The Logos Structure of The World
The Logos Structure of The World
The Logos Structure of The World
Reality
6. The Development
7.
of
I-Consciousness
Self-Sensing
Meditation
10. Perceptual
Meditation
Epilogue
Bibliographical
References
Translator's
Foreword
1. Becoming Aware of the Logos (West Stockbridge, MA: Lindisfarne Press. 1985).
2. Der Sprechende Mensch (Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann, 1992).
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
Foreword
10
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
Foreword
11
What was an intuitive leap for Goethe can become a systematic unfolding of our faculties. In the same way as a book
would not make sense if paper and ink were only chemically
identified, while the forms of the letters were analyzed in
terms of analytic geometry, so, too, the elements of nature are
integrated not only into systemic ecological cycles but also as
an organism whose existence utters its own sense. This corresponds to the inner understanding that makes a word into
meaning. Thus the phenomena of nature are considered both
"meaning"meaning
is
established
between
(The
two
12
FRIEDEMANN-ECKART SCHWARZKOPF
Introduction
* Georg Khlewind, The Life of the Soul (Hudson, N.Y.: Lindisfarne Press, 1990) [Das
I.then der Seele, 1982]; Die Wahrheit Tun ("Doing the Truth"). 1978; Die Diener des
Logos ("Servants of the Logos"), 1981; Das Licht des Wortes ("Light of the Word"),
1984, all published by Verlag Freies Geistesleben in Stuttgart, Germany.
14
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF MM W<>KM>
Introduction
15
16
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OE THE W O R L D
The word is the form of the idea through which t lie re appears the words relation to an I. The life span of the word in a
human being leads from the given language (and the thinking
bound to it), through abstract thinking independent of language, to meditative thinking, which is also independent of
language. Meditative thinking seeks to understand words in
Introduction
17
their primal or original meaning and remain within that understanding, or even pass beyond it. In the process, a "thinking"
develops that is adequate to the ideas of natural phenomena.
The completion, and ultimately the redemption, of the given
text of nature begins in perceptual meditation.
Meditation is the continuation of creation as it is given. If
language initially structures creation into components, then in
perceptual meditation we read creation together again
through the accessibility of the higher word-nature. And
thereby the world receives meaning, like a text.
For the attentive observer the world will appear, in every
phase of cognitive life, to be structured by the word, or Logos.
Only an I-being has a "world." And I-beings have a world only
because the world has the nature and structure of the word, the
Logos, which in turn is accessible only to I-beings. In the first
epoch of consciousness, that of simplicity, the world is given
to human beings as reality. Percept and concept are given
together; they are separated only in a later configuration of
consciousness. Therefore in this first epoch the reality structured by the concepts provided by language is also given as a
unified whole. In the second phase of consciousnesswhich
ultimately leads to the emancipation of thinking from languagethe given world is structured by concepts grasped by
human beings. Generally, these are abstract concepts, like
those of the natural sciences, or they may be higher, meditative
ideas. In any case, in this second reality perceiving and thinking are strictly separated; and their synthesis is no longer given
but is performed by the human being. Thus, this second reality
is also structured by the Logos; it is structured and unified
through concepts.
This applies also to the third, potential development of consciousness, in which human beings realize the language character of the world through their own free deeds. The language
18
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OE THE W O R L D
Prelude
Every theory and every science begin with questions. Questions arise when we look at something twice because we were
not satisfied with the first view of what we saw. That is, the
existence of questions presumes two different glances, two
separate views, the second of which is conscious and deliberate. These two different views necessarily originate in two different possibilities of the seeing consciousness, which can be
at home on two different planes.
The first view or picture of reality is given to us, and it is
already a picture at that moment, not a reality, as is often
supposed. Reality is the last secret and can be attained only
through conscious questioning. The first picture is given
through the soul's superconscious and subconscious structure.
It is filtered, dulled, and immobilized because of the necessary
dependence of the cognizing principle in human beings on the
physical organism. As a result, only a part of the totality of the
world reaches conscious experience. Since our questions and
answers also become a part of reality, reality is not finished or
fixed: it blossoms within, and through, the human being.
Our questions concern the given picture, the first view. Epistemology deals with the question of how this "given" arises.
The sciences deal with the question of how to complete, correct, and understand the given picture. And the philosophy of
science deals with the question of how science is possible.
/. The Questions
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OE THE W O R L D
2 . The Given
Reflection on
Consciousness
When we begin to reflect on consciousness, we discover its processes, as well as their resultswe find thinking, perceiving,
speaking, as well as concepts, percepts, words. We can notice
that these processes and contents already existed, or arose, prior
to reflection. Even the ability to reflect is given, though the act
of reflection itself is a free deed. Were this deed also given and
not free, the given as such could not be discovered.
1. Rudolf Steiner, An Outline of Occult Science (GA 13) (Hudson, N.Y.: Anthroposophie Press, 1989), chapter ' T h e Nature of Humanity."
2. Rudolf Steiner, Metamorphoses of the Soul, vol. 1 (GA 59) (London: Rudolf Steiner
Press, 1983), lecture of October 28, 1909.
24
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
The discovery that the human faculties are given and that
we did not produce them by ourselves can call forth wonder,
gratitude, and joy in usjoy in the existence of consciousness,
in the ability to turn attention to any theme we choose, joy in
this autonomy. This joy, which is kindled by the above experience and not by the mental picture of it, is the soul's best starting point for a schooling of consciousness.
Epistemologieal
This means that the given image of the outer and inner
world changes in the course of our life according to our circumstances; therefore, too, it can vary from individual to
individual.
4
3. Rudolf Steiner, A Theory of Knowledge (GA 2, p. 27 ff) (Hudson, N.Y.: Anthroposophie Press, 1978), pp. 14,15.
4. See Steiner, Truth and Knowledge (GA 3, p.47ff) (Blauvelt, N.Y.: Rudolf Steiner
Publications. 1981), pp. 53,54.
5. See Steiner, A Theory of Knowledge (GA 2, p. 241), p. 16; and Anthroposophie: Ein
Fragment ("Anthroposophy: A Fragment") (GA 45) (Drnach, Switzerland: Rudolf
Steiner Verlag, 1980), chapter 2.
The
25
Given
The same is true for sensory qualities. The high conceptuall y corresponding to sensory qualities, which surpasses the
concepts of objects in scope and vitality, is "formed" in childhood through superconscious intuitions. When a child begins
to distinguish colors, no change occurs in the physical organization of its eyes; rather, the child grasps the idea of color
itself, or of individual colors.
We can also reflect on the contents of consciousness as
such, regardless of their potential reference to the perceptual
world. We find memory pictures (representations), fantasy
images, words, sentences, thoughts, emotions, wishes, and so
on. If current thinking ceases, this world, too, is a conglomeration of unconnected details.
