Daimonic Power - Sfameni
Daimonic Power - Sfameni
Daimonic Power - Sfameni
Chapter28
Da imon ic Pow er
Giulia Sfameni Gasparro
The Problem
A Long-LastingSystem
In dealing with daimonic power in the Greek religious tradition, we need to make a premise:we cannot, in fact, presume that we can reconstruct a daimonology, in the sense of a
clearly defined doctrine or a coherent and final system of ideas. Rather, daimonology is
a more or less homogeneous and articulated set of ideas and beliefs, sometimes associated
with ritual practice, relating to the category of the divine which the Greeks, from the time
of Homer, denoted by the term daimon/daimones. This set of ideas is to be assessed in the
context of the Greek religious tradition as it originated and developed over time, without
dogmas and institutions or official religious authorities with the power to impose rigid regulatory uniformity on beliefs and ritual practices. There is, also, the difficulty of applying
clear steps within this long historical process, establishing, as it were, the precise phases
and isolating compact, autonomous blocks within the mobile flow of ethnicnational
religious beliefs. Avoiding anachronisms by interpreting the sources of the Archaic and
Classical age in the light of subsequent developments, according to ideological schemes of a
different historicalcultural situation, seems to be key. The more or less complex formulations of the Hellenistic and Roman Imperial periods must, therefore, be placed in relation to
earlier traditions, to measure any continuity, mutations, or innovations.
The Sources
There are numerous problems stemming from the nature of the source material available
for the study of daimonic power. Literary texts outnumber direct documents, such as
inscriptions. It is difficult, indeed sometimes impossible, to differentiate, within the literary
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 413
3/16/2015 7:59:14 PM
Historiographical Overview
Although the scholarly debate on the subject has generated numerous, authoritative
works, recent studies taking a broad documentary and methodological look at the whole
chronological span of Greek daimonology are still extant. Useful and praiseworthy
early studies in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries (Hild 1892; Andres 1918;
Heinze 1965 [1892]) aimed at providing a broad overview of the theme for the Archaic
and Classical ages, and, in part, for the early Hellenistic period. Later research, however,
focused merely on specific contexts. This research often provided a philosophical reflection aimed at systematizing the complex, shifting horizon of Greek religious traditions rather than looking at the specifically religious aspects of the topic. In this field we
should mention the many, varied studies on the Pythagorean environment, including,
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 414
3/16/2015 7:59:14 PM
DaimonicPower415
of particular interest, that by Detienne (1963), which also reflects on the Platonic context.
The latter, in fact, throughout its long history, is deeply interested in the daimonological
theme, often adopted as an interpretative key to bridge the gap between popular belief
and worship on the one hand, and rational speculation of philosophers on the other.
After Jensen (1966) and the contribution of Marx-Wolf (2009), the documented essay
by Timotin (2012) is of interest. From an eminently philosophical perspective, this work
examines the history of the notion of daimon from Plato to the last Platonists. From
Porphyry to Iamblichos, up to Proklos and Damaskios, these last Hellenes opposed the
increasingly pervasive and ultimately victorious affirmation of Christianity. They tried,
with all the tools of philosophical reflection, to propose a new interpretation of the traditional Greek religious heritage. Daimonological exegesis, variously articulated according to context, often offered them an interpretative key to include aspects of this heritage
deemed incompatible with the canons of the philosophical religion they desired.
In On Isis and Osiris Plutarch also appeals to the authority of Plato, Pythagoras,
Xenokrates, and Krysippos,who,
following the lead of early writers on sacred subjects (theologoi), allege (the dai
mones) to have been stronger than men, yet not possessing the divine quality
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 415
3/16/2015 7:59:14 PM
Some modern scholars have questioned whether the men of the golden race (Hes.
Op. 1216), who became daimones after death, could have been a distinct category for
Hesiod. Instead, it has been argued that he understands daimones in the Homeric sense
of gods, beings of divine status without special connotations. Such a view contradicts
the entire ancient tradition, which always understood Hesiods daimones as beings of
special status within the general theological scheme, different from the greatgods.
