Music and Cultural Theory
Music and Cultural Theory
Music and Cultural Theory
I would like to thank the following friends and colleagues for their patience, help, input
and encouragement while I was working on this review: Sara Cohen (Liverpool), Franco
Fabbri (Milan), Alessandra Gallone (Milan), Lucy Green (London), Dave Harker (Manchester), David Horn (Liverpool), Andrew Hugill (Leicester), Margit Kronberg (Gteborg), Dave
Laing (London), Greg Lee (Hong Kong), Richard Middleton (Newcastle), Kay Richardson
(Liverpool), Garry Tamlyn (Brisbane) and Marta Ulha (Rio de Janeiro). Although considerable input from all these people is incorporated in this review, they cannot be held responsible for the use or misuse of their ideas in this text.
application of cultural theory has had some success in grasping affect in music as socially and culturally constituted. This book should in other words
help cultural theorists to understand music and help musicians or musicologists to understand the work they do from the viewpoint of theories of culture and society.
In chapter one, the authors basically argue that the few musicologists to
have dealt with the problem of affect and meaning in music, have, in one
way or another, misrepresented the nature of musical communication. Only
one music theorist, Leonard B. Meyer, they claim, has consistently confronted the difficulty (p.11), although his analyses of classical music are
compelling only because the consequences of social mediations to this tradition are revealed intuitively and through omission (p.14). Shepherd and
Wicke then take on scholars of cultural studies who, like most musicologists,
they argue, have a concept of music as a thing. For scholars from both
disciplines, we are told, either music contains meaning in its material qualities as a phenomenon autonomous in relation to social and cultural processes, or it acts as an inscrutable black box, the role of whose internal
characteristics in the transmission or creation of social and cultural meanings is neither considered or understood (p.15). The reason for this sad
state of affairs is then attributed to the idea that Saussures concept of the
arbitrary sign is inapplicable to music. For example, Nattiez and Kristeva are
seen to be so dominated by notions of the arbitrary sign as to be incapable
of providing any satisfactory theories of meaning in music. The way forward, say the authors, is suggested by way of the more structuralist dimensions of Saussures work (p.23). However, a few pages later the authors
point to incipient tension between, on the one hand, Saussures idea that
the sounds of words can have no necessary or logical connection to their
customary meanings (p.26) and, on the other, what the authors see as the
intrinsically iconic nature of music.2 This polarisation of arbitrary and immanent modes of signification becomes one of the books recurrent themes.
The next four chapters, constituting over one third of the entire text, are devoted almost entirely to reviewing the work of a selection of cultural, literary, linguistic and psychoanalytical authorities. The gist of this section is that
although these scholars may be credited to varying degrees with insights of
varying validity about some aspect of language, society and conceivable
links between music and either of these two, none of the work discussed can
really be endorsed as substantially contributing to an overall theory of music
as a form of human communication. One idea the authors do embrace is the
structural homology, especially as found in the work of Willis and Shepherd,
its importance heralded as the first time a theoretical protocol existed
through which the social and cultural meanings of music, as articulated
through musics internal, technical characteristics, could be grasped and understood within the framework of cultural analysis (p.38). Another set of
ideas the authors clearly find relevant to their aim is Althussers inclusion of
subjectivity and relative autonomy in theories of ideology (pp.48-55).
The first part of chapter four (pp.56-62) reviews the work of selected psy2.
I always thought Saussure meant that the sounds of words need not have any such connection to those using those sounds, and that one important aspect of etymological semiotics was to explain the necessary and logical connection between the sounds of words
and their customary meanings. The problem of iconicity is discussed later on in this
review.
Chora = bodily site of the first signifying processes of the fetus (p.76).
For a critique of concepts of the Other, see Tagg (1996).
5.
6.
7.
8.
Austrian musicologist, author of Sound and Symbol (1956, Princeton University Press).
Shepherd and Wicke (p.136), quoting Bierwisch (no page reference).
Consubstantiation is my terminological interpretation of one important aspect of what the
authors seem to mean by the saddle. Originally used by Christian theologians in the exegesis of the Holy Trinity, consubstantial simply means having the same substance.
The authors base this critique on their interpretation of the Foucaults use of the term.
What the authors actually have in mind is nevertheless obscure since they make no reference to any work by Foucault.
A little later on, the authors become even more adamant: the complexity and versatility
of the sonic saddle demonstrate the ultimate futility of using concepts as the signifier or
the museme to explain primary signification in music and, through that, secondary signification (p.168).
