Give A Man A Fish by James Ferguson
Give A Man A Fish by James Ferguson
Give A Man A Fish by James Ferguson
man
a fish
Introduction.
Cash Transfers and the New Welfare States
From Neoliberalism to the Politics of Distribution 1
3. Distributed Livelihoods
Dependence and the Labor of Distribution in the Lives
of the Southern African Poor (and Not-So-Poor) 89
5. Declarations of Dependence
Labor, Personhood, and Welfare in Southern Africa 141
6. A Rightful Share
Distribution beyond Gift and Market 165
Conclusion.
What Next for Distributive Politics? 191
Notes 217
References 237
Index 259
Foreword
viii foreword
main goals of social life. Proposals like the basic income grant seek to
scale this sort of morality up to the level of the nation-state and beyond.
Just as previous studies by anthropologists of actually existing forms
rather than of ideal models of capitalism and socialism provoked politi-
cal economists to think about the role of markets and planning in a new
way, Ferguson’s study of the actually existing forms of mutuality that are
emerging across the global South should provoke political activists to
think about social justice in a new way. The book seeks to go beyond the
now-familiar critiques of neoliberal capitalism and open up a new debate
about what a better future might look like for us all. In doing so, it re-
mains true to the radical spirit of anthropology that Lewis Henry Morgan
himself practiced.
Thomas Gibson
Editor, Lewis Henry Morgan Monograph Series
foreword ix
Preface and Acknowledgments
2 introduction
similar major nationwide programs in Botswana and Namibia, along
with smaller ones in Lesotho, Swaziland, and Mozambique, as well as
pilot and regional programs (intended to soon be scaled up to the nation-
wide level) in Malawi, Zambia, and Zimbabwe.5
Southern Africa (and especially South Africa) has sometimes been seen
not only as an instance of neoliberalism but even as a paradigmatic case
of it (see, e.g., Klein 2008). And if neoliberalism is, as some accounts have
(rather Eurocentrically) tended to suggest, first and foremost a worldwide
project centered on the erosion, rollback, or downsizing of the Keynes-
ian “social” states that dominated the post–World War II (Western) world
(see, e.g., Harvey 2007), it seems clear enough in what direction “neo-
liberal” southern Africa must be headed: toward the heartless world of
neoliberal capitalism, in which the welfare state withers while the poor
are ever more exposed to the depredations of “the market.” With the is-
sues framed in this way, even the most astute of the region’s many critical
observers have sometimes paid less attention than they should have to a
remarkable set of events in the region, events that have in fact led to sus-
tained expansions (rather than reductions) in programs of social assistance
and indeed to the emergence of what could reasonably be described as a new
kind of welfare state. And while many influential accounts of neoliberal-
ism have seen only ever-growing social exclusion, we here must also take
stock of a new kind of inclusion as millions of poor citizens previously
ignored or worse by the state have become direct beneficiaries of cash
payments.6
The most influential critical accounts of neoliberalism in southern
Africa center on the region’s economic core, South Africa, so it is impor-
tant briefly to review how such accounts understand South Africa’s post-
apartheid transition and the economic changes that came in its wake. As
the story is generally told, the African National Congress (anc) party
that took the reins of government after the 1994 transition, having aban-
doned its old commitments to socialist economic transformation, opted
for what Patrick Bond (2005, 6) has termed a “homegrown” structural ad-
justment program, yielding without much of a fight to the World Bank/
imf orthodoxy of the time that called for the opening up of markets (via
deregulation and privatization), in the hopes of making the new South
Africa an attractive destination for international capital investment. Fol-
lowing a brief and transitional commitment to a “Reconstruction and
4 introduction
named “neoliberalism.” The result is a strange state of affairs in which
nearly every intellectual and politician in South Africa today condemns
“neoliberalism” but no major political parties have emerged advocating
any very substantially different policy path (at least until very recently).10
The second problem is not unrelated. It is that the now-standard criti-
cal accounts of South Africa’s “neoliberalism” fail to attend to the very
substantial ways in which that country (pioneering a path for many of its
neighbors) has taken a turn that, in some respects at least, seems almost
the opposite of the standard neoliberal model: that is, by elaborating an
enormous system of non-contributory social benefits that today trans-
fers 3.4 percent of the nation’s gdp directly to “the poor” via non-market
cash payments that are now received by more than 30 percent of the entire
population (National Treasury 2013, 84–86).
It seems clear that this development was the product of a quite partic-
ular conjuncture. For it was at just the moment that the post-apartheid
anc regime came to power, with a mandate to transform the economic
conditions of the poor and working-class people who made up its po-
litical base, that a worldwide economic restructuring undermined the
low-wage employment that had long provided the entire region with
its economic core. (On the brutally abrupt collapse of labor markets for
low-wage and low-skilled labor, see Seekings and Nattrass 2005; Marais
2011.) Facing the pressing political need to deliver concrete changes to
the new black political majority, and with “pro-market” economic poli-
cies failing to yield the rapid economic growth that had been supposed to
“lift all boats,” social protection became a key domain of policy innova-
tion. South Africa and several of its neighbors had long had quite well-
developed social welfare systems for whites, but provisioning for blacks
was rudimentary at best (see chapter 2). As part of the transition to the
new, post-apartheid regime, pension rates were equalized across racial
groups, and social assistance rapidly became of much greater economic
value for the majority populations. At the same time, a decision was made
to implement a substantial new nationwide cash benefit for those caring
for small children. Similar programs were soon taken up by neighboring
countries Namibia and (to a lesser extent) Botswana, and the range of ben-
eficiaries was rapidly expanded (in South Africa, the age limit for a child’s
eligibility was gradually raised from seven in 1998 to the current age limit
of eighteen).11 The rapid growth of such programs responded not only
6 introduction
as widely distributed (yet) as in South Africa, but here too both expendi-
tures and the number of recipients have expanded rapidly in recent years.
