Moretti The Comfort of Civilization PDF
Moretti The Comfort of Civilization PDF
Moretti The Comfort of Civilization PDF
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
University of California Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Representations.
http://www.jstor.org
FRANCO
MORETTI
A CERTAIN
MAGNETISM
REPRESENTATIONS
OF CALIFORNIA
115
REPRESENTATIONS
REPRESENTATIONS
He is to cultivate
individualcapabilities
so as to becomeuseful,and itis alreadypresupposed thatthereis no harmonyin hismannerof existencenorcan therebe, becausehe
is obligedtomakehimself
usefulinone direction
and must,therefore,
neglecteverything
else.(WM5.3)
Only if the individual renounces the bourgeois who dwells withinhim will
he be able to become an harmonious entity,be "fulland happy."Only then will
he feel that he again "belongs" to his world, and only then will the strifethat
pervades the modern age be at an end. For the aestheticutopia is a socialutopia:
and Reasonimplantsocialprinciples
in him,
Thoughneed maydriveMan intosociety,
intosociety,
Beautyalonecanconferon hima socialcharacter.
Tastealonebringsharmony
becauseitestablishes
dividea
harmonyin theindividual.All otherformsof perception
part
man,becausetheyare exclusively
basedeitheron thesensuousor on theintellectual
ofhisbeing;onlytheperception
oftheBeautifulmakessomething
wholeofhim,because
bothhisnaturesmustaccordwithit.5
Schiller is wishinghere for the advent of a "social" society,spontaneously
cohesive,devoid of lacerationsand strife.It is for thisend that "beauty,""play,"
and "art" are necessary.And yet,it is clear,these cannot reallymodifythe functioningof the great, alienated social mechanisms: the "mechanical" state,proaesthetic
ductionforprofit.To bringharmony"to the individualand to society,"
education followsa more indirectand elusive strategy.Instead of directlyconfrontingthe great powers of social life, it creates a new realm of existence in
which those abstractand deformingforces penetrate less violentlyand can be
reconstitutedin syntonywith the individual aspiration toward harmony.This
realm is organized accordingto thedictatesof "beauty"and "play"; it is pervaded
with the "happiness" of the individual; and the Bildungsroman
is its narrative
explication.Fine. As always,however,when one is dealing withutopias,the question arises: whereexactlyis the realm of aestheticharmony to be located? Furthermore,whichaspectsof modern lifehas iteffectively
involvedand organized?
The Art of Living
A fairlysimple and reasonable answercan be offeredfor these questions.Schiller'saesthetic"sociableness,"likeHumboldt'sartistic"work;'represents
in fact the precapitalistcommunityand its craftsmanship;just as typicallyprebourgeois is the idea-dealt withat lengthby WernerSombart-that man is "the
meteyard of all things."6The notorious "Deutsche misere" corroborates this
hypothesis,whichcontainswithouta doubt much of the truth.The allure of On
Meisterwould thereforebe born, in
theAesthetic
EducationofMan or of Wilhelm
large measure, of the regretfor a lost harmony.As likelyas thisseems, I would
like to propose here a differenttype of historicalinterpretation:that aesthetic
organicity,and the happiness that comes withit, belong not only to a past that
The Comfortof Civilization 1 19
REPRESENTATIONS
It is theindividualities-particularly
thosemostdevelopedindividualities
... towhomwe
shallreferas representative
individuals-who
theevolutionary
individually
incorporate
generic
apex ofa givensociety.'0
These greatmen, Hegel had written,seem to followonlytheirpassions,their
freewill,but what theywant is the universal,and thisis theirpathos."
Consequently:
It wasnotunhappinesstheychosebutexertion,
and laborin theserviceoftheir
conflict,
end. Andevenwhentheyreachedtheirgoal,peacefulenjoyment
and happinesswasnot
theirlot.Their actionsare theirentirebeing.... Whentheirend is attained,theyfall
asidelikeemptyhusks.Theymayhaveundergonegreatdifficulties
inordertoaccomplish
theirpurpose,butas soon as theyhavedone so, theydie earlylikeAlexander,
are murdered likeCaesar,or deportedlikeNapoleon.... The fearfulconsolation[is] thatthe
12
greatmenof history
did notenjoywhatis calledhappiness.