10. The authors use of timbre at this stage (p.153, ff.) is very confusing because it was
thrown out with other culturally insensitive categories a few pages back (pp.146-7) and
has not been redefined.
jects internal world the material binding between saddle and elements
of signification, internal states of awareness and being and, on the other
hand, the external world with its materiality (including the sound medium)
and its sociocultural processes (including practices of signification) is unfolded in a series of flowcharts. This expos constitutes the theoretical nub of
Music and Cultural Theory (pp.169-177).
After revisiting differences between language (qualified recurrently as cerebral, cognitive, rational, denotative, etc.) and music (corporeal, affective, emotional, iconic, etc.) in the light of their theoretical expos
(pp.178-203), the authors devote a substantial part of books last eleven
pages (5%) to a backtracking exercise in which they seek to dispel impressions of reductionism and to re-integrate their own ideas with other views of
the relationships between music, the individual and the external world.
Critique
The topic Music and Cultural Theory is vast and must be radically reduced
or distilled to fit into a book of standard length. Criteria of inclusion, exclusion and focus are therefore vital to the understanding and success of the
authors project.11
The cultural theory of this book is really Cultural Theory, i.e. the university
(sub)discipline established in the United Kingdom in the 1960s. As both concept and institution in this sense, cultural theory is virtually unknown in
most nations of the world, even in France.12 To the majority of readers who
are neither British nor au fait with the mainly British institution of Cultural
Theory, the book is much more likely to be interpreted from its title as dealing with any theory, formulated anywhere in the world at any time in history,
that can shed light on music as a cultural phenomenon. Important input into
the discussion of music and culture from, for example, Africa, the Arab
world, Argentina, China, Greece, India, Indonesia, Italy, Russia and Sweden
is absent, as are European medieval, renaissance, rationalist and romantic
theories relevant to the topic.13 A similarly narrow ethnic and historical focus
raises concern about whose music the cultural theory of the book relates
to, since its rare and cursory references to identifiable musical events are
11. Since criticism of focus forms a substantial part of this review, I have in an appendix
included bibliographical reference to some of the most relevant works absent from Music
and Cultural Theory. In order not to overburden this text with such references and in order
to save space, works mentioned in this review, in particular those cited by Shepherd and
Wicke, are not referenced in my bibliography. I have also only inserted parenthesised
dates in the main text in connection with the citation of particular passages. Most authors
I mention are listed in the bibliography together with reference to work of particular relevance.
12. In France itself, the French gurus of British Cultural Theory are academically categorised
as literary theorists, linguists, semiologists, sociologists, etc.
13. See, for example, Nketia (1974), Vega (1941), the Ntyastra (India), or Jayadipura,
Jakub, Wignyarumeska, Suryaputra and Wayan Rai (Indonesia, all cited in Hood,
1997:58). For further references to non-European theories of music and culture see, for
example, the entries Arabic music, China, India in The New Grove Dictionary of Music
and Musicians (London, 1995). See also Peter Crossley-Hollands account of music in
China, Egypt, Mesopotamia, Greece and the Arab world in The Pelican History of Music,
volume 1 (ed. A Robertson, London: Penguin, 1960). As a musicologist resident in Sweden
for twenty-four years, I have tried, without much success, to make the English-language
community of popular music scholars aware of Scandinavian work of relevance to our field
of enquiry. Of particular importance here is the work of Ling (1983, 1985, 1989, 1992).
Kivy, S Davies or Rosen,21 nor that of Bjrnberg, Brackett, Lacasse or Tamlyn. The common denominator of much of the work excluded in zone ten is
of course that it features the semiotic analysis of actual pieces of music, an
activity which the authors of Music and Cultural Theory explicitly preclude
from their own project. However, although such restriction of method is understandable in a publication targeted at an English language Cultural Theory readership, it does not explain musicological exclusion zones one
through nine. These lacunae are to a considerable extent attributable to
general problems of semiotic theory and method.
