2011economies of Abandonment PDF
2011economies of Abandonment PDF
2011economies of Abandonment PDF
A ian W
Alger
War
ar, -
ar,
Bretton W
Woods, ; Marshall Plan, ; Gold Standard Collapse,
Opec Embargo,
Nonaligned
Movement,
US Withdraws
from
om V
Vietnam,
Asian Financial
Crisis,
Berlin W
Wall
Falls,
Israel, ; Suez,
March
ch on W
Washington, ; Stonewalll R
Riots, ;
; W
Wounded Knee,
Keynesian Economics
Neo-Liberalism
Cultural Recognition
Economies ofAbandonment
Social Belonging and Endurance in Late Liberalism
A Qaedaa A
AlAttacks US,
Financial Markets
Collapse,
Elizabeth A.Povinelli
Anarcho Liberalism
Civilizational Securitization
Australian : c, ; c, ; c, ; c,
2011 Duke University Press. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper . Designed by Jennifer Hill. Typeset in Arno Pro by Tseng Information
Systems, Inc. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data appear on the last printed
page of this book.
To Nuki Bilbil
May she rest in peace
Even if she is not
Where I wish she were
Contents
Preface
ix
Acknowledgments xiii
Introduction
One
Two
Three
Road Kill
Ethical Substance, Exhaustion, Endurance101
Four
Events of Abandonment131
Five
Conclusion
Notes 193
211
Index 225
Bibliography
Preface
I have heard what the talkers were talking, the talk of the
beginning and the end,
But I do not talk of the beginning or the end.
There was never any more inception than there is now,
Nor any more youth or age than there is now;
And will never be any more perfection than there is now,
Nor any more heaven or hell than there is now.
Out of the dimness opposite equals advance, always
substance and increase, always sex,
Always a knit of identity, always distinction, always a
breed of life.
WAlT WhITmAN, Song of myself
Preface
enduring difference. Ethnographic material is culled from a variety of personal and professional relationships I have had in the United States and
Australia and culminates as one moves through the chapters. This material is situated in a variety of discursive fields including political theory
and philosophy, anthropology, and cultural and legal studies, and also
through academic and activist thought and writing. One reader of this
text described it as austere ethnography, a description meant to indicate
a move away from a now longstanding commitment in anthropology to
thick description. I myself like a term that James Clifford used, during a
dissertation hearing, sociography, to describe a way of writing the social
from the point of view of social projects.
But this way of writing ethnographicallyor sociographicallyalso
presupposes an entire corpus of previous and projected writerly projects.
Although certainly able to stand on its own, this book is the second in a
series of books I am writing under the broad rubric of Dwelling in Late
Liberalism. The Empire of Love was the first volume in this series and a
subsequent volume will focus on an augmented reality project that this
book mentions, if only glancingly.
Economies of Abandonment is conceptualized as an argument that
builds across chapters, rather than as a set of thematically related essays.
Material elaborated in an initial chapter is referred to in subsequent chapters. Material acting to support a point in one chapter is elaborated and
made the center of a subsequent chapter. I have tried to make each chapter as self-contained as possible, which means that there is some repetition of information. And I have tried to allow for innovative readings, say,
starting with chapter 3 on ethical substance and moving back to chapter 2
on recognition, camouflage, and espionage. Nevertheless, this is a book
written to unravel an argument step by step. Two works of fiction frame
this book: Ursula Le Guins The Ones Who Walk Away from Omelas
and Charles Burnetts 1977 film, The Killer of Sheep, the one written loosely
within the genre of science fiction, the other, a quasi-documentary of the
Watts neighborhood, the scene of the infamous 1968 black uprising. Le
Guins story sets the framework for the introduction and first two chapters, Burnetts film for the last three. Two other divisions mirror this one.
First, while gesturing to the critical importance of eventfulness and ethical substance chapters 1 and 2 focus more heavily of the use of tense in
Preface
xi
Acknowledgments
This book emerged from the generosity of conversation and life. I would like first to thank
members of the Karrabing Indigenous Corporation, in particular Linda Yarrowin, Rex Sing, Rex
Edmunds, Cecilia Lewis, Trevor Bianamu, and
Robyn Lane. Also essential were colleagues at the
School for Social and Policy Research at Charles
Darwin University, especially conversations with
Tess Lea and David Lamb; the Institute for Public Knowledge at New York University, especially
Akhil Bilgrami, Craig Calhoun, Francis Ferguson,
xiv
Acknowledgments
Acknowledgments
xv
Algerian War, -
Bretton Woods, ; Marshall Plan, ; Gold Standard Collapse,
Opec Embargo,
Nonaligned
Movement,
US Withdraws
from Vietnam,
Asian Financial
Crisis,
Berlin Wall
Falls,
Israel, ; Suez,
Keynesian Economics
Neo-Liberalism
Cultural Recognition
Anarcho Liberalism
Civilizational Securitization
Australian : c, ; c, ; c, ; c,
Introduction
Introduction
for. But it is, nevertheless, dependent on a childs being naked and constrained in a cramped space and being covered with festering sores from
sitting in its own excrement, and on these facts being known by all Omelas inhabitants. Some actually visit the childs fetid chamber. Some have
merely heard of it since they were children themselves. But every member of Omelas must assume some relationship among his or her present
personal happiness, their solidarity with the present happiness of the millions inhabiting Omelas, and the present suffering of one small human
being. A child is being beaten, and unlike Freud no one in Omelas can
pretend it is mere psychic fantasy. Some offer facile excuses for preferring their happiness to the childs. At this point, they reason, the child is
too degraded and imbecile to know any real joy. She is so destroyed and
so used to her destitution that liberating her would do more harm than
good. Others face the true paradox. For them their tears at the bitter injustice dry when they begin to perceive the terrible justice of reality, and
to accept it.1 Others leave Omelas. Not en masse. They leave one by one:
The place they go is a place even less imaginable to most of us than the
city of happiness. I cannot describe it at all. It is possible that it does not
exist. But they seem to know where they are going, the ones who walk
away from Omelas.2
The Ones Who Walk Away from Omelas was conceived as a fictional
engagement with William Jamess The Moral Philosopher and the Moral
Life and more broadly to the moral philosophy of American pragmatism,
of which James was a leading voice. James begins his essay with the position that there can be no final truth in ethics any more than in physics,
until the last man has had his experience and said his say.3 This ethical
position was deeply influenced by the semiotic musings of Jamess colleague Charles Sanders Peirce. More specifically, James broadly borrows
Peirces understanding of the temporal and modal structure of the final
interpretant and applies it to the question of ethical truth. Ethical readings of the kind that interested James have a specific temporal and modal
structure; a variant of the future anterior. Ethical readings are the toward
which the actual, as the sum total of all interpretants, tends.4 But this
actual is already in the durative present. The future anterior is what will
have been the ultimate truth, good, and justice of this existing action,
event and experience, after every last man has had his experience and his
say. This truth might only become available with the point of view of the
last man. But this last man is supposedly simply standing where we are
standing, seeing what is front of our eyes but outside our field of vision.
Regardless of her agreement or disagreement with James, Le Guins
account of temporality, eventfulness, and ethics opens a productive avenue for critically engaging the affective attachments and practical relationship of subjects to the unequal distribution of life and death, of hope
and harm, and of endurance and exhaustion in late liberalism, a phrase
I will elaborate below. One reading of Le Guin would alter three ways
in which liberal subjects normally understand and experience the social
tense, eventfulness, and ethical substance of thriving, suffering, and lethality. First, as opposed to those who would read ethics from the perspective of future ends, this reading of Le Guin would insist that there
is no horizon in which a changed material version of this child could be
incorporated into the material and emotional good of the city without
that good being compromised. The ethical nature of the relationship between the residents of Omelas and the child in the broom closet cannot,
therefore, be deferred to some future anterior perspectivewhat will
have been the positive outcome of this suffering from the perspective of
a future interpreter we cannot as of yet know. In late liberalism, as opposed to Omelas, the future anterior is sometimes marked by the perfective, sometimes the imperfective. But in both cases the ethical nature of
present action is interpreted from the point of view of a reflexive future
horizon and its cognate discourses, such as that of sacrificial love.5 The
childs suffering disappears when seen from the perspective of what it will
have beenor been for. Because Le Guin refuses to grant to Omelas the
truth of this ethical point of view, the ethical relationship that links the
citizens of Omelas to the child in the broom closet cannot be removed
from the durative present of her suffering. Hers is not so much a sacrifice in the city as an organ of the city. To be sure, whether the political life
of the city should be based on an alternative ethical tensethe durative
presentand whether the question of politics should bear any relation to
the question of ethics are important, if separate, questions that I explore
later.
Second, the nature of the suffering that interests Le Guin is ordinary,
chronic, and cruddy rather than catastrophic, crisis-laden, and sublime.
Introduction
Granted the child in the broom closet is covered in sores and, every so
often, is given a kick. But for the most part her misery is a quieter form of
abjection, despair, impoverishment, and boredom. She is not a part of a
system of disposability because she cannot be disposed with. In the oscillation between this state of neither great crisis nor final redemption there
is nothing spectacular to report. Indeed, nothing happens that rises to the
level of an event let alone a crisis. The small childs life-as-suffering will
drift across a series of quasi-events into a form of death that can be certified as due to the vagary of natural causes. As a result any ethical impulse dependent on a certain kind of event and eventfulnessa crisis
flounders in this closet. How does one construct an ethics in relation to
this kind of dispersed suffering?
Finally, any goods generated from the kind of misery found in this
broom closet must be seen as socially cosubstantial as well as temporally nontransferable. The happiness of citizens of Omelas is substantially within the small childs unhappiness; their well-being is part of a
larger mode of corporeal embodiment in which her carnal misery is a
vital organ; the usefulness of the child is inseparable from the distension
of her body through the bodies of the citizens of Omelas. And these are
not metaphors. She and they are not like a shared body; they are a shared
body. Or, as I have put it previously, they share a mutual, if distributed,
form of enfleshment.6 The solidarity the citizens of Omelas share with each
other must, as of necessity, loop through her. As a result, the ethical imperative is not to put oneself in the childs place, nor is it to experience the
anxiety of potentially being put in her place. Le Guins fiction rejects this
ethics of liberal empathy. Instead, the ethical imperative is to know that
your own good life is already in her broom closet, and as a result, either
you must create a new organization of enfleshment by compromising on
the goods to which you have grown accustomed (and grown accustomed
to thinking of as yours including the health of your body) or admit that
the current organization of enfleshment is more important to you than
her suffering.7
That Le Guin allows some people to walk away from Omelas rather
than stay and fight its injustice may seem a cop-out. That Le Guin is unable to describe the place they go seems even more of one. How to come
to grips with Le Guins refusal, or inability, to provide a substantive alter-
Introduction
My analysis of the social worlds and projects that provide the sociographic
core of this book emerges from very longstanding friendshipsfor instance a twenty-six-year relationship with friends in north Australiaand
much shorter onesI have been in deep conversation with members of
alternative queer projects for only six years. Throughout this book I discuss how my friends in Australia have been working on an augmented
reality project as a way of maintaining within late liberalism an ethical relationship to themselves and their country. My discussions of alternative
projects of embodied sociality have a more diffused focus. But what interests this book about these social worlds is fourfold. First, I am interested
in them as projects, a term that is loosely modeled on the meaning that
the moral philosopher Bernard Williams gave to the concepts of moral
projects and actions. Responding to utilitarian understandings of the
good, Williams argues that moral projects cannot be measured, as many
utilitarian approaches would have it, by assessing happiness or pleasure,
or any action for that matter, from the point of view of a systemized impartial perspective. Happiness, goodness, and justice are never judged by
a set of impartial decisions or from the perspective of the view from nowhere.10 And this is because happiness depends on a person being taken
up or involved in any of a vast range of projects and commitments.11 To
be taken up and to be involved has a much stronger meaning for Williams than to be merely interested in something. Projects are the thick
subjective background effects of a life as it has been lived; and these thick
subjectivities provide the context of moral and political calculation. All
judgments and views always occur within thick and particular life projectsa point most anthropologists would take as axiomatic. But it is also
a point that foregrounds the fact that in any given social world, multiple
moral and political calculations proliferate because no one ever lives the
exact same projectin Omelas, for instance, the good life would be the
contested space between the child in the broom closet and each and every
citizens project, including those who decide to remain in the city and
those who walk away from it.
Whereas Williams is interested in projects from the point of view of
individual moral agents, I am interested in them from the point of view
of the social worlds in which these projects are situated, and not all of
these equally. I am interested in those social projects that attempt to capacitate an alternative set of human and posthuman worlds. (The view
from nowhere is from this perspective a social project that has as its
background assumption that background assumptions can be emptied
out.) When I say I am interested in social projects I am gesturing to specific arrangements (agencements) that extend beyond simple human sociality or human beings. As will become clear, a social project is dependent on a host of interlocking concepts, materials, and forces that include
human and nonhuman agencies and organisms. Focusing primarily on
the human dimension of these social projects, critical social theory has
used many phrases to describe these worlds. Michael Warner has used
the term counterpublics, Charles Taylor new social imaginaries, and
Nancy Frazer subaltern counterpublics. I have used the phrase radical
worlds.12 Much earlier, Foucault coined the term heterotopia to refer
to a set of countersites (sortes de contre-emplacements) that are real localized sites in the world and yet contested inversions of the world (je suis
l-bas, l o je ne suis pas).13 Some of these worlds may, from one perspective, seem more voluntarist than others. Alternative spiritual publics
that I discuss in subsequent chapters might seem to be this sort of voluntarist counterpublic. It may appear that members of these social projects
choose to place themselves within this or that alternative world. Others
may seem to be structurally located within normative worlds in such a
way that their everyday actions are heterotopic whether they intend them
to be or not. My Indigenous friends in Australia would seem good candidates for this less voluntary form of the otherwise. But I hope the following chapters give lie to such simple divisions of the willand put serious
pressure on the quasi-mystical concept of the will itselfbut there is
nevertheless a discursive power of the fantasy of the will and its volitions
that needs to be noted.
In any case, we have social worlds, social projects, and individuated
Introduction
ideas one has, whether one considers these ideas in their objective extrinsic reality or in their formal intrinsic reality.18 Ideas and affects are two
kinds of modes of thought that differ in nature. An idea represents
something while an affect does not. An affect is not nothing, but it is also
not something in the same way as an extrinsic or intrinsic idea. An affect
is a force of existing (vis existendi) that is neither the realized thing (an
idea), nor the accomplishment of a thing (an act, potentia agendi). This
perspective on the force of existing is clearly engaging Spinozas claim
that things, finite and determinate kinds of existence, strive (conatus) to
persevere in their being. For Deleuze, the perpetual variation between vis
existendi and potentia agendibetween striving to persevere and any
actual idea or action that emerges from this strivingprovides a space of
potentiality where new forms of life can emerge. But it is exactly in this
ontotheoretical spacing that a different, sociological question emerges:
How do new forms of social life maintain the force of existing in specific
social spacings of life? How do they endure the effort it takes to strive to
persevere? And how in answering these questions do new, if not ontotheoretical, then political and ethical concerns emerge?
The question of how new possibilities of life are able to maintain their
force of existence in specific organizations of social space becomes especially acute in the wake of Giorgio Agambens reflections on Deleuzes
immanent philosophy and his own work on the biopolitical. In his reflections on Deleuzes Immanence: A Life, Agamben calls for the development of a coherent ontology of potentiality (dynamis) that would upend
the primacy of actuality (energeia).19 For Agamben potentiality has a dual
nature: while the actual can only be, the potential can be or not be.20 And
it is exactly within this ontological duality of the potential that new possibilities of life are sheltered. But for Agamben, not all potentialities have
the same potential when it comes to the kinds and degrees of difference
necessary to disturb current biopolitical formations. In the difficult last
few sections of Homo Sacer, Agamben turns to a series of uncertain and
nameless terrains where life and death enter zones of indistinction.21
The American comatose patient Karen Quinlan exemplifies such spaces:
Karen Quinlans bodywhich wavers between life and death according
to the progress of medicine and the changes in legal decisionsis a legal
being as much as it is a biological being. A law that seeks to decide on life
10
Introduction
is embodied in a life that coincides with death.22 Death and life, far from
having become more exact, now [oscillate] from one pole to other with
the greatest indeterminacy.23 Failing to be actual, death and life become
pure potential. They can be or not be. And it is in these maximally intensified zones of oscillation and indeterminacy that new forms of life and
worlds will emerge and the ways and the forms of a new politics must
be thought.24 But rather than answering our question of how new forms
of social life can survive the perpetual variation of being, Agambens
examples intensify it. How can new forms of life, let alone the political
thought they might foster, persevere in such spaces? How can new social
worlds endure the wavering of death that defines these spaces?25 Indeed, so unlikely are the possibilities of new life surviving in these spaces
that, cribbing off Brian Massumi, we might describe instances of survival
as moments of miraculization.26
The social projects that interest this book may not have the force to act
in the sense of making anything like a definitive event occur in the world
(becoming a counterpublic is an achievement), but they exist, nevertheless, in the Spinozan sense of persisting in their being. And insofar as they
do, these alternative worlds maintain the otherwise that stares back at us
without perhaps being able to speak to us.
But if the point is not to discover the eternal or the universal, but to
find the singular conditions under which something new is produced,
then two specific aspects of social life need to be emphasized. This is of
special concern to those trying to write an anthropology of the otherwise.
On the one hand, attempting to address the question of the endurance,
let alone the survival, of alternative forms of life in the gale force of curtailing social winds opens a set of new ethical and political questions. If
the possibilities of new forms of life dwell and are sheltered within the
variation between the force of existing and the power of acting within
these intensified zones of being and not being, then what does immanent
critique demand of those who live in these zones? This problem becomes
particularly clear if we think of potentiality as the ethical substance of
immanent critique. If, as Michel Foucault defined it, ethical substance
is the prime material (matire principale) of moral reflection, conduct,
and evaluation, then the ethical substance of immanent critique would
be intensified potentiality, insofar as intensified potentiality is the ma-
terial on which ethical work (travail thique) is carried out. But this ethical work is distributed across different social groups. Thus it is important
to note, again following Foucaults reading of the use of pleasure among
the Greeks and the practice of critique more generally, that pleasure and
critique are generally available materials and practices, irrespective of the
fact that only some people make use of them. But the general availability
of intensified potential doesnt seem to be equally available in the same
way. Certainly all subjects exist in the variation between vis existendi and
potentia agendi and between modes of being and not being. But the intensity of this variation and its zoning are neither uniform nor uniformly
distributed. As a result a gap seems to open between those who reflect on
and evaluate ethical substance and those who are this ethical substance.
Thus, on the other hand, we need to understand, first, that late liberalism is
a social projectit is a metadiscourse that aggregates aspects of the social
worldand we need to understand, second, how this aggregation occurs
through and across other social projects and their material supports.
This book argues that a key means by which late liberalism aggregates
social worlds is through figurations of tense, eventfulness, and ethical
substance. So let me say a few things about how I understand the tense,
eventfulness, and ethical substance in late liberalism, beginning with
tense.
Tense, Eventfulness, Ethical Substance
The aspect of tense that interests me is broadly social rather than strictly
linguistic. I am interested in the social divisions of tense that help shape
how social belonging, abandonment, and endurance are enunciated and
experienced within late liberalism. From a grammatical perspective, tense
and event are themselves difficult to disambiguate. Metapragmatic approaches to discourse, for instance, understand tense and event to emerge
from the intersection between what is being narrated and the act of narrating itthe time during or over which the state or action denoted by
a verb occurs. In the grammatical past, for instance, the event being narrated is marked as prior to the act of narrating, while in the grammatical present tense the event being narrated coincides with the act of narrating it. Languages demonstrate a wide variety of ways of configuring
11
12
Introduction
the temporal relationship between what is being narrated and the act
of narrating it.27 French marks this relationship in a different way than
does English; English in a different way than the Australian Indigenous
language Emiyenggal. Emile Benveniste noted long ago, In one way or
another a language always makes a distinction of tense. Sometimes, as
in French and English, a past and future is separated by a present;
sometimes, as in various Amerindian languages, the preterite-present
is opposed to a future or a present future or distinguished from a past.
But for Benveniste what is shared across these differences is a line of
separation whose reference is the present, a time that Benveniste puts
in scare quotes to emphasize its performative nature.28 Thus, how various
narratives of belonging, abandonment, and endurance are socially enunciated and experienced depends in part on the ways that the relationship between the time of narration and the event narrated, or, put in another way, the event of narration and the narrated event, is grammatically
marked. What Le Guin is doing, for instance, is arguing that the event of
the childs misery cannot be narrated as if it were in the past perfect or the
future anterior. The grammar of the childs misery must be written in the
durative present.
What interests me is how these strictly grammatical figurations are absorbed into other discourses, affective attachments, and practices of late
liberalism. Take, for instance, teleological and eschatological discourses.
Grammars might differently mark the temporal relationship between
what is being narrated and the act of narrating it, constituting in the process the linguistic event, but in late liberalism this linguistic variation is
inflected by a shared teleological discourse that apprehends events as
[the] realization of an already given end or telos and a shared eschatological discourse that waits for extreme or ultimate moments and
events which immediately precede or accompany the end of history
and its reversal into eternity.29 In other words, the differences in narrative tense are metadiscursively refigured through teleological and eschatological discourses such as sacrifice and sacrificial love. As chapter 5
unpacks in more detail, discussions of sacrificial love can figure death,
whether an individuals death in war or a generations loss in structural
readjustment, as best understood from the perspective of the redemptive
end from which this death gains its meaning.
13
14
Introduction
ment. Crises and catastrophes are kinds of events that seem to demand, as
if authored from outside human agency, an ethical response. Not surprisingly then, these kinds of events become what inform the social science
of suffering and thriving, the politics of assembly and dispersal, and the
socially constituted senses of the extraordinary and everyday, as the work
of Veena Das and Joo Biehl have helped make clear.32 What techniques,
such as statistics, allow nonperceptual quasi- events to be transformed
into perceptual events, even catastrophes? What are the temporal and
epistemological presuppositions that foreclose an anthropology of ordinary suffering and thus an anthropological understanding of the dynamic
by which extraordinary events of violence are folded into everyday routinesand visa versa? How and why do things move from potentiality to
eventfulness to availability for various social projects? How might we turn
from an ontology of potentiality to a sociology of potentiality in which
potentiality is always embodied in specific social worlds? How can we
grasp some of the qualities of a material object that is nevertheless a discursive object? How can we talk about subject-effects and object-effects
without making materiality disappear or making its different manifestations irrelevant to the unequal organization of social life? And finally, how
can we simultaneously recognize that discourse makes objects appear,
that it does so under different material conditions, and that the matter
that matters forth from discourse is not identical to discourse?
These questions become especially pertinent when we turn to the
problem of ethical substance in late liberalism. If we take seriously Le
Guins narrative of the cosubstantiality of bodies in Omelas, then how
should we understand the relationship between ethical substance and
critical theory? Attempting to address the question of the endurance, let
alone the survival, of alternative forms of life in the gale force of curtailing social winds opens a set of new ethical and political questions. As
noted above, if the possibilities of new forms of life dwell and are sheltered within the variation between the force of existing and the power of
acting within these intensified zones of being and not being, then what
does immanent critique demand of those who live in these zones? This
problem becomes particularly clear if we think of potentiality as the ethical substance of immanent critique.
When I use the phrase ethical substance, I am clearly thinking here of
15
16
Introduction
chapters, is that the ethical substance of immanent critical theory is embodied potentiality insofar as embodied potentiality is the prime material
of moral reflection and evaluation. In some ways the gap between those
who reflect on and evaluate ethical substance and those who are ethical substance mirrors a much older gap in critical theory. We can think
here of the ways that Louis Althusser struggled to specify how intellectuals and the proletariat were differently situated in and represented class
struggle.35 But rather than dwell on the question of critical theorys proper
stance toward the subject that it posits as the engine of history, in this
introduction I want to examine a slightly different set of concerns. First,
I should note that I am myself aligned with the general project of immanent critique to find a source of a social otherwise outside a gesture of
transcendental consciousness. My alignment with immanent critique is
no doubt due to a certain aesthetic and theoretical predisposition to this
framework. But it also emerges out of a longstanding commitment to a
set of local Indigenous Australian understandings of the immanent geontological (the being of geology) source of life and its possibilities. Second,
given these commitments I want to turn from an ontology of potentiality
to a sociology of potentiality. Rather than the question of the variation of
being and not being or affects and ideas in general, I want to understand
this variation in specific historical contexts. But I am making a general
claim; namely, that potentiality and its perpetual variations never occur
in a general way, but always, as Delueze himself noted, in specific agencementsarrangements of connecting concepts, materials, and forces that
make a common compositional unity.
Before elaborating what an alternative glossary might consist of, let
me turn to what I mean by neoliberalism and by way of this explain why I
use the chronotrope of late liberalism rather than other available chronotropes such as liberalism, neoliberalism, postcolonial liberalism, or diasporic liberalism. It is critical to this discussion that even as I describe
how I am using these terms I do not think that they are referring to some
given state of affairs. Liberalism, late liberalism, and neoliberalism do not
exist as things in the ordinary sense of the term but rather as actions like a
sighting or a citing. They exist insofar as they are evoked to conjure, shape,
aggregate, and evaluate a variety of social worlds, and each of these conjurings, shapings, aggregations, and evaluations disperse liberalism as a
global terrain.
Neoliberalism
17
18
Introduction
than the doors of various broom closets being swung open, the occupants
of these closets were shuffled around while new justifications for belonging and abandonment emerged. Some continental disparities continued.
Africa remained mired in what Achille Mbembe calls a necropolitics
the spatial demarcation of Africa as a society of spectacular killing and
death.48 Other continents emerged as major economic and social forces.
China and India of coursebut also South Americaemerged as major
centers for a renewed revolutionary Left fueled by such means as petrol
pesos (Venezuela) and production centers (Brazil) even while the material benefits of the revolution remains unclear. (If Harvey is right, the
rise in the capital power of these states corresponds with the formation of
a new landless proletariat.) In other, long-developed contexts, wealth was
reorganized. Andreas Cornia and Julius Court have shown that from the
1960s to the 1990s, inequality of wealth has increased in the vast majority
of developed and developing countries and has decreased only in France
and Norway.49 In the United States, countless economists on the right
and left have noted a dramatic concentration of wealth in the top one
percent of the population. If middle- and working-class Americans didnt
feel the shift in wealth, this was largely due to consumption practices that
depended on the acquisition of a huge middle- class debt through easy
credit.
What new political opportunities are made available by these old wineskins is unclear. Some think that the new globally striated nature of accumulation by dispossession will provide the possibility for new supranational grassroots political alliances, such as alliances between residents
of small American towns in Maine fighting the company Poland Springs
for control of municipal waters and residents of the Indian city of Varanasi protesting Coca-Cola Companys access to scarce water supplies.50
Others propose that class struggle might be giving way more generally
to the multitude or to a loosely organized anarchist Left.51 What does
seem clear is that neoliberalism is not a thing but a pragmatic concept
a toolin a field of multiple maneuvers among those who support and
benefit from it, those who support it and suffer from it, and those who
oppose it and benefit from it neverthelesseach action changing if only
slightly the field of maneuver itself.52 Again, from a certain logical point of
view, this field of maneuver is available to anyone, but in the actual worlds
19
20
Introduction
Changing amount of U.S. Treasury Securities held by selected states, in billions of dollars.
(source : Major Foreign Holders of Treasury Securities, February 27, 2009. Department of the
Treasury, Federal Reserve Board)
talism. By the time Foucault was giving his 197879 lectures, The Birth
of Biopolitics (Naissance de la Biopolitique), he had become interested in
what he called todays liberal . . . or neoliberal program (la programmation librale ou, comme on dit, neolibrale notre epoque). Of decisive import for Foucault was the noncorrespondence between laissezfaire liberalism and neoliberalism. Neoliberals did not merely wish to free
the economy from the Keynesian regulatory state; they wished to free
the truth games of capitalism from the market itselfthe market should
be the general measure of all social activities and values.56 In a recent
New York Times Book Review essay, Tony Judt asked how and why liberal
democracies like the United States, Britain, and Australia stopped assessing social programs and actions on the basis of political philosophy and
instead restricted themselves to issues of profit and loss, and languages of
21
22
Introduction
ing whether this or that person did or didnt care about the vulnerable or
that this or that social welfare program was or was not a failure. Instead
we need to start asking what are the measures of failure, the arts of failure,
such that people believe and experience cultural recognition and social
welfare as failures. After all, as I hope subsequent chapters will make clear,
failure is not an ideal form floating outside social space. Failure is instead
a socially mediated term for assessing the social world. When chapter 4
asks why social welfare in Australia suddenly seemed to stop working at
the turn of the century, it doesnt try to first define what failure is or isnt.
Instead it demonstrates how within a neoliberal framework any social investment that does not have a clear end in market valuea projectable
moment when state input values (money, services, care) can be replaced
by market output value (workers compensated and supported by nothing
except the market)fails economically and morally. And a social investment is an economic and moral failure, whether or not the investment is
life-enhancing.
By 2003, in Australia where I have focused most of my quarter-century
or so of research, the neoliberal reorientation of global economic hegemony seemed well under way as well as the accumulations by dispossession it sparked. The global commodity boom fueled by the production boom in China and Southeast Asia raised the Australian dollar to
near parity with the American dollar (by 2011 it had achieved parity). The
Australian mining industry led the way in producing a twenty-two billion dollar federal surplus in 2008. (Other primary exporting states were
seeing similar surplus booms.) In this economic environment, Australia
seemed sheltered by the double-digit expansion of the Chinese economy
and vigorously courted new trade agreements with it. But rather than expanding social welfare to its Indigenous citizens, the conservative federal government reversed a longstanding commitment to cultural recognition and reconciliation. I discuss this at length in the next chapter, but
here is just a taste. In July 2007, the government announced an intervention in Aboriginal affairs in the Northern Territory. The government
pegged its declaration of emergency to the release of the Little Children
Are Sacred report that claimed that some Aboriginal children were being
sexually abused because of the fetid nature of Indigenous communities.
The government called for a move beyond the politics of recognition
23
24
Introduction
and reconciliation to a free market approach to Indigenous affairs. Everyone agreed that Indigenous life would initially be much worse. But, in a
move readers should now be able to anticipate, from the perspective of
the future good that market integration would bring, this present suffering, we were told, should be bracketed. Focus on the future.
This form of neoliberal governance was itself shaken at the end of my
writing of this book. By the fall of 2008 the crisis of capitalism and liberalism wasnt merely formal in sense of what kinds of state forms could
not only be compatible with capitalism but were necessary to its current
formation. It was now linked to a very different set of circumstances. A
global financial credit crisis arose in large part from the collapse of a host
of new financial instruments intended to manipulate the assets of longterm market investments for enormous short-term profit. The collapse
of the credit market led to the collapse of consumption in the United
States, production in China, commodity exports in the Organization of
Petroleum Exporting Countries and Australia, and currencies in Eastern
Europe. China did not immediately emerge as an independent engine
of growth as widely hoped, although it continued to grow and, by this
growth, buffer the effects of the recession in commodity export centers
such as Australia. But Russia, Venezuela, and Dubai were caught banking too heavily and exclusively on high oil revenues.59 By March of 2009,
the World Bank predicted that worldwide gross domestic product would
shrink for the first time since the Second World War.60 The Brussels Forum
followed suit, with the president of the World Bank, Robert Zoellick, stating that 2009 would be a dangerous year, with issues going beyond the
economic to political and social instability.61 In the midst of these events
many proposals were advanced to fix global capitalism or to bring it finally
to its knees. To those arguing that we were witnessing the end of neoliberalism and, subsequently, the end of capitalism, Amartya Sen reminded the
readers of the New York Review of Books that even Adam Smith envisioned
a world of diverse economic formations (free markets and governmentcontrolled social domains such as education) within capitalism. Smith
never thought that capitalism, with its signature characteristics of market
transactions, profit motivation, and individually based private property,
was sufficient.62 That Sen was incited to defend capitalism by differentiating it from neoliberalism suggests something late about liberalism, not
in the sense that we are seeing its last hurrah, but that it has entered a
new stage of reflexivity. With the calming of the markets, the loosening of
credit, and the tentative return to consumption, some of this reflexivity
may yet wane. And how this globally systemic crisis is resolved in liberal
democracies, if it is resolved, is as of yet unclear. We see some contours of
a post-postBretton Woods world emergingthe return of a more robust
regulatory environment, the partial nationalization of industry and banks,
and the call for a global currency independent of the U.S. dollar.63
If this book seeks to understand how social projects that lie on the cusp
of being endure, then it turns not to an ontotheoretical answer, but to a
sociographic which roots analysis in the actual conditions of neoliberalismand late liberalism.
Late Liberalism
So why do I use the phrase late liberalism? By late liberalism, as distinct from these varieties and specificities of capitalism and state, I mean
the shape that liberal governmentality has taken as it responds to a series
of legitimacy crises in the wake of anticolonial, new social movements,
and new Islamic movements. But in a broader sense late liberalism is a
belated response to the challenge of social difference and the alternative social worlds and projects potentially sheltered there. From the 1950s
onward, and culminating in the dramatic world events of 1968, anticolonial and new social movements transfigured the prior way in which liberalism governed alternative forms of life by putting extreme pressure
on its legitimating frameworksimperial arts of paternalist and civilizational governance. Anticolonial and new social movements refigured
these paternalistic arts of civilizational care into acts of colonial domination and dispossession. Activists and their theorists, such as W. E. B.
Du Bois and Frantz Fanon, claimed that Western arts of caring for the
colonized and subaltern were not rectifying human inequalities but creating and entrenching them. But this legitimacy crisis was, over time,
turned into a crisis of culture for the governed as state after state instituted formal or informal policies of cultural recognition (or cognate policies such as multiculturalism) as a strategy for addressing the challenge
of internal and external difference that they faced. The political theorists
25
26
Introduction
Wendy Brown and Patchen Markell have described this as the culturalization of politics.64 In the wake of the liberal states recognition of past
harm, the crisis would no longer be a crisis of liberal legitimacy but a crisis
of how to allow cultures a space within liberalism without rupturing the
core frameworks of liberal justice. In short, in late liberalism to care for
difference is to make a space for culture to care for difference without disturbing key ways of figuring experienceordinary habitual truths. And
thus to assess care in late liberalism is to assess the capacity of culture as
an agent of care.
No matter how superficially they might seem the same thing, the culturalization of politics was not the same as the colonial critique of liberalism. As the first two chapters elaborate in more detail, late liberal cultural
recognition incorporated and disciplined the challenge that anticolonial
and new social movements posed to liberal forms of government by shifting the locale of the crisis and creating a definitive, though undefined,
limit on the formative legal and social power of cultural difference. For
this shift to become practical, culture had to become pliant to legal and
social science analysis and political and social incorporation. In the first
instance, culture had to become equivalent to an artifactsomething
that could be said to have specific qualities that could then be measured
and evaluated. Anthropologists of a certain structural and structuralfunctionalism ilk were helpful here. They truly believe(d) that culture is a
set of rulesrules of descent and kinship or ritual and symbolic orders
that people do or do not follow as one follows a recipe. The souffl rises
or fails toand its success depends upon what the rules are for making
it and whether one follows them. In the second instance, this version of
culture had to come out of the mouths of others. But even here, only a
specific kind of other will dothe general other, the other that complies
with the rules.
