Kockelman 2006 Representations of The World Memories
Kockelman 2006 Representations of The World Memories
Kockelman 2006 Representations of The World Memories
Abstract
Mental states are retheorized from the standpoint of social statuses (qua
commitments and entitlements to signify and interpret in particular ways)
and speech acts (qua signs with propositional contents). Using ideas developed in The semiotic stance (2005a), it theorizes five interrelated semiotic
processes that are usually understood in a psychological idiom: memories,
perceptions, beliefs, intentions, and plans. It uses this theory to account
for the key features of human-specific modes of intentionality (or theory
of mind), as well as the key dimensions along which culture-specific
modes of intentionality may vary (or ethnopsychologies). And it theorizes
emotion in terms of a framework that bridges the distinction between
social constructions and natural kinds.
1. Introduction
Intentionality is usually understood to be that quality of mental states
whereby they are directed at objects or states of aairs. For example,
Brentano, one of the first to theorize this quality, thought that each mental state includes an object within itself (1995 [1874]: 88), but not necessarily corresponding to something existing outside of the mind. In his
own words, [i]n presentation something is presented, in judgment something is armed or denied, in love loved, in hate hated, in desire desired
and so on (1995 [1874]: 88). Famously, Brentanos notion of intentionality was a major influence on Frege and Husserl; Frege and Husserl were
major influences on Wittgenstein and Heidegger, respectively; and Wittgenstein and Heidegger were major influences on analytic and continental
philosophy more generally (see Dummett 1994). In short, many of the
most important categories and cleavages within modern philosophy can
be traced back to intentionality in one guise or another.
Semiotica 1621/4 (2006), 73125
DOI 10.1515/SEM.2006.074
00371998/06/01620073
6 Walter de Gruyter
74
P. Kockelman
75
76
P. Kockelman
77
78
P. Kockelman
Section 7 shows how intentional statuses become implicated in epistemes that allow them to be the objects of empirical investigations, theoretical representations, and practical interventions.
And section 8 shows how the phenomena currently grouped under the
term emotion can be understood relative to the foregoing framework.
2.
In The semiotic stance, it was argued that many interpretants are ultimate interpretants: they involve a change in status, where status is understood as a set of commitments and entitlements to signify and interpret in
particular ways (as evinced in the sanctioning practices of a community
and as embodied in the dispositions of its members). Unlike most interpretants, such ultimate interpretants are not signs that stand for something else; rather, they are dispositions to signify and interpret. And insofar as they are not signs that stand for something else, but merely
dispositions to signify and interpret, they are invisible being known
only through the signs that lead to them (insofar as they are interpretants), or through the patterned modes of signifying and interpreting that
follow from them (insofar as they are dispositions to signify and interpret).7 Using Colapietros metaphor (1989), the underlying idea is that ultimate interpretants have both roots and fruits.
These ultimate interpretants were also called embodied signs to stress
that they involved thirdness (like signs more generally), but that they
were non-sensible (unlike signs more generally). Examples were oered
such as social statuses (being a mother or banker) and intentional statuses
(believing god is dead or intending to grow a large mustache).8 And the
idea of semiotic framing was put forth: on the one hand, sign events may
be understood to lead to, and follow from, embodied signs; and on the
other hand, embodied signs may be understood to lead to, and follow
from, sign events. That is, one can focus on relatively public sign events
(such as speech acts) that lead to or follow from relative private embodied
signs (such as social and intentional statuses); or, inverting the frame, one
can focus on relatively private embodied signs that lead to or follow from
relatively public sign events.
The two views are equivalent, like the two perspectives of a Necker
cube, but the former focuses on non-sensible entities being mediated
through sensible events; and the latter focuses on sensible events being
mediated through non-sensible entities. It may now be seen that semiotic
framing allows one to focus on intentional statuses (the non-sensible
79
entities) or on speech acts (the sensible events) or, generalizing to nonpropositional semiosis, semiotic framing allows one to focus on either embodied signs or sign events. In short, at this level of analysis, the distinction between derivative and originary intentionality is reduced to a
question of semiotic framing, such that to ask which came first the
sign event or the embodied sign (the speech act or the mental state) is
equivalent to asking whether it was the chicken or the egg.
The basic structure of these embodied signs, with their roots and fruits,
is shown in figure 1. There is a class of antecedent sign events, or roots
(labeled A1, A2, A3, etc.). This is the class of signs events that lead to
the embodied sign (so far as it is an interpretant of them). There is a class
of consequent sign events, or fruits (labeled C1, C2, C3, etc.). This is the
class of sign (and interpretant) events that follow from the embodied sign
(so far as it disposes one to signify (and interpret) in particular ways).
And there is the non-sensible but inferable mediating variable that links
them (M). This is the embodied sign (or intentional status) itself.
To summarize the peculiar features of embodied signs, note the following. The antecedent and consequent sign events are sensible; whereas the mediating variable is non-sensible. The antecedent sign events
are prior to the consequent sign events (as presupposed by the terminology). There is no mapping between particular antecedent sign events
and particular consequent sign events; there is only a mapping between
the class of antecedent sign events and the class of consequent sign
events. That is, any antecedent sign event can lead to the mediating
variable, and any consequent sign event can follow from the mediating
variable (i.e., following either the seeing of a rattlesnake or the hearing
of ssst could be either the yelling of snake or the unholstering of a pistol). The class of antecedent sign events, like the class of consequent
sign events, is heterogeneous: the various antecedent sign events, and
the various consequent sign events, are not sensible tokens of a common type (i.e., seeing a rattlesnake has very little in common, as a phenomenological experience, with hearing ssst).9 Their commonality as a
class is entirely due to their leading to, or following from, the same
mediating variable. Thus, to define antecedent sign events as a class,
one must necessarily specify the consequent sign events as a class, and
the mediating variable between them (and vice versa). There need not
be a many-to-many relation between the number of dierent antecedent
events and the number of dierent consequent events: there may be a
many-to-one relation, a one-to-many relation, a few-to-few relation, a
few-to-one relation, and so forth. Finally, temporal latency is possible.
That is, while the consequent event must follow the antecedent event, it
need not follow it instantaneously.10
80
P. Kockelman
Figure 1. Antecedent sign events, consequent sign events, and mediating embodied sign. See Tomasello and Call (1997: 37).
81
82
P. Kockelman
83
and physical causes there are Newtons, and in the realm of intentionality
and psychological motivations there are Dostoyevskys.