Eco (1990:256, ff.), referring to Peirce and Morris, emphasises the necessity
of integrating syntax, semantics and pragmatics in the study of signification.22 He points out how rhetoricians and sophists, philosophers and anthropologists, even the most abstract and theoretical among them, have
throughout the ages concerned themselves not just with the relationship between expression and content but with the intended meaning and interpretations or effects of statements.23 Eco further holds that pragmatics in no
way implies depriving semiotics of an object of study because it incorporates
the totality of the construction of meaning.24
Music and Cultural Theory lacks the semiotic objects and pragmatic concretion that are widely held to be essential to semiotic inquiry. Indeed, the authors plainly state that they will not only steer clear of actual musical
statements but also abandon discussion of musicians intentions, musicians
verbal reference to musical structures, listeners associations and reactions,
etc. as irrelevant to their particular purpose. The absence of these central
aspects of semiotic theory and method radically undermines the epistemological credibility of the authors stated purpose. Such absence leads furthermore to a less convincing and less readable book because the rich palette of
musical experience is sadly missing from its pages. There is an almost clinical absence of the wonder of music the urge to move different parts of
our bodies in an infinite variety of ways, the sensation of goose pimples, the
21. The Davies and Rosen references are taken from Treitler (1997).
22. Put simply, syntax deals with aspects of signification bearing on the temporal relationship
of signifying elements (signs) within a given mode of communication, semantics with the
relation between such signs and what they stand for or stand as, pragmatics with all cultural and social aspects related to the production and interpretation of meaning related to
syntax and semantics. The pragmatics of musical signification can therefore be understood to cover such phenomena as, on the one hand, the sociocultural position and signifying intentions of those transmitting, making or producing music, and, on the other
hand, the sociocultural position, interpretations, reactions, functions, uses, etc. made by
those hearing the same music.
23. La retorica greca e latina, cos come lintera linguistica dei sofisti, possono essere [considerate] come forme di un pragmatica del discorso. Ma anche nelle pi astratte definizioni
classiche di significazione ci sono elementi pragmatici tutte le definizioni del segno tengono conto non solo del rapporto fra espressione e contenuto,ma anche di quello fra
lespressione e la reazione mentale dellinterprete. Eco also reminds us that such figures
as Wittegenstein, Peirce, Morris, Meade and Habermas, as well as St Augustine, Roger
Bacon, Occam, Abelard, Locke and others were all interested in the intended meaning and
interpretations of statements, not only in abstract relations of expression to content (Eco
1990:266).
24. My italics. Dire che la pragmatica una dimensione della semiotica non significa privarla
di un oggetto. Significa invece che lapprocio pragmatico ha a che vedere con la totalit
della semiosi, la quale, per essere compresa pienamente, devessere avvicinata anche da
un punto di vista pragmatico. La sintattica e la semantica, quando si trovano in splendido
isolamento diventano discipline perverse (Eco, 1990:259)
10
11
The catastrophe for women that results from such reductionism is that if
they do not live up to the socially constructed phantasm of woman=mother=nurturer, then they will be regarded as either fallen or abnormal (Kristeva 1990:48). The resultant disaster for men is that as long as the full
29. For example Chambers, as quoted by the authors (p.15), Grossberg (Is there life after
punk in On Record, ed. Frith & Goodwin, New York, 1990: 113) and Lull (Popular Music
and Communication, ed. J Lull, Newbury Park, 1992: 29-30). For critique of rockologist
reduction of forceful low-pitch beat and backbeat to sexuality, see Tagg (1994) and Tamlyn (1998).
30. I am referring to the way in which the authors, in the final pages of their book, criticise
essentialisation, by which they seem to mean the sort of reductionism under discussion
here. Exaggerating my impressions on reading the authors warnings, I felt a like a young
man leaving home and being told in a few words by my father, who had beaten me
throughout childhood, that violence is bad.
12
experience of what our society and culture, including some of its theorists,
see fit to essentialise as feminine the non-verbal, the corporeal, the kinaesthetic, etc. , then we, by biological definition unable to experience
motherhood within ourselves, will continue to be alienated from our own
bodies, emotions and their social construction. In short, although I am in no
way suggesting that the authors subscribe to the notion just criticised, even
less condone its ideological implications, I think they have given too much
space to reductionist notions of body and femininity, too little to refuting
them.
Discussion of language sometimes runs into similar difficulties. Denotation
and the arbitrary sign are put forward as the overriding traits of language
and little or no problematisation is given to such aspects of linguistic signification as intonation, accentuation, speech rhythm and melody, vocal timbre, diction, phonation, volume, facial expression, bodily gesture, social
rules, etc. (e.g. Bolinger 1989, Fonagy 1972). Nor is the issue of denotation
through pitch addressed (tonemes), nor the frequent refutation by modern
linguists of denotations semiotic primacy (e.g. Cruise 1988, Harris 1981,
Kress 1993).31 We are in other words presented with a reductionist and simplified Saussurean notion of language.
I have already suggested that the authors restricted semiotic and musicological perspectives relate to the books failure to mediate a sense of music.