As of 2008, some 12 percent of Namibia’s total population were receiving
social grants (Levine, Van der Berg, and Yu 2009; Garcia and Moore 2012,
287–90). Botswana also has a comprehensive non-contributory old age
pension system as well as a major program providing cash payments to
those caring for orphaned children—no small thing in a country where
some 15 percent of all children are reckoned to be orphans (Dahl 2009).
Social protection schemes are less developed in other southern African
countries, but the successes of the South African model have inspired
even the poorest states in the region to attempt to emulate it, albeit with
much lower levels of benefits. Swaziland, for instance, now has a univer-
sal old age pension, and even Lesotho (long widely regarded as lacking
the financial means to attempt any sort of social protection) introduced a
modest old age pension in 2004 and is now developing a program of child
care grants (Garcia and Moore 2012, 264).
It is now well documented that these programs, in their own terms,
“work.” For South Africa, where the programs have been studied most
intensively and for the longest time, a robust consensus now exists
that, as one recent evaluation study put it, “South Africa’s social grants
have been extremely successful at reducing poverty” (dsd, sassa, and
unicef 2012, 3; see also the authoritative overview of the evidence in
Neves et al. 2009). According to a recent national survey, the percentage
of households that reported experiencing hunger decreased from 29.3
percent to 12.6 percent between 2002 and 2012 (Statistics South Africa
2012, 4). A recent comprehensive evaluation of the Child Support Grant
program concluded that it clearly yielded “positive developmental im-
pact” not only in nutrition but also in educational and health outcomes
while at the same time providing some protection to adolescent recipi-
ents from “risky behaviors” in the context of the high hiv prevalence. A
recent survey of living standards (based not on reported income but on
concrete lifestyle markers such as the presence of running water or flush
toilets and ownership of key goods and appliances) found that the pro-
portion of South African adults falling into the lowest of ten categories
for living standards had fallen from 11 percent of the population in 2001
to just 1 percent in 2011.13 Major declines were also found in the other low-
est categories, along with substantial rises in proportions occupying the
It is not only quantitative surveys that attest to the efficacy and impor-
tance of the expanded programs of cash transfer. Among the scores of ex-
perts and ethnographic researchers whom I have consulted in the course
of this project, many with very long and intimate familiarity with the so-
cial realities of the region’s poverty, none doubted that social grants are
playing an absolutely vital role in sustaining poor households and com-
munities and in preventing the worst sorts of destitution. When I asked
one such highly knowledgeable researcher what South Africa would be
like without the grants, he paused before replying simply, “Apocalyptic.
Off the chart.”
In Namibia, social protection programs have been less well studied
and assessed, but what data is available suggests that the effects of the
programs have been broadly similar to those in South Africa. A recent
overview found that these schemes are making “a substantial and grow-
ing contribution to poverty reduction” and concluded that social cash
transfers have lowered the number of “poor” individuals by 10 percent
and the “very poor” by 22 percent (Levine, Van der Berg, and Yu 2009,
49, 50). The report also finds the programs to be broadly sustainable in
fiscal terms, projecting a gradual reduction in social grant expenditures
(as a percentage of gdp), since gdp growth is expected to outpace the
projected growth in number of recipients (Leving, Van der Berg, and Yu
2009, 42, 45).
Not surprisingly, these programs have been generally popular among
those receiving the cash payments.15 What is perhaps more surprising
is that a broad acceptance of these programs appears to extend across
nearly the whole range of society, with feelings about the legitimacy of
8 introduction
public assistance quite widely shared across both class and race divides.
Jeremy Seekings has shown that, when asked about both specific social
assistance programs and a range of scenarios in which a person in a
certain situation might or might not “deserve” government assistance,
South Africans of different races proved to have surprisingly similar views
(Seekings 2008c). At least in South Africa (and thanks to a history that
I trace in chapter 2), it seems to be broadly accepted that it is a normal
and proper part of the mission of the state to issue monthly cash pay-
ments to a wide range of people deemed to be in need. Indeed, despite
their substantial size and cost, the programs of social grants that I have
described here are not a particularly contentious or embattled feature of
the political landscape in any of the countries I have reviewed here. To my
knowledge, in fact, no major political party has ever proposed eliminat-
ing them, or even reducing their amounts.
