Personal Identity
Personal Identity
Personal Identity
INTRODUCTION
The term personal identity' means different things to different people. Psychologists
use it to refer to a person's self-image--to one's beliefs about the sort of person one
is and how one differs from others. In philosophy the term normally refers to
philosophical questions about ourselves that arise by virtue of our being people,
questions that may otherwise have little in common. Some philosophers use the
term more loosely and include such topics as the nature of self-knowledge, selfdeception, rationality, and the will. This entry covers personal identity in the stricter
sense.
GENERAL OVERVIEWS
Penelhum 1967 and Perry 2008 are good but a bit dated. The others are reliable
guides to current debates. The encyclopedia articles by Garrett 1998 and **Olson
2008** survey the field; DeGrazia 2005 approaches the subject from an ethicist's
perspective.
TEXTBOOKS
Shoemaker and Swinburne 1984 is a classic. Perry's 1978's dialogue covers the
same themes in a witty and entertaining way. Noonan 2003 is a systematic treatise
in the traditional style and has near-definitive status. Shoemaker 2009 is a good
guide to the intersection of metaphysics and ethics. Garrett 1998, though not strictly
a textbook, is accessible enough to be used as one.
Garrett, B. (1998). Personal Identity and Self-Consciousness, London: Routledge.
A partisan but highly readable discussion of identity over time, what matters
practically, and first-person reference.
Noonan, H. (2003). Personal Identity, 2e, London and New York: Routledge.
A comprehensive and masterly work, with important original contributions. Most
undergraduates will it hard going, but for the adept it is indispensable. The new
2
BIBLIOGRAPHIES
**PhilPapers** is the best place to look for recent items; Kolak and Martin 1991 is a
valuable source of material up to about 1990.
Kolak, D. and R. Martin (eds.). (1991). Self and Identity, New York: Macmillan.
This collection includes an enormous bibliography, sadly now rather out of date. It
construes personal identity very broadly.
*PhilPapers: Personal Identity [http://philpapers.org/browse/personal-identity]*.
Maintained by David Bourget and David Chalmers.
Not strictly a bibliography but a compendium of online sources. Coverage is
patchy and some information is inaccurate, but very useful nonetheless. Items of
all ages are constantly being added.
ANTHOLOGIES
Martin and Barresi 2002 is the only up-to-date collection of previously published
work by more than one author. Perry 2008, the most widely used anthology, is
useful mainly for its historical sources. Perry 2002 is a valuable collection of his
own papers. Of the collections of new work, Rorty 1976 is indispensable, with
important contributions by all the big names of its day. Dancy 1997 is also first rate,
though devoted only partly to personal identity. Paul, et al. 2005, Petrus 2003, and
3
HISTORICAL SOURCES
Most of the big names of Western philosophy had something to say about some
aspect of personal identity. This list is restricted to the items that most influence
current debates, many of which are conveniently collected in Perry's anthology
Personal Identity (see *Anthologies*). Throughout much of history debates focused
on whether we are material or immaterial, mortal or immortal, Plato 1997 being the
most famous example. Personal identity over time in general became a major
theme only with Locke 1975; Butler 2008 and Reid 1941 criticize his view. Hume
1978 and Kant 1997, in different ways, are skeptical about the metaphysics of
personal identity.
Butler, J. (2008). The Analogy of Religion, Appendix.
Argues that memory cannot constitute personal identity because it presupposes
identity, and contrasts the strict philosophical identity of people with the loose and
popular identity of other things. Original work 1736. Also in Perry 2008.
Hume, D. (1978). A Treatise of Human Nature, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Book 1, Part 4, Section 2, pp. 199-210 argues that nothing can survive any
change whatever, and section 6, pp. 251-263, makes the famous claim that each
of us is nothing but a bundle of perceptions. The Appendix has a section on
personal identity at pp. 633-636. A difficult but enormously influential source.
Original work 1739. Partly reprinted in Perry 2008.
Kant, I. (1997). Critique of Pure Reason, P. Guyer, A. Wood (trs.), Cambridge
University Press.