Not only was culture made into an object that one could possess or
insufficiently create, the actions of different cultures were assigned different tensesnot merely different times, as Johannes Fabian so nicely
demonstrated, but different tenses.65 And this is what I tried to suggest
in The Empire of Love by way of the division between the autological subject and the genealogical society. In brief the autological subject refers to
multiple discourses and practices that invoke the autonomous and self-
determining subject, and which are therefore linked to, but not exhausted
in, liberalisms emphasis on freedom, more narrowly conceived as a political philosophy. The genealogical society, on the other hand, refers to
discourses that stress social constraint and determination in processes of
subject constitution and construe the subject as bound by various kinds
of inheritances. But these discourses of freedom and constraint are themselves animated by an imaginary of national and civilizational tense. Foucault noted as much in his Collge de France lectures, Society Must Be
Defended, where he argued that Europe witnessed an inversion of the
temporal axis of the [political] demand. Reading the work of Abb de
Sieyes in the broad context of new-regime France, Foucault argued that
the political demand would no longer be made in the name of a past
right that was established by either a consensus, a victory, or an invasion.
Instead the demand would be articulated in terms of a potentiality, a
future, a future that is immediate, which is already present in the present
because it concerns a certain function of Statist universality that is already
fulfilled by a nation within the social body, and which is therefore demanding that its status as a single nation must be effectively recognized,
and recognized in the juridical form of the State.66
But the temporal inversion Foucault diagnosed was not merely a transformation of Europe in relation to itself. The inversion of the temporal
axis of the demand had a dual address. It constituted a division of tense
within Europe (what it had been and what it was now becoming) and
a division between Europe and non-Europe (what Europeans were becoming and what non-Europeans were). This doubly situated inversion
of tense connects the two major if fitful developments (the consolidation of demos and colons) that marked the long European dure from the
fourteenth to the seventeenth century and was consolidated in the eighteenth to the nineteenth. It locates this dure in a topological knot in
which Europe (demos) is in the body of the colonies (colons) as surely
as the citizens of Omelas are in the body of the child in the broom closet.
As democracy fitfully expanded across Europe and European conquest
across the globe the truth of some would be increasingly judged in terms
of a past perfect beingtheir already having been or, their potential to
stop being what they are still in essencewhile the truth of others would
be judged from their potentiality. The futures of some, or the hopes that
27
28
Introduction
they have for their future, can never be a future. They can only drag others
into the past (Osama bin Laden [Radical Islam going backward] coordinated the bombings). And for others, no matter what harms they
do, the truth of these harms is deferred into the future. What is happening isnt happening because it is what it will have been when the last man
has his say. The society of potentiality (demos) seemed to demand societies of fixity (colons), as if the future anterior of freedom demanded
the clawing determination of the customary to make its difference visible
and palpable. Indeed, so fundamentally is this history internal to modern
Europes language of itself that its foundational terms of critical reference are saturated by this temporal inversion. Even the seemingly neutral social scientific term, the social cannot escape these same historical
conditions, on the contrary: the historicity of the autological subject and
genealogical society is internal to the historicity of the sign, the social,
and consequently to the divisions of social belonging, social worlds, and
social projects that I am examining.67 That we can say, the social as opposed to the individual, and that we can compare different (individual)
social worlds presupposes the division between the autological subject
and genealogical society.68
Late liberalism is not an epochal form that emerged in the wake of
national, anticolonial, and new social movements, and subsequently
ceased to adapt to new conditions. Late liberalism is no more a unified
thing then is neoliberalism: they are both uneven terrains of social maneuver. This has become exceedingly clear in the wake of the 9/11 attacks.
Though not born at this moment, a reactionary position to cultural difference, especially Anglo-American forms of multiculturalism, has taken
on new force since the attacks. The rise of this reactionary movement is
perhaps exemplified by the influence of Samuel P. Huntingtons The Clash
of Civilizations in neoconservative circles, but no matter whether we use
this text or another as a marker, we have witnessed over the last decade a
new and intensive shift in the governance of social difference. As the next
two chapters make clear, culture is once again being inflected by a civilizational rhetoric. And this civilizational rhetoric has been articulated to
national and international security. British, French, and German politicians such as David Cameron, Nicolas Sarkozy, and Angela Merkel have
declared state multiculturalism a failure and called for a robust defense
of western liberal principles.69 As chapter 3 argues, however, this seeming
29
30
Introduction
31
32
Introduction
33
34
Introduction
two problems, according to Waldron. The first is evidentiary (first occupancy is nearly impossible to prove because its truth stretches into prerecorded history); the second is the hierarchies of justice (the fact of
being first, even if it could be proved, is only one of a set of values that
must be assessed when deciding issues of justice). According to Waldron,
Indigenous claims made on the basis of prior occupancy gain moral force
from the human interest in stability, security, certainty, and peace, and
for the sake of those values it prohibits overturning existing arrangements
irrespective of how they were arrived at.75 But they also suffer from an
ever-decreasing moral weight as the event of dispossession recedes into
historical time.
In a brilliant critique of Waldron, Robert Nichols slowly unpacks the
assumptions built into his model and analysis. Nichols notes that in order
to divide Indigenous claims into the categories of first and prior occupancy, Waldron must assume that contract theory, the principles of personhood it presupposes, and the ontological categories of being it projects
are also indigenous categoriesthat is, universal, general epistemological
and ontological categories. Numerous Indigenous studies scholars, from
Vine Deloria to Dale Turner in the United States, and Deborah Bird Rose
to Irene Watson in Australia, have decisively demonstrated this not to be
the case.76 Moreover, scholars such as Glen Coulthard and J. Khaulani
Kauanui have shown dispossession is not a historical event but an ongoing process.77
When I speak of the governance of prior, I am specifically interested
in the social genealogies of these kinds of political theoretical abstractions. There is not enough space here to discuss at length the conditions
that gave rise to the governance of the prior in the modern settler nationstate, the nation-state system more generally, or the Indigenous as a specific and general formation within the history of colonial settlement, let
alone the variations and complexities of these interlocking relations of
the governance of the prior with the divisions of the autological subject
and genealogical society.78 This much I can say, if all too briefly. The conditions of the governance of the prior were in place before the emergence
of the modern liberal nation-state. And this is true whether we believe
that the modern nation-state emerged in the eighteenth-century Americas, as does Benedict Anderson, or only after the Second World War, as
35
36
Introduction
The governance of the prior. The settler citizen differentiates, localizes, and temporalizes
its territorial claims by creating two distinct and contrasting categories, the native and the
foreigner, locating their territorial claims in the past (native) and future (foreigner).
37
38
Introduction
terra nullius than to negotiate treaties with the variety of inhabitants they
confronted. More generally, according to Kathleen Wilson, the projection
of Englishness was increasingly authoritarian and paternalist by the time
it reached Australia.86 The 1901 Federal Constitution, which established
Australia as an independent Commonwealth, for the most part continued
to treat the aboriginal native population as a spectral presence, referring
to the Indigenous population in just two of its sections. Section 51(xxvi)
gave the federal parliament the power to make laws for the peace, order,
and good government . . . with respect to people of any race, other than the
aboriginal race in any State, for whom it is deemed necessary to make special laws. Section 127 prohibited the parliament from counting aboriginal natives in the consensus. To be sure, the frontier was rife with organized and disorganized violence, seizures, resistances, and informal land
agreements.87 Which is merely to say that in Australia the problem of the
priority of the prior was confronted through a variety of tacticswarfare,
genocide, and illegal property transfers. Unlike in the United States, all of
these huddled under the cover of the doctrine of terra nullius. But like in
the United States, in Australia specific tactics for maneuvering around the
governance of the prior were not merely about Indigenous-state relations
but about federal dynamics. Sections 51(xxvi) and 127 were less about
the state in relation to Indigenous people than about struggles between
Commonwealth and state powers. Internal power within the federal government was also at stake in the 1967 referendum that provided the federal government with the power to make laws with respect to people
of any race, other than the aboriginal race in any State, for whom it is
deemed necessary to make special laws, giving rise to the modern land
rights regime.
And yet, even given these diverse histories, what the governance of
prior shows is that from a critical point of view, the Indigenous does not
confront the state, nor does the state confront the Indigenous. Both are
caught in strategic maneuvers around a shared problematic; the nationstate and the Indigenous cite a shared discourse originating in a history
that predates both of their emergence. A formation of power articulated
as tense and eventthe governance of the prioris foundational to the
imaginary of sovereign power to both settler and Indigenous as such and
to late liberalism more generally.
39
40
Introduction
While it seems clear to me that the social tense, events, and ethical
substance are unavoidable from the point of view of settler nationalism,
I think it is legitimate to ask what relevance the above discussion has
for other forms of historical and contemporary social difference. For instance, how does this discussion help us understand the unequal distribution of life and death, of hope and harm, and of exhaustion and endurance when the social referent of these distributions seems to be based
on sexuality and race? There are several ways of answering the question
of how the interests of this book relate to problems of social belonging,
abandonment, and endurance outside the Indigenous context.
The first would point out isomorphisms cutting across Indigenous
and non-Indigenous contexts. In Israel, for instance, tactics of disenfranchisement of Palestinians operate as if they were culled from a condensed
settler manual. An initial Israeli creole nationalism, organized around the
image of the sabre, indicates how many Israeli Jews attempted to ground
their territorial claims in the past perfect of indigeneityliterally writing these claims as facts on the ground.88 Israel, however, also presents
its difference from Palestine as a difference of social tense, rooting its
general being in the autological destiny of Europe as opposed to the customary past of a socially primitive Palestinian population.89 These temporal discourses have spatial entailments. In East Jerusalem, Palestinians
must show an unbroken residency to their homes and lands in order to
maintain their right over their homes. Persons leaving for school or work
abroad are claimed to have severed their traditional attachment and thus
annulled their rights of place. This method of disenfranchisement is isomorphic to the way in which the Australian Native Title Act (1993) recognizes Indigenous native title. Indigenous claimants must prove an unbroken physical and cultural connection to their traditional lands even
if previous governments forcibly removed them. In France, too, we hear
similar strains of civilizational tense. Although interested in the viability
of racial analysis to discourses of lacit, in Da la question sociale la question raciale?, Eric and Didier Fassin demonstrate, in a painful irony, how
the homosexual has become a figure of the autological subject wielded
against the backward-looking Muslim migrant.90 And in Turkey, Dicle
Koacolu has shown how the tradition effect (the genealogical society) continues to frame so-called honor killings in contemporary Tur-
41
42
Introduction
the prior: these are not abstract theoretical truths but socially invested
aggregating tools that transform the variegated space of liberalism with
its multitudinous collection of ways of immanent life in order to make
them conform to a set of expectations and accountings that do work in
the actual world. This is why I try to describe the two broad conditions
in which this book was conceived and written. It is not to argue that the
social division of tense and its relation to eventfulness and ethical substance exist at all modes and levels of analysis of late liberalism. But that
they are available across all modes and levels of practicing late liberalism,
of justifying its exclusions and inclusions, of making good of its goods and
good of its harms.
Chapter by Chapter
This introduction can be thought of as a robust presentation of the thematics and concepts that organize this book. Chapters should be read
together and in sequence. One can read them separately. Although all
these thematics and concepts are always in the scene, each chapter takes
a different aspect on the tense, eventfulness, and ethical substance of late
liberalism. If a reader is mostly interested in the dynamics of recognition
in late liberalism, she could read the first two chapters. If a reader is interested in the problem of embodiment and endurance in late liberalism she
could start with chapters 3 and 4. However, because later chapters assume
material discussed in previous chapters, the argument makes the most
sense if read consecutively.
The first two chapters examine the contemporary politics of recognitionin the contemporary moment often voiced as an opposition to the
politics of cultural recognitionas a central technique of late liberalism.
Chapter 1, The Part That Has No Part, examines two unrelated cases of
social difference in two different national settings with two seemingly different outcomes. I examine the recent national emergency in Aboriginal
affairs in Australia prompted by a report on sexual abuse in Aboriginal
communities and the recent U.S. Supreme Court decision upholding a
preliminary injunction exempting the religious group, Unio do Vegetal,
from the Controlled Substances Act. I pick these two examples for their
contrasts: they are situated in different national traditions (Australia and
the United States); they touch on different kinds of social panics (sexual
panics and drug panics); and they involve different aspects of the state
apparatus (parliament and judiciary). They also come to opposite conclusions: the Australian Intervention argues against protecting traditional
customs; Gonzales v. O Centro Esprita Beneficente Unio do Vegetal decides
to offer protection to religious expression. But I chose these two cases because they demonstrate how the tense of the other is available whenever
the problem of cultural recognition arises and how this tense is inflected
by the question of security. This availability means that the divisions of
social tense provide a unified, if mobile, discursive field that makes maneuvers within it appear as if they were antagonistic to it. The support of
or assault on the genealogical society seems opposed to the support of
or assault on the autological subject, rather than merely a movement in a
dead division. And this movement within a given order allows us to ask
what is and is not a moment of the politicalwhat part has no part in the
social divisions of tense and what political potential might this part have.
Chapter 2, The Brackets of Recognition, continues my examination
of the late liberal politics of recognition and my interest in the potentiality
of the part that has no part within this mode of governance. Chapter 1
examined how various forms of social tense (the divisions of autological
subject and genealogical society; the governance of the prior) manage the
line between policing and politics in order to make difference intelligible
in late liberalism. The second chapter puts more pressure on recognition
itself. It asks what form, or mode, recognition takes when the moment
of intelligibility is deferred, bracketed, or denied and recognition is not
able to overcome liberal intolerance. I argue that when viewed from the
brackets of recognition, recognition as such is only one of three modalities of how late liberalism governs difference, the others being camouflage and espionage.
Chapters 3 and 4 examine how the part that has no part in the given
orders of the sayable and visible endures in these kinds of social spacings.
Chapter 3, Road Kill, asks what the conditions are of life lived within
these brackets from the point of view of an ethics of substance. Moving
across an ethnography of the radical green movement and an Indigenous
Australian mixed-media project, I pivot the discussion on the relationship
between ethical substance and biopolitics, especially as these intersect
43
44
Introduction
around the problems of excess, exhaustion, and endurance in late liberalism. If ethics is the realm in which we reflect and act at the intersection
of right conduct and the good life, then our ethical relation to life within
these differential zones of abandonment and vulnerability is fraught, to
say the least. The life worth living is not necessarily found within these
zones because the zones create such reduced conditions of life that the
political desire for them to spawn or foster alternative worlds can seem
naive at best and sadistic at worst. What would happen if, on the one
hand, we allowed for a wider field of substantiality into our critique of
biopolitics and substance, and on the one hand, we dwelled more fully in
the conditions of excess, exhaustion, and endurance that characterize the
spaces and zones of late liberal exposure and abandonment?
Chapter 4, Events of Abandonment, returns to Indigenous Australia. In this chapter, I examine modes of eventfulness and discourses of
lethality in contemporary Australia, focusing first on the contemporary
carnal conditions of Indigenous life and second on recent state security
measures said to be a reaction to the post-9/11 world. I do so in order to
understand the dynamic conditions that qualify one kind of lethality as
state killing and another as a more amorphous condition of letting die.
I do so in order to understand how present-tense modes of living and
dying are transformed into future anterior modes of the proper life.
Chapter 5, After Good and Evil, Whither Sacrificial Love?, continues
this discussion but turns it to eschatological discourses of sacrifice and
sacrificial love, the imaginary of a form of killing as a mode of life giving,
in late liberalism. The question whether this or that sacrifice is worth it
opens the events of suffering and dying, if not to the problematic of being
and time, then to the problematic of being and tensethe narrative relation among social, economic, and political values and subjective finitudes
and how, where, and whether subjective finitudes are seen to occur and
lead. I embed arguments between the Bush administration and its critics
about the competing rhetorics of good and evil and sacrifice and sacrificial love in contemporary critical theorys romance with Christian modes
of sacrificial love. It concludes by asking what lies beyond good and evil,
if sacrifice and sacrificial love provides a means of memorialized denial
of human suffering.
The conclusion, Negative Critique, Positive Sociographies, returns
45
Chapter One
Traditions of Dysfunction
48
Chapter One
Australia accepted this the sooner the harms of the past could be extinguished. The federal government would, forcibly if necessary, puncture
the sovereignty of Indigenous communities and liberate countless Indigenous children who were languishing in their broom closetsworse,
being raped in these sealed-off spaces, their abuse aided and abetted by
childless advocates kowtowing to the sanctity of traditional law.
What would the anthropologist Johannes Fabian make of The Politics
of Suffering? In Time and the Other, Fabian characterized the relation between anthropology and its object as a political cosmology, at the center
of which lay a constitutive contradiction. On the one hand, anthropology
has its empirical foundation in ethnographic research, inquiries which
even hard-nosed practitioners carry out as communicative interactions
and, on the other hand, when these same ethnographers represent their
knowledge in teaching and writing they do this in terms of a discourse that
consistently places those who are talked about in a time other than that of
the one who talks.6 Demonstrating how the event of ethnographic narration was misaligned to the narrated event that provided its foundation
allowed Fabian to align the writing practices of modern anthropology to
the historical desires of a modern Hegelianism, in which the function
of the non-Western other is to entail a Western unfolding.7 The problem
with modern anthropology, according to Fabian, was that the contemporary ethnographic subject, often a single individual, was continually
transfigured into a mass subject living in the past tense. Peoples contemporary lives were reduced to a set of ancient needs: the durative unfolding
present was narratively transfigured into a frozen past perfect. Suttons
text would seem an exemplary if belated case in point.
Fabian insisted that the people anthropologists speak withor more
broadly interact withare not in a different time from the interactional
encounter itself. And his point was to demonstrate how locating them
in another time (the past perfect of the genealogical society) aligns the
anthropological narrative with the most conservative of Western civilizational philosophies and agendas. Suttons reverses this argument. Because contemporary Australian anthropologists refuse to speak honestly about the harms of traditional Indigenous culture, they are unable
to understand that the time of traditional custom is out of joint with modern society. It is this temporal dissonance that is causing the present social
49
50
Chapter One
next chapter in order to make a space for subsequent discussions in chapters 3 and 4 about the maneuvers of social worlds and projects who are
addressed by, exist in, or are a result of these tactics of recognition and
social belonging.
In this chapter I discuss in some detail two seemingly unrelated cases:
the politics of the Australian Intervention and the jurisprudence of spiritually based drug consumption in the United States pivoting on the case
Gonzales v. O Centro Esprita Beneficente Unio do Vegetal (2006). As I
noted in the introduction, these two examples cut across state and national borders (Australia and the United States), involve different kinds
of social panics (sexual panics and drug panics), and focus attention on
different aspects of the state apparatus (parliament and judiciary). Moreover, the two social worlds and projects differ significantly in relationship
to the governance of the prior in late liberalism and in relationship to
the entanglements of power and the will. In the case of Indigenous Australians we seem to be witnessing a structural relationship between the
state and Indigenous people that is independent of any particular persons will to be different. Members of the Unio do Vegetal congregation
would seem a more stereotypically volitional form of association. Additionally, the two cases seem to relate very differently to the governance of
the priorthe Indigenous Australians are a clear and forceful case of the
governance of the prior, the Unio do Vegetal congregation is not. And
finally, the Australian state and U.S. judiciary seem to come to opposite
conclusions: proponents of the Australian federal Intervention in Indigenous life argue against protecting traditional customs, while the Supreme
Court in Gonzales v. UDV offers constitutional protection to religious expression. But I am not aiming to produce a comparative sociography of
late liberalism, at least not comparative in the sense of comparing two
distinct entities in order to produce a higher order unity.
Instead this chapter first discusses each case as it reveals how late liberal governance makes use of an array of social tenses to legitimate its
powers over life and death. Second, I discuss how this mobilization of
social tense manages the potential eruption of noise (phonos) such that
the fundamental ordering of social roles is not disturbed. And finally,
I examine how this management of noise faces and creates new social
projects and worlds. I focus on these three aspects for several reasons.
51
52
Chapter One
On June 21, 2007, the then prime minister of Australia, John Howard, declared a national emergency in relation to the abuse of children in Indigenous communities in the Northern Territory. Howards declaration
came in the wake of the Little Children Are Sacred report of the Northern
Territory Board of Inquiry into the Protection of Aboriginal Children
from Sexual Abuse. As I noted above, in the name of this national emergency, Howards government assumed broad and unprecedented powers
over Indigenous affairs in the Northern Territory, including Indigenous
welfare, education, land tenure, and health. Howards announcement
came with carrot and stick. As a carrot Howard promised millions of
dollars for Indigenous health, education, and employment training. As
a stick the federal government assumed control over seventy-three Indigenous townships through the forcible acquisition of five-year leases
over townships on Indigenous-owned land, community living areas, and
other designated Indigenous areas and sent, under the cover of military
police, medical personnel to conduct compulsory sexual health exams for
all children under the age of sixteen. Business managers with powers to
control and direct all Indigenous programs and their assets, including the
monitoring of all community communication and video equipment, were
also sent to take control of all Commonwealth programs in Indigenous
town camps and rural communities.10
One of the first actions of these business managers was to shift Indigenous workers from the Community Development Employment
Programme (CDEP, a work and training program within a social welfare
framework, loosely called work for the dole) to welfare. Publically proclaiming its neoliberal (enterprise culture) commitments, the federal
government nevertheless began the Intervention by shifting as many Indigenous people from the CDEP to welfare as possible. This shift from
work to welfare was necessary if the federal government wished to control
the wealth and spending of Indigenous people in remote communities
and town camps. For legal reasons, persons on the CDEP couldnt have
their wages managed. Once all Indigenous people were placed on welfare,
payments could be tied to school attendance and other behavioural indices; furthermore, fifty percent of payments could be given in the form
of debit cards that restricted purchasing choices of Indigenous men and
women to selected stores for selected items while prohibiting other purchases such as alcohol and pornography. But shifting Indigenous men and
women from CDEP to welfare came with a dramatic lowering of incomes
in a population already suffering general and sustained poverty. Speaking
53
54
Chapter One
to Leon Compton on Darwin ABC radio on July 23, 2007, Mal Brough
made the link between welfare and social control explicit:
ComPton: Are you saying that money from CDEP is the problem in
child sexual abuse and alcoholism and violence?
Brough: Absolutely, there is no doubt that there is a contributing factor beyond the CDEP payments and because for
all intents and purposes they are a welfare paymentit
is the cash that is being used to buy the drugs and alcohol that have caused so many . . . so much of the pain for
these children. There is just no doubt about that.11
Although Howard pegged his declaration of emergency to the release
of the Little Children Are Sacred report, he did not restrict himself to its
recommendations. Instead he endorsed the longstanding call of the minister for families, community services and Indigenous affairs, Mal Brough,
for a move beyond the politics of recognition (self-determination) and
reconciliation with Indigenous people to a neoliberal approach to Indigenous affairs. Indigenous people needed to stop worrying about their culture, move out of rural regions, and accept whatever jobs they could get
in the cities. If they wouldnt move on their own accord, the federal government would starve them out by reducing their income.
By September, the Howard government, which controlled the federal
parliament, passed the Northern Territory National Emergency Response
Act (2007). The act gave the federal government sweeping powers over
Indigenous land tenure, welfare, alcohol consumption, and education.12
Throughout the Northern Territory large bright blue or yellow signs were
erected at the entrance of Indigenous communities announcing that pornography and alcohol were banned and in the process publicly branding
Indigenous communities as spaces of perversion and decay. (An unexpected consequence, from an Indigenous point of view, was that some
areas previously understandable as public or private lands were suddenly
and publically visible as Indigenous land.) Because many of the provisions of the proposed emergency legislation were racially discriminatory,
the federal government added an amendment that suspended the application of the Racial Discrimination Act to the legislation. Two years later, in
2009, one of the authors of the Children Are Sacred report, Patricia Ander-
55
56
Chapter One
fused to rethink his rejection of the Kelowna Accord, one of his first acts
of government in 2006, which was meant to put $5 billion into Indigenous
employment, housing, and social programs.17
The support of the Intervention by the Labour Rudd government suggests how the Intervention seemed to dramatically upset previous alignments between the Left and Right and thus signal a radical new political
epoch in Australia. That the arts of care announced and practiced in the
Intervention have rattled the political order is undisputable from a certain
perspective. At the beginning of June 2008 Dr. Alyssa Vass, spokesperson
for the Darwin Aboriginal Rights Coalition, told an inquiry of the Senate Select Committee on Regional and Remote Indigenous Communities: The punitive discriminatory approach taken by the intervention has
made life more difficult for families, has been disempowering to the extreme and perpetuated destructive negative stereotypes.18 But by the end
of June 2008 the West Australian Childrens Court magistrate, Dr. Sue
Gordon, and Major General Dave Chalmers issued a report calling for
increased spending on housing and police, fully funded clinics, a choicebased welfare debit system, and community-based alcohol management
rather than an alcohol ban. But they also advocated for the elimination
of unviable settlements. Divisions also emerged between Indigenous
scholars and politicians, played out in regional and national settings.19 In
a searing critique of Howards policies, a Northern Territory Labour parliamentary member, Marion Scrymgour, referred to the Northern Territory National Emergency Response Act as the black kids Tampa. (In
August 2001, the Howard government refuse to let a Norwegian freighter,
the MV Tampa, enter Australian waters after it rescued 438 mainly Afghan
asylum seekers; many people believed that this violation of international
law was an election year stunt.) Scrymgour was the first Indigenous minister in any Australian governmentat the time the minister for family
and community services, and environment and heritage in the Northern Territory government.20 In a previous moment her words would have
carried a certain irreproachable weight. But Brough immediately called
for Scrymgour to resign. She initially refused. But after two years of controversy, Scrymgour left the Northern Territory Labour Party, which immediately elevated another Indigenous woman, Alison Anderson, to her
portfolio. Soon after, it emerged that only three hundred houses would be
built from the AuD$672 million Strategic Indigenous Housing and Infrastructure Programthe bulk of the money going to administrative costs
and the builders. Facing a stalled and underfunded housing initiative, the
refusal of health care workers and teachers to move into Indigenous communities, and large amounts of dedicated funds going to non-Indigenous
administrators, Anderson threatened to quit. And quit she did, on August 4, 2009.21
And Anderson was right: it is uncertain how much of the $587 million
actually allocated for the first twelve months of the Intervention has been
spent, nor is it clear on what it has been spent. Preliminary analysis suggests, rather unsurprisingly, that a large percentage has been allocated to
the employment of non-Indigenous bureaucrats, bureaucratic agencies,
police, and researchers. Part of the problem of tracking the actual distribution of wealth is the bureaucratic practice of proliferating and changing program names; redirecting previous unspent or promised budgetary
allowances; and closing programs without a subsequent account of where
their allocated but unused funds have gone. Even if we could clarify the
deceptive bookkeeping, it would remain unclear how to assess the social
value of the Intervention. What will be the individuated and thus quantifiable units to be measured? The creation of new houses, play yards, and
schools? The quieting of communities? Will any studies be undertaken
to show where the trouble makers have gone? And if so, will the money
spent to show where they have gone be deducted from funds allocated for
the building of Indigenous housing? Will these facts be factored into the
assessment of the Intervention? We already know that many people have
shifted to the cities, living in the long grass, struggling to meet basic rental,
food, and clothing needs on their new government-enforced budget.
But no one advocating for the Intervention pretended that life would
be easier for Indigenous citizens in the present. In fact they emphasized
that life would be harder during the transition from a welfare-based politics of self-determination to a neoliberal enterprise culture and that
Indigenous people would need to endure this difficult period as best
they could. The Howard government acknowledged thisthat life in
the present would be worse for many Indigenous men and women. The
Labour government has agreed, saying it would remain unclear for some
time how the Intervention would impact Indigenous liveswhether it
57
58
Chapter One
will have made any positive difference in basic service delivery, housing,
health, or education.22 By July 2009 the Productivity Commission was
reporting that the key indicators of Indigenous disadvantage were far
worse than anyone had thoughtthe gap between Indigenous and nonIndigenous Australians was either unchanged or widening across eighty
percent of social statistics, including education, life expectancy, jobs and
income, preventable diseases, overcrowding, incarceration, and community violence.23 According to the Productivity Commission the only programs that seemed to be closing this gap were cooperative approaches between Indigenous people and government, nonprofit and private sectors,
conceived from the bottom up rather than top down. And it is exactly
in these ordinary bureaucratic statements that we witness how the time
of harm is always belatedsomething that happened when no one was
looking; always something to come and then coming too late.
In light of statements that Indigenous lives already difficult to endure
would be made more difficult, what makes the Intervention seem like a
sensible good, a form of life enhancement rather than, say, state killing or
neoliberal modes of making die? What discourses of social belonging and
abandonment, caring and disregard made the emergency Intervention
seem necessary, and by making it seem necessary, allowed the Howard
and the subsequent Labour governments to create a narrative form that
conjured away the social harms of the durative present? What does care
consist of such that when a form of creating harm for others is thought of
and experienced as a form of caring for others? To begin to answer these
questions we must begin with what supposedly started this social drama,
the Little Children Are Sacred report.
The report, commissioned by the Northern Territory Labour government, written by Rex Wild and Patricia Anderson, and publicly released
on June 15, 2007, begins dramatically, noting a breakdown of Aboriginal
culture caused by a number of underlying conditions of Indigenous life.
Excessive consumption of alcohol is variously described as the cause or
result of poverty, unemployment, lack of education, boredom and overcrowded and inadequate housing. The use of other drugs and petrol sniffing can be added to these. Together, they lead to excessive violence. In
the worst case scenario it leads to sexual abuse of children.24 The Little
Children Are Sacred report was careful to dispel five myths about Indige-
nous sexual abuse: that Aboriginal men are the only offenders; Aboriginal law is the reason for high levels of sexual abuse; Aboriginal law is used
as an excuse to justify abuse; Aboriginal culture is the reason for underreporting; and Aboriginal men do not have an important role to play in
preventing child sexual abuse. And yet, it was in terms of these myths that
federal government spokespersons and the national media made sense
of the abuse. When the report circulated in the national press, the point
that received the most attention was not the supposed breakdown of Indigenous culture but the abuse of children by men acting according to
traditional marriage laws. Again and again the media reported older traditional men raping young girls and boys and justifying this sexual abuse
in terms of traditional marriage practices. Film clips of young people running amok in Aboriginal communities and townships supplemented these
stories. Conservative commentators rushed to claim their pyrrhic victory,
indicting supporters of multiculturalism for their naive understanding of
Indigenous customs even as they loudly proclaimed the collapse of the
Indigenous social order. And the ubiquitous billboards proclaimed at the
entrance of every Indigenous community its scarlet letter of shame.
Throughout, the national media promoted the promarket and promodernization visions of particular Indigenous men and women who had
close ties to the Howard government, such as Noel Pearson, or academics,
such as Peter Sutton, who castigated progressive white Australians for
wishing to lock Indigenous people into national museums. What Indigenous people wanted, according to these Indigenous men and women
and their non-Indigenous allies, was to be free-enterprise subjectsto
have real jobs, to live in the real world of contemporary Western society,
where horizons were oriented to the future not the past. Even after the
Rudd Labour government came into power, newspapers and other public media continued to foreground the link between child sexual abuse,
traditional law, and the governance of the prior trumping the governance
of freedom. Take, for instance, an article in The Australian, Secrets in the
Shadows, published in June 2008. The story begins dramatically with a
teenage boy, who dropped dead after a footy match near Papunya in
central Australia. Although nobodys fault, his death set off a round of
vicious violence in a world where payback, retribution, spearings and
mob violence are ever-present. Dismissing the moaning of critics that
59
60
Chapter One
the intervention was a land grab and not about child sexual abuse, the
article foregrounds the moaning of children through hearsay about rampant sex abuse, and asserts that the cause of the abuse is the traditional
law of elder men and kowtowing white enablers.25 Community workers,
terrified that the 12-year-old boy would rape again, took to sleeping in the
boys house at night. When FACS [Department of Family and Community Services] finally came to take the child into care, after a delay of many
weeks, the boys family whisked the child into cultural business. Police refused to transgress on ceremonial ground and FACS workers retreated.
The use of a sex panic to intervene in racial politics is hardly new. A
similar disruption occurred in the United States in 1965 after the release
of the Report on the Negro Family: The Case for National Action, popularly
known as the Moynihan Report. Daniel Moynihan was a sociologist and
assistant secretary of labor under President John F. Kennedy. The Moynihan Report correlated black female-headed households to a tangle of
pathology . . . capable of perpetuating itself without assistance from the
white world. As William Graebner notes, the report appeared just as the
civil rights movement was negotiating the turn to black power, a moment Moynihan understood as crucial to whether the black movement
would radicalize. As Sutton did with Indigenous Australians, so Moynihan did with African Americans, blaming the radical inequality between
whites and blacks on internal pathologies rather than contemporary institutional arrangements (although, in Moynihans case, this pathology was
said to have emerged from the institution of slavery, three centuries of
injustice, rather than a traditional precolonial practice that could somehow be abstracted from contemporary actions). The Right seized on the
report. Nothing was wrong with America or American law or American
capitalism. What was wrong was black culture. A direct political line leads
from the Moynihan Report to the Reagan demonization of the racialized
figure of the welfare queen to the Clinton administrations dismantling
of the welfare system.26 The legislation that emerged is particularly interesting to the recent Australian case, given how, as Anna Marie Smith has
shown, a series of programs under the Personal Responsibility and Work
Opportunity Reconciliation Act, which replaced the Aid to Families with
Dependent Children, intertwined sexual regulation and welfare reform.27
For example, to receive support the woman must provide the state with
the name of the biological father. The state then pursues a child support
action that, if successful, forces the father to pay the state, not the mother,
for the benefits she receives.
Moreover, as among African-Americans in the United States, in Australia, most Indigenous men and women living in the rural north are used
to being the locus of social experimentation, and the nodal point of a national anxiety organized around free and collective agency projected onto
their ways of life. They are used to hearing government officialswho
themselves continually change as governments replace governments
announce rivers of money and infrastructure that subsequently turn into
a dirty trickle by the time it reaches them. They are used to hearing that
the harms in their present lives should be bracketed. They are used to
being aggressively abandoned within a temporal horizon of a future perspective: a future from whose perspective their present suffering has already been mourned and buried. And they are used to the two poles of social belonging, autology and genealogy, being used as the means through
which new programs are justified. After all, the reliance on the specter of
genealogical determination was as vital an organ of social control under
the previous regime of self-determination through cultural recognition
as it is now a vital organ in the Intervention. In the previous regime of
recognitionwhich, I should note here, continues alongside the current
attack on recognitionthe evidence determining whether an Indigenous
difference was truly Indigenous referred to the same specter of customary
law.28 Native title, land rights, and cultural heritage and property laws demanded of Indigenous people a genealogical reckoning, not within their
own language of obligation and belonging, caring and being cared for,
but with a liberal imaginary of individual determination. What a surprise
that Sutton could so easily invert the values of Indigenous culture: he
had spent the previous decade vigorously arguing that Indigenous people
should be divided between traditional owners and historical people
based on various individuals adherence to past social forms and practices. If you think that any people can be split into groups based on the
siphoning of complex contemporary practices into premodern and modern action, then you can flip the values of these actions back and forth
negative, positive; positive, negative.
61
62
Chapter One
Gonzales v. UDV takes us far from the Northern Territory of Australia and
its current accounts of the sexual dysfunction of its Indigenous citizens.
Instead we enter the somewhat rarified realm of judicial reflection about
matters of state powers, religious expression, and international security.
But it is exactly the difference in social location, situation, and genre that
allows us to begin to see the ways in which social tense is available and
dispersed in late liberalism and thus the multiple ways the powers of
making live and making die reappear there.
The bare facts of the case are well known and undisputed. Gonzales v.