Such lack of musicogenic substance is also influenced by a reductionist view
of our art. For example, what appears to be regarded as the primarily cerebral character of syntactical signification in classical music seems to take
no account of the fact that people fainted from sheer affect upon hearing a
false recapitulation,32 nor of the cardinal importance attached to timbre,
texture and to the beat during the ascendancy of the Central European classical idiom.33 The same reductionist view of music semiotics can also be discerned in a more pervasive sense, in that virtually all aspects of musical
signification theorised in the book seem to have been slimmed down to those
31. Moreover, arbitrary signs cannot originate as such since without other initial types of semiotic relationship (e.g. icons or indices) it would be impossible to develop the conventions
on which arbitrary signs rely for their subsequent denotative qualities. Eco (1990:6) qualifies the imagined solidity of denotative signification through arbitrary signs as rigid designation, pointing out that language always says something more than its inaccessible
literal meaning, something which is already lost right from the start of the textual utterance.
32. False recapitulation: restatement of the main theme of a sonata form movement in a different key to that in which it appeared at the start of the movement and in which it is
expected to reappear after the movements development section. I regret that I have
been unable to find any primary source for the observations about fainting.
33. This was also a period of ascendancy for rationalism and colonialism. For documentation
and discussion of timbre and texture in the work of J S Bach, see Klingfors (1991), especially the chapters dealing with intonation, singing, violins and ensembles. Regarding the
beat, it is worth noting that Johann Beer (1655-1700, Austrian composer, singer, instrumentalist and satirical novelist) wrote that people with no sense of regular pulse have no
sense of honour and that regular time is the soul of music (Beer 1719: 166, ff.). Similarly, Mozarts father Leopold held that accompanists who cant keep to a regular beat are
vulgar and amateurish (Mozart 1756: 266), while J S Bachs composition pupil Kirnberger
(1721-1783) stated that a good music teacher always keep his pupils on various types of
dance music so they become rooted in the automatic aspect of the beat (Kirnberger
1771). Finally, the author of J S Bachs obituary (1754) saw fit to record that the deceased
was a very accurate conductor and in matters of tempo extremely reliable (Bach-Dokumente III, 1972: 666). All citations are from Klingfors (1991: 346-350).
13
that fit the authors model, i.e. those easily perceived as evidencing a relationship either between sounds able to exist in similar physical form inside
and outside what members of the same given culture regard as music, or
that between sounds understood in the same way as music and their biogenic effect on the human body. These two types of homologous relationship form the basis of reasoning behind the models of musical signification
the authors present. I would call the former type sonic anaphone in that
there is a homologous relationship between the sound heard and what the
same listener feels or understands, in sonic terms, by that sound.34 The latter type I would call either a tactile or kinetic anaphone, depending on
whether the overriding perception was one of touch or movement, and assuming that the authors have not entered the realm of bio-acoustic universals.35 There are three main problems with this effective reduction of
musical signification.
Firstly, I am unclear as to whether the authors are in fact concerned with
bio-acoustic universals and as to where, if at all, they think a line can be
drawn between, at one end of the scale, the response of the nervus vagus
under sedation36 and, at the other end, experiencing a brook with its rural
connotations on hearing the piano accompaniment to Wohin? from Schuberts Die schne Mllerin, or identifying a B52 bomber and feeling indignation at the carpet bombing of Vietnam on hearing Jimi Hendrix play The
Stars and Stripes at Woodstock in 1968. In other words, some guidelines as
to where bio-acoustics stop and musical meaning starts, a distinction essential to any theory of primary signification, should have been provided.
Secondly, although it is clear that musical sounds can be homologous with
sensations of touch and movement (e.g. smooth and wavy, rough and
jerky), it is dubious whether such synaesthetic or, rather, transmodal homologies are necessarily iconic.37 According to (my reading of) Peircean
semiotics, where the concept originated, icons are, in simple terms, those
signs sharing physical traits in common with what they stand for or stand
as. Thus, while the sound of a recording of an Alsatian dog barking will usually be identified in terms like its a big dog, that same sound is in fact iconic
only to the extent that it is structurally and physically similar to that of a
large dog barking in a similar way, i.e. the recorded sound is an icon of a
physically similar sound. However, the relationship between the same recorded sound and large dog is indexical, not iconic, because there is no similarity of physical structure between that bark and the dog in its entirety. The
notion of dog obtained from hearing the recorded bark relies instead on (i)
previous knowledge that such barking sounds issue almost exclusively from
large dogs, (ii) acceptance of the synecdoche that the mere sound of a dog
barking, without representation of its snout, paws, tail, habits, character,
34. Anaphone, analogous with the word analogy (= another way of saying the same thing),
simply means another way of sounding the same thing. Anaphones can be sonic (musical
sounds resembling sounds outside music), tactile (musical sounds resembling sensations
of touch), or kinetic (musical sounds resembling patterns of movement). For a more
detailed account or musical sign types, see Tagg (1992).
