Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology
Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology
Middle-Range Theory in Historical Archaeology
Archaeology
Peter Kosso*
1. Introduction: Conceptual Background
EVIDENCE in archaeology,
since it is an informational
link between the unobservable past and observable
data in the present, must be accountable
to
justification
that the link is secure and accurate. The same accountability
is
true of evidence in the natural sciences where epistemic responsibility
requires
an understanding
of the connection
between the manifest data (streaks in a
bubble chamber, for example) and the theorized entities (alpha particles) of
which the data are evidence. In the archaeological
case, Lewis Binford has
suggested that the informational
link is understood,
and hence the evidence is
made meaningful
and reliable, through middle-range
theories which describe
the formation process of the data. Applying this approach to the more specific
case of historical
archaeology,
M. Leone and P. Potter suggest that the
documentary
record of the past and the material record could be used as
independent
sources of middle-range
theories for each other.* They indicate
though, that this epistemic opportunity
in historical
archaeology
is rarely
exploited.
The purpose of this paper is to present an analysis of evidence in a particular
case of historical archaeology to show the middle-range
theories in action. By
focusing on how the evidential link is made between observational
data and
the objects and events of theoretical interest it will be shown that middle-range
theories are almost always implicit in the evidence, and that they can be
articulated
and evaluated
for their independence
from the theories their
evidence is used to test. It is this independence
that allows the theoryinfluenced
evidence to be objective evidence nonetheless.
Furthermore,
the
implicit status of the middle-range
theories in the case at hand motivates the
suggestion that documentary
and material information
participate more often
University,
AZ 8601 l-
163
1993.
0
003%3681/93
S6.00 + 0.00
1993. Pergamon Press Ltd
164
in such a reciprocal relation than Leone and Potter indicate. The middle-range
theorizing simply goes without saying.
This is not to be a discussion of the structure of confirmation. It is not about
the nature of the connection between the evidence, once youve got it, and a
hypothesis. It is rather about the nature of the evidence itself and its relation to
theoretical claims invoked to enhance the informational value of data.
As a case study, this is an empirical contribution to a description of
archaeological and scientific evidence, a description that requires a component
of conceptual analysis as well. Like science itself, philosophy of science must
offer both general theorizing and specific evidence. The specifics of this case
will be more meaningful if presented in their theoretical context, that is, with a
preliminary sketch of the conceptual analysis it is intended to complement. To
this end, I now briefly outline the theorizing which will help structure the
subsequent evidence.3
The accomplishment of theorizing, in science as in our everyday knowledge
about the world around us, is to make expansive claims about what is
happening or has happened behind the scenes, beyond what is manifest in
experience. Theories make claims about unobservable objects and events of all
sorts, the tiny, the distant, the cumulative, the past. Evidential claims which
function to test a theory must be relevant to these objects and events
mentioned by the theory, and to the accessible, particular objects and events
which are mid-sized, here and now. A complete picture of evidence then, must
include claims, theoretical claims, which describe the link between accessible
objects and the phenomena which make contact with theory. It is an appeal to
theory, to revive a previous example, which allows the physicist to call these
streaks in the bubble chamber indicators of alpha decay. These streaks mean
alpha decay.
The claims which add this kind of meaning and relevance to the data are
often descriptions of how the data are formed. In describing the causal process
which led from phenomenon of evidential interest (alpha decay) to the final
observable event (streaks), the data are shown to be an image of the phenomenon. Elsewhere4 I have referred to these claims which reveal the evidentially
relevant information in observations as accounting theories, indicating that
scientific evidence is not simply an episode of observation but an observation
that is accountable in the sense that the scientist, or at least the scientific
community at large, must know the circumstances of formation of the observation to know both what it means - that is, in what sense it is relevant to the
particular theory for which it is evidence - and to know that it is reliably
The full treatment
of this conceptual
analysis can be found in P. Kosso, Science and
Objectivity,
The Journal of Philosophy 86 (1989), 245-257, and P. Kosso,
Method
in
Archaeology:
Middle-Range
Theory as Hermeneutics,
American Antiquity 56 621-627.