How did this come about? In South Africa, especially, it is very clear
that the original ambition of the post-apartheid regime was hardly to
create a welfare state catering to those excluded from the world of wage
labor. Its first political imperative, on the contrary, was to generate jobs
and to improve the condition of workers. The anc, of course, had its in-
tellectual roots on the political Left, and it has governed from the start as
part of a “tripartite alliance” linking it with the powerful trade union fed-
eration cosatu and the South African Communist Party. Partly for this
reason, a high value has long been placed on labor as the central mode of
social incorporation, and on “the workers” as the figuration of those to
whom the government must answer (see Barchiesi 2011). But in the con-
text of new economic realities, as the country went through a wrenching
economic restructuring that shed jobs as much as it created them, more
and more of the population looked to government as a direct provider
and provisioner. “Ser vice delivery” was the new slogan, and increasingly
black South Africans sought their “liberation” in the form of direct state
provision of such goods as housing, electricity, water, sanitation, and
social ser vices. “Ser vice delivery protests,” indeed, became a familiar
feature of everyday life in poor and working-class neighborhoods across
the country. In this context, a patchwork of older programs of social as-
sistance (inherited from the apartheid regime and newly deracialized)
provided the starting point for the development of a vast institutional ap-
paratus that would make it possible for the new state to provide highly
10 introduction
only those directly employed by capitalists who were exploited by capital-
ism. People from the poor rural peripheries of the southern African po-
litical economy, even if not directly employed, were not at all marginal to
the production system. On the contrary, thanks to the role they played in
the reproduction of labor, they were in fact central to the massive produc-
tion of wealth that was occurring at the industrial centers of this regional
system. This was an analytical claim (i.e., that even the region’s most pe-
ripheral people and locales were in fact vital for capitalism, “reproduc-
ing the labor force”) that contained embedded within it both a functional
imperative (“social reproduction” could only take place via the provision
of at least some minimal “social wage” enabling it) and an ethical claim
(those who were helping to generate wealth were also entitled to share
in it).
But the developments of recent years force us to question the logic
that allowed an earlier generation of critics to link the productivity of
the industrial economy to the entire society in such a direct and com-
pelling way. In a labor-scarce political economy, even the most remote
rural reaches of the southern African region could plausibly be under-
stood as providing vitally needed labor reserves for a vast and encom-
passing system of production. Today, however, a restructured capitalism
has ever less need for the ready supply of low-wage, low-skilled laborers
that the migrant labor system generated. As Tania Li (2010) has argued in
an Asian context, the marginalization and impoverishment of so many
today cannot be regarded as “a strategy of global capital” but is instead,
in her terms, “a sign of their very limited relevance to capital at any scale”
(2010, 67). This point was made to me most dramatically in the comment
of a South African social researcher with long experience working with
poor rural communities. “I wish this weren’t true,” he said, “but the fact
is that there are at least ten million people out there who could drop dead
tomorrow and the jse [Johannesburg Stock Exchange] wouldn’t register
so much as a ripple.”18
Under such circumstances, it has become more and more difficult to
argue that the value produced at the region’s industrial centers is gener-
ated by the suffering of those at its periphery; instead, the suffering of the
poor and marginalized appears as functionally isolated from a production
system that simply no longer has any use for them. And if such people in-
creasingly receive social payments, this cannot plausibly be understood as
12 introduction
sumption and thereby stimulating the economy (Soares et al. 2010; cf.
Lo Vuolo 2013). But what was once largely a Latin American phenom-
enon has gone global. A 2009 World Bank report traced the growth of
cash transfer programs across scores of countries worldwide, noting that
“countries have been adopting or considering adopting cct programs at
a prodigious rate” (2009, 1). Hanlon, Barrientos, and Hulme (2010) have
characterized this shift as a “development revolution from the global
South” and pointed to “a wave of new thinking” rooted in the conviction
that “it is better to give money to poor people directly so that they can
find effective ways to escape from poverty” (2010, 1). A recent literature
review done by the United Kingdom’s official development aid agency
identified the spread of cash transfers as a “quiet revolution” and noted
that such programs are now estimated to reach between 0.75 and 1 billion
people (dfid 2011, i).
Southern Africa, as I have noted, arrived at such programs via its own
route, and due to a unique history. But beyond southern Africa, social
protection schemes elsewhere on the continent were until recently ru-
dimentary or nonexistent. In fact, only a few years ago, social assistance
hardly seemed to be in the cards for a continent renowned for “weak
states” characterized by feeble fiscal capacity, bureaucratic dysfunction,
and widespread corruption. Yet in the wake of the much-touted success of
cash transfer programs elsewhere (and especially the examples in nearby
southern Africa), today there is an explosion of new programs for trans-
ferring cash to “the poor” across a number of African states (albeit at sig-
nificantly lower levels of benefits than those seen in southern Africa). A
recent World Bank review identified no fewer than 123 cash transfer pro-
grams in operation across the continent and provided detailed reviews
of programs in 28 countries (Garcia and Moore 2012; see also Ellis, De-
vereux, and White 2009; World Bank 2009).
Most of the discussion about these programs has been in the public
policy field—asking questions about whether or how well such programs
“work,” how they can be improved or scaled up, and so on. I have sug-
gested that the empirical evidence (at least for southern Africa) strongly
indicates that these programs do in fact yield powerful improvements to
a range of measurable “development” goods (for reviews of similar evi-
dence worldwide, see Hanlon, Barrientos, and Hulme 2010; dfid 2011).
There is a strong case, that is, that these programs have amounted to
14 introduction
dustrial economy and something approaching full employment, at least for
male “heads of household.” Where “welfare” institutions were developed
in the colonial world (as in South Africa and a few other places in Africa),
they were chiefly for whites and a few privileged others. In colonial settings
in which huge proportions of the population were both impoverished
and outside the wage economy, “informal” social security such as “the
African extended family” was the only solution that could be imagined.
