Intuition As A Philosophical Method in India - Raju, P. T.
Intuition As A Philosophical Method in India - Raju, P. T.
Intuition As A Philosophical Method in India - Raju, P. T.
Author(s): P. T. Raju
Reviewed work(s):
Source: Philosophy East and West, Vol. 2, No. 3 (Oct., 1952), pp. 187-207
Published by: University of Hawai'i Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1397270 .
Accessed: 06/12/2011 07:28
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy
East and West.
http://www.jstor.org
P. T. RAJU
Intuition
Method
Philosophical
in
India
188
P. T. RAJU
and that people belonging to the one are by nature psychologically different
from those belonging to the other. But one might retort by saying that the
true difference is that between the progressive and the backward,and that
it is one of degree but not of kind. The backward,therefore, do not insist
that their cultural and philosophical achievements,obtained by fits and starts,
should continue to be improved by only the same intuitive methods and by
fits and starts.
There is a further misunderstandingabout Indian philosophy, namely,
that it is a single school or system of thought. It is almost as correctto speak
of Western philosophy as a single philosophy as to speakof Indianphilosophy
as one. If one important school holds strong views on the dependabilityor
otherwise of intellect, the same is wrongly attributedto all the others. Again,
the term Indian philosophy is made to refer to the ancient systems alone,
as if Indian philosophy were something ancient like Greek philosophy. It is
true that India is better known for her ancient philosophies than for any
new systems, but many contemporaryphilosophers in India have not been
satisfied with everything of ancient thought and have shown inclinations
toward new ideas. And none of the new philosophers has made intuition
his philosophical method, though almost every one has admitted the truth
of intuition and the shortcomings of intellect.
II
Before proceeding with the discussion,the meaning of the word intuition
needs to be clarified. Intuition means immediate or unmediatedknowledge.
Etymologically, it means "looking into," that is, it is knowledge obtained
not by looking outside one's self-whatever the word self means, and its
meaning may not be discussedfor the present-but by looking inside one's
self.
Now, is looking into one's self necessarily unmediated? This is a controversial question; and the answer depends on how the process of "looking
into" and the nature of the self are understood. If the "looking into" also
needs an instrument (karana), then the process is mediated, and knowledge
so obtained is not immediate knowledge. First, even if some instrumentality
is needed, if the self is understoodto be identical with the mind (manas)as it is in Western philosophy and psychology in general-then it is its
own instrument,and the resulting knowledge may be regardedas unmediated
in the sense of being not mediated by something other than the agent of
that cognition. However, even in Western psychology, there has been a
growing feeling that there is a core to be called the self in our experience,
189
which is not exhausted by the mental processes.2 This distinction was more
clearly made by the ancient Indian philosophers.3 Even when this distinction is accepted, the self may be regarded as being capable of looking into
itself in some way, without the help of the mind; and as the instrument
and the agent would here be identical, the resulting knowledge can be said
to be unmediated and therefore intuitive. The present case, which is the
second, is the self's knowledge of itself, when it is different from the mind,
while the previous case is one in which the self is regardedas identical with
the mind. We may next have a third situation, in which the self is considered to be different from the mind and yet, through the instrumentality
(karanatva) of the mind, that is, through introspection, it cognizes such
mental processes as emotions, feelings, and sentiments. In this case, as the
instrument is different from the self, the agent, knowledge cannot be said
to be unmediated. Then we have a fourth situation: Some cognitions
need not only the instrumentalityof the mind, but also that of the senses
(indriyas), for instance, the perceptual cognition of the tree in front of me.
And whether the self, as agent, is regarded as identical with the mind or
not, perceptual cognition is mediated and not unmediated. Quite often
Western philosophers treat perception as direct and immediate knowledge.
Even the Sanskrit word aparoksam (not beyond senses) implies that view.