84
P. Kockelman
85
surprised that certain of its behaviors can lead to changes in circumstance. This is the realm of behavioralism. To understand an entity as
semiotic is to understand it as having embodied signs which mediate between antecedent sign events and consequent sign events, and hence interpreting sensible events (or antecedent sign events) via embodied signs,
and as interpreting embodied signs via sensible events (or consequent
sign events). Indeed, there is nothing anthropomorphizing or fetishizing in the fact that humans see animals as having purposes. Rather, animals experience purchasefully and behave purposefully and any human account of animal behavior must turn on this (even if animals dont
understand other animals behavior as such and hence dont purposively act to change the purposes of other animals). Finally, to understand an entity as sapient, is to understand the embodied signs that organize its behavior as having propositional content, and hence being both
indexically related to the world and inferentially related to other embodied signs. This is the realm of the representational whole, and the exemplary embodied signs are perceptions, beliefs, and intentions.
Using this idiom, one can contrast human primates and non-human
primates, and infant and non-infant human primates. In particular, nonhuman primates are relatively responsive, animate, sentient, and semiotic;
but they only understand other conspecifics as responsive, animate, and
sentient. Human primates are relatively responsive, animate, sentient, semiotic, and sapient, but only begin to understand other conspecifics as semiotic between nine and twelve months (as evinced in joint-attention),
and only begin to understand other conspecifics as sapient between one
to three years (as evinced in language use).13 Human primates also, of
course, tend to understand non-human primates and infant humans as responsive, animate, sentient, semiotic (correctly), and sapient (incorrectly).
Indeed, the ethnographic record shows that human primates are willing
to understand just about every process, natural or cultural, as sapient.14
And one suspects that, just as humans anthropomorphize non-human primate behavior (treat sentient and semiotic behavior as sapient), nonhuman primates probably simian-pomorphize human primate behavior
(treat sapient and semiotic behavior as sentient). And much of Heideggers critique of western metaphysics is that it attempts to understand
semiosis in terms of sapience, or non-propositional modes of semiosis in
terms of propositional modes of semiosis: to understand residence in the
world in terms of representations of the world. Attempts to understand
the behavior of entities in terms of capacities that are above or below its
understanding thereby bumping it up or down this hierarchy are
part and parcel of what anthropologists call fetishization and reification, respectively.
86
P. Kockelman
Tomasello (1999) has argued that the human capacity to see other conspecifics as semiotic (what he calls intentional) is a phylogenetic adaptation, and the ability to see other conspecifics as sapient (what he calls
mental) is the precipitate of this phylogenetic adaptation in conjunction
with ontogenetic development in historical time. His hypothesis is quite
elegant, and it should be paraphrased in terms of the framework oered
here (1999: 10, 48). Human primates have cognitive skills that originated
via biological inheritance working in phylogenetic time in particular,
the ability to identify with conspecifics and thereby understand them in
semiotic (or intentional) terms. That is, human primates can understand
the embodied signs of other human primates (in particular, their purposes). With these cognitive skills, and the modes of socialization and
sociogenesis they allow, they exploit cultural resources that evolved in
historical time which we might theorize as all the culture-specific constituents of the residential whole (aordances, instruments, actions, roles,
and identities) and all the culture-specific constituents of the representational whole (perceptions, memories, beliefs, intentions, and plans). And
they do this in ontogenetic time. In particular, benefiting from accumulated historical traditions (i.e., the constituents of the residential and
representational wholes), through joint-attention they learn linguistic
symbols (and subsequently all the language-specific cognitive resources
that such symbols enable: construal, metaphor, displacement, generativity, performativity, etc.), and they come to internalize complicated constructions involving these symbols (and hence acquire dialogic thinking,
meta-cognition, and related discourse-based cognitive resources). Broadly
speaking, then, it is a theory of intentionality that makes reference to
complicated interactions among dierent processes that are occurring on
three separate time-scales (phylogenetic, historical, ontogenetic), and
thereby complicates many of the more rarified philosophical arguments
regarding primary and derivative intentionality.
4.
The last two sections focused on embodied signs: the invisible forces that
mediate between antecedent sign events and consequent sign events. Using Lintons understanding of status and Peirces understanding of ultimate (representational) interpretants, they were understood both as a
complex kind of interpretant that an antecedent sign event could lead to,
and as a complex kind of sign that a consequent sign event could follow
from. Indeed, through semiotic framing, they could be understood not
only as (embodied) signs, but also as (dynamic) objects and (ultimate)
87
88
P. Kockelman
Relational
Normative
Epistemic
A role which is
maximally public
(i.e., perceivable
and interpretable);
and a role which
is minimally
ambiguous (i.e.,
one-to-one and
onto).
A role which
provides necessary
and sucient
criteria for
inferring (and/or
ascribing) the
intentional status
in question.
89
there are signs that indicate the type of intentional state that is directed
(say, believe or hope).
Second, these signs of modes of commitment and contents of commitment may have propositional contents or not. For example, I feel disgusted by the mess in your room is a relatively propositional sign of
both the content of commitment (the mess in the room) and the mode
of commitment (the feeling of disgust). In contrast, yuck is a nonpropositional sign of the content of commitment (e.g., the disgusting object it indexes), and a non-propositional sign of the mode of commitment
(e.g., disgust per se).
Third, propositional signs of modes of commitment or contents of
commitment may involve grammatical forms (or operators) or lexical
forms (or predicates). For example, the modal auxiliary verbs may and
must are grammatical operators that can indicate degrees of deontic (and
epistemic) commitment and entitlement; whereas the adjectives permitted
and obligated are lexical predicates that can indicate degrees of deontic
entitlement and commitment. Other grammatical operators include verbal categories such as status (e.g., I was going to go), mood (e.g., take
out the trash), and illocutionary force (e.g., if only it would rain). And
other lexical predicates include what linguists call propositional attitudes
denoting intentional statuses words like believe, know, and hope.
Fourth, non-propositional signs of modes of commitment or contents
of commitment may involve indexical-symbols or iconic-indices. For example, interjections like ugh (and many forms of prosody) are relatively
indexical-symbols of modes of commitment, and relatively iconic-indices
of contents of commitment. And facial expressions (as well as tears and
laughter) and direction of attention (as well as changes in it, as occur in
joint-attention) are relatively iconic-indices (and sometimes indexicalsymbols) of modes of commitment and iconic-indices of contents of commitment. (Notice that the iconic-index/indexical-symbol division is not
the same as the grammatical operator/lexical predicate distinction. And
note that both are relative notions.)16
This typology correlates with several other important semiotic and social features. First, as a general tendency, the more an intentional status
has a sign of both its mode and content of commitment, the more a sign
is propositional (versus non-propositional), the more a sign is lexical
(versus grammatical), and the more a sign is indexical-symbolic (versus
iconic-indexical), the more the signer can control the expression of its
sign, the more the signer can composes the sign-object relation, and the
more the signer can commit to the interpretant of the sign-object relation.
Insofar as the question of control, composition, and commitment arises
with any semiotic process, one can ask these questions of intentionality.