The Paralogisms (A341-405 and B436-432) argue that we cannot know, either a
priori or on the basis of introspection, that we are substances, that we are
mereologically simple, or that we persist through time. Very difficult. Original work
1781 and 1787.
Locke, J. (1975). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, P. Nidditch (ed.),
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Book 2, chapter 28, Of Identity and Diversity' (added in the second edition), is the
point of departure for modern discussions of personal identity, and the source of
psychological-continuity accounts. The text is notoriously baffling, and scholars
debate what view Locke meant to endorse. Original work 1694. Partly reprinted in
Perry 2008.
Plato. (1997). Phaedo, G. M. A. Grube (tr.), in Complete Works, J. Cooper (ed.),
Indianapolis: Hackett.
Socrates' discussion of death on the night of his execution. The arguments for the
5
PSYCHOLOGICAL-CONTINUITY ACCOUNTS
The view that we persist by virtue of some sort of psychological continuity has
dominated debates on personal identity since Locke. The unifying idea is that a
being existing at another time is you if and only its mental states or capacities then
depend causally in some way on your current states or capacities, or vice versa.
There is debate over the details: for instance about whether our mental states have
to be continuously physically realized for us to persist, as Johnston 1987,
Shoemaker 1997, and Unger 1990 argue, or whether other sorts of causal
dependence suffice, as Shoemaker 1984 claims. Van Inwagen 1997 attacks
Shoemaker 1984's view, while Olson 1997 objects to psychological-continuity
views of all sorts. Noonan 1998 and Shoemaker 2008 defend psychologicalcontinuity views against these objections. Williams 1970 is a classic critical
discussion influencing all later authors.
Johnston, M. (1987). Human Beings. Journal of Philosophy 84, 59-83.
Criticizes the method of cases commonly used in arguing about personal identity
and advocates a physically qualified psychological-continuity view. Reprinted in
J. Kim and E. Sosa, eds., Metaphysics: An Anthology, Oxford: Blackwell 1999.
Olson, E. (1997). The Human Animal: Personal Identity Without Psychology, New
York: Oxford University Press.
Objects that any account of our identity over time with a psychological component
is incompatible with our being animals, raising metaphysical and epistemological
problems.
Noonan, H. (1998). Animalism Versus Lockeanism: A Current Controversy,
7
you in a way that would suffice for him or her to be you, were it not for the existence
of the other. What would happen to you then? Many respond that neither being
would be you, precisely because there are two of them. Others deny that identity
can be determined by such extrinsic factors. Parfit's Personal Identity uses
discontent with the first response to argue for the practical unimportance of identity;
but that is another topic (see *What Matters in Identity*). Heller 1987, Lewis 1976,
Noonan 2003, and Perry 1972 argue against extrinsicness, based on the view that
we are composed of temporal parts. Nozick 1981 argues in support of it, without
giving any metaphysical basis. Thomson 1987 uses fission cases to cast doubt on
psychological-continuity accounts.
Heller, M. (1987). The Best Candidate Approach to Diachronic Identity,
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65, 434-451.
Though not about personal identity per se, the paper articulates well the thought
that whether a being existing at another time is identical to one existing now
should not depend on whether there is competition.
Lewis, D. (1976). Survival and Identity, in The Identities of Persons, (ed.) A. Rorty,
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Ingenious and influential defense of the claim that one can survive division as
both resulting beings because in that case there were two of you all along.
Reprinted with postscripts in his Philosophical Papers vol. I, New York: Oxford
University Press, 1983, and in Martin and Barresi 2002.
Noonan, H. (2003). Personal Identity, 2e, London and New York: Routledge.
Ch. 7 is clear and insightful discussion of the extrinsicness debate. (This chapter
is unchanged from the first edition of 1989.)
Nozick, R. (1981). Personal Identity Through Time, in his Philosophical
Explanations, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 27-70.
The most famous defense of a best-candidate or closest-continuer theory.
Reprinted in Martin and Barresi 2002.
Perry, J. (1972). Can the Self Divide?, Journal of Philosophy 69, 463-488.