But if we are to be thorough in our application of the idea of immediacy,
we have to say that even sense perception is mediated. But, in all the
cases mentioned so far, mediation is not voluntary: it is spontaneous
like the workings of our involuntary nervous system. And for the reason
that knowledge is not deliberately mediated, we say that perception in all
the above cases is direct. But in the fifth situation, namely, that of inference,
the resulting cognition is voluntarily mediated and is accepted by all as
mediated knowledge.
III
In Indian philosophy, the words used for mediate and immediate knowledge are paroksajinan and aparoksajina. As indicated above, the words
literally mean "knowledge beyond senses" and "knowledge not beyond
senses." But later, the second word came to mean both sense perception and
the highest intuition, which is that of the Brahman, the Absolute, and
largely corresponds to the intellectual intuition of Kant, particularly as
2
See Leon Litwinski, "Towards a Reinstatement of the Concept of Self," The British Journal
of Psychology, General Section, August, 1951 .
3Self (atman) does not mean the same as soul (jiva) for any Indian philosophers except the
Jainas.
190
P. T. RAJU
191
IV
The above points refer mainly to intuition as the direct and unmediated
knowledge of the Brahman, Atman, and Nirvana. But the word intuition
is used also in the sense of the knowledge of physical objects and other
6See Mahayana-sutralankara
I. 12, SylvainLevi, ed. (Paris: LibrarieHonore Champion,1907).
192
P. T. RAJU
193
is not the whole of Indian philosophy. According to the Nyaya and the
Vaisesika schools, perception of the Brahman or Isvara (God) is not the
same as perception of reality, for these two schools accept the eternality
of atoms, space, time, and atman (self), which are therefore separate from
the Brahman or Isvara and are as real as it or he. But the more important
point is that, at the stage of liberation (mukti), at which atman regains its
pure state, it does not perceive anything, since it is by nature unconscious.
Thus, there is no scope for any darsana (perception), even if by dariana
is meant the unpolluted perception of the original reality. So, the word
dariana has to be understood as is the word view, which means not only
the view I have of the street or scenery before me but also the view I hold
of the nature of mind, matter, etc. Such an interpretationis necessitatedby
the synonyms of the word darsanain the sense of philosophy, such as mata
(opinion, doctrine) and siddhanta (doctrine, theory). For instance, the
Saiva philosophy is called not only SaivadarSanabut also Saivasiddhanta.
Another reason given for the opinion that the method of Indian philosophy is intuitive is that philosophy in India is also called moksasastra,the
science of salvation or liberation. Indian philosophy aims, it is said, at
pointing out the path to liberation; and, as the state of liberation, which
is the original pure state of one's self, is known only through intuition
and not through intellect, it is thought that the method of Indian philosophy
must be intuitive and not logical. Almost all the Indian systems speak of
moksa (liberation) as the aim of philosophical activity. Therefore, they
must discuss the nature of moksa, the method or way (marga) of attaining
moksa, and the nature of reality, both phenomenal and noumenal, with
reference to which moksa has to be explained. But, it must be pointed out,
none of the problems connected with these topics can be solved by means
of intuition alone. Neither human nature nor the nature of the physical
world can be explained merely through intuition. Indeed, reason cannot
work in a vacuum and with mere assumptionsor axioms arbitrarilyaccepted,
if it is to explain any existent fact. Therefore, it is based upon intuition
in the widest sense of direct experience, whether sensuous or non-sensuous.
The truths of intuition are integrated into a system by reason.8 The nature
of moksa cannot be explained, therefore, without the help of reason, and
philosophy consists of this explanation. Hence, even for those systems for
which moksa is the ultimate aim of philosophy, philosophical method consists not merely in intuition but also in rationally integrating the intuited
8 In this sense, even human beings are accredited with intuitive understanding by some Western
thinkers, while Kant thought that God alone might possess it. See W. H. Walsh, Reason and
Experience (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1947), pp. 57 ff.
