University of California Press American Musicological Society
University of California Press American Musicological Society
University of California Press American Musicological Society
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
University of California Press and American Musicological Society are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to Journal of the American Musicological Society.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Reviews 169
The End of Early Music: A Period Performers History of Music for the Twenty-
First Century, by Bruce Haynes. Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press, 2007. xix, 284 pp.
The premise underlying Bruce Hayness book is that a paradigm shift in how
musicians understand and interpret older Western compositions began during
the 1960s and 1970s. In thirteen chapters (grouped into five parts), Haynes
characterizes three broad currents in the performance of early music during
the twentieth century as Romantic, Modern, and Period (p. 32; the terms
are always capitalized). Against these Haynes postulates a Rhetorical style
that was prevalent during the eighteenth century. Haynes argues, with wit and
passion, that restoration of this Rhetorical style has made it possible for certain
present-day performers to achieve a type of historical authenticity. But the
meaning of this last term never becomes clear, and the argument is weakened
by haphazard organization, as well as an impoverished sense of what history is
and how it might relate to musical performance. Following the delineation of
the three styles in the first part, part 2 considers the changing relationships
between composers, works, and performance during the later eighteenth
and nineteenth centuries. This section analyzes popular concepts of work
and performance and lays the ground for part 3 on Anachronism and
Authenticity. Part 4 delineates aspects of Baroque performance practice that
Haynes considers important for achieving Rhetorical style, and part 5 summa-
rizes the authors view that present-day performers of early music should
adopt what he considers authentic Rhetorical approaches, freeing themselves
from the continuing influence of Modern style.
Part 5 shares its title The End of Early Music with the book as a
wholeapart from the the quotes on early, which should not be dismissed
as scare quotes but rather as signaling that the word here has a special
meaning. But that meaning remains elusive, nor is it clear whether the double
entendre in the title is intended: is the end of early music its demise or its
purpose? Early music itself is never defined as a repertoire, discipline, or
culture, though it is each of these at different points in the discussion.
Chronologically, Haynes looks back no further than Lully, and the only
compositions considered in depth are ensemble works of the late Baroque,
particularly those of J. S. Bach. Haynes defines his three twentieth-century
performance styles mainly by association: Romantic style with canonism,
Modern style with strait playing, Period style with rhetoric. Strait play-
ing (from straitjacket) is a play on what Richard Taruskin called straight
style;1 a more or less synonymous expression is click-track Baroque, derived
1. Haynes cites Taruskin from a review reprinted as The Crooked Straight, and the Rough
Places Plain in Taruskins Text and Act: Essays on Music and Performance (New York and Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1995), 31620where the reference is to straight performers, not
style.
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
170 Journal of the American Musicological Society
2. Whether the latter goes back specifically to Sol Babitz, as Haynes indicates, is unclear. The
expression does occur in the article by Babitz that Haynes cites (p. 57, referring to Early Music
Laboratory Bulletin 11 [1974]), but it is on p. 28, not p. 8. Babitz also compared Wanda
Landowskas harpsichord playing to a sewing machine in a letter published in the New York
Review of Books (11 March 1965).
3. Haynes evidently reached this view after his attendance at the Fifty-Ninth Annual Meeting
of the American Musicological Society in Montreal, November 1993.
4. Haynes (p. 107) cites Clive Brown, Classical and Romantic Performing Practice, 1750
1900 (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 30ff. and 234 [sic]; only the lat-
ter page is relevant to Mendelssohns view.
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Reviews 171
5. Haynes (p. 174) cites Cicero from M. H. Abramss famous The Mirror and the Lamp:
Romantic Theory and the Critical Tradition (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1953), 71; the text in question reads: ut enim nulla materies tam facilis ad exardescendum est,
quae nisi admoto igni ignem concipere possit, sic nulla mens est tam ad comprehendendam vim
oratoris parata, quae possit incendi, nisi ipse inflammatus ad eam et ardens accesserit (For just as
no substance is so capable of catching fire, to produce flame without the application of flame [a
spark], so no mind is so prepared to grasp the power of a speaker, to be able to burn, unless the
speaker comes to that mind himself inflamed with passion); De orat. 2.190. Carl Dahlhaus, in
Si vis me flere . . ., Die Musikforschung 25 (1972): 5152, pointed out, in addition, a
Horatian parallel to the admonitions of Quantz and Bach: Si vis me flere, dolendum est primum
ipsi tibi (If you would have me weep, first you must grieve); Ars poet., 102.