An important discussion of fission cases, advocating an interesting variant on the
usual temporal-parts account. Reprinted in Perry 2002.
Thomson. J. J. (1987). Ruminations on an Account of Personal Identity, in Thomson
(ed.), On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright, 215-240. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
A good critical discussion of psychological-continuity accounts and their
9
the bodily criterion against objections. Reprinted in his Problems of the Self.
ANTICRITERIALISM
While some argue about whether the conditions of our persistence through time are
psychological or brute physical, others doubt whether there are any such
conditions to be known. Personal identity, they say, is simple and unanalyzable. A
related question is whether our identity over time can be indeterminate (though it is
not very clear what the relation is). Chisholm 1976, Lowe 1998, Merricks 1998, and
Swinburne 1997 all argue in support of some simple view or other; Unger 1990 and
Zimmerman 1998 argue against. Yet another vaguely related topic that has to be
mentioned somewhere is reductionism, the view that our identity over time consists
in something that can be described without mentioning people. Parfit 1984
endorses it; Shoemaker 1985 finds it obscure. The entire constellation of issues is
poorly understood.
Chisholm, R. (1976). Person and Object, La Salle, IL: Open Court.
Ch. 3, especially pp. 108-113, argues that our persistence does not consist in any
conditions that we could use as evidence for it; criteria of personal identity over
time can only be epistemic. Partly reprinted in M. Rea (ed.), Material Constitution,
Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield 1997, 209-235.
Lowe, E. J. (1998). Persistence and Substance, in his The Possibility of
Metaphysics, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Argues that there must be things whose persistence is primitive and does not
consist in facts about anything else.
Merricks, T. (1998). There Are no Criteria of Identity over Time, Nos 32, 106-124.
Important argument for the claim that there is no nontrivial set of necessary and
sufficient conditions for anything, including a person, to persist.
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and Persons, Oxford University Press.
Chs. 10 and 11 are the most influential source of reductionism.
Shoemaker, S. (1985). Critical Notice of D. Parfit, Reasons and Persons, Mind 94,
443-453.
Asks what Parfitian reductionism could amount to. Reprinted in slightly abridged
form in Dancy 1997.
Swinburne, R. (1984). Personal Identity: the Dualist Theory, in Shoemaker and
Swinburne, Personal Identity.
11
PERSONAL ONTOLOGY
Personal ontology refers to the basic metaphysical nature of human people:
whether we are material or immaterial, momentary or persisting, abstract or
concrete, and so on. This has been an important recent area of research. Olson
2007 and van Inwagen 2002 survey a range of possible answers to the question,
while Baker 2000 and Hudson 2001 are book-length defenses of particular
answers. Chisholm 1989, Lowe 2001, Unger 1979, and Zimmerman 2003 argue for
very different but equally surprising views.
14
An argument in the style of Chisholm against our being material things of any
kind, based on the metaphysicals of material objects in general.
ANIMALISM
Animalism is the view that human people are biological organisms. It is generally
taken to imply that our identity over time consists in some brute physical condition
to do with biology, contrary to all psychological-continuity views. Ayers 1990, Olson
2003, and Snowdon 1990 argue in support of animalism, while van Inwagen 1990
defends it against objections. Johnston 2007 and Unger 2000 object to its
implications about our identity over time; Hudson 2007 and Olson 2007 attack it on
other metaphysical grounds.
Ayers, M. (1990). Locke, vol. 2, London: Routledge.
Ch. 19 is a fascinating discussion of animal identity; ch. 25 argues for animalism
and against Lockean views.
Hudson, H. (2007.) I Am Not an Animal!, in P. van Inwagen and D. Zimmerman
(eds.), Persons: Human and Divine, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 216-236.
A very clear critical discussion. Hudson has a good nose for metaphysical
problems and is one of animalism's ablest critics.
Johnston, M. (2007). Human Beings Revisited: My Body is not an Animal, in D.
Zimmerman (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, vol. 3, Oxford University Press.
A perceptive critical discussion of animalism with an important new objection.
Olson, E. (2003). An Argument for Animalism, in Martin, R and M. Barresi (eds.).