194
P. T. RAJU
truths. Furthermore,it should not be forgotten that for those schools for
which the original pure state of self (atman) is not conscious, that is, the
Nyaya and the Vaisesika, there can be no intuition of moksa. Its nature is
only inferred with the help of reason. Again, for those schools for which
the Brahman is not the only reality, intuition of the Brahman does not
explain the nature of the other realities. Explanation of these realities and
their mutual interrelationshipsis the work of reason and not merely of
intuition. For instance, the existence of atoms is logically proved by the
Vaisesikas, and most of the followers of this school do not claim to have
experienced them intuitively; and this intuition, they say, is heard of in the
and the Yoga, though they say that
Vedas and the Puranas. The Samhkhya
atman is by nature conscious, treat it as different from prakrti (nature);
and so, intuition of the former does not explain the nature of the latter.
The Sramkhyaproves the plurality of selves and their differencefrom nature
with the help of reason. Further, most schools do not accept moksa
(liberation) and the state of the individual during liberation merely on the
basis of intuition. They prove the truth of both with the help of logic,
with phenomenal experience as the starting point.
Another important reason for the view that Indian philosophy depends
on intuition as its method may be the reliance by many schools on scripture
(sruti). The sruti consists of a number of utterancesabout the experiences
of several discoverers of inner truths, which are therefore intuitions. But
though the Vedic seers may be said to have based their statementson intuitions, their followers and commentatorswho expounded their views did not
use intuition for their argument. In the discussionsamong themselves, they
depended upon grammar and etymology for the interpretation of verbal
statements,and upon perceptionand inference for the interpretationof ideas.
Again, not all the Indian schools accept the fruti as authority. The Buddhists
and the Jainas, in their controversieswith the followers of the Vedic tradition, depended exclusively upon perception and inference for establishing
their conclusions, as did also the Vedic followers in their controversieswith
the Buddhists and the Jainas. Yet, all these schools accepted intuition in
the sense of suprarational,non-discursiveknowledge, which is direct experience (aparoksanubhiti) of the ultimate reality,whatever that be. Indeed,
intuition in the sense of direct perception or sensation is accepted by all
schools, though many of them are aware of the defects of perception as a
form of knowledge. Some of the later CQrvakas,e.g., Jayarasi,the author of
Tattvopaplavasimha;Buddhistslike Nagarjuna, the author of Madhyamikakarikas; and Advaitins like Sriharsa,the author of Khandana-khandtakhdya,
195
point out the shortcomings not only of inference but also of perception.
Again, most of the Indian philosophers accept two kinds of perception, the
determinate and the indeterminate. Indeterminateperception is pure sense
awareness;but discursionenters determinateperception, which is relational.
It is knowledge in which the distinction between subject and predicate is a
moment. It is always of the form, "That is an X." Some schools, e.g., the
Nyaya, do not accept indeterminate perception as knowledge at all, for
knowledge is either true or false, and the question of truth and falsity is not
relevant to indeterminateperception. Others, however, e.g., the Buddhists,
treat indeterminateperceptionas a form of knowledge. But now, for schools
like the Nyaya, intuition, in the sense of non-discursiveknowledge, cannot
be a philosophical method at all, for the simple reason that it can be neither
true nor false. But philosophy has to be either true or false.
Another important doctrine to be referred to in this connection is that
of pr,amanya,the nature of truth. Very interesting controversieshave been
carriedon by the several schools about the question as to whether a cognition
is true by itself or made true by another cognition. This is not the same
question as whether cognition is self-revelatory or not. For the highest
intuition, namely, the intuition of the Brahman, if one has it, there can be
no other cognition either to prove or disprove it. In the case of my perception of the book in front of me, I may know that I know the book, but
this knowledge that I know the book does not make my knowledge of the
book either true or false. So, even if we accept the self-revelatorycharacter
of knowledge at the empirical level, the self-revelatorycharacterof knowledge is not the same as the truth of that cognition. Now, the Naiyayikas
(followers of the Nyaya) maintain that no cognition by itself is either true
or false, but is made so by another cognition.9 If every cognition has to
refer beyond itself to another cognition in order to be true or false, then
non-discursiveknowledge cannot be true; and in order to be true knowledge
must be discursive. So, accordingto the epistemology of the Nyaya, intuition
as immediate non-discursiveknowledge can be neither true nor false.