The distinction between what is given and what we actually
cognize may be made in different ways. When one articulates
a theory of knowledge (an epistemology), one must examine
the origin and development of the adult's given image of the
world and conceive the idea of the given quite radically. This
means artificially removingin a thought experimentthe
6. See Steiner, A Theory cf Knowledge (GA2, pp. 30-32), pp. 17-19; and The Philosophy
of Freedom (GA 4, pp. 60, 89, 94, 137) (Hudson, N.Y.: Anthroposophie Press, 1986),
pp. 50, 78, 83,84, 125.
26
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
10
The
Given
27
processes by which the given is given is superconscious. In earlier epochs of the evolution of consciousness human beings
actually experienced this giving, and today children still experience it when learning to speak.
Since the "first form" of reality enters consciousness already
finished as we become aware of it, we can almost experience
we may call it a "boundary experience"that the processes that
"give" this reality occur superconsciously. After all, for there to
be "finished" results, processes must have occurred first. We do
not know how we speak, nor how sounds are formed, nor how
the grammar and syntax of our mother tonguenever fully
described or describableare acquired in early childhood; nor
do we know how a perception comes about.
Even thinking is to be found within the g i v e n , even though
it is the activity in which we participate most consciously
because we ourselves produce it. Thinking does not appear
without our active participation. Yet it is in no way arbitrary or
subjective: it has its own inherent lawfulness, its own nature,
which is manifest in its how, its logic. Thus thinking is not only
formally given, but how it proceeds, its lawfulness, is produced superconsciously. Its rules are not consciously formulated and they can never be exhaustively described. In this
11
11
28
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OE THE W O R L D
All these activities, including mental picturing (representation), are actually faculties for doing something without knowing how to do it. This ability enables us to initiate processes in
consciousness, although we are not conscious of the processes
but only of their results. This is similar to our voluntary body
movements: we set the body in motion with our will and chart
the course of its movement in a mental image. Then we perceive the result, but we do not consciously follow the act of the
movement in its "how."
Such human faculties are given from "above," from the
spiritual plane, and they intervene in the living and sentient
body to express and articulate themselves in it. The way these
faculties are given to us changes in the course of the development of the individual and of humanity as a whole (see chapter
8). It is characteristic of contemporary adults that the connection between consciousness and its superconscious sources is
interrupted by an abyss or gap that divides the plane of the past
from that of the p r e s e n t .
14
Consciousness
Each of the three basic functions of consciousnessperceiving, thinking, and speaking (which are the basis also of other
human faculties)has a distinct character and is experienced
differently by adults today. Perception, for instance, poses
many riddles. The disjointed particulars of perception immediately provoke questions; they are not at all transparent or comprehensible to contemporary perceiving.
The difference in the "givenness" of perceiving and thinking lies not only in that perceiving is mediated through the
14. See Kiihlewind, Das Licht des Wortes, chapter 1.
The
29
Given
senses while new concepts, new thoughts, appear in consciousness through intuition; much more significant is the fact
that thoughts and concepts are only wholly comprehensible
and transparent to us when they are really thought. Though we
can certainly say things we do not understand, we cannot possibly think anything we do not understand thoroughly. Nothing
remains hidden in the finished thought; so there is nothing
more to search for in it once it has been t h o u g h t .
15
30
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
The Given
31
yet any other concepts besides the ones language gives, and
they structure the world. In this state of innocence, questions
cannot yet be asked.
In general, questionsand with questions, scienceare
possible only after thinking has emancipated itself from its
teacher, namely, language. This emancipation takes place in the
epoch of the consciousness soul. In earlier times, the pursuit of
32
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
science was the privilege of a few chosen individuals, precursors of our age, who partially exemplified and foreshadowed
the structure of the consciousness s o u l .
With the exception of this elite, who anticipated later developmental stages, everything was still given to people at this
earlier stage in the evolution of consciousness.Today the world
is given to us in a different way. In the more dreamlike phase
of consciousness, people experienced as given even the cognitive processes that have now moved into the realm of the
superconscious. The given we are conscious of today is on the
plane of finished thoughts, finished perceptions; that is, on the
plane of the past. In earlier times, this plane was considered to
be merely the final point of the experienced, given world.
Nowadays, however, impulses from the subconscious, all of
which are destructive for our soul life, have joined these finished thoughts and perceptions. This is the field that psychology deals with (see chapter 8 ) .
16
Regarding
Concepts
16. Rudolf Steiner, "The Human Soul and the Evolution of the World," lecture 5 (ms.
translation), (GA 212, lecture of May 7, 1922).
The
Given
33
The second discovery reveals the distinction between concept and word. For adults the line separating them is sharp and
34
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
The Given
35
36
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
means that the appearance of the plant fits with what we know
to be characteristic of columbines. Nevertheless, we see or
perceive phenomena only because we have concepts; we comprehend the outer characteristics and qualities of the plant
such as the color, form, size, number of stamensconceptually. These concepts stand in, so to speak, for the natural phenomenon's concepts and thus allow us to categorize and
identify it. Still, they are merely substitute concepts and not
the functional or creative ideas that correspond to, and are, the
essence of the phenomenon.
Since the external characteristics of natural phenomena are
so clearly "super-ficial" ["above the surface"], our understanding of concepts has become falsified. We have forgotten that
concepts above all, and in their essence, consist of understanding. Therefore we seek the essential of the concept in the
direction of abstraction. The "essential" and " c o m m o n " properties and characteristics of the objects of perception are
derived from the individual object through abstraction. However, abstraction presupposes knowledge of the concept. To
determine the "essential and c o m m o n " characteristics and
thereby to define or limit the individual objects under considerationin other words, to "select" them outrequires a
norm. This norm is the c o n c e p t .
18
This abstraction model of concepts emphasizes their generality, in contrast to the particular individual object of perception. Whereas the universals of scholasticismwhich are
ideas based on understandingcould express themselves in
particulars as universalia in re, the abstract concept, on the
other hand, can hardly, if at all, be seen in the individual
object; nor can it help us to grasp individual details. For exam-
is. See Steiner, A Theory of Knowledge (GA 2), chapter 10 entitled "The Inner Nature
of Thinking."
The Given
37
38
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
The
Given
39
40
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
Even though only what is conceptual can enter thinking consciousness, this same consciousnessin flagrant self-contradictionspeaks of the existence of nonconceptual, idea-less
things. Nonconceptual things were first "discovered" in the
realm of sensory perception; later they were transferred to a
"transcendental" cosmic realm, beyond the reach of thinking
consciousness. What resulted were inherently self-contradictory
constructs of thoughtno one ever actually saw a "thing-initself" or the "subconscious"which would also have to be
tested by thought. This contradiction, testing nonideal constructs through thinking, already contains its own verdict.
Let us now look more closely at the field of sense perception.
We can perceive because of our given senses. These consist
of a sense organwhich can be more or less localized in the
organismand an organization of consciousness, which is
teachable and without which the sense organ does not function.