KOSSO, Science and Objectivity, ibid.
165
Ibid.
166
for justification,
and the theories which justify evidence do not bring any
epistemic privileges into the account. They must pass their own evidential and
conceptual tests. There is a kind of hermeneutic circularity in all of this, in that
the specific, particular
reports of observation
are guided by more general
understanding
of theories, while the theoretical claims are themselves shaped
by the specifics of evidence. But it need not be a problematic
circle insofar as
we can insist on an independence
between the theories which influence a
particular
observation
and the theory for which that observation
is evidence.
All evidence is guided by theory, but not necessarily by the same theory it is
used to test.
But this is a big, conceptual
issue, and the programme
here is to consider
some particular evidence. The bulk of the exposition is to be done through an
example in historical Greek archaeology,
where evidence is sought about the
colonization
by Classical Athens.
Evidence and theory in archaeology do not make for a typical case study in
the philosophy
of science, but with the reciprocating
relation between theory
and evidence as will be shown here, it is wise to look for similarities between
the status of evidence in archaeology and in natural science. Similarities in the
nature of observation
in archaeology and natural science were pointed out by
John Fritz even before Binford introduced the concept of middle-range
theory.
Fritz classified prehistoric events and objects as being indirectly observed in the
same sense as distant galaxies or atoms are indirectly observed. Much of what
follows here will be built on Fritzs foundation.
167
The example analysed here is an on-going project. It is not a closed case, and
so the evidence will be both actual, observations that have already been made,
and potential, relevant observations proposed but yet to be carried out. In
either case it is important to know of the theoretical influence which makes the
observation relevant to the hypothesis. Of these evidential claims, care will be
taken to identify two kinds: those which describe the manifest state of affairs,
the data, and those which describe the phenomena which are not manifest.
The final set of claims to be identified in the case will be those theoretical
claims used to link the manifest data to the relevant phenomena. These will be
the background information employed to tell us what the observations mean
-that
is, what they indicate about the hypothesis. These are the middle-range
theories, or the accounting theories, which attest to the relevance and accuracy
of the observations. These are what make observations into evidence.
Once all these components of the evidence and testing have been identified,
the analysis will continue by assessing the relation between the hypothesis, that
is, the theory being tested, and the accounting theories. In particular, we will
evaluate the independence between these two components to check for any
covert circularity in the presentation of evidence. Finally, each case will end
with a discussion of the negotiation between theory and evidence. When things
go wrong and evidence does not match hypothetical expectation, something
has to give. With the large cast of participants in each evidential claim there is
apparently much work to be done in deciding which to revise or reject.
Initially, none are immune to revision and the ensuing give-and-take between
evidence and theory is a necessary concluding step in each case.
these settlements
I have
learned
with much
help from
corre-
168
%ee, for example, R. Meiggs, The Athenian Empire (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972).
p. 121.
Archaeology
169
Map I.
Euboea. It is a determinate claim about specific events in the past in the sense
that the concept of a cleruchy is reasonably well distinguished and the region
of southern Euboea is a distinctive region due to its isolation by mountains
from the rest of the island. It is a theoretical claim in the sense that it describes
unobservable objects and events.
The motivation for proposing the cleruchy hypothesis and for spending time
and money to test it is from two sources, written evidence (history) and
material evidence (archaeology).
Consider first the historical record.
Herodotus and Thucydides both mention cleruchies but make only one
reference each, and neither is in southern Euboea. Herodotus writes of a
cleruchy at Chalkis in central Euboea, while Thucydides tells of a cleruchy at
Mytilini on the island of Lesbos, near the coast of Asia Minor. Later historians
add more accounts of cleruchies. Diodorus Siculus, a Sicilian writing four
centuries after the fact, writes that Athens dispatched 1000 cleruchs to be
divided into three cleruchy communities, one on Naxos, another on Andros,
Much of this work was conducted under the title of the Canadian Karystia Project, work that
was staffed and directed by SEEP personnel. Descriptions
of the work and the cleruchy hypothesis
can be found in D. Keller and M. Wallace, The Canadian
Karystia Project, Ectros Du Mona?