According to some Buddhists,every cognition is false by itself, but is made
true by another cognition, the second cognition here being the cognition that
the object cognized serves the purpose for which it is meant. This is a
pragmatic conception of truth. But it means that, so far as the empirical
world is concerned,pure intuition by itself, even as indeterminateperception
(nirvikalpakapratyaksa), cannot be true, unless made so by another cognition. Hence, knowledge at the empirical level must be discursive.
9This
interpretationis given to the doctrinesof the otherschoolsalso. See the author'sThought
and Reality (London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd., 1937), Part III, chap. VIII.
196
P. T. RAJU
197
follower of the Vedic tradition only if it has been able to furnish a commentary on the Veddnta-sutras.This shows that neither the Nyaya and the
Vaisesika nor the Sahkhya and the Yoga started their philosophical activity
as elaborations and interpretationsof the Upanisadic intuitive statements.
To be sure, they acceptedthe possibility of intuiting empirical and noumenal
realities, but they did not use intuition either in expounding their doctrines
or in controverting those of their rivals.
It is only the Vedantic schools that startedas expounders,interpreters,and
systematizersof the Upanisadic statements. The Vedanta-s&trascomposed
by Badarayanafor systematizing the Upanisadic statements and removing
contradictionswere later found inadequatefor the purpose. As controversies
arose among the Vedantic followers themselves and between the Vedantins
and their rivals, need was felt for further clarificationand development of
the ideas. And so, commentaries and commentaries upon commentaries
had to be written, and this kind of work continued with more or less vigor
until about the fifteenth century. Besides the Vedas, there were other kinds
of scriptures,such as the Agamas of the Saivas and the Vaisnavas, which
also were regardedby some as of equal authority. And in order to remove
conflict between them and the Upanisads, commentaries reinterpretingthe
Vedanta-sutrasand the Upaniads were written. Thus, clear-cut differences
developed among the Vedantic schools.
The activity of writing commentariesupon commentarieswill perhaps be
interpretedas being based upon intuition as a philosophical method. It may
be contended that there was an original intuition and the rest was merely
its elaboration. Even if the contention were true, elaborationand interpretation were not intuitively done. It was with the help of logic and reason
that the whole superstructureof a system was raised on an idea accepted
on the authority of some scripture. And the scripture was nothing more
than a revelation to one or more seekers of truth, and was later accepted as
truth by his or their followers on authority.
Now, does this acceptanceof an original intuition justify us in saying that,
for Indian philosophy, the philosophical method is intuition? First, many
schools did not follow the method of writing commentaries upon commentaries on the intuitive wisdom of the Upanisads and the Vedanta-sitras
for developing and expounding their systems. Second, different schools and
sub-schools of the Vedanta understood and interpreted these original intuitions in quite different ways, and in order to justify their understandingand
interpretationthey used logic and reason. Their method was to show that
rival interpretationswere illogical and contrary to fact. Anyone who goes
through the commentariesof Saikara and Ramanujaon the Vedanta-sutras
198
P. T. RAJU
199
VII
Provided we do not forget that Indian philosophy has been primarily
concerned with the inner life of man and with the place of man in the
universe and his destiny, we may say that it is neither more intuitive nor
less intellectual in its methods than Western philosophy. Taking into further
200
P. T. RAJU
considerationthe fact that Indian philosophy has had no significantdevelopment since about the fifteenth century and therefore cannot show as many
ramificationsand as much progress as modern and contemporaryWestern
philosophy can, we may say with justificationthat, up to the fifteenth century, Indian philosophy showed as vigorous a development of logic as could
be expected. The elaboratedefinitions,the methods of definition,and logical
analysis of concepts which the Neo-Nyiya gave us and the practiceof which
was later adopted by the other schools would leave no doubt in the minds
of any serious student about the intellectualism of the methods of the
philosophers of that time. But if we consider philosophy as interpretation
of experienceand experienceas both inner and outer, and as primarilydirect,
we have to accept also the view that no philosophy can dispense with intuition. Quite often, the Middle Ages of Europe are referred to as the Dark
Ages, and the medieval period of European philosophy as having no philosophy but only theology; and it is also said that the period tolerated no
freedom of inquiry and put arbitrarylimits on reason. But Whitehead says
that it was a period of reason.l2 The Schoolmen argued and argued, even
about the number of angels that could dance on the point of a needle. It is
the modern period, he says, that turned its attention to history, fact, and
experience. It is an accepted method now to start from experience, argue
about it, and test our arguments again by experience. That is, we use both
intuition and intellect. When it is said that the Middle Ages were opposed
to the free use of reason, it is meant that they were opposed to that freedom
of inquiry which is not merely arguing but also discovery. And discovery
includes direct experience. Intellect cannot work without intuition, and intuition needs intellect for its development and as a check.