Plato provides the earliest attestation of this interpretation. In the Cratylus
(397e398a) and Leg. (713cd) there is talk of a race of daimons, defined as superior, a
particular category of superhuman beings that acts as guardians of men at the time of
Kronos. This notion can also be found in the Pythagoreans, whose interest in Hesiod,
whom they considered almost a sacred writer, is well known. At the same time, this
interpretation makes nonsense of the deeper import of the myth of the four races and
certainly reflects its authors attempt to construct a coherent framework for the disorderly religious inheritance that he was trying to rethink in terms of his own ethicalview.
Among the various meanings of the myth, we may insist here upon its vocation, in
terms of nature and functions, as a classification of beings which operates on different levels of reality that are notionally distinct, but does not imply any break within a
homogeneous, continuous chain of being. The history of man is linked to that of the
gods by virtue of the metamorphosis into daimones of the golden race of mortal men
(Hes. Op.109).
The word daimon retains, throughout Greek tradition from the Homeric poems to
the very end, its meaning as a synonym of theos. It has its own specific nuancesalready
evident in Homerwhich embody a supernatural presence and power, difficult for
humans to identify, and that often intervenes unexpectedly, bringing with it risks for
people. Among the many examples analysed by Franois (1957), we need merely to
recall Menelaus reflection on the outcome of his fight with Hector (Hom. Il. 17.89104).
Within the terms used to define the divine power that protects the Trojan hero, daimon
alternates with theos, but takes on the meaning of an indefinite supernatural force that
directs the course of events according to its own design, which humans cannot oppose.
In Hesiods text, the variables of meaning of the words used to identify superhuman
powers, such as theos and daimon, are emphasized to indicate a particular status. The
poets moralizing perspective represents the daimones as guardians of mortal men,
acting justly, but also as plutodotoi, bestowers of wealth. This is their geras basileion
or royal privilege, which characterizes their position as divine beings (Hes. Th. 1226).
In Hesiods scheme we can see a whole series of ideas, familiar from different levels
of Greek religious tradition, neatly imbricated into a consistent framework. The dai
mones, as an ancient race of men hidden beneath the earth, are related to the souls
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 416
3/16/2015 7:59:14 PM
DaimonicPower417
of the dead. The role of watchers (phylakes) suggests a notion familiar from Homeric
poems, and recurrent in later Greek tradition. In lyric (Pind. Ol. 13.105; Pind. Pyth.
5.1223) and gnomic (Thgn. 14950, 1616, 4026, 6378) poetry, tragedy (Aesch. Pers.
158, 825 and passim; Soph. OC 76; Eur. Med. 1347; Eur. Alc. 499, 561; Eur. Andr. 98, 974;
Eur. Phoen. 1653), history (Xen. An. 5.2.25.), and oratory (Lys. 2.78f), the daimon appears
as a divine agent intervening at will in human affairs, positively or negatively, for good
or ill, often to revenge crimes, as the Daimon Alastor in works of tragedy (Aesch. Per.
355554), and invariably exercising a decisive influence upon humanfate.
From Euripides (Bacch. 894)who provides the first testimonyonwards, in the
semantic sphere of theos/oi and daimon/es, along with the neuter to theion attested for
the first time in Aesch. Cho. 957, we see the neuter to daimonion. Both forms of neuter
substantivized adjective, according to the contexts, have an abstract (the divine, the
daimonic) or collective sense, that is, corresponding to theoi and daimones. These two
new semantic formations were to have an important role in influencing the evolution
of the meaning of Greek theology and daimonology. These terms are often used as
alternative and converging designations of the power that stands over and directs cosmic and human life. In the many peculiar articulations of a polytheistic scenario (on
which see, in this volume, Pirenne-Delforge and Pironti, Chapter4), they also assume a
differentiated significance and make it possible to circumscribe, in the various historical contexts, the two distinct spheres of the divine and the daimonic.