To use once again Schiller'sterminology:these individualsmay be "advantageous to the species" but theyare not "fulland happy" men. They are "representatives,"
for Heller, "of the evolutionarygenericapex of a given society,"
of
its major historicalturningsand acquisitions.But preciselyfor thisreason they
are notrepresentativesof those times"of ordinaryadministration"that,we will
see, constitutethe privilegedhistoricalbackdrop of the novel, especiallyof the
13 Here the "representativeindividual"does not want "exertion,
Bildungsroman.
conflict,and labor in the serviceof theirend": thesestruggleswilltakeplace (and
in an extremelyproblematicway) only in Stendhal, whose heroes, not without
reason, are takenin by the "world-historical"
model of Napoleon; theythus give
life to a narrativeplot whose typicalevent is a clash withthe existingorder. But
the hero of theBildungsroman,
like Heller's "particular,""wantsa lifefreeofconflict,
wants to feel at ease in the world as it is."14 His compass is personal happiness,
and the plot that will permit him to realize it will follow the model of organic
integration:
the polar opposite of the conflictualplot.
Although theyare differentin many ways,the studies of Lefebvre,Kosik,
and Heller neverthelessall converge toward a single goal, the formulationof a
critiqueof everydaylife. They want to "disalienate"it,reveal itswretchednessor
transience,unmask the "happiness" itpromisesas somethingmean or imaginary.
In doing this,all threeoppose it,more or less echoing Hegel, withthe great and
revolutionarymarchof universalhistory,and therecan be no doubt that,against
such a backdrop, thishappiness seems a trulypoor and fragileentity.
Furtheralong,in discussingthe stanceof theBildungsroman
towardthe French
revolution,we too will finda particularlylucid example of the alteritybetween
the two spheres of life.A difficulty
remains,however:the viewpointof universal
history,on whichthe critiqueof everydayliferests,is certainlynot the only one
possible,and above all it is nottheone assumedbynovelistic
form.Not blind to the
The Comfortof Civilization 121
REPRESENTATIONS
the home,where most of everydaylife takes place. Moreover,it raids all sortsof
aesthetic material to constructwhat will be the typicalhousehold of modern
times.In Meisterthe"harmoniousobjects"par excellence,
thosethatmake theworld
an inviting"homeland,"are preciselyhomes, and thisis even more true forPride
and Prejudice.The crucial episode, here, is Elizabeth Bennett'svisitto Pemberley,
Darcy'scountryresidence. Pemberleyis open to the public: it is a monumentof
"beauty"fortheadmirationof outsiders.But thereis nothingmuseum-likeabout
it,and the reactionit arouses in Elizabeth certainlyis not "aesthetic."On seeing
Pemberley,she instead thinksof Darcy for the firsttimeas a possible husbandnot because of ambitionor avarice,but because Pemberleyrevealsthatthe everyday-domestic-life ofa man likeDarcycan preciselybe somethingvery"beautiful"
Beautiful?Not exactly.Jane Austen, who chose her words with legendary
precision,attributesthe adjective beautifulonly to the "natural" beauty of the
estate. The house, the rooms, and the furnitureare not "beautiful"-they are
"handsome."A termthatindicatesa "decorous" and "balanced" beauty,"without
harshness,""comfortable"(as the etymologyitselfsuggests).A beauty,in a word,
of human proportions.Repeated threetimesin a page to indicateobjects,handsomereappears a page later-four timesin ten lines!-to designate Darcy.
"Handsome": a beauty that is not in the least threateningor disconcerting,
not in the least autonomous. It envelops the ideal of a golden mean, of a clear
and reciprocal translatability
between the individual and his context. It is the
miracle of eighteenth-century
"taste"-of the "artisticperiod" that literaryhistoriographysees as ending withGoethe'sdeath. An "artistic"period not because
markedby a matchlessaestheticproduction,but because art stillseems withinit
to form a whole with "life."With the life of the social elite, of course, which
becomes ever more broad and rich,while artisticproduction (especially architecture and painting but also music), which has not yet installed itselfin the
"marketplace,"remains in good part within the bounds and rhythmsof that
existence. The two spheres thus achieve a "natural" fusion,withoutsuffering
any resultingdisgrace or deformation.