90
P. Kockelman
In particular, to control the expression of a sign is to control the expression of an intentional role; to compose the relation between a sign and a
object is to compose the relation between an intentional role and an intentional status; and to commit to the interpretant of a sign-object relation is to commit to the intentional attitude of an intentional role-status
relation. For example, one has fewer degrees of control, composition,
and commitment with facial expression than with interjections, with
modal auxiliary verbs than with propositional attitudes, and so forth. Indeed, partially scaling with this typology is a distinction between normative regimentation and causal regimentation: hence, facial expressions will
tend to be more cross-cultural than interjections; and grammatical operators will tend to be more cross-linguistic than propositional attitudes. In
short, this typology of common pairings of intentional statuses with intentional roles correlates with the degree of sharedness (across semiotic
communities) and the degree of sincerity (between expressing of role and
inhabiting of status) of the pair.
5.
91
92
P. Kockelman
93
signs and antecedent and consequent sign events, this is the question of
how iconic-indexical (or iconically overlapping in quality and indexically
related though causality) the embodied sign is with either the antecedent
sign event (I saw him do it) or the consequent sign event (I want to do it).
In short, by attending to the grammar of certain linguistically-encoded
signs of intentional statuses, one has a way of accounting for the genus of
intentionality itself (complement-taking predicates), various species of intentionality (complement-taking predicates grouped as a function of their
relative tightness), and the logic of intentionality (how much causal/ontological overlap there is between a mode of commitment and a content of
commitment). This point has broader implications insofar as understandings of intentionality (as a putative psychological phenomenon) are often
grounded in, if not derived from, these overt linguistic encodings. This
conclusion is surprisingly absent in works by philosophers of Mind, although their data is primarily morphosyntactic (cf. Brentano 1995 [1874];
Ryle 1984 [1949]; Searle 1983). As will be seen in sections 6 and 7, the
lexicalization of modes of commitment is a condition for speakers understanding of intentionality: hence, these facts will have ramifications for
speakers theories of mind insofar as their intuitions about mind are so
often grounded in their experience with language.
94
P. Kockelman
95
these styles is necessarily prior, the former has had explanatory privilege
over the latter in western philosophy and linguistics, while the latter has
been underappreciated and undertheorized (Brandom 1994). In this section, the sign-interpretant approach to semiotics introduced in earlier essays is further articulated in terms of propositionally contentful signs and
interpretants. The key text is Brandoms Making it Explicit, and various
authors whom Brandom is in indebted to or in dialogue with from
Kant, Frege, Wittgenstein, Sellars and Dummett to Anscombe, Davidson, Austin, Grice and Searle. Nonetheless, none of these scholars would
probably agree with precisely this formulation.
In light of these theoretical commitments, there are three basic constituents of the representational whole: observations, assertions, and actions
(see Brandom 1994: chapters 3 and 4). Each of these constituents is a semiotic process, and hence has a sign, an object, and an interpretant. As
with the constituents of the residential whole, the constituents of the representational whole are mainly defined via their objects in this case, intentional statuses. Intentional statuses involve a mode of commitment and
a content of commitment. The content of commitment is just a proposition. And the mode of commitment is a way of relating to the content of
commitment. In this regard, the intentional status, or object-component,
of an assertion is an epistemic commitment (to a propositional content).18
The intentional status of an observation is an empirical commitment (to a
propositional content). And the intentional status of an action is a practical commitment (to a propositional content). When these modes of commitment are lexicalized, they are often called propositional attitudes
in this case, the words believe, perceive, and intend. And when these
modes of commitment are psychologized, they are often called psychological states in this case, belief, perception, and intention. (While
there are other modes of commitment, for present purposes these are the
three most important kinds.)19
If an epistemic, empirical, or practical commitment to a proposition is
an intentional status, it has an intentional role: any enactment of that
commitment to a proposition. To have an epistemic, empirical, or practical commitment to a propositional content, and hence to hold a particular intentional status, is to be committed and entitled to certain modes of
signifying and interpreting in particular, those modes of signifying and
interpreting that logically and causally, or inferentially and indexically,
cohere with ones epistemic, empirical, and practical commitments. To
assert (e.g., utter a declarative sentence), to observe (e.g. attend to a state
of aairs), and to act (e.g., engage in a controlled behavior) are perhaps
the most emblematic roles of these intentional statuses. In particular, to
assert, observe or act is to undertake an epistemic, empirical, or practical
96
P. Kockelman
97
Observation
Assertion
Action
Couched as Mode of
Commitment
Empirical
Epistemic
Practical
Memory
X
Perception
X
Belief
X
X
Intention
Plan
X
X
X
X
X
98
P. Kockelman
99
100
P. Kockelman
101
102
P. Kockelman
103
reason for actions, and hence can count as a reason for the others actions. And, in the case of individuals with the same (group) identity, and
hence the same value(s), insofar as ones identity can provide a reason for
ones actions, it can act as a reason for the others actions. In this way, in
the case of shared roles and shared identities, ones practical commitments
can provide reasons for anothers practical commitments. Indeed, particular identities that purport or attempt to be transcendental identities involve values that all rational people should commit to (e.g., the categorical imperative or the golden rule).31
Finally, just as questions of coherence arose in the residential whole,
they arise in the representational whole. In particular, there are five kinds
of coherence that can be defined in terms of the foregoing discussion:
rational, causal, representational, intersubjective, and sincerity. Rational
coherence (or inferential coherence) is just the degree to which commitments that may stand as reasons or in need of reasons actually do. What
is the reason for ones epistemic commitment, and what is ones epistemic
commitment a reason for? What is the reason for ones practical commitment? And what is ones empirical commitment a reason for? Causal coherence (or indexical coherence) is the degree to which the states of aairs
represented by the propositional content of empirical commitments actually caused the empirical commitment, or the degree to which the states
of aairs represented by the propositional content of practical commitments actually cause the state of aairs. Was a perception caused by a
state of aairs, and was an action causal of a state of aairs? Representational coherence is the degree to which commitments are satisfied.32 This
is not the causality of the connection but the correctness of the connection. Are beliefs true? Are perceptions veridical? Are intentions sated?
Intersubjective coherence is the degree to which intentional statuses attributed are acknowledged, and the degree to which intentional statuses undertaken are attributed. Are ones understanding of ones own intentional
statuses in agreement with others understanding of them? And sincerity
coherence is the degree to which the intentional status undertaken is acknowledged. Does one believe what one asserts, intend what one promises to do, remember what one recounts?
Insofar as the constituents of the representational whole are holistically
governed, these five kinds of coherence can exist (or not) at many dierent levels: representational whole, institutional whole, situational whole,
intersubjective whole, or experiential whole. Finally, by focusing on coherence is not to stress that coherence is unmarked (or the usual everyday
case): the representational whole can be massively incoherent globally
or locally. The emphasis is rather that coherence is a normative question
that exists in (at least) five dimensions. Just as in the case of coherence
104
P. Kockelman
discussed in Residence in the world, to find more coherence than is (socially) warranted is a key feature of fetishization.
7.