Then, too, the conditions under which payments are received in the
new welfare states of the South look quite different from earlier Northern
models. In the North, the central conception was typically of a “safety net”
that could provide social support for a “breadwinner” (often presumed to
be a male “head of household”) and his “dependents” in conditions either
of the worker’s old age or death or those exceptional contingencies that
might interrupt wage labor (accident, disability, temporary economic
slumps). And the usual mechanism for ensuring such payments was a
kind of insurance system, based on payments made into a “system” by
those who might one day need to be caught by the “net.”22 But the south-
ern African schemes I have reviewed here are non-contributory, meaning
that they are paid out of general treasury funds and make no reference
to prior “contributions” by beneficiaries.23 Such payments are made with
no reference to employment histories and are allocated instead based on
such labor-independent criteria as absolute age (for pensions) or num-
ber of children being cared for (for child care grants). What is more, the
large share of the population that has come to rely on such grants strains
any notion of a “safety net” as an extraordinary measure for dealing with
abnormal contingencies. In South Africa today, for instance, 44 percent
of all households receive one or another sort of grant (Statistics South
Africa 2013, 19–20), meaning that, across many of the country’s regions
and neighborhoods, being at least partially supported by social transfers
is more the norm than it is the exception. In the poorest communities, in
fact, the ability to access an income often depends less on one’s ability to
work than on the ability to claim a condition that might give one access
to a monthly cash transfer. Anxieties that poor women might decide to
have children simply for the income do not appear to be well founded
(birth rates have in fact gone down or stabilized since the child care grant
was introduced [Macleod and Tracey 2009, Neves et al. 2009]). And econ-
omists’ worries that disability grants may perversely incentivize such
16 introduction
to impose responsibilities on fathers, or to impose “proper” behavior or
family forms.25
Most radically, some new thinking on social policy is beginning to
break from the central conception of the classic welfare states—the con-
ception that social payments are fundamentally a way of dealing with the
interruption of a “normal” situation in which adult heads-of-households
(most of all men) earn wages that support their dependents. Until now,
social protection programs in the region have effectively ignored the fact
of mass unemployment, supposing that “social” support is needed only
for “dependent” categories such as the elderly, those caring for children,
and the disabled. Working-age “able-bodied” men, in contrast, are all
counterfactually presumed to be able to support themselves through
their labor. Directly challenging such conceptions, a campaign in South
Africa and Namibia has in recent years proposed a “basic income grant”
(big) that would provide a small monthly cash payment to each and every
individual citizen. The amount of the payment was initially set at R100
(N$100) per person (an amount that was, at the time of the initial pro-
posal, worth about US$16). (The proposal is discussed at greater length
in later chapters, especially chapter 6; see also dsd 2002; Standing and
Samson 2003; Meth 2008; Haarmann et al. 2009.) In such a program,
there would be no means testing of any kind, so all citizens would receive
the grant (though the better-off would have their $16 and then some re-
couped through the tax system). In this conception, receipt of a social
payment would make no reference to gender, age, employment status, or
family configuration, and even “able-bodied” working-age men would be
eligible. In this, the most innovative of the new social payment schemes
recently envisaged or implemented in the region, cash transfers to citi-
zens are completely divorced from calculations about wage labor and
family structure alike.
As discussed in the next chapter, powerful criticisms can be leveled
against most currently existing cash transfer programs precisely on the
grounds that they do not go far enough toward the radical rethinking of
the meaning of social payments that can be observed in the basic income
grant campaign. Indeed, I will argue at some length that social policy
across the region is in too many ways still trapped within the terms of the
old European “social” state, as if that old imagined world of breadwinners
and their dependents could be meaningfully mapped onto social settings
“If we create enough jobs to keep the youth off the streets, we will be
saved. If we cannot, South Africa will implode.” I put the statement in
quotation marks because it has become a gospel truth. Question it and
you risk being declared insane.
18 introduction
political system has been a racial dictatorship or a democracy, or
whether our labour law has been rigid or flexible—we cannot employ
everybody. We can’t even come close. To think that we can is to indulge
in millenarian thinking, as if Jesus will come and remake the world, as
if there is a thing called magic.
Deep down, we know this. For while we talk about creating jobs, we
have been doing something else—we have been handing out grants.
Some say that it is a stopgap measure, just to tide us over until jobs are
found. Others say that it is creating a culture of idleness from which
there will be no return.
But if we are honest, it is what we do now and what we will keep doing
forever. It is a substitute for work and it holds the country together; it
has saved many millions from starvation and misery.
A whole series of taboos that govern thought and discourse around em-
ployment all across the world are here summarily discarded as so much
superstition. While leaders in every nation promise jobs for all, Steinberg
simply states it as a fact that, for a huge swath of the population, wage
labor–based livelihoods are simply not going to return, and new forms of
distribution are a permanent and necessary feature of the new world. Won’t
the expansion of grants create “dependency” and undermine the will to
work? According to Steinberg, “that is dead thinking that made sense long
ago, in a time when jobs were plentiful. There isn’t sufficient demand to
employ this country’s young men. We will either give them grants or they
will get nothing. They are our fellow citizens, after all. To put some money
in their pockets to spend as they wish is to confer upon them some dignity”
and to bring “life, not idleness” to the lives of the poor.27 Indeed, he sug-
gested in a companion column a few weeks later that in a context in which
millions have inherited structural unemployment from their parents,
where the promise of decent jobs is “not even a living memory,” arguing
that welfare will make people lazy “borders on madness.”28
I will return to Steinberg’s provocative arguments in the book’s con-
clusion. For the time being, I offer this short excerpt only as an example
Beyond the specifics of the new programs of social assistance, this book is
also about a broader set of questions that they have provoked—questions
about the general processes of distribution as they unfold in contempo-
rary societies, and about the sorts of binding claims and counterclaims
that can be made about these processes. It is this that I refer to as the
politics of distribution, and this volume has the ambition of linking the
recent rise of new sorts of welfare states in the global South to the possi-
bilities and dangers of emergent forms of distributive politics that are un-
folding in contexts where ever more “working-age” people are supported
by means other than wage labor.
