LEWIS, Harry WOODFIELD, Andrew. (1985) 'Content and Community'
LEWIS, Harry WOODFIELD, Andrew. (1985) 'Content and Community'
LEWIS, Harry WOODFIELD, Andrew. (1985) 'Content and Community'
The Aristotelian Society and Blackwell Publishing are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes.
http://www.jstor.org
CONTENT
AND COMMUNITY
178
A. LEWIS
I-HARRY
179
sofa.
180
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
181
could not exist for a community. But its usage would by Burge's
argument fail to determine the contents of the attitudes
expressed by it, until reference was made to the ways of the hostcommunity. The only contrast needed in order to characterize
the phenomena presented by Burge is that between languages.
He makes no use of the contrast between individual and
community except to that end.
The claimed direct link between content and community is
thus revealed as mediated by the notion of language identity.
This suggests that the argument needs to be re-cast. The link
taken for granted by Burge between (on the one hand) the social
factors that fix the language and the notions it expresses and (on
the other) the contents of individuals' thoughts, needs to be
made good. Even if it established its ostensible conclusion,
Burge's case would fall short of showing that there could not be a
solitary thinker; for it is an unargued assumption that his
thinkers are members of communities. He does not suggest that
there would be no attitudes without community, but only that
where a person already belongs to a community, some facts
about the community enter into the determination of the
content of her thoughts.
III
We shall consider a less direct argument to show the impossibility
of a solitary thinker, to wit: any thinker must have a language;
any language-user must have a community; so any thinker must
have a community.
We should not assimilate thinking too readily to a use of
language. There are many attitudes whose content is not
literally expressed by any sentence of their owner's language. A
variety of examples may be used to argue for this observation,
if indeed argument is required. If there are de re attitudes
properly expressed using indexical pronouns, their content will
not typically be expressed by any complete sentence, where
what the sentence expresses is taken to be what it brings to its
contexts. Any figurative or metaphorical use of language may
lend itself to the expression of attitudes whose contents cannot be
'translated' into another sentence taken literally. Nonetheless, if
I say 'It's raining and it's not raining', what I think, and what I
convey, may be true, even though the sentence I utter, taken
182
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
183
Interpretation',
184
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
pretation requires in the first place two roles rather than two
people, even if it is only when we credit the bilingual with two
personalities that we can make sense of the hypothesis that both
roles could be played by one person.
If interpretation is taking place, must interpreter and
informant be members of a community? If we hark back to the
forerunner of radical interpretation, Quine's radical translation,
we are apt to assume that they are severally members of
communities, but not that they are fellow-members of any one
community. For the moment we may hold in suspense the
assumption that there are two communities in the background,
responsible for the languages, and focus on the activity of
interpretation. This is usually talked of as a collaborative
activity; for more than the passive observation of speechbehaviour is needed to establish experimentally the patterns of
assents, dissents or neither (Quine), or the pattern of holdings*true (Davidson), that forms the empirical basis of interpretation.
There is, however, a lack of mutuality in this supposedly 'social'
activity, for it is motivated only by the interpreter's need to
associate sentences held true with observable situations or with
the interpreter's occurrent beliefs. There seems no reason to
honour a pair related by no more than the minimal requirements
for interpretation with the title 'community'.
Interpretation requires also two languages. These are usually
represented as the languages of communities; but that they are
communal
languages is a background assumption, not an
Moreover it is not clear that we have a
conclusion.
argued
ready-made argument for the communal nature of language
from the premiss (even if granted) that any language must at
some time have been interpreted. For all this could yield would
be further pairs of interpreters and informants. Although an
actual human community could provide the personnel for such
activities, they could be carried on without it; after all, the facts
of human generation by pairwise relations of mothers and fathers
do not make siblings of us all. Furthermore, both Quine and
Davidson find ultimately that pairs of speakers of 'the same'
natural languages are indulging in radical translation or
interpretation. As I have noted already, this view has to find
intelligible the restriction of a language to a single speaker.
Thus the first step provides no easy transition from thought to
185
186
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
IV
We can now refine the second step, and look for argument to
either of two conclusions: that any language is a community's
language (not just one individual's); or that anyone who has a
language must belong to a community (whether or not her
language is also the community's language). If either conclusion
is true, there will be some latent contradiction in the notion of a
lifelong social isolate who possesses an idiolect: a language all his
own, spoken by no one else.
