses how axiom systems can be modeled using abstract concepts like points represented by tables and lines by chairs to demonstrate properties without relying on visual diagrams.
The document discusses Euclid's axioms for geometry and their flaws. It provides Euclid's original five axioms, then discusses how they are insufficient to prove key theorems like the existence of points on a line. The document introduces Hilbert's reformulation of geometry axioms in the late 19th century to address issues with Euclid's system. It also discusses how axiom systems can be modeled using abstract concepts like points represented by tables and lines by chairs to demonstrate properties without relying on visual diagrams.
The document discusses Euclid's axioms of geometry, flaws in Euclid's system, Hilbert's axiomatic approach, and betweenness axioms.
The five axioms of Euclidean geometry are: 1) Given two distinct points P and Q, there is a line through P and Q. 2) Any line segment can be extended indefinitely. 3) Given two distinct points P and Q, a circle centered at P with radius PQ can be drawn. 4) All right angles are congruent. 5) Given any line l and a point P not on l, there exists a line through P that is parallel to l.
The flaw is that it assumes without proof that the bisector of the vertex angle meets the opposite side between the endpoints, which requires the betweenness axioms.
Flaws in Euclid
The Five Axioms
Given two distinct points P and Q, there is a line
through P and Q.
Any line segment can be extended indefinitely.
Given two distinct points P and Q, a circle
centered at P with radius PQ can be drawn.
All right angles are congruent.
Given any line l and a point P not on l, there
exists a line through P that is parallel to l. Using these axioms, try to prove that points and lines exist.
Given two distinct points P and Q, there is a line
through P and Q.
Any line segment can be extended indefinitely.
Given two distinct points P and Q, a circle
centered at P with radius PQ can be drawn.
All right angles are congruent.
Given any line l and a point P not on l, there
exists a line through P that is parallel to l. Using these axioms, try to prove that given a line l, there exists a point lying on l.
Given two distinct points P and Q, there is a line
through P and Q.
Any line segment can be extended indefinitely.
Given two distinct points P and Q, a circle
centered at P with radius PQ can be drawn.
All right angles are congruent.
Given any line l and a point P not on l, there
exists a line through P that is parallel to l. Using these axioms, try to prove that given a line l, there exists a point !T lying on l.
Given two distinct points P and Q, there is a line
through P and Q.
Any line segment can be extended indefinitely.
Given two distinct points P and Q, a circle
centered at P with radius PQ can be drawn.
All right angles are congruent.
Given any line l and a point P not on l, there
exists a line through P that is parallel to l. "trictly, under Euclidean Geometry, we have no guarantee that points and lines exist. #t is also $ust based on our %unfounded& assumptions that lines contain points. A simple abstract axiomatic system
Undefined terms: Fe's Fo's, and the
relation belongs to
Axiom 1: There exist exactly three
distinct Fe's in this system.
Axiom 2: Two distinct Fe's belong to
exactly one Fo.
Axiom 3: Not all Fe's belong to the
same Fo.
Axiom 4: Any two distinct Fo's contain
at least one Fe that belongs to both. Prove the ollowing Theorems.
Fe-Fo Theorem 1. Two distinct Fo's contain
exactly one Fe in common.
Fe-Fo Theorem 2. There are exactly three Fo's.
Fe-Fo Theorem 3. !ach Fo has exactly two
Fe's that belong to it. #n proving the results in the previous slide, you may have imagined dots or dashes on a sheet of paper. 'e will ta(e the point of view that these dots and dashes are a model for the given geometry. )ore generally, given an axiom system, we can interpret the undefined terms in some way %does not have to be dots or dashes&. #f the axioms are satisfied based on our interpretation, then we can call our interpretation a model. "ample )odel* Designate the Fe's as people and the Fo's as committees.
Axiom 1: There exist exactly three distinct
people.
Axiom 2: Two distinct people belong to exactly
one committee.
Axiom 3: Not all people belong to the same
committee.
Axiom 4: Any two distinct committees contain
at least one person who belongs to both. "ample )odel* Designate the Fe's as books and the Fo's as bags.
Axiom 1: There exist exactly three distinct
books.
Axiom 2: Two distinct books belong to exactly
one bag.