It is useful to start by considering the issue of distribution in its most
general form. How are the goods we produce distributed? Which of them
may I have access to? Differently organized societies, economic anthro-
pologists have long pointed out, have provided a wide range of different
institutional answers to that question, ranging from the obligatory rules
for meat-sharing among hunter-gatherers to such famously elaborate cer-
emonial gifting institutions as the kula ring and the potlatch (Mauss [1924]
2000). But in modern capitalist societies, a standard account would point
out that while I may access certain goods directly by producing them my-
self or receive others as gifts, the normal way that people access most of
the goods and ser vices they consume is via “the market.” Which, then,
of the vast quantity of goods produced each year, are distributed to me?
In the simplest terms, I may have those goods which I can buy. And how
is it that I have a certain quantity of funds to buy goods? The usual answer
to this question is that I work for it. I exchange my labor (or its products)
for money, and then can use the money to buy the quantity of goods
that “the market” allows. Whether one reads neoclassical economists
or their Marxist critics, it would be easy to arrive at the conclusion that
20 introduction
distribution in capitalist societies is organized by “the market,” that the
exchange of labor is the source of most people’s purchasing power, and
that purchasing power in the market is both the fundamental mechanism
of distribution and the underlying source of consumption.
Even some of the most articulate and insightful recent critics of the
hegemony of work seem to accept the basic premise that, as Kathi Weeks
(2011, 6–7) puts it, “Waged work . . . is, of course, the way most people ac-
quire access to the necessities of food, clothing, and shelter” (emphasis
added). But plainly that is simply not the case in much of Africa, where
only small minorities participate in waged work and where a range of
other activities and mechanism allow “most people” to obtain their live-
lihoods. And lest we write this off too quickly as a symptom of Africa’s
“underdeveloped” condition, let us linger for a moment on the suppos-
edly “advanced capitalist” United States, generally taken as a country in
which the wage labor form is especially dominant. Here, too, I want to
suggest, paid labor may be less central to processes of distribution than
is often imagined. Indeed, in the United States, as in the rest of the world,
the question of how people actually gain access to the things they need
turns out to be far more complicated than simply exchanging their labor.
We are used to tracking a very narrowly defined official “unemploy-
ment rate” (the percentage of the workforce that is, at any moment, ac-
tively seeking but failing to find employment). The fact that this rate is
generally in the single digits (currently around 7 percent) might lead one
to believe that the rest of the population (the ninety-odd percent who
are not “unemployed”) is in fact employed. But in fact, official labor force
statistics for 2012 show that only 58.6 percent of the adult population of the
United States is actually in employment.29 In a total national population of 314
million, just 142 million were (as of 2012) employed.30 Of the rest, only
12 million were officially “unemployed,” while nearly 90 million adults31
were reported as neither employed nor unemployed but simply “not in the
labor force” (i.e., “those who have no job and are not looking for one”).32
These adults of course include traditional “dependent” categories such as
retirees and stay-at-home mothers, but it includes many others, too. In-
deed, a recent article by New York Times columnist David Leonhardt noted
with alarm that even at the core of the classic “breadwinner” group (men
aged 25 to 54), nearly one out of five were neither employed nor seeking
employment but “managing to get by some other way.”33
22 introduction
This is, of course, even more true in southern Africa, where massive
unemployment is the norm and a myriad of distributive practices (from
“informal” remittances and kinship-based sharing to state programs of
grants and pensions) have long furnished livelihoods to a huge chunk of
the populations (see chapter 3). Yet the distributive mechanisms through
which so many Americans and Africans alike make their way in the world
are widely disparaged. As discussed at some length in chapter 1, a kind of
productivist common sense has too often rendered distribution subsid-
iary, invisible, or even contemptible.
This neglect and denigration of distributive modes of livelihood has
continued, even as such livelihoods have become increasingly important
across much of the world. As Mike Davis (2006) has pointed out, vast
masses of poor people across the global South have left rural livelihoods
for city living in recent decades. Yet instead of being swept up in an in-
dustrial revolution that would turn them into proletarians (as both mod-
ernization theory and Marxism might have predicted), they have more
often been recruited into informal slums where they eke out a living via
a complex range of livelihood strategies to which agriculture and formal-
sector wage labor alike are often marginal (see chapter 3). The exclusion
from wage labor of those exiting small-scale agriculture (whether they
come to the city or remain in the countryside) is certainly not happening
everywhere (as witnessed by the massive recruitment of rural peasants
as industrial workers in some regions of very rapid economic growth,
notably in China), and one should beware of the temptation to extrapo-
late current tendencies toward some inevitable global future of universal
mass redundancy. But it is unmistakably the case that (for the present
and for the foreseeable near future, and across much of the world) people
lacking access both to land and to waged employment form an increas-
ingly prominent part of our social and political reality. Equally important,
those occupying such precarious and ill-defined social locations are both
pioneering new modes of livelihood and making new kinds of political
demands. It is in this context that distributive practices and distributive
politics are acquiring a new centrality.