If social isolation is conceptually, if not psychologically,
" In 'Thought and Talk', op. cit. p. 157.
187
188
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
thanthelimitation
ofhumanintelligence?
Letusaskhowsucha
languagemightbe acquired.
IfS, ouridiolectophone,
is to bea
lifelongsocialisolate,he cannothavelearned
it
at
his
mother's
knee.(ButI notethatsomeonecouldlearn
an idiolectsocially.
His parentsmightinventit, and
teachit to him,withouthis
meetinganyotherpersonwhospokeit.) Thus
wemustassume
heinventedit. Thishe dideitherby
replicating
withinhimself
thoseelementsof languagelearninggiven
socially
to therestof
us;orbyfindinganalternative
wayintolanguage.Itwouldbeg
thequestionto saythatthe latteris
impossible;
forthatisjust
whatthehumanrace,takencollectively,
achieved.
Wehaveyet
touncovertheessential
socialelementinlanguagecreation,that
wouldshowhow the racecouldachieve
whatno individual,
however
well-endowed
intellectually,
could.
Anassumption
of thistreatment
ofidiolectshasbeenthatan
idiolect
will be differentfromanyother
language.Nothingin
thedefinitions
proposed
required
this,
however,
andit neednot
beso.Twopeoplecouldsharethesame
idiolect
just
sharethe sameheight;exceptthat 'share' astheycould
is a dangerously
ambiguous
termto use there.If we allowthat the
notionof
idiolect
is intelligible,I cannotsee that we
can
rule
out the
possibility
of the independent
invention
by
two
people
of the
same
language,howeverimprobable
it
may
be.
A versionof Wittgenstein's
commentson his
reporting
languagemight still be thought to sensationa
conclusive
refutation
of thethesisthatanidiolect,asprovide
described,
is
possible.In spiteofmygenerous
description,
it mightbeheld
thata solitaryuser of the 'language'
could
not mustera
distinction
betweencorrectandincorrect
use.Inthecaseofthe
impoverished
'language'of Philosophical
Investigations
258,
Wittgenstein
hadanargument
toshowwhy'whatever
is
going
to
seem
righttomeisright'.Soa defenceofthe
idiolect
should
take
the
formofshowinghowitsusercouldcometo
detecterror.(Itis
not
enoughto claimthatthelanguagecaninfact
bemisused;
a
sense
mustbe givento discovery
of themisuse.)Thiscallsforthe
possibility
of checkingon the correctness
of pastusage.
I am makingthe simplifying
assumption
that the usagein
question
is 'fact-stating
discourse'.
This
abstraction
awayfrom
the
complexity
of therealworldis defensible
ad
hominem;
andI
know
ofnoonewhoallowsthata 'fact-stating'
idiolectmightbe
189
190
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
life.'7
Taking our cue from this, let us compare the individual's
instantaneous and unchecked judgment both with the same
judgment in the context of communal agreement and with the
same judgment as one of a series by that individual. For I submit
that any reinforcement provided for an individual's momentary
judgment by his community can be paralleled by reinforcement
available from the historyof his own judgments. Schematically:
many minds on one occasion of judgment can be paralleled by
one mind on several occasions. If 'agreement in judgment' is
possible at one moment for many minds, it is also possible for one
mind at many times.18 Appropriate but entirely analogous
assumptions are needed in both cases. Let the judgment in
question be 'This is an oak tree'. If several people assent to that
sentence at the time, they must (in order to agree) refer to the
"
of Mathematics(edited by G. H. von
17Wittgenstein, L., Remarkson the Foundations
191
same object, and mean the same by 'oak tree'. If one person
assents to it on several occasions, in order for hisjudgments to be
in agreement, his reference and his language must likewise
concur. The many-person case is not yet revealed as privileged.
We are by now, however, alerted to the ambiguity of 'agree'.