105
What is crucial about speech act predicates (e.g., say, ask, order, and
so forth), is that they confer propositional content on illocutionary force.
And just as there are usually only a handful of grammatical operators for
indexing illocutionary force (optatives, exclamatives, imperatives, interrogatives, and declaratives), there may be hundreds of lexical predicates
for referring to it. The movement from illocutionary force (or grammatical operator) to explicit performative (or lexical predicate) is a movement
from closed class to open class. In the case of intentional statuses, as in
the case of speech acts, this process involves a number of important and
interrelated features: conceptualization, semantic fields, language-internal
glossing, metaphorical elaboration, and projection.
First, conceptualization is the process whereby modes of commitment
come to have conceptual content, insofar as the ISPs that refer to them
are implicated (as referring and predicating expressions) in utterances
that have propositional content. Insofar as concepts expressed by ISPs
are the inferentially articulated objects of ISPs, one may inquire into the
conceptual structure of ISPs like belief, intention, and fear. In particular, a number of questions can be posed. Are the conceptual contents of
certain ISPs more basic or primary than the conceptual content of other
ISPs? For example, does knowing necessary depend on believing, but
not vice versa; or does lust necessarily depend on desire, but not vice
versa? Are there basic ISPs ones whose conceptual structures does not
depend on the conceptual structure of other ISPs, but whose conceptual
structure other ISPs depend on? How does the conceptual structure of
such predicates dier as a function of whether the speaker using them is
an expert or not? How should these words be translated or calibrated
across languages, cultures, and eras? Are some concepts found in all languages, cultures, and eras? One can ask about how these concepts are
structured. For example, are emotion concepts structured like a script?
Are there basic level terms? Are expert definitions structured like Aristotelian categories? Finally, one may ask how the conceptual structure of
ISPs relate to the practical content of intentional statuses. For example,
if emotions are structured like a script, how does this script-like structure
relate to roots and fruits of emotional statuses meaning the actual sign
events that lead to them and follow from them?
Second, in the movement from grammatical operator to lexical predicate, there may be a large number of ISPs, constituting a kind of semantic
field of modes of commitment (i.e., a lexicon of mental states), which are
all related to each other via relations like synonymy, antonymy, partonomy, taxonomy, and so forth. In this way, a menagerie of putative mental
kinds acquires a kind of objectivity so far as these ISPs seem both to refer
to concrete things, and to belong to a common genus. For example, just
106
P. Kockelman
as there are dierent kinds of fruit (bananas, apples, oranges) and different kinds of food more generally (fruit, vegetables, etc.), there are different kinds of emotions (say, fear, joy, anger, etc.) and dierent kinds of
intentional statuses more generally (say, the volitive, the cognitive, and
the emotive).
Third, so far as these ISPs have conceptual content, this semantic field
of intentional statuses allows for language-internal glossing. For example,
belief is a kind of knowledge, there are two key components to mind:
emotion and cognition, fear and shame are types of emotion, desire
and belief are basic intentional states, and so on. Peoples understanding
of intentional statuses, or mental states, can be articulated and explicit
rather than just intuitive and implicit. There are dictionaries, and selfhelp books, basic psychology texts, and maxims. Again, a kind of objectivity is introduced so far as speakers can define, and hence regiment and
standardize, the definitions of intentional statuses.
Fourth, these ISPs are often derived through metaphorical elaboration.
For example, among the Qeqchi-Maya (Kockelman 2003b, 2005b),
most ISPs are articulated in terms of relatively concrete processes involving the heart: for the heart to shrink is to become afraid; for the heart to
double is to become conflicted; for the heart to be red is to be jealous; for
something to get lost in the heart is to forget it; and so on. In this way,
lexical constructions expressing relatively abstract concepts (intentional
statuses) are metaphorically articulated in terms of lexical constructions
expressing relatively concrete concepts (color, size, shape, number, etc.).
In this way, relatively novel and abstract concepts can be readily introduced, and readily understood, in terms of the properties of the relatively
old and concrete domain the terms were borrowed from. And, in this
way, inferences appropriate in the concrete domain may be extended to
be appropriate in the abstract domain. This metaphorical construal of
the abstract through the concrete is another process whereby intentional
statuses acquire a kind of objectivity.
And fifth, lexicalization may lead to projection: the process whereby
features belonging to the signs (of objects) are projected onto the objects
(of signs). In regard to the representational whole, projection is the way in
which linguistic or semiotic features of ISPs are understood as ontological
or natural features of the intentional statuses that such ISPs seem to refer
to (cf. Whorf 1956 [1939]). In certain cases, such as explicit metaphor, this
process is relatively trivial: for example, the degree to which one actually
takes ones heart to be red when one is jealous, or to double when one is
conflicted. In other cases, involving grammatical features, this is less trivial: for example, the degree to which one takes intentional statuses to be
ontological states (believe), state-changes (become angry), or activities
107
(think) insofar as the ISPs that refer to these statuses are semantic states,
state-changes, or activities. Indeed, as discussed in section 4, intentionality as a genus-level phenomenon is often phrased (following Brentano) as
object-directedness, and exemplified by listing the ISPs that are all just
complement-taking predicates. That is, the object-directedness of mental
states is related to the complement-takingness of intentional status predicates. And notice how many philosophers will take the intentionality of
mental states to be equal to the intentionality of speech acts, and theorize all the properties of mental states using evidence derived from speech
acts and then take these features to be fundamental to mental states
rather than to speech acts (see Searle 1983 as the canonical example). In
any case, this is yet another process whereby the putative referents of ISPs
acquire a kind of objectivity through the phenomenal, structural, and semantic properties of the signs themselves.
In conjunction with lexicalization (and its attendant features: conceptualization, semantic fields, language-internal glossing, metaphor, and projection) is displacement: the way that ISPs, insofar as they are lexical
predicates (such as nouns and verbs), may take grammatical operators
that displace them in space, time, possibility, and person. That is, ISPs
such as believe, fear, and desire can be attributed to oneself and
others, in the present, past or future, and in actual, possible or counterfactual worlds. For example, one can say I believe that . . . , you believe
that . . . , and she believes that . . . One can say I fear that . . . , I feared
that . . . , and I will fear that . . . And one can say I want to . . . , I may
want to . . . , and I would have wanted to . . . Displacement is a function of the fact that ISPs are operated on by grammatical categories
that are shifters person, tense, mood, and status. These shifters calibrate the spatial-temporal-logical-personal position of the narrated event
relative to the speech event (see Goman 1981 [1979]; Jakobson 1990).
In this way, ISPs allow one to displace the mode of commitment event
from the sign event, or the event of having an intentional status from the
event of indicating that one has it. This giving of the mode of commitment an event-like character (being positioned in space and time, and
being particular to a specific person or a possible world) is another way
in which intentional statuses acquire a kind of objectivity. Displacement is related to several other properties which should be discussed
in detail: tightness, ascription, transparency, meta-intentionality, and
assertability.