Distributive issues in the southern African region are probably most
readily identifiable in the tense debates around land reform and the na-
tionalization of mineral resources. Yet such explosive issues have some-
times taken the spotlight away from another distributive discussion—the
24 introduction
its own distinctive history in Africa, especially in the settler-colonial soci-
eties of southern Africa, and it is only out of that peculiar and highly racial-
ized history that a new kind of social protection has emerged.
Chapter 3 reviews the way that new state programs of distribution
intersect with long-established vernacular processes and practices of dis-
tribution. There is a vast and rich regional literature on the multiple
livelihood practices that are utilized by low-income people across the region
and on the social relationships that sustain and enable such practices. This
chapter attempts to distill the key insights of this literature and to draw
some lessons from it about how to understand the place of what I term
“distributive labor” in the regional political economy. The fact that dis-
tribution and production are here (like the social and the economic) so
intimately entangled requires us to bring together domains that are often
kept separate. Chapter 4 follows up on this point by tracing the concep-
tual dualism that continues to plague thinking about market and society
and the pernicious effect of such dualism on understanding distributive
processes and distributive politics. It traces a persistent conceptual error
found on the political Left (confusing money and markets with capital-
ism) and explores an alternative framework for understanding “cash pay-
ment” and the socialities with which it is associated. Here certain new
thinking emerging in the domain of social policy provides both an object
of analysis and a sophisticated inspiration.
The “mutualities of poverty” that bind poor southern Africans to both
markets and each other are, of course, riddled with inequalities. In liveli-
hoods that depend on distributive relations (whether with other persons
or with institutions), distributive practices are typically bound up with
relations of dependence that are unequal, hierarchical, and oft en ex-
ploitative or abusive. Chapter 5 explores the ironic fact that, in societies
we like to think of as “liberated” and “postcolonial,” many actively seek
precisely such hierarchical and dependent relationships with well-placed
others. Tracing a regional history in which social orders based on the
scarcity and value of people were abruptly overturned by ones in which
people came to be regarded as in surplus, it seeks to historicize both the
contemporary hunger of many of “the poor” for social dependence and
the evident eagerness of the propertied classes to evade such entangle-
ments. Understood against this long history, the chapter argues, the de-
sire for dependent relations with powerful others is not some archaic and
26 introduction
what I have elsewhere called a “politics of the anti-” (Ferguson 2010). In
place of such denunciations, the more pressing issue seems to me to be
the challenge of positive government, the need to develop real strategies
and tactics that would enable one to mobilize around specific programs
or initiatives that one might be for, not against.
In his 1979 lectures on neoliberalism (2008), Michel Foucault famously
spoke of the “absence of a socialist art of government,” and the historic fail-
ure of the Left to develop an “autonomous governmentality” comparable to
liberalism. And he concluded his discussion of socialist governmentality
by insisting that the answers to the Left’s governmental problems require
not yet another search through our sacred texts but a process of concep-
tual and institutional innovation. “If there is a really socialist governmen-
tality, then it is not hidden within socialism and its texts. It cannot be
deduced from them. It must be invented” (2008, 94).
Such invention will probably happen (if it does) not in the lectures of
philosophers or anthropologists but in the push and shove of actual gov-
erning and actual politics. And my suggestion is that important elements
of such invention may be emerging as we speak, in the working out of
new forms of “social” governance and new modalities of distribution in
the new welfare states of the global South.
That is not, of course, to say that the sorts of programs I analyze here
are in any simple way socialist, or necessarily subversive of dominant cap-
italist forms of economic organization. On the contrary, the programs I
analyze in the book are creatures of their time. In certain ways, they un-
doubtedly do partake of the neoliberal spirit of the age. As I have noted
elsewhere (2007), even the proposals for the basic income grant (big)
(which I have suggested is the most conceptually ambitious and interest-
ing of the new cash transfer schemes on offer in the region) have relied on
a number of characteristically neoliberal arguments.
One example of this is the common use of ideas of “investment” and
“human capital” as justification for social grants, including the standard
neoliberal move to treat the poor individual as a kind of micro-enterprise.
The big would (as the big Coalition website once claimed) “enable work-
ing families to invest more of their incomes in nutrition, education and
health care—with corresponding productivity gains” (Tilton 2005). Ar-
guments for social transfers today in fact normally rely on language that
recasts social spending as investing in a kind of capital (see Fine 2000
28 introduction
while the standard neoliberal objection to social assistance points to the
danger of “dependency” on the state, contemporary advocates for new
social transfer programs use neoliberal reasoning to neatly reverse the
argument. It is the existing “safety net,” say promoters of a basic income
grant, that breeds dependency, since any economically productive poor
person, under the current system, is surrounded by dependents who must
be supported. This dependency constitutes a “tax” on the productivity of
the poor, which both creates a disincentive to work and degrades human
capital. The “dependency” of absolute poverty is a drag on productiv-
ity, and it makes workers unable to be economically active, to search for
better jobs, and so on. What is more, insecurity breeds passivity and in-
hibits entrepreneurship and risk-taking. A poor South African thinking
of starting a small business under present circumstances, for instance,
must consider the terrible risk of falling into destitution and hunger in
the event of failure. The same person with a monthly big payment would
be empowered to be much bolder. Providing basic income security for all,
it is claimed, will enable the poor to behave as proper neoliberal subjects
(i.e., as entrepreneurs and risk-takers); the status quo prevents it, and
promotes “dependency” (see, e.g., dsd 2002, 61). In this conception, the
big would provide not a “safety net” (the circus image of old-style welfare
as protection against hazard) but a “springboard”—a facilitator of risky
(but presumably empowering) neoliberal flight (Ferguson 2007).