It is the miracle,we have said, of eighteenth-century
taste.To associate such
a fusionwithbad tastemightseem a gratuitousslap in the face: in the end, when
a musicalcigarettecase playsMozart'sserenade,somethinghas changed.Grantedbut the pointis thatthe kitschthatwillengulfthe followingcentury-and which
is already leering in the castle episode in Meisteror in the Rosing chapters of
Pride and Prejudice-is not distinguishedfrom neoclassical tastebecause it has
betrayeditsaspirationsbut because ithas remained faithfulto themin a historical
contextthathas by now changed too radically.And what has especiallychanged
is the position and self-knowledgeof the aestheticsphere: "My dear Fraulein,"
observesthe musicianKlesmerin George Eliot'sDaniel Deronda,"you have develcould still
of the salon."This Standpunkt
oped yourqualities fromthe Standpunkt
The Comfortof Civilization 123
REPRESENTATIONS
psychic
unitywhichdependson butdoesnotcoincidewiththem.Ourconsciousendeavors
aim towardsparticularinterests
and potentialities.
The development
of everyhuman
being,whenitis examinedin termsof identifiable
items,appearsas a bundleof develdirections
and quitedifferent
opmentallineswhichexpandindifferent
lengths.Butman
butonlyinsofaras theyhelp
himself
doesnotcultivate
throughtheirisolatedperfections,
to develophis indefinable
personalunity.In otherwords:cultureis thewaythatleads
to theunfoldedunity.
fromtheclosedunitythroughtheunfoldedmultiplicity
towardssomething
This can referonlyto a development
prearrangedin the gersketched
out withinitself,
as a kindof idealplan.2'
minating
forcesof personality,
During the same yearsin whichSimmel was recapitulatingthisideal of individual culture-aware, likewise,that the development of capitalismand of the
metropoli had rendered it by then unattainable (and it is not by chance that
Lukacs was following
neitherplaya deciding role in theBildungsroman)-Gyorgy
an analogous path. The TheoryoftheNovel:
whichcomprehends
The contentofsuchmaturity
isan idealoffreehumanity
and affirms
thestructures
ofsociallifeas necessary
formsofhumancommunity,
yet,atthesametime,
onlyseesthemas an occasionfortheactiveexpressionof theessentiallifesubstance-in
notin theirrigidpoliticaland
otherwords,whichtakespossessionof thesestructures,
butas thenecessary
instruments
ofaimswhichgo farbeyond
legalbeing-for-themselves,
them....
be shownas a worldofconvention,
The socialworldmusttherefore
whichis partially
open to penetration
bylivingmeaning.
A new principleof heterogeneity
is therebyintroducedintothe outsideworld:a
hierarchy
ofthevariousstructures
and layersofstructures
accordingtotheirpenetrability
is irrationaland incapableof beingrationalised;
and the
by meaning.This hierarchy
to thepossibility
of a
meaning,in thisparticular
case,is notobjectivebutis tantamount
itselfin action.22
personality
fulfilling
There is one point on whichLukaicsand Simmel seem particularlyto agree:
formodern "personality"to reach itsgoal in a professional
thatitis fairlydifficult
occupation alone, thatis to say,in work.Workhas become too fragmentedin its
nature and also too "objective:"too imperviousto "livingmeaning."Those who
devote themselvesto a modern professionmust give up theirown personality:
thus Max Weber,writingin the same years as Simmel and Lukaics.And in his
letteron the antithesisbetweenthe nobilityand thebourgeoisie,WilhelmMeister
likewisestates:
A bourgeoismayacquiremeritand withgreattroublecultivate
hismind,buthispersonhe maydo. (WM 5.3)
alityis lost,whatever
That this not happen, Meistersuggests that one turn to occupations at the
same timemore pliable and more integral:the "pedagogic" vocation,"aesthetic"
enjoyment-we willsee otherexamples shortly.But Meisteralso suggeststhatwe
willfindthe keyto modern personality,and to its sphere of everydayoperation,
not so much in specific"activities"but in a peculiar disposition
of thesoul. This
126
REPRESENTATIONS
infiltrates
littleby littleinto each occupation, ruminateson it, appraises it, and
assails it if it mustin its effortsto render it consonant withthe developmentof
the individual as an "unfolded unity."In this way we can trulysay withJean
Baudrillard thateverydaylife is a system
ofinterpretation;
the same holds true for
personality.Both are waysof "reshaping"the world,of perceivingand judging
it,accordingto human proportions.In the wordsof Lukacs quoted above, external realityacquires value according to the "possibilityof a personalityfulfilling
itselfin [it]."Whateverlies beyondthiscircleand cannotbe translatedinto"experience"becomes, conversely,"insignificant":
it does not attractthe eye,the novel
has no desire to tellit. It is,to paraphrase Sennett,"thefallof public perception":
an ethical-intellectual
nearsightednessthatblurs our image of the modern individual. Withoutit, however,everythingleads one to believe that the individual
would be difficultto imagine.