35. For discussion of musical universals, see Hood (1990), Imberty (1990), Tagg (1993) and
Marconi (1996).
36. It is not a good idea to drop a metal tray of instruments during brain surgery because the
nervus vagus may react to the sound and make the patients body move.
37. Transmodal = transferred from one sense mode (e.g. sound) to another (e.g. touch,
vision).
14
etc., can represent dog in its entirety. Other plausible canine attributes derivable from the same bark, such as big teeth, dogs breath or danger (or
the nobility of a mans best friend), lie at other levels of indexicality thanks
to further links of causality or proximity. Applying these points of semiotic
terminology to a well-known musical example, the relationship of the sound
of the pianists semiquaver arpeggiations in Schuberts Die schne Mllerin
to brook are much less iconic than that of the recorded sound of a barking
dog to dog, because, as Rsing (1977) has shown, there is very little demonstrable physical similarity between such highly stylised musicalisations
of brooks and the sounds of appropriate brooks recorded and analysed for
purposes of comparison. Nevertheless, since a culturally definable population is able to identify physical similarities between the sound of the piano
arpeggiations and a small but significant subset of sonic properties belonging to certain types of brook small, contiguous, ceaselessly overlapping
sonic events in quick succession inside the middle pitch range of audibility
and forming repeated patterns of short duration , that part of the semiotic
equation may be qualifiable as iconic. However, empirical evidence suggests
that what sonically constitutes the kind of babbling (as of a brook) perceptible in the sounds of the Schubert piano arpeggiations is also iconically relatable to, for example, fluttering (as of sails) or rustling (as of leaves).38
The iconicity of the Schubert sounds in relation to brook is therefore as ambiguous as it is incomplete. At the same time, other essential, non-sonic,
physical and corporeally experienceable attributes of apposite brooks, such
as cold and wet, are absent, while their culturally specific connotations of
idyllic rurality are of an unequivocally indexical character. Of course, Shepherd and Wicke are at liberty to redefine whatever terms they like and to
extend widely accepted notions of iconicity to include non-arbitrary signification that exhibits no demonstrable similarity of physical structure, as in
the case of transmodal homologies (tactile and kinetic anaphones). However, such revision of conventional wisdom at such a basic level of semiotic
theory cannot be taken for granted and the authors should have explained
such idiosyncrasies of terminology.
Thirdly, even if, with the terminological sleight of hand just discussed, the
authors extend the concept of iconicity to cover all types of structural homology in music, no other musical sign type seems to enter into their field
of vision or hearing. Episodic markers, style indicators and genre synecdoches,39 in all their possible forms and functions, are far more indexically
than iconically constituted, and are all omitted from discussion. There is no
room in this review to account for these complex aspects of musical signification, but if, as I would argue, episodic markers, style indicators and genre
synecdoches are each as important as anaphones (structural homologies) in
the mediation of musical meaning, then readers must resort to trust and
good will if they are to accept the authors quite generalised theories of musical signification.
It was in this spirit of good will that I earnestly hoped to find nuggets of wisdom in the book. I was delighted to register two related areas in which I felt
that Shepherd and Wicke had managed to provide insights into music: (i)
38. The semantic field covered by such musical gesture is the topic of detailed discussion in an
analysis of The Dream of Olwen in Ten Little Title Tunes, forthcoming research report by
P Tagg and R Clarida.
39. For explanation of these terms, see Tagg (1992).
15
the relationship between language and music, (ii) the refinement of musics
semiological moment. Although the former suffers from lapses of reductionism, their argumentation, as I interpret it, about gestural consubstantiality
between the hearing of a sound in the medium of music and, put crudely in
my terms, the culturally modifiable bio-acoustic experience upon hearing it
(what the authors call sonic saddle and elements of signification) to be
both convincing and potentially useful to the development of our understanding of some important aspects of musical signification. Similarly, their
problematisation of the semiological moment within the (socialised) individual hearing music raises important questions about what it is we consider
music to be capable of communicating. This is where the final set of problems start.