A similarly ironic reversal can be observed around another character-
istically neoliberal element: the valorization of transparency, evaluation,
and measurable quantifiable outputs that is at the heart of what has been
termed “audit culture” (Strathern 2000). These neoliberal elements have
often been associated with Foucauldian ideas of “governmentality” and
with objectionable forms of control and surveillance. But in the push for
cash transfers, both in southern Africa and around the world, the “neolib-
eral” demand for transparent indicators and measurable results has often
been used to argue precisely for “no-strings” cash grants—for the simple
reason that such programs are relatively easily implemented, can be ef-
fectively evaluated, and generally produce (as most development projects
do not) immediate and quantifiable gains in a range of “development”
indicators of health, nutrition, education, and so on (World Bank 2009).
The relative simplicity and “transparency” of cash transfers is another
point on which neoliberal reasoning is deployed toward a political end not
30 introduction
was advocating for a guaranteed income in terms very similar to those
of today’s advocates of basic income. At the same moment in history
that Richard Nixon was proposing a “Family Assistance Plan” that would
have provided a minimum income for all households with children, his
ideological opponent on the Left wing of the U.S. mainstream, George
McGovern, was campaigning on a platform that called for giving every
U.S. citizen a redistributive cash payment of $1,000 per year. Such strange
bedfellows are misunderstood if they are thought to reveal the sinister
“neoliberal” essence lying beneath an only-apparently progressive policy
proposal. What they reveal is only the radical political indeterminacy
that always attends any specific governmental technique. As I have ar-
gued elsewhere (Ferguson 2010), specific institutional and intellectual
mechanisms can be combined in a great variety of ways to accomplish
quite different social and political ends. With social technologies as with
any other sort, it is not the machines or the mechanisms that decide what
they will be used to do.
Stephen Collier (2012, 188) has recently pointed out that those who see
“neoliberal” elements as marking the necessary and nefarious presence
of a sinister “big Leviathan” known as “neoliberalism” or “the neoliberal
project” are ironically reproducing the reasoning of the original neolib-
eral, Friedrich von Hayek, who erroneously believed that there could be
no such thing as a “mixed economy” since the presence of “socialist” ele-
ments of planning and redistribution could only lead to “serfdom” (i.e.,
totalitarian dictatorship). Just as Hayek could not imagine that (as Collier
[2012, 188] puts it) “elements of the Marxist programme could function
in systems that bear no resemblance to a dictatorship of the proletariat”
so do contemporary “anti-neoliberalism” critics seem to struggle to
imagine how ideas and techniques with “neoliberal” origins or affinities
might contribute to quite different sorts of political and social systems
than those imagined by the likes of Hayek and Friedman. Yet if history
has shown us anything, it is that it has no respect for original intentions,
promiscuously throwing together diverse institutional and conceptual el-
ements with little regard for ideological purity. Just as socialist elements
ended up mingled with liberal capitalism to yield what we today know as
social democracy or the welfare state, so might apparently “neoliberal”
elements today be in the process of becoming something else (cf. Fergu-
son 2010).
32 introduction
open to the unexpected, ready to “increase the experiments wherever
possible,” and attentive to the ways that new conditions may be opening
up new possibilities for politics and policy alike.
Where does such a politics lead? This book’s conclusion briefly re-
views a range of interesting and politically promising current “experi-
ments” (institutional and intellectual), but this is nothing more than a
beginning of what must be a long process of analysis, assessment, and
reimagination involving a range of interested actors. In fact, there can
be no deductive answer to the question of where distributive politics is
going. Instead, this book is animated by Foucault’s experimental and em-
pirical sensibility, and by the conviction that a politics adequate to the
times must be more than a set of normative certainties that one brings to
bear on an issue. It must be a process of discovery and invention.
1. The “end of history” and “world is flat” arguments are associated with best-
selling books by Francis Fukuyama and Thomas Friedman, respectively. The most in-
fluential critical accounts operating at the same “meta” level are perhaps David Harvey
2007, Mike Davis 2006, and (in a more popular vein) Naomi Klein 2008.
2. Even in Bangladesh (home of Muhammed Yunus’s Grameen Bank and long the
poster child for microcredit as anti-poverty remedy), Ananya Roy’s revealing study
(2010) has concluded that microcredit/microfinance programs there, successful as
they have often been, have in fact been less about investment and interest than about
public subsidies to the poor. “Despite the rhetoric of credit and entrepreneurship,”
she observes, “the Bangladesh institutions seem to be engaged in forms of social
protection,” following a “logic of development” that “fits much more comfortably in
the ‘social protection’ family of programs and policies than in the ‘micro-enterprises’
family” (2010, 116, 117).
3. Hanlon, Barrientos, and Hulme 2010.
4. “Southern Africa” is both a conventional unit of scholarly specialization and a re-
gion that is meaningfully integrated both economically (insofar as it is oriented around
the powerful industrial “core” economy of South Africa) and politically (via the South-
ern African Development Community, a regional grouping that began as an associa-
tion of anti-apartheid “front line” states but today includes all the states in the region,
including South Africa). Note that I will give special attention throughout to two states
within the region, South Africa and Namibia, that have especially extensive and (from
my point of view) interesting systems of social assistance, but I will also refer where
appropriate to neighboring states where similar (if less extensive) programs have been
introduced or contemplated (including the two countries for which I have the most
sustained direct research experience, Lesotho and Zambia).