UDV addressed the concerns of a demographically insignificant group in
the United States, members of the Unio do Vegetal community. According to its official history, the Unio do Vegetal is a Christian religion established in Brazil on July 21, 1961, in Porto Velho, Rondnia, Brazil, by the
rubber-tapper Jos Gabriel da Costa. The vegetable of spiritual benefit is
ayahuasca, a hallucinogenic black tea brewed from Banisteriopsis caapi vine
and Psychotria viridis plant. I have never imbibed ayahuasca, but others report its physiological and spiritual effects by word of mouth, in YouTube
testimonies, online blogs, underground zines, and alternative spirituality
magazines. These also provide information on where one can go to access
this form of spiritual enlightenment.29 Venues differ significantly in terms
of crass comfort. Friends of mine describe the settings they have drunk
ayahuasca as ranging from ratty dens where couches are stained with
vomit to smart new age venues with tasteful vomitoriums. The Unio do
Vegetal is not the only formal and informal group to celebrate the spiritual
powers of the ayahuasca plant. Other spiritual groups that use this plant
include Santo Daime, PaDeva Church, and Irmandade Beneficente Natureza Divina. These churches trace their religious practices to the period
prior to the Spanish conquest of the Americas, but embed their contemporary beliefs in various spiritual discourses including Christianity, Wicca,
shamanism, and neopaganism. The membership of these churches is relatively small. The Unio do Vegetal claims about ten thousand members.
Only a couple hundred are resident in the United States.
Prior to Gonzales v. UDV, one large roadblock stood in the way of those
persons in the United States who wished to explore the spiritual offerings
of these churches. In Brazil the possession and use of ayahuasca was legalized in 1992.30 But in the United States the key hallucinogenic component
of ayahuasca, dimethyltryptamine, or Dmt, is defined as a Schedule 1 class
drug under the Controlled Substances Act. Schedule 1 drugs are drugs
classified as having a high abuse risk and no safe, accepted medical use in
the United States. Other Schedule 1 drugs include heroin, marijuana, LSD,
PCP, and crack cocaine.31 Trafficking in these drugs is a federal crime.
First offenses carry a penalty of up to twenty years in prison if no death
or serious injury occurs and not less than twenty years if they do, in addition to a $1 million fine for individuals and $5 million fine for groups. The
second offense carries a penalty of up to thirty years in prison if no death
or serious injury occurs and not less than twenty years if they do, in addition to a $2 million fine for individuals and $10 million fine for groups.
It was exactly the issue of drug trafficking that wound the Unio do
Vegetal in the U.S. Supreme Court.32 On May 21, 1999, the U.S. Customs
Service seized a shipmen of ayahuasca tea heading from church headquarters in Brasilia, Brazil, to John Bronfman and the Unio do Vegetal headquarters in New Mexico. A subsequent search of Bronfmans
house turned up thirty gallons of ayahuasca. The federal government
did not file criminal charges against any member of the Unio do Vegetal, but threatened to do so. In a preemptive strike on November 2000,
mestres (leaders) of the church filed suit against the Customs Service.33
They claimed that the Customs Service had violated their First Amendment rights (free exercise of religion), the Fourth Amendment (search
and seizure), Fifth Amendment (due process), and Fourteenth Amendment (due process, equal protection) rights, as well as their rights under
the Religious Freedom Restoration Act and various international treaties
and obligations. The Unio do Vegetal asked the court to prohibit the
government from prosecuting them, to return the seized tea, the holding
of which they considered sacrilegious, and to declare legal the ceremonial use of ayahuasca, which they claimed was a necessary and essential
part of their religious practice. The U.S. 10th Circuit Court of Appeals in
Boulder, Colorado, agreed to execute a preliminary injunction exempting
the Unio do Vegetal from the Controlled Substances Act. This exemption would allow the Unio do Vegetal to import, distribute, and use a
Schedule 1controlled substance for religious purposes. The federal gov-
63
64
Chapter One
65
66
Chapter One
Boerne v. Flores did not involve the ingestion of Schedule 1 drugs, nor did it
involve a minority religion. It concerned a zoning ordinance and a church
faade. The archbishop of San Antonio, Texas, sued local zoning authorities for violating his rights under the Religious Freedom Restoration Act
by denying him a permit to expand a church as he saw fit. The Boerne
zoning authority argued that local preservation ordinances forbid the
construction and the federal Religious Freedom Restoration Act was an
unconstitutional infringement on local government rights and prerogatives. The Supreme Court agreed, ruling that Congress had exceeded its
constitutional powers by intruding onto local and state prerogatives to
regulate the health and welfare of its citizens and by predetermining what
laws were or were not constitutional under the Fourteenth Amendment,
a power reserved to the Supreme Court.
While Boerne severely restricted the application of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act, most jurists believed the compelling interest criterion it wrote into law remained in force in federal cases. But this opinion
had not been tested. And so, the questions before the Roberts Court included: What legal force remained in the Religious Freedom Restoration
Act after Boerne? Did the compelling interest test apply to federal law and
international treaty? Was the securing of health, borders, and international relations a significant enough governmental interest to trump the
free expression of a minority religion? What about the United Nations
Convention on Psychotropic Substances of 1971? In wake of 9/11, was
there a new compelling interest in state security that overrode all minority
concerns? And what, if anything, did the special rights of Native Americans as enshrined in the amended American Indian Religious Freedom
Restoration Act have to do with the rights of the Unio do Vegetal?
It may seem surprising that the American Indian Religious Freedom
Restoration Act was raised at all in Gonzales v. UDV. After all, the Unio
do Vegetal is a self-declared Christian religion not an Indigenous religion,
and as such seems to be differently situated within the governance of the
prior. Unio do Vegetal originated in Brazil, and thus has a migratory relationship to the territorial integrity of the United States. Moreover, the
Unio do Vegetal claimed that its rights were violated in relation to the
Religious Freedom Restoration Act not the American Indian Religious
Freedom Restoration Act. Nevertheless, the Unio do Vegetal, the federal
attorney generals office, and the Roberts Court all argued whether the
Unio do Vegetal were similarly situated as Native Americans to religious expression. In other words the technical legal questionwhether
neutral law of general applicability touched the free expression jurisprudence, whether the distinction between religious belief and action mattered, and whether these issues affected questions of the compelling state
interest testpivoted on broader understandings of the relevance of the
governance of the prior to the general governance of difference in late
liberalism. Who belonged within the exemptions of the governance of
difference and how did these exemptions relate to the governance of the
prior? Who were abandoned to make their own way? The answers were
disputed. Lets start with the federal attorney generals office.
According to the attorney generals office, Native Americans are an exception within the chattering crowds of religious minorities because, as
the political theorist Will Kymlicka puts it, they are a national minority
with unique if qualified claims of sovereignty based on a set of genealogical principles that linked them to the event of settler conquest.36 In other
words, they seem differently situated in the governance of the prior than
do the congregants of the uDV. The federal governments position was
simple. The Unio do Vegetal did not, according to the government, fall
within these principles of the governance of the prior. Its religious beliefs were extraterritorial and its principles of inclusion were based on
Christian proselytizing rather than genealogical descent. And yet the attorney general also argued that the members of Unio do Vegetal should
be treated as if they were Native Americans when it came to what piece of
legislation was relevant to them (the American Indian Religious Freedom
Restoration Act rather than the Religious Freedom Restoration Act).
The federal governments interest in protecting the unique status of
Native Americans by grounding their difference in the governance of
prior was not, however, motivated simply by high regard for the worth
of Indigenous difference. It was also motivated by an understanding of
how the governance of the prior helps discipline the proliferation of alternative social projects and their practical reach. The constitutional event
allows the state to sort populations into pre- and postconstitutional entities even as the territorial distortions of the constitutional event (the fact
that the coverage of the constitutional event changed over time as new
67
68
Chapter One
Restoration Act specifies that only Native Americans are except from the
Schedule 1 prohibition of the ingestion of peyote. And the Drug Enforcement Agency is slowing changing its regulatory practices to conform to
this restricted social referent. But the Native American Church itself continues to be open to all irrespective of their racial or ethnic profile. Thus
perhaps more than protecting the rights of religion, the American Indian
Religious Freedom Restoration Act restricts which members of a religion can be exempted from prosecution under the law. In other words,
the American Indian Religious Freedom Religious Act seemed to close
a gap between membership in a religion and membership in a racial descent group. The potential racial discrimination embedded in this legislation is preempted by the discourse of the governance of the prior, namely
the special trust relation the federal government has to Native American
tribes.
The gap between membership in a religious community and membership in a descent groupa difference written into the discursive separation of the Religious Freedom Restoration Act and the American Indian
Religious Freedom Reformation Actthreatened to reopen in the State
of Utah v. Mooney (2004). In Utah v. Mooney, James and Linda Mooney,
along with their church, the Oklevueha Earthwalks Native American
Church (collectively, the Mooneys) were charged by the State of Utah
with multiple felony counts of engag[ing] in a continuing criminal enterprise and of engaging in a pattern of unlawful activity by possessing
and distributing peyote, a controlled substance, to members and visitors
in their religious services.39 The State of Utah claimed that the Mooneys
and other members of the Oklevueha Earthwalks Native American
Church were not exempt from prosecution under the Controlled Substances Act because they were not members of a federally recognized
tribe. They read the definition of the term Indian (any tribe, band, nation, pueblo, or other organized group or community of Indians . . . which
is recognized as eligible for the special programs and services provided
by the United States to Indians because of their status as Indians) in the
American Indian Religious Freedom Restoration Act as exempting only
federally recognized tribal members. The Utah supreme court disagreed
with this narrow reading, finding the Mooneys Indians under the law.
Thus while the Utah supreme court loosened who may be recognized as
69
70
Chapter One
The decision of the Roberts Court to uphold the preliminary injunction against the prosecution of the Unio do Vegetal under the Controlled Substances Act seems to travel in the opposite direction from the
Howard and Rudd administrations decisions to initiate and then uphold
the Intervention. The difference between these two cases doesnt appear
merely at the surfacethe Roberts Court refusal to demonize the alternative bodily practices (illegal drug ingestion) of a minority religion occurred at nearly the same moment that the Howard government declared
a national emergency based on the specter of Indigenous bodily practices
(illegal sexual practices). Not only do we seem to be seeing a different
judgment but we also seem to be witnessing a different mood and stance
toward the minority social projects and worlds that crisscross the nation.
Gonzales v. UDV is soothing and practical, allowing and monitoring difference. In the case of the Intervention in Australia, the mood and stance
was hysterical and confrontational. As the first decision of the Roberts
Court, Gonzales v. UDV was hailed as signaling a potential softening of
judicial ideological positions, especially important after the controversial
intervention of the Supreme Court in Bush v. Gore, which effectively decided the 2000 election by halting the Florida ballot recount. The Intervention, meanwhile, was widely considered to have roiled the social and
political field, hardened ideological positions, broken longstanding alliances and friendships, and shattered a longstanding consensus on the importance of multiculturalism to the making of the Australian nation.
But were either of these cases instances of a political eventor indices of a broader political shift in recognition in late liberalism? Lets
take the Australian case. The sex panic did alter one level of the political
order. But, as much as something like a political event seems to have occurred, the question remains how to relate this level of political disruption to another level of political conservation. Did the Intervention actu-
71
72
Chapter One
flection and debate. The same can be said about the Unio do Vegetals
relationship to the governance of the prior. Are the Unio do Vegetal the
same or different from other Indigenous groups? The Unio do Vegetal
leadership argues that there is no difference between what their church
does and what the Native American Church does. And who decides
which of these will be the truth of this group: the extraterritorial nature
of the Unio do Vegetal (and then what about the Comanche empire,
which straddled the current divisions between Mexico and the United
States)42 or the Christian rewriting of pre-Christian practices (and what
about the Native American Church with its complex dialogical relation
to Christian notions of communion)?
In the Australian case, similar problems of indeterminacy arise. Sutton
might be able to differentiate between traditional and modern, customary and historical peoples, but this differentiation cannot survive an encounter with the material conditions of actual Indigenous social worlds.
What Indigenous man or woman cannot be addressed from the perspective of either the autological subject or the genealogical society? Some
have job skills in education, construction, and power and water management; some keep outstations where their deceased relatives inhabited the
landscape. Some make their way through the competing Christian ideologies that aggressively address them, casting their deceased relatives as
devils if they appear to them. Most of their modes of kinship and association have had to address competing discourses of race, friendship, and
stranger intimacy as they do nothing more than go to school, buy a can of
Coke, visit a doctor, or fill out their unemployment forms. These modes
of association are the unintelligible knots (nots) in the social divisions of
tense defining late liberalismthe part that has no part in the distribution of social roles and places. But even as they are caught in the divisions
of social belonging, the members of the Unio do Vegetal and contemporary Indigenous Australians in the Northern Territory resist this division
insofar as they remain and endure. As neither this nor that they stand as
a constant refusal of the techniques of recognition and their inversion
in late liberalism.43 They are the part that has no partthe noise of the
unsayablefound neither on one side nor on the other of the temporal
division of social space, but in the space that cannot be contained by this
division.
73
Chapter Two
76
Chapter Two
nition itself, arguing that recognition is not a single entity but is instead
one of three modes, or forms, of apprehending alternative social projects
and worlds in late liberalism. If the previous chapter was interested in the
way recognition prevents the eruption of a political event in the vicinity
of the part that has no part, this chapter asks what form, or mode, recognition takes when this moment of intelligibility is deferred, bracketed, or
denied and recognition is not able to overcome liberal intolerance.
After all, as even Le Guins short story The Ones Who Walk Away
from Omelas makes clear, the fictional citizens of Omelas have several
different ethical responses to the abused child in their midst. They reconcile. They refuse to reconcile. They stay. They leave. The public, political,
and juridical discourses surrounding the Intervention in Australia and the
U.S. Supreme Court case Gonzales v. O Centro Esprita Beneficente Unio
do Vegetal demonstrate the variety of responses that a set of nonfictional
subjects, embedded in governmental and legal institutions, take to the
injustices done to alternative social, religious, and cultural projects and
worlds in their midstincluding whether or not they experience a disciplinary action taken against them as an injustice. The responses of these
actual persons vary as surely as do those of their fictional counterparts.
They refuse recognition. They grant the favors of recognition. They decide that recognition should be granted carte blanche or on a case-by-case
basis. And these responses meet a variety of other responses outside the
strict confines of parliament, Congress, and law, such as when liberal academics and pundits say such uncontroversial things as: We need to denounce the social projects of the other (Sutton); We need to be able to
live with the impasses of justice (Scalia); And we need to proceed in a
case-by-case manner (Roberts).
The statement that we must proceed case by case, or cognate statements such as that we need to begin with what we can agree upon suggest
the complex temporal and spatial nature of recognition. Until a specific
political struggle for recognition is resolved, alternative social projects
must hide in plain or not so plain sight, and states must be ready to discipline them. Moreover, no one assumes that the social projects and worlds
denied recognition evaporate when a verdict is announced. In short, the
dynamics of recognition depend on a temporal suspension of judgment
that manifests as a social spacinga bracketing of the other in a no-mans
77
78
Chapter Two
of law waiting for permission to enter. The social worlds of the impractical and disagreeable remain in durative time. They persist. But they do
not persist in the abstract. From the perspective of dominant worlds, the
condition in which they endure has the temporal structure of limboan
edge of life located somewhere between given and new social positions
and roles, and between the conditions of the past and the promise of the
future. Nicolas Rothwell of The Australian noted this suspension of being
a year after the beginning of the Intervention: Aboriginal societies of the
Centre and Top End are now in a disquieting limbo, at the mercy of their
bureaucratic masters and administrators in distant Canberra. Everything
is transition, reform, new initiatives both economic and social. The revolution promised a year ago is not over, or even well advanced. Indeed, it
has scarcely begun.2 But from the perspective of the bracketed, the problem is how to endure the material conditions that compose their limbo.
Not only are the parts that have no part in the given orders of the sayable and visible continuing to live as they wait in their waiting rooms,
when we open the brackets of recognition and examine the clamorous,
sprawling social worlds living within, against, on top of these brackets,
we find that the broom closet might not be the best metaphor for the
spatial distribution of this form of social abandonment. And we find that
recognition might not be the most useful way of conceptualizing the
dynamics at play. And thus the second thing we need to remember is that
recognition is simply one of several forms that the apprehension of alternative social projects and worlds take in late liberalism. When the security of the state, its specific organizational integration with the market,
and its enmeshment within dominating discourses of ethics and rights
are threatened, recognition appears in a different modality. When we look
into and around the waiting rooms of history, what we see is not recognition but recognition in another state, or another state of apprehension;
namely, espionage and camouflage. By these terms, I mean to refer to
actual practices of cloaking as well as a much broader and diverse set
of discourses about modes of concealment that allow otherwise visible
organisms or objects to remain indiscernible from the surrounding environment. Espionage and camouflage are, in other words, the modes of
recognition that become visible when, as a result of some threat to late
liberal security or some bracketing of the politics of recognition, the tense
of the other is written as a suspension of the present and the future. In
79
80
Chapter Two
emerges in social time. We are told that recognition has its proper limits;
that liberals always seek to overstep those limits because of their deep
commitment to tolerance; and that, as a result, liberals must be careful to
discipline their good impulses especially at the divide between the modern autological subject and medieval genealogical society. But Clegg also
insists that the proper comportment to this trembling should be understood through a temporal spacing. In other words, he finds at hand a temporal framework on which the red line of intolerance can be drawn. The
confrontation, Clegg tells his readers, is not merely between people, but
across time. Denying them recognition is not denying recognition to the
people who are among you, but people who are in your past. The child in
the broom closet isand the Muslim next door and the Indigenous man
down the road might bein a different geological sediment.
Though hardly aligned with and strikingly more complex than Huntingtons political project, some philosophers of language have likewise
presented the problem of recognition in terms of incommensurate semantic fields. They ask how and why radically incompatible ethical and
epistemological horizons are aligned or not; how people interpret and decide between them; and how they characterize these interpretations and
the practical worlds that result within or alongside them. Scholars such as
Gadamer, de Man, and Derrida have vigorously argued about the degree,
source, and condition of distortion in translations (and interpretations)
across incommensurate semantic fields; about the risk of assigning and
acting on these translations in ordinary life; and about the social productivity of foregrounding indeterminacy and undecidability as a progressive
social ideal.5
The ability to commensurate two textual (or social) fields without distortion or the ability to decide between two translations or interpretations on the basis of truth and accuracy puts more than metaphysics at
risk (though as Derrida has noted, it also puts metaphysics at risk).6 The
stakes of these distortions seem high, given, as Jim Hopkins has argued,
that the ability to spontaneously, continually, and with remarkable precision and accuracy interpret one another seems fundamental to our
co-operative and cognitive lives.7 The American philosopher Donald
Davidson located the purest form of the philosophical problem of truth
and incommensurability in colonial history insofar as his notion of radi-
81
82
Chapter Two
cal interpretation finds its starkest expression there. Davidson uses the
phrase radical interpretation to indicate the semantic dynamics that are
operating when people interpret an utterance in the context of radical linguistic (and social) alterity.8 How could the Hawaiians have understood
James Cook, or Cook the Hawaiians, without producing serious distortions?9 As he puts it, Hesitation over whether to translate a saying of
another by one or another of various non-synonymous sentences of mine
does not necessarily reflect a lack of information: it is just that beyond a
point there is no deciding, even in principle, between the view that the
Other has used words as we do but has more or less weird beliefs, and the
view that we have translated him wrong. Torn between the need to make
sense of a speakers words and the need to make sense of his patterns of
belief, the best we can do is choose a theory of translation that maximizes
agreement.10
Davidson props the possibility of radical interpretation on the principle of charity, namely, that speakers and listeners assume that the other
is acting according to a set of rational linguistic conventions like their
own.11 This convention allows speakers and hearers constantly to readjust
their passing theories about the meaning of words as they realize that
others are not using them as the listener would. As a result, if our aim is
to understand the speaker as she or he wishes to be understood, then we
modify our own language assumptions in the direction of a speakers own
as, in the course of conversation, we realize that the two are divergent
that the semantic way the other uses hippopotamus is the way we use
orange, for example.12 In short, we negotiate charitably. And like liberal
respect, charity begins and ends at home. According to Davidson, If we
cannot find a way to interpret the utterances and other behaviors of a
creature as revealing a set of beliefs largely consistent and true by our own
standards, we have no reason to count that creature as rational, as having
beliefs, or as saying anything.13 That creature becomes noisebecomes
a creature as it becomes noise.
At the basis of all of these theories of translation, the political theorist
Mahmood Mamdani has argued, is a more or less sophisticated version
of culture talk: the idea that there are cultures and that each culture
can be defined by some internal essence or arrangement of sense and
value.14 For Mamdani and other political theorists, like Patchen Markell,
culture talk is a second-order discourse.15 It registers the facticity of a moment of embodied social dissonance and it characterizes this dissonance
as the effect of a kind of thing (culture). This social dissonance might
be a fleeting feeling at the edge of an encounter or a pronounced and
well-defined event. The occasion of a dissonance that threatens to turn
into intolerance may be publicly discussed or silently reflected upon. It
can involve human or nonhuman animals, organic or inorganic life. What
is at stake is how these exemplary moments of reasoned public debate,
animated by the trembling of recognition, sit side by side with quieter
even silentmoments of trembling and the reflections they produce. In
other words, the social terrain of late liberal recognition is not reducible
to a single kind of eventthe same kind of seismic shock that levels all
houses equally or in the same way.
Take the claim made by some of my Indigenous friends in Australia,
whom I have known and lived closely with since I was twenty-two, that
animals should be allowed to die in their own way. This is not indifference
on their part, but an ethics they themselves learned as a way of life prior
to their developing an explicit, propositionally based way of justifying it
to themselves and others. But when this dying presents, from my point
of view, unnecessary pain to an animal, my response to the competing
claims of the animals pain and my friends moral stance prompts a response that certainly has cognitive aspects, but also involves an embodied
interpretation, a set of affective and energetic interpretations. I turn my
head away as my body becomes upset, even as I think about the difference between what I think and what they think. Even if I take to heart
Donna Haraways call to take seriously the idea that human nature is an
interspecies relationshipthat within the child in the broom closet are
all sorts of living beingsI do not know how to square this hermeneutic
circle.16 And I would say that in these moments I tremble and my trembling is not in the past tense. I tremble in a durative sense. I continue to
feel the shores of liquefaction lapping at my breast each time I am confronted by these competing claims; the terror and liquefaction doesnt kill
me, nor do they lead to a simple distribution of master and slave.
And yet, for a variety of reasons, I keep the content of these reflections
close to my chest. I have not presented or debated them in publicor at
least not until here and now. At various moments, I talk with my friends
83
84
Chapter Two
Bernard Williams and disability activists such as the late Harriet McBryde
Johnson responded publicly in the genre of dispassionate argument.17
Johnsons widely reported decision to debate Singer in public was meant
to defeat the substance of Singers argument by reason and addressthe
content of her argument and the fact of who was authoring these words,
a woman born severely disabled and thus, within Singers framework, a
nonperson at the time of her birth. Singers response and the various replies to him are not at stake here.18
What is at stake is how these kinds of exchanges are characterized,
valued, and evaluated in late liberalism. In late liberal democratic contexts, these kinds of exchangesthe content of their argument and the
pragmatics of how they argueare typically understood as exemplary
acts of deliberative communication safely protected under the genre of
constitutionally protected and celebrated liberal public reason. But this
typical characterization masks the fact that Singers propositions and
Johnsons counterpropositions are not merely one kind of thinga token
of a type of thing that is stable across all social contextsamong other
kinds of things. What they were doing as they debated at Princeton University is open to multiple metadiscursive characterizations. Habermas,
for instance, might celebrate their engagement insofar as he can use it as
an instance of the procedural basis of a (re)integrated public sphere. For
Habermas, debates such as theirs enhance democratic society by modeling how justice is achieved and the good life made material in late liberalism.
But others do not agree. Many European countries would consider
Singers position as falling within the parameters of prohibited hate
speech. The redline of tolerance is drawn in front of his argument no
matter how persuasive it might beindeed, precisely because it might
have persuasive power a red line of tolerance might be needed. And Singer
is not the only person barred from proceeding. Having himself suffered
the accusation of engaging in hate speech, Singer defended in an article in
The Guardian the rights of the radical animal rights group PEtA (People
for the Ethical Treatment of Animals) to post posters headlined To Animals, All People are Nazis. As Singer noted, PEtA adapted this line from
the Polish-born Jewish writer Isaac Bashevis Singer. In the same week
that Germany and the World Jewish Congress rejected the idea that defa-
85
86
Chapter Two
87
88
Chapter Two
what ones next step will be. In any case, from a Peircean perspective, this
entire spiraling matrix of interpretation is internal to political semiosis.
It is no surprise then that Pierre Bourdieu and Paul de Man read
Peirce and Heidegger as engaged in a similar project of precognitive
understanding and rhetoric as buildingor that earlier, John Wild read
William James from the perspective of an existential phenomenology.23
Heideggers early philosophical project rested on elaborating the hermeneutic conditions of Dasein.24 Within this early philosophy, interpretationunderstanding as interpretationis not originally within propositionally based language games. As Mark Wrathall has argued, Heidegger
understood propositionally based language games as presupposing a
prior mode of interpretation (a primary meaning) in which a thing
or activity . . . refers to or relates to other activities or entities in such a
way that the disclosure of meaning is not dependent on our possessing
a system of signs.25 Understanding as interpretation is within the practical comportment of everyday lifea comportment rooted in practical
understanding and grounded in a variety of interpretants, the total effect
of which produces what Bourdieu referred to as habitus.26 This does not
mean that understanding as interpretation is outside language and consciousness, or linguistic consciousness, or that it is within the individual
subject. Understanding is instead a complex topology that interdigitates
the internal and external, subject and object, affect and reason; a topological spacing that Lacan called extimacy.27
For thinkers like Peirce, Bourdieu, and de Man what moments of trembling mean, in the sense of their semantic and propositional sense, cannot be found in the trembling itself, nor can the trembling be reduced to
semantic or propositional sense. The meaning of the trembling of recognition is only secured through a second-order interpretive actthe various available ways of saying how these trembles should be socially understood, absorbed, and distributed and the demanding environments that
impose repressive and productive consequences of using one or another
of these ways of understanding and evaluating them. These second-order
interpretative acts say what kind of thing the tremble is and thus what
proper stance (actions, relations, and feelings) one should take toward
it. But a gap, a difference, remains between these first- and second-order
modes of interpretation because they are differently grounded. Not only
89
90
Chapter Two
We can also return to a case discussed in chapter 1. In the wake of the Little
Children Are Sacred report, the Australian federal government loudly announced the end of the previous regime of cultural recognition. But this
announcement did not wipe the legislative or juridical slate clean. It was
not a sovereign act in this sense: for the most part, the existing legislation,
a maze of incommensurate laws pertaining to land usage in Indigenous
country, remained on the books. We can take even a very few of the major
bureaucratic entities and their legislative regimes affecting land usage in
the Northern Territory of Australia: Aboriginal Land Trusts set up under
the Aboriginal Land Rights (Northern Territory) Act in 1976; land councils established under the same act; the Aboriginal Areas and Protection
Authority set up under the revised Aboriginal Sacred Sites Act in 1989; the
Native Title Act passed in 1993 but then subsequently amended; the Aboriginal Councils and Associations Act, 1976; and the Local Government
Act, 1978. These pieces of legislation and their implementation place demands on (recognize) Indigenous subjects and groups in slightly to significantly different ways. The Aboriginal Land Rights Act and the Native
Title Act pivot on a model of human descent from clan-based estates.
The Aboriginal Councils and Associations Act allows for economic associations independent of these clan-based groups. The Local Government
Act is based on residential principles that do not assume descent or market associations. And the Aboriginal Areas Protection Authority can use
any of these criteriadescent, economic, residential, ritualfor making
a judgment about what aspects of the country should be registered as a
sacred siteand who has authority to register them. And groups organized on the basis of all of these acts might be operating on the same
piece of land with different intentions and outcomes.
These few legal regimes do not begin to saturate the density of property relations in the region where the Intervention was located. Other
property forms would include, at the very least, forms of title such as freehold, leasehold, life estates, ground leases, and pastoral lease and rights
regimes based on common law, international law, and statutory law.
Through these various bureaucratic entities and their regulatory regimes
pass numerous kinds of goods and services, including housing, land development, land management and protection, employment schemes such as
the Community Development Employment Program (CDEP), and more
recently, shared responsibility agreements.30 These legislative regimes derive their meaning, often explicitly, from their surrounding legislative and
discursive contexts, without these surrounding contexts fully determining that meaning or its ultimate direction. And yet, considered as a field,
these reappear as a set of incommensurate, though often mutually referring, state regimes that are themselves constantly under revision.
For example, leading up to and following the federal emergency intervention in Indigenous affairs, some of this legislation changed. Aboriginal Councils and Associations have become the Office of the Registrar of
Indigenous Corporations, and the local governments are currently being
consolidated into the twentytwenty concept: twenty central town hubs
by 2020. But these changes do not occur instantly, nor leave a pristinely
commensurated field in their wake. These competing, at times incommensurate, legislative regimes exist simultaneously even where they are
not explicitly referred to or mobilized.
It is within these dissonant, often incommensurate legislative and bureaucratic terrains that Indigenous people must make their way. And because they exist as incommensurate fields, they provide a potential field
of maneuver for Indigenous and non-Indigenous subjects supporting and
opposing these policies. In short, dissonance itself may be a means of conserving power as much as a source of interference to power. In the above
cases, the dissonances within these legislative fields provide different degrees of maneuverability or blockage to various actors within them.
It is not necessary to choose between these two broad and competing
causesthe seismic shocks that occur when two semantic-civilizational
orders collide, and the internal incommensurability within late liberalism.
The trembling of recognition is no doubt produced by any of a number of
factors internal and external to late liberalismit has plural conditions
as well as plural states. It can be caused by various social orders confronting each other, especially when a given or emergent mode of social
life challenges one or the other side of late liberal deliberative and moral
sense, or both sides at the same time. It can also be caused by struggles
within any given late liberal order, especially when moral sense and deliberative sense are metathematized as religious sense and rational sense.
And it can be located within any given social order or within any given
social subject. So a subject might find herself trembling, liquefying, be-
91
92
Chapter Two
cause, for example, she might think she should love across radical difference but in fact is physically and affectively repulsed by some aspect of
a concrete otherthey insist that I let this small animal bloat and die,
and believe that to summon the courage to kill it is to enter the domain
of abominable cruelty because each and every entity must be allowed
to encounter its own deathand because she cannot be sure if her repulsion has a theological or (merely) cultural origin, and cannot be sure
if it matters whether her repulsion has a cultural, physical, reasoned, or
spiritual ground. But she might not notice, remember, or self-consciously
consider other quasi-events of trembling. Maybe these will resurface in
her dreams, intensified or dispersed across a number of phantasmagorical
figures.
What is necessary to understand is that these moments of trembling
produce a variety of reactions, the intelligibility of which are socially external to the trembling even as the reactions are an internal expression
(interpretation) of the force of this dissonance in a scene. And it is necessary to understand that this intelligibility is embedded in a variety of
demanding environments that passively and actively enforce one mode
of intelligibility and justification over another. In other words, scholarly
and political interest in the causes of the trembling of recognition and
their interest in the problem of justice and justification when red lines of
intolerance and incarceration are drawn is due in no small part to the fact
that this trembling leads to acts of state and public enhancement of life
for some at the expense of others. After all, when recognition encounters,
or manufactures, an unrepentant alterity, it does not simply tremble. Nor
does the liberal state merely transfer these public tremors to the realm of
private beliefs (no matter how many times the transformation of public
religion into private belief is held up as the exemplary transformation of
secularism). Where the security of the state is challenged, the state of recognition publicly denounces the redlined public, enacts repressive laws to
eliminate it, and hunts down its recalcitrant members.
When recognition is formally withheld or granted as a suspended judgment, issues of justification come to the foreground. Political theorists
and political philosophers have attempted to discover some overarching
principles on which to ground justice and justification in these moments
of overt oppression. We might even say that the dominant strain of theo-
retical thought has focused on social justice in the moments that states
decide an alternative social project cannot be accepted as a member of
the national or international community. What norms can be imagined
against which judgment can be judged? To be sure, the juridical history
of constitutional democracies is littered with cases in which jurists have
noted that a prior cultural or social judgment was not based on reason
but on mere prejudice (a culturally grounded gut reaction). In other
words, when the projected future became the actual present, those who
decide who will be designated as the part who has no part come to view
their past decisions in a negative light. And yet the conservation of the
narrative configuration of tense in the new judgment insulates that new
judgment from reflexive memoryjuridical judgment from reflexive
judgment. After all, we might think that when jurists consider how many
times past judicial judgments of the worth of the other have been revised,
they would, in the face of a new decision, liquefy in terror that their judgment too will, from the perspective of the future, be revealed to have been
merely a culturally inflected gut reaction. We might expect them to understand, alongside Derrida, that Justice is annulled at the very moment of
the verdict.31 But they do not in general do so. As a result, brackets continue to proliferate without acquiring any special supernatural powers to
transubstantiate immediately or fully the life-worlds so bracketed. And
thus, for longer or shorter, and more or less effectively, these life-worlds
must develop a mode of living within the brackets of recognition. What
happens to the people who are the part that has no part in late liberalism?
What happens to recognition?
Espionage, Camouflage, Recognition
93
94
Chapter Two
ecological activists. The National Animal Interest Alliance and the American Legislative Exchange Council, which provide model legislation that
can be downloaded off their websites, were among the powerful lobby
interests that pushed the amendment of the AEPA, transforming it into
the Animal Enterprise Terrorism Act of 2006, which did as Walsh suggested, criminalizing not merely violent acts but any act that is experienced as a threat by those against whom the act is aimed and any act that
supports and promotes these acts. The Internet was being dividedon
the one hand were websites that could openly oppose the politics of the
radical ecological movement because their view of violence to nonhuman
animals could be understood as a site for public debate; on the other hand
were websites that would open their managers to criminal prosecution
because these had been effectively characterized as on the other side of
the red line of tolerance.
All of these examples presuppose a volitional agent on the other side
of the red line. The mouvance anarcho-autonome, the Earth Liberation
Front, and Earth First! are imagined to be composed of individuals who
choose to separate themselves from dominant neoliberal orders in the
creases that these orders make available and to hide themselves within
these same orders. As volitional actors they are more available to neoliberal techniques of making die, as opposed to others who might simply
find themselves in a structural space no longer valued by the market and
its cultural forces. For these people, the softer forms of letting die will
do. They will be allowed to continue to persist in the seams of neoliberalism and late liberalism until they exhaust themselves. But in both cases,
the techniques of persistence that these alternative social projects devise
must be covered in various kinds of camouflage lest too much public attention merit state attention.
Take, for instance, documents from the U.S. Supreme Courts decision
to uphold the 10th District Courts preliminary injunction that allowed
the Unio do Vegetal exemption from prosecution under the Controlled
Substance Act. During the presentation of the case, a debate emerged
about how to understand the covert means by which the Unio do Vegetal moved ayahuasca across the border. The 10th Circuit Federal District
Court acknowledged that the Unio do Vegetal president, Jeffrey Bronfman, misled customs brokers about the substance he was importing from
95
96
Chapter Two
But Robertss practical reason did more than make these worlds disappear. His practical reason also discursively and functionally integrated
the Unio do Vegetal into the same bureaucratic order that monitors the
rest of the United States through secret, though warranted, or warrantless wiretaps. Not surprisingly, many people would view Robertss practical reason to be the result of a new dynamic of recognition that predates
or postdates the 9/11 attacks. Many people have argued, in contexts more
broad than this decision, that the emergence of tactics such as camouflage and espionage postdates the attacksand indeed, that continuing
to discuss the politics of recognition now demonstrates a naive failure to
understand the fundamental transformation the liberal democratic state
has undergone.35 For them the recognition of cultural difference has been
absorbed by state security, something the courts adjudicate (such as in
Hamdan v. Gonzales, heard in the same session as Gonzales v. UDV) but
do not abrogateand something that has long been under way such as
is seen in the passage of legislation such as the Animal Enterprise Terrorism Act.