Classique/Classicaf
Views 30 (1986). 155-I 59; D. Keller and M. Wallace, The Canadian Karystia
Project, 1986, Ethos Du Monde Classique/Classical
Views 31 (1987), 225227; D. Keller and
M. Wallace, How to Catch a Cleruch, Canadian Archaeological Bulletin, Fall (1987), 6-7; and
D. Keller and M. Wallace, The Canadian Karystia Project: Two Classical Farmsteads,
Ethos Du
Monae Classique/Classical
Views 32 (1988), 151-l 57.
Epistemological
questions about the historical record, questions of accuracy and trustworthiness of the accounts, will be taken up later. I do not intend for any of these historical reports to be
believed unequivocally,
but it is helpful at this point to present who said what about cleruchies.
170
and a third on Euboea. Plutarch, in the Life of Pericles, mentions the sending
of 500 cleruchs to Naxos and 250 to Andros. Though no ancient author says
explicitly
how many cleruchs went to Euboea,
we can put together the
information
from Diodorus and from Plutarch to conclude that the remaining
250 cleruchs of the 1000 reported by Diodorus went to Euboea. Furthermore,
while the northern
two-thirds
of Euboea were culturally
and economically
most closely associated with the mainland of Greece, the southern third of the
island participated
more with the Cycladic islands, like Andros and Naxos.
This is reason to think that a dispatch of cleruchs to Andros, Naxos. and
Euboea might well be a mission to the Cyclades, that is, to Andros, Naxos, and
southern Euboea. Thus, the inference from the historical
sources gives some
reason to think that Athens sent 250 cleruchs to southern Euboea. There is
some reason, that is, to entertain the cleruchy hypothesis.
Interestingly,
the evidence for southern
Euboeas Cycladic connection
is
largely archaeological
evidence. Much of the prehistoric
pottery found in
southern Euboea shows similarity to Cycladic pottery and can thereby be seen
as indicative of interaction
with Cycladic islands. The architecture
of modern
houses in southern Euboea also shows distinct similarities to Cycladic styles
and dissimilarity
from that of the northern
two-thirds
of Euboea.12 This is
interesting for an analysis of the nature of the evidence because it is a case of
archaeology
helping to make sense of the historical evidence. Through an
independent
analysis of ceramic remains, the informational
content of the
textual data is enhanced. We see more fully what the text means in light of the
background
knowledge about pottery.
These historical accounts might be thought of as direct references in that
they mention cleruchies explicitly, but it would be misleading to regard them as
direct information
about events in the past. This is information
that has been
passed along by the historian,
via his sources and with his writing, through
time. There is work to be done in securing the credibility
of these ancient
writers on this particular
subject. Diodorus
and Plutarch,
after all, were
describing events that had taken place centuries earlier and their evidence is
acceptable only insofar as we can keep track of how they would know about
these things. Diodorus,
in fact, is often inaccurate
in his tales of ancient
Greece, underscoring
the need for justification
of his particular claims about
cleruchies. Pausanias, also writing centuries after cleruchs had come and gone,
also makes explicit reference to the cleruchs sent to Euboea and Naxos, and
Pausanias
enjoys a good reputation
for accuracy. This is due largely to his
frequent description
of landscapes and monuments,
features of the land and
%x,
for example,
D. Keller, Archaeological
Survey in Southern
Euboea,
Greece: A
Reconstruction
of Human Activity from Neolithic Times through the Byzantine Period, (unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation,
Indiana University,
1983, pp. 64465.
171
culture that are preserved today and can be checked against his account. Here
again, archaeology, the study of the material record, is used in accounting for
historical evidence.
There is another complication in reading the written evidence for cleruchies,
even when the writing is explicitly about that kind of settlement. The ancient
authors did not always use the same word to refer to a cleruchy. Thucydides,
for example, used the term apoikia (~UCOW~~U)
rather than cleruchy (~S~pon~os)
in his account of the settlement at Mytilini,n but scholars know from the
context what he meant. He meant to describe a cleruchy.