Trial, Opportunity,Episode
If we read Meister,or even betterPride and Prejudice,with a dose of
healthycriticalingenuity,sooner or later arises the inevitablequestion of what
preciselythe main charactersare "doing."Wernergives a response upon seeing
Wilhelmanew: "Look at him, how he stands! How it all suits and fitstogether!
How idlingmakesone flourish!"(WM 8.1). Yes,in the end Wilhelmand Elizabeth
but rather
engage in "idling."But this,we have seen, does not mean doing nothing
means not entrustingthe definitionof one's personalityto any one activity.
We have here a furtherconvergencebetweenthe particularitiesof everyday
lifeand the categoriesof the theoryof the novel. By not defininghimselfin only
one sphere of life,the novelisticprotagonistceases to be definableas a "role"the "merchant"Werner,the "minister"Collins, the "mother" of the Bennett
sisters.He becomes instead,to echo Philippe Hamon, a "polyparadigmaticcharacter."That is to say,he becomes an entitydefined by various, heterogeneous
traitsthatmay even contradictone another.23
To explain the genesis of this"polyparadigmaticity,"
narrativetheoryusually
makes use of some conception of "realism."Somewhere along the line we learn
to representexistencein a more "faithful"way.If thisis true, however,how do
we explain whysuch a multiplicity
of traitsalwaysapplies to a verysmall number
in
Another
of characters a novel?
explanation is needed. Perhaps by puttinga
polyparadigmaticcharacterat the center of a story,every event becomes autoEach eventdrawsitsmeaningthrough
maticallyattractedintotheorbitof'personality.
its reflectionat the other levels of Wilhelmand Elizabeth'sexistence,fromthe
internalharmonythatit helps to bind or crack.
It is thereforenot a question of representingthingsor people in a more
truthful
waybut of deciding thata certain aspect of existenceis more meaningful
The Comfortof Civilization 127
than others and can consequentlyhave a special functionin the story'sorganization-a "central"functionthatputs the narrationinto perspectivewhereinthe
plot has its center,in fact,in the multilateraldevelopment of the protagonist.
This "focused" perceptionof a structureis preciselythe image of social relationthatis the point of departure and
ships mostconsonantwiththe anthropocentrism
arrivalof everydaylife.
But plot is still,nevertheless,a diachronicsuccession of events. How do we
reconcile our spatial metaphors of "centrality"and "focus;"which transmitan
idea of equilibriumand harmony,witha temporaldimensionthatimplieschange
and instability?In other words: how do we reconcile a novelistic
plot, which is
uncertainand gripping,withthe familiarand pleasing rhythmof everydaylife?
Withthe rhythmof "ordinaryadministration"?
Perhaps we can start by observing that the "ordinary"course of modern
everydaylife does not coincide, as at firstsightwould appear inevitable,with
banality,inertia,and repetition.Lefebvre,who initiallyheld this position,had
later to writea few hundred pages to refuteit.24More concisely,Karel Kosik:
The everyday
has itsexperienceand wisdom,itssophistication,
itsforecasting.
It has its
butalso itsspecialoccasions,itsroutinebutalso itsfestivity.
replicability
The everyday
is
to theunusual,thefestive,
thespecial,or to History:hyposthusnotmeantas a contrast
as a routineoverHistory,
as theexceptional,
theeveryday
is itselftheresult
of a
tatizing
certainmystification.25
Kosik is right.Modern everydaylife is no longer reducible to a mere repetitionof prescribed,"uneventful,"narrativelyinsignificant
eventsthat therefore
do not meritbeing related.The interventionof personalityhas brokendown the
rigid barrierbetween"workday"monotonyand "holiday"exception:
One dayin winter,
as I camehome,mymother,
seeingthatI wascold,offeredme some
take.I declinedatfirst,
and then,forno particular
tea,a thingI did notordinarily
reason,
changedmymind.She sentout forone of thoseshort,plumplittlecakescalled'petites
madeleines'. . .