Consciousness contributes the conceptual part to sense perceptionboth in a child's perception of color, for instance, and in
the givenness of particulars or individual objects of sensation.
Without this contributionas we saw when we artificially
removed all concepts in a thought experimentthere remains
only an unstructured continuum.
As adults, we receive from the sensesas raw material for
thinkinga picture consisting of particulars. This picture is
already structured conceptually before any current thinking
activity begins. In fact, we can observe that when adults perceive something with which they are sufficiently
familiar,
they "simply and immediately" recognize it for what it i s
for example, as table or pencilwithout thought or memory.
However, if, for example, we do not know the functional
concept "table," and do not develop it on the basis of perception, we do not see a table but only a smooth wooden surface
The
Given
41
19. See Steiner. Anthroposophie: Ein Fragment. (GA 45. chapter 6).
20. Ibid.. (GA 45, pp. 35ft. chapter 2 and Theory of Knowledge, (GA 2, chapter 7).
42
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
The Given
43
44
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E : OE THE: W O R L D
The
Given
45
46
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OE THE: W O R L D
22
22. Rudolf Steiner, lecture of May 26. 1922 (GA 212). available as TheJiuman Heart
(Spring Valley, N.Y.: Mercury Press, 1985); (GA 2 IS. lecture of November 19, 1922);
and A Modern Art of Education (GA 307) ( H u d s o n , N.Y.: Anthropospphic Press,
1972), lecture of August 10, 1923.
48
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
If we were to strip our given picture of the world of all concepts, this would leave only an unstructured c o n t i n u u m ,
which could no longer be called experience. *
At the same time, however, the separation of subject and
object would disappear. The term "subject" here refers
merely to the place of the experience; both thinking and perceiving provide the subject with something universal and
intersubjective. To deny this with regard to thinking would be
naive and self-contradictory. Even perception is only subjective in that different individuals' different and unique points
of view in relation to the objecttheir different sensory
capacities, sets of concepts, and differing abilities to conceptualizeinfluence the given picture. Nevertheless, there can
be no doubt that we live in a shared perceptual world. Indeed,
we cannot even discuss this doubt because such a discussion
and its subject matter presuppose a shared perceptual world.
By the same token, however, we cannot tell with absolute certainty whether the sensory qualities we perceivefor example, the colors we seeare exactly the same as everyone else
perceives.
24
24.
25.
26.
pp.
of the Given
49
object
in such a way that we consider our inner lifeof
thinking, feeling, and willingas part of the subject and the
perceptual world as part of the o b j e c t . The distinction is, of
course, not exact, but it will do for the purpose of our discussion here.
28
Our inner world is likewise similarly structured in its givenness. Naturally, then, we have to wonder how this preexisting
structure, without which we would not experience anything
consciously, arose. We have to ask, too, what our own human
"organization" signifies and what its purpose is.
27. See Steiner, Philosophy of Freedom (GA 4, pp. 88, 112, 247), pp. 77, 100, 235;
(GA 78, lecture of August 29, 1921), summarized in Fruits of Anthroposophy (London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1986), pp.7-8.
28. Ibid., (GA 4, pp. 125, 126, 132), pp. 114, 115, 119.
50
i M I LOGOS S I K I K I U K I ; OF THE W O R L D
our sensory activity and therefore of a nonconceptual character. But this view would have to assume a present mental picturing, judgment, or memory of each time we perceive a
thingwhich clearly contradicts our observation that when we
see familiar objects, they are already conceptually defined.
0
of the Given
51
I MI I iMiuN S u n n
it K! 01
un
WORLD
ii..i Dill) i.\ ih< |..|, M l.uiguage hul also by the expressive,
" |m . i k 111 r behavioi oi the adult environment, behind which
lies the adults ability to speak and to grasp the world and situations conceptually. Except for a few exceptional situations,
human beings continuously communicate through gestures,
mimicry, looks, and movements.
Behind audible, spoken language and "speaking" behavior
lies hidden the powerful concealed aspect of language,
namely, the speech intention. Without this speech intention,
which corresponds to the listener's understanding, speech
does not normally happen. When a child learns to speak, this
"immaterial" reality (understanding) {^directly accessible. If it
were not, the child could not understand what was heard.
Language is unique in that it is not just perception but meaningful perception. Children must grasp both perception and meaning at the same time. This is the source of the consciousness
functions of perceiving and thinking, which are later separated.
1
of the
Given
53
I III
Loons
S I K l K I I ) RE O F THE W O R L D
IIM .is
55
attainable for all people and that will make connections possible
that are valid and identical for everyone.
The basis of human freedom is the activity of reading
between two givensperceptions and conceptsbecause the
activity by which these two are "read together" is not given.
Consequently, for the cognizing subject, freedom exists only
in new cognitions, for what we have already cognized and
understood must be considered part of the given.
1111
l o o o s N I K i K ruRE
OF THE W O R L D
of the
Given
only concepts we know are those our language gives us. The
systems of speaking and thinking are one and the same; in
Humboldt's words, we are in the "energetic" phase of language development. In this phase languages do not simply
label something that already exists; rather they demarcate and
define the "somethings." Concepts indicate where "something" ends, where its boundary is, for "in the given there actually are no discrete entities, but everything is in continuous
c o n n e c t i o n . " This statement obviously refers to the "directly
given."
The epoch or stage of consciousness described above may
also be called the epoch of the magic word. On the one hand,
there was no separation or distinction between word, concept,
and "thing;" on the other, people still experienced the word in
its living occurrence, in its "arriving"and not only in its
immobilized and finished form on the consciousness level of
the past. Communication between I-beings through speech or
speech-song was then an immediate and spiritual interaction.
For instance, in the Kalevala (Song III), the battle between
Vajnemojnen and Joukahajnen, a direct test of the power of
the I, is fought through singing. The weaker of the two must
yield to the power of the words of the stronger; they force him
into the course of events they foretell or dictate.
30
%K
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
of the
Given
59
31. Rudolf Steiner has repeatedly alluded to this; see, for example, his Philosophy of
Freedom (GA 4), chapter 7.
60
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
lhe
62
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
The Language
of Reality
63
unci become one. We do not know whether this was the case
lor people in archaic times, because they had neither the
concept of "reality" nor that of "truth." They lived in the true
reality without looking for it or questioning it. People question and search for true reality only when they have lost it.
People in those early times did not need a synthesis of percept
and concept because for them they were still united. We, however, experience them as given separately. (The story of how
iliis true reality was lost will follow later.)
Today the above-mentioned two feelingsthe sensation of
reality and the experience of evidencedetermine what is true
;md real. Nevertheless, it is conceivable that thinking and perceiving could come together in a human, conscious synthesis
and form a true or full reality.