The point in mentioning these uncertainties in the written record is one that
is obvious to historians. The historical text is not a direct access to the events
of the past. Its not even close. Evidential claims about the past which come
from a written record are always in need of accounting in the sense of requiring
some verification of their accuracy and reliability, and of requiring an interpretation to pinpoint just what the text means, for as Kuhn points out, there
are many ways to read a text.14
Besides the ancient sources which explicitly refer to cleruchies, there is
implicit textual evidence that can be finessed from accounts of other, related
phenomena. For example, the Athenian Tribute Lists, inscriptions found in the
Athenian Agora, listing the taxesI collected from the communities in the
empire, can be used as a source of information about cleruchies. In the year
450 B.C., Andros paid 12 talents in taxes to Athens. (One talent is equal to
6000 drachmas, a drachma being a days wage.) The subsequent year, 449,
Andros paid only 6 talents. This abrupt reduction can be explained by the
establishment of a cleruchy on the island. If the cleruchs from Athens seize a
large proportion of farmland, the commercial value of the island, as realized
by the pre-settlement residents, is diminished and the locals, in all fairness, are
assessed a lower tax. In this way, establishment of a cleruchy causes an abrupt
decrease in payment of talents to Athens, allowing historians to use the
Athenian Tribute Lists as a rough indicator of cleruchies.
The Athenian Tribute Lists record for Karystos, the principle town in
southern Euboea, a payment in 450 B.C. of 7+ talents, and in 449 a payment of
5 talents. There is no corresponding drop in the assessment for Chalkis or
Eretria, the major towns in the northern two-thirds of the island. This suggests
a cleruchy in the domain of Karystos as a cleruchy would explain the reduced
tax assessment and would fit nicely with the coincident reduction on Andros.
There are no tax records for Naxos prior to 447 B.C., but the assessment in
See A. Graham,
Colony and Mother City in Ancient Greece (Manchester:
Manchester
University Press, 1983), p. 170.
l4T. Kuhn The Essential Tension (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1977), p. xii.
ISThe ATd actually lists the Quota, one sixteenth of the taxes paid. I am grateful to Mac Wallace
for clarification
of this point.
172
that year is quite minimal, an assessment that is compatible with the theory
that Naxos, Andros, and southern Euboea were all saddled with cleruchies in
the year 450/449 B.C.
Further implicit written evidence of a cleruchy in southern Euboea is in the
indication that Karystos did not participate in the Euboean revolts against
Athens of 446 and 424 B.C. It is as if the Karystians were kept under control
by resident Athenian loyalists. This, like the rest of the textual evidence
presented so far, is surely not conclusive proof of a cleruchy in southern
Euboea, but it is motivation for the hypothesis.
There is also archaeological evidence which makes the hypothesis plausible.
A recent archaeological survey by Don Keller of the Karystian Bay
watershedI revealed an apparent network of Classical-period farms on the
Paximadhi peninsula (see Map 2 below). The method of survey archaeology is
to walk over large areas of land, noting artifactual remains that are visible on
the surface. There is no excavation involved. From the surface deposits of
ceramics, worked stones, and remains of walls, information about the habitation and use of the land can be reconstructed. Survey information is a
valuable complement to excavation in that it allows for an account of patterns
of land use and of behaviour spread over a large area.
It is exactly this kind of pattern-of-habitation
information that turned up on
the Paximadhi. A network of sites emerged and the sites were dated as being of
Classical period (500 B.C.-320 B.C.) on the basis of the pottery remains found
on the surface at each site. (There will be more on how this is done and on the
uncertainties involved when we discuss the relevant middle-range theories.)
These sites were identified as farms on the basis of several features. Those with
remaining identifiable groundplans resemble the groundplan of farm sites in
Attica, the function of the Attic sites being known through inscriptional and
other types of evidence. The pottery on the putative farm sites in Euboea is
largely coarseware - the crude, functional stuff associated with domestic
chores - and the relatively small amount of fineware tends to rule out any
possible interpretation of the sites as being aristocratic domiciles. And finally,
the sites are located in proximity to heavily terraced land, olive presses, and
threshing floors, indicating a link between the sites of habitation and the
activities of farming. Interestingly, the Paximadhi is no longer farmed. Today
the land is marginal at best and the peninsula is barren. But the wealth of
terraces and abundance of habitation sites indicates agricultural activity in the
past, and the even spacing of the farm sites further indicates a planned
community rather than a spontaneous growth over time. If the land was
marginal in Classical times, this might explain why the tribute reduction for
Euboea was only 7+ to 5 as compared to the more impressive reduction of 12
lbKeller,
op. cit.,
note
12.