In thisall too familiarexample fromProust,the graynessof modern everyday life is seen to preserve withinitselfthe "Sunday mornings"of childhood
("and all the flowersin our garden and in M. Swann's park, and the water-lilies
on the Vivonne and the good folkof the villageand theirlittledwellingsand the
parishchurchand the whole of Combray"),onlyto returnthemto us at the most
insignificant
moments,fromthe depths "of mycup of tea."And the spark of the
entire process is preciselythe work,voluntaryor not, of personality,which the
novel uses to bringto lifea sortof temporalthirddimension,withever-expanding confines,in whichnothingcan be declared a priorias entirelywithoutsignificance,and nothingas absolutelysignificant.Nothingis mere repetition;nothing
128
REPRESENTATIONS
REPRESENTATIONS
and thus again is differentfromthe short storyor tragedy-that one does not
get in too "deep," for if no episode in itselfis immune to meaning, no episode,
on the otherhand, can containthe entiremeaning of existence.No characterwill
ever entirelyreveal his essence in a single gestureor encounter.(Elizabeth Bennett,by forcingin thisway her interpretationof Darcy,therebyrisksdestroying
her "novel.")28
mustovercome consists
The "trial"thatthe protagonistof theBildungsroman
thus in accepting the defermentof the ultimatemeaning of his existence. It is
thenew pedagogical ideal of theeighteenthcentury,whichsubstitutesadmiration
forprecocitywiththe image of a gradual growth,a fewsteps at a time.29For this
to happen-and Rousseau returnsconstantlyto this point in Emile-one must
firstof all learn to controlthe imagination,whichis at the originof thetwoerrors
thatcan lead us astrayfromthe path toward"maturity."
Restlessness,firstof all,
the "ramblingthoughts"of Robinson Crusoe, makes man too much of a wanderer,too detached fromhis environment,therebypreventinghim fromextracting all the potentialmeaningitcontains.But even more thanrestlessness,intensity
compels him to see an excessof meaning in those thingsaround him and to bind
himselfto them too thoroughlyand too quickly.Prematurely:in ways that are
not those of an "adult."
The middle road of the hero of the Bildungsroman
is lined withcharacters
who err in the opposite directions.Restless characters,such as Lydia Bennett,
who are preyto futility;and intensecharacters,theirpatheticinnocence driving
them to a tragicend: Mariane, Aurelie, the Harpist. And, of course, Mignon.
The episode that decides her death-one of the most disagreeablycruel in all
of world literature-embodies withouthalf-tonesthe eighteenth-century
repudiation of premature and passionate desire (the episode takes the form of a
mysteryin 5.12 and is explained in 8.3). Mignon,one night,secretlyentersinto
Wilhelm'sbedroom, spurred on by a desire that she cannot yetwell define. She
hides and waitsforWilhelmto arrive,but Philine arrivesinstead,slips into bed,
as does Wilhelm,halfdrunk,momentslater.From her hidingplace, Mignon will
be the silentwitnessto the nightof love betweenthe two.
Not much can be said about the meaning of thisscene: it is such a veryclear
and banal "everythinghas its time and place." But it is a savage banality:when
Goethe shows us his philistineside he does absolutelynothingto appear affable.
In an episode like this we see the convex side of everydaylife: that part of it
whichfaces not the elect individualbut ratherthe outside world. Its conventions
seem so flexibleand inoffensive,almost withoutconfines-but only as long as
one remainswithinthem,and withina spiritualdispositionconsonantwiththem.
If one givesin to the flightof imagination,however,one thendiscoversthatthose
confinesdo indeed exist, and with a cuttingedge: but then it is too late. The
limbsthatare severed fromthe organism,in Meister,
can neverbe rejoined. That
most fervidand alive interiority,
because it is not yetobjectified,and perhaps is
The Comfortof Civilization 131
REPRESENTATIONS
all the more interesting-to use the flutegivento himby the Queen of the Night.
Uneasy surrogatesforwords,more "potent"than thembut tremendouslymore
enigmatic,the notes of the flutetell us that the crucial point in Tamino's trial
rests not so much on not emittingany sound, but on not emittingany sound
endowedwithmeaning.Either all language is renounced, or one is used thatis by
definitionasemantic.No "meaning" is given,or can be given,to the trial.It lies
beyond the realm of the verbal sphere and wants to remain outside of it. Conversely,language becomes "twaddle": it suits Papageno, not Tamino, and it will
never be an essentialstage in thejourney of formation.30
Those who are familiarwithMeisterand Prideand Prejudiceknow well that,
in these works,the paradigm is reversed. Here, if anything,one talkstoo much.