These new technologies of surveillance have already been absorbed
into new ways of conceptualizing the global market. Bruce Mehlman, the
assistant secretary for technology policy, United States Department of
Commerce, delivered a talk on February 14, 2002, at a Biometrics Consortium Conference, in which he articulated global terrorism, national
security, and economic dominance through the concept of espionage.36
According to Mehlman, biometrics would allow Americans to defend
themselves in all these domains from the perimeter-busting practices of
others, even as it would provide a means of uncloaking those camouflaged within their borders. The problematic at play is not tolerance and
worth but (bio-)informatics and population management: how to make
the camouflaged stand out, to be perceived surreptitiously, to be tracked
in order to manage its threat. Perhaps ironically, even as the Australian
state was implementing the Intervention, China was threatening to prosecute members of the Australian-British mining group Rio Tinto for domestic espionage. But, if we turn the angle of this gaze, if we are looking
from the perspective of the camouflaged, the problem is not the agony
of worth but the agony of action: getting in without being seen and clandestinely navigating internal and external perimeters in order to change
the existing order. The problem is not about being deemed worthy or
97
98
Chapter Two
having worth for who one is in ones most robust social skin, but what one
could potentially do, how one could potentially transform the world as it
is given, or dominantly given, and make it into the world that it is not. But
however much their hierarchical relationship may have changed, or intensified, since 9/11, the modal relations of recognition, espionage, and camouflage preexisted the new security state, their origins found in and tied
to the emergence of late liberalism as a response to anticolonial struggle
and new social movements. Espionage and camouflage are not new states
of recognition, nor are they the end of recognition. Rather, they assume a
different relationship as late liberalism becomes entangled in a post-9/11
neoliberalism, and produce different forms of making die.
At first blush, it seems significant to the survival of an alternative social
project that recognition can be explicitly granted, withheld, or deferred.
And for specific alternative social projects this is no doubt the case. After
all, recognition brings with it a host of material and immaterial infrastructures that help shape and capacitate life. But, as we know, every act of
recognition creates new zones of potential life that is as yet neither prohibited nor allowed. Thus, what matters from the point of view of a specific alternative social project seems to matter less from the point of view
of the dynamics of recognition.
If the distinction between explicit and deferred refusals of recognition doesnt capture the immanent social field that make these refusals
intelligible and justifiable, then it does capture a critical tactic by which
late liberalism secures the positivity of recognition. Moments of explicit
recognition of the worth of the other, or moments in which this worth is
refused, create the illusion that espionage and camouflage are external to
recognition. And this sequencing of recognition, camouflage, and espionage is an important tactic for evacuating the durative lives of those living
in the brackets of recognition. A typical way of understanding the relationship among recognition, espionage, and camouflage, is to see recognition as the first moment, followed by espionage and camouflage. Or to see
espionage and camouflage as the first moments, followed by recognition.
In both cases, recognition, espionage, and camouflage are seen as distinct
moments, each external to the other. But when we view recognition from
inside its brackets we begin to understand recognitions multiple modalities and better appreciate the clamorous, sprawling social worlds living
99
100
Chapter Two
of life circulate, or are prohibited from circulating, across various communicative media.
Moreover, as I hope the previous chapters discussion of the Australian
Intervention made clear, when the dynamics of recognition are operating within the metadynamics of the autological subject and genealogical
society, governments and publics can rapidly shuttle between calls for
the recognition of social difference and calls to refuse not merely social
difference but to reduce life to such a degree that that social difference
cannot survive. In these displaced zones of recognition people sometimes
put their energies into the reelaboration of the self rather than the identification of the self for certain others. In these social fields, the point may
well be to reshape habitudes ahead of recognition, to test something out
rather than translate it, not to produce meanings that can be translated, or
embodiments that can be recognized. This is especially true when we are
discussing subaltern publics that violate moral and deliberative sense. By
the time normative law and publics deliberate, commensurate and decide
their horizons of moral sense, the bodies before them have changed, as
have (hopefully) the conditions of embodied reason itself. But to engage
in these practices of self-elaboration or self-maintenance a social group
may spy on those who join them, assume that they are being spied on, and
camouflage themselves in the cloak of authorized identities.
Chapter Three
Road Kill
Ethical Substance, Exhaustion, Endurance
If late liberalism, as distinct from laissez-faire liberalism and neoliberalism, refers to the effects of
anti- and postcolonial and new social movements
on how difference is treated in liberal worlds, the
1970s saw a robust set of alternative languages of
difference emerging in these movements wake.
In 1977, three years after Ursula Le Guin received
the Hugo Award for Best Short Story for The
Ones Who Walk Away from Omelas, Charles
Burnett submitted his master of fine arts thesis,
the film Killer of Sheep, to the School of Film, Uni-
102
Chapter Three
Road Kill
the chaos of local gray economies. They finally purchase a used engine for
fifteen dollars from a local purveyor of such items, lug it down a precarious set of stairs, nearly but not quite dropping it along the way, and then
heave it onto the back of a borrowed truck. But by the time that they have
reached this final platform of their desire, they experience themselves as
having no energy left. And this is not a metaphor. It is a fact of muscle,
bone, and will, whatever we mean by this last term. The motor sits on
the edge of the truck bed. They do not move it any further. Their bodies
exhausted, as well as their minds, they convince each other the motor
is secure. They start the truck, move a few feet, and the engine falls off.
Thats it. The engine is busted. The motor wont run now if it ever would
have.
No matter that Burnett ends this meditation on race, poverty, and
hope with Stan in the same position in the same slaughterhouse pushing
a group of sheep down a metal corridor to their slaughter, he claims his
film was meant to be hopeful. What is hopeful about Stan is his perseverancehe has decided to persevere and fight on despite societys place
for him.3 Stan remains a thing in Spinozas sense, a particular modification of the possible if unknowable attributes of life, insofar as he continues to strive (conatus) to persevere in his being. We might say that Stan
stares in the face the question of how to endure as he strives to persevere.
But it is important for us to note that Stan himself would like to change
the conditions in which he striveshe is striving to change the conditions in which this perseverance occurs. The harrowing nature of the film
is the vertiginous precipice of Stans being and becoming as the viewer
comes to understand that the only thing separating Stan from the sheep
is his will to persevere.
Insofar as Burnett sees these kinds of spaces as hopeful, as sites where
a potential alternative social project exists in the actual world, he shares
this optimism with a strain of critical theorythe immanent critical
theory of scholars, such as Gilles Delueze, who were also developing a
theory of potentiality in the 1970s. Burnett filmed Killer of Sheep during
the transition from Keynesian liberalism to neoliberalism and during the
emergence of late liberalism as a strategy for governing the challenge of
postcolonial and new social movements. Thus whether intending to or
not, Burnett was a part of a much broader discourse of potentiality and
103
104
Chapter Three
endurance, of hospitality and livability. In 1979, Commonwealth delegates signed the Lusaka Declaration of the Commonwealth on Racism
and Racial Prejudice at the fifth Commonwealth Heads of Government
Meeting in Lusaka, Zambia. The Lusaka Declaration stated the commitment of signatory states to legal equality without any distinction or exclusion based on race, colour, sex, descent, or national or ethnic origin.
The declaration focused on three main groupsthose suffering under
apartheid in South Africa, economic immigrants, and Indigenous minorities. In relation to Indigenous minorities, the Lusaka Declaration noted
that the legacies of colonialism and racism in the past may make desirable special provisions for the social and economic enhancement of indigenous populations. In doing so it acknowledged that Indigeneity was
not a form of life that was finding it easy to flourish within the settlerstate. In Canada, Australia, and the United States, the life expectancy,
educational levels, and disease profiles of Indigenous people better fit the
third world than the first world in which they were situated. The Australian states commitment in the 1970s to the politics of the cultural recognition (self-determination) of Indigenous people through land rights
legislation should be seen in this broader light.
At issue were not merely the inhabitants of the earth, but also the earth
itself. In 1979, James Lovelock, a chemist and National Aeronautics and
Space Administration consultant, published Gaia: A New Look at Life on
Earth. In it he proposed that the earth was a supraorganism of which
humans were mere part rather than center. The Gaia theory helped spawn
the deep ecology movement, whose scope was a biospheric perspective
on all living and nonliving parts of the earthand critiqued the distinction between living and nonliving as being nothing more than the deforming nature of the human perspective. Although castigated by the likes of
Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Dawkins as more high priests of a neopagan new age religion than natural scientists, Lovelock and his collaborators have continued to seek science-based evidence for their theory.
Their aim is not merely to test a hypothesis but to influence human governance overor withina form of life that is not, by many natural science definitions, life. For most natural scientists, life is that which can replicate itself. Gaia cannot. It can only provide the conditions of hospitality
within which the life proper to it can flourish. Thus, if Gaia is life, then it
Road Kill
is a life whose function is not to replicate itself, but others. PEtA, Earth
First!, the Animal Liberation Front, the Earth Liberation Front: these are
the names of only a few of the best known ecology groups pushing every
member of the human race to assume some relationship between his or
her present personal happiness and the present suffering of other species
on the earth and the earth itself. The citizens of Omelas must think outside the closet.
But the earth has its competitors. In 1979, Margaret Thatcher became
prime minister of Great Britain. During her tenure she set into motion
what were then radical principles of limited government through the dismantling of key elements of social welfare; expanded market freedom
through the crushing of trade unionism and the privatization of state-run
enterprises in schooling, education, and health; and taxation reform in
which taxes on the wealthy were significantly lowered and indirect taxes
significantly increased, thereby redistributing the burden of state finance
from the rich to the middle class and poor. All state-based regulatory
regimes, including environmental protection, were portrayed as hostile to
the flourishing of capital (an argument that reemerges in debates about
the human contribution to global climate change). Ronald Reagan would
become president of the United States a year later, after pushing through
a similar policy agenda in California during his terms as governor from
1967 to 1975. Thatcher and Reagan would become the heroes of the Atlantic neoliberal movement. Key to their governing strategy was dismantling
social alliances within the Labour and Democratic parties of their respective countries through the demonization of racial and sexual minorities
and alternative publics.4 If the conservative state was to replicate itself, it
needed to deny the conditions of hospitality within which progressive life
forms flourished.
Meanwhile, throughout 1979, Foucault was presenting his Collge de
France lectures on the birth of biopolitics.5 The course was the third of a
series focusing on the arts of governance and formations of power (the
first two were Society Must Be Defended and Security, Territory, Population).
In the course, Foucault proposed a series of shiftsor reorganizations
that marked the advent of biopolitics, including a shift from law to truth;
from the rights of man to the efficiencies of markets; and from revolutions against the state to management by the state.6 These reflections on
105
106
Chapter Three
biopolitics occurred during the same period that Foucault was working
on his histories of sexuality and beginning to reflect on askesis and ethical substance. In The Use of Pleasure, for instance, Foucault argued that
in the Greek episteme the ethical substance was bodily pleasure insofar
as it was the material of moral reflection, conduct, and evaluation.7 The
ethical work (travail thique) of the self was to establish proper conduct in
relation to this ethical substancethe prime material of a persons moral
conductso as to bring into being the self that was the object of ones
behavior.8 But how does one endure the conditions of neoliberalism and
late liberalism long enoughor in a sturdy enough fashionto accomplish this performative trick?
This was not Foucaults focus at the time. A number of more recent
critical theorists have, however, taken up the broad problem of how to
understand the intersection of biopolitics and ethical substance in the
light of broader transformations of liberal markets and powers. Judith
Butler, Rosi Braidotti, Elizabeth Grosz, and Brian Massumi, among others,
have attempted to formulate a critical theory of vulnerability, bodily materiality, and embodied potentiality that would have as its ground something other than a metaphysics of substance. These and other scholars
rejected the understanding of substance as embedded in a hierarchy of
being in which being has a primary sense (substance) and a secondary
sense (qualities, quantities, relations, and modalities of substances). In
other words, they rejected the idea that substances are kinds of beings
that are self-identical, while quality, quantity, and so on can only predicate, modify, and find a dwelling in substances. The problem critical theorists faced was how to address substance, materiality, and embodiment
without treating substance as a singular, stable, independent, and ultimate
referent of an immovable and unmoving being against which social and
culture forces brace, qualify, quantify, or relate?9 The difficulty of finding
a space between the metaphysics of substance and some other ordering
of substance has led to accusations that critical theory simply evacuated
substanceor, the bodyor made everything socially constructed,
docile, and perfectly malleable to language games. Butlers work is often
presented as an exemplary case of how the critique of the metaphysics
of substance, intended to radically destabilize normative governance,
has unintentionally led to a radical desubstantialization of the body and
world.
Road Kill
In response to this reception, many critical theorists have tried to specify further what they were seeking to do when they crossed the governance of life with the ethics of substance. Since Gender Trouble, Butler
has been quite careful to specify what she meant by the metaphysics of
substance and to what aspect of life she was applying her critique. Her aim
was not to evacuate substance per se. She sought to critique the ontology
of self-identical, self-enclosing being and the mobilization of this ontology in the governance of persons. How, she asked, was the deployment
of a metaphysics of immovable and original substance used to support
the politics of gender and sexuality? Critiquing the metaphysics of substance mattered because of the ways in which this metaphysics propped
up the liberal humanist concept of the (sexed) person, and the humanist
governance of populations through a notion of the proper life of substantial anatomy.10 To resist biopolitical governance we had to decenter the
self-identical substance in which it covertly dwelled. The decentering that
was needed had to go beyond the usual operations of subjects and their
predicates, substances, and the attributes. The critique of the metaphysics
of substance needed not merely to take an ethical stance against the determination of gender identity by a self-identical anatomical substance
(the sexist stance); nor merely to take an ethical stance against the multiple qualifications of self-identical anatomical substance by gender (the
culturalist stance). It had to fundamentally resist the biopolitics operating
through these ontologies, and epistemologies, of self-abiding substance.
Power did not merely make attributes stick to substances. Power produced cartilage and skinand life itselfin such a way that attributes
emerged as natural to them and thus was, in critical ways, cosubstantial
with them.
And yet there remains a deep confusion about the grounds and aims
of critique when critique is influenced by a concept of biopolitics and
aimed at substance and its ethical reflection. Or, put another way, critical
confusion arises when the governance of life intersects with life, the bodywithout-organs with the body-with-organs. As a result, a funny thing happened on the way to decentering substance, interrogating the conditions of
its formations, and formulating a politics of hospitable dwelling organized
around ethical substance (reflecting ethically on the techniques of the
self). Everything took on an almost infinite plasticity or such an extreme
potentiality that any acknowledgment of the actuality and consequences
107
108
Chapter Three
Road Kill
stripped more or less easily depending on what they were made of. Their
material composition would influence their functionality and whether it
would be exhausted as the nuts were rounded. In other words, the shaping, carving, and assembling of materiality encounters the material being
shaped, carved, and assembled. In this way, the forms of equipment that
compose the discursive construction of materiality are constantly producing embodied life and unintegrated life at the same time. There is always
a shaping and an errantness. The unintegrated, errant aspect of materiality is what I am calling carnality. This dynamic between corporeality and
carnality is not merely a function of equipment in a narrow sense, but an
entire arrangement of the condition in which someone builds a world
in the case of Stan, not merely that the nuts he uses can be made of a
harder or softer, more or less pliant steel, but also that he only has so much
money to spend renovating his car, and so must purchase the cheaper,
softer versions that are more liable to being stripped. The errant nature of
carnality is not, however, merely negative. It iscarnality is always within
corporeal formations. But the difference between corporeality (the arts
of material formation) and carnality (the mattering forth of the worth
vis--vis these arts of formation) can, as this chapter will show, become
the positive occasion for alternative forms of life.
All of these ways of specifying aspects of embodied being are efforts to
answer the charge of the evacuation of the materiality of being in the critique of the organization of matter. Second, critical theorists emphasize
that the biopolitical is not a space of life but a spacing of life; not a living
difference but a differential within the living. Unfortunately, much of this
discussion has focused on genealogies of Greek and Roman antiquities
internal to European governmentalities, rather than the emergence of
critical cleavages within biopolitics at the intersections of neoliberalism
and late liberalism. I will come back to this. Third, critical theorists focus
on the conditions of emergence of the otherwise rather than the origin of
the other. As Deleuze put it, sounding much like the geneaological Foucault, the point is not to discover the eternal or the universal, but to find
the condition under which something new is produced.14 And fourth,
critical theorists consider these differentially distributed zones of vulnerability and abandonment as spaces in which, at least potentially, a new
ethics of life and sociability could emerge. These four points are critically
109
110
Chapter Three
Road Kill
In 2008, in the middle of Anson Bay, at the mouth of the Daly River in
the Northern Territory of Australia, I was crashing about in a ten-foot tin
dinghy with friends of mine, and some kids in our care. They are Indigenous and Australian. I am neither. The adults and I are all roughly the
same age, though I am the oldest. We had known each other for twentyfour years at that point. We were out on the boat that day doing preliminary work on what we were calling the mobile phone project, a digital
project that seeks to use mixed-reality technology to embed traditional,
historical, and contemporary knowledge back into the landscape. Imagine a tourist, or one of our great-great-grandchildren in the same area.
They open our website, which shows where a gPS-activated mixed-reality
story is located, and then download this information into their smartphone. Now imagine this same person floating off the shore of a pristine
beach in Anson Bay. She activates her gPS and video camera and holds up
her smartphone. As she moves the phone around she see various hypertexts and video options available to her. Suddenly the land is speaking its
history and culture without any long-term material impact on the landscape. And the person can only hear this story in the place from which
it came.
On that particular day we were trying to get to Banagula, where many
of the stories would be located. Banagula is a beach on the southern shore
of the vast and semi-remote estuarine Daly River. It was the dry season,
when the tides forcefully rush into and out of the Daly River. As they did,
our dinghy reared up and slammed down in the open sea. To move the
boat anywhere but straight into the waves would capsize the boat. To continue straight into them was giving us head concussions and hypothermia.
The motor we had bought, cobbling together our various monetary and
111
112
Chapter Three
social resources, was not powerful enough either to lift the dinghy above
the waves or to navigate them with firm intent. This was the only boat
available to us, and it had a hole in it. There was no paddle. No one had life
vests. We worried about the fuel we were expending, having had only so
much money to fill up the few plastic containers onboard. The one worry
we didnt have was food. We were skilled hunters and we had collected
a bounty of road kill along the way, some of which was on board. In our
immediate surround, other boats, powered by enormous motors, cruised
past us, smoothly lifting well-groomed white bodies across the water.
Why were we doing this? A simple answer would be that we thought
our mobile phone project might help reanimaterather than reproducea local understanding of the relationship among place, people,
and knowledge that is oriented to the production of mutual obligation
rather than detached truth, even while it might provide the basis for a
new media tourist enterprise. For my Indigenous colleagues to know is
to practice an embodied commitment to place that over time becomes an
embodied obligation. To know is an exercise, an askesis, whose goal is to
produce embodied obligation between places and its peoples. But as in
Stans case in Killer of Sheep, these exercises of the self must be supported
materially. Thus, we all hoped that this form of knowing might produce
a dual form of valueepistemological and capital. In the meantime, like
Stan, my Indigenous colleagues must find a way of enduringof capacitating the will to endureuntil these material supports are in place. Their
bodies must be able to endure the transition. The equipment in which
their bodies are embedded must be able to endure the transition.
Like Stan, my friends live in a world that is hardly ready to hand. If
ethical substance is the material of ones reflexive actions, the material of
their reflexive action exists within a given organization of power that continually throws them in the vertiginous gap of being and becoming and
failing to become. The major federal legislative accomplishment effecting
Indigenous people in the Northern Territory, the Aboriginal Land Rights
Act of 1976, only obliquely addressed the conditions of their lives. They
grew up in a small Indigenous settlement during the heyday of cultural
recognition (self determination). But while they practiced the rituals
and knew the traditional narratives that composed the surrounding lands,
they failed to meet the narrow legal definition of the local descent group.16
Road Kill
And the men and women in this boat are hardly atypical. While national
publics celebrated the redemptive powers of self-determination, the local
condition of Indigenous life hardly improved. If you are Indigenous in
Australia it is statistically probable that your life is and will be very much
worse than that of other Australians in terms of health, education, wealth,
life expectancy, and mental outlook. Take Linda Yarrowin, who was thirtyfive at the time we made this trip. By then she had lost five of her nine siblings (to septicemia, tuberculosis, pneumonia, collision with car, throat
cancer). Her father and his brothers had died from aneurisms and kidney
failure when they were in their mid-fifties, near to the average life expectancy of Indigenous men. In 2007, Linda and the others on the boat had
abandoned their natal community because of a wave of horrific violence
there, even though in leaving they lost a rare thing for Indigenous young
adults, permanent jobs in education and infrastructure. The riot that led
them to make the decision to leave was so notorious that the local government promised them homes in the area where we were working on the
cell phone project.
Thus, when I refer to those of us on the boat, the we that I conjure is
both a joint and divided being. Whereas in Killer of Sheep, Burnett rarely
shifts focus from the shared experience of African American members
of the Watts ghetto, for those of us on the boat, not all members share an
equivalent relationship to a variety of resources, nor are we the outcome
of equal kinds of social investments and the futures. We are engaged in
a joint social project and yet each of our projects is slightly askance the
other. We are a unified social group from the perspective of this social
project and yet the we is divided, and this division is not merely between them and me. Each of them has a different individual project,
as will become clear over the next two chapters, because of larger or
smaller differences in upbringing, ability, and aspiration. But apropos
to the discussion at hand, they and I are starkly divided according to a
broad set of social statistics. And these statistics are not outside the boat.
The boat is the artifact of our various potentials. My friends know where
to find used and exhausted objects we can recycle into living materials;
I can funnel salary and research funds and bureaucratic connections.
But none of this is enough; and none of it could ever support more than
what we have. Our affective attachments and anxieties are also different
113
FEmALE
mALE
ConDition*
Surviving
13
14
1 renal disease
7 homeless
3 diabetes
1 heart disease
15 not known
Deceased
31
25
4
2
61
2
4
67
8
4
44
21
16
43
Siblings
3 infant mortality
1 vehicular
1 tuberculosis
1 septicemia
1 cancer
1 renal disease
1 murder
Their Parents
Surviving
Deceased
Average age at death
The Parents Siblings
Surviving
Deceased
Average age at death
Road Kill
though we had then known each other for twenty-four years. When I
leave this boat and then Australia I enter a very different set of localities
and demanding environments than they do. All of this is made harder
by the 2007 Intervention, when state funds were radically curtailed for
projects such as ours. And then, by the fall of 2008, the market mechanism was in total shambles. Every capital enterprise we approached to
help finance the training and infrastructure of our project wanted reassurances that an immediate market product could be produced. And
the state refused to fund any projects that could not demonstrate a market outcome.
We eventually made it to Banagula. On other days we dont make it
back or do so barely. But we keep meeting and trying to raise resources
to support the project. We are neither defeated, nor are we successful. We
persevere. But if the most general purpose of this project is to coconstitute
human bodies and geontological place by using the multimedia capacities of the Internet to reinforce local protocols about land use, knowledge
acquisition, and embodied obligation, then the actual lives supporting
this ethical practice hardly seem sufficient to achieve its goals. We are a
miniscule group if one takes even the smallest step backward from this
scene. The context of these peoples lives may be typical, but their will
to persevere is not. I could give you a variety of statistics about the percentage that this small group of people represents from any of a variety
of social perspectives. Behind us are enormous crowds of people who
cannot, could not, or did not survive the initial exclusions of recognition
built into the politics of recognition that subtended self-determination
and the subsequent abandonments of the federal Intervention. So small
is this percentage that their existence as a group of people persevering in
the sea is indeed miraculous.17
It is true that doing something keeps everyone from sliding into nothing; a point I will return to in the next chapter. But getting anywhere in
this context involves a variety of illegal and quasi-legal actionswhich
again differentially affect us. I can lose my visa privileges. They can be incarcerated, as little infractions become a criminal record. For instance, the
same vehicles that Altman and Hinkson describe as creating the conditions for a new type of Indigenous territoriality are often unroadworthy
and unregistered.18 Driving infractions slowly accumulate, often leading
115
116
Chapter Three
Rather than these questions of endurance, resistance, and will, critical theory has by and large focused on two other problems that arise in
the vicinity of alternative social projects. On the one hand, it asks what
are the conditions in which new forms of life emerge, and, on the other
hand, it asks how one judges (evaluates, assesses) one form of life over
another. Much of the most heated debate in contemporary critical theory
has revolved around these two questions as they are differently addressed
by normative and immanent social theory.21 I have already mentioned
Deleuzes argument that the perpetual variation between vis existendi
and potentia agendi provides a space where new forms of life can emerge.
Michel Serres, the philosopher of science whose work helped found the
new science studies of Bruno Latour, provides a more materialist account
of the same in his romping account of the parasite. Serres plays on the
dual meaning of parasite in French, as an organism that lives on or in
another organism and as static or noise. For Serres, static, or noise, is the
indwelling outcome of every space of building.22 His understanding of
Road Kill
117
118
Chapter Three
ated relationship to a partially working world, and the low level of camouflage and espionage that using and being in sublegal equipment entail.
This way of life is recycled back and forth across forms of materiality.
Their paths of thought and existence are traced through and in these
assemblages of materiality.24 Those copper wires and the boat and engine
that cant lift above the waves are a part of my friends bodies as certainly
as their cartilage and blood pressure. The entire contraption of it- andus slams into our differently cared-for tendons, exhausting all, but some
more seriously than others. Then tendons become one more thing that
must be repaired without the proper resources to do so. In short, materiality (carnality)flesh and machineemerges out of as much as it is the
late liberal and neoliberal regime (corporeality) that addresses us all but
all of us differently.
No one is going to kill us or lock us up for trying to succeed, though
many of this group will be locked up for using illegal resources; they are
just going to let us exhaust ourselves. They are making a wager that few
people will be able to be like Stan or the group on our boat, so few that
the otherwise we represent will never be able to sustain itself, let alone extend, thicken, and become dominant. Late liberalism knits together internationally a careful weave of sovereign killing (capital punishment and
assassinations), criminalization of life staples such as certain food, drugs,
and forms of protective gear, and self-righteous neglect. All three tactics,
insofar as they presume universal access to legal forms of self-subsistence,
are legal forms of bad faith.
In other words, those of us on the boat trying to cross Anson Bay are
not being killed by the state in any way that would be recognizable as
state killing. As Foucault observed, the state only rarely exercises its right
to kill. Instead it directs life, letting those who wish to swim against the
tide to do so until they cross a line or exhaust themselves. And, as Serres noted, the struggle for recognition rarely commences before the outcome is certain: There is no war. Or there is only war when the result
is certain. There is murder but not war. There is no equality. There is no
face-to-face.25 Most opposition to alternative social projects happens in
a different way. An authorless wager is made that very few people will be
able to continue to preserve in the face of prevailing material obstacles.
They will not be able to sustain their perseverance. So the wager is made
Road Kill
to wait until an alternative social project exhausts itself, produces marketable values, or becomes a serious threat to late liberalism.
Lets say a coast guard catches us without life jackets on an unsound
boatwe might be fined. This fine wouldnt be calibrated according
to our incomes. Something like this happened. In July 2009, this same
group of friends and I were in Darwin looking for material to fix a car
when a fisheries and water official came to the door of one of the houses
we keep in Darwin. The official wanted to discuss a fine he was, perhaps,
obligated to give one of my friends, the named owner of the boat we use.
A few months before, the boat had stalled again, this time drifting off to
sea. After some time, realizing that the seas would not run in their favor
this time, they set off a boat alarm that signals an emergency. They were
rescued. But no one told them that, because the boat was not equipped
with the necessary safety equipment and was overloaded with people,
they would be heavily fined. My friends were lucky that day. The official
used his discretion to lower the fine significantly. Even so, if my friends
were forced to pay the fine they would have to decide whether to skimp
on fuel for the boat, food for the month, or shoes for their children; to
take a job that might pay better but would never give them the temporal and material resources to make this trip across the bay. Because it
appears to be their choice, no one seems to be killing their will to be
otherwise.
But static is neither abstractly positive nor negative. Serres notes,
Noise is a joker necessary to the system. It can take on any value, and is
thus unpredictable so that the system is never stable.26 Take, for instance,
another boat ride for the same project in 2008. At a place called Bamayak,
four of us got off the boat to look inland for a water hole. The rest motored
off to go fishing. When, near sunset, we returned to the beach where wed
gotten off, our boat was nowhere in sight. There we were, stuck in a region
without human population or infrastructure. We had found swamp water
deep in the hinterland, and there were shellfish in the mangrove swamps,
so we werent going to starve or die from thirst anytime soon. But no one
wanted to spend the night warding off the plague of mosquitoes sure to
come at sunset. After a while, we spotted a small dinghy on the horizon
coming slowly toward us. On board were three white people. We recognized them as part of an exclusive, expensive tourist fishing outfit that
119
120
Chapter Three
operates just off Indigenous lands. When we asked if they could spare a
bottle or two of water they told us they didnt have much. It was clear that
we were stranded in the middle of nowhere. And we could see their huge
mother ship anchored offshore, no doubt keeping the beer chilled for
their return.
Oh well, alls well that ends well. Just before the dusk raised the whir
of mosquitoes, we saw our boat on the horizon, heading toward our
shore. They also had been stranded. The motor had refused to start. Why
it stopped working and why it started working again soon became the
topic of a heated conversation. We traded possibilities, which soon sorted
themselves into three: engine failure, say, a faulty spark plug or saltcorroded wiring; punishment from maroi, old people who lived in the
landscape, who were punishing us for never visiting them; the Christian
God, who looks after everyone if they believe in his son Jesus Christ. We
mulled these possibilities over. People took various positions and various
combinations of positions in the argument on the boat. But it wasnt clear
whether we could hold these three possibilities simultaneously, nor what
the goods and futures offered by each would do in the worlds we variously
inhabited. It was 2008, after all. Every day we heard on the television and
radio, and read in the paper, about a national emergency in relation to
the abuse of children in Indigenous communities in the Northern Territory. The states obligation to self-determination was being thrown out
the window. Did being in a world of maroi do anything, explain anything,
lock anything together in such a way that it made other statements and
practices practical or impractical, self-evidently true or absurd, coherent
or incoherent, sane or mad? But in this incoherence and madness, we are
obliged to feel this problem, we find ourselves responsible for it, even if
in the negative formation.
It may be exactly this experience of obligation and responsibility that
makes our adventure an ethical act, and the geontological an ethical substance in Foucaults sense. But we are not trying to become something
different. We are instead trying to extend something over space and time
that has no viable language outside this iteration of its persistence. We are
trying to be within a social imaginary in which the substance of human
life is cosubstantial with geological/geographic life. We believe, to various degrees of conviction, that the essence of their ancestors, whose route
Road Kill
If you look up the name Project X on the internet, you will find that it
refers to a movie, a place, a building, and an idea about the radical ecological movement. The movie Project X, starring the young Matthew Broderick, critiques animal experimentation through a sentimental story about
an air force pilot and a chimpanzee who has been taught sign language.
Project X is also a social project located in a small intentional radical faerie
community in central Tennessee. In 2006, one member of Project X, Sandor Katz, published The Revolution Will Not Be Microwaved, a book on the
radical food movement. Some of the movements he discusses in the book
include feral foraging, dumpster diving, food gleaning, and road kill collection. Like many books written for the progressive Left, The Revolution
Will Not Be Microwaved is written in a mixed genre: a to do and how to
do book. Like The Monkey Wrench Gang, Edward Abbeys lightly fictional
121
122
Chapter Three
Road Kill
existence within a specific social imaginary. Waste oil is only waste and
oilit has the qualities and modalities of waste and oilfrom within
the social machinery of capital. Oil, and specific oils, is the corporeal
effect of a specific construction of materiality, a manufacturing process,
and its technical and social relations of production. Waste is a termand
a set of attitudesused to refer to the errant, unintegrated remainder of
this construction process.
But if Marx understood nature to be the historical residue of human
activity, Katzs deep-ecological point of view roots material unfolding in
a posthuman perspective. In an online interview Katz foregrounds the
interpenetration of beings: In every breath that you ever take without
going to the grocery store, there are untold numbers of different microorganisms, including not only bacteria, but fungi, and who knows what
else.28 These breaths and these substances are produced and dwell in
industrial forms of agrocapital but are not reducible to these forms.
Insofar as they are not, they are capable of creating new forms and
aggregations of life and exemplify the distinction between the orders of
carnality and corporeality. Oil is burned or cannot be burned under certain technological conditions, but in being burned it produces something
else. It produces a material remainder within the organization of neoliberalism and late liberalism that then provides the material conditions in
which new social projects can be built. This material dynamic between
corporeality and carnality sweeps into itself an assemblage of interlocking
concepts, materials, and forces that include human and nonhuman agencies and organisms. The flesh that Katz is working with is not humanist
flesh. Nor is there any easy separation between flesh and nonflesh. For
Katz and supporters of the deep ecology movement, the separation of
the flesh from nonflesh, human flesh from bacteria and fungus, entails
not only the act of separation but also a claim about sovereigntywhat
carnal forms, and in what configurations, have the right to exist, survive,
be killed? What can be exhausted because this exhaustion is necessary
for the endurance of something else? Deep ecology, posthumanism, and
biopolitics would seem to converge around a central problem even as the
issue of exhaustion raises, like a worm curled in the heart, the problem of
endurance, of what endures and what can explain the fact of endurance.
Thus only in the most severely restricted and artificial sense does capi-
123
124
Chapter Three
tal saturate the material conditions of the world. It may produce and commodify a kind of industrial substance (oil) in order to be a commodity
(have exchange value) that can produce another kind of commodity (a
deep-fried food with certain qualities); and make a commodity chain that
divides the world into commodities and wasteful excess. Capital makes oil
and waste simultaneously. But, for Katz, it also makes a different kind of
excess, a difference beyond capital, outside the containment or definition
of capital. This excess has at least two dimensions. It has the dimension
of substance: forms of being that emerge from new biotic habitats. And it
has the dimension of relationality: forms of relationality that can emerge
from the striated possibilities of these new substances and habitats. Katz
seeks to intervene in this process by recycling capital waste production
into an anticapitalist social movement and a set of new social relations
that will underpin them.
But even as Katz and others engage in a practice of life whose ethical substance is biospheric, their project is liable to absorption by capital
whose economic horizon is global. Not long after Katz began his biofuel
project, biofuels emerged as a significant sector of the consumer market and commodity speculation. Biofuel was, of course, just one sector
within a more generally frenzied market in commodity speculation. Each
nation made use of different kinds of materialsin Australia it was ores
and minerals; in the United States, biofuel; in Africa, precious metals
and stones; and in oPEC nations, oil. At the height of the commodity
boom, the Australian dollar came close to parity with the U.S. dollar, further suppressing the financial underpinning of the mobile phone project
I discussed in the last section. As U.S. corporate agriculture shifted from
the food to biofuel market, the price of basic food products such as rice,
flour, and corn rose significantly. This led in turn to a new or intensified
exhaustion of people in places such as Egypt, Central Africa, and Indonesia, where government-subsidized staples and rocketing prices created
a crisis of government.29 In a draft report, A Note on Rising Fuel Prices,
not intended for circulation but widely available on the Internet, Donald
Mitchell notes that the World Banks index of food prices increased 140
percent from January 2002 to February 2008. He attributes this precipitous increase to a number of factors but singles out the large increase in
biofuels production in the US and EU.30 Practices cultivated by people
Road Kill
like Katz in one zone of social abandonment were absorbed into regulated and unregulated liberal and neoliberal capital that in turn led to the
creation or intensification of new zones of social abandonment.31 What
we witness in all these alternative social projects seeking to develop a new
ethical substance, such as Katz is trying to door to sustain one such
as we were doing in our boatis an entwinement of endurance and exhaustion. We can think of the exhaustion of both flesh and material from
two perspectives: the exhaustions produced by and then reabsorbed into
the system, such as waste oil, and the exhaustions produced when trying
to create alternative ethical substances. In encouraging these new substances and relations, which actually dwell in the world even though they
have no proper dwelling there, Katz and others produce themselves as a
form of excessthings that can be exhausted, killed, placed in suspended
animation, or redeployed in a market. As Katz notes, many of the practices he describes violate statutory laws and social norms, to say nothing
of placing the practitioner under the general cloud of opprobrium that
settles over a radical environmental activist.