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 417
3/16/2015 7:59:14 PM
The date of the Pythagorean Commentaries is uncertain (an early Pythagorean work or
an expression of second or first century bce Neopythagorism). The text contains different
senses of daimon because it draws upon sources of diverse age and origins:the idea that
the daimones and heroes are equivalent to the souls that swarm in the air, analogous to the
doctrine of Thales, may hark back to an Archaic idea, such as daimonic influence upon
animals. The oracular function of these daimonic beings, and, in particular, the ascription
of purifying and apotropaic rituals, as well as scrying and kledonomancy, to the daimonic
world, probably derives from intellectual speculations in a Pythagorean milieu, similar to
that represented by commentary on the Derveni Papyrus in Platos Symposium, and continued in the Platonic tradition from Xenokrates to Plutarch and Porphyry.
Before examining these authors, the position of Empedocles (c. 490430 bce) should
be mentioned. He was a complex, original figure of great philosophical and religious
interest. In his poems (On Nature and Purifications), which have reached us through
an indirect fragmentary tradition, we see the notion of the daimon as a psychic entity
involved in the cosmic drama of the struggle between Neikos (Strike) and Philia (Love),
and caught in a cycle of painful transmigrations into different bodies (humans, animals, plants). Empedocles daimones are entities closely linked to the anthropological
sphere. In fact, the poet-philosopher, having evoked the cycle of metensomatosis (reincarnation) to which the murderer and perjurer must be subjected, far from the blessed,
who like long-lived daimons have attained life, can claim to be one of them, exiled by
divine decree and wandering (fr. 115; cf. Plut. De def. or. 418e,420d).
Plato
The intermediate and intermediary nature of daimones reformulates the polyvalent
meaning represented by the popular notion of daimon, and appears formalized for the
first time in the well-known Platonic myth ofEros.
In the myth, Diotima of Mantinea tells Sokrates (Pl. Symp. 203a204c), in support
of the revelation that Eros is a daimon:he is a big daimon, and the entire daimonion is
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 418
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
DaimonicPower419
half-way (metaxu) between god and mortal. The power (dynamis) of the daimones is to
play between heaven and earth, flying upwards with our worship and our prayers, and
descending with the heavenly answer and commandments... They form the medium
of the prophetic arts, of the priestly rites of sacrifice, initiation, and incantation, of divination and sorcery (202d203a). The theological aim of the discourse is clear in the
conclusion, The god will not mingle with the human, and it is only through this (to
daimonion) that the gods have intercourse and conversation with men, whether waking or sleeping. The wise woman concludes, The daimones are many and of many
kinds (203a).
This is probably a collective representation shared both by ordinary people and
by the learned, as the same idea is found in an increasing number of texts from the
fourth century bce onwards. In several dialogues, Plato develops the notion of a personal daimon who protects the individual during this life and guides him in the life to
come (Phd. 107d108b, 113d; Resp. 620de), and maybe is actually the superior, divine
part of the soul (Ti. 90ac). Plato also makes use of the traditional tripartite scheme of
gods/daimones/heroes to define the categories of superhuman beings.
The intermediate beings, who are subject to pain, form the link between the poles of
the universe, acting as interpreters, and interpreters of all things, to one another and to
the highest gods. Their agency is at work in dreams and oracles, and forms the basis of
various city cults (984e985a).
The Epinomis bears witness to the process of systematization of the Pythagorean
and Platonic doctrine, with regard to the intermediate and intermediary status of the
daimones. It also foreshadows a theme developed later by Xenokrates and Plutarch by
expressing the notion of daimon as a tool for reinterpreting Greek myths and cults.
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 419
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 420
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
DaimonicPower421
with an organically structured and functioning daimonology in which several contributions converge, not only Platonic, naturally, but also Pythagorean.
Many voices contributed to the formulation of the daimonological theories that were
particularly in favour in Platonic environments and were more or less influenced by
Pythagorism. The major exponents of this tradition included Antiochus of Ascalon
(late second, early first century bce) and Maximus of Tyre (second century ce),
who affected other philosophical traditions in various ways, from Aristotelianism to
Stoicism.