One talkstoo much: the formationof the individual,once seen withineveryday
life,involveslanguage primarilyas a tool of conversation.
A decisiveturningpoint
in Wilhelm'sBildungis when he abandons the "theatrical"rhetoricof impassioned
monologue forthe much more prosaic art of dialogue. Elizabeth and Darcy,for
theirpart, mustliterallylearn to talk to one another: only thus willtheybe able
to overcome those "embarrassingmomentsof silence" that mark and frustrate
theireveryencounter.
"To learn to talkto one another,"to talkto one another"sincerely."
These are
circumlocutionsto say that one must trustin language. In the magic circle of
everydaylife language in fact appears-as does work-as a sociablesocial institution. If one abandons oneself to it withoutreserve, the double operation of
"expressingoneself" and of "understandingothers"thenbecomes possible. One
willbe able, in otherwords,to reach an agreement:as everyconversationbeyond
a mere exchange of civilities(or of insults) presupposes the willingnessof the
participantsto abandon their own viewpointin order to embrace that of the
other.3'It is a secretinclination-just as strongin Goethe as in Jane Austen-to
separate conversationfrom that violent,noisy,and partial discussion that had
accompanied the formationof eighteenth-century
public opinion, a discussion
thattookplace in strictly
publicplaces-cafes, inns,postalcenters-and excluded
on principleall interestin and referenceto the privateconditionof the participants: each spoke only as a member of the public.32In comparison with this
historicalprecedent,conversationbringsthe linguisticexchange back to a more
domestic and "familiar"space. It is reserved for persons who know each other
well; one is not only not unaware of the personal import of one's words but
actuallystrivesto understandand giveworthto thatelement.Conversationseems,
more so than the "rational public debate" that Jurgen Habermas sees at the
foundation of public opinion, to lead back to the less demanding language of
"worldliness"-"se rendre agreable dans la societe"'-examined by Peter Brooks
in The Novel of Worldliness.33
It is as if the term conversation
were stillfaithfulto
The Comfortof Civilization 133
correct and severe decision about present things,but with this he had the mistakeof
whereas the verdictsof
expressingthese individualdecisions witha kind of universality,
134
REPRESENTATIONS
if
theintellect
haveforceonlyonceand thatin thedefinite
case,and wouldbe incorrect
one appliedthemto others.(WM5.1)
Here again is the anthropocentricvocationof everydaylifethat,withthe art
of conversation,subjugatesthe manifestationsof thoughtand draws fromthem
a plasticand pliable language, a refinedand inedited rhetoricof the "concrete."
The language and rhetoric,ifone thinksabout it,of the novel:the firstand only
literarygenre thatnot onlyhas chosen not to accentuateitsirreducibility
to what
we call "ordinarylanguage" but has even contributed,as littleelse has, to the
diffusionand nobilitationof the idea itselfof linguistic"normality"and to the
of thatmode of discoursewhichaims at continuallyconverting
makingmeaningful
the concrete into the abstractand vice versa. Once again it is that eighteenthcenturytastefor includingand harmonizing:the comfortof equilibrium.
If all this is contained in the conversationalform,what remains outside of
it? Or to put the problem in historicalterms,"against"what formof the manifestation
of thoughtdo Goetheand Austenconjureup theirmagnificent
dialogues?
The beginningsof an answercan be found in a memorable chapterof L'AncienRegimeetla Revolution:"How, towardsthe middle of the Eighteenthcentury,
men of lettershave become the mostimportantpoliticalmen in the country,and
of the consequences whichhave resulted."In these pages, Tocqueville reflectson
the peculiaritiesof the Enlightenmentintellectualin France: neither "mixed
up in everydayaffairsor administration,as in England, nor "as in Germany,
totallyextraneousto politics,confinedto the world of pure philosophyor of the
belleslettres."
The fact is that there emerges in France a new and explosive form of the
manifestationof thought. It is at once fundamentallyand stubbornlypolitical
("French intellectualscontinuallyare concerned withproblems connected with
the activitiesof government")and withoutrestrictionabstract
("All believe thatit
is good to substitutewith simple and elementaryrules, based on reason and
natural law, those complex customs sanctioned by traditionwhich govern our
society").