5. Garcia and Moore 2012; for Zimbabwe, see unicef 2012.
6. On the theme of exclusion, see, for example, Wacquant 2009; Sassen 2010.
More recently, scholars have paid more attention to the ways that new forms of
inclusion-via-social-policy may also be part of the “neoliberal” story (see Collier 2011;
Muehlebach 2012).
7. See Bond 2000 and Marais 2001 for accounts of this “neoliberal” turn.
8. The most recent official unemployment rate was reported as 25.2 percent, with an
“expanded” definition (including all those desiring employment regardless of whether
they are actively seeking it) at 35.1 percent. Youth unemployment was reported at 66 per-
cent. “Employment Down for First Quarter of 2014,” Mail and Guardian, May 5, 2014.
9. While not directly concerned with questions of social assistance, Hart (2008) has
provided a related assessment of the limits of dominant neoliberalism narratives, insist-
ing that understanding the specific political dynamics of concrete points of local politi-
cal struggle in South Africa will require a more complex political and analytic strategy
than simply “exposing neoliberal class power.” See also Parnell and Robinson 2012.
10. The newly founded eff (Economic Freedom Fighters) led by Julius Malema
(treated in chapter 6) may prove an exception to this, for better or worse. It is also
worth noting the recent emergence of two small alternative Left parties, the Demo-
cratic Left Front (dlf) and the Workers and Socialist Party (wasp), though clearly
neither can at this point be termed major political parties.
11. For an overview of the development of social pensions in the region, see De-
vereux 2007; on the South African Child Support Grant program, see Lund 2008 and
dsd, sassa, and unicef 2012.
12. See National Treasury 2012 (85). Other grants include the War Veterans Grant,
the Disability Grant, the Foster Care Grant, and the Care Dependency Grant.
13. Bond (2014) has disputed the reliability of these figures, claiming that many of
the toilets, taps, and other new facilities tallied in the survey are in fact functioning
imperfectly or not at all. This is likely true, but the same must have been true of the
counts from earlier years (i.e., not all the counted infrastructural assets would have
been functional). It is hard to see how considerations of this kind can stand in the way
of acknowledging such a marked improvement over only a few years—a trend that is
consistent with other difficult-to-dismiss data, such as the self-reported hunger fig-
ures cited above, as well as the extensive field studies reviewed in the authoritative
report of Neves et al. 2009.
14. “Impressive Shift in Living Standards Trends,” press release, South African
Institute of Race Relations, August 28, 2012.
15. Dubbeld (2013) has recently reported that some rural recipients (in South Afri-
ca’s KwaZulu-Natal province) condemn the proliferation of grants as corrosive of “tra-
dition” and contrast the current world of grants unfavorably with a remembered past
where men could earn more adequate incomes via wage labor. A yearning for wage
labor and the social structure that it supported, however, should not be mistaken for a
1. For a thoughtful reflection on the problematic use of “teach a man to fish” rea-
soning in the contemporary development fad for “sustainability,” see Swidler and
Watkins 2009.
2. “anc Has Tough Job Rallying West Coast’s Frustrated Fishermen,” Business Day,
February 24, 2006. A comprehensive study exploring the difficulties the post-apartheid
South African fishing industry has faced in seeking to expand access to historically ex-
cluded groups concluded by pointing to the global industry trends referenced above,
noting that “small-scale bona fide fishers are up against heavy odds, all over the
world” (Hersoug 2002, 223).
3. “Mpulungu Job Hunt Kills 9,” Zambia Daily Mail, May 29, 2012, accessed June 4,
2012, http://www.daily-mail.co.zm/?p=4484.
4. See discussion later in this chapter as well as chapter 6; cf. Ferguson 2013.
5. This history has recently been insightfully reviewed by Weeks (2011).
6. As Brian Turner has usefully pointed out in a discussion of T. H. Marshall’s En-
glish context, citizenship has historically been associated with (typically male) par-
ticipation in the formal labor market, sometimes supplemented with (again male)
military ser vice (thus the “worker-citizen” and the “soldier-citizen”). Women have
historically been granted social rights not as individuals but as parts of “families,”
within which they have enjoyed certain entitlements “as fertile adults who are replen-
ishing the nation” (Turner 2010, 70).
7. On the related association of the domestic domain with humanitarian practice,
see Malkki 2015.
8. “Alan Simpson Calls Social Security ‘Cow with 310 Million Tits,’ Causes Uproar,”
Talking Points Memo, August 25, 2010, accessed September 27, 2013, http://talkingpoints
memo.com/dc/alan-simspon-calls-social-security-cow-with-310-million-tits-causes
-uproar.
9. In the Communist Manifesto, they famously described the lumpenproletariat as
“the social scum, that passively rotting mass thrown off by the layers of the old soci-
ety” ([1848] 1998, 48); as late as 1870 Engels described it as “this scum of depraved ele-
ments from all classes . . . the worst of all possible allies” (Engels [1870] 1968, 229).
Elsewhere, Marx suggested such a class acted as an “industrial reserve army” whose
function under capitalism was keeping wages low. For a critical account of the limita-
tions of such Marxian functionalism in the context of massive labor surplus, see Li
2010 and cf. this book’s conclusion. On Marx’s concept of the lumpenproletariat, see
also Stallybrass 1990 and the discussion in chapter 3.
10. “Any distribution whatever of the means of consumption,” he later wrote, “is
only a consequence of the distribution of the conditions of production themselves,”
and for a given arrangement of the elements of production, the distribution of the