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 421
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 422
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
DaimonicPower423
not to be absorbed by the worship rendered to the daimones, which leads away from the
higher god. He evokes the opinion of the wise men, according towhom
most of the earthly daimones are absorbed with created things, and are riveted
to blood and burnt offerings and magical enchantments, and are bound to other
things of this sort, and can do nothing better than healing the body and predicting
the coming fortune of men and cities, and that all their knowledge and power concerns merely mortal activities. (8.60; trans. Chadwick1965)
The two key themes of Porphyrys discourse are evoked:first, there is the close connection between daimonic power and the practice of blood sacrifice. These terrestrial
beings nourish themselves with the vapours emanating from the victim, and, in particular, with its blood, causing that thickening of the pneumatic vehicle that binds them
firmly to the corruptible and passionate world. The second key notion is that the power
of daimons is concerned solely with bodily and worldly goods, whose possession nevertheless risks, as Celsus stresses, distancing man from those higher goods in which
can be found his true spiritual and religious dimension. Adaimonic presence was considered necessary for the maintenance of cosmic order, although such a presence possessed disturbing and even dangerous aspects due to its ability to distract man from the
real spiritual good. The uninterrupted tension of the soul must be directed towards the
supreme, transcendentdeity.
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 423
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
In the opinion of Porphyry, the information related to daimones is confusing, and leads
to incorrect judgements aboutthem.
Porphyry illustrates a doctrine that, by being linked to the theological schema set
forth in Daimones as a Category of Superhuman Beings in the 'Theology' of the Greeks,
above, places the daimones in direct relation to the Universal Soul (Psyche). They are,
in fact, none other than psychai (souls) derived from the Universal Soul and destined
to govern the sublunary regions. The souls, with pneumatic support, that is, a sort of
material garment, are distinguished from each other with regard to the relationship
established with this inferior component, later defined as corporeal, passive and corruptible (2.39.2). Those souls that manage to dominate the pneuma by directing it in
agreement with reason become good daimones and exert a beneficial power on the
various cosmic regions and on human activity (2.38.2). They are thus identified with
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 424
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
DaimonicPower425
the gods, as functioning typically in the polytheistic tradition. Porphyry adds a category of intermediary daimons. He explicitly appeals to the Platonic doctrine of the
Symposium (202e) to define these beings as those who announce the affairs of men
to the gods, and the will of the gods to men; carrying our prayers, indeed, to the gods
as judges, but oracularly unfolding to us the exhortations and admonitions of the gods
(2.38.3).
To these beings, man mistakenly attributes feelings of revenge and the ability to
cause injury if they are not worshipped. This malevolent capacity is instead characteristic of those souls who, overwhelmed by the passionate support of the pneuma, are
themselves prey to sensitive appetites. Although belonging to the common category
of daimones, these souls can rightly be termed malevolent (2.38.4). Porphyry then
expounds a complex daimonology that uses various elements already present in an
extensive and well-established tradition that, in Greece, flowing from a diverse and
mobile substrate of Archaic folk beliefs, seems to have found, in ancient Pythagorism, a
fruitful soil where it could take root to assume more or less elaborate shapes and move
towards new solutions.
Having defined the unique character of the daimons as being invisible and imperceptible to the senses, Porphyry affirms their ability to assume various guises so that
they can manifest themselves visibly. The evil daimons occupy the regions near to the
earth and attempt to commit all sorts of evil and violent acts against men. Instead, the
intervention of the good daimons, even when aimed at correcting human behaviour, is
distinguished by its regularity and moderation (2.39.14).