First, if one adds to the discussion of displacement the account of tightness oered in section 4, one sees that there are really three events that
may be positioned relative to each other: the sign event (or the event
in which one expresses an utterance that involves an ISP); the mode of
108
P. Kockelman
109
110
P. Kockelman
statuses, involves ISPs that are parts of assertions and hence can both
stand as reasons (for other assertions) and stand in need of reasons (by
other assertions).35 For example, one can ask someone to explain why
they ascribe an intentional status to another person; and one can ascribe
an intentional status to another person to explain why (say, they engaged
in some controlled behavior). In particular, as with any assertion, the
speaker is responsible to justify her entitlement to the epistemic commitment undertaken by that assertion; and the speaker authorizes others to
undertake that epistemic commitment. In this way, questions of discursive responsibility and authority arise as to intentional statuses predicated
of people and properties predicated of intentional statuses. For example,
arguments may arise as to what counts as good evidence for ascribing an
intentional status, or what behavior may be predicted if someone has
been ascribed an intentional status, and hence one may debate what are
rational and irrational intentional statuses given a persons experience.
Such assertions are therefore subject to challenge, justification, argument,
revision, testimony, repetition, inculcation, extirpation, gossip, and so
forth. In this way, assertions ascribing intentional statuses, and the reasons that lead to them and follow from them, can become fodder for public discussions and political interventions. In the next section, these points
will be generalized.
8.
111
112
P. Kockelman
113
114
P. Kockelman
9.
In The semiotic stance, the following example was given to show the
ways in which any interpretative event may give rise to a number of simultaneous signs: upon hearing a gunshot (as a sign), one may be suffused with adrenaline (aective interpretant); one might make a frightened facial expression (relatively non-purposeful energetic interpretant);
one may run over to look what happened (relatively purposeful energetic
interpretant); one might say that scared the hell out of me (representational interpretant); one may never go into that part of the woods again
(ultimate interpretant); and one might forever believe that the woods are
filled with dangerous men (ultimate representational interpretant). This
example was provided to show that most interpretants are not mental
signs, or even subsequent utterances (a` la answers to questions), but various modes of embodied comportment: feelings, (re)actions, assertions,
and habits. And it was noted that all these interpretants are, through
semiotic framing, just signs (or dispositions to signify) that themselves
can be interpreted by others indeed, they are often bundled together
as evidence for a single ascription: Jake must be terrified of the woods.
To this set of interpretants, one may now add the local episteme in
which terror is understood (say, as a psychological entity that is relatively
115
116
P. Kockelman
(and, to some extent, cross-species) set, including anger, fear, disgust, sadness, joy, and surprise.42 Next, irruptive motivational states aect cognitive processes involved in long-term, planned action, and seem to be designed to enforce commitments to strategies that would otherwise be
disrupted by individual calculations of self-interest (see Frank 1988).
These are the most poorly understood; but are essentially complicated ultimate interpretants. Examples of such states are jealousy, guilt, envy,
and shame. Lastly, Griths uses Averills definition of socially-sustained
pretense as a transitory social role . . . that includes an individuals appraisal of the situation, and is interpreted as a passion rather than as an
action (Averill 1980: 312). Thus the aect program of anger is to be
contrasted with the socially-sustained pretense sense of being angry,
which involves a characteristic, but culturally-dependent pattern of behavior that is appropriate in certain situations, and which is thought to
be impossible to control. Socially sustained pretense, then, is just an ultimate (representational) interpretant under another name; and which
comes along with a representational interpretant of the role as relatively
uncontrolled. (And, in general, socially sustained pretence is a covert social construction, in the terms discussed in The semiotic stance.)
Note, then, that although one may be angry as an aect program or
as a socially-sustained pretense or even, perhaps, as an irruptive motivational state, the pathologies of such modalities of anger are distinct (even
if such modalities are referred to with the same term, even if similar conditions may elicit both modalities, even if one modality may influence another, and even if they are culturally valued in similar ways). In this way,
for the purposes of expert reasoning (generalization, induction, etc.),43 it
does not help scholars to group such forms of anger together what one
discovers about one form cannot be used to understand the others (Griffiths 1997). It is for this reason that Griths argues that the category delimited by our everyday concept of emotion does not constitute a natural kind.
Second, assuming that what Griths says is plausible, a key question is
why second-order interpretations, or epistemes, of such disparate domains
take them to belong to a single, unified domain. While most scholars tend
to think emotions have the quality of passivity in contrast to other cognitive phenomena, in a semiotic idiom, one would rather say that semiotic
processes understood in terms of emotion have signs that are relatively
dicult to control, sign-object relations that are relatively dicult to
compose, and interpretants of sign-object relations that are relatively difficult to commit to. Relatedly, insofar as aect programs involve the most
emblematic roles of emotional statuses (that is, facial expressions), and
insofar as aect programs are on the boundary of what is regimented by
117
natural causes versus cultural norms (and hence what is maximally motivated), properties (and theories) of aect programs are easily projected
onto other seemingly emotional phenomena: naturalness, motivation, uncontrollability, and so forth. And relatedly, emotions seem causally articulated, but not logically articulated caught up in indexicality, but
not inference. In this way, one does not demand a reason for them, or invoke them if a reason is demanded. That is, relatively speaking, they fall
out of the inferential articulation, and inter- and intra-personal inheritance (of commitments and entitlements), that was seen to be fundamental to beliefs, perceptions, and intentions.
And finally, the distinction between natural kinds and social constructions is far too simple. As mentioned in The semiotic stance, a distinction between natural constructions and social kinds should be introduced. In particular, a social kind takes into account the relation between
two relations: or how one relatively motivated set of non-propositional
semiotic processes (say, facial expressions as non-purposeful energetic
interpretants) is articulated in terms of one relatively motivated set
of propositional semiotic processes (say, in the spirit of section 4,
complement-taking predicates that denote emotions as representational
interpretants). Such an abstract formulation of a social kind is a way of
grounding social kinds in reflexive semiosis, or the ways in which signers
use one set of signs to interpret and/or regiment the meaning of another
set of signs in this case, the way both lay-speakers and psychologists
gloss the meaning of facial expressions in terms of a vocabulary of emotion words. One might then use the term natural construction to describe
cross-cultural social kinds: or shared patterns of regimentation linking
sets of propositional and non-propositional semiotic processes, or modes
of residence in the world and modes of representation of the world.
If human beings are those entities whose agency is both enabled and
constrained by the fact that their modes of residence in the world are
never commensurate with their modes of representations of the world),
then the relevant locus for cross-cultural comparison should not be some
mode of residence or representation (e.g., comparing their facial expressions, or comparing their emotion vocabulary) but rather a relationship between the two (e.g., comparing one groups interpretation of facial
expressions in terms of their emotional vocabulary with another groups
interpretation of facial expressions in terms of their emotional vocabulary). So far as human-being is constituted by reflexivity, shared modes
of human-being should turn on shared patterns of reflexivity. Natural
constructions and social kinds, then, are a way of formulating crosscultural and culture-specific processes in terms of relations between residence and representation.