The two feelings would then interpenetrate, and the feeling
for reality would be illuminedwhich it usually is not
while the feeling of evidence would no longer remain abstract
but be filled with warmth and life and become a concrete perception. In other words, full reality would emerge from the
interpntration of a perception and itsadequateconcept.
Then no questions would remain, and the desire for knowledge
would be satisfied. Without this interpntration of percept and
concept, the given remains questionable; that is, it needs to be
completed. With regard to the reality we perceive, neither the
given percept nor the concept by itself constitutes the full reality. Neither the original union of these two elements in archaic
consciousnesswhere the concepts of language structure the
perceptual worldnor their new synthesis is additive. Rather,
both the concept and the perceptual element undergo a qualitative change when they interpenetratesomething we can
experience daily, if we pay attention.
12. See Steiner, Truth and Knowledge (GA 3), Preface, and The Philosophy of Freedom (GA 4), chapter entitled "The Consequences of Monism."
64
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
The Language
of Reality
65
66
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
The Language
of Reality
67
68
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
34
35
33. See Steiner, Truth and Knowledge (GA 3), chapter 5, pp. 69, 70.
34. See Steiner, The Philosophy of Freedom (GA 4), chapter 5, pp.76, 80.
35. Rudolf Steiner, (GA 212, lectures of May 27 and June 17, 1922).
69
70
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OE T H E W O R L D
71
72
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
73
36. See also Steiner. Die geistige Vereinigung der Menschheit durch den ChristusImpuls (GA 165) (Dornach. Switzerland: Rudolf Steiner Verlag. 1981). lecture of January 15,1916.
*"Universals" before their embodiment in matter. Translator's note.
**"Universals," understood after being experienced in their embodied reality. Translator's note.
"Universalia in re" "universals" as the functional idea according to which a thing
is given its conceptual definition while it is in use. Translator's note.
74
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
The Language
of Reality
75
76
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
38. See Steiner, A Theory of Knowledge (GA 2, pp. 136-137). pp. 120-121; Truth
and Knowledge (GA 3, p. 11), p.l 1 and The Fruits of Anthroposophy (GA 78, pp.
27, 3 1 , 32), (Hudson, N.Y.: Anthroposophie Press, 1986), lecture of August 30,
1921, summarized pp. 8-1).
The Language
of Reality
77
78
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
79
80
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
what we mean by "nature." What we call "nature" at a particular point in our development both as species and as individuals
is already a particular picture, and we have participated, either
consciously or unconsciously, in its creation. This is true both
for the given perceptual picture and for the second, conscious
cognitive understanding. Everything we speak about is always
a picture that already contains our activity. To claim that, in
this sense, nature has always existed would be naive; this
would imply that if people like us had faced the given reality
of nature before we did, they would have seen the same picture
of nature that we do, or at least a qualitatively similar one.
Seen as a text, however, nature is a letter we did not write
it would not be a riddle to us if we had written itnor is it
being written now, at this momentthe natural sciences would
not be possible if it were. A text is always an interpreted text;
it means what its reader understands. We are or could be readers of the letter that is nature. Our understanding is a reality,
one that previously did not exist. For the moment, however, it
is not yet clear whether nature is a text at all.
The givennature, perceiving, thinking, attention, and so
onis given, without any present contribution on our part.
This is the meaning of the term "given" in principle, in its
extreme form, beyond any epistemology, i.e., without any
structuring of the given. As soon as we have a mental picture
of it, however, the given is structured; this is the stage of particulars. Neither this structure nor the picture of the given exist
apart from us. After all, even human beings in their "givenn e s s " are not their own creations. We only become our own
creations; we become what we cognize ourselves to be (not
what we imagine or fancy).
Thus, everything we speak or think about or we ask questions about is already a mental picture, a k n o w n element, a
The Language
of Reality
81
82
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
The Language
of Reality
83
40
39. Rudolf Steiner, Goethean Science (GA I) (Spring Valley, N.Y.: Mercury Press.
1988), previously translated as Goethe the Scientist; A Theory of Knowledge (GA 2);
Truth and Knowledge (GA 3); The Philosophy of Freedom (GA 4); Goethe's World
View (GA 6) (Spring Valley, N.Y.: Mercury Press, 1985).
40. Rudolf Steiner. A Road to Self-Knowledge (GA 16) (London: Rudolf Steiner
Press. 1975); The Riddle of Man (GA 20) (Spring Valley. N.Y.: Mercury Press. 1990);
The Case for Anthroposophy (GA 21) (London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1970); AnthroposophicalLeading Thoughts (GA 26) (London: Rudolf Steiner Press. 1973).
The Sensation of
RealityObservations
85
every perception as a representational mental picture. Compared with perceptions, mental pictures do not appear real;
they are definitely phenomena of consciousness. Perceptions,
however, appear to be really there, to be real.
Moreover, we can remember or mentally picture a landscape at any time, but we can see it only in the present moment
and when it is present with us. Our mental pictures and our
thinking, then, are independent of all external, that is, of all
perceptual, factors. Perception, however, does not depend only
on us. Therefore the phenomenon of perception has on the one
hand the character of the presentin the incomprehensible
pastand on the other hand the character of the pastin its
conceptuality.
Perception always shows us something "more," and this is
precisely what seems to be its nonconceptual part. This may be
an illusion, however, because the element which we experience is just the aspect which we do not conceive conceptually:
namely, the difference between the percept and the mental picture. This incomprehensibility does not necessarily imply that
what we do not grasp is actually nonconceptual. To j u m p to
that conclusion has led us from nominalism to materialism,
which is convinced that only the nonideal or nonconceptual
exists and is "real." Instead, we can attribute the incomprehensibility of the percept to the inability of our modern consciousness to grasp living, sentient, and willingin short, higher
concepts. The concepts we can understand, and also our memory pictures, belong to the plane of the past, and that is why
they do not evoke the feeling of reality in us.
2. To experience something as re^l it must be present in
space and time. The temporal present, a point between future
and past, is difficult to understand. Spatial presence is also not
easy to understand; for instance, we need only ask how far
86
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OE THE W O R L D
41. Massimo Scaligero. Segreti del Tempo e del Spazio (Rome: Tilopa, 1964).
The Character
of Perceptual Reality
87
88
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
The Character
of Perceptual Reality
89
remains on the plane of the past until the next act of understanding. When we perceive something, however, this inner
pendulum or oscillation between the planes continues for as
long as we are perceiving attentively. In perception, we can
experience the phase of surrender to what we perceive more
intensely and not only momentarilyand also experience the
definite return of consciousness to itself. This return coincides
with the conceptual assimilation of what we experienced while
being given over to perception.
These two phases of the activity of consciousness also differ in their degree of wakefulness or self-consciousness. In the
phase of being given over to perception, self-awareness is
asleep; it awakens only in the second phase. Except for special
cases, such as artistic perceptions, or those carried out as a
consciousness exercise, the two phases alternate very quickly
into one another. Still, we can see that the first phase of being
given over to our perception is akin to inhalationas in astonishmentwhile understanding, the second phase, is related to
exhalationas in naming t h i n g s .