Given this,I would not exclude the notion thatthe relaxed and sturdylanguage of novelisticconversationhas its opposite not in silence but in the revolutionarypamphlet or oration. This is an antithesisthat brings with it many
others: the "curbing" earthiness of concretenessagainst the cold and daring
of the "I" in "you" against
universalismof principles;the dialogic convertibility
the rigid demarcation between orator and audience; the attentiontoward the
patient weaving of a plot against the urge to tear, the passion for "beginning
anew."Irreconcilable contraststhat tell us a common truth-everyday life and
revolutionare incompatible-and a littleless common truth: that this incomThe ComfortofCivilization 135
Notes
The followingpages are taken fromthe firstchapter of my TheProseoftheWorld,to
be published by Verso (London) in 1986. The book undertakes a reconstructionof
fromGoethe to Flaubert and George Eliot, seen as the
the European Bildungsroman,
mostsignificant
attempt,on the part of Westernculture,to come symbolically
to terms
withmodernity.An effortis made in the workto bringto lightconnectionsbetween
fieldsof research and spheres of life that are usually considered distantfrom one
another: narrativetheory,aestheticideology,nineteenth-century
philosophyof history,sociologyof everydaylife,historyof youth,the world of the metropolisand of
the capitalistmarketplace....
Concerningtheinternaldynamicsof the study:in the firstchapterthearchetypal
is examined in its "aesthetic"foundation,as formulated
model of the Bildungsroman
byGoethe and Jane Austen. In thesecond chaptertheworksof Stendhaland Pushkin
of politics,novelisticrhetoric,and
are discussed,especiallyregardingtheintertwining
aesthetic realism. The third chapter deals with the works of Balzac and Flaubert,
interpretedin thelightof ambiguous tensionsthatlinktheformationof theindividual
withcapitalistdevelopment. In the fourthchapter an effortis made to trace a particularlyEnglish traditionof the Bildungsroman-fromFielding to Scott, Charlotte
Bronte,and Dickens-concluding withthe revivaland exhaustionof Goethian problematicsin the worksof George Eliot.
1. "We are moved by the storyof a good deed and by the sightof every harmonious
object; we thenfeel thatwe are not quite in a strangecountry;we fondlyimagine that
we are nearer a home, towards which what is best and most inward withinus is
striving";Johann Wolfgangvon Goethe, Wilhelm
Meister,
trans.R. 0. Moon (London,
1947), book 7, chap. 1. All furtherreferencesto WilhelmMeister(hereafterWM)
appear in the text.
the madness of the Harpist:
2. It is throughworkthatone can cure, at least temporarily,
"I find the means of curing insanityvery simple. They are the same by which you
preventhealthypeople frombecominginsane. Their activityhas to be aroused, accustom them to order.... An active life bringswithit so many incidentsthat he must
feel how true it is thateverykind of doubt can be removed by activity"(WM 5.16).
136
REPRESENTATIONS
12. Ibid.
13. "Our comparison of novel and drama shows that the novel's manner of portrayalis
closerto life,or ratherto the normal appearance of life,than thatof drama"; Gyorgy
Lukacs, The HistoricalNovel, trans. H. and S. Mitchell (London, 1962), 138. That
thisaffirmation
refersto the historical
novel rendersit,in myopinion, more meaningful still.
14. Heller,Sociologia,66.
15. Ibid., 407-8.
16. Ibid., 408.
17. Abraham Moles, Il Kitsch:L'artedeltafelicitd,Italian trans. (Rome, 1979), 42-43, 46,
47, 53; originallypublished as Le Kitsch:L'Artdu bonheur(Paris, 1971).
18. I have discussed the ups and downs of the aestheticdimension in twentieth-century
life in "From the Waste Land to the ArtificialParadise," in Signs Takenfor Wonders
(London, 1983).
19. Philippe Aries,Padriefiglinell'Europamedievalee moderna,Italian trans. (Bari, 1976),
trans.R. Baldick (New York,
282-83; published in English as Centuries
ofChildhood,
1962).
20. Richard Sennett,TheFall ofPublicMan (New York, 1977).
21. Georg Simmel, "On the Concept and Tragedy of Culture,"in The Conflict
in Modern
Cultureand OtherEssays,trans.K. P. Etzkorn(New York, 1968), 27-46, esp. 28 - 29.
22. GyorgyLukdcs, The TheoryoftheNovel,trans.A. Bostock (Cambridge, Mass., 1971),
133-34, 137-38.