Middle-Range
to 6 for Andros.
173
it would be interesting
hypothesis,
since
174
Paximadhi
Peninsula
Map 2.
important
shipments of grain via Andros to Athens. Many of the Paximadhi
farmsites have an excellent view of both the sea lands and the good Karystian
farmlands.
None of this proves that there was an Athenian cleruchy on the Paximadhi
peninsula.
But altogether the written and material remains make it reasonable
to pursue the cleruchy hypothesis in its now more precise formulation.
The
Paximadhi supported at least part of a settlement of 250 cleruchs from the year
450/449 B.C. until roughly 405 B.C. when the Athenian empire dissolved. This
is the hypothesis to be tested.
4. The Evidence
The evidence for the testing was generated by further archaeological
work as
suggested
by the initial
survey and the predictions
of the hypothesis.
Confirmation
of the hypothesis would be furthered by a linked community
of
roughly 250 farmsteads with coincident
periods of occupation
from roughly
450 to 405 B.C., and perhaps with evidence of unusually close ties to Athens.
To this end, other areas of southern Euboea, namely the vicinities of Geraistos,
Marmari, and Kallianou,
were surveyed in 1984, revealing that the pattern of
finds in the Paximadhi was distinctive. Then the remainder of the Paximadhi
peninsula
was surveyed in 1986. (Only the eastern side, the Karystian
bay
watershed, was done in the initial survey by Keller.) The 1986 survey showed a
continuation
in the regular settlement pattern, finding more sites of roughly
Classical period and apparently for use as farmsteads. The surface materials, in
other words, seemed to bear out the prediction of an extensive community
of
coincident
occupation
cleruchy.
175
farmsteads.
But the surface remains could not fix the dates of
of the sites with sufficient precision to count as clear evidence of a
This precise
dating
could
By excavating
176
177
context
whether
excavation.
Very few of the finds are whole pots, and a very few more are
complete enough to make obvious, without any inferential reconstruction,
the
shape of the whole vessel. Mostly the data are small fragments of the body,
rim, or base of a broken vessel. Unfortunately,
these fragments
are not
stamped with their date or place of origin, nor are they or the places they are
found marked for their use (as, for example, being a farm or a farm tool). This
important
information,
the information
that is relevant to claims about a
cleruchy, must be somehow unnested from the more manifest. The data must
be linked to the evidence.
The first step in the archaeological
case is to record all of the useful data by
carefully describing the apparent physical features of the ceramics. This is the
pottery inventory and anyone, regardless of their knowledge of archaeology or
of the past, can do it. All it takes is average eyesight and maybe above-average
patience. In the process of inventory,
a sherd is described in a standardized
language. Its colour, for example, is compared under controlled
lighting to
patches of colour on the standard Munsell colour chart so that an intersubjective colour assessment is made. The ceramic fabric is inspected for inclusions
and the relative number, size, and colour of the inclusions is noted. The sherd
itself is measured for thickness and its shape is described using standardized
terms such as rolled rim or strap handle. And finally the surface of the sherd
is inspected for treatment such as glaze, slip, incisions or impressed design. All
of these inventory features are readily apparent on the potsherds. The inventory reports are the data in this case of archaeological
testing, but they are not
the evidence because they make no contact with the objects and events
described by theory. They are, as yet, not relevant to the phenomena
predicted
by the hypothesis.