118
P. Kockelman
Notes
1. In certain cases, it may just be a concept rather than a proposition, and hence refer to a
referent rather than represent a state of aairs. For example, I hate cheese or I want my
mother.
2. See Haugeland (1998) for a wonderful summary of various understandings of
intentionality.
3. So, for example, Searle will argue that the intentionality of speech acts is derivative of
the intentionality of mental states, and that mental states are pretty much what philosophers like Descartes take them to be: The capacity of speech acts to represent objects
and states of aairs in the world is an extension of the more biologically fundamental
capacities of the mind (or brain) to relate the organism to the world by way of such
mental states as belief and desire, and especially thought and action (1983: vii). And
scholars like Haugeland (1997) and Brandom (1994) will argue that the intentionality
of mental states is derivative of the intentionality of speech acts and, more generally,
that mental states and even speech acts are not what they are traditionally understood to be.
4. Speech acts were treated in The semiotic stance. Here the emphasis is on declarative
utterances.
5. Such an approach radically alters attempts to come to grips with intentionality in terms
of binary distinctions like originary versus derived, or speech act versus mental state,
and such an approach necessarily takes into account empirical research in primatology,
developmental psychology, anthropology, and linguistics.
6. Unlike Residence in the world, in which the organizing principle was dierent things
(the constituents of the residential whole) mediated in similar ways, the organizing
principle here is similar things (the constituents of the representational whole) mediated
in dierent ways.
7. For example, I know you are a husband insofar as 1) I saw the sign-event in which you
were married (e.g., a wedding), or 2) I see the patterns of interaction you have with
your spouse (e.g., exclusive lovemaking, shared credit cards, public intimacy, wedding
rings, and so forth).
8. Indeed, it was noted that, as a function of semiotic framing, embodied signs could be
understood in several ways: first, as an (ultimate) interpretant of another sign; second,
as a (dynamic) object that gives rise to a sign; third, as an (embodied) sign that gives
rise to an interpretant.
9. That is, the various antecedent sign events need not have any sensible properties in
common; and the various consequent sign events need not have any sensible properties
in common.
10. Though one suspects that the longer the latency, the more dicult the inference.
11. This is even true of purchases and functions. For example, from one particular interpretation of an artificed object (someone wields it a particular way), one can infer its
function, and then oer any number of other appropriate interpretants of it.
12. It should be noted that many scholars think our ability to understand psychological
forces comes before our ability to understand physical forces. For example, Collingwood argues that, Causal propositions . . . are descriptions of relations between natural
events in anthropomorphic terms (1972: 322, quoted in Tomasello and Call 1997: 388).
13. Joint attention (in the wide sense of this term) turning to observe what another is
observing or ostending, or observing or ostending so another turns to observe is
the exemplar of this two-part process: interpreting others signs of embodied signs;
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
119
signifying embodied signs for others interpretants. In joint attention, the intentional
role is either an observing position or an ostensive action; the intentional status is the
object of observation or ostension; and the interpretant is a change in observing position. Thus, in joint attention, the intentional status need not have propositional content
(though it can have propositional content for parents and older children); the ground,
or relation between the intentional role and intentional status, is maximally iconicindexical (rather than indexical-symbolic); and the intentional attitude is an energetic
interpretant (though it can be an ultimate (representational) interpretant for parents
and older children). As noted, joint attention is the developmental milestone: nonhuman primates never acquire the ability; and human primates only acquire it at nine
to twelve months of age. For later observational and ostensive behavior, the intentional
attitude can be an ultimate representational interpretant, the ground can be symbolic
(look! or get a load of him), and the intentional status can have propositional content.
Purposes were prior to purchases, functions, statuses, and values; epistemic commitments are prior to empirical and practical commitments; and, somewhat paradoxically,
purposes are prior to epistemic commitments and hence purposeful actions are prior
to assertions (which are, of course, purposeful speech actions!), but assertions are prior
to intentional actions and observations. The following hierarchy emerges. Assertions
are prior to observations and (intentional) actions; (purposeful) actions are prior to affordances, instruments, roles, and identities; and (purposeful) actions are prior to assertions. Regarding consciousness, we might distinguish between merely phanerons (sensations due to incoming sound waves and light waves), experience (sensations paired
with non-propositional semiotic objects), and perception (sensations paired with semiotic objects. And ditto, regarding behavior, we might distinguish between mere movement, purposeful action, and intentional action.
This typology only focuses on intentional roles (as signs) and intentional statuses (as
objects), ignoring intentional attitudes (as interpretants).
And finally, in the realm of relatively non-emblematic roles, it should be stressed that
any mode of comportment (i.e., heeding an aordance, wielding an instrument, undertaking an action, performing a role, or filling an identity) may follow from an intentional status as a consequent sign event (or lead to an intentional status as an antecedent sign event), and hence constitute an intentional role. For example, the action of
walking across a rotting bridge may index a belief that it will hold ones weight, whereas tiptoeing across it may index a fear that it wont. Roles and identities index beliefs,
desires, structures of feeling, and so forth. Roles index knowledge: being a lawyer, a
doctor, a dressmaker, a wine taster, and so forth. Many emotions are inferred by anothers heeding of aordances in non-canonical ways (interpreting alleys as hiding
places), or wielding instruments in non-canonical ways (holding a knife upside down
as if to stab rather than slice). These signs are maximally metonymic: they primarily
index other objects (instruments index functions, actions index purposes, roles index
statuses, etc.), but they come to index intentional statuses by being in frequent contiguity with them precisely by being one of the fruits of that intentional status as an embodied sign. The key point, then, is that the fruits of embodied signs the consequent
sign events are often the best signs, and hence intentional roles, of that embodied
sign, or intentional status.
Here the proposition is given a mental interpretation (as maximally subjective); and the
state of aairs is given a worldly interpretation (maximally objective).
Brandom calls these doxastic commitments.
These need not be lexicalized in any language because they already have the most ubiquitous signs: declarative sentences, directions of attention, and controlled behaviors.
120
P. Kockelman
20. There is of course non-licensed attribution, and non-attributed undertakings: we attribute intentional statuses to people who did not do something that would license it; and
we undertake intentional statuses that people fail to attribute. All this depends on local
understandings of what counts as good evidence for an intentional status. The DSM
IV, for example is one expert account of what licenses a psychiatrist to attribute an intentional status depression, anxiety, and so forth. And, of course, being attributed
such an intentional status, especially if the attributor is an expert, often leads to acknowledging it.