6. Against Mengelbergs legendary performance of the Saint Matthew Passion Towe sets an
earlier one by Siegfried Ochs; see Present-day Misconceptions about Bach Performance Practice
in the Nineteenth Century: The Evidence of the Recordings, in A Bach Tribute: Essays in Honor
of William H. Scheide, ed. Paul Brainard and Ray Robinson, 22131 (Kassel: Brenreiter, 1993),
at 223.
7. The Akademie fr Alte Musik Berlin is represented by a sample from their 1995 recording
of Bachs Air on the G String (BWV 1068/2) (Harmonia Mundi HMX 2908074.77).
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
172 Journal of the American Musicological Society
greater dynamic variation, but this is partly a matter of its audio engineering
and larger ensemble, and its online excerpt simply plays louder than Rifkins.
The differences between the recordings are real, but in none of Hayness Bach
clipsnot even one featuring his own playing (he has had a long career as
maker and player of early oboes)do I hear the unpredictability or spon-
taneity that he considers crucial to the Rhetorical style.
For Haynes, rhetoric is the key element that was lacking in Romantic,
Modern, and early Period performance. But an index entry for Rhetoric, de-
fined, takes one only to a definition of Rhetorical music, which is glossed,
not very helpfully, as music made when musical Rhetoric was valued and
used (p. 15). Hayness source for rhetorical as denominating a whole ap-
proach to music is Nikolaus Harnoncourt, whose 1982 collection of essays
and talks bears the title Music as Rhetoric.8 But neither author gives the de-
tailed analysis of musical texts and practices that would be necessary to
demonstrate that a Baroque work, or some way of performing it, resembles
actual verbal rhetoric.9 If a song by Machaut, Schubert, or Elliott Carter is any
less rhetorical than one by Lambert or Telemann, neither Haynes nor
Harnoncourt tells us how. Yet both authors imply that use of historical prac-
tices will insure that a performance of music by one of the two latter com-
posers will be somehow rhetorical. These practices presumably include the
devices of articulation and ornamentation that Haynes discusses in part 4;
familiar subjects in writings on Baroque performance, these are rhetorical
only metaphorically. Indeed, as Haynes writes, some things described by
Greek and Latin names that sound like diseaseshe mentions parrhesia,
the use of unfamiliar dissonancesturn out to be familiar Baroque orna-
ments, like the appoggiatura (p. 188). This is to admit that the rhetorical
aspect of such things is largely nominal.10
Looming behind Hayness Modern style is Taruskins idea of a literalistic
twentieth-century approach to performance heavily influenced by modernist
composition, especially Stravinskian neo-Classicism. But Haynes also delin-
eates a trend toward anti-Modernism in recent performances (p. 61); for
8. Nikolaus Harnoncourt, Musik als Klangrede: Wege zu einem neuen Musikverstndnis; Essays
und Vortrge (Salzburg: Residenz, 1982), trans. Mary ONeill as Baroque Music Today: Music as
Speech; Ways to a New Understanding of Music (Portland, OR: Amadeus, 1988).
9. Haynes does cite (p. 167) a work that includes just such an analysis: Patricia M. Ranum,
The Harmonic Orator: The Phrasing and Rhetoric of the Melody in French Baroque Airs (N.p.:
Pendragon, 2001). Harnoncourt mentions English funerals and French tombeaux of the seven-
teenth and eighteenth centuries as instrumental genres modeled on a specific sort of rhetorical ex-
ercise, here the funeral oration (Grabrede); the idea was subsequently fleshed out in Clemens
Goldberg, Stilisierung als kunstvermittelnder Prozess: Die franzsischen Tombeau-Stcke im 17.
Jahrhundert (Laaber: Laaber-Verlag, 1987).