Two people may assent to the same thought, without coming to
an agreement that it is true. The former is a necessary
condition of the latter, but it is not sufficient. If the latter is
conceived as a social act involving two people, there will be no
obvious analogue for a single person. However, a step from the
one to the other is the recognitionof sameness of assent. And the
persisting individual may follow the momentary colleague at
least to this point. As this is the crucial step for comparison and
so for checking, let us look closely at it.
First I must note that the term 'judgment' is misleading. The
kind of agreement that (according to the 'communitarian'
interpretation) underpins rule-following is agreement (or better,
coincidence) in pre-linguistic responses, not in judgment
proper. And that is how it should be, if the claim is that language
could not have developed without coincidence of responses.
Of course, a possible position would be that some social
communality of pre-linguistic responses was required for any
individual to have a language. But that would be an unsupported
claim, and only if some content could be given to the alleged
communality could it be evaluated. Once such content was given
(e.g. along the lines of mutual perception of responses) I could
seek to model it in the persisting individual. There is a further
problem in the notion of genuinely social sharing that is
supposed to take place prior to language: the mutuality or
communality involved would have to be possible for creatures
without language.
So the claim that needs scrutiny is this: the only intelligible
kind of checking of responses is inter-personal; even given
time, I cannot compare my own responses one with another.
And this claim hardly needs to be refuted. To compare any two
responses, the least that is needed is the awareness of the
responses, the awareness of that to which they are responses, and
the awareness that they are both responses to that stimulus.
(This is intended to be a minimal characterization. Clearly no
less will do. I do not find it plausible myself that all these
192
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
193
194
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
195
Wittgenstein,
21 Gilbert,
196
I-HARRY
A. LEWIS
2" In preparing this paper I have benefited from discussions with Mark Johnston,
Philip Pettit, Pamela Tate and Roger White.
CONTENT
AND COMMUNITY
Woodfield
I
198
II-ANDREW WOODFIELD
not think they are the only kind, nor do I think they are basic, as
section III will reveal.
Let us start by considering actual human languages, such as
Arabic, English, Mandarin or any of the several thousand or so
others that are in daily use. Some, like Cornish, are dying out. It
is said that only two persons are left who can speak fluent
Cornish. I find it helpful to say that the basic purpose of a
language is to facilitate communication. The truth of this
functional claim depends, I think, upon facts about how the
language originated. A genuine language has to have evolved
because it has successfully mediated communication in the past,
or if it is an artificial language, it has to have been designed for
that purpose. The concept of a natural language is partly
explicated by the platitude that natural languages have evolved
for sending messages. The various components of a language are
there for the same purpose, but derivatively, as the organs of a
body are there to keep the whole animal alive, or as the parts of a
machine are tailored to its overall purpose. The thesis holds, as
Aristotle says, 'generally and for the most part'. It is not falsified
by putative counter-examples of the 'Robinson Crusoe' kind in
which a language is not used for communication. All sorts of
exceptional situations are imaginable. Platitudes about functions
can admit of exceptions and yet reveal essential truths.
Lewis is right that individuals who talk to one another do not
ipsofacto bind themselves into a community. It happens that
people who converse a lot tend to live close together, consequently they tend to enter into social relations and adopt shared
norms. Using the same tool is not sharing a norm.3
Yet, if one considers any living natural language, with all its
richness and tradition, one knows that there must have been a
3A related point is made by Bach and Harnish, when they note that successful
communication in L requireswhat they call the 'Linguistic Presumption':'The mutual
belief in the linguistic community C that
(i) the members of C share L, and
(ii) that whenever any member S utters any e (expression)in L to any other member
H, H can identify what S is saying, given that H knows the meaning(s) of e in L and is
aware of the appropriate background information' (Kent Bach and Robert M. Harnish
and SpeechActs, p. 7. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
(1979) LinguisticCommunication
Without such a presumption, neither S nor H would be entitled to assume that e
means to the other what it means to himself. So the mutual belief is something else that is
shared by people who converse in L. But of course this is not sufficient to forge a social
community.