(2002). Personal Identity, Oxford: Blackwell.
Clear statement of the too-many-thinkers argument: because human animals
have all the psychological and behavioral features that we have, they are what we
are. Reprinted in van Inwagen and Zimmerman 2008.
Olson, E. (2007). What Are We? A Study in Personal Ontology, New York: Oxford
University Press.
Chapter 9 discusses a variety of metaphysical objections to animalism,
concluding that it may require a sparse ontology of material objects.
Snowdon, P. (1990). Persons, Animals, and Ourselves, in C. Gill (ed.), The Person
and the Human Mind, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
A perceptive argument for animalism in the Oxford style.
16
SYNCHRONIC IDENTITY
Whereas personal identity over time is about what determines whether a person
existing at one time also exists at other times, synchronic identity is about what
determines how many of us there are at any one time. This question has received
less attention than its importance might merit, and is often confused with others.
(For better or worse, the vast literature on commissurotomy and multiple personality
seldom addresses it.) Liberals, represented by Campbell and McMahan 2010,
Puccetti 1973, Rovane 1998, Wilkes 1988, and, more tentatively, Nagel 1971, say
that the number of human people can vary independently of the number of human
organisms. Conservatives deny this: Brown 2001 and van Inwagen 1990 criticize
arguments for liberal views, while Olson 2003 attacks the views themselves.
Brown, M. (2001). Multiple Personality and Personal Identity, Philosophical
Psychology 14, 435-47.
Argues that multiple personality can be explained in terms of failure of
autobiographical memory and is of no metaphysical import, and attempts to
diagnose the attraction of liberal views.
Campbell, T. and J. McMahan. (2010). Animalism and the Varieties of Conjoined
Twinning, Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 31: 285-301.
Argues that the number of people in cases of conjoined twins is inconsistent with
any familiar account of what we are, and in particular with our being organisms.
Nagel, T. (1971). Brain Bisection and the Unity of Consciousness. Synthse 22,
396-413.
Influential but inconclusive paper about whether commissurotomy creates two
conscious beings within a single organism. Reprinted in his Mortal Questions,
Cambridge University Press 1979, and in Perry 2008 (see *Anthologies*).
Olson, E. (2003). Was Jekyll Hyde? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
17
66: 328-348.
Argues that it is metaphysically impossible for two or more people to share a
single human being owing to multiple personality.
Puccetti, R. 1973. Brain Bisection and Personal Identity, British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science 24, 339-355.
Argues that lack of coordination between cerebral hemispheres implies that there
are two people within every normal human being.
Rovane, C. 1998. The Bounds of Agency, Princeton University Press.
Argues that the number of people at a given time is determined by facts about the
unity of agency. Human beings who cooperate can make up a group person (and
fail to be people themselves), while a disunified human being can be the home of
several people.
van Inwagen, P. (1990). Material Beings, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Section 12 argues that no amount of psychological disunity, even the possession
of two separate organs of thought, implies the existence of two thinking beings.
Wilkes, K. (1988). Real People: Personal Identity Without Thought Experiments,
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Chapters 4 and 5 are careful discussions of the scientific literature on multiple
personality and commissurotomy, respectively.
PERSONHOOD
What is it to be a person? What is necessary, and what suffices, for something to
count as a person, as opposed to a nonperson? What have we people (or persons)
got that nonpeople haven't got? The question acquires much of its interest from the
consideration of difficult cases. Could a rational parrot be a person, as Locke
thought? An intelligent computer (if there could be such a thing)? At what point in
our development do we ourselves become people? Baker 2000, Dennett 1976,
and Frankfurt 1971 argue that to be a person is (roughly) to have certain
psychological capacities. Wiggins 1980 objects to this, and Snowdon 1996
criticizes his proposal. Wilkes 1988 discusses the personhood of infants and
foetuses. Strawson 1959 and Ayer 1964 are mainly concerned with what sort of
thing could be a subject of thought and consciousness.
Ayer, A. J. (1964). The Concept of a Person, in his The Concept of a Person and
Other Essays, London: Macmillan.
A wide-ranging critical discussion of Strawson.
18
19