In the United States, a series of federal acts has labeled radical environmentalists as the number one domestic terrorist threat. The most
notorious of these federal acts are the Animal Enterprise Terrorism Act
of 2006, which amended and renamed the Animal Enterprise Protection
Act of 1992, and the Violent Radicalization and Homegrown Terrorism
Prevention Act of 2007. The amendments codified in the Animal Enterprise Terrorism Act are significant in two ways: first, they define violence
from the perspective of the offended party; second, the promotion, circulation, or support of violent acts include reporting on them in online
forums. Another thing that was new was the focus that the Federal Bureau
of Investigations placed on enforcing the most extreme readings of the
law. Managers of these online forums could be, and were, prosecuted. The
first examples of this new zeal were the so-called ShAC-7 (the corporation, Stop Huntington Animal Cruelty, and six activists associated with
it) and the Sacramento prosecutions of Earth Liberation Front members
and the emergence of a cross-agency strategy called Operation Backfire
targeting radical ecological movements.32 The ShAC-7 were not prosecuted for engaging in violent acts but for taking a political position in
relation to them in an online forum. The federal prosecution presented
125
126
Chapter Three
numerous witnesses who testified to having been incited to commit violent acts after reading the forum and to having experienced the forum and
other street activisms as violent threats.
As proposed in 2007, the Violent Radicalization and Homegrown Terrorism Prevention Act, amended to the Homeland Security Act, would
receive an estimated budget of $22 million over four years. In it, violent radicalization would be defined as an extremist belief system for
facilitating ideologically based violence to advance political, religious, or
social change, while homegrown terrorism would be defined as the use,
planned use, or threatened use, of force or violence by a group or individual born, raised, or based and operating primarily within the United
States or any possession of the United States to intimidate or coerce the
United States government, the civilian population of the United States,
or any segment thereof, in furtherance of political or social objectives.
Ideologically based violence would be defined as the use, planned use,
or threatened use of force or violence by a group or individual to promote the group or individuals political, religious, or social beliefs. The
act would establish a National Commission on the Prevention of Violent
Radicalization and Homegrown Terrorism to examine and report on facts
and causes of violent radicalization, homegrown terrorism, and ideologically based violence in the United States. The commission would have a
restricted lifespan; it would be terminated thirty days after its final report.
But, following the termination of the commission, the secretary of homeland security would establish or designate a university-based Center of
Excellence for the Study of Violent Radicalization and Homegrown Terrorism in the United States to assist federal, state, local, and tribal homeland security officials, through training, education, and research, in preventing violent radicalization and homegrown terrorism in the United
States. It would require the secretary to conduct a survey of methodologies implemented by foreign nations to prevent violent radicalization and
homegrown terrorism; and to report to Congress on lessons learned from
survey results. The bill also would support efforts by the Department of
Homeland Security to prevent ideologically based violence and homegrown terrorism that violates the constitutional and civil rights or civil
liberties of U.S. citizens or lawful permanent residents.33 The bill passed
the U.S. House on an overwhelming vote of 4046 but then stalled in the
Senate Committee on Homeland Security and Governmental Affairs.
Road Kill
All of these major and minor legislative changes also triggered innovations in the prison system. Green activists were placed in newly created
Communication Management Units along with other so-called terrorists. Communication Management Units, colloquially known as Cmus,
were created in 2008, outside the congressional review process, in order
to house inmates who, due to their current offense of conviction, offence
conduct, or other verified information, require increased monitoring of
communication between inmates and persons in the community in order
to protect the safety, security, and orderly operation of Federal Bureau
of Prisons facilities and protect the public. The rationale for moving
members of the radical ecological movement into Cmus is the same rationale for prosecuting themthat their communicative function within
the movement provides the movement with its ability to act covertly
and anonymously.34 To date, there are two known Cmus, one located in
Terre Haute, Indiana, and the other in Marion, Indiana. These new prison
spaces and new prison populations provide employment opportunities
for local populations, a point not lost on the governor of Michigan, who
offered to use his prison system to house Guantanamo Bay detainees.35
In short, working excess, Katz and others risk becoming excess. And
this excess simultaneously provides the conditions of new postcapitalist
forms of sociality and new, commodifiable, forms of repressive violence.
Katz is well aware of this risk even though his activities are not allied with
the violent-action wing of the green movement. The threat of exhaustion haunts his surrounds. In his vicinity are others who felt the force of
federal prosecution, in their case for tree spiking, and have shifted the
mode of their politics to antiviolent, local fostering of alternative communities.36 Some still believe that only violence will force a change
by moving the center further to the radical Left. But they are no longer
fit enough, or can no longer imagine the internal resources for living on
the run.
The issue of exhaustionof getting burned outis thus, not surprisingly, a substantial matter in the radical ecological movement. In writings and interviews Katz and his interlocutors continually contrast the
vigor of his body and spirit with the status of his body as hiV positive.
What can account for his endurance in the context of internal and external predators? Or his nonexhaustion in the face of the zones of state abandonment in which he lives and attempts to convert the excesses of capital
127
128
Chapter Three
into the enduring fuel of a counterlife? We can think here of the exhaustion of flesh and material. In celebrating Katzs amazing endurance, and
finding ourselves less interested in those who lack it, we see the point I
made above. Critical theory and progressive activism invest in the endurance of life in spaces of state and social abandonment because they consider these spaces capable of providing a potential for cultivating a new
ethics of life and sociality.
But if ethics is a realm in which we not merely reflect on but act at the
intersection of right conduct and the good life, then critical theorys ethical relation to life within these extreme zones of potentiality is fraught,
to say the least. The life worth living is not necessarily found within these
zones of maximal potential because the zones create such reduced conditions of life that the political desire for them to spawn or foster alternative worlds can seem naive at best and sadistic at worst. But once we
view potentiality as socially constituted and materially distributed, then
we find ourselves in the morally viscous realm of excess, exhaustion, and
endurance, a realm that includes affective, physical, and social conditions
that can depress the brain and immune system, rupture organs as well as
bonds with families and friends, and orient violence inward. If we must
persist in potentiality, we must endure it as a space, a materiality, and a
temporality. As we all know, materiality-as-potentiality is never itself outside given organizations of power. Stan and those of us in the boat, for
instance, strive to persevere within a neoliberal form of biopower. Thus
the potentiality for living otherwise emerges from the differential capture
and distribution of embodied and unintegrated life in neoliberalism and
from the striated zones of indistinction and abandonment they create.
When looked at in this way, the ethics of substance has a quite complex
topological relation to the biopolitical management of life.
As much as Stan, Katz, Lindamy colleague on the mobile phone
projectand her family share certain exhausting conditions of neoliberalism and late liberalism, to understand the different modalities of this
sharing, we must remember that the biopolitical is a spacing rather than a
space.37 As we move from the intentional communities of central Tennessee to Indigenous northern Australia, we see some of the contours of this
biopolitical spacing. Unlike Katz, my Indigenous colleagues are not trying
to overthrow capital but to live otherwise within its seams. They do not
Road Kill
choose to drop out. They were born at the far end of liberal capitalisms
exhaust system. As a result they engage as a matter of course in the exact
activities that Katz promotesferal foraging, dumpster diving, gleaning,
and road kill collecting. And, as a result, their practices of recycling can
be formally described as stealing or unlicensed food production and consumption from the perspective of law. They move around within the gray
economy of substanceunregistered and unregisterable cars and boats,
unlicensed gunsthat can lead to the bright lights of legal detention that
further mark their bodies in such a way that they are driven deeper into
social zones of abandonment and excess. Moreover in the Australian case
the biopolitical is marked by the division of the autological subject and
genealogical society.38 The embrace of the customary by the politics of
recognition was demonized by the politics of the neoliberalism as if the
customary were a quality of the Indigenous rather than the internal limit
of Western capital, colonialism, and democracy.39
Enduring Immanent Critical Theory
And so where are we left? If it is true that to be in these spaces of abandonment, exhaustion, and excess radically reduces being and true also
that it is being in these spaces that provides the possibility of being otherwise, then what should an ethically informed politics be? Should a political movement work to make these spaces less lethal and enervating? But
what if it is exactly this enervating lethality that is the condition of this
particular kind of world-making activity? And what about the fact that, no
more than Stan, my colleagues may not want to be potentiality, or mere
potentiality, or potentiality like this? They want to strive to persist in the
being they find proper to the world, but in another mode. To return to
some transcendental fixed point, or a set of normative, even if revisable,
horizons is, in the light of these lived worlds, a means of avoiding the
nature of the given world exactly at the moment when the given world
is what needs to be theorized. It is true that norms provide a feeling of
safety insofar as they provide an experience of possible judgment and assessment and, retroactively, a place of certainty. But these norms hardly
make these spaces disappear for those who inhabit them.
Critical theorists can cut into the accumulationabandonment
129
130
Chapter Three
Chapter Four
Events of Abandonment
Chapter 3 began with a scene from Charles Burnetts 1977 film Killer of Sheep. The scene slowly
follows the films protagonist, Stan, and his friend
as they lug a used car engine down a winding
set of stairs and heave the engine onto the back
of a borrowed truck, only to have it fall off and
crack as they begin to drive away. In chapter 3,
the interest was the dilemma of ethical substance
when read from the perspective of the materiality
of becoming otherwiseof embodied potentiality and endurance for the part that has no part
132
Chapter Four
in late liberalism. But one could easily turn the scene in a slightly different direction so that it highlights a different aspect of the problem of embodied potentiality and endurance in late liberalism. From this angle we
would remain standing in the domain of ethical substance, but we would
be looking at how the nature of social events contributed to the ways
that life and death, endurance and exhaustion, and hope and harm are
distributed in late liberalismand how this distribution is made ethically and politically sensible and compelling. After all, from one vantage
point the loss of the engine is not a big deal. It cost the protagonists fifteen dollars in 1977, which, taking inflation into account, would be about
fifty-five dollars today. Indeed, Killer of Sheep seems especially interested
in exploring the modes of exhaustion and endurance that are ordinary,
chronic, and cruddy rather than catastrophic, crisis-laden, and sublime.
There are many scenes that tease at viewer anxiety organized around the
dramatic and spectacular: a group of neighborhood kids try to move an
empty freight train carriage along the tracks as one of them lies in front
of its wheels, his head hanging across the rail; a small girl is left alone in
an old truck on an inclined street after weve seen that the brakes of the
truck are not that reliable. But these scenes never culminate in the kind
of violent event that a generic modern viewer might anticipate. Indeed,
the film is remarkably devoid of blood or violence except for that which
occurs in the slaughterhouse. No one is killed if we exempt the sheep, not
something we should casually do. Nevertheless, no humans are tortured.
No police grace the film, though their specter is constantly invoked.
The absence of explosive and intensified violence is notable, given the
setting of the film. Burnett was filming in Watts twelve years after the
1965 uprising. But the absence of cinematic violence allows Burnett to
conjure another form of violence: the violence of enervation, the weakening of the will rather than the killing of life. Stans wife remarks on his
bottomless exhaustion, and viewers see him in a constant state of somnolence. Something and yet nothing has happened to cause Stan to be
so exhaustedit is hard to point to anything as the event in relation to
which his exhaustion is the effect. Instead his hope and despair are conjured through the endurance of the exhaustion of numerous small quasievents. Little things pile up. But these little things dont recursively enclose or intensify in such a way that a thisness is easily formed. It is hard
Events of Abandonment
to pull a thisness out of the ongoing flow of the everyday because so much
decomposition happens below the threshold of awareness and theorization. The event is a pile of clothes in the washroom, a roll of linoleum in
the kitchen. Sometimes these quasi-events are the result of a purposeful aggregation of energy, of a project, such as Stans attempt to buy the
engine or put down a new kitchen floor. But whether aggregated into a
project or remaining in the diffused background of everyday life, these
quasi-events rarely appear to be catastrophic in the ordinary sense of the
word. They are not, for instance, the kind of event that riveted the United
States in the wake of Hurricane Katrina. The engine is not the ceiling of
the New Orleans Superdome. It is not a modernist wonderthe largest
fixed-dome stadium in the worldwhose fragility in the face of a natural
event transformed a catastrophe into a sublime event and intensified an
ethical demand that even a president couldnt simply fly over.
The imperceptible relationship between quasi-events and ordinary life
poses a set of problems to the usual way we think about ethical and political demand. After all, life is, or might seem to many people within late liberalism to be, what happens around, between, or in spite of the periodic
rupture of the ordinary. But the ordinary does not exist. The ordinary
is a statistical projection of a variety of socially distributed ordinaries
what the texture of the ordinary is for some is not for others. As a consequence any discussion of the relationship among ordinary exhaustion,
quasi-events, and endurance in the late liberal governance of difference
must be situated within the various ways that eventfulness is distributed
in late liberalism, such that people experience the kinds of events that
make up their lives not only as ordinary but generalizable. We can think
of the ordinary as the local spacing of eventfulness. This complex spacing makes it difficult to answer such questions as Who, if anyone, is killing Stan? and What are the conditions that make the claim that Stan is
being killed so nonsensical and impractical? Broad claims made in the
wake of Agambens work on the camp become unhelpful.1 That Watts is
a concentration camp and that Stan has been reduced to bare life, or that
we are all in a camp and all of our lives have been stripped bare, do not
help us understand how various forms of eventfulness distribute the texture of enervation and endurance in late liberalism.
With Stan in the background I want to focus this chapter on modes
133
134
Chapter Four
Events of Abandonment
Its Nothing
Late liberal societies hardly lack the neighborhoods and dingy broom
closets that so interested Burnett and Le Guin. No less than the citizens
of Omelas, members of these societies are fully aware of the existence of
these spaces in their polis and make decisions about the relation between
the suffering that occurs in them and their own well-being. And these
neighborhoods, flavelas, residential towers, and rural ghettos are witness
to the full range of quasi-events that interested Burnett and Le Guin.
These run down, often fetid spaces are periodically the occasion for public hand-wringing, outrage, and scandal. In Australia, for instance, Indigenous rural and urban communities are open broom closets of poverty,
disease, and despair. But if you walked through them you would not necessarily see the decomposition that composes them. Take for instance Indigenous housing in the far north of Australia.
To be sure, Indigenous housing in rural ghettos and town camps can
rapidly unsettle an unsuspecting visitor. A year before the sea voyage I
described in the last chapter, a schoolteacher visited a sixty-six-year-old
woman who was dying of oral cancer in an Indigenous communitythe
birthplace of those on the voyage. Inside the cinder block house where
the dying woman lived were a series of rooms, unfurnished except for old
stained mattresses on the floor, where dogs with scabies sometimes slept,
a single steel-framed bed in the front room (what most Australians would
call the den), and a wobbly table on which stood a broken television set.
In the kitchen were carcasses of various animals and fish, opened jams,
loaves of bread, sugar, tea, bowls and pans with days-old remainders of
cooked food, and running through them all various sizes of cockroaches.
The inside toilet had been backed up for weeks. There was no hot water.
When we bathed this dying woman we boiled water on the stove in old
flour drums. Sewn through all of this were the syringes, empty pill bottles,
new and used bandages used to care for this woman, and beer cans, wine
coolers, and other addictive substances her relatives were using as they
stayed there. Many people on the porch were drunk, stoned, or hung over.
Not far distant, a fight had broken out between the two sides of the community, part of the longstanding war that would eventually drive my
friends off the community. Following the discussion from the last chapter,
135
136
Chapter Four
we might say that the house was in an extreme condition of noise. When
the schoolteacher entered the house she too entered a heightened condition of static. She found herself unable to cross the doorframe, and then
found herself blushing, hot, with what she later described as embarrassment. The scene she witnessed, the broken nature of the dying womans
home, the ruined infrastructure, the infestations of insects and vermin,
the garbage and medical waste strewn about paralyzed her. Who she was
before she crossed the doorframe was different from who she was afterwards. What or who was to blame?
For this schoolteacher the doorway was a threshold that marked out
an event, experienced as a rupture in her ordinary life and its taken-forgranted conditions and rhythms. The immediate and long-term ethical
and political implications of this rupture are difficult to know. From conversations that I had with her, I got a sense that she suddenly experienced herself as a deeply habituated being rather than simply herself and
as someone who had taken certain basic material conditions of life for
granted. But for how long and to what end this experience lasted I do
not know. Perhaps she changed the party she voted for in subsequent
elections. Perhaps she looked at people differently on the street. Perhaps
she blamed non-Indigenous people. Perhaps she blamed Indigenous
people. Perhaps she blamed the state. Perhaps she blamed traditional
Indigenous culture. All of these possibilities were available to her. Conservative critics were at that very moment blaming Indigenous people
for refusing to care for the all-but-free housing they received from the
government. Some anthropologists were arguing that Indigenous uses of
housing reflected the persistence of traditional culture in modern life. So
this narrative went, because Indigenous people are traditionally oriented
to disposable housing they treat their houses like bush camps. According
to these anthropologists the solution is to educate Indigenous families
about the nature of the modern home. Not surprisingly, some advocates
of the federal Intervention leaned on this anthropological reasoning to
support a shift in the way Indigenous housing is financed and managed.
Privatizing Indigenous housing would, they argue, inculcate an ethos of
modern material responsibility.4
But the specific experience of the schoolteacher is not a general experience. Experiential events are not existents in the sense that many people
Events of Abandonment
137
138
Chapter Four
forces that locks together human and nonhuman agencies and organisms. For example, on July 10, 2009, I was driving in the Northern Territory of Australia along a back highway that connects the Darwin suburbs
to the Palmerston suburbs, a distance of about twenty-five kilometers.
In the small rented truck with me were several Indigenous friends and
colleagues of mine, some of whom I have known since they were teens:
Gigi Lewis, then thirty-five, her partner, Rex Edmunds, then forty-six, and
three young teenage boys in their care. We were moving some household
items, including a washing machine tied down in the back of the truck,
from Gigis mothers house in Darwin to Gigi and Rexs new house in
Palmerston, and in the process moving Gigis family from a state of quasihomelessness into government housing. As we paused for a red traffic
light, Gigi showed me two large staph infections growing on her leg under
her skin and I show her the staph infections I had on my forehead. Rex
was drinking in the backseat, relaxing after a long week of laying a water
pipe in a small rural community, Bulgul, located about three hundred
kilometers south of Darwin. The water pipe was part of the infrastructure
of an augmented-reality project that we and another set of families had
been working on for the previous two years, in collaboration with various
Northern Territory government agencies and libraries and the local university.
However, between the idea of the project and the effects we hoped
the project would produce and the actual project lay a material and discursive world. And although it should be common sense at this point it
is still necessary to note that, while the actual world stood between all of
us in that truck and the idea we had of the project, the actual world does
not address all of us in the same way. We are and are not the same thing
in the sense that we may be an aggregation vis--vis our intentions to
build this augmented-reality project, but we are constantly disaggregated
by the world around us. Take for instance our efforts to lay the pipeline.
To accomplish this task we decided to rent a small trench-digging machine, which meant driving into Darwin to rent it, dig the ditch the same
day, and then drive it back. Our other option was to dig the hundredmeter trench by hand through sun-baked, hardened soil with crowbars
and pickaxes. But to rent the trench digger we needed a credit card and
the ability to pay. Of the ten Indigenous adults working on the project,
Events of Abandonment
and their extended family, no one had a credit card or the ability to pay,
so we used mine. On the long drive down to Bulgul, on one of the many
dirt roads, several attachments on the trench-digger flew off, which meant
several of us had to drive back along the road to find them. When we
finally got the trench-digger off the truck, Rex learned to use it by using
it. Relatives in the region with access to sympathetic construction firms
donated the piping. We collaboratively consulted on how to attach various parts of the piping and how to bury it as we attached the parts and
buried the pipe. After finishing there was a little leakage at the tap. More
than wed like to have seen, but not so much that we were willing to dig
up the entire pipeline after an exhausting day.
What is at stake here then is the materiality of our idea as it encounters different agencements. These arrangements shape and direct actions
such as our decision to move large household appliances a day after returning from Bulgul, no matter that we were all exhausted, because my
truck was still available (I was leaving in a couple days for the United
States). But these arrangements also continually and slowly decompose
that unity. When we reached our destination, we were chagrined to discover that the lid of the washing machine had flown off. Or, maybe, we
hoped, we had never put it on the truck and so we would find it at Gigis
mothers house. But when we drove back to Darwin, carefully following
our tracks, there it was on the side of the road, crumpled and flattened
from having been repeatedly run over in rush hour traffic. The lid could
not endure the conditions of my friends lives any more than our bodies
seem able to fully cope as a constant feeding ground for bacteria. The
next morning I left the apartment at the university where I stayed when
in town, and drove to their house, where they were still lamenting the lid.
Without it the machine would not run and wash the clothes that housed
the bacteria that gave us staph sores. How would they afford a new washing machine? Why hadnt someone tied down the washing machine more
carefully and securely? Dont blame me, I said, guilty because I had been
among those securing the washing machine to the back of the truck. I
am blaming Rex, Gigi said, He was drunk. Not really, said Rex, and
besides, We are getting somewhere. One of Gigis daughters laughed,
and asked, Wheres that? Were still alive, Rex said. Were still trying,
Gigi agreed conciliatorily.
139
140
Chapter Four
Gigi and Rexs claim that their family was getting somewhere on the
basis of little more than the fact that they are still alive and trying condenses
a set of tacit references to a shared background. For nearly two years prior
to moving into their new home in Palmerston, they and the other Indigenous members of the augmented-reality project had been homeless. Prior
to that they had spent their lives, as had their parents and grandparents,
in a small rural Indigenous community across the Darwin harborthe
community where the schoolteacher visited the woman dying of cancer.
They had grown up in the shadow of the land rights movement and the
celebration of Indigenous cultural difference more generally. Land rights
and cultural recognition in Australia was exemplary of the logic of care
in late liberalism. By making a space for traditional Indigenous culture,
the state argued it was making a space for this traditional culture to care
for Indigenous people. But land rights legislation, and public discourse
on Indigenous culture more generally, differentiated among Indigenous
people on the basis of the tradition effectthe assessment of different
Indigenous people on the basis of their correspondence to a modernist
anthropological understanding of the clan and its territory.7 In caring for
Indigenous people in this way, land rights placed a division into Indigenous social worlds that then internally divided Indigenous communities.
However imperfect, this way of life started to unravel in 2007. As reported in the local Darwin newspaper, on March 15, 2007, Gigi and her
family and five other families were threatened with chainsaws and pipes,
watched their cars and houses being torched, and their dogs beaten to
death. Four families lost rare, well-paying jobs in education, housing, and
water works. Why they were driven outwhat caused this explosion of
violencecannot be answered, except in the most narrow sense (soand-so hit so-and-so and then their friends got involved), without immediately being drawn into discourses of care and harm in late liberalism
and neoliberalism. For instance, the newspaper did not report that Gigis
grandparents, and most of the senior and now deceased members of the
community, had continually petitioned the government to recognize all
community members as traditional owners irrespective of their clan affiliations in order to avoid creating internal divisions and the violence
they feared would flow from them. Instead follow-up news stories insinuated that traditional land struggles were to blame for the riot, that the
Events of Abandonment
violence was caused by ancient clan conflicts rather than by the modern
creation of clans as a way of managing difference in late liberalism. Public meetings were held, attended by the leaders of Department of Family,
Housing, Community Services and Indigenous Affairs in the Northern
Territory Labor government, in which the displaced people were held up
as examples of the failures of land rights policies to protect Indigenous
people living in communities outside their traditional country. The families driven out were promised new housing, schooling, and jobs at Bulgul,
a site closer to their traditional countries. Fifty people promptly moved to
Bulgul and set up a tent settlement.
But then, on June 21, 2007, the then prime minister of Australia, John
Howard, declared a national emergency in relation to the abuse of children in Indigenous communities in the Northern Territory. Indigenous
people living in remote communities, or those like my friends who were
promised housing in or nearer to their traditional country, were told to
move closer to the cities where infrastructural and service delivery costs
were lower, even if doing so would endanger their lives. The people who
made the promises to the displaced persons confronted the budgetary
consequences of these promises and suddenly became difficult to reach.
In the year that followed, the income of two of the six families driven off
went from roughly $AuD28,000 to $AuD12,000 per year after they lost
their permanent jobs and were moved onto the Community Development Employment Program (CDEP, a work and training program within
a social welfare framework, loosely called work for the dole).
We continue to push the project, no matter hostile relatives in the region, government agencies refusal to help erect a shed paid for by private
contributions, the biggest financial collapse since the Great Depression,
and the everyday obstacles of their poverty and others racism. But since
being run out of their community their income has been slashed in half.
And so the used cars they can afford break down at a faster rate than they
can afford to fix them. Their secondhand boats are stranded offshore without petrol. Neighbors call the police for quality-of-life infractions. And
other relatives with nowhere to spend the night sleep in makeshift tents
on nearby beaches or in overcrowded flats. And still other relatives, involved in assaults and petty thefts, must be bailed out of jail. My friends
quickly moved from being a big event that demanded address to being
141
142
Chapter Four
Events of Abandonment
released its report in 1979, the contents of which were so scandalous that
the federal government started a $50 million five-year Aboriginal Public
Health Improvement Program in response. The program, administered
by the Department of Aboriginal Affairs, focused in particular on inadequate water, sewage, and power systems in rural Aboriginal communities.8 Unfortunately, the crisis in Indigenous health has continued to make
front-page headlines, periodically prompting the organization of special
inquests and parliamentary committees at the federal and state levels and
the reorganization of government agencies responsible for Indigenous
health, education, and welfare. Although the Australian Bureau of Statistics reports that after adjusting for age differences between the populations, Indigenous Australians were twice as likely to report their health as
fair or poor as non-Indigenous Australians, the bureau also notes that the
statistics it compiled are likely to be underestimates of the true rates of
illness in the Indigenous population because of the under-identification
of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander people in these data collections.9
This longstanding and appalling state of Indigenous health periodically
prompts the question of what or who is to blame and, consequentially,
what is to be done.
It is a somewhat arbitrary decision to begin the history of the lethal
conditions of Indigenous worlds in 1969. Since colonization, British administrators, the Australian state, and a variety of domestic and international publics have asked and answered the questions of what and who
is to blame for the fetid state of Indigenous life. Prior to the federal governments listing of health as one of four critical domains in Indigenous
affairs, not merely the poor health of the Indigenous but also their high
death rates were discussed, explained, and managed in terms of a series of
historically fluctuating accounts of the causes and cures of social pathology. In the early years of Australian federation, the lethal conditions of
Indigenous life were justified in social Darwinian terms. Full-blooded
Indigenous subjects would be allowed to live a somewhat traditional life
as they faded into human evolutionary history, while mixed bloods
would be slowly interbred with the white population until all traces of
cultural and genetic difference disappeared. From the perspective of a
future world in which Indigenous people would be museum pieces, the
immediate suffering of living people will have made ethical sense.
143
144
Chapter Four
Events of Abandonment
If we are to keep the esky lid from sailing off into the ever-expanding air
of like events that slowly wears away the will to sustain alternative social
projects, the case to take the lid seriously, to care for and about it, must
be made in the contemporary spacings of harm and eventfulness in neoliberalism and late liberalism. I would be surprised if most Australian citizens would confuse their mode of happiness with the mode of happiness
of the fictional citizens of Omelas. Although they share some of the same
characteristics, the broom closets perforating Australia do not work the
same magic on Australians as they do on the citizens of Omelas. Things
are not that good. The middle class is periodically squeezed between rich
and poor. There are mortgages to worry about. There are new individual
labor contracts to negotiate. In Le Guins imaginary society, nothing but
a robust happiness acts as a comparative backdrop to the everyday abuse
of the small child. Not so in Oz. True, like the fetid space of the broom
closet in Omelas, Indigenous communities are often cruddy, corrosive,
and uneventful. An agentless slow death characterizes their mode of lethality. Quiet deaths. Slow deaths. Rotting worlds. The everyday drifts
toward death: one more drink, one more sore; a bad cold, bad food; a
small pain in the chest. Any claim that these forms of decay matter can be
referred back to the general condition of human lifeeveryone is slowly
dying! But unlike Omelas, these kinds of deaths only periodically fix the
gaze of national and international publics. When they do, they dont do
so in a way that unambiguously concretizes their ultimate, or immediate,
cause, agent, and effect. Who is killing these people? What is killing them?
145
146
Chapter Four
Answers must yield to the complexity of an entire system. One can see
why a subject within late liberal society dreams of something decisive,
clear, sublime.
Late liberal subjects do not have to be awoken from sleep to see deathscapes with much clearer borders, agencies, and intensities. In contrast to
cruddy, cumulative, and chronic lethality are special forms of enemy and
spectacular forms of death that capture and rivet the imagination of late
liberal societies and act as an alibi for the concentration and consolidation
of state executive power. Certain kinds of enemies, events, and history are
seen as having a spectacular, even sublime, quality: they cut time in two;
they present decisive ideological struggles; and they demand that exceptional measures be taken. Those within late liberal societies seeking to
increase state surveillance powers cite these decisive kinds of enemy and
devastating images of airplanes, nightclubs, and towers exploding and
vomiting forth singed and dismembered bodies. The lethal state of Indigenous life hardly competes with the society of the terrorist spectacle:
bodies in hoods, in naked piles, attached to real or fake electrodes. Bodies
disappear only to reappear with drill marks. These forms of violence seem
to oppose and stand outside of the everyday uneventful forms of misery
and dying that characterize Indigenous life. These new terrorist forms of
death are spectacular in outward form. In appearing to be spectacular,
they seem to create the ontological necessity to respond ethicallya demand that we take sides. And citizens and their governments do.
Take for instance, the Australian governments response to the Bali
nightclubs bombings. Those spectacular killings were continually cited
alongside an omnipresent, invisible domestic and international terrorist threat when the conservative government of John Howard sought to
modify the Crimes Act of 1914. Passed in 2005, amendments to the Crimes
Act gives the Australian Security Intelligence Organization the power to
detain any person for up to seven days without charge if he or she is suspected on reasonable grounds of being involved in any terrorist activity.
During this time, detainees are prohibited from exercising their right to
have a lawyer present; to silence; and to protect themselves against selfincrimination.11 While Australia does not have a declaration of rights
that enshrines freedom of speech in general, the High Court of Australia
found a specific implied right of freedom of political speech in Australian
Events of Abandonment
Capital Television v. Commonwealth (1992).12 It is exactly this more circumscribed right that the amendments to the Crimes Act restricted. What has
especially worried free speech advocates is the definition of terrorist activity under the advocacy clause. There, a terrorist is defined as anyone
who advocates the doing of a terrorist act (whether or not a terrorist act
has occurred or will occur), including praising the doing of a terrorist
act in circumstances where there is a risk that such praise might have the
effect of leading a person to commit a terrorist act.13
These carceral forms of state power, premised on actual and potential spectacularly catastrophic mass deaths, incited mass protests and engaged public and private consciences. In November 2005, in major cities
throughout Australia, thousands of people marched against the new
crime amendments. The news media highlighted, and in some instances
violated, the far-reaching scope of the new terrorist laws. Beyond the specific crime amendments, these protests were aimed at what many left or
progressive people saw as an uncritical alliance forged by the Howard
government with the Bush administration that compromised fundamental Australian principles of social and personal justice. For example, while
Australia has a long history of strongly opposing the death penalty domestically and internationally, since the Bali bombings of October 2002
there has been a significant silence about the death penalty for terrorists. And while no troops are stationed in Indigenous communities to
shoot at armed and unarmed people resisting the lethal state of Indigenous life, police have faced a number of Indigenous riots in places such
as Red Hook, Palm Island, and, most recently, Aurukun, after alleged
police abuse and murder. The Howard government has stationed Australian troops in foreign nation-states, ostensibly as part of humanitarian
efforts. For instance, troops entered East Timor to stop the carnage
that erupted as Indonesia withdrew from the region. However, critics argued that the government, after decades of refusing to intervene against
Indonesian atrocities in the region, was merely attempting to gain strategic control over the Sunrise Oil Field. Likewise, critics saw the Australian intervention in the Solomon Islands as compromised by the governments refusal to publicly renounce a first-strike policy in the Asian Pacific
and its continual references to the Islamic fundamentalist infiltration of
the Pacific via Southeast Asia.
147
148
Chapter Four
There is serious debate about why Howard, whose government predated by four years the U.S. Supreme Court appointment of George W.
Bush to the presidency in 2000, made such a firm commitment to the
international unilateralism of the U.S. neoconservative movement. Some
have argued that Howard is a true believer whose political thinking ultimately derives from Milton Friedmans school of laissez-faire capitalism,
developed at the University of Chicago while Leo Strauss taught there.14
As a result, so this story goes, Howards foreign policy could be easily
adapted to the Straussian neoconservativism of the current Bush administration with its deep, resonant ties to Carl Schmitts theories of political
theology. Others have insisted that Howard is an extraordinarily skilled
modern prince, astutely morphing his partys message to fit shifting public anxieties about the location of economic, social, and political threats
and never letting belief get too much in the way of securing and holding power. Whether believing or not, Howards allegiance to the liberal
democratic parliamentary system seems shaky, if not outright hostile, to
some of his critics. For instance, Ian Duncanson argued that the Howard
government reflected a kind of Peronism in which the separation of
powers, foundational to liberal democracies, was replaced by elections
in which victories become empty mandates to pursue previously undisclosed or hitherto non-existent policies and by opportunistic opinion
polls in which majority opinions act as plebiscites on single issues.15
Indeed, Howards refusal in the mid- to late 1990s to countenance even
a hint of contemporary national responsibility for past historical wrongs
carried out against the Indigenous population foreshadowed rather than
reflected the U.S. neoconservative disdain for guilt-saturated liberalism.
But for whatever reason, this strong state rhetoric continually foregrounds and creates spectacular scenes of killing. Two other examples
suffice. One occurred in late August 2001 as the United Nations World
Conference against Racism in Durban, South Africa, was under way.
The Norwegian vessel Tampa picked up some 433 asylum seekers who
found themselves trapped on a sinking ship as they traveled from Indonesia to Australia. The asylum seekers were mainly Afghani people fleeing the Taliban. The Tampa sought to drop off its unintended passengers
on Christmas Island. On August 27, Howard declared that the asylum
seekers would not be allowed into Australia or Australian territory, in-
Events of Abandonment
cluding Christmas Island. Instead, Howard pushed ahead with the socalled Pacific solution, the use of economic incentives to entice the nearbankrupt state of Nauru to establish a detention center for asylum seekers
attempting to enter Australia. As many have noted, Nauru agreed to set
up these detention camps in exchange for Australian foreign aid after its
material resources had been exhausted by a history of British and Australian extractive capital. Still more shocking was Howards stance on
the children overboard controversy. It was alleged that some families
threw their children overboard in order to force the governments hand.
Howard figured this decision as a sign of the barbarous cunning of these
asylum seekers.16 Prior to the establishment of the security state in Guantnamo Bay (which, as we know, swept up the Australian David Hicks),
Howard was testing how far the international community was willing to
go to stop what he and his government readily admitted were potentially
permanent detention camps. These camps were just, argued Howard, because they were good for Australian nationalism. Very quickly international human rights groups at the Durban conference, as well as members of the United Nations, denounced Howards Pacific solution as a
violation of the U.N. refugee convention.17 How could they not, if for no
other reason than that this solution, like the post-9/11 U.S. mantra that
the government must protect the homeland,18 had shocking resonances
with fascist rhetorics of the Second World War?