Axiom 3:Not all books belong to the same bag.
Axiom 4: Any two distinct bags contain at least
one book that is on both. The "se o models
All theorems in the system are also correct
statements in the model.
Fe-Fo Theorem 1. Two distinct Fo's contain
exactly one Fe in common.
Fe-Fo Theorem 2. There are exactly three
Fo's.
Fe-Fo Theorem 3. !ach Fo has exactly two
Fe's that belong to it. The "se o models
All theorems in the system are also correct
statements in the model.
Fe-Fo Theorem 1. Two distinct committees
contain exactly one #erson in common.
Fe-Fo Theorem 2. There are exactly three
committees.
Fe-Fo Theorem 3. !ach committee has
exactly two #ersons that belong to it. The use of models
)odels are +laboratories, for experimenting
with the axiomatic system.
)athematicians often discover that one model
has applications to completely different models. -ac( to Euclid.s Elements /onstruct an e0uilateral triangle 12roposition 34 based on the following 1Euclidean4 axioms. 3.Given two distinct points P and Q, there is a line through P and Q. 5.Given two distinct points P and Q, a circle centered at P with radius PQ can be drawn. The first proposition 3.To construct an e0uilateral triangle on a given finite straight line. There is a flaw in the logic because of the assumption that the two circles will have a point of intersection.
6uite a few of Euclid.s proofs, such as the
construction of an e0uilateral triangle or the "A" theorem, are based on reasoning from diagrams.
7owever, as we.ve shown, diagrams can be
deceptive.
A larger system of explicit axioms is needed.
!ne of the first set of axioms introduced to
remedy the defects of Euclid.s wor( was given by )orit8 2asch in 3995.
ote: This was around 5;;; years after Euclid.s
Elements. <avid 7ilbert %39=5>3?@A&
2resented not the
first, but perhaps the most intuitive set of axioms, closest in spirit to Euclid.s. !ne must be able to say at all timesBinstead of points, lines and planesBtables, chairs and beer mugs. > <avid 7ilbert Euclid.s axioms in this sense 3.Given two distinct tables P and Q, there is a chair through P and Q. 5.Given two distinct tables P and Q, a circle centered at P with radius PQ can be drawn. /an you (now use these to construct an e0uilateral triangle* Euclid still relied on visual reasoning.
2oint C that which has no part
Dine C breadthless length
"urface C that which has length and breadth
only #n an axiomatic method
2oints, lines and planes are undefined terms.
'e use models to represent these terms.
#n this system, points are not necessarily
represented as dots, and lines are not necessarily represented as long straight stro(es. The Five sets of 7ilbert.s axioms
Axioms of #ncidence
Axioms of -etweenness
Axioms of 2arallels
Axioms of /ongruence
Axioms of /ontinuity An exercise
/onsider the following proof %found in some
high school geometry texts& that the base angles of an isosceles triangle are congruent.
Det the bisector of / meet A- at <.
A/< is congruent to -/< by "A".
A is congruent to -.
Find the flaw in the proof.
7ow do we (now that < lies between A and -* 'e need -etweenness axioms to prove that the bisector of / does meet A- in a point between A and -. -etweenness Axioms %7ilbert&
otation A E - E / to mean +point - is between
points A and /, 3. #f A E - E /, then A, -, and / are three distinct points lying on the same line, and / E - E A. 1fills a gap in one flaw above4 -etweenness Axioms %7ilbert& 2. Given any two distinct points - and <, there exists points A, /, and E lying on -< such that A E - E <, - E / E <, and - E < E E. 1ensures that there are points between - and <, and that the line -< does not end at - or <4 3. #f A, -, and / are three distinct points lying on the same line, then one and only one of the points is between the other two. 1ensures that a line is not circular4 Exercise Given two points A and -, consider the two rays A- and -A. a.<raw diagrams to show that A- -A F A-, and A- -A F A-. b.2rove these formulas. Use the definitions of segment and ray, as given on the next slide.
Given two points A and -. The segment A- is
the set whose members are A, -, and all the points that lie on line A- that are between A and -.
The ray A- is the following set of points on A-:
all points on segment A- and all points / on A- such that A E - E /.