Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will
Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will
Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will
Introduction:
Is it possible that there be both foreknowledge of events and that the wills behind the
events remain free? Cicero, as presented by Augustine, is adamant that the two cannot be
reconciled. His argument is simple, and all the more powerful for that simplicity. If there is
foreknowledge of events, then they must happen in a certain order. But, if a certain order of
things, then a certain order of causes, for nothing can happen if not preceded by some efficient
cause.1 Therefore, all things would happen in accord with a fixed chain of causality. Such a
chain of causality would lead to a necessity in the happening of all events, and thus do away
with choice. This ultimately leads Cicero to deny foreknowledge of future things, in order to
make men free.2 Augustine states that in so doing Cicero makes them sacrilegious.3 This is
because the acceptance of divine foreknowledge, of course, is necessary for a man of faith.
Cicero, however, is simply anxious to respect his own experience of choice.
So, are they irreconcilable, as Cicero would have it? Must men of faith abandon their
free will in order to uphold divine omniscience? Augustine presents a very clear response, The
religious mind chooses both, confesses both, and maintains both by the faith of piety.4 So, the
Christian, according to Augustine, must hold both that his will is free and that his future actions
are nonetheless foreknown.
With such a response to Cicero, Augustine has purposefully given himself the task of
explaining how it is that ones faith confesses both without being in logical contradiction. This
1
Augustine, City of God in Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, Vol. 2, Augustine: City of God and On Christian Doctrine,
ed. Philip Schaff (Peabody, Mass.: Hendrickson Publishers, 1994), 90
2
Augustine, City of God, 90
3
Ibid., 91
4
Ibid., 91
even really incomplete, nonetheless leaves one aspect of the problem apparently unanswered,
and that it is this aspect that keeps contemporary writers concerned.
Finally, I intend to lay out Augustines solution in the City of God. The response therein
includes, and, moreover, is for the sake of that underlying premise which solves the aspect the
more traditional answer relies upon.
Ibid., 91
The order in events is the fundamental question under dispute. Granting free will and thus no
certain order seems to deny divine prescience; granting divine prescience affirms a certain
order and seems to destroy free will.
6
7
Augustine, Confessions, trans. John K. Ryan (New York: Doubleday, 1960), 303
Augustine, Confessions, 303
Boethius, Consolation of Philosophy, trans. Richard Green (New York: Bobbs-Merril Company Inc., 1962), 116-117
Among, however, the many articulations of the difficulty at hand, there are some that
pertain more to the traditional solution and to Augustines particular treatment in the City of
God. It is these accounts that are most pertinent to our current consideration.
Nelson Pike, for one, has dwelt extensively on the subject in numerous articles 9 and his
book, God and Timelessness. By the term timelessness, Pike understands the being outside of
time in the sense understood by Boethius. In his book, Pike claims that timelessness gets rid of
the necessity placed on events by the foreknowledge of those events. After all, nothing is being
seen before it happens; rather it is all seen at once. But, he further argues, while timelessness
may place God outside of time, nevertheless such a quality in God would not allow Him to know
the now.10 God would know all the nows, but not the now. Being outside of time, Pike argues,
God cannot see reality as successive, and thus cannot know it as it is in itself. God would know
all of history, but not where in history the actual temporal position exists. So, God would not
be strictly omniscient.
On the other hand, Pike argues, if one does not resort to timelessness, then mens wills
are bound by necessity.11 This latter position he also deals with in his articles. He holds, in
particular, that if Gods knowledge is true because God is omniscient, then the foreknowledge
he has necessitates that Smith do p at time t, meaning it is not in Smiths power to do
otherwise.
See Divine Omniscience and Voluntary action, Philosophical Review (1965), Of God and Freedom: A Rejoinder,
Philosophical Review (1966)
10
Nelson Pike, God and Timelessness (New York: Schocken Books, 1970), Ch. V
11
Nelson Pike, God and Timelessness, Ch. IV
Another author, Paul Helm, argues against Pike first position, and attempts a
resuscitation of the traditional notion of timelessness.12 However, after arguing for this, he
nonetheless agrees with Pikes position that foreknowledge, even that of a timeless and
omniscient God, destroys free will. There cannot be free will even if Gods knowledge of
human actions is timeless.13 His reasoning is straightforward, and very similar to Pikes. If it is
the case that God knows with certainty, then it is impossible that anything other than that
which He knows come about. But, free will is based on the premise that one may do otherwise.
Both, then, agree as to the fundamental problem of foreknowledge and free will. Pike
has stated that timelessness solves the difficulty insofar as it means that God does not know
something before it happens, hence we can be understood to cause his knowledge. But, he is
absolutely certain that if God knows something before it happens, then happen it must. Helm
points out that, regardless of Gods timelessness, it will still be the case that God knows actions
as following upon each other, and thus according to the before and after. Therefore, even if
God is timeless, there is still a certain order of events and causes. Helm, then, is resigned to
what Pike is unable to get around. Whether or not God is in time, Gods knowledge of all events
in time necessitates a certain order in those events. Pike, in trying to escape, negates Gods
omniscience. Helm points out that he, Pike, does not actually negate the omniscience of God,
but neither does he escape the problem of a certain order to things. In effect, none of them
have moved beyond Ciceros formulation of the problem. Certain and necessary order has yet
to be successfully avoided or explained.
12
13
The traditional solution makes it clear that Gods eternity means He sees all at once,
thus seeing the event as it is happening. But how, one may still ask, does this solve the difficulty
of a necessary order of causes and events? In short, perhaps Gods timelessness solves the
difficulty, but it is not immediately apparent how it does so, as evidenced by the positions of
Pike and Helm.