In order to arrive at the presentation of their potentially productive theory
of the semiological moment, the authors resort on several occasions to an
intellectual scorched earth policy. For example, those who present ideas or
information about the nature of musical meaning by doing the anthropological dirty work of interviewing fans and musicians are discarded as irrelevant
to their project, while those who engage in the musicological and empirical
donkey work of relating musical structures (the authors medium or matter) to the connotative reception of music are branded as responsible for
making music as music a second-class citizen.
Music as music is a strange expression implying that some music is either less music or not music at all. The last time I heard it was in 1990 at
a film music symposium in Siena when Morricone, a figure of some repute
in both the popular and art music spheres, was rebuked by two professors
of musicology for being a film composer rather than a composer of music
as music.40 Clearly, these Italian musicologists had scant knowledge of Purcells, J S Bachs, Mozarts, Beethovens or Verdis ability to commute between varying types of musical signification. Through such lack of historical
perspective, the two Italian academics were unashamed to act as keepers
of the seal for an autonomous aesthetics of music (as music) in the institutions employing them to implement such an agenda. Now, I am in no way
suggesting that Shepherd and Wicke would pooh-pooh Morricone in such an
ahistorical fashion or consciously aim to propagate an autonomous aesthetics of music. It is, however, clear that their notion of music as music,
their implicit disqualification of connotative aspects of musical signification
as inferior (second-class), and their books lack of historical perspective all
bear striking resemblance to the professors grounds for disapproving of
Morricone who, as a film composer, must work with overtly connotative elements of musical signification. The two Italians and our two authors seem
to agree that this kind of making or thinking about music is suspect. It is in
this way that Shepherd and Wicke set up false states of antagonistic contradiction between types of musical signification that are integral and complementary rather than rankable as primary and secondary in a theoretical
hierarchy. The authors preoccupation with primary signification, in my
mind a nebulous concept which became even more elusive by reading their
book, may be justifiable, but answers to questions about musical meaning
are far more likely to be found in integration than in antagonistic confrontation with other types of signification. For example, reverting to the Schubert
40. I vividly recall the attack of these dumbfounded musicologists as they formulated the desperate rhetorical question C la musica di film e c la musica musica, no?
16
17
body, but also with the entire sociocultural field of which music is an inextricable part. In short, although the authors unequivocally state in the final
chapter that such integration is their intention, and although the external
world is at least featured in their theoretical model, large parts of the book
set a very different agenda, more specifically one which facilitates the institutionalisation of popular music (as music) in accordance with, rather than
in opposition to, the ideological rules of the game. This contradiction and the
problems discussed earlier, together with some linguistic and terminological
faux-pas, unnecessarily jeopardise what I believe to be the potential viability
of the authors theoretical models.42 Nevertheless, readers surviving the
books first three quarters may be able to glean some useful ideas from its
last quarter. In particular, some aspects of the distinction between language
and music, as well as the authors theories of the semiological moment,
may prove to be innovative contributions to the discussion of musical signification if they are given some empirical grounding.
Summing up this review, I am regrettably unable, for the following reasons,
to recommend the book to any substantial readership. It cannot work as an
undergraduate text on account of the esoteric language and convoluted style
of writing. I cannot recommend it to postgraduates due to shortcomings in
terms of subject restriction, definitions, terminology, reductionism and semiotic theory. I also fear that very few musicians and music educators will accept ideas from a book about music which contains no substantial reference
to music nor to the experience of music. Finally, I am not convinced that the
book provides a satisfactory account of cultural theory relevant to musicology, while I am as sure as I am troubled that the picture of musicology presented in the book for the edification of cultural theorists is not so much
incomplete as downright misleading. I am truly disheartened at having to
summarise my opinions in these terms because it is clear that the book is
the result of much hard work and because the good ideas contained within
it are so obscured by its problems.
42. Further difficulties of comprehension concern two areas: (i) what to a musicologist seems
to be a Cultural Theory propensity for constructing abstract nouns from past participles,
such as connectedness, relatedness, embeddedness, words whose meaning I can only
guess; (ii) terms and phrases whose meanings are neither defined nor comprehensible
from the context, or which are used in different ways on different occasions. For example,
I still have no idea what technology of articulation, musics internal characteristics or
the continually unfolding sound-image, all apparently important to the books main theory, actually mean. Nor do my dictionary or I agree with the authors implied definition of
cognition and cognitive. Particularly obscure is the authors multifarious use of conceptual hierarchies. Readers are apparently expected to distinguish between all the following
rankings: first and second order actions; first, second and third order awareness;
first and second semiology; primary and secondary processes (of cognition); primary
and secondary use of language, not to mention primary and secondary signification.