This requisite contact comes with the next step in the treatment of the finds,
the preparation
of a catalogue. This requires substantial
background
knowledge on the part of the individual cataloguer and the archaeological
community as a whole. A sherd which has been inventoried
is now evaluated by the
experts in an effort to determine the type of vessel it is from, the use of the
vessel, and, most importantly,
its date. The type of vessel is judged by
comparing
dimensions,
fabric, and cross-sectional
shape of the sherd to
corresponding
features of whole or nearly-whole
vessels found elsewhere. The
use of the vessel can then be inferred from its shape and from the context in
which it and its comperanda
are found.
Dating the sherd is also dependent on the identification
of the type of vessel
(or in some cases on the physical features of the material or surface treatment).
The sherd is distinguished
by the vessel it is from, or by distinctive decoration
SHIPS 24:2-B
178
or glaze, and can be then associated with similar pieces that have been found
elsewhere in datable circumstances. Some excavations, notably in Athens at
the Agora and the Kerameikos, and at Corinth, have uncovered specimens of
pottery in context with dated inscriptions, with coins, or associated with
buildings that are datable by historic reference. From these excavations come
source-books of pottery types and their dates. This punctuated information
can be filled out through studies of stylistic evolution and through seriation
studies, attending to relative amounts of ceramic styles as a function of time.
The accuracy of dating these reference materials is of course dependent on a
thorough understanding of their context. An object kept for generations as an
heirloom, for example, might eventually be discarded with a coin of much later
period. A casual analysis of the tailings of an archaeological dig, for another
example, might find a beer bottle next to an overlooked neolithic potsherd, but
it would be a mistake to date one artifact by its association with the other.
Thus, the datable circumstances of the Athenian Agora require an understanding of the texts and buildings, including the intent and accuracy of the
writing of the texts found with the pottery or of texts about the buildings, and
the circumstances of deposition.
By attending to the comparable features of the pottery found on the
Paximadhi peninsula and by matching these features to pottery found in
datable contexts, the catalogued sherds bear information of their own dates information, that is, of activities in the past. Soft, powdery, orange fineware
with black glaze, for example, is indicative of activities in the Classical period.
This kind of pottery means occupation of the site during that time period. But
it is so meaningful only with the support of the antecedent claims which make
the general connections between the ceramic data and the evidential dates. In
this case these are claims about the coincidence of pots and texts or pots and
historic buildings in the Athenian Agora, the dating of coincident inscriptions
or coins, and the accuracy of this dating as secured by knowing the circumstances of deposition, the intent of the writing (that it is not itself a fiction) and
the like. Its not that these claims are suspect or complicated. The reason for
pointing them out is simply to show that they are being relied on and that they
are, at least in part, claims about the past. They are, in the archaeological
context, theoretical claims. And since they are being used to make the
connection between the manifest archaeological record and the information it
has to offer about the past, these are middle-range theories. They are used to
tell the SEEP archaeologists what the sherds mean for the cleruchy hypothesis.
These middle-range theories are all pretty simple claims, about the veracity
of the dating material and the legitimacy of dating a particular pot by its
association with a particular text, but simple accounting claims may be all that
are needed in this case because it is pretty simple information that is being
sought in the pottery from the Paximadhi. All we are getting by way of
Middle-Range
179
180
to detect
an object
and
at the same
time
181
Agora.
theory
does
not
a cleruchy,
sponsor
influence
on the evidence
evidence.
self-serving
It is rather
used to
testing.
independent
182
Paximadhi, these cleruchs, used each particular style at a slightly shifted time
period than did the Athenians. Unfortunately, the most coherent of these
pictures would have the lower class, displaced cleruchs getting the pottery
styles later than the resident Athenians, thereby giving the Palio Pithari pottery
even later dates and worsening the fit between evidence and hypothesis.
The fate of the cleruchy hypothesis is still up in the air. The outcome though
will have a relevance beyond writing the history of southern Euboea. The
degree of certainty in our understanding of whether or not there is a cleruchy
near Karystos will influence our understanding of the texts which originally
motivated the hypothesis. It will add meaning to the figures of the Athenian
Tribute Lists and assist in interpreting the ancient authors. In this way, a
dialectic of assistance between textual and material records is established to
take advantage of the independence of the two sources of information. As
Leone and Potter suggest each source can be profitably used in the role of
middle-range theory for the other. It is a back-and-forth sort of negotiation
between the historical and archaeological claims. Reading the texts will suggest
an interpretation of the material data (as the reading of Diodorus and Plutarch
motivated the hypothesis that the Paximadhi sites were part of a cleruchy), and
in turn the archaeological evidence may influence an interpretation of texts.