21. As intimated, if there are intentional statuses and intentional roles, then there must be
intentional attitudes or others interpretants of ones intentional status which arise
because of ones intentional role. In particular, most intentional attitudes are just ultimate (representational) interpretants of others or ones own intentional status: treating
others or oneself as if epistemically, empirically, or practically committed to some
proposition, and sanctioning behavior accordingly. That is, intentional statuses, like
objects more generally, are primarily instituted by others attitudes towards them, as
evinced by the sanctioning practices of a community, and as embodied in the dispositions of its members.
22. Epistemic, empirical, and practical commitments are inferentially articulated: if one is
epistemically, empirically, or practically committed to a proposition, one is epistemically, empirically, or practically committed to any other propositions which may be
logically derived from it. Brandom (1994: 168170) characterizes inferential articulation in terms of inheritance of commitments and entitlements. Committive inference is
being committed to one proposition as a consequence of being committed to another
proposition. Permissive inference is being entitled to one proposition as a consequence
of being entitled to another proposition. And incompatible inference is having ones entitlement to a proposition be precluded as a consequence of being committed to another proposition.
23. Sellars (1963) referred to actions as language-exit moves (where position within
language game responded to via nonlinguistic situation), and to observations as
language-entry moves (where nonlinguistic situation responded to be adoption of position within language game), and to assertions or claims as intra-language moves
(where position in language game responded to be adoption of another position in language game).
24. This is Sellars interpretation of Kants maxim that percepts without concepts are
blind.
25. Loosely speaking, having an epistemic commitment caused by a state of aairs is the
rationalist version of Piageian accommodation (or Austins appropriateness); and having a practical commitment cause a state of aairs is the rationalist version of Piagian
assimilation (or Austins eectiveness). That is, perceptions are causally appropriate
and logically eective; intentions are logically appropriate and causally eective.
26. In Brandoms framework (1994: 261), intention is sometimes understood as an intentional status (practical commitment) and sometimes understood as an intentional attitude (acknowledgment of practical commitment). When they are understood as attitudes, intentions are causes: for in a properly trained agent acknowledgment of
practical commitment reliable causally elicits performances. This then is inferentialisms answer to the question of how mind aects body.
27. In the tradition of Anscombe (1957), Davidson (1980) argues that a performance (or
controlled behavior) is an action (under any description) if it is intentional under some
description. He argues that it is intentional under some description if that description
figures as the conclusion of a piece of practical reasoning that exhibits the agents
28.
29.
30.
31.
32.
33.
34.
35.
36.
121
reasons for doing it. And he oers an account of primary reasons (e.g., a belief plus a
pro-attitude) to explain what it is for a reason to rationalize a controlled behavior according to a practical inference. Phrasing this in the idiom introduced here, a controlled behavior is intentional (under some description) and an action (under any description) insofar as it is the acknowledgment or self-attribution of a practical
commitment. And an intentional action is rational insofar as it stands as the conclusion
of an inference turning on an epistemic commitment and a pro-attitude (Brandom
1994: 233, 255).
Even Freud was an attempt to use desire to rationalize (unintentional) action. That is,
just as (saited) desire may be used to rationalize intentional actions, (frustrated) desires
may be used to rationalize unintentional actions.
To make this point explicit, note the following example: to attribute to an individual a
preference for staying dry is just to take inferences of this form (only remaining in the
car will keep me dry, so I will remain in the car), as entitlement preserving; and is to
license pattern of inferences. And to endorse such a pattern is to implicitly attribute
preference to individual that could be explicitly attributed by undertaking commitment
to ascriptional claim: A wants to stay dry (Brandom 1994: 248).
Crucially, Davidson (1980) thinks reasons are causes: primary reasons rationalize actions, first by providing reasons for them and second by serving to bring them about.
In contrast, Brandom thinks Davidson conflated commitment and entitlement to that
commitment: one can act intentionally without having reasons to do so; and one may
have a reason to act, and have an intention to act, but not act. For Brandom, the
causal nature of statuses happens because of attitudes towards statues insofar as statuses determine what roles are proper. In this way, the only access statuses have to the
causal order is through the attitudes of signers (1994: 260). What observable states of
aairs causally elicits in perception, is attitudes acknowledgments of empirical commitments; and what attitudes (acknowledgment of practical commitments) causally elicits in action is the production of performance. This is what it means to say that a performance must not only be caused by an intention, but be caused by it in the right way.
In sum, exhibiting a bit of practical reasoning rationalizes practical commitment; accepting a practical inference as entitling someone to practical commitment requires
endorsing inference as permissively good (but can be defeased by incompatible commitments), but doesnt require that scorekeeper endorse premise (which would pick
out objective entitlement or unconditional ought) (Brandom 1994: 253).
In general, there can be failures of presupposition (regarding the existence of a referent)
and failures of foci (regarding the applicability of predicate to a referent).
As Brandom notes, Thought of in this way, the distinction between de dicto and de re
should not be understood to distinguish two kinds of belief or even belief-contents, but
two kinds of ascription in particular two dierent styles in which the content of the
commitment ascribed can be specified (1994: 503).
In certain cases say, via reported speech this can happen: she said ouch!
As Brandom puts it, The introduction of a sentential operator that functions as S believes that . . . or S is committed to the claim that . . . does in English make it possible not merely implicitly or in practice to take someone to be committed to a claim, but
explicitly to say that someone is committed to a claim, and to which claim. The explicit
is the claimable, what can be given as a reason and have reasons demanded for it; ascriptional locutions make implicit attributions explicit as the contents of claims (1994:
498).
Finally, we might ask what are some of the key topics, questions, stakes, theories,
methodologies, methods, epistemic practices, and ethical practices of an episteme, and
122
37.
38.
39.
40.
41.
42.
P. Kockelman
what have they been in its past? These questions can, of course, be asked of any episteme; and part of knowing the history and culture of an episteme is knowing how the
answers to these questions, normatively speaking, change or remain the same over its
lifetime. Indeed, just as a large part of doing convincing research is knowing which of
these norms to adhere to, a large part of doing creative research is knowing which of
these norms to break.
Though, it may also be related to Wittgensteins form of life, Kuhns paradigms, Canguilhems history of epistemology, and latter-day science studies scholars who are immersed in and reacting to these ideas: Latour, Simon, Shan, Woolgar, and so forth.
This would involve related ideas such as the historical ontology of Hacking (2002);
though Hacking tends to focus on theory and intervention (see, for example, his
1983 monograph entitled Representing and Intervening).
Experiments with American and European middle- and upper-class children has offered a fairly consistent model of Western folk psychology. For example, there are
systematic taxonomic and partonomic interrelations among various mental states
(DAndrade 1995; Rips and Conrad 1989; and Wellman 1990). There is a notion of
the mind as distinct from the body, yet held in the brain and equivalent to the self
(Johnson 1987). There is a notion of the privateness of mental states, and their representational capacity (DAndrade 1995; Wellman 1990). There is a notion of real entities able to be distinguished from mental entities on the basis of sensory evidence, public existence, and temporal consistency (Wellman and Estes 1986). Some studies show
that there is a tendency to personify the mind, such that children move towards a conception of the mind as an independent entity (Wellman and Hickling 1994). And studies
show that subjects think that people can and should know the mental states of others.