199
200
II-ANDREW
WOODFIELD
201
202
II-ANDREW
WOODFIELD
203
204
II-ANDREW
WOODFIELD
something is or is not the case, regardlesswhether or not somebody has put it into words, and regardlesseven whether or not it
has been thought.''"He also affirmsthat 'There is indeedno doubt
that thinkabilityis a propertyof any proposition,but it is also obvious that it does not form part of the concept of a proposition'."4
Again, the connection with language is not completely
severed by this formulation, since a propositionmight exist only
in so far as it couldbe put into words. Moreover, Bolzano is not
committed to propositions as Platonic entities, for he says 'One
must not ascribe being, existence or reality to propositions in
themselves'.' The Fregean tradition flourishes today. Popper
advocates the objectivity of 'World 3', whose denizens are
autonomous of any mind.'" Christopher Peacocke consciously
adopts Fregean terminology in his recent book.'7
Frege's logicist motivation is well-known. Both he and
Bolzano deplored the post-Kantian tendency to 'psychologise'
logic, which in their view propagated doubts about its objective
validity. If thoughts can be shown to be objective, then
presumablylogical relationsbetween them can also be objective.
0oFrege,G. (1918 originally) 'Thoughts', p. 4, in LogicalInvestigations,
(ed) P. T.
Geach, Blackwell, Oxford 1977.
"
Frege (op. cit.), p. 18 footnote: 'A person sees a thing, has an idea, graspsor thinksa
thought. When he graspsof thinksa thought he does not create it but only comes to stand
in a relation to what already existed-a differentrelation from seeing a thing or having
an idea.'
"2See the editor's introduction (p. xxix) to BernardBolzano (originally 1837) Theory
of
Science,edited and translated by Rolf George, Blackwell, Oxford 1972.
'"Bolzano, (op. cit.) pp. 20-1.
'4ibid. p. 26.
'5ibid. p. 21.
16 Popper, K. (1972) Objective
Knowledge,esp. chapters 3 & 4. Clarendon, Oxford.
17Peacocke, C. (1983) Senseand ContentClarendon, Oxford (see esp. p. 106).
205
206
II-ANDREW
WOODFIELD
207
correct S about its identity. Tyler Burge, in his ingenious antiindividualist argument, sets up clearly-defined situations in
which precisely this kind of phenomenon occurs. The Cartesian
intimacy between subject and thought-content gets sundered
when the thought is communalised. S can aim at a certain
thought and miss it, yet be under the impression he has hit it.
Thus we find Burge saying that his argument gets under way 'in
any case where it is intuitively possible to attribute a mental
state or event whose content involves a notion that the subject
incompletely understands."'9 Burge treats standard concepts as
symbolic instruments for people to 'think with'. Operating with
thoughts is seen as a cognitive skill, at which some people are
more adept than others. Burge sees the community as 'defining'
the notionof sofa; my third criterion is clearly applicable to his
conception of a notion.
I have said there are many alternative methods of constructing
conceptions of communal thought. To see some of these, it is
helpful to focus on the different ways one might try to explicate
the 'grasping' relation. I shall sketch just four possible methods,
two of which seem reasonably plausible.
(1) The 'Dasein' Model. For a (suitably receptive) S to think a
standard thought it is sufficient for S to be appropriately
ensconced in the relevant cultural environment. Nothing hinges
on S's inner condition. Two individuals could be internally
identical, one of whom thinks that P, the other does not, solely
because the former stands in the external relation, the latter does
not. This Hegelian or Heideggerian position entails the
wholesale rejection of the Cartesian concept of mind. The model
not only conflates 'having a thought' with 'having a thought
available', it is also wholly at odds with what is known about the
dependence of cognition upon brain processes.
(2) The 'Internalised Token' Model. S thinks standard
thought T iff there is a token of T, (call it t), inside S, and S
stands in the 'thinks*' relation to t.20The crucial feature of this
model is that the inner token t is itself a standardised entity. The
9 Burge T. (1979) 'Individualism and the Mental' p. 79, MidwestStudiesin Philosophy
vol. IV (eds) P. A. French, T. E Uehling and H. K. Wettstein, University of Minnesota,
Minneapolis.
"
For more on 'thinks*'see Hartry Field (1978) 'Mental Representation',Erkenntnis
13,
9-61.
208
II-ANDREW
WOODFIELD
209
210
II-ANDREWWOODFIELD
211
212
II-ANDREWWOODFIELD
213
214
II-ANDREWWOODFIELD