This new expression of sovereignty does not show itself in public
spectacles of drawn and quartered bodies or inflamed racist rhetoric. It
is tucked away in distant detention centers. It is important to note that
mandatory detention has been part of the migration policy of Australia
since 1992 and that it was a Labour government that removed the 273day limit on mandatory detention. In other words, it is not simply the
neoconservative movement that is responsible for the fetid conditions
in detention camps on Nauru and Manus Island and on Australian soil,
such as at the Woomera Immigration Reception and Processing Centre.
As early as 1998, Amnesty International cited the mandatory detention
of adults and children as a violation of human rights, noting the U.N.
Human Rights Committee had found Australia in violation of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. In the eight years that
followed, various U.N. committees and commissions have investigated
149
150
Chapter Four
Events of Abandonment
151
152
Chapter Four
Australia, with its strong history of social equity (as opposed to the more
vapid value of social equality), is slowly installing neoliberal markets and
cultivating the neoliberal subjects who will occupy them.
It is at the intersection of these state and market forms and forces and
the shifting governance of difference that the lethal conditions of late liberal societies must be understood. And these lethal conditions need to
be understood not merely in terms of the facts on the ground but also
in terms of our scholarly attachments to certain modes of time, eventfulness, and ethics. The security states ability to capture countervailing
energies and imaginaries is not restricted to those who march, protest,
and organize against the security state, but also includes those who think
critically inside and outside the universities.
If we are interested in how the assignment of responsibility and the
demand for an ethical and political response are embedded in the discourse and experience of the event, then we need to understand, on the
one hand, how difficult it is to experience the ethical call of events that
do not strike us as catastrophic or sublime and, on the other hand, how
the divisions of late liberalism, especially the division between the freesubject (autological subject) and the customarily constrained subject
(genealogical society), is always at hand to interpret the ultimate cause
and purpose of these events. In other words, any attempt to understand
the social imaginaries characterizing lethal conditions within late liberal
societies must take into account the topological relationship between
forms, modes, and qualities of killing (strong and weak state killing); the
modes and forms of agency, causality, and eventfulness on which they rely
(event, quasi-event); and the divisions of difference at hand to account
for them.
But how do we critically reflect on the conditions and ethical demands
of lethality in late liberal societies when life and its imaginaries are located
at the catachresis of strong and weak states and catastrophic and quasievents, late liberalism and neoliberalism? It seems to me that two avenues need to be followed. Along the first, we would examine violence and
lethality from a perspective that does not assume the qualities, vitalities,
and borders of the catastrophic itself. Several scholars have been pursuing this project.24 In Life and Words, Veena Das notes the anthropological attachment to the kind of violence that characterizes the catastrophe.
Events of Abandonment
153
154
Chapter Four
literally kills them. The cruddy, cumulative, and corrosive aspects of life
have spread so deep into the everyday that, as Ludwig Wittgenstein says,
there is nothing more I can say other than that is what is.27
Sinking In
If we need to examine epistemological techniques that transform quasievents into catastrophic events, then we also need to understand how the
very nature of the quasi-event makes it an effective means for shifting
accountability away from neoliberalism onto those who suffer in neoliberalism. And, we need to understand how these quasi-events are where
the struggle to maintain an alternative social world is at its deepest if also
its most tenuous and subtle. In other words, the politics of the otherwise
occurs at moments that themselves have the nature of the quasi-event.
Take, for instance, an interaction between a young Indigenous man in
his late thirties and his family. The young Indigenous mans social profile is typical of most people of his age living in his community. Despite
the horrific nature of the following account, if you met him, you would
often see him in good spirits. This young man characterizes himself as an
alcoholic. Like everyone in his family, he has had sores (staphylococcal and streptococcal infections) on and off since he was a child, bearing the scars on his body. He has high blood pressure but does not take
his medication regularly. He was hospitalized for congestive heart failure,
just as his mother was in her last stages of oral cancer. His father died of a
stroke when he was in his teens. His mothers youngest brother died years
earlier of kidney failure associated with septicemia. His younger brother
has a congenital heart condition. Three weeks after he was released from
the hospital, his eldest sister was taken to the hospital with septicemia.
Her treatment resulted in massive congestive heart failure. Although told
by doctors and family to stop drinking, this young man started drinking
again within a week of his release from the hospital. Further, what would
perhaps be more surprising to the sensibilities of many Australians, he
demanded that his family members drive him to a local shop to buy alcohol with the money he had saved during his hospitalization. When family
members refused, he angrily told them he could do what he wanted with
his body. He knew the risks; they were his to take; how he gambled with
Events of Abandonment
his life was his business. These were his words, risk, gamble, my body.
Only the future could say whether he won or lost his gamble, was right or
wrong in his approach to this world of misery.
Forty years his senior, his aunt vehemently disagreed not only with his
account of the location of his risk but also with the underlying logic of his
social imaginary. To his statement that his body was his alone, she replied,
No, that is not your body; that is my body. When you die, my body will
suffer and die. When she referred to her physical risk, this woman was
not simply referring to a generalizable empathic form of grief. She was not
saying, I will mourn you as an individual. Her brother was this young
mans father. Thus, she and he share one body: They are both murrumurru (long yam), an ancestral being from which they both substantively
descend as surely as an average non-Indigenous Australian believes that
he or she shares the genetic substance of his or her mother and father. In
other words, the woman was attempting to mobilize a discourse of socially cosubstantial corporeality against her nephews social imaginary of
individuated bodies engaged in private wagers. His language of privatized
loss, and its incumbent discourse of individual risk, was not met by the
risk of another private loss but by an appeal to a cosubstantial distribution
of life, health, and social beinga position much closer to Le Guins than
to the young mans.
As a second instance we could return to my friends and me, who
were driving around Darwin and Palmerston with the washing machine
strapped onto the back of my rented truck. If the washing machine is
built to survive some determined amount of uses, every time it is used it
is suffused, my friends think, with the formative effects of human sweat
on things and places. Sweat (minthene) is a persons essential substance
layered with the essential substances from which it was formed, including human and nonhuman beings and the organic and inorganic nature of
specific places. It passes down from ancestors and passes into places out
of which it passes again into people. The ordinary and extraordinary examples are multiple. Hunting implements smell their users. Uncles press
their sweat on nephews in ritual, as do aunts their nieces. Landscapes react both in a general way, and according to the specific ancestral beings
who inhabit them, to different peoples stink. And as people live in these
landscapes, shit and piss in them, burn and bury their clothes and other
155
156
Chapter Four
Events of Abandonment
Thus by the time that the nephew and aunt fought, state and business
were amplifying and channeling the nephews rather than the aunts social
imaginary into agencies of social life in such a way that the one is sensible,
practical, and productive, while the other is insensible, impractical, and
sterile. They divide the complex histories and intersubjectivies of the aunt
and her nephew into stereotypes of the battle of ancient law and modernity. The aunt is hardly some pristine adherent of an ancient order. And
by the time the aunt makes her argument, the language game of individual
risk has already organized social, economic, and political life increasingly
around the neoliberal view of her nephewthat bodies and values are
poker chips in individual games of chance and that the social is an impediment to the production of value. This view has social ramifications
that are especially hard on the poor. As Craig Calhoun concisely puts it,
privatizing risk makes individuals bear the brunt of hardships that are
predictable in the statistical aggregate without effective mechanisms to
share the burden, let alone reduce the risk.29 Privatizing risk creates and
fosters a language game in which the social is practiced as nothing more
than an aggregate of individuated risk calculators working according to
mathematically predictable econometric models. I am not in you. You are
not in me. We are merely playing the same game of chance whose truth
lies not here and now between us but there and then in who wins and who
loses. No one is killing me. I am killing myself. Maybe . . . well see . . . the
future will tell.
To see how these new approaches to risk work their way through state
agencies, take, for instance, the Australian Institute of Health and Welfare
(AihW), a bureaucratic arm of the federal government. When the AihW
released its report on Indigenous health and welfare in 2006, it reported a
relationship between socio-economic status and health . . . with people
at the lowest socio-economic levels experiencing the highest rates of illness and death.30 The AihW seemed to be saying that the agents of harm
may be pathogenic, but the vector of harm is socioeconomicstructural
racism is killing these people.31 The answer to the question of what, or
who, is to blame for the stubborn persistence of Indigenous ill health depends on what is considered a social vector, as opposed to an individual
choice.
This wasnt exactly what the AihW was claiming. It immediately quali-
157
158
Chapter Four
fied its claim by stating, Socio-economic status does not alone explain
the variations in health status that exist between groups in society.32
According to the AihW, to understand health status one must look beyond socioeconomic status to individual risk and behavioral practices.
Indeed, from a neoliberal point of view, the social is the aggregation of
these individual behaviors. The sentence poverty is a risk to your health
is quickly denuded of force within a neoliberal language game that reduces risk to individual choice. The behaviors that put one at risk, according to the AihW, are associated with individual choice (immunization,
smoking, diet and exercise, and high blood pressure) rather than racial
discrimination.
Thus, what wonder that the conservative Howard government was
able to respond to the question of what, or who, is to be held accountable for the lethal conditions in Indigenous communities by pointing, at
one and the same time, to the individual and her culture, but never at
the sociopolitical conditions in which these emerge. Cultural and social
logics of exactly the sort articulated by the aunt are, according to Howard,
an impediment to the maintenance of a unified social fabric and to the
fostering of an entrepreneurial spirit among Indigenous people. Indeed,
they are said to be the cause of poverty along with longstanding federal
and state commitments to Indigenous social welfare. When Indigenous
people stop seeing their social worlds from the perspective of local cultural sense or from state-backed social welfare, then they will emerge
from poverty and with this emergence gain the health that all other Australians have. But the nephew is also to blame by choosing to harm himself through alcohol consumption.
Then, then, then. . . . Local men and women are quite familiar with the
temporal ethics of this future anterior. Needless to say, it is the aunt who
is sober, the nephew who is not; the aunt is outside the logic of life as a
set of privatized risks, the nephew is not. Nevertheless, as an incentive
to Indigenous people to take up the nephews position, Howard committed his government to withdrawing federal economic support from
rural Indigenous communities as part of the mainstreaming of Indigenous people and policy. Is this withdrawal, seen throughout late liberal
worlds, a form of state killing? Howard would say, clearly not. In his corner are many Indigenous men and women. Noel Pearson, an Aboriginal
Events of Abandonment
activist, has famously and forcefully argued that state welfare, when applied to Indigenous peoples, is a technique of numbing Indigenous and
non-Indigenous people to the radical state of dysfunction in Aboriginal
communities.33 For Pearson, Indigenous subjects are so destroyed and so
used to their destitution that only liberating them from a failed social welfare net and local social imaginaries will save them. In the future, according to Howard, Pearson, and others, the young mans stultifying life will
be shown to have been the vigorous beginning of a new day for Indigenous welfare. The evidence will not be in for quite some time, of course.
Was self-determination and its manifestation through the social welfare system a failure? What if we do not accept that the social welfare net
and local social imaginaries are not working in some general way but only
in a specific way? Why arent they seen to be working? What isnt working? Much of the public debate focused on true feelingwhether Mal
Brough really cared about Aboriginal children, whether John Howard
didnt really care, or whether neither of them cared and both of them
were simply engaged in a land grab or seeking a poll boost.34 For instance,
whatever we call the Community Development Employment Program
work for the dole, dole top-up, community development schemethe
best statistics show that the program raised the personal income and employment of rural Indigenous men and women.35 Assessing the relationship between employment, physical and mental health, and vague sets
of life qualities is much harder, and not merely because it confronts an
exceedingly difficult statistical task. Assessing the relationship between
employment and other social indices is difficult because first one has to
agree what a social ill is, or an instance of social care. This said, if the CDEP
doesnt lead to so-called normal employment, and normal employment
is considered the ultimate social good because of how it helps the efficiency of the market and corporate profit, then the CDEP has failed, no
matter that it preserved and enhanced local lives. In neoliberalism to care
for others is to refuse to preserve life if it lies outside a market value. Thus
Howard and Kevin Rudd can say that life will get much harder for Indigenous people but that this harm is a good.
But no matter how we transform, or dont, quasi- events into catastrophes, the contemporary assessment of responsibility for these quasievents and catastrophes emerges within the tensions among social wel-
159
160
Chapter Four
fare, laissez-faire, and neoliberalism and between these and late liberalism.
To ask and answer the question of who is to blame for the slow catastrophe in spaces such as African American neighborhoods and Indigenous
ghettos is to take a stance within liberalism as it organizes markets and
difference. Likewise, to care for others is to make a claim; it is to make a
small theoretical gesture. To care is to embody an argument about what
a good life is and how such a good life comes into being. Thus the arts of
caring for others always emerge from and are a reflection on broader historical material conditions and institutional arrangements. The point is
not, therefore, to argue that someone really cares or doesnt really care.
In the first instance, the question is, what do we believe care to consist of,
such that when we experience a form of relating to one another socially,
we experience that form of relating as a form of caring for others?
What we believe care to consist of is directly related to where we believe failure resides or what we believe failure consists of. Perhaps the
arts of care should be oriented to the potentiality within the actual, to
removing the actual hindrances that impede groups strivingwhether
they are striving to change their world through a social project or to remain as they are within a world changing around them. The arts of care
would then focus on the differential distribution of the ease of coping.
Caring would sink into the recesses of the everyday, the ordinary, and the
mundane. What it would discover there is that everything is jerry-rigged.
Rather than menacing terrorists, they would find people trying to make a
small, frail shelter.
These issues do not need to be addressed if we are dreaming of future
worlds in which no one has these sores or these life expectancies, even as
others are never impeded in their quest to accumulate as much wealth
as possible. But the actual cost-benefit analysis occurring is not the balance between the risk of untreated staphylococci or streptococci versus
the risk of developing a drug-resistant form, but the risk of untreated
staphylococci or streptococci within certain populations and the cost of
investing in poverty-stricken communities for the short or long term. The
presupposition underlying the treatment of infections in indigenous communities is that the communities themselves will remain fetid. Within a
neoliberal state, any social investment that does not have a clear end
a projected moment when input value (money, services, care) can be re-
Health conditions
Health conditions
among Indigenous
among Indigenous
and non-Indigenous
and non-Indigenous
Australians, 20012006
20012006
Australians,
Australian
sources : Australian
((sources:
Bureau of
of Statistics
Statistics
Bureau
and
Australian
Institute
and Australian Institute
of Health
Health and
and Welfare)
Welfare)
of
162
Chapter Four
Chapter Five
164
Chapter Five
the administration who advocate a broader approach to the collective responsibilities of wartime sacrifice and the possibilities of wartime sacrificial love. If the nation is at war, then why are sacrifices asked only of the
military and their families and not of the citizenry more generally? And
how does waging a war premised on an absolute division between those
who stand with us and all others square with another message preached
in Christian pulpits every Easter season: the message of a sacrificial love
offered not merely to friends but, more profoundly, to enemies?
As much as many might wish to hold the Bush administration responsible for every last bit of the mischief of our times, this we cannot
nail to its coffin: Bushs is not the first U.S. administration to promote
a Christian-inflected millennial governance. His administration has certainly pressed the cause. We are only now beginning to appreciate the
organizational ties connecting specific Christian groups and the various
arms of the state apparatus.2 Scholars and activists have been particularly
worried about the ties between the U.S. military and specific evangelical
groups and about religio-political litmus tests used for appointments to
the Justice Department and the Environmental Protection Agency.3 But
equally worrisome are the complex entanglements of conservative Christian movements in neoliberal state functionsnot merely the states
public embrace of religious groups for the outsourcing of federal social
service funding, but also the states covert ties to conservative Christian
agendas, such as the personal and business connections among the Bush
administration, the Family Research Council, and Blackwater Worldwide.4 But the second Bush was not the first.
Twenty years prior to the George W. Bush administration, Ronald
Reagans belief that he was living in the end-time helped shape his foreign policy.5 I would not be the first to note that the Evil Empire provided a discursive footprint for the Axis of Evil. And long before Bush
and Reagan, the concept of manifest destiny, as Ernest Tuveson wrote in
1968, expressed a specific U.S. Christian millennial utopianism in which
America was understood to have been chosen by God to arbitrate a global
war between good and evil.6 Therefore, what may be more disturbing
than yet another U.S. administration articulating yet another millennial
fantasy is how this fantasy seems to have drifted across the Atlantic and
Pacific, encompassing the Blair ministry in Great Britain and less publicly
165
166
Chapter Five
political and social Right, foreign policy is figured not as sacrifice or sacrificial love but as a millennial struggle between good and evil. And, according to Bush, God is not neutral in this struggle.9 From the point of
view of progressive Christians such as James McGinnis, founder of the
Institute for Peace and Justice, the Christian concept of sacrificial love
offers an alternative to these conservative Knights of Faith.10 Tacking between the concept of sacrifice and the concept of sacrificial love, such
progressive critiques castigate the Bush administration for its refusal to
stress the collective sacrifice a nation is normally called on to make in
times of war. If the United States is at war, then all Americans should be
asked to make the necessary social and economic sacrifices of warnot
merely to give up golf. Perhaps if Americans had been encouraged to
think of themselves as at war, then the orgy of spending encouraged by
the housing bubble would have been replaced by a more circumspect sacrificial logic. The exorbitant margins of profit demanded of corporate executives as the price of Wall Street investment might have been tempered.
But We the People was, instead, rewritten as He and I the Competitors, the first person and the nonperson who need not even be specified
lexically.11 McGinnis, for instance, argues that Christian sacrifice teaches
us to share burdens felt by individuals of a community among the community and that Christian sacrificial love teaches us to turn our cheeks to
our enemies. Beyond good and evil lies another message, the cultivation
of modes of sacrifice for the other that defines sacrificial love.
Here we see that where the Bush administration in its critiques has
focused on good and evil, to the exclusion of sacrifice and sacrificial love,
a space has opened for a broader discussion about a certain deficit in late
liberal thought. For all the administrations early emphasis on compassion, critics argue, it has discouraged the kind of neighborliness that is
collective in its imaginary, public in its burdens, and sacrificial in the face
of the need of the other. For all the rhetorical emphasis on faith, religion emerges in administration policies only as a site for state outsourcing and the social production of individualized risk. Compassion means
little more than sympathy for others unable to leverage the kinds of capital necessary to make huge profit at the center or margins of the market.
Under considerable pressure Bush did begin to acknowledge the suffering and sacrifice consequent to his war policies. In a prime-time ad-
dress delivered on June 28, 2005, at Fort Bragg, North Carolina, Bush
stated: Every picture [from the war] is horrifying, and the suffering is
real. Amid all this violence, I know Americans ask the question: Is the
sacrifice worth it? It is worth it, and it is vital to the future security of our
country.12 Is the sacrifice worth it? Answering this question actually presupposes two prior discussions. The first is the discussion of modalities
of expenditure and abandonment in our times, from expenditures and
abandonments whose social weight is barely noticeable to those whose
social weight begins to unravel the social order, from the soft deaths of
pastoral care to the hard deaths of sovereign killing, from making live to
making die. In other words, deciding that this or that sacrifice is worth it
depends on how we narrate forms of killing and making die, making live
and letting suffer, in the various domains of social lifepolitics, market,
and civil society. And this discussion presupposes a second.
The question whether this or that sacrifice is worth it opens the events
of suffering and dying, if not to the problematic of being and time, then to
the problematic of being and tensethe narrative relation among social,
economic, and political values and subjective finitudes and how, where,
and whether subjective finitudes are seen to occur and lead. We can begin
to see what is at stake here if we rephrase what Bush said in this way: Is
the sacrifice worth it? It is if we establish a specific relationship between
violence and redemption that will define the social imaginary of suffering and dying. If we can do so, killing and dying will be understood and
experienced as a mode of birth, as a way of bringing new being into existence. For instance, insofar as killing can be narrated in the future perfect,
it can become a way of giving; violent death becomes sacrifice and ceases
to be scandalous.13 Indeed, by denying the present perfect of suffering and
death, we can make suffering and death something to strive for, celebrate,
and memorialize.
Given its penchant for memorialized denial, the very narrative of sacrifice and sacrificial love presents a set of dilemmas for progressive critics
when they mobilize these narratives against the millennial imaginary of
good and evil. And this is what interests me here. How do discourses of
sacrificial love coordinate violence and redemption in such a way that suffering and dyingthe mortifications of the flesh of othersare continually read from the perspective of the future perfect, the redeemed end of
167
168
Chapter Five
169
170
Chapter Five
publication of Structural Transformation of the Public Sphereto presuppose certain behaviors, knowledges, and sensibilities genealogically related to Christianity and its various disciplines of truth. Thus when we
refer to the secular West, liberal society, or constitutional democracies,
we are referring to a set of multiplex transpositions that mutually reorganized, and made sense of a divide between, the religious and the secular.19 Contra Marx, the state did not become Christian when it gave up
Christianity as a state religion; it became so when the practices of the self,
internal to Christianity and the modern democratic society, were reorganized. In short, secularism and Christianity, and the political and religious more generally, were mutually reconstituted in complex historical
encounters within and outside of Europe. If the secular West is Christian, so this argument goes, it is not because Christians are a majority
within the North Atlantic or because people of religious conviction have
hijacked the state but because secularism and its governmentalities (including the seemingly contrastive French and Anglo-American models of
national inclusion) and Christianity and its practices of the self came to
presuppose compatible modes of social, communicative, and corporeal
comportment and their relation to truth production. As a result, studies
of religion should not define religion and then extract social truths or
ethical principles from this definition. Studies of religion should instead
focus on how people, in coordinating the political, economic, and religious dimensions of social life, make sense of accumulation, expenditure,
and abandonment.
These practices of social coordination are not what have riveted recent critical theory, although I will come back to them shortly. Instead
of examining how people coordinate political, economic, and religious
principles and practices and how these practices of coordination, among
other things, organize, account for, and maneuver around the paradoxes,
contradictions, and problems within actually existing liberal democracies,
many critical theorists seek to distill from Christian doctrine an essential Christian form that can serve as a basis for providing constitutional
democracies a universal and/or transcendental foundation in a postmetaphysical world. And it is to sacrificial love, more specifically, that critical
theorists have turned, with surprising frequency, as that which offers a
revolutionary ethical foundation for democratic governance.
Take, for example, Slavoj ieks recent writings on what he calls the
most deplorable aspects of the postmodern era and the revolutionary
insights of the Christian legacy (postmodern politics, liberal democracy,
and Christian sacrificial love).20 To understand what is at stake in his writings, we need to begin with his opposition to what he calls multicultural
globalization. iek believes that the collapse of the Soviet Union and
the emergence of neoliberal capitalism left the progressive Left without
grounds for making convincing claims about social conscience, democratic justice, or human rights. Against those who would reestablish
democratic justice on a multicultural foundation, iek argues that multiculturalism is an impediment rather than a solution to the problem of
judgment and justice. For him, multiculturalism collapses justice, ethics,
and subjectivity to the iterative sameness of the market, evacuating any
possibility of establishing a transcendental ground on which antagonistic
claims about conscience, justice, or human rights can be made or adjudicated. Where there is no antagonism, so the argument goes, there can be
no meaningful difference, and, contrastingly, where there is antagonism
without transcendental ground, there can be no means for adjudicating
meaningful difference peacefully. Because the postmodern Left occupies
both of these contradictory positions at the same time, it cannot oppose
the vicious extremes of capitalism, the emergence of religious fundamentalism, or the xenophobias of the racist Right. All must be loved equally,
and all should have equal opportunity for thriving; conversely, all must be
equally despised and destroyed.
As much as iek skewersand misconstruesthe so- called postmodern Left, he is also aware of the varieties of radical evil that have
accompanied a specific social groups claim over the content of the Universal: colonialism, anti-Semitism, slavery, homophobia. For iek, only
Christian sacrificial lovethe relationship of absolute love to the radical
other that Christ established on Golgothaoffers a revolutionary means
of avoiding the radical evils associated with projects that specify the content of the Universal and projects that empty out the possibility of Absolute Judgment. The Christian model of sacrificial love, the phantasm of
the Crucifixion, is a fragile absolute in which we are commanded to love
not merely our friend and neighbor but, more radically, our enemy. This
command unplugs Christian subjects from the specificities of their so-
171
172
Chapter Five
cial roles and, insofar as it does so, unplugs their political decisions from
their social and ethical boundaries, providing a Universal foundation to
constitutional democracies currently adrift in a postmetaphysical world.21
In the shadow of the happy event of the Crucifixion, Christians can die in
relation to the given world while catching a glimpse of Another Space.
Unplugging is an act, a temporal event, that changes eternity itself by redefining the possibility of the world. And here we see ieks memorialization of suffering and death by an absolute denial of the present perfect
nature of subjective finitudethat there is a form of killing and dying
that does not need to be experienced, because it can be experienced as
a form of radical birth. Death can remain a joyous denial. So can killing.
Someone or something is killed, extinguished. Someone did the killing.
But iek, Habermas, and Joseph Ratzinger can reassure one another that
this is a minor issue in the context of the major event of the Good News.22
iek is not alone in his march to Golgotha in search of an ethical
foundation for liberal governance. Nor am I alone in noting the return to
religion beyond religion in recent critical theory. John Roberts has discussed this ethicoreligious turn in the work of Jacques Derrida, Alain Badiou, Antonio Negri, iek, and Roy Bhaskar, differentiating among a
weak Messianic tradition as exemplified in Derridas writing, a strong
Messianic tradition in Badious and ieks writings, and an ecumenical libertarianism in Bhaskars and Negris writings. Roberts argues that
these diverse thinkers situate an ethics of conviction as a passionate act
and this passionate act as the ground of responsibility: Ethics becomes
a site of the passionate political judgment and decision.23 Passionate political judgment finds its apotheosis in sacrificial love, and the paradoxical
nature of this passion finds its apotheosis in the work of Derrida.
Derrida began addressing the political potential and paradox of JudeoChristian discourses of sacrificial love and the political responsibility and
ethical obligations of Europe to the other (what has been promised
under the name of Europe) in a series of essays stretching back to the
mid-1990s.24 These mediations are, of course, deconstructive in nature,
seeking not to resolve the impasse of reason witnessed at Calvary but instead to locate the obligation of the North Atlantic to the radical other in
this impassethe mysterium tremendum, the awefulnessof the Christian gift of death. The gift of death cannot be rationalized by any proce-
173
174
Chapter Five
me. Derrida insists that the totality of the annihilation of this law of sacrificial love cannot be underestimated. If I were merely commanded to
love my neighbor as much as I love myself, or in the same way that I love
myself, then when I died, I could believe that some part of me would live
on. This is especially true if I imagine that I am the product of a cultural
or civilizational horizon. I can then imagine that my neighbor would carry
me forward in my absence. Not so with my enemy. The new law, the fulfillment of Abrahams interrupted sacrifice of Isaac, ruptures the security of
this continuity in community and the communitarian illusion on which it
is based. In killing myself for my enemythe Absolute OtherI am extinguished in my particularity and my generality. My self, my ethnos, my
entire aspirational horizon will be consumed by this terrifying demand.
Yet, to the fascination of Derridas ethical reflections, this is exactly what
Yahweh asks of Abraham. And in making this demand on Abraham, Derrida argues, God not only asks him to commit this abominable sacrifice
for the other but also becomes an absolute stranger to him. No known
or knowable system of justice can justify it. There is only an absolute
otherness that demands absolute obedience beyond common, ethnic, or
ethical sense. Maybe this is why the holy hide away in desert caves: lest a
stranger appear on the horizon, demanding this ultimate sacrifice. Yet this
is the dowry that Europe carries, what is internal to the call for recognition of the Christian legacy of Europe in the EU constitution. For it was
exactly in the shadow of an increasingly virulent, religiously and racially
inflected, European stance against immigrants that Derrida wrote, and
wrote against Schmitts too-easy distinction between the private enemy
(inimicos) and the public enemy (hostes).26
What obligation, Derrida asks, does this impasse of love, justice, and
obligation impose on the North Atlantic?27 How can this law claim a
moral imperative over anyone when it cannot ground itself in any sensible order of ethics, justice, or sociality? Should a stranger appear to a
penitent, coming from the South or East or within the West, or flying
toward her across a brilliant morning sky, how does the penitent know
whether this stranger is bound? Is this law transitive? Must she do unto
me as I would do unto her? As I watch her approach, I cannot assume
that she knows this directive or, if she knows it, feels obligated by it. This
stranger may never have heard these words before or may have heard of
them only as a report from an alien, perhaps unholy, place. Indeed, a for-
eign state might severely regulate or ban outright certain Christian sects,
their broadcast channels, and their emissaries to keep its citizenry from
being exposed to these unholy words. Other states might react by passing resolutions supporting freedom of religion through trade sanctions.
But maybe the stranger is closer to home, one of us. Perhaps she is a practicing sociobiologist who espouses a theory of the selfish gene, thinking
that altruistic love is biologically absurd. For her, this directive does not
command the status of a general moral imperative. It is (merely) a local
code or custom, spoken at a specific place, a specific time, open to anthropological analysis. She would not agree that any general political theory
should be animated by these words. What do I do with her? Something
must be preserved, but it is not clear what, or who. Can she live among us?
Can I kill her to preserve the law of love? What else can I kill to preserve
my law of sacrificial love?
These and other attempts to elicit an ethical dynamic from a reading of
Christian doctrine have forged a new, for some frightening, alliance between conservative theologians and the critical Left. iek takes pride in
upending the usual oppositions between the critical Left and the religious
Rightand in cementing his reputation as the perpetual provocateur. Yet
to be persuaded by these readings, we must first accept that religions, and
Christianity in particular, can be definedthat doctrines and paradoxes
exist in them and can be analyzed independent of their social conditions.
We must already abide within a certain social imaginary of liberalism in
which concepts have an abstract and objectified being and agency that
can be detached from the social routines of their formation and citation.
We must think that Christianity is a thing with qualities and essences before we can find it secretly working its ethical magic within the domains
of the modern democratic state. But what if Christianity were not a thing
but part and parcel of a set of social maneuvers within liberal democracies? What if Christian sacrificial love were not a paradox but part of the
means by which the paradoxes, contradictions, and violences of actually
existing liberalism were stilled if not resolved? If Christian sacrificial love
were not a paradox but a means of maneuvering around extant politicaleconomic contradictions, then the first task we would face would be to remember that the narrations from which we draw this paradox are always
already within the natural history of discourse.28
Take, for example, the Abrahamic and Christian narratives from which
175
176
Chapter Five
fices abound, but sacrificial love is rare. Indeed, we see an increasing confidence among liberal democrats in claiming and justifying an absolute
intolerance for competing forms of religion and politics. Red lines demarcate difference, especially where difference becomes a call to arms.
The war on terror cannot be held responsible for the appearance of
these red lines. Defenders of the liberal public spherein both deliberative and substantive varietieshave always held to some red line to
absolute difference. Indeed, we would be hard pressed to find a subject
within liberal democracies who believes that there is no horizon of otherness past which sacrificial love could not, at least theoretically, extend.
Very few people seem willing to unplug themselves unconditionally from
their social and ethical horizon. A nonsacrificial love might be easier to
findfor instance, the position of some Christian evangelical churches
on homosexuality: Love the sinner, hate the sin. But the kind of relation
iek sees Christian sacrificial love establishing with the Absolute Other
is rare, and where it might exist there are laws proscribing it. Caveats proliferate. Dilemmas abound. Legislation piles up. Should the acceptance of
strangers depend on whether they seek to join us in making a joint economic, social, or political world or seek to kill us and our way of life? Are
we creating strangers among us by refusing to embrace cultural difference
in the public sphere and confront the persistence of class inequalities in
the market? Is French republicanism causing the recurrent rioting in the
suburbs of Paris, or is it a bulwark against racism?29 At the minimum,
most liberals agree that tolerance should be extended if the other is willing to do the same, if the difference between the other and me is not so
great as to annihilate me, and if the other can make this difference legible
to me within the deliberative public sphere. At the maximum, consensus
begins to fall apart. We argue whether there are cases in which we should
even empathize with others, let alone die on their behalf. Indeed, cultural
conservatives argue that encouraging our children to empathize with religious suicide bombers may lead them down a treacherous slope that ends
in jihadist camps in Afghanistan and Pakistan.
Yet for those like Habermas who see the liberal public sphere as the
best foundation for political society, the factual limit of tolerance does
not negate the normative orientation of liberalism to revise reflexively
its most fundamental assumptions about justice and the good life. In-
177
178
Chapter Five
It is easy to draw a genealogical relationship between the liberal dialectics of empathetic deliberation and the theological command that we lay
down our life for the other. One can argue, as Charles Taylor and others
have done, that insofar as liberalism seeks to base justice and the good
life on the general perspective of humankind rather than on the particular borders of self, ethnos, and nation, these movements write Christs
signature into the secular.30 But if we think that there is a Christian sacrificial logic, then as much as there is a Christian signature within the very
dynamic of affective public reason, this signature also has all the signs
of a bad forgery. A profound shift has occurred. We are no longer under
the unconditioned command that we give our life for our enemy. We are
under a very conditioned command that we hone our abilities to know
when it makes sense for us, and them, to give a gift of death that does not
really kill. Take, for instance, ubiquitous guiding statements of the practical public sphere such as Lets start with what we can agree about and
We need to be able to live with impasses. These practical statements
refer to and entail the self-evident dependency of liberal justice on the
horizon of unfolding time and the perspective of ends. In liberal systems
of law and public reason, present-tense judgments about moral limits and
the economic impoverishment of others are referred to a future horizon
of rectified sense and bodies. In other words, the tense of public deliberation reflects and reinforces the commonsense tense of sacrificial love. It is,
as Michael Dillon and Julien Reid note, the liberal way of making war
wrapping various kinds of killing within the imaginary of making life.31
So doxic are these statements that many people must struggle to remember that, as much as we might wish it did, empathetic deliberation
does not provide a pause button on social practice and its unfolding. As
much as we might wish it would, social time does not stop and wait for us
to sort things out. As other folks are deliberating their fateand I think
that this point cannot be overemphasizedthe subjects of dominant repugnance, or subjects who challenge dominant modes of life intentionally or not, continue to live. They eat. They sleep. They hope or despair.
They maneuver around a world in which they areand they know they
area social problem. Their lives might be crushed in the meantime. But
empathetic deliberation allows the liberal subject never to have to encounter the people assigned to the brackets of the disagreeable. They do
not exist in the present because I bracket them in order to proceed, nor
will they exist in the future because this future is imagined as a place in
which they do not exist. In short, empathetic deliberation can claim a
genealogy to Judeo-Christian sacrificial love because it uses this spiritual
relation to assign the disagreeable and uncomfortable to the historically
undead.
A similar discursive maneuver around sacrificial love occurs in contemporary sovereign politics. To be sure, as they stare into the pit that
mars Manhattan, many Americans do not hear the theological command
to give up their lives for those responsible. Nevertheless, many people say
that their sons and daughters, their spouses, or their parents are making
exactly this kind of sacrifice in Iraq and Afghanistan. While the United
States consumes its way to economic prosperity, or speculates its way to
economic catastrophe, these people say that their loved ones are willing
to make a principled death far from suburbs and malls. And this time no
god holds back the hands of the slayer. The public may be barred from
doing so, but families and friends see the bodies of their beloveds returned to them wrapped in flags. The mortician repairs the torn body, but
for a final internmentuntil, for some, the redemption of the dead. These
individuals and families have made what the second President Bush and
179
180
Chapter Five
War critics can say that these discursively unfolding references to the
sacrifices of war do not make the deaths of men and women in Iraq and
Afghanistan sacrifices. We should lament the loss of life in Iraq because
those who have died did not have to die in an illegal and unnecessary
warBush and Cheney sacrificed these men and women for power and
profit. But saying this might too quickly dismiss the performative force
of such rhetorical maneuvers and, more troubling, too quickly skirt past
how deeply counterdiscourses are tethered to a compatible imaginary.
We can agree that Bushs sacrificial rhetoric masks the callous disregard
that men who hunger for state and market power have for the lives of the
U.S. troops and Iraqi citizens. And we can agree that most people in the
battlefield are not agreeing to be the sacrificial lamb. Everyone, or those
in their right minds, is trying desperately to remain alive and in one piece.