So much is admitted even by Western philosophers. ProfessorMontague
writes that the "theory that truth can be attained by a supra-rationaland
supersensuousfaculty of intuition is mysticism."13He says further: "Intuition
might be defined not only as imagination touched with conviction, but also
as the outcome of sub-consciousinduction or deduction."14 And intuition
touched with conviction is the same whether it occurs in the scientist or the
poet.5l This imagination is that function of mind which forms hypotheses.
Logically it is the function of forming hypotheses, and psychologically it is
imagination. Again, ProfessorMontague writes: "It is the latter business of
comparing the newly born hypotheses of imagination with the established
1 A. N. Whitehead,Scienceand the Modern World (New York: The New AmericanLibrary
of World Literature,Inc., 1949), p. 39. Certaintendenciesin contemporarylogical positivism
may be called tendenciesof "unbridledrationalism."
"W. P. Montague,Waysof Knowing (London: George Allen and Unwin, Ltd., 1948), p. 55.
1 Ibid., p. 66.
Ibid., p. 64.
201
202
P. T. RAJU
like the followers of Sankara,say that what is true from one point of view
and false from another can be neither true nor false. Others say that it is
both true and false. But all this elaborationof the ideas of truth and falsity
is the work of intellect, not of intuition.
Taking Bergson, for instance, should we say that he used intuition as a
philosophical method? In spite of all his strictures against intellect and
logic, it was only with their help that he attempted to show their shortcomings. All that he succeeded in proving was that there is such a form
of cognition as intuition and that it is with its help that we can cognize
time or duration. But is the experience of space the same as the concept
of space? The experience of space is as much an intuition as the experience
of time. Kant said as much, before Bergson, in calling space and time
forms of intuition; even as forms of intuition, they are as much intuited.
If successionis not time, simultaneityis not space. We need not here discuss
the question of whether time or space is or is not spiritual. But there are
many things in the world which we know through intuition in the sense
of direct experience. And so long as we are preparedto leave them unrelated
and unco-ordinatedwith each other, reason does not enter the scene. But
when we attempt to co-ordinateand relate them and disprove false intuitions
and confirm the true, we need the work of reason. Bergson, for example,
had to use reason for relating time with space and other objects of experience
and in developing principles of this interrelating.
Bradleyalso admittedthe necessityof intuition, when he said that, without
the "This" in immediate experience, thought cannot work; otherwise, the
workings of thought would be a consistent fairy tale without relevance to
actuality.17Mr. Walsh says that Bradley admits somewhat tacitly the truth
of intellectual intuition in our experience,which Kant thought belongs only
to God's experience.'8 Thought cannot incorporatethe immediacy of feeling and sense and therefore remains until the end "an unearthly ballet of
bloodless categories"and a "spectralwoof of impalpable abstractions." In
order to succeed in its work and attain its objective, thought must pass into
something other and higher. And this higher, which is to retain the mediacy
of thought and the immediacy of feeling and sense, can be nothing other
than intellectual intuition, which creates sensations according to its conceptions.