(The dating of the Palio Pithari site makes it less likely that the Euboea
described in the sending of cleruchs to Andros, Naxos, and Euboea was
southern Euboea. Or perhaps Diodorus, Plutarch, and Pausanias got the whole
thing wrong and there were no cleruchs at all.) Thus the theory of Euboean
cleruchs can participate with middle-range theories in other circumstances. So
too with the evidential claims discussed in this case, for example the pottery
catalogue. What is an accomplishment on this project can be a tool on
another.
The point in presenting these details of evidence in the test of the cleruchy
hypothesis is simply to show that in this test-case the middle-range theories,
the accounting theories, are at work and can be identified and talked about.
They are the required informational links between the archaeological record,
the data, and the events and objects of the past which are relevant to the
hypothesis and are the evidence. They are what you have to know to make the
connection between what is on the ground and the objects and events of
interest, that is, those things which make contact with the theory being tested.
Furthermore the example shows that the middle-range theories are simply
theoretical accomplishments from other concerns. They endure their own trial
by evidence and must stand by their own justification.
5. Summary and Generalizations
This paper began with some predictions about the nature of archaeological
and scientific evidence, predictions based on a conceptual argument. Claims
Middle-Range
183
about the unobserved require evidence of the unobserved, and this in turn calls
for connections between the data of observation and these evidential claims
about phenomena. Claims about these connections are theoretical claims in the
sense of being descriptive of unobservable events and objects. To account for
the formation of the observed data, to show what the data mean with respect
to the hypothesis, requires some mention of what is going on behind the
scenes. In this sense there must be middle-range theorizing. The prediction is
that all evidence will be made meaningful and credible with the support of
middle-range theories.
This prediction has been put to the test by evidence from historical archaeology. The analysis showed that middle-range theories are at work and can be
articulated. Furthermore, they are not of a special kind of theory. Any theory
could be used in the role of middle-range and in the examples we have caught
the theoretical accomplishments of one context in the act of accounting for the
evidence in another. And finally, these accounting theories are not, as the idea
of middle-range is sometimes interpreted, of middling generality. Some
accounting claims are very general, as about physical interactions, while others
are specific as about a particular detector or a particular ancient author. This
distinguishes Binfords use, and the use here, of the label middle-range theory
from alternative applications by, for example, Schaffe34 who means exactly
theories of mid-generality, regardless of their use.
The philosophical point in all of this is not to show that archaeology makes
hypotheses and tests them against the evidence as is the practice in natural
sciences. The point is rather about the evidence used in this process and, for
that matter, in any process of acquiring knowledge beyond the manifest. The
evidence will be influenced by theory and the influencing theories can be
articulated. And insofar as we can insist on independence between these
influencing theories and the object theory, the hypothesis, the evidence will be
objective and the testing will be meaningful. Thus it is not that we rely on only
the best theories to account for the evidence, if by best is implied some
dispensation from doubt. We rely on regular old theories, themselves part of
the web of scientific beliefs. The examples show that beliefs which give
meaning to the observations are themselves part of the network, and their
epistemic contribution does not come from some epistemic priority but from
an epistemic independence.
Acknowledgements - I am
Southern Euboea Exploration
of the
Project, Don Keller, Cynthia Kosso, Roz Schneider and
*See K. Schaffer, Theory Structure in the Biochemical Sciences, The Journal of Medicine and
Philosophy 5 (1980), 57-95.
184
Mac Wallace, for their help toward my understanding and enjoying archaeology, and
for letting me carry the zambilis.
The conclusions expressed in this paper, such as the status of the cleruchy hypothesis
in light of the current evidence or the ambiguity of certain evidence, are entirely my own
and do not necessarily match the views of the archaeologists of the Southern Euboea
Exploration Project.
My work has been supported by a grant from the National Science Foundation,
number DIR-8917989.