23. The novelisticprotagonistcan no longer be presented as the hero of the classical
epic-shrewd Odysseus,fleet-footed
Achilles,wise Nestor.One's Christianname must
be, and is, enough-"Wilhelm," "Elizabeth."Such a mannerof namingdenotes a great
and thus suggestsa complete and almost "natural"knowledgeof the perfamiliarity
son in question,but it above all gives to our knowledge,as it were,the utmostliberty,
neither constrainingit, leading it in a precise direction nor binding it to a clearly
defined subject. It is a "knowledge" that combines a maximum of certaintywith a
minimumof commitment.It is so open and inexhaustiblethatit can never trulybe
put to a test.What happens withnovelisticheroes is what happens withour friends
and relatives:we know them,while we do not know who theyare.
24. "One of the more recentformsof the critiqueof everydaylifehas been the critique
of the real via the surreal.Surrealism,in departing from the everydaytoward the
extraordinaryand the surprising. . . rendered the prosaic unsupportable."Furthermore: "Under the sign of the Supernatural,the literatureof the nineteenthcentury
launched an attackagainst everydaylife thathas not lost any of its force"; Lefebvre,
Critica,34 and 122.
25. Kosik, "Metaphysicsof EverydayLife,"43.
26. "A complete scheme of ritesof passage theoreticallyincludespreliminal
rites(ritesof
rites(ritesof incorporaseparation),liminalrites(ritesof transition),and postliminal
tion)"; thusArnold Van Gennep in his classicanalysisof primitiveinitiation,TheRites
ofPassage, trans. M. Vizedom and G. Caffee (Chicago, 1960), 11. The "transition"
space, oftenassociated withyouth,is seen to be verynarrow,severelyregulated,and
merelyfunctionalto the passage fromthe infantileaggregationto theadult one. Once
thispassage is complete,the "transition"space loses all value. The patternis stillfully
valid forTheMagicFlute,but itshierarchyis unequivocallyoverturnedin Meister.
Here
the "transition"of youthis vastlyexpanded; one lives in it in complete liberty,and,
above all, it is transformedinto the mostmeaningful
part of one's existence,precisely
thatone which"meritsbeing told."We findan analogous overturningin the relationship betweenthose typicalperiods of transitionknownas courtship,engagement,and
marriage. In archaic societies courtship and engagement chronologicallyprecede
marrigebut,froma logical standpoint,are a consequence of it: one mustget married,
and thereforeone mustfirstget engaged, but the value of courtshipand engagement
ends here; theyare purelyinstrumental.In the modern world,and in the novel, the
opposite is true. Marriage is the consequence of a satisfyingcourtshipand engageendswithmarriages,itneverthelessnarrates
ment,and ifthereforetheBildungsroman
courtships.The emotiveand intellectualcenterof gravityhas decidedlychanged.
27. Thus Wilhelmto the "gentlemanfromC." who is about to leave for war (Theatrical
Mission,4.1 1): "Oh how fortunateyou are to be lead by destinyto where a true man
can call upon his best powers, where all that he has become in life,all that he has
learned is changed in a moment'stimeintoactionand appears in itsutmostsplendor!"
Needless to say,the gentlemanfromC. sees itin a totallydifferentway,and his answer
chillsWilhelm'sepic enthusiasms.
28. This dialecticof meaning and episode is the basis of the novelisticchapterAn extraorof a text,the chaptersetsup a balance between
dinarymechanismof self-segmentation
our satisfactionwithwhat we have learned (the meaning thathas been attributedto
an event) and our curiosityfor what we stilldo not know (that meaning is as a rule
alwaysincomplete).We can thus continueour reading (givingin to our curiosity)or
interruptit (declaring ourselves satisfied).The narrativestructureauthorizesboth
choices and therebyrenders symbolicallyplausible the irregularrhythmof interruptionsand resumptionsto whichthereader is in anycase constrainedbythedimensions
themselvesof a novel.
Thanks to thistruemiracleof self-regulation
thatis thechapter,thenovel imparts
to literaryenjoymenta totallyunique character,which Poe in his Philosophy
of Com"If any work is too long to be read at one sitting,we
positionfound self-destructive:
mustbe contentto dispense withthe immenselyimportanteffectderivablefromunity
of impression-for, if two sittingsbe required,the affairsof the world interfere,and
eveythinglike totalityis at once destroyed";in SelectedWritings
ofEdgar AllanPoe, ed.
David Galloway(Harmondsworth,Eng., 1967), 482. What Poe did not manage to see
is that the novel quite simplywantsthe affairsof the world to interfere.Unlike the
138
REPRESENTATIONS
29.
30.
31.
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.