44
44. See Steiner, A Road to Self-Knowledge (GA 16), chapter 1; Study of Man (GA
293) (London: Rudolf Steiner Press. 1966). lecture of August 29, 1919: The Philosophy of Freedom (GA 4), chapters 4 and 6 and Appendix of 1918.
90
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
6. Further comparisons reveal that, in thinking, we are dealing only with our own attention', it is all that is required for
effective thinking. Perception, however, requires the activity
of a sense organ in addition to our attention. Usually, people
consider only the sense organ, even though it is a fundamental
insight for a theory of sensory perception thatas we all
notice frequentlyeven if our sense organs are receptive, we
do not perceive anything unless our attention is "there" also.
Even though all the necessary physical and physiological processes are taking place in the sense organs and in the part of
the nervous system connected to them, there is still no perception without attention. These processes may be necessary for
perception, but they are not sufficient in themselves to make it
happen.
Our thinking is also accompanied by physiological processes in the brain. The source of these processes, however, is
not in the external environment; they are activated by thinking
itself. As we have discussed in chapter 1, believing that these
processes are our thinking or its cause, would lead us merely
to an input/output system. This raises the question of the origin
of the input; that is, we would have to ask what initiates and
controls the physiological processes in the brain. In this brainbased model, "logic" would correspond to physiological lawfulness; in that case, we could neither speak of " l o g i c " nor of
physiological laws because both of these require a reference
point, a subject, independent of physiology.
7. The two feelings we have discussed, the feeling of evidence and the feeling of reality, cannot be proven, nor can their
content; such proof is neither possible nor necessary. Something that is self-evident to us cannot be proven any further
beyond that, and we cannot, and do not need to, prove the
existence of something our sense of reality tells us is there. In
The Character
of Perceptual
Reality
91
92
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
also incorrect. In fact, our sense of touch conveys such undifferentiated impressions that we can say it does not, by itself,
really convey anything except the point where our body
touches an object. We perceive the object's qualities, such as
its roughness, hardness, and so on, only with the help of other
senses, such as the sense of movement.
8. Perceptions are often connected with feelings. For the
most part, these feelings are "self-feeling," or "selfs e n s i n g , " and not cognitive: for example, desires, sympathies, hate, and envy. The other part is "cognitive" and feels
the "that" out there, as for example also in passive artistic
activity or in the feeling of evidence. In cognitive exercises,
too, cognitive feelings are awakened. Both of these feelings
self-feeling and cognitive feelingare "powerful" because
they do not appear on the plane of past consciousness. That is
why thoughts are powerless over the self-feeling feelings,
which appear as inevitable as percepts. Thoughts can at most
hint at what cognitive feelings convey, if they can describe it
at all.
46
93
94
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
Insofar as the sensory world and its things consist of qualities, particulars ("that") rather than of "substances"in other
words, insofar as they are configurations, "are thus," are
48. The sense of movement can be disturbed in connection with other senses, such as
the sense of balance. The sense of life can be. disrupted through artificially raising or
lowering the sensation of life; as a result, its regulative function can cease.
49. Rudolf Steiner, Die geistigen Hintergrunde der Menschlichen Geschichte (GA 170)
(Dornach, Switzerland: Rudolf Steiner Verlag, 1964), lecture of September 2, 1916;
and Karl Konig, Sinnesentwicklung mid Leibeserfahrung (Stuttgart: Verlag Freies Geistesleben, 1978).
95
idea-likewe can perceive and know them with the attention of our I-being, which is adapted and qualified to perceive
configuration, thusness, and ideas. The sense organs by themselves, on the other hand, are not capable of cognizing these,
because ideality can be cognized only by the human spirit, by
the I. Even the elements of things, the sensory qualities, are
ideal; therefore our instructed attention is obviously the vehicle for all our perceptions. The sense organs, then, have a different function, one that is indispensable for conscious
perception. After all, our attention and our sense organs have
to work together for conscious perception to come about.
The physical-physiological processes in the sense organs
correspond more or less to the physical contact in the sense of
touch.
The processes taking place in the brain when we are thinking also correspond to touch. However, these processes are set
in motion only by thinking itself. These processes taking place
in the brain mirror and, at the same time, immobilize and dull
intuitive t h i n k i n g , which thus sinks down onto the plane of
the past. The more intuitive thinking is, the fewer traces it will
leave in our physical organism and the more it will free itself
from the body.
50
50. See Steiner, The Riddle of Man (GA 20), "New Perspectives"; The Case for
Anthroposophy (GA 21), chapter 1.
96
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
(see chapter 2, "Regarding Concepts"); but it does not immobilize themin fact, they cannot be immobilized precisely
because they are higher concepts.*
These powerful concepts do not enter the plane of the past.
Yet what we have left behind remains alive and retains its
character of "presence." It meets the same destiny as that of
* See Kuhlewind, The Life of the Soul, chapter 2. See note 46.
97
98
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
51. Sec Steiner. The ( use for Anthroposopliy (GA 21). chapter 1.
The Character
of Perceptual Reality
99
100
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
phenomena of nature. These ideas are analogous to the functional ideas behind man-made objects. They are not "grasped"
or "conceived," yet enter our consciousness through the
sensesnot through the sense organsalbeit only in metamorphosed form. To gain a clearer understanding of this metamorphosis, we will briefly discuss the nature of these ideas.
When we conceive a new idea, a "clear and bright" will is
doubtlessly active in this production. The cognitive feeling of
evidence guides the intuition in our thinking. In other words,
the three soul functions of thinking, feeling, and willing form a
unity in the act of intuition, but they break apart in our mirrored
consciousness. Similarly, we can expectand observation confirms thisthat the ideas behind nature address all three human
soul functions. A firm, unchanging creational will stands behind
every natural p h e n o m e n o n , and we adapt our will to this will
of the world. "In experiencing the process [of the perception of
nature], we realize that through this reversal of our will, our
soul takes hold of a spiritual element outside itself."
54
55
54. See Steiner, The World of the Senses and the World of the Spirit (GA 134) (Spring
Valley, N.Y.: Anthroposophie Press, 1979), lecture of December 28, 1911; The Mission of the Archangel Michael (GA 194), lecture of November 30, 1919; Study of Man
(G A 293), lecture of August 23, 1919.
55. See Steiner. The Riddle of Man (GA 20). "New Perspectives."
The Character
of Perceptual Reality
101
enhance the quality on the other branch of the twofold relationship, namely, in the activity of our attention.
Ancient science investigated the hierarchy of the senses starting from the lower senses and proceeding upward. It examined
their "why," their intention, but ultimately their investigation
was aimed at the " w h o " of this intention. The impressions
transmitted by the middle senses were considered a system of
signs that one could read. Cognition was the investigation of
this speech or writing of the godsof its meaning. Cognition
dealt with ideas. During that period people knew from experience that ideas do not emerge accidentally, independently of a
person. Therefore, they spoke of the I-related idea, the word.