Actuarial probability shows that someone will diethat many will die.
But no one wants to be that one or to have his or her beloved be that one.
And so Humvees are provided with extra plating. Military engineers try
to beat improvised explosive devices by jamming radar frequencies. Families raise moneyor trim it from already stretched budgetsto send reinforced body armor to their kids, siblings, or spouses in the battlefield.
Meanwhile, U.S. financial speculators are selling the poor and members
of the middle class mortgages that they know will bankrupt them. Are
Americans living through a perverse era? Yes. Does this perversion negate
the performativity of sacrifice as a national rhetoric? Yes, and no.
As horrifying as these facts are, they do not negate the rhetorical force
of sacrifice and sacrificial love that Bush and others evoke. The cynical
reason of the progressive Left does not puncture the rhetoric of sacrificial love, because it merely contests the particular end to which a life is
given rather than the general problem of sacrifice as a life-giving process.
To say that the killed and maimed have died or are dying in vain suggests that there is some horizon of redeemed life where this killing and
maiming would be rectified. In other words, sacrifice plays the role of
the empty signifier, in Ernesto Laclaus sense, creating centering effects
in the realm of the political for critics and supporters of the war.34 For
some, the real site of sacrifice is, and should have remained, Afghanistan.
For some, the real site of sacrifice is Iraq. (If we put our faith in poll numbers, in 2003 seven in ten Americans believed that Saddam Hussein had
181
182
Chapter Five
a role in the 9/11 attacks. In 2006, 43 percent believed that Hussein was
personally involved in the attacks, while 85 percent of the active soldiers
in Iraq believed this.)35 For them, the war is in self-defense. For some,
this horizon is the principle of freedom, making the war against Islam
the decisive ideological struggle of the 21st century.36 For others, the
sacrifice is for the defense of Christianity itself, a Christianity that believes the End of Days depends on the rebuilding of the Jewish Temple in
Jerusalem. (And if reports from military classrooms and training grounds
are correct, the U.S. chain of command is increasingly evangelical, with
God as its ultimate commander in chief.37) For still others, an increasingly disillusioned group, the sacrifice was for Iraqis and Afghans themselves. They enlistedor saw their deployment as helpingto lift Iraqis
and Afghans out of the misery of (Islamic, dictatorial) oppression. Bush
referred exactly to this redemptive form of killing when he insisted that
he would not withdraw American troops from Iraq prematurely lest their
ultimate sacrifice be in vain.
The centering effect of sacrifice and sacrificial love enfolds not only
the many occupational forces killed in Iraq and Afghanistan but also the
countless counterinsurgents and civilians killed alongside them. All are
articulated within the same logic that transforms the killing of occupation
forces, innocent Iraqi and Afghan civilians, and the variety of antioccupational forces into a unified form of sacrificial life. Deaththeirs and
oursis given so that something can be remade into a truer, higher form
of being that we might catch a glimpse of as we make the ultimate sacrifice. Not only is our death a sacrifice in this sense, but the deaths of the
enemies who arrived on my doorstep unexpectedly on 9/11 in New York
and Washington and 7/7 in London are opportunities from this perspective. Even extrajudicial killings are sacrificial in this sense. It is from
this perspective that U.S. soldiers are dying for the enemy. They are dying
so something will be born anew. Once again, but this time in sovereign
war making, the democratic state can narratively articulate its political
strategy to Judeo-Christian sacrificial love because it uses this spiritual
legacy to assign massive killing to the redeemed horizon of the undead.
The same no one who was whispering the creed of sacrificial love in
the ears of those standing at Ground Zero in Manhattan is whispering
in the ear of the neoliberal market. Even if a specific theological figura-
tion of self-denial provided the discursive and subject conditions for the
emergence of Western capitalism (if we follow Max Weber), the resultant
political economy of capitalism seems to have opened rather than closed
a gap between the law of ontotheological self-sacrifice (crucifixion for
the other) and the law of economic self-aggrandizement (individualized
profit maximization), wherein, as I noted above, the We the People of
the national imaginary becomes the he and I who never have to meet.
Since the 1970s, market conservatives and, increasingly, labor democrats
in the United States and Europe have promulgated a promarket philosophy that emphasizes privatization and individualization as the way of alleviating poverty. To right and left we have watched the slow dismantling
of the neocorporatist compromise that lasted from the end of the Second World War to around 1973 and the collapse of the Bretton Woods
Agreements. In the wake of this collapse we are witnessing a shift in the
practical business of the state as a mechanism of wealth redistributing
to the practical business of the state as a source of corporate wealth and
welfare through tax breaks and finance. Social, economic, and political
life is increasingly organized around the neoliberal view that bodies and
values are stakes in individual games of chance and that any collective
agency (other than the corporation) is an impediment to the production of value. And the privatization of risk creates and fosters a language
game in which the social is practiced as nothing more than an aggregate
of individuated risk calculators working according to mathematically predictable econometric models. I am not in you. You are not in me. We are
merely playing the same game of chance, whose truth lies not here and
now between us but there and then in who wins and who loses. No one
is killing me. And I am killing no one. We are each only responsible for
ourselves.38 And every actual hardship I suffer can be referred to a future
generationoften comprising ones own childrenthat will do better,
no matter that every generation has among it many people not making as
much as others or not quite making it at all. As Hannah Arendt put it in
even darker times, The fact that with monotonous but abstract uniformity the same fate had befallen a mass of individuals did not prevent their
judging themselves in terms of individual failure or the world in terms of
specific injustice.39
As with the empathic public sphere and the war on terror, the mar-
183
184
Chapter Five
ket would seem to hold little promise if we are looking for people fulfilling the command that they lay down their lives for enemies, neighbors,
or friends. It is pretty brutal out there in the North Atlantic. Whether
we accept David Harveys claim that the Iraq war signals a new American empire or Giovanni Arrighis that it signals the end of an Americandominated phase of capitalism, the rise of Chinese manufacturing, Brazilian enterprise, and Indian technologies has put renewed strain on the
North Atlantic economies.40 Every day newspapers report a new viciousness in private equity in the United States. The collapse of the mortgage
bubble brought on as much by predatory loans and speculative greed as
by gullible or swindled homeowners occurs side by side with less publicized but equally vicious predations. On September 23, 2007, the New
York Times reported on a widespread investment practice in which private
equity firms acquire nursing homes, dramatically reduce costs by cutting
care, and thus increase their profit margins so that they can be sold for significant gains.41 All of this can be satirized to great profit. But in any case,
sacrificial love hardly seems the proper way of characterizing the practices
of this new economy.
Once again progressive critics should be skeptical of the compassion
of market neoliberals. And once again, given the sensibleness of this skepticism, we need to ask why the rhetoric of sacrificial love can have such
a powerful illocutionary force nonetheless. In previous chapters I noted
that social welfare is neither a success nor failure in the abstract. It is a socially mediated way of assessing the social world. If neoliberalism understands all social investments that do not have a clear enda projectable
moment when input values (money, services, care) can be replaced by
output valueas failing economically and morally, then it might be hard
to defend social programs which presuppose a world in which the state
should care for the most vulnerable.
In a similar way, the question Is the sacrifice worth it? can be answered in the affirmative only if a specific relationship between violence
and redemption defines the social imaginary of suffering and dying. If
mortified bodies are read from the perspective of the redeemed end of
individual responsibility, then the present-tense harms generating goods
for some but not for others can be stretched across the horizon of time in
such a way that the harms themselves become goods. Suffering and dying
185
186
Chapter Five
new formation of power. What other grounds might allow for such leaps
of progressive faith that renounce the body, its finitude and difference, as
greater than the social good? And this leads to the last area that must be
carefully investigated. Can something other than sacrificial love lie beyond the millennial governance of good and evil? Here, perhaps to the
surprise of some, we find that we have a variety of options. Arendt is
an obvious touchstone. For her, the concept of Greek immortality provided an ethical ground for political life far removed from the transcendental antiworldliness of Christianity.44 The willingness to suffer and die
remains central in Arendts political philosophylife is not, after all, the
first value of Arendt, or the second or third. But the wager of death does
not take the hero from the world. Among the ancient Greeks, a heroic
death allowed a person to remain in the world as an immortal, and this
heroic death bequeathed to those left behind the task to bear the burden of a fractured present through the narrativized remembrance. But the
Greeks are not the only ones, or even the first. Buddhist meditations on
the corpse meet new globalized technologies of massacre in Thailand.45
Indigenous geontologies try to refigure the economies of abandonment
in Australia.46 What might be the fates of these refusals of good and evil
on our fragmented presents?
Conclusion
188
Conclusion
existence will look like. And so she lets us watch them walk away from
Omelas with little more than a suggestion that this emigration is a profoundly ethical act. But those who leave Omelas leave the child behind.
Why dont they stay and fight, or burn down Omelas if that is what it
would take to liberate the child?
How more realistic does Charles Burnetts Killer of Sheep seem, ending
as it does with the protagonist Stan working in the same slaughterhouse as
when the film began. We do not see anyone walking out of Watts. Burnett
ends his meditation on race, poverty, and hope by showing Stan pushing
a group of sheep down a metal corridor to their slaughter. And throughout, Burnett foregrounds the near impossibility of escaping Watts when
the equipment that residents have on hand is not reliablewhen Heideggers famous ease of coping has not been built with them in mind.
Take, for example, one scene in the film: Burnett follows the attempt of
Stans family and friends to spend a day at the seashore. They borrow a
car that has clearly seen better days. It begins to break down almost immediately, finally falling to pieces halfway to the shore. Stan and his family
and friends stand on the side of the road, stranded between Watts and the
coast. But while many viewers might not see anything revolutionary in
these scenes, Burnett sees otherwise. For Burnett, Stan is hopeful because
he has decided to persevere and fight on despite societys place for him.1
He remains something inspirational insofar as he continues to strive to
persevere in being.
Burnetts hopeful take on social transformation, when viewed unflinchingly from inside the material conditions of the part that has no
part in late liberalism, provides an interesting rejoinder to those who demand to know the positive content of an alternative form of social life
before setting off on a journey. And it provides an interesting challenge
to those who would demand a normative solution to any critique of the
actual world. Like Burnett, many critical theorists might seem to open the
question of the social otherwise only to leave readers with nowhere to go,
no description of where or what an elsewhere might consist of, and with
nothing in ones pocket but sheer persistence in the face of a set of seemingly unmovable barriers. This, many argue, is especially true of the hope
that immanent critique places in spaces of radical potentiality. If this is
hope, skeptics say, it is a very denuded and awkward form of hope. What
good does immanent critique do for a practical politics if, after stripping
social life bareexposing the brutality of social injusticeit provides it
with no alternative clothing?
Three kinds of criticism are typically leveled at narratives that focus
on moments of sheer potentiality such as we see in The Ones Who Walk
Away from Omelas, Killer of Sheep, and this book: that they lack a normative direction around which a practical politics could be built; that
they are parasitical on a given normative world; and that they reflect the
precritical political positions of the author. The first argument asserts that
there is something wrong with a form of knowledge that does not propose a positive, alternative shelter for the exposed body. A fundamental
rule of scholarship has been broken: every critical social analysis must
have a normative horizon against which progressive action can orient
itself and social movements can be assessed. Immanent critique and critical theory are, instead, mere parasites of the normative.2 Although I have
not discussed his work in this book, Theodor Adorno and his concept of
negative dialectics is a favorite hobbyhorse of these kinds of criticisms.
Prior to the charges against the philosophers of potentiality, there were
charges against the determinate negations of Adorno. His understanding of negative dialectics as parasitic on the ordinary nondialectical mode
of capitalhis argument that the purpose of negative dialectics was to
point out specific contradictions between what liberal capital claims and
what it actually deliversallowed critics to characterize negative dialectics as providing little more than an aesthetically ornate style of skepticism and aloofness.3 To say, not this, does not tell us what then? or
where then? Where are all those people going, those who walk away
from Omelas? And to say, as Burnett does, that the protagonist of Killer
of Sheep is hopeful for nothing more than his continued willful striving
leaves us no insight into how he is able to capacitate his will or how he
will move from willful striving to positive living.
Moreover, according to critics, when theorists do provide substantive answers they are wildly naive and abstract from a policy perspective, and because these theorists are not neutral and disinterested, their
conclusions are untrustworthy.4 Critical theory, and especially immanent
critique, doesnt seek to find the truth of the world, according to these
critics, but rather attempts to shape the truth of the world to reflect its
189
190
Conclusion
tween claims of social unity and claims of social difference and diversity,
and to make palpable the nonidentity between claims about normative
worlds and actual worlds. Negative dialectics insists that we must rigorously demonstrate the noncorrespondence between what is claimed and
what is, and the techniques of power that allow the claimed world to appear not merely as the actual world but the best of all actual worlds. One
must unwork this identitymake it unworkabletransform it from the
background that allows an ease of copying for some but not others. The
activist and personality from New Yorks Lower East Side, Valerie Solanas, made a similar point in her SCum Manifesto, wherein she called
for the unworking of capitalism. SCum will become members of the
unwork force, the fuck-up force; they will get jobs of various kinds and
unwork. For example, SCum salesgirls will not charge for merchandise;
SCum telephone operators will not charge for calls; SCum office and factory workers, in addition to fucking up their work, will secretly destroy
equipment. SCum will unwork at a job until fired, then get a new job to
unwork at.7
In other words, negative critique and critical theory more generally
dont lack a relationship to normativity. They shift the focus on normativity from a horizonal to a background perspective. And it is exactly as
background that normativity provides critical theory with a specific kind
of positivity. What appears to be a radically empty gesture (not this) is
revealed to be a positive act. The citizens of Omelas who say not this
act insofar as they make a statement. Stans continual refusal to collapse
under the weight of a thousand mute obstacles (not that) should be
understood as a series of quasi-events that provide the preconditions
in which some new social content might be nurtured. My Indigenous
friends, who are trying to create an augmented reality project that would
then support them socially and economically, continue to do something
as long as they refuse to do nothing. All of these fictive and real characters
are acting positively in a social world that is built in such a way that it is
unreliable for them whether or not the statement not this immediately
produces a what then. Not this makes a difference even if it does not
immediately produce a propositional otherwise. Each of these differences
is unique because of their differential distribution across the social worlds
of late liberalism.
191
192
Conclusion
Notes
194
Notes to Introduction
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
Notes to Introduction
195
196
Notes to Introduction
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
omy will shrink this quarter and next, tipping the land down under into a recession for the first time since 1991. JPMorgan sees the jobless ratea record low
4% just 10 months agorising to 9% by 2010. Wiseman, Boom in Australia
Goes Bust as Global Slowdown Hits.
Andrews, World Bank Says Global Economy Will Shrink in 09.
Freedman, Zoellick Calls 2009 a Dangerous Year as Crisis Curtails Trade.
Sen, Capitalism beyond the Crisis.
In the same month, the prime minister of China, Wen Jiabao, facing a rapid slowdown of growth and the subsequent displacement of labor, chastised American
unregulated capitala form of capital that many economists believe China had
aspired to.
Brown, Regulating Aversion; Markell, Bound by Recognition.
Fabian, Time and the Other.
Foucault, Society Must Be Defended, 222. See also Arendts description of the
messianic (prophetic) mode of facism in which the Leader is always right in
his actions and since these are planned for centuries to come, the ultimate test of
what he does has been removed beyond the experience of his contemporaries.
Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism, 81.
Arendt, Foucault, and others long ago outlined some of the genealogical conditions of the social. Arendt argued that the Social emerged from and rearticulated the classical division between the biological processes and the realm of
necessity located with the private realm and actions of freedom located in the
public realm of political action. Foucault focused on the emergence of the social
with the emergence of the nation as a new ground and reference of legitimate
power (biopolitics) and knowing (probability). Both emphasized the increasing self-evident nature of the referent, the social, to the human worlds in which
human life consisted. See Arendt, The Human Condition, 3849; Foucault, Society Must Be Defended, esp. 21338.
Thus I am perhaps closest to Foucaults understanding of writing a general history as opposed to writing a total history insofar as the latter claims a total description that draws all phenomena around a simple centera principle, a
meaning, a spirit, a world view, an overall shape, whereas the former would
deploy the space of a dispersion. See Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge
and the Discourse on Language, 911.
Burns, British Multiculturalism Criticized.
See Fanon, Black Skin, White Masks; Bhabha, Interrogating Identity; Fuss,
Identification Papers.
Spinoza, Ethics, 168.
Butler, What Is Critique?
It is in fact what allows political theorists of multiculturalism, such as Will
Kymlicka, to say that immigrants, indigenous people, and the unmarked settler
Notes to Introduction
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
present the nation with distinct modalities and claims of belonging. Kymlicka,
Multicultural Citizenship, 1033.
Waldron, Indigeneity.
Ibid., 55.
Deloria, The World We Used to Live In; Rose, Dingo Makes Us Human;
Turner, This Is Not a Peace Pipe; Watson, Aboriginal Sovereignties.
Coulthard, Subjects of Empire; Kauanui, Hawaiian Blood. That settlement is
an ongoing historical struggle is a point that Waldron is aware of. His discussion of Indigenous rights is explicitly situated in the ongoing conflict between
the Palestinian and Israeli states. See Waldron, Indigeneity.
For a longer discussion, see Povinelli, The Empire of Love.
Anderson, Imagined Communities; Kelly and Kaplan, Represented Communities.
Anderson, Western Nationalism and Eastern Nationalism, 33.
Scheckel, The Insistence of the Indian, 16.
Ibid., 17.
See Padgen, The Fall of Natural Man; Todorov, The Conquest of the Americas.
The infamous notion of domestic dependent nationalism was elaborated across
the so-called Marshall Trilogy, Johnson v. MacIntosh (1823), Cherokee Nation v.
Georgia (1831), and Worcester v. Georgia (1832).
The justices insisted that, legally, the treatment of Indians in conquered territories did not provide a precedent for the status of Puerto Ricans, who were prior
subjects of Spain. Yet the language of Downes v. Bidwell resonates with the landmark decision of Cherokee Nation v. the State of Georgia in 1831, which rendered Indians as members of domestic dependent nations, foreign to the rights
guaranteed by states and territories, but domestic for federal purposes. As alien
races, Puerto Ricans were rendered foreign in a domestic sense by their perceived resemblance to alien races deemed to be incapable of self-government at
home. Kaplan, The Anarchy of Empire, 10.
Wilson, The Sense of the People; Duncanson Scripting Empire. See also Ford,
Settler Sovereignty.
See, for instance, Reynolds, Dispossession.
Abu El Haj, Facts on the Ground.
See, for instance, Goldberg, The Threat of Race.
Fassin, Going Dutch; Fassin and Fassin, Da la question sociale la question raciale?
Koacolu, The Tradition Effect.
Hilgers, Autochthony as Capital in a Global Age; Lan, Guns and Rain; Geschiere and Jackson, Autochthony and the Crisis of Citizenship.
Bentley, The Fourth Dimension.
197
198
1 As part of this debate see Austin-Broos, Making a Difference, and Lattas and
Morris, The Politics of Suffering and the Politics of Anthropology.
2 Pearson states that Sutton provides hope that the debate on Indigenous policy
is becoming much more forthright and that issues that habitually have been
skirted around or alluded to only in anthropological code are being discussed
with a refreshing bluntness. Pearson, Face Reality of Violence, n.p.
3 Sutton, The Politics of Suffering, 85.
4 Ibid, 43.
5 Not surprisingly Sutton was also part of the academic backlash against socalled postmodern anthropologists who supposedly refused to abide by the selfevident nature of these differences, let alone their hierarchical relationship. See
Sutton, The Politics of Suffering.
6 Fabian, The Other Revisited, 143.
7 Ibid., 140.
8 For Rancire, to count as political, an act or movement must involve more than
power, the power to rebel, or the power to suppress. These may be mere instances of policing, which he understands as an order of bodies that defines
the allocation of ways of doing, ways of being, and ways of saying, and sees
those bodies are assigned by the name to a particular place and task; it is an
order of the visible and the sayable that sees that a particular activity is visible
and another is not, that this speech is understood as discourse and another as
noise. In other words, for Rancire, policing is not so much the disciplining
of bodies as a rule governing their appearing and a configuration of occupations and the properties of the spaces where these occupations are distributed.
In contrast to policing, the political is manifested when a part that has had no
parta part that has been treated and understood as nothing but noisebecomes visible, palpable, and articulate. Rancire, Disagreement, 29.
9 Ibid.
10 Under pressure from human rights activists, the federal government made the
program voluntary.
11 Jane Simpson, Ploughing Salt into the Ruins of the NTBroughs Endgame
with CDEP and the Little ChildrenBob Gosford ( June 24, 2007), University of Sydney, Transient Languages and Cultures blog, http://blogs.usyd.edu.au/
elac.
12 Laura Beacroft and Melanie Poole, Overview of Northern Territory Emergency
Response.
13 See Anderson, The Intervention.
14 As of the writing of this book, the Labour government is discussing how it might
reinstate the Racial Discrimination Act without suspending the Intervention.
15 The full text reads: A national welfare card that will allow the Government
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
199
200
201
202
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
standing of rhetoric. De Man, Allegories of Reading, 89. See Peirce, Pragmatism, 40910.
Wild, The Radical Empiricism of William James.
Of course there is some debate among philosophers about this. My own reading of Heidegger is influenced by Arendts student William OGrady, and by the
external realism promoted by Dreyfus and Carmen. See Dreyfus, Being-in-theWorld; Carmen, Heideggers Analytic.
Wrathall, Heidegger and Unconcealment, 130.
Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice.
See Miller, Extimit.
See, for instance, Baker and Morris, Descartes Dualism.
Singer, To Defame Religion Is a Human Right.
Shared Responsibility Agreements were announced after the Howard government decommissioned the Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Commission
(AtSiC). See Council of Australian Governments (CoAg) Department of Immigration and Multicultural and Indigenous Affairs, Shared Responsibility
Agreements (2005), www.indigenous.gov.au.
Derrida, Force of Law.
Walsh, The Animal Enterprise Protection Act.
See para. 22.
Ibid.
See, for instance, Der Derian, Decoding the National Security Strategy of the
United States of America; Masco, Survival Is Your Business.
Bruce Mehlmann, Putting Biometrics to Work for America, Biometrics Consortium Conference (2002), Arlington, Va., www.itl.nist.gov.
Chapter Three. Road Kill
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
of the Greek polis to the life-enhancing logic of the Social. But if Arendt was
clear, if controversially so, about her stance on the relationship between life and
necessity, Foucault was less clear on the relationship between his thinking about
biopolitics and substance. See Arendt, The Human Condition.
Foucault, The Use of Pleasure, 26.
Ibid., 2728. See also Butler, Giving an Account of Oneself.
Note that Rosi Braidotti uses the term material, or more specific bodily materiality rather than substance. Indeed, she explicitly refuses the metaphysics
of substance although the concept of being is central to her work. See Braidotti,
Metamorphoses, 65116.
Butler notes, Humanist conceptions of the subject tend to assume a substantive person who is the bearer of various essential and nonessential attributes.
Butler, Gender Trouble, 10.
See Braidotti, Metamorphoses. Butlers more recent work likewise attempts to
foreground the fundamental vulnerability of the exposed body as a modality of
existence that is neither ontological nor desubstantial. See, for instance, Butler,
Precarious Life.
Massumi, A Shock to Thought, 83.
Povinelli, The Empire of Love, 79.
Deleuze and Parnet, Dialogues, vii.
Foucault, The Ethics of the Concern for the Self as a Practice of Freedom.
See Povinelli, The Cunning of Recognition.
Massumi, A Shock to Thought, 83.
Altman and Hinkson, Mobility and Modernity in Arnhem Land.
See Johnson, Royal Commission into Aboriginal Deaths in Custody.
Made more poignant by the fact that he suffered debilitating bouts of depression, William James wrote on conditions in which conflicts of the will arise.
Take for instance, he writes, freezing mornings when we know we must get out
of bed, and yet the warm couch feels too delicious, the cold outside too cruel,
and resolution faints away and postpones itself again and again as it seemed
on the verge of bursting the resistance and passing over into the decisive act.
For James, what causes us finally to rise is not more will but less inhibition. At
some point there are no contradictory or paralyzing suggestions, and up we
go. James, Will, 691. See also, Richardson, William James, 80.
For instance, Nancy Fraser and Nancy Hartsock critiqued Foucaults concept of
docile power as leaving no site for resistance and no ability to evaluate one form
of resistance over another. They argue that without a fixed point, or normative
horizon, against which progressive action can orient itself and social movements
can be assessed, nothing can emerge and nothing can be discriminated. See, for
instance, Fraser, Foucault on Modern Power; Hartsock, Money, Sex, and Power.
Noise is sterocal: it makes the occupation of an expanse intolerable and thus
gets it for itself. Serres, The Parasite, 94.
203
204
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
unmovable axis of sexual difference has led her to demonize queer theory from
a majoritarian point-of-view. See Braidotti, Metamorphosis, 65116.
38 Povinelli, The Empire of Love.
39 See Duncan Kennedys classic essay The Structure of Blackstones Commentaries.
40 See Braidotti, Metamorphoses.
Chapter Four. Events of Abandonment
205
206
1 The interview was announced and excerpted in Bush Has Given Up Golf for
Troops, on Jonathan Martins blog, Politico, www.politico.com (May 13, 2008).
2 Much of this information is emerging only because of judicial pressure. See, e.g.,
Abramowitz, Service Logs of White House Visitors Are Public Records, Judge
Rules.
3 Critics are worried by the influence of fundamentalist Christian groups like
Military Ministry, a national organization and a subsidiary of the controversial fundamentalist Christian organization Campus Crusade for Christ. Military Ministrys national website states that it targets basic training installations
and has converted thousands of soldiers to evangelical Christianity. See Leopold, Military Evangelism Deeper, Wider Than First Thought. A top adviser
to Gonzales, Monica Goodling is quoted as having judged prosecutors on the
basis of whether they were sufficiently conservative on the core issues of god,
guns + gays. Lightblau, Report Faults Aides in Hiring at Justice Dept. Similar
problems were reported at the Environmental Protection Agency, where Vice
President Dick Cheneys office was reported to have removed statements on
the health risks posed by global warming because they did not comply with the
Bush administrations political and market ideology. Revkin, Cheneys Office
Said to Edit Draft Testimony.
4 For the connections among the White House, Blackwater, and the Family Research Council, see Scahill, Blackwater.
5 Ostling, Harris, and James Castelli, Religion: Armageddon and the End
Times, n.p.
6 Tuveson, Redeemer Nation. See also Weinstein and Seay, With God on Our Side;
Wagner-Pacifici, The Innocuousness of State Lethality in an Age of National
Security; Chang and Mehan, Discourse in a Religious Mode; and Hartnett
and Stengrim, War Rhetorics.
7 See, e.g., the comment by the former prime minister Tony Blair that if you
have faith about these things then you realise that judgement is made by other
people. If you believe in God, its made by God as well, in McSmith, Blair:
God Will Be My Judge on Iraq, n.p.
8 See, e.g., Mamdani, Good Muslim, Bad Muslim.
9 George Bush, Address to a Joint Session of Congress and the American People
(September 20, 2001), http://georgewbush-whitehouse.archives.gov.
10 James McGinnis, Teaching Peace after 9/11 and the War on Iraq: The Most
Weighty Task for Christian Leaders and Educators (n.d.), at the Institute for
Peace and Justice website, www.ipj-ppj.org.
11 Emile Benveniste famously noted that the third person should be, more precisely, thought of as the nonperson and was not always specified lexically. Benveniste, Problems in General Linguistics, 72831.
207
208
12 President Addresses Nation, Discusses Iraq, War on Terror (June 28, 2005),
http://georgewbush-whitehouse.archives.gov.
13 In a reading of Herman Melvilles civil war poem Shiloh, Michael Warner examines how violence can be made scandalous. See Warner, What Like a Bullet
Can Undeceive.
14 Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 48.
15 Anderson, Imagined Communities, 7.
16 Jrgen Habermas, Religion in the Public Sphere, 1, 2.
17 See Ratzinger and Habermas, The Dialectics of Secularization.
18 Habermas attempts to answer these questions in Between Naturalism and Religion.
19 For a genealogy of the secular, see Asad, Formations of the Secular.
20 iek, The Fragile Absolute, 1.
21 iek, A Leftist Plea for Eurocentrism. See also Rancire, Disagreement; and
iek, Fragile Absolute.
22 Ratzinger and Habermas, Dialectics of Secularization.
23 Roberts, The Ethics of Conviction, 37.
24 Most notable are the essays compiled in Derrida, The Gift of Death and Derrida, The Politics of Friendship. For the quotation, see Redfield, Derrida, Europe,
Today, 374.
25 Derrida, The Gift of Death, 65.
26 Schmitt, The Concept of the Political, 29.
27 Derrida discusses the peregrinations of obligation across The Gift of Death and
The Politics of Friendship.
28 I borrow the phrase natural history of discourse from Michael Silverstein and
Greg Urban, who use it to refer to the process by which moments of speech
are moved through social institutions in such a way that they appear to be socially neutral, authoritative pronouncements about social life. See Silverstein
and Urban, The Natural History of Discourse.
29 For a critical account of contemporary debates over race and racism in France,
see Fassin and Fassin, De la question sociale la question raciale.
30 Taylor, A Secular Age.
31 Dillon and Reid, The Liberal Way of War.
32 President Bush Addresses American Legion National Convention, (August 31,
2006), http://georgewbush-whitehouse.archives.gov.
33 Address to a Joint Session of Congress and the American People (September 20, 2001); State of the Union addresses for January 29, 2002; January 28, 2003 January 20, 2004; February 2, 2005; and January 31, 2006, http://
georgewbush-whitehouse.archives.gov.
34 Laclau, On Populist Reason, 69.
35 Milbank and Deane, Hussein Link to 9/11 Lingers in Many Minds. See also
Zogby Poll (February 28, 2006), www.zogby.com.
Notes to Conclusion
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
209
Bibliography
Aazmi, Feza. From the Graveyard of Civilizations: A Muslim Rejoinder to Huntingtons Clash of Civilizations.
London: Trafford, 2007.
Abbey, Edward. The Monkey Wrench Gang. New York:
Harper, 2000.
Abramowitz, Michael. Service Logs of White House
Visitors Are Public Records, Judge Rules. Washington
Post, December 18, 2007. www.washingtonpost.com.
Abu El Haj, Nadia. Facts on the Ground: Archaeological
Practice and Territorial Self-Fashioning in Israeli Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002.
Adorno, Theodor. Negative Dialectics. London: Routledge, 1990.
Agamben, Giorgio. Absolute Immanence. Potentialities, Collected Essays in Philosophy, edited and translated by Daniel Heller-Roazen, 22039. Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2000.
. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life.
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998.
Althusser, Louis. Philosophy as a Revolutionary
Weapon: Interview conducted by Maria Antonietta
Macciocchi. Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays,
1122. New York: Monthly Review Press, 2001.
Altman, Jon, and Matthew Cameron Gray. The Effects
of the CDEP Scheme on the Economic Status of Indigenous Australians: Some Analyses Using the 1996
Census. Discussion paper no. 195, Centre for Aboriginal Economic Policy Research, Australia National
University, Canberra, 2000. http://caepr.anu.edu.au/.
212
Bibliography
Altman, Jon, and Melinda Hinkson. Mobility and Modernity in Arnhem Land:
The Social Universe of Kuninjku Trucks. Journal of Material Culture 12 (2007):
181203.
Altman, Jon, and Boyd Hunter. Indigenous Poverty. Australian Poverty: Then and
Now, edited by Ruth Fincher and John Nieuwenhuysen, 23857. Melbourne:
Melbourne University Press, 1998.
Anderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities: Reflections of the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism. Revised and extended edition. London: Verso, 1991.
. Western Nationalism and Eastern Nationalism: Is There a Difference?
New Left Review 9 (2001): 3142.
Anderson, Ian. The National Aboriginal Health Strategy. Health Policy in Australia, edited by Heather Gardner, 11935. Melbourne: Oxford University Press,
1997.
Anderson, Patricia. The Intervention: Some Reflections Two Years On. University of Melbourne Social Justice Initiative, Annual Social Justice Lecture,
June 24, 2009. http://socialjustice.unimelb.edu.au/.
Andrews, Edmund L. World Bank Says Global Economy Will Shrink in 09. New
York Times, March 9, 2009. www.nytimes.com.
Appadurai, Arjun. Grassroots Globalization and the Research Imagination. Public
Culture 12.1 (2000): 119.
Arendt, Hannah. The Human Condition. 2nd edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998.
. The Origins of Totalitarianism. San Diego: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich,
1979.
Arrighi, Giovanni. Adam Smith in Beijing: Lineages of the Twenty-First Century. London: Verso, 2007.
. The Long Twentieth Century: Money, Power, and the Origins of Our Times.
London: Verso, 1994.
Asad, Talal. Formations of the Secular: Christianity, Islam, Modernity. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2003.
. On Suicide Bombing. New York: Columbia University Press, 2007.
Austin-Broos, Diane. Making a Difference: The Politics of Writing about Suffering. Oceania 80.1 (2010): 10212.
Baker, Gordon, and Katherine J. Morris. Descartes Dualism. London: Routledge,
1996.
Baker, Tom, and Jonathan Simon, eds. Embracing Risk: The Changing Culture of
Insurance and Responsibility. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2002.
Bakhtin, Mikhail. M. Forms of Time and of the Chronotope in the Novel: Notes
towards a Historical Poetics. The Dialogical Imagination: Four Essays, edited by
Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist, 84258. Austin: University of Texas Press,
1981.
Bibliography
Balibar, tienne. Eschatology versus Teleology: The Suspended Dialogue between Derrida and Althusser. Derrida and the Time of the Political, edited by
Pheng Cheah and Suzanne Guerlac, 5773. Durham: Duke University Press,
2009.
Bari, Judi. Timber Wars. Monroe, Me.: Common Courage Press, 1994.
Beacroft, Laura, and Melanie Poole. Overview of Northern Territory Emergency
Response. Centre for Aboriginal Economic Policy Research, Australian National University College of Arts and Sciences, 2008. www.caepr.anu.edu.au.
Benjamin, Walter. Critique of Violence. Reflections: Essays, Aphorisms, Autobiographical Writings, 277300. New York: Schocken, 1986.
Bentley, Nancy. The Fourth Dimension: Kinlessness and African American Narrative. Critical Inquiry 35.2 (2009): 27092.
Benveniste, Emile. Subjectivity in Language. Problems in General Linguistics,
translated by Mary Elizabeth Meek, 22330. Coral Gables: University of Miami
Press, 1971.
Berlant, Lauren. Slow Death (Sovereignty, Obesity, Lateral Agency). Critical
Inquiry 33.4 (2007): 75480.
Bhabha, Homi. Interrogating Identity: Frantz Fanon and the Postcolonial Prerogative. The Location of Culture, 4065. London: Routledge, 2004.
Biehl, Joo. Vita: Life in a Zone of Social Abandonment. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2005.
Bilger, Burkhard. Natures Spoils: The Delighted of Fermented Foods. New
Yorker, November 22, 2010, 10415.
Bourdieu, Pierre. The Essence of Neoliberalism. Translated by Jeremy J. Shapiro.
Le Monde Diplomatique, December 1998. www.mondediplo.com.
. Outline of a Theory of Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1977.
Braidotti, Rosi. Metamorphoses: Towards a Materialist Theory of Becoming. London:
Polity Press, 2002.
Braudel, Fernand. Civilization and Capitalism, 15th18th Centuries. Translated by
Sin Reynolds. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992.
Brock, Peggy. Outback Ghettos. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Brown, Wendy. American Nightmare: Neoliberalism, Neoconservatism, and DeDemocratization. Political Theory 34.6 (2006): 690714.