These studies accord with the number of mental state terms in English there are over
200 word devoted to the emotions alone (Wallace and Carson 1973) and with the
propensity to use such terms in describing the behavior of others (Friestad and Wright
1995).
It should be stressed that one cannot account for emotions without simultaneously offering an account of selfhood and agency the former, as what is at stake in an interpretation; and the second as determining emotions as those mental entities over which
one has relatively little agency, as the western ethnotheory often has it.)
Indeed, most sophisticated accounts of emotions do not see them as internal states,
but as the relatively systematic bundling of some combination of the following components: eliciting situation; physiological change; reflexive signal; relatively controlled response; subjective feeling; and second-order interpretations of this ensemble of components as relatively uncontrollable, subjective, and natural. As may be seen with this
example, The semiotic stance naturally incorporates these components, and goes far
beyond them. Notice how the attempt to include appraisals in understandings of emotion is usually theorized as a way of bring concepts, or cognition, back into our understanding of aective phenomena. Notice that only representational interpretants require concepts per se; yet all interpretants require meaningfulness.
Natural kinds are categories that supposedly correspond to some real distinctions in
nature and around which theories are constructed (Griths 1997: 171).
Note that while aect programs may be cross-culturally shared, in dierent cultures
they may nonetheless have distinct behavioral entailments, co-occurring signs, modes
of interpretation, and classes of eliciting objects. In sum, while aect programs themselves may very well be natural kinds, they at best serve as a cross-culturally distributed
set of stereotypic physiological responses that individual cultures may experience, elaborate, and interpret in their own locally specific ways. To paraphrase what Sahlins
123
(1977) said regarding Berlin and Kays (1969) seminal work on basic color terms, such
programs are not the imperatives of culture, but its implements.
43. Though perhaps for the purposes of local reasoning, a point not considered by such
authors.
References
Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.
Austin, J. L. (2003 [1955]). How to Do Things with Words, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Averill, James R. (1980). A constructivist view of emotion. In Emotion: Theory, Research,
and Experience, R. Plutchik and H. Kellerman (eds.), 305340. New York: Academic
Press.
Berlin, Brent and Kay, Paul (1969). Basic Color Terms: Their Universality and Evolution.
Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Brandom, Robert (1994). Making it Explicit: Reasoning, Representing, and Discursive Commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brentano, Franz (1995 [1874]). Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint. New York: Routledge.
Colapietro, Vincent M. (1989). Peirces Approach to the Self: A Semiotic Perspective on
Human Subjectivity. Albany: Albany State University of New York Press.
Collingwood, R. J. (1972). Essay on Metaphysics. Chicago: Gateway.
DAndrade, Roy (1995). The Development of Cognitive Anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Darwin, Charles (1965 [1872]). The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Davidson, Donald (1980). Actions, reasons, and causes. In Essays on Actions and Events, 3
20. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dennett, Daniel C. (1978). Intentional systems. In Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on
Mind and Psychology, 322. Montgomery/Vermont: Bradford Books.
Dummett, Michael (1994). The legacy of Brentano. In Origins of Analytic Philosophy, 28
42. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Ekman, Paul (1982). Emotions in the Human Face. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Frank, R. H. (1988). Passions within Reason: The Strategic Role of the Emotions. New York:
Norton.
Friestad, M. and Wright, P. (1995). Persuasion knowledge: Lay peoples and researchers beliefs about the psychology of advertising. Journal of Consumer Research 22, 6274.
Givon, Talmy (1980). The binding hierarchy and the typology of complements. Studies in
Language 4 (3), 333377.
Goman, Erving (1981 [1979]). Footing. In Forms of Talk, 124159. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Grice, Paul (1989). The causal theory of perception. In Studies in the Ways of Words, 224
247. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Griths, Paul E. (1997). What Emotions Really Are. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hacking, Ian (1983). Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of
Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
(2002). Making up people. In Historical Ontology, 99114. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
124
P. Kockelman
Haugeland, John (1998). The intentionality all-stars. In Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind, 127170. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Jakobson, Roman (1990). Shifters and verbal categories. In On Language, L. R. Waugh and
M. Monville-Burston (eds.), 386392. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
James, William (1950 [1890]). The scope of psychology. In The Principles of Psychology, 1
11. New York: Dover.
Johnson, Mark (1987). The Body in the Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Kockelman, Paul (2002). Stance and subjectivity among the Qeqchi-Maya: Minding language and measuring labor under neoliberal globalization. Unpublished PhD dissertation,
University of Chicago.
(2003a). The meaning of interjections in Qeqchi-Maya: From emotive reaction to social
and discursive action. Current Anthropology 44 (4), 467490.
(2003b). The interclausal relations hierarchy in Qeqchi-Maya. International Journal of
American Linguistics 69 (1), 2548.
(2005a). The semiotic stance. Semiotica 157 (1/4), 233304.
(2005b). Stance and subjectivity. Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 14 (2), 127150.
Lillard, A. (1998). Ethnopsychologies: Cultural variations in theories of mind. Psychological
Bulletin 123 (1), 332.
Premack, D. and Woodru, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4, 515526.
Rips, L. J. and Conrad, F. G. (1989). Folk psychology of mental activities. Psychological
Review 96 (2), 187207.
Ryle, Gilbert (1984 [1949]). The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Sahlins, Marshall (1977). Colors and cultures. In Symbolic Anthropology, J. L. Dolgin (ed.),
165180. New York: Columbia University Press.
Searle, John R. (1983). Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sellars, Wilfrid (1963). Science, Perception, and Reality. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
(1997 [1956]). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Silverstein, Michael (1981). The limits of awareness ( Sociolinguistic Working Paper 84).
Austin: Southwest Educational Development Laboratory.
(1993). Of nominatives and datives: Universal grammar from the bottom up. In Advances
in Role and Reference Grammar, Robert D. Van Valin (ed.), 465498. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Tomasello, Michael (1999). The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Tomasello, Michael and Call, Josep (1997). Primate Cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.
Tomasello, Michael, Call, Josep, and Hare, Brian (2003). Chimpanzees understand psychological states the question is which ones and to what extent. Trends in Cognitive Science
7 (4), 153156.
Van Valin, Robert D. Jr. and LaPolla, Randy J. (1997). Syntax: Structure, Meaning, and
Function. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wallace, A. F. and Carson, M. T. (1973). Sharing and diversity in emotion terminology.
Ethos 1, 129.
Wellman, H. M. (1990). The Childs Theory of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.
Wellman, H. M. and Estes, D. (1986). Early understanding of mental entities: A reexamination of childhood realism. Child Development 57, 910923.
125