16
17
Ibid., 91
Ibid., 91
It does not follow that, though there is for God a certain order of all causes,
there must be nothing depending on the free exercise of our wills, for our wills
themselves are included in that order of causes which is certain to God, and is
embraced by His foreknowledge He who foreknew all causes of things would
certainly among those causes not be ignorant of our wills.18
In line with this, he further adds,
In His supreme will resides the power which acts on the wills of all created
spirits For, as He is the creator of all natures, so also is He the bestower of all
powers (Wills) have no power except that he has bestowed on them.19
Concluding,
Wherefore our wills have just so much power as God willed and foreknew that
they should have; and therefore whatever power they have, they have it within
most certain limits; and whatever they are to do, they are most assuredly to do,
for He whose foreknowledge is infallible foreknew that they would have the
power to do it, and would do it.20
So, Augustine wants to say that God is the cause of all things, and this includes the very power
of our willing. Insofar as God causes all things, so far does He know them. Our wills cannot be a
mystery to Him in themselves, or in their action, since He causes them as they are.
B) Gods Causality and Human Freedom
This should be a startling claim on Augustines part. He is proposing that the only way to
solve the certain order question is to acknowledge that God is causing all things. The
traditional solution seemed to be good precisely insofar as it got away from saying that God
must be causing all actions if it is the case that He knows them before they are performed. Are
we then to resolve the question by abandoning the idea of solving the paradox? Worse yet, is
Augustine giving away our free will?
18
Ibid., 91
Ibid., 91-92
20
Ibid., 92
19
10
Far from it. We do many things which, if we were not willing, we would certainly not
do.21 Augustine is still keenly aware that we will what we will when we will it. No, Augustine is
not asking us to rethink our freedom, at least not the fact that we are free, but he is asking us
to rethink something far more profound. He is asking us to rethink God. God, as Creator, is
Someone we can never fully comprehend. We may know that He is, and, to some extent, what
attributes He has. But, what He is in Himself, that is beyond us. This is what Augustines answer
pushes us to see, acknowledge, and accept. We are natural, God is supernatural. Only with that
realization, the realization that God is beyond, can we at least start to solve the paradox of
freedom and certain order.
So, our wills themselves are included in that order of causes which is certain to God.
Gods causality includes our causality. What do you have that you have not received?22 All
that we have is given us, including our causality. All we possess and hold, including our wills, is a
gift. For, as He is the creator of all natures, so also is He the bestower of all powers. Our very
act of willing is given, for it has being. A man has no power through himself; he is a created
thing. What he has must be given.
Gods causality, then, is not of the human realm. It is of a kind that we cannot
comprehend, because the actuality it brings to that which it causes is not necessarily external to
that thing. It can be internal; otherwise, the things caused could not exist. If God does not make
a thing as it is, including its interior being, how could that thing be? While it is impossible to
fully conceive of such a powerful cause, nonetheless, our knowledge of creation, and what it
21
22
Ibid., 92
1 Cor. 4:7
11
23
12
So, once more, God causes our wills as they naturally exist, namely as free. There is necessity,
but, Augustine further points out, just as there is necessity in God that does not compromise
His omnipotence, so is there necessity in our wills which does not compromise our freedom.24
C) Gods Eternality, Certain Order of Events
Now that it is clear that mans will may be free and still caused, it similarly becomes
clear how the necessary order in events is not an unsolvable difficulty. This is on account of
Gods eternality.
Gods eternality is proclaimed in the psalm Augustine quotes, as is Gods
unchangeableness. Since God hath spoken once, His act of creation is not separate in itself
from any other act He has done. Thus, His single, eternal Word comprehends within it, as
Augustine argued, all the powers given to creatures, and all being. The speaking of the Word
includes all events, comprehends all happenings. The order is no secret to God, He is its
underlying cause. His knowledge is not outside the thing known. As Aquinas would put it, Gods
knowledge cannot be distinct from his causal act.25 For, God is simple.
So, while it is true to say that God knows all things because He causes them, it is just the
same to say that they are the way they are because He knows them that way. In other words,
God knows the order of events in the same way He causes those events. His knowledge is not
separate from His causality. Therefore, God knows what will happen before it happens in the
same way that He causes mans free will. There is nothing in that knowledge, then, which may
compromise the nature or action of the things known. In comprehending the order of things
24
25
Ibid., 92
Aquinas, Summa Theologiae (Taurini, Rome: Marietti, 1948), Ia, q. 14, a. 8
13
and events, God knows the things as they are, namely contingent. So, there is contingency in
things. They could do otherwise, according to their own nature. Again, just as God creates and
knows mans freedom without compromising it, so does He know the contingent nature of
man. Cicero is thus answered, as are Pike and Helm. The question of order in events and causes
can be solved by a proper understanding of the nature of Gods causality and knowledge. When
properly understood, Gods act of causation need not interfere with the human will, though it
still causes that will internally.
Conclusion:
In conclusion, Augustine has shown us that the will of man can be subject to the
necessity of Gods causality, and that this necessity, due to Gods one simple act, includes a
certain order of events and happenings. But, the causal power of God is exercised internally in
creation, and thus informs our very power of willing and also the contingency of events. We do
what we will, as we will it. God knows what we will, for He knows the created will as the giver
of its being and the giver of its ability to will freely. God is beyond any conception we might
have of Him, but we must see Him as the author of all being, including any being that is in our
will. All is in His power, even unto our power. What do we have that has not been given us? But
our power is ours, and we do what we do through our own willing, which is included in the
causal knowledge of the Creator. To end with the words of St. Augustine,
It is not the case, therefore, that because God foreknew what would be in the
power of our wills, there is for that reason nothing to the power of our wills. For
He who foreknew this did not foreknow nothing.26
26
14