17F. H. Bradley, The Principles of Logic (London: Oxford University Press, 1922), Vol. II,
p. 660. See also Rudolf Carnap, Meaning and Necessity (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
n.d.), p. 12. Just as Bradley says that reason cannot determine whether a proposition is factually
true or not without immediate experience, Carnap admits that semantics cannot determine the
same without direct observation.
'8 Reason and Experience, p. 62.
203
VIII
204
P. T. RAJU
trines, we may say that in Western philosophy, too, the presence of intuition
is admitted not only at the level of sensation and perception, but also at
that of intellect or thought. Intuition is the grasping of an object as a solid
unity or integrality. It is present, therefore, not only when pure qualities
like colors and smells are grasped but also when individual objects like
pens and pencils, universals like humanity and redness,and the Absolute or
Brahman at the suprarationallevel are cognized. When I perceive a pen
as a pen and not merely as a combination of qualities like colors and touch,
I have an intuition. That the pen is perceived as a pen and not always as
a group of qualities is shown when, in the erroneous perception of a pencil
as a pen, we make the contradicting judgment, "It is a pencil and not a
pen." We do not say that we did not really perceive this or that quality, but
that we did not perceive this or that object. The knowledge that we did
not really perceive this or that quality is a result of later analysis of our
experience. And even when we perceive a color like red, we have intuition,
because the object is seen as a solid unity. A quality is a quality only when
it is seen in relation to its substance.
Regarding the cognition of universals, there are two views: accordingto
Plato, they are only remembered but not perceived, whereas, according to
Aristotle, they are perceived in the particulars. But Aristotle says that they
are only intellectually intuited and not sensuously. Among the Indian philosophers, the Naiyiyikas say that universals are sensuously intuited. Now,
even taking Plato's doctrine,when we rememberan object, do we remember
it as a solid unity or as a group or combination of interrelated elements?
In rememberingan object as a solid unity, there is an element of intuition,
whether the object is a physical object or a universal. And Plato treats the
Ideas as substances, which shows that the universals are solid unities and
not mere groupings of elements. So, if we accept the view that the cognition
of any solid unity involves intuition, then there must be intuition at the level
of thought also.
One may now ask: If thought, like perception, involves intuition, what
is the differencebetween the two? Is not thought said to be discursiveand
perception non-discursive?In answer, it may be asked: If the perception of
a book is of the form "It is a book" and not merely of the form "book,"is
not perception also discursive? Perception itself becomes relational knowledge with the relation between "It" and "book." We may hold that there
is a stage in perception at which cognition is of the simple form "book."
But when I wish to communicatemy knowledge or bring it to the level of
communicabilityor even to that level at which I can relate it to other bits
of my own knowledge, it would be of the form "It is a book" and would
205
be relational.For all these stages,philosophershave usedthe wordperception. Even if we believe that perceptionis originallyof the form "book"
and is intuitive,it is potentiallyrelationaland discursive,becauseit later
assumesthe form "It is a book." "It"and "book"then becomeelementsof
the originalperception"book." But the elementsnow remainintuitions;
and againthe awarenessof the whole,thoughdiscursive,retainsan intuitive
background.
At the level of thinking,we pass beyonddemonstrativereference.But
even when we make a judgmentlike "Manis mortal,"we have two solid
formal unities,"man"and "mortal,"distinctlyentertainedby thoughtand
relatedby it. These solid unitiesare intuitions.If so, even at the level of
we have intuition.
thought or understanding,
The above discussionshows that, except at the highest (that is, of the
Absolute and of the mystic) and the lowest levels of cognition, thought
cannot work without intuitions and intuitions cannot be understoodwithout
206
P. T. RAJU
207