. Neo-liberalism and the End of Liberal Democracy. Theory and Event 7.1
(2003). www.muse.jhu.edu/journals/theory_and_event/.
. Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2008.
Buck-Morss, Susan. The Origin of Negative Dialectics: Theodor W. Adorno, Walter
Benjamin and the Frankfurt Institute. New York: Free Press, 1977.
Burchell, David. Despair and Defeat Also a White Problem. Australian, May 12,
2008, 8.
213
214
Bibliography
Bibliography
Davidson, Donald. Belief and the Basis of Meaning. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 14154. New York: Oxford University Press, 1984.
. On Saying That. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 93108. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1984.
. Radical Interpretation. Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, 12539.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984.
de Grazia, Victoria. Irresistible Empire: Americas Advance through Twentieth-Century
Europe. Cambridge: Belknap, 2005.
de Man, Paul. Allegories of Reading: Figural Language in Rousseau, Nietzsche, Rilke,
and Proust. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1979.
Deleuze, Gilles. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Translated by Hugh Tomlinson. New
York: Columbia University Press, 1983.
.On Spinoza, Lectures by Gilles Deleuze, posted on the afterhailstorm
blog, 2007. http://deleuzelectures.blogspot.com.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Claire Parnet. Dialogues. New York: Columbia University
Press, 2002.
Deloria Jr, Vine. The World We Used to Live In: Remembering the Powers of the Medicine Man. Golden, Colo.: Fulcrom Publishing, 2006.
Der Derian, James. Decoding the National Security Strategy of the United States
of America. boundary 2 30.3 (2003): 1927.
Derrida, Jacques. Des tours de Babel. Difference in Translation, edited and translated by Joseph F. Graham, 165207. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1985.
. The Ends of Man. Margins of Philosophy, 10936. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1985.
. Force of Law: The Mythical Foundation of Authority. Deconstruction
and the Possibility of Justice, edited by Drucilla Cornell, Michael Rosenfeld, and
David Gray Carlson, 367. New York: Routledge, 1992.
. The Gift of Death. Translated by David Willis. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995.
. The Politics of Friendship. Translated by George Collins. London: Verso,
2005.
Dillon, Michael, and Julien Reid. The Liberal Way of War: Killing to Make Life Live.
London: Routledge, 2009.
Dreyfus, Herbert L. Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heideggers Being and
Time, Division I. Cambridge: mit Press, 1991.
Duhigg, Charles. At Many Homes, More Profit and Less Nursing. New York
Times, September 23, 2007. www.nytimes.com.
Duncanson, Ian. The Peronist and the Ghost in the State of Australia. Law/Text/
Culture 8 (2004): 10736.
. Scripting Empire: The Englishman and Playing for Safety in Law and
History. Melbourne University Law Review 24 (2000): 95264.
215
216
Bibliography
Eichengreen, Barry. The European Economy since 1945: Coordinated Capitalism and
Beyond. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008.
Esposito, Roberto. Bios: Biopolitics and Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2008.
Fabian, Johannes. The Other Revisited: Critical Afterthoughts. Anthropological
Theory 6.2 (2006): 13952.
. Time and the Other. Reprint edition. New York: Columbia University
Press, 2002.
Fanon, Frantz. White Skin, Black Masks. New York: Grove Press, 2008.
Fassin, Didier, and Eric Fassin. Da la question sociale la question raciale? Representer la societ francaise. Paris: La Decouverte, 2005.
Fassin, Eric. Going Dutch. Bidoun: Arts and Culture from the Middle East, no. 10,
(2007): 6263. Also available at www.bidoun.org.
Fekete, John. The Dispossessed and Triton: Act and System in Utopian Science Fiction. Science Fiction Studies 18.6 (1979): 12943.
Fennell, Catherine. Project Heat and Sensory Politics in Redeveloping Chicago
Public Housing. Ethnography 12.1 (2011): 4064.
Ford, Lisa. Settler Sovereignty: Jurisdiction and Indigenous People in America and Australia, 17881836. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2010.
Foucault, Michel. The Archaeology of Knowledge and the Discourse on Language.
Translated by A. M. Sheridan Smith. New York: Pantheon, 1982.
. The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the College de France, 19781979. Translated by Graham Burchell. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008.
. Des espaces autres. Architecture, Mouvement, Continuit 5 (1984): 4649.
. The Ethics of the Concern for Self as a Practice of Freedom. Ethics:
Subjectivity and Truth, edited by Paul Rabinow, 281303. New York: New Press,
2006.
. Security, Population, Territory: Lectures at the College de France, 19771978.
Translated by Graham Burchell. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2009.
. Society Must Be Defended, Lectures at the College de France, 19751976.
Translated by David Macey. London: Picador, 2003.
. The Use of Pleasure, History of Sexuality, Volume 2. Translated by Robert
Hurley. New York: Vintage Press, 1990.
Franklin, Matthew. Swan Cuts Deep as Revenue Sinks. Australian, May 12, 2008, 1.
Fraser, Nancy. Foucault on Modern Power: Empirical Insights and Normative
Confusions. Unruly Practices: Power, Discourse, and Gender in Contemporary
Social Theory, 1734. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989.
. Rethinking Recognition. New Left Review 3 (2000): 10720.
Freedman, Jennifer. Zoellick Calls 2009 a Dangerous Year as Crisis Curtails
Trade. March 21, 2009. Website of Bloomberg company. www.bloomberg.com.
Fudge, Judy, and Rosemary Owens. Precarious Work: Women and the New Economy.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
Bibliography
217
218
Bibliography
Bibliography
219
220
Bibliography
Marr, David, and Marian Wilkinson. Dark Victory. Crows Nest: Allen and Unwin,
2003.
Martiniello, Jennifer. Howards New TampaAboriginal Children Overboard.
Asian Tribune, July 28, 2007. www.asiantribune.com.
Marx, Karl. On the Jewish Question. The Marx-Engels Reader, edited by
Robert C. Tucker, 2652. New York: W. W. Norton, 1978.
Masco, Joseph. Survival Is Your Business: Engineering Affect and Ruins in
Nuclear America. Cultural Anthropology 23.2 (2008): 36198.
Massood, Paula. Aesthetic Appropriate to Conditions: Killer of Sheep, (Neo)
Realism, and the Documentary Impulse. Wide Angle 21.4 (1999): 2041.
Massumi, Brian. The Politics of Everyday Fear. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993.
. A Shock to Thought: Expressions after Deleuze and Guattari. London: Routledge, 2002.
Mbembe, Achille. Necropolitics. Public Culture 15.1 (2003): 1140.
McFate, Montgomery. Anthropology and Counterinsurgency: The Strange Story
of Their Curious Relationship. Military Review 85.2 (2005): 1821.
McKeom, Adam. Melancholy Order: Asian Migration and the Globalization of Borders. New York: Columbia University Press, 2007.
McSmith, Andy. Blair: God Will Be My Judge on Iraq. Independent, March 4,
2006. www.independent.co.uk.
Melville, Chris, and Ollie Owen. China in Africa: A New Era of South-South
Cooperation. Open Democracy, July 7, 2005. www.opendemocracy.net.
Milanovic, Branko. Worlds Apart: Measuring International and Global Inequality.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005.
Milbank, Dana, and Claudia Deane. Hussein Link to 9/11 Lingers in Many
Minds. Washington Post, September 6, 2003.
Miller, Jacques-Alain. Extimit. Lacan Theory of Discourse: Subject, Structure and
Society, edited by Mark Bracher, 7487. New York: New York University Press,
1994.
Mitchell, Donald. A Note on Rising Food Prices. Policy Research Working Paper
4682, July 2008. World Bank Development Prospects Group. Available at the
Social Sciences Research Network website. www.ssrn.com.
Mullarkey, John. Deleuze and Materialism: One or Several Matters. A Deleuzean
Century? edited by Ian Buchanan, 5984. Durham: Duke University Press, 1999.
Murray, Charles. Losing Ground: American Social Policy, 195080. New York: Basic
Books, 1982.
Nagel, Thomas. The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989.
Norton, Chris. Black Independent Cinema and the Influence of Neoliberalism:
Futility, Struggle and Hope in the Face of Reality. Image 5 (1997). www
.imagesjournal.com.
Bibliography
221
222
Bibliography
Reynolds, Henry. Dispossession: Black Australia and White Invaders. St. Leonards,
nSW: Allen and Unwin Academic, 1996.
Richardson, Robert D. William James: In the Maelstrom of American Modernism.
New York, Houghton Mifflin, 2006.
Risor, Helene. Twenty Hanging Dolls and a Lynching: Defacing Dangerousness
and Enacting Citizenship in El Alto, Bolivia. Public Culture 22.3 (2010): 46586.
Roberts, John. The Ethics of Conviction: Marxism, Ontology, and Religion.
Radical Philosophy 121 (2003): 3647.
Robinson, Natasha. Secrets in the Shadow. Australian Online, June 21, 2008.
www.theaustralian.news.com.au.
Rose, Deborah Bird. Dingo Makes Us Human: Life and Land in an Australian
Aboriginal Culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Rothwell, Nicolas. No Question of Turning Back. Australian Online, June 21,
2008. www.theaustralian.news.com.au.
Rudd, Kevin. Kevin Rudds Sorry Speech. Transcript of speech to Parliament.
Sydney Morning Herald, February 13, 2008. www.smh.com.au.
Sahlins, Marshall. How Natives Think: About Captain Cook, for Example. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1995.
Saulny, Susan. Michigan Prison Is Considered for Detainees. New York Times,
August 12, 2009. www.nytimes.com.
Scahill, Jeremy. Blackwater: The Rise of the Worlds Most Powerful Mercenary Army.
New York: Nation Books, 2008.
Schaler, Jeffrey D., ed. Peter Singer Under Fire: The Moral Iconoclast Faces His Critics.
Chicago: Open Court Press, 2009.
Scheckel, Susan. The Insistence of the Indian: Race and Nationalism in NineteenthCentury American Culture. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998.
Schmitt, Carl. The Concept of the Political. Translated by George Schwab. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 2007.
Scrimgeour, D. How Think Tanks Are Misleading Us on Aboriginal Childrens
Health. Crikey, September 24, 2007. www.crikey.com.au.
Scrymgour, Marion. Whose National Emergency Caboolture and Kirribili or
Milikapiti and Multijulu? Charles Perkins Oration, October 27, 2007. www.abc
.net.au.
Select Committee on a Certain Maritime Incident: Report. Canberra: Commonwealth
of Australia, 2002.
Sen, Amartya. Capitalism beyond the Crisis. New York Review of Books, 56.5
(2009). www.nybooks.com.
Serres, Michel. The Parasite. Translated by Lawrence R. Scher. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982.
Silverstein, Michael. Metapragmatic Discourse and Metapragmatic Function.
Reflexive Language: Reported Speech and Metapragmatics, edited by John Lucy,
3358. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993.
Bibliography
Silverstein, Michael, and Greg Urban. The Natural History of Discourse. Natural
Histories of Discourse, edited by Michael Silverstein and Greg Urban, 120. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
Simon, Linda. William Jamess Lost Souls in Ursula Le Guins Utopia. Philosophy
and Literature 28.1 (2006): 89102.
Singer, Peter. To Defame Religion Is a Human Right. Guardian Online, April 15,
2009. www.guardian.co.uk.
Smith, Anna Marie. The New Right Discourse on Race and Sexuality: Britain, 1968
1990. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
. Welfare Reform and Sexual Regulation. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007.
Solanus, Valerie. The Scum Manifesto. London: Verso, 2004.
Spinoza, Baruch. Ethics. Translated and edited by G. H. R. Parkinson. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2000.
Stannard, Matthew B. Montgomery McFates Mission: Can One Anthropologist
Possibly Steer the Course in Iraq? San Francisco Chronicle, April 29, 2007.
Sutton, Peter. The Politics of Suffering: Indigenous Australia and the End of the Liberal
Consensus. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 2009.
Taylor, Charles. Modern Social Imaginaries. Durham: Duke University Press, 2004.
. A Secular Age. Cambridge: Belknap, 2007.
. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1989.
Todorov, Tzveton. The Conquest of the Americas, The Question of the Other. Norman:
University of Oklahoma Press, 1999.
Trouillot, Michel Rolph. Global Transformations: Anthropology and the Modern
World. New York: Palgrave, 2003.
Turner, Dale. This Is Not a Peace Pipe: Towards a Critical Indigenous Philosophy.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2009.
Tuveson, Ernest. Redeemer Nation: The Idea of Americas Millennial Role. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1980.
Vigh, Henrik. Crisis and Chronicity: Anthropological Perspectives on Continuous Conflict and Decline. Ethnos 73.1 (2008): 524.
Wagner-Pacifici, Robin. The Innocuousness of State Lethality in an Age of National Security. South Atlantic Quarterly 107 (2008): 45983.
Waldby, Catherine. Umbilical Cord Blood: from Social Gift to Venture Capital.
BioSocieties 1.1 (2006): 5570.
Waldron, Jeremy. Indigeneity? First Peoples and Last Occupancy. New Zealand
Journal of Public and International Law 1.1 (2003): 5582.
Wallerstein, Immanuel. The Demise of Neoliberal Globalization. MR Zine 1.2
(2008). www.monthlyreview.org.
. The End of the World as We Know It: Social Science for the Twenty-First
Century. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2001.
223
224
Bibliography
Walsh, Edward J. The Animal Enterprise Protection Act: A Scientists Perspective Brings the Law into Focus. Lab Animal 29.2 (2000). Available at www
.naiaonline.org.
Warhurst, John. The Australian Federal Election of 10 November 2001. Australian
Journal of Political Science 37 (2002): 15360.
Warner, Michael. Publics and Counterpublics. New York: Zone, 2002.
. What Like a Bullet Can Undeceive. Public Culture 15.1 (2003): 4154.
Watson, Irene. Aboriginal Sovereignties: Past, Present and Future (Im)Possibilities. Our Patch: Enacting Australian Sovereignty Post-2001, edited by Suvendrini
Perera, 2343. Perth: API Network, 2006.
. Sovereign Spaces: Caring for Country and the Homeless Position of
Aboriginal Peoples. South Atlantic Quarterly 108.1 (2009): 2751.
Wax, Dustin M., ed. Anthropology at the Dawn of the Cold War: The Influence of
Foundations, McCarthyism and the CIA. London: Pluto Press, 2008.
Weinstein, Michael L., and Davin Seay. With God on Our Side: One Mans War
against an Evangelical Coup in Americas Military. New York: St. Martins, 2006.
Weller, Patrick. Dont Tell the Prime Minister. Carlton North, Victoria: Scribe Publications, 2002.
Wild, John. The Radical Empiricism of William James. New York: Doubleday, 1969.
Wild, Rex, and Patricia Anderson. Ampke Akelyernemane Make Mekarle, Little
Children Are Sacred. Darwin: Board of Inquiry into the Protection of Aboriginal
Children from Sexual Abuse, 2007.
Williams, Bernard. Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Williams, Bernard, with J. J. C. Smart. Utilitarianism: For and Against. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1973.
Williams, Howard. Adornos Negative Dialectics. Hegel, Heraclitus, and Marxs
Dialectic. New York: St. Martins Press, 1989.
Wilson, Kathleen. The Sense of the People: Politics, Culture and Imperialism in
England 17151785. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.
Wiseman, John. Boom in Australia Goes Bust As Global Slowdown Hits. USA
Today. December 28, 2008. www.usatoday.com.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. On Certainty. New York: Harper Perennial, 1972.
Wrathall, Mark A. Heidegger and Unconcealment: Truth, Language, and Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.
iek, Slavoj. The Fragile Absolute; or, Why Is the Christian Legacy Worth Fighting
For? London: Verso, 2001.
. A Leftist Plea for Eurocentrism. Critical Inquiry 24.4 (1998): 9881009.
Index
226
Index
Animal Liberation Front, 94, 105, 204n34
Animal rights, 8586, 94, 121
Anthropology, x, 14, 4950; of otherwise, 10
Anticolonialism, ix, 2526, 2829, 98, 79
Anti-commodity, 122. See also
Commodity
Anti-Semitism, 171
Appadurai, Arjun, 195n50
Archive, digital, 142. See also Augmented
reality
Arendt, Hannah, 183, 186, 196nn6667,
2023n6, 209n39, 209n44
Arrangements, 5, 7, 1617, 20, 35, 60, 82,
109, 139, 160, 168
Arrighi, Giovanni, 18, 184, 195n40, 195n42
Asad, Talal, 208n19, 209n9
Askesis, 15, 106, 112
At-hand, 13, 30, 52, 81, 152; ready-to-hand,
29, 112; unready-at-hand, 192
Augmented reality, x, 6, 110, 138, 140,
142, 191
Austin-Broos, Diane, 198n1
Australia, x, 67, 1617, 2324, 30, 3435,
3844, 4752, 5556, 5860, 11011,
11315, 12829, 13738, 14052, 15457
Australian Capital Television v. Commonwealth (1992), 147, 205n12
Australian Institute of Health and Welfare, 157
Australian Security Intelligence Organization, 146
Autological subject, 13, 26, 28, 34, 35,
4041, 43, 68, 70, 7273, 75, 81, 100,
129, 152
Bakhtin, M. M., 194n27
Balibar, tienne, 194n29
Bali bombings, 14647
Behrooz and Ors v. Secretary of the Department of Immigration and Multicultural
and Indigenous Affairs (2004), 150,
206n21
Index
Carmen, Taylor, 202n24
Carnality, 108, 110, 11718, 121, 123; errantness and, 109. See also Corporeality
Chakrabarty, Dipesh, 77, 201n1
China, 19, 20, 2324, 97
Christianity, 62, 170, 175, 182, 186; conservative, 164; culture of, 165; faith and,
166, 16869
Chronotrope, xi, 56, 16
City of Boerne v. Flores (1997), 6465
Civilization, 28, 80, 91, 165, 174; borders
and boundaries of, 86; division of, 13;
securitization of, xvii. See also Care;
Tense
Civil rights movement, 60
Civil society, 17, 167
Clinton, Bill, 60
Colonialism, 30, 38, 104, 129, 171
Commodity, 2324, 122
Commodity speculation, 124
Common politics, 72
Commonsense, 31, 138, 179
Communication Management Units, 127
Communitarian illusion, 174
Community Development Employment Scheme (CDEP), 5355, 90, 141,
159, 198
Compassion, 166, 184
Compassionate conservatism, 185
Conatus, 9, 103, 116. See also Striving
Constitutional events, 13, 67
Constitutional protection, 51
Constitutions: Australian, 39; democracy and, 93, 16870, 172; EU, 165, 169,
174; powers of, 66; process and, 194;
scrutiny and, 65; U.S., 63, 64, 66, 68,
126
Controlled substances, 64
Controlled Substances Act, 42, 63, 65, 68,
7071, 96, 200n31
Corporeality, 117, 118, 155, 170; carnality
vs., 10810, 121, 123
227
228
Index
Detention camps, 149, 150
Difference, x, 9, 31, 71, 75, 88, 101, 109, 143,
160, 186; absolute, 13, 48, 177; cultural,
26, 97, 140, 177; divisions of, 152; governance of, 34, 43, 50, 52, 67, 133, 141,
152, 190; indifference and, 15, 83, 84;
Indigenous, 61, 67; meaningful, 171;
political, 168; social, 5, 25, 28, 29, 30,
40, 42, 77, 100, 191
Digital archive, 142. See also Augmented
reality
Dispossession, 25; accumulation by,
1819; Indigenous, 18, 35
Diversity, 80, 191
Dreyfus, Herbert L., 202n24
Durative present, 2, 3, 12, 58
Durative tense, 3, 12, 32, 49, 78, 83, 96,
98, 130
Dwelling, x, 33, 1067, 125, 168; sciences,
32
Dynamis, 9
Earth First!, 95, 105
Earth Liberation Front, 9495, 105, 125
Ease of coping, 144, 160, 188
East Timor, 147
Eichengreen, Barry, 195n37
Embodiment, 45, 10, 14, 30, 42, 10910,
121, 128; material, 130; obligation and,
112, 115, 142; potentiality and, 16, 106,
131; reason and, 100; social dissonance
and, 6, 83
Empathy, 4, 162, 176; deliberation and,
17879
Employment Division v. Smith (1990), 65,
68
Empty signifier, 181
Endurance: of alternative worlds, 10, 14,
29, 41, 121, 125, 131; distribution of, 3,
5, 11, 40; ethics of, 44, 79; event and,
13234; forms of, 116; materiality and,
142; miracles of, 45, 122, 12728; nar-
Index
eventfulness and, xi; foundations of,
170, 172, 186; futures and, 23, 130,
143, 173
Ethnographic narration, 49
European Union, 89, 165
European Union Constitution, 165, 169,
174
Evangelicalism, 65, 164, 177, 182
Eventfulness, x, xi, 35, 11, 1314, 2932,
34, 4142, 79, 13334, 14445, 15053,
162, 165, 192
Events, 2, 10, 17, 35, 44, 83, 108, 121, 146,
156, 167, 173; catastrophic, 3, 1314, 32,
13234, 144, 147, 15254, 179, 185; constitutional, 13, 67; experiential, 136, 137;
extraordinary, 14; intimate, 13; lethal,
134; like, 145; linguistic, 12; narrated,
12, 49, 176; perceptual, 14; political,
52, 71, 72, 76; public, 151; quasi-, 45,
1314, 84, 92, 13235, 142, 144, 15254,
159, 191; social, 132; spectacular, 134,
141, 153; sublime, 133; temporality and,
36, 172; tense and, 11, 34, 39, 40; violent, 132
Eventualization (evenementialization), 15
Evil, 44, 163, 16468, 18586; radical, 171
Exhaustion, 3, 5, 32, 40, 44, 99, 110, 123
25, 12730, 13234
Existential phenomenology, 88
Existents, 13637
Extimacy, 89
Fabian, Johannes, 26, 30, 49, 52, 196n65,
198n6
Fanon, Frantz, 25, 30, 196n7
Finitude, 44, 167, 172, 186
First Nations, 55
Food movement, 111, 12122, 129
Fordism, 102, 151
Formations of power, 1056, 134
Forms of life, alternative, 14, 25, 95, 109,
188
229
230
Index
Habituated being, 136
Habitus, 88
Hacking, Ian, 153, 206n26
Hamdan v. Rumsfeld, 64, 97
Haraway, Donna, 83, 201n16
Harvey, David, 1719, 184, 194n36,
195nn4344
Hate speech, 85, 86, 89
Healthabitat, 137
Heidegger, Martin, 88, 102, 202n24
Hermeneutics, 15, 83
Heterotopic, 5, 7, 15
Hezbollah, 151
Homeland Security Act, 126
Homophobia, 171
Hope, 1023, 179, 18788
Hospitality, 104, 105
Howard, John, 17, 48, 5259, 71, 141, 146
50, 156, 15859, 165
Human rights, 14950, 171
Huntington, Samuel, 28, 8081, 201n3
Illocutionary force, 184
Immanence: critical theory and, 8, 10,
1416, 3233, 103, 129; life and, 42; obligation and, 33; philosophy and, 9; social field and, 98; social theory and, 116
Incommensurability, 30, 32, 86; legislation and, 8991; semantic, 81; state
regimes and, 91; understanding and, 89
Indeterminacy, 10, 7273, 81, 142
India, 1819, 20, 153, 184
Indigeneity: critical theory and, 41; dispossession and, 18; geontology and,
120, 186; health and, 113, 137, 14344,
157, 161; native title and, 40, 90, 113, 115,
117; politics of the prior and, 3436;
self-determination and, 54, 57, 61, 104;
sexual abuse and, 5860; sovereignty
and, 49; state relations and, 39, 57, 158;
territoriality and, 5354, 90, 115; traditions and customs of, 47, 50, 59, 61, 66,
129, 136, 159
Index
146, 148; state, 58, 118, 15153, 157; techniques of, 22
Lacan, Jacques, 88
Laissez-faire, 2022, 29, 101, 148, 160
Land rights, ii, 90, 104, 140
Language games, 88, 106, 157, 183, 185
Late liberalism, ix, 3, 1112, 16, 2529, 34,
36, 42, 43, 5052, 71, 75, 7980, 83, 101,
118, 133, 152, 165, 168, 192
Lea, Tess, 137
Lebanon, 15051
Le Guin, Ursula, x, xi, 1, 35, 1214, 45,
76, 101, 108, 135, 145, 155, 162, 187, 193n1
Left, 33, 56, 147, 168, 183; anarchist, 19, 94;
critical, 175; postmodern, 171; progressive, 121, 147, 171, 181; radical, 127; revolutionary, 19
Lethality, 44, 129, 146, 15253, 162
Letting die, 22, 29, 44, 9495, 134. See also
Making die
Letting suffer, 167
Liberal Democratic Party (Great Britain), 80
Liberalism: diasporic, xi, 6, 16; governmentality and, 22, 25; intolerance and,
43, 7576, 7981, 92, 177; justice, 26,
7677, 85, 92, 171, 17778, 190; Keynesian, 103; laissez-faire, 2122; late, ix,
3, 1112, 16, 2529, 34, 36, 42, 43, 5052,
71, 75, 7980, 83, 101, 118, 133, 152, 165,
168, 192; neo-, 1617, 1925, 98, 129, 134,
154, 159, 184; postcolonial, xi, 6, 16; in
public sphere, 77, 86, 169, 17778
Liberation theology, 185
Liberty, 169, 180
Life: aggregations of, 30, 32; anti-, 186;
arts of, 108, 118; attributes of, 103; bare,
31, 133, 189; conditions of, 77; death
vs., 10, 51; distributions of, 5, 155; edge
of, 78; embodied, 109; enhancing, 23,
44; ethical relation to, 44, 109; everyday, 81, 111, 133; form of, 10, 14, 25, 29,
31, 104, 109, 118, 154, 179, 192; geological, 120; good, 5, 6, 44, 85, 128, 160, 173,
177; hegemonic, 30; immanent, 42;
making, 153; logic of, 158; political, 186;
possibilities of, 8, 10, 16; practice of,
124; proper, 44, 104; space of, 109; social, 5, 10, 14, 144, 170, 176, 188, 189; way
of, 140, 177; world, 18, 79, 93, 99, 130
Little Children Are Sacred, 23, 48, 5354,
58, 90
Local Government Act (Australia), 90
Logos, 50
Love, 8, 92; absolute, 171; altruistic, 175;
law of, 173, 175; nonsacrificial, 177; sacrificial, xi, 3, 5, 1213, 4445, 16372,
17476, 178, 182, 18486; unconditional, 176
Lusaka Declaration of the Commonwealth on Racism and Racial Prejudice, 104
Making die, 22, 29, 58, 62, 95, 98, 134, 167
Making live, 22, 29, 62, 134, 167
Mamdani, Mahmood, 82, 201n14, 207n8
Manifest Destiny, 38, 164
Markell, Patchen, 26, 82, 196n64, 201n15
Market: biofuel, 124; capital, 122; class inequalities and, 177; conservatives and,
183; efficiency in, 159; financial crisis
and, 115; forms of, 8, 13, 17, 20, 29, 78,
106, 152, 160, 183; global, 2325, 97, 173,
178; multiculturalism and, 171; neoliberal, 18, 2124, 105, 151, 152, 162, 182,
184; Smiths vision of, 24; values of,
95, 119, 159
Marx, Karl, 123, 16970, 202n6
Massumi, Brian, 10, 106, 108, 14445,
194n26, 203n12, 203n17, 204n24, 205n10
Material composition, 8, 16, 109, 137
Materiality (Matiere), 10, 15; assemblages
of, 118, 123, 134; discursive construction
of, 14, 1089; sociality of, 134; substance and, 79, 106, 108, 128, 13031
231
232
Index
Material responsibility, 136
Mbembe, Achille, 19, 134, 195n48, 205n3
Media: communicative, 100, 173; mass,
144; mixed, 43; multi, 115; new, 112;
news, 59, 147, 150; print, 37
Messianism, 172
Metaphysics of substance, 1068
Middle East, 169
Millennialism, 163, 166; governance and,
16465, 186; imaginary, 167
Mobility, 102
Mode of production, 102, 151
Mode of transformation, 41
Moral evaluation, 10, 16, 106
Morality: capital and, 162; of conduct,
10, 106
Moral limits, 178
Moral reason, 31, 77, 89
Moral reflection, 10, 16, 106
Moral sense, 1, 13, 8689, 91, 100
Mortgage bubble, 181, 184
Movements: conservative Christian, 164;
ecological, 34, 9495, 104, 12223, 125,
127; food, 111, 12122, 129; Green, 43,
64, 122, 127; social, ix, 2526, 2829, 50,
79, 98, 101, 103, 124, 189
Moynihan Report, 60, 200n26
Multiculturalism, 25, 71, 196; failure of, 28,
59, 171; globalization and, 171; state, 29
Muslims, 40, 8081, 151, 165
MV Tampa, 56, 148
Narration, 175; act of, 176; event of, 12,
176; time of, 12
National Animal Interest Alliance, 9495
National Association for Biomedical Research, 94
National Commission on the Prevention
of Violent Radicalization and Homegrown Terrorism, 12526
Native American Church, 65, 6869, 73
Native Title Act, xvi, 40, 61, 90
Nauru, 149
Necropolitics, 19
Negative dialectics, 18991, 209n3
Neighbors, 166, 171, 17374, 176, 184
Neoconservativism, 29, 87, 14849
Neoliberalism, 1617, 1925, 98, 129, 134,
154, 159, 184
Noise, 5051, 73, 82, 116, 119, 121, 13637.
See also Parasites
Normative worlds, 7, 31, 189, 191
Normativity, 110, 188, 191; achievement
and, 22; commitment and, 32; governance and, 106; horizon and, 129, 185,
189; orientation and, 177; projection
and, 192; public, 100; structure of, 185;
theory of, 33, 189
North Atlantic, 170, 172, 174, 184
Northern Territory National Emergency Response Act (2007), 43, 5458,
6061, 7172, 76, 78, 84, 90, 97, 100,
115, 136, 142
Obligation, 34, 61, 63, 84, 130, 156, 172,
174; embodied, 112, 115, 142; immanent,
32, 33; state, 120
Office of the Registrar of Indigenous
Corporations, 91
Oklevueha Earthwalks Native American
Church, 69
Ones Who Walk Away from Omelas,
The, x, xi, 16, 14, 27, 45, 76, 84, 101,
105, 135, 145, 18788, 191, 193n1
On the Jewish Question (Marx), 169
Ontological duality, 9
Ontological necessity, 146
Ontological reduction, 108
Ontology: of being, 107; categories of, 35;
of potentiality, 9, 14, 16
Operation Backfire, 125
Organic intellectual, 122
Other, absolute, 174, 177, 185
Otherwise: anthropology of, 10; be-
Index
coming, 121, 131; endurance of, 118;
politics of, 154; propositional, 191;
radical, 130, 10; social, 5, 16, 29, 188;
sources of, 7, 99, 109, 110, 119, 128;
spacing of, 15
Pacific Solution, 149
Pakistan, 153, 177
Palestine, 40
Parasites, 116, 144, 189, 192, 203n22. See
also Static
Paris suburbs, 177
Pastoral care, 167, 185
Peirce, Charles Sanders, 2, 8788, 193n4,
201n22, 202n
People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals (PEtA), 86, 105
Performative tense, 13
Performativity, 12, 106, 176, 181
Perseverance, 11516, 119, 128; in-being,
9, 103, 188
Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act, 60
Phonos, 50, 51
Poiesis, 33
Policing, 43, 50, 52, 71, 75
Politics: cosmology and, 4950; culturalization of, 26; eventfulness and, 52,
7172, 76; of the otherwise, 154; policing and, 43, 50, 52, 75; semiosis and, 88;
theology and, 148; theory of, x, 35, 42,
82, 16869, 175
Pornography, 53, 87, 89
Postcoloniality: liberalism, xi, 6, 16;
movements, 101, 103; worlds, 79
Postmetaphysical world, 172
Postmodernism, 171
Potentia agendi, 9, 11, 15, 31, 116
Potentiality, 9, 128, 188; embodied, 106,
132; ethical substance and, 10; part
that has no part, 43, 75; sociology of,
1416
233
234
Index
Recognition (continued)
politics of, 23, 4243, 50, 54, 75, 7778,
97, 115, 129, 165; trembling of, 7980,
8384, 8689, 9192
Reconciliation, cultural, 23, 48
Recycling, 122, 124, 129
Redemption, 4, 99, 167, 176, 179, 184
Referentiality, 176, 180
Regulatory regimes, 90, 105
Religion: conviction and, 16970; expression and, 43, 6264, 6667; minorities
and, 6667; progressive, 166, 186
Religious Freedom Restoration Act
(1993), 6370
Rhetoric, 28, 44, 50, 88, 14849, 16566,
18081, 184
Risk, 81, 127, 154, 160; individual, 155,
15758; individualized, 166; individuated, 157, 183; privatized, 15758, 183;
security, 22, 29
Roberts, John, 64, 6667, 7071, 9697
Sacred sites, 90
Sacrifice, 32, 163, 174, 183; sacrificial love,
xi, 3, 5, 1213, 4445, 16473, 17577,
17982, 18486
San Salvador, 185
Sarkozy, Nicolas, 28, 93
Schmitt, Carl, 148, 168, 174, 208n14
SCum Manifesto, 191
Secular democracies, 168, 170
Secularism, 92; politics of, 165, 16869;
public reason and, 169, 178; in public
sphere, 16970, 176, 178
Semantics, 81, 82, 86, 88
Semiosis, 88
Sen, Amartya, 24
Sense: common-, 31, 138, 179; deliberative, 89, 91, 100; ethical, 143, 162, 174;
moral, 1, 13, 8689, 91, 100
Serres, Michel, 30, 11617, 119, 137, 203n22,
204n25, 205n5, 209n2
Index
x, xi, 3, 5, 1011, 1516, 2932, 34, 40,
4243, 79, 101, 1067, 110, 112, 120, 125,
13032, 134, 165, 192; metaphysics of,
1068. See also Materiality
Sutton, Peter, 2, 4749, 5961, 73, 76,
198nn35
Taylor, Charles, 7, 178, 193n12, 208n30,
209n5
Teleology, 1213
Tense, x, 26, 30, 37, 42, 93, 99, 179, 192;
alternative ethical, 3; being and, 11, 44,
167; civilizational, 27, 40; durative, 3,
12, 32, 49, 78, 83, 96, 98, 130; durative
present, 2, 3, 12, 58; ethical, 3; future
anterior, 2, 3, 5, 12, 13, 28, 36, 44, 77,
96, 158; future perfect, 167, 168; imperfect, 3; past perfect, 12, 13, 27, 31, 36, 40,
49, 50, 77, 96; power and, xi, 39, 51, 62,
75; present, 11, 12, 44, 178, 184; present
perfect, 167, 172; social, 3, 11, 13, 29, 31,
34, 4041, 43, 5052, 62, 7273, 75, 77,
165, 167; subjunctive, 31
Terra nullius, 39
Terror, 18, 34, 80, 83, 93
Terrorism, 64, 95, 97, 151; domestic, 125,
152; homegrown, 12526; laws against,
94, 125, 14647; as spectacle, 146
Thailand, 186
Thick description, x
Tolerance, 85, 95, 97; lack of, 43, 75, 76,
7981, 8384, 92, 177
Tracings, 192
Trade unions, 17, 105, 156
Tradition: belief and, 48, 111, 117; culture
and, 130, 140; custom and, 43, 51, 73;
effect of, 40, 140; land and, 14041;
law and, 4960; life and, 143; marriage
and, 59; narratives and, 112
Traditional owners, 61, 140
Translation, 8182
Travail ethique, 11, 15, 106, 110
235
236
Index
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 154, 156, 201n7,
206n27
Worlds: actual, 19, 42, 50, 72, 79, 103, 138,
158, 188, 191; alternative social, ix, 5, 7,
10, 44, 52, 7677, 79, 89, 154, 165; postmetaphysical, 172