Less prejudicial to comprehension but important to the establishment of popular music as
an area of scholarly enquiry is the consistent misspelling of timbral (adjectival derivative
of timbre) as timbrel. If adjectives deriving from centre and genre are central or
centric (not centrel), and general or generic (not genrel), then there is no reason
why the adjectival suffix for timbre should take the -el form of nominal suffixes like personnel or colonel. Even if timbral (sometimes timbric) is a relatively new word coined
by popular music scholars, it has been in use for some time in our subject. In short, the
scholarly credibility of popular music studies is not enhanced by inability to follow satisfactory orthographic practices established by precedent in our own area as well as in written
English as a whole. One the other hand, the misspelling of immanent (inherent) as imminent (overhanging) and the enthusiastic tautology corporeal and somatic are no more
than minor blunders of the kind found in almost any text, including this review.
18
ASSAFIEV, Boris. 1976. Die musikalische Form als Proze. 1976, Berlin: Verlag neue
1990. Sounding the Mainstream. An Analysis of the Songs Performed in the Swedish Eurovision Song Contest Semi-Finals 1959-1983. Popular Music Research
(ed. K Roe & U Karlsson): 121-132. Gteborg: NORDICOM.
1992. Music video and the semiotics of popular music. Secondo convegno europeo di analisi musicale (ed. R Dalmonte & M Baroni): 379-388. Trento: Univer-
19
EGGEBRECHT, Hans-Heinrich. 1977. Funktionale Musik. Musikalisches Denken: 153192. Wilhelmshaven: Heinrichshofen: 153-192.
EISLER, Hanns. 1973. Musik und Politik, 1 (ed. G Mayer). Leipzig: VEB DVfM.
FABBRI, Franco. 1982. A Theory of Musical Genres. Popular Music Perspectives (ed. D
1997. Il Rasa del suono. Musica/Realt, 53: 53-64 [The surface of sound].
IMBERTY, Michel. 1976. Le problme de la mdiation smantique en psychologie de la
musique. Versus Quaderni di studi semiotici, 13:35-48.
IMBERTY, Michel. 1990. La psychologie cognitive, peut-elle contribuer au dbat sur les
universaux musicaux? La musica come linguaggio universale (ed. R Pozzi): 113132. Firenze: Leo S Olschki [Can cognitive psychology contribute to the debate
about musical universals?].
JAKOBSON, Roman. 1976. Six leons sur le son et le sens. Paris: ditions de Minuit.
JAMESON, Frederic. 1981 The Political Unconscious. Narrative as a Socially Symbolic
Act. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
JIRNEK, Jaroslav. 1981. Semantische Analyse der Musik. Die Zeichen (ed. H W
20
KLINGFORS, Gunno. 1991. Bach gr igen: kllkritiska studier i J S Bachs uppfrandepraxis. Gteborg: Skrifter frn Musikvetenskapliga institutionen [The return of
Bach: source critical studies of performance practice].
KRSESS, Gunther.1993. Against arbitrariness: the social production of the sign as a foundational issue in critical discourse analysis. Discourse & Society , 4/2: 169-192.
KRETZSCHMAR, Hermann. 1919. Fhrer durch den Konzertsaal. Leipzig: Peters.
KRISTEVA, Julia. 1990. Valda verk (ed. E Witt-Brattstrm). Stockholm: Natur och Kultur.
Translation of Stabat Mater from Histoires damour. Paris: Denol, 1983.
LEHURAY, Peter and DAY, James (eds.). 1988. Music and Aesthetics in the Eighteenth
and Early Nineteenth Centuries. Cambridge University Press.
LESCHE, Carl. On Psychophysical Measurement. Svensk tidskrift fr musikforskning,
53: 93-106.
LACASSE, Serge. 1995. Une analyse des rapports texte-musique dans Digging In The
Dirt de Peter Gabriel. MA diss. Qubec: cole de musique, Facult des Arts, Universit Laval.
LIDOV, David. 1987. Mind and body in music. Semiotica, 66/3: 69-97.
LING, Jan. 1983. Europas musikhistoria -1730. 1983, Uppsala: Esselte.
1985. The Sociology of Music. Canadian University Music Review, 1984/5: 1-16.
1989. Musik som klassisk konst. En 1700-talsid som blev klassisk. Frihetens
former en vnbok till Sven-Eric Liedman: 171-187. Lund: Arkiv [Music as classical art. An 18th century idea that became a classic].