The world was wordlike, word-natured. Cognition, then, was a
dialogue with nature; people sensed creative beingsor at least
their representatives: nature beings, such as nature gods, mountain gods, river gods or spiritsbehind nature.
However, the above-mentioned transformation of our consciousness caused the language concepts concerning nature to
dry up into mere names. As a result, the former perceptual
world of signs turns into one of things. And as this happens,
the dialogue with nature ends because if the perceptual world
consists of things rather than ideas, then no beings stand
behind our percepts. Our investigation no longer proceeds in
an upward movement. What was formerly considered raw
material provided by the middle senses or the sense of touch
now itself becomes "the reality." It is no longer complemented
with ideasor so it seems.
In truth, however, we simply fail to notice that this "reality" is interwoven with ideas. Nevertheless, this "reality" is
endowed with the feeling of reality, which originates in the
higher, comprehending, yet dreamlike participation in the
perceptual world, an experience not accompanied by selfawareness and still part of a unified existence. The higher
102
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
The Character
of Perceptual
Reality
103
perception;* in fact, all the senses are always to some extent involved in perception although one sense definitely
predominates. For example, when we do not understand our
partner in a conversation, we hear only words, his or her
voice. In other words, the percept begins to descend the ladder of the senses. In the same way, people who cannot read
see only the black shapes of the letters on the page.
The power of the ideas of nature not only gives us the sense
of reality, but it also enables us to perceive in the first place.
These willing, sensing, and living ideas create forms of will,
sensation, and lifethat is, the mineral, animal, and plant
kingdomsand are active within them. Our attention can
57. See Steiner. Anthroposophie: Ein Fragment (GA 45). chapter 6.
58. See Steiner. The Case for Anthroposophy (GA 21), chapter 4.
104
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
unite itself with these ideas; however, we are usually conscious only of that part of an encounter that has been subdued
by its physical and physiological effects. Nowadays, our
senses function only when they are affected by the mineralphysical influence of nature and in this way assist our attention. Thus, we can describe the share of attention in perception
as follows: "Perception is the boundary where our thoughts
touch the creative thoughts o u t s i d e . "
Our ordinary thinking, which belongs to the plane of the
past, takes us to the boundary of the perceptible, which is alive
and therefore cannot be comprehended by our thinking. Perception, then, begins at the point beyond which thinking cannot penetrate into the creativearrestedcosmic thinking.
59
59. Rudolf Steiner, Foundations of Esotericism (GA 93a) (London: Rudolf Stciner
Press. 1982), lecture of October 12, 1905; and Spiritual Science as a Foundation for
Social Forms (GA 199) (Hudson, N.Y.: Anthroposophic Press. 1986), lectures of
August 8 and 14, 1920.
105
61
60. Rudolf Steiner, The Boundaries of Natural Science (GA 322) (Hudson, N.Y.:
Anthroposophie Press, 1983), lectures of October 2 and 3, 1920. See also this book,
chapter 10.
61. Rudolf Steiner, The Riddle of Humanity (GA 170) (London: Rudolf Steiner Press.
1990), lecture of August 13, 1916.
62. See Steiner, Spiritual Science as a Foundation for Social Forms, lecture of August
8, 1920.
106
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THH W O R L D
6 . The Development of
I-Consciousness
108
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
The Development
of I-Consciousnesss
109
which became inner experience because it began to be independent from the given elementschanges into the duality of
mind (intellect) and soul (or heart). At first, the soul is still
experienced as a perceptive cloud of feeling that inspires the
intellect. However, in the age of the consciousness soul the living, unreflecting mind subdivides into two planes of consciousness, that of the pastwith its clear outlines, on which
we moderns mostly "live" and of which we are conscious
and that of the present, which we can also call the imaginative
plane, which has nowadays shifted into the superconscious
realm. Every understanding and every intuition comes from
this plane of the present like a flash of grace. This plane is also
the source of the superconscious " h o w " of our thinking, and
every intuition, every new idea, is actually a condensation of
this "how."
Along with the separation of mind into past and present, the
soul or heartnot today's soul, but the cognizing soulalso
subdivides: into cognitive feeling and self-sensing feeling.
Cognitive feeling lives above the plane of the present; selfsensing feeling belongs to the plane of the past and is part of
the subconscious of the modern soul. Therefore it is aware of
itselfrather than of something out therein emotions such
as envy, ambition, and so on.
Since the plane of the present has now moved into the
superconscious realm, a change from one plane to the other
makes discontinuities possible, even when we are fully awake
and conscious. To remain conscious, our consciousness must
at least briefly touch the level of the present repeatedly. If it
remained continually on the level of the past, our consciousness would no longer be "conscious." This is how the structure
and capacity typical of the consciousness soul develop:
namely its ability to reflect upon itself, to look from the plane
of the present onto that of the past, and to experienceat the
110
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
7.
Self-Sensing
112
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
Self-Sen.si tig
113
and to think with such unparalleled ease. This is also the reason why adults no longer have this wonderful ability. In part,
indeed for the most part, the above-mentioned forces are transformed, in adults, into self-sensing ones, and the attention is
split and divided between world and egoity.
Self-sensing is possible only for I-beings. The sensations of
animals are completely preformed and serve only their biological life. Animals have no freedom in sensationthey can
only react. Thus, they cannot distinguish between sensation
caused by inner sources and those caused by outer sources.
Always, their whole sensitivity reacts and is active. There is no
uninvolved, free entity that could be aware of or experience
such reactions. Therefore, we find egoity only in I-beings. The
ego is the reflected, self-sensing form of the I; it is self-sensing
instead of self-aware.
63
Similarly, before the soul separated into cognitive and selfsensing feelings, the experience of evidence in the field of religion was given to people in the form of "faith." Our experience of evidence in mathematics or logic is a vestige of this.
64. See Khlewind, Das Licht des Wortes, chapter entitled "Das Leben der Bewusstseinsseele."
Changes
in the Given
115
116
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
Thus, what is given to us from above, from the superconscious, is joined by what is "given" from below, from the
subconscious. Indeed, what is given from the subconscious
now plays a leading role in human life and has become a world
power. Human beings now live by secondary instincts and
passions, originating in the subconscious. Our thinking could
help us orient ourselves, but it has been influenced by what
comes out of the subconscious and now accepts and spreads
so-called insights and new dogmas as knowledge. As a result,
the inclinations, habits, and addictions originating in our subconscious gain scientific justification.
We do not learn to speak and think "by nature" but by education and the imitation of models. Similarly, everything in
human development, the good and the bad, comes about
through education. For example, certain individuals, our forerunners in the history of thoughtinspired by powers
unknown to themdeveloped trains of thought that then elaborated and coached our collective subconscious impulses.