Porphyry concludes that:On this account a wise and temperate man will be afraid,
in a religious sense, to use sacrifices of this kind, through which he will attract to himself such-like daimones; but he will endeavor in all possible ways to purify his soul
(2.43.1). Porphyrys perspective, with its firm condemnation of blood sacrifice, reveals
the specific originality of some of its aspects, primarily the fundamental anthropological motivation of the entire context, oriented to the salvation of the soul. This perspective nevertheless presents itself as a last, radical result of attitudes and trends variously
present in the Greek tradition, where sometimes the criticism of sacrifice is found
within a theological framework with a structure that, by degrees, links ritual practice,
or other aspects of worship considered somewhat at odds with divine dignity, with the
daimonic rank, seen as intermediate between gods andmen.
Daimones andCult
Some documents, particularly epigraphic, reveal more clearly traditional popular
beliefs and rituals and show the process by which Greek religious thinking came to distinguish between the words theoi and daimones so as to define two categories of divine
beings. In the inscriptions from the oracular sanctuary of Zeus at Dodona, a couple
ask Zeus Naios and Dione by praying to which of the gods or heroes or daimones and
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 425
3/16/2015 7:59:15 PM
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 426
3/16/2015 7:59:16 PM
DaimonicPower427
Suggested Reading
After Detienne (1963) and Jensen (1966), who emphasize the importance of the Pythagoreans
in the history of Greek daimonology, few monographs have been devoted to the theme in
recent years. Marx-Wolf (2009, 2011) investigates the way in which third-century bce
Platonists used daimonology as a medium to establish a hierarchy in the realm of spirits and
to organize a complex ritual praxis (theurgia). Timotin (2011) tracks changes in the notion of
daimon in the Platonic tradition, from the Old Academy to the last Neoplatonists. He analyses the relationship between daimonology, cosmology, and theories of thesoul.
References
Andres, F. 1918. Daimon, RE, suppl. 3:267322.
Babbit, F.C. 1962 [1936]. Plutarchus Moralia V. London.
Chadwick, H. 1965. Origen. Contra Celsum. Cambridge.
Detienne, M. 1963. De la pense religieuse la pense philosophique. La notion de damn dans
le pythagorisme ancient.Paris.
Franois, G. 1959. Le polythisme et lemploi au singulier des mots QEOS, DAIMWN dans la
littrature grecque dHomre Platon.Paris.
Graf, F. and Johnston, S.I. 2013. Ritual Texts for the Afterlife (2nd edn). London.
Heinze, R. 1965 [1892]. Xenokrates. Darstellung der Lehre und Sammlung der Fragmente.
Leipzig.
Hild, J. A. 1892. Daemon, in Dictionnaire des Antiquits grecques et romaines, ed. Ch.
Daremberg and E. Saglio, 919.Paris.
Jensen, S.S. 1966. Dualism and Demonology:The Function of Demonology in Pythagorean and
Platonic Thought. Munksgaard.
Marx-Wolf, H. 2009. Platonists and High Priests:Daemonology, Ritual and Social Order in
the Third Century CE. Diss., University of Michigan, Ann Arbor,MI.
Nowak, N. 1960. Zur Entwicklungsgeschichte des Begriffes Daimon. Eine Untersuchung
epigraphischer Zeugnisse von 5 Jh. v.Chr. bis zum 5.Jh. n.Chr.. Diss.,Bonn.
Sandbach, F.H. 1972. Menandri Reliquiae Selectae. Oxford.
Sfameni Gasparro, G. 1997. Daimn and Tuch in the Hellenistic Religious Experience, in
Conventional Values in the Hellenistic World. International Conference Rungstedgaard
2528 January 1995, ed. B. Bilde, P. Engberg-Pedesen, and L. Hannestad, 67109. Aarhus.
Sfameni Gasparro, G. 2001. Magie et dmonologie dans les Papyrus Graecae Magicae, in Res
Orientales, vol. 13:Dmons et merveilles dOrient, ed. R. Gyselen, 15774. Bures-sur-Yvette.
Timotin, A. 2011. La dmonologie platonicienne. Histoire de la notion de daimon de Platon
aux derniers noplatoniciens. Leiden.
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 427
3/16/2015 7:59:16 PM
Eidinow171114OUK.indb 428
3/16/2015 7:59:16 PM