1992. From empfindsamer style to down-home village nostalgia. Secondo convegno europeo di analisi musicale (ed R Dalmonte & M Baroni): 321-340. Trento:
Universit degli studi.
LISSA, Zofia. 1973. Ebenen des musikalischen Verstehens. Musik und Verstehen (ed. P
Faltin). Kln: Gerig [Levels of musical understanding].
LOMAX, Alan. 1978. Folk Song Style and Culture. New Brunswick: Transaction (1st publ.
1968).
LOTHMAN, Juri. 1977. Filmens semiotik. Stockholm: Pan / Nordstedts [The semiotics of
film].
MARCONI, Luca. 1996. Gli universali e il concetto di musica. PUM 9: 87-95 [Universals
and the concept of music].
MARCONI, Luca and STEFANI, Gino (eds.). 1987. Il senso in musica. Antologia di semiotica musicale. Bologna: CLUEB [Meaning in music. An anthology of music semiotics].
MARTHY, Jnos. 1974. Music and the Bourgeois, Music and the Proletarian. Budapest:
Akadmiai Kiad.
Ritmo e rito. 1995. Dagli schemi comportamentali alle strutture musicali. Musica/
Realt, 47: 95-108 [Rhythm and rite. From behavioural patterns to musical structures].
MCCLARY, Susan & WALSER, Robert. 1990. Start Making Sense: Musicology Wrestles with
Rock. On Record (ed. S Frith & A Goodwin): 277-292. London: Routledge.
MELLERS, Wilfrid. 1980. Bach and the Dance of God. London: Faber.
MELLERS, Wilfrid and HARMAN, Alec. 1962. Man and his Music. London: Barrie & Rockliff.
MERRIAM, Alan P. 1964. The Anthropology of Music. Evanston: Northwestern University
Press.
MERSENE, Marin. 1963. Harmonie universelle. Paris (reprint of 1936 version of original
1636 text).
MONELLE, Raymond. 1992. Linguistics and Semiotics in Music. Chur: Harwood Academic.
MORRIS Charles. 1938. Foundations of a Theory of Signs. Chicago University Press.
MOZART, Leopold. 1756. Grundliche Violinschule, I. Salzburg. Cited in Klingfors (1991).
NETTL, Bruno. 1964. Theory and Method in Ethnomusicology. London: Collier-Macmillan.
NKETIA, J H Kwabena. 1974. The Music of Africa. New York: Norton.
PEIRCE, Charles Sanders. 1934-48. Collected Papers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
RAYNOR, Henry. 1978. A Social History of Music. New York: Taplinger.
ROBINSON, Jenefer (ed.). 1997. Music and Meaning. Ithaca & London: Cornell University
21
Press.
1993. Universal music and the case of death. Critical Quarterly, 35/2: 54-85.
1996. Popular music versus the Other. Paper delivered at symposium Music
and Life-world. Otherness and Transgression in the Culture of the 20th Century,
Cascais, 1996.
TAMLYN, Garry. 1991. Anarchy in the UK. A test study of Philip Taggs Affect Analysis
in relation to Punk Rock. MA diss. Sydney: Department of Music, University of
New South Wales.
1985. Music as sign and process. Analytica. Studies in the Description and
Analysis of Music: 97-116. Stockholm: Kungliga Musikaliska Akademien.
1987. Some Peircean and Greimasian Semiotic Concepts as Applied to Music. The
Semiotic Web 1986. Basic Concepts of Studies in Musical Signification: 445459. Berlin, New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
1990. Semiotics as a Common Language of Musicology. La musica come linguaggio universale (ed. R Pozzi): 133-150. Firenze: Leo S. Olschki.
THEODORAKIS, Mikis. 1971. Journals of Resistance. London: Hart-Davis, MacGibbon (first
published by Flammarion, Paris 1971).
TREITLER, Leo. 1997. Language and the Interpretation of Music. Music and Meaning (ed.
J Robinson): 23-56. Ithaca (NY) and London: Cornell University Press.
VEGA, Carlos. 1941. La msica populr argentina, tomo II: fraseloga. Buenos Aires:
Facultad de Filosofia y Letras de la Universidad de Buenos Aires.
WALKER, Daniel P (ed) 1978. Studies in Musical Science in the Late Renaissance. London: Studies of the Warburg Institute, 37.
WEBER, Max. 1969. The Rational and Social Foundations of Music. Carbondale (IL). First
publ 1922 as Die rationalen und soziologischen Grundlagen der Musik (Tbingen).