All inspirations and thoughts that are prompted by our collective subconscious share two characteristic features: they
cannot be thought through logicallythat is, thinking can
penetrate them only up to a certain limitand they give the
sensation of an overwhelming persuasive power that covers
up the fact that we cannot really think them through. We have
good reason to assume a subconscious origin for every
impenetrable, incomprehensible thought, or train of thought.
The whole sphere of egoity is connected to the subconscious.
People do not decide to become egoists; it happens without
our will.
This twofold change in the giventhe shift of both the process of thinking and cognitive feeling into the superconscious
and the arising of the subconsciousadmonishes us to change
our attitude and behavior toward it. Only a free being, or one
117
118
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
Changes
in the Given
119
I
I
I
I
120
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE OF THE W O R L D
or a textoffers an opportunity for our attention to become distracted from our consciously chosen subject. We can direct our
attention to anything we choose; however, as we know from
experience, it is difficult to keep our attention focused on an
uninteresting and unappealing theme. Associations influencing
us from the subconscious realm of the soul distract us against
our conscious will and our conscious intention.
The discontinuous form of attention in thinking, representing, and perceiving makes it possible for these activities to proceed step by step in understanding, thereby freeing these
functions from the necessity of understanding immediately and
intuitively. At the same time, this discontinuous form offers our
subconscious impulses the opportunity to intervene in the flow
of the attention we have consciously directed in a particular
way. This in turn restricts the autonomy of our consciousness
in controlling and maintaining our attention.
At first, attention cannot experience and meet itself in its
discontinuous form; it cannot meet itself (see chapter 6)
because it is constantly interrupted. Our attention is continuously falling out of its present and leaves its traces as a past
for example, in finished thoughts, percepts, mental representations. This development was necessary for the sake of the
growth of I-consciousness.
Once we have learned discontinuous, conceptual thinking
and have become able to synthesize, and once this has brought
us to the structure of the consciousness soul, we can continue
the further development of consciousness through conscious
schooling. For, by this time, because of the structure of the
consciousness soul, we no longer receive anything positive
from the given without effort on our part. Our first goal has to
be to strengthen the autonomy of our consciousness, that is,
to strengthen our attention, a considerable part of which is
caught in subconscious formations and habits.
Changes
in the Given
121
122
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
science.
Nevertheless, another experience precedes it, namely, the
insight that our thinking and representing attention is a more
powerful reality than the thought or pictured theme because
the latter is brought forth or maintained by this attention.
While attention cannot experience its own discontinuity
because it is continuously falling out of the reality of the timeless present into the unreality of the past, it can nevertheless
develop toward continuity by exercising. The less attention is
interruptedthe less discontinuous it isthe more alive and
present it becomes and the closer it moves toward the experience of evidence and of itself. Evidence is the property of reality; in other words, reality is self-evident. This points to the
one and common source for realityits effective causeand
the cognition of it. Reality actuates the cognition of itself. But
in the process of cognition, "reality" becomes reality (see
chapter 4). Cognizing and cognized reality coincide and
become one; they are one in our experience of them in the
immediate present: they are this experience.
68. Ibid., chapter entitled "The Fundamental Experience of the Spirit."
123
124
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
Changes
in the Given
125
specimens. That is, "oak" then was not a " n a m e " (as it now is
for us) but a character, a function, a meaningful designation of
a relationship and connection. For us the "oak" remains external; we find it "thinkable" not in itself but only on account of
its outer characteristics. In fact, we think of the oakin contrast to the ideas and functions of man-made objects or mathematical conceptsonly nominalistically.
Formerly, natural phenomena were seen and understood not
as things but primarily as relations. That is, they were understood more as a continuity. Nowadays, however, we perceive
particulars, individual things, as the primary given. Then we
try to find the connections between them in the sphere of
mechanics, rather than reading them on the model of language, of linguistic and textual interconnections, as people in
ancient times did. If we do not read a text, it stands out as
something existential. Only through our reading does a text
become truth. The perceptual world of nature is difficult to
read because of its initially discontinuous structure, which is
largely a result of inadequate concepts.
9.
Meditation
Meditation
127
128
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
Meditation
129
similar to such creative words as, for example, the ideas of natural phenomena.
In chapter 8 we showed that when we are dealing exclusively with thoughts and linguistic or textual phenomena, reality and truth coincide in the experience of evidence. In the
sphere of perception, on the other hand, reality and truth are
separated, because we cannot fully think through the percept if
it is a part of nature; instead, we need higher concepts. Nevertheless, the outer image of nature, which has qualities and a
lawfulness that can be described even without being read,
leads us to the conclusion that we are dealing with a text.
Wherever we discover differences and similarities, analogies
and relations, we also find concepts, and wherever concepts
appear in the perceptual world, we are dealing with a text.
The truths accessible to modern thinking become conscious
when mirrored by our organism. As a result, these truths have
lost their quality of reality. In contrast, the part of perception
that is initially unthinkable remains aliveprecisely because
we cannot really think itthus kindling the sensation of reality. As this part is active, the sensation of reality it evokes
unites itself with the thinkable part of perception, that is, with
the familiar nominal concepts. As a result, in thinking we have
truth without reality, and in perception we have reality without
truth.
Meditation is an attemptby means of concentration and a
continuity of attention in thinking and representingto reach
a truth saturated with reality in the experience of evidence. In
perception on the other hand, that is to say, in perceptual meditation, the attempt isagain in the experience of e v i d e n c e
to come to a reality saturated with truth. Meditation in any
form always involves words. In fact, even the themes of pictorial and perceptual meditation are wordlike, although we cannot express such " w o r d s " in a particular language.
130
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E OF THE W O R L D
Meditation themes have been conceived with enhanced powers of cognition and are expressed in the form of a text or a picture. In perceptual meditation, we take our theme from nature;
the phenomena of nature are in themselves expressions of
higher concepts. The subjects we choose to meditate on do not
describe facts or refer to a world that is already past. Rather,
they point to the common source of world and cognition, that
is, to the Logos. In the Logos all being is cognition and already
contains the latter. We can cognize and know our outer and
inner worlds because they are Logos worlds and are created
through the Word. The text or theme we meditate on is taken
from a phase of the way the word travels "downward" toward
the world of the past and is then expressed in the words of a
particular language or in a picture. For this reason a meditator
can find the way up to the source of the theme through meditation that is, we find the way into a "wordless" sphere, "wordless" if we define "word" as necessarily always having a sound.
" W o r d " implies structure also in a higher sensethe structure of a fluid, airy, warmthlike element. Because our ordinary
language "structures" a much more dense and solid medium,
when we meditate we have to develop a much more powerful
faculty of structuring within our attention in order to be able
to cognize at all in the thinner clement. It is difficult to
express higher experiences in the words or pictures of ordi70
nary consciousness.
However, we can overcome this difficulty if we resort to the
primal meaning of words or to an archetype or symbol that is
equally meaningful.
Meditation always lives in the sphere of evidence. There,
truth and reality are one, reality and cognition are one being:
70. See Rudolf Sterner. Kunst unci Kunsterkenntnis (GA 271) (Dornach. Switzerland:
Rudolf Steiner Verlag, 1985), lectures of May 5 and 6, 19IS.
Meditation
131
the original, primeval word, not spoken, not audible, and not
part of one particular language; it is the creative Word through
which nature, our perceptual world, was created. In meditation
we leave the plane of the past of our consciousness, then our
theme becomes a task, which we can and must realize, so that
the reality to be gained is at the same time truth, that is, evidence. We realize a text when we understand it, and we realize
our I when our attention meets itself. Similarly, we create the
reality of what we meditate on when our consciousness, now
one with our theme, ascends to the corresponding level of the
Word, the level from which our theme was taken.
10. Perceptual
Meditation
Perceptual
Meditation
133
Conversation may be considered the archetype of perception. In conversation, we take in what our partner has said
and break it up into sounds, words, thoughts, and I-cognition.
Perhaps we hear the words but do not understand the other person's thoughts; in that case, we do not make use of the transparency of the word-sense. If we are unable to think what the
other has said, the utterance will remain stuck on the level of
the words. If we do not understand the language in which the
utterance was made, what we heard remains only noise or, at
most, sound. With this, our perception descends into the
sphere of the middle senses. Our lower senses do not become
transparent because the next higher functions above them are
unable to understand what the lower senses convey.
Obviously, the natural world is not spoken in the here and
now; rather, it is a finished text, much like a letter that was
written in the past and must now be read. As long as we do not
even know the individual letters of the text, much less the corresponding concepts and I-beings, nature remains for us a perception on the level of the middle senses and of the sense of
touch. What happens when we do not understand our partner
in conversation shows us that the middle senses convey
unthinkable concepts to us, and do so superconsciously.
Perceptual meditation has the task of understanding the text
of nature. To achieve this, we must raise our thinking to a more
intuitive and living plane. Only then will our perceptual attention, now concentrated and trained to a heightened sensitivity
for different qualities, be able to intuit the corresponding
higher ideas. In other words, our thinking must not descend to
the level of the past.
The text of nature does not consist of predetermined letters
or signs whose meaning is clearly defined. Discovering these
letters and signs is in itself a stage of meditation. All such acts
of discovery constitute the finding of an understanding; they
134
T H E LOGOS-STRUCTURE O F THE W O R L D
Perceptual
Meditation
135
136
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
71. See Steiner, A Road to Self-Knowledge (GA 16), chapter 1; Anthroposophie: Ein
Fragment, Appendix 5; The Being of Man and His Future Evolution (GA 107) (London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1981 ), lecture of December 8, 1908; An Occult Physiology
(GA 128) (London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1983). lecture of March 23, 1911; (GA 165),
lecture of January 2, 1916; Chance. Providence, and Necessity (GA 163). lecture of
August 30, 1915; (GA 205), lecture of July 16, 1921; (GA 206). lectures of August 12
and 13, 1921; The Human Heart (GA 212), lecture of May 26, 1922; (GA 218), lectures of October 20, 1922 and December 9, 1922; Pastoral Medicine (GA 318) (Hudson, N.Y.: Anthroposophie Press, 1987), lecture of September 10, 1924.
Perceptual
Meditation
137
138
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
Perceptual
Meditation
139
140
Epilogue
73. See Kuhlewind, Stages of Consciousness, chapter "The Two Stages of Consciousness."
142
T H E L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F THE W O R L D
74. See Khle wind. The Life of the Soul, chapters 3 and 5.
Bibliographical
References
B o o k s by Rudolf Steiner:
The Being of Man and His Future Evolution ( G A 107). London: Rudolf
Steiner Press, 1981.
The Boundaries of Natural Science ( G A 322). H u d s o n , N.Y.: A n t h r o p o sophie Press, 1983. (GA 322).
The Case for Anthroposophy (GA 21). London: Rudolf Steiner Press, 1970.
Chance, Providence, and Necessity ( G A 163). H u d s o n , N.Y.: A n t h r o p o sophie Press, 1988.
The Effects of Spiritual Development ( G A 145). L o n d o n : Rudolf
Steiner Press, 1978.
Foundations of Esotericism (GA 9 3 a ) . L o n d o n : Rudolf Steiner Press,
1982.
Fruits of Anthroposophy. Hudson, N.Y.: A n t h r o p o s o p h i e Press, 1986.
Goethean Science (GA 1), previously translated as Goethe the Scientist.
Spring Valley, N.Y.: Mercury Press, 1988.
Goethe's World View (GA 6). Spring Valley, N.Y.: Mercury Press, 1985.
How Do I Find the Christ ( G A 182). H u d s o n , N.Y.: A n t h r o p o s o p h i e
Press, 1941.
The Human Heart (GA 212). Spring Valley, N.Y.: Mercury Press, 1985.
Knowledge and Initiation (GA 211). Vancouver, B.C.: Steiner Book
Centre, n.d.
Macrocosm and Microcosm, (GA 119). L o n d o n : Rudolf Steiner Press,
1968.
Metamorphoses of the Soul, vol. 1 ( G A 59). L o n d o n , Rudolf Steiner
Press, 1983.
The Michael Mystery (GA 26). Spring Valley, N.Y.: St. George Publications, 1984.
The Mission of the Archangel Michael ( G A 194). Spring Valley, N.Y.:
A n t h r o p o s o p h i e Press, 1961.
A Modern Art of Education ( G A 307). Hudson, N.Y.: A n t h r o p o s o p h i e
Press, 1 9 7 2 . '
An Occult Physiology (GA 128). London: Rudolf Steiner Press. 1983.
An Outline of Occult Science (GA 13). H u d s o n , N.Y.: A n t h r o p o s o p h i e
Press, 1989.
144
THE L O G O S - S T R U C T U R E O F T H E W O R L D
B o o k s by G e o r g K h l e w i n d :
Der Sprechende Mensch ("The Speaking H u m a n Being"). Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann, 1992.
Die Diener des Logos ("Servants of the L o g o s " ) . Stuttgart: Verlag Freies
Geistesleben, 1981.
Die Wahrheit Tun ("Doing the T r u t h " ) . Stuttgart: Verlag Freies G e i stesleben, 1978.
The Life of the Soul. Hudson, N.Y.: Lindisfarne Press, 1990; \Das Lehen
der Seele]. Stuttgart: Verlag Freies Geistesleben, 1982.
Schooling of Consciousness. Fair O a k s , California: Rudolf Steiner College Publications, 1985.
Stages of Consciousness. Hudson, N.Y.: Lindislarne Press. 1984.