10. On this issue, see especially Peter Williams, The Snares and Delusions of Musical
Rhetoric: Some Examples from Recent Writings on J. S. Bach, in Alte Musik: Praxis und
Reflexion, ed. Peter Reidemeister and Veronika Gutmann, 23040 (Winterthur, Switzerland:
Amadeus, 1983).
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Reviews 173
Haynes, this bears out the familiar idea that Baroque performance had some-
thing in common with jazz. Parallels between the two styles, however, lie at a
high level of abstraction. It is easy to imagine that Baroque musicians some-
times performed with the exuberance heard in the Grapelli-South recording.11
But the latter reduces Bachs complex phrasing and harmony to a recurring
four-bar pattern, effectively converting a fugal ritornello form into a chaconne.
This is less startling than it might have been seventy years ago, now that it
has become commonplace for early-music performers to improvise actual
chaconnes. But such improvisation must be remote from what one heard in
eighteenth-century performances of music by Bach, or even Telemann.
It is probably no coincidence that twentieth-century composers were ex-
ploring improvisation at the same time that it became interesting to perform-
ers of early music. Yet Carter, explaining his decision not to incorporate
improvisation into his own compositions, reported: Ive always had the im-
pression of improvisation of the most rewarding kind when good performers
take the trouble to play music that is carefully written out as if they were
thinking it up themselves while they played it.12 Haynes admits as much,
observing that the best performers of written music give the illusion that they
are improvising (since to read mechanically is the kiss of death) (p. 209). For
Haynes, then, what really matters is that one not perform mechanicallylike
a trained bird, as C. P. E. Bach famously put it.13
For Haynes, Modern and early Period performance indeed was mechani-
cal, a failing that he traces to nineteenth-century canonism and the tyranny
of the conductor. Both evils are exaggerated, however. Haynes asserts that
seventeenth- and eighteenth-century music was not meant to be heard re-
peatedly (p. 84). Yet Frescobaldis keyboard works and Corellis violin
sonatas were reprinted and copied into manuscripts for more than a century
after the first publication of each; were they any less canonic than were
Beethoven symphonies and certain Schubert songs for the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries? In some repertories, musicians surely did become tools of
a conductor who makes the players aware of the hidden intentions of the
composer as the German cantor Johann Samuel Petri put it already in the
11. Haynes identifies his audio sample no. 52 as the swing version, but it is actually a
portion of the Improvisation sur le Premire [sic] Mouvement du Concerto en r mineur de
Jean-Sbastien Bach recorded two days later; for a transcription, see Benjamin Givan, The
South-Grappelli Recordings of the Bach Double Violin Concerto, Popular Music and Society 29
(2006): 34151. According to Givan, the Swing Interpretation, released on the opposite side
of the same ten-inch disk, had disappointed the producer for the lack of improvisation involved; at
this writing it is accessible at http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=gQZw3nema0Q (consulted
12 December 2009).
12. Allen Edwards, Flawed Words and Stubborn Sounds: A Conversation with Elliott Carter
(New York: Norton, 1972), 78.
13. C. P. E. Bach, Versuch ber die wahre Art das Clavier zu spielen (Berlin, 175362), i.3.7;
trans. William J. Mitchell in Essay on the True Art of Playing Keyboard Instruments (New York:
Norton, 1949), 150.
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
174 Journal of the American Musicological Society
14. Auf die etwas knstlicher versteckten Absichten des Komponisten aber soll der Direktor
bey der Probe die Musiker aufmerksam machen, damit sie sie bald entdekken knnen. Johann
Samuel Petri, Anleitung zur praktischen Musik, 2nd ed. (Leipzig: Breitkopf, 1782; repr., Munich:
Katzbichler, 1999), 181; quoted (p. 100) from John Spitzer and Neal Zaslaw, The Birth of the
Orchestra: History of an Institution, 16501815 (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2004), 386. Haynes, following Spitzer and Zaslaw, gives the word composer in the plural, not
the singular; he neglects to translate the adjective knstlicher, which could mean more artistic
but could also mean more artfulreferring to things that are merely clever, or perhaps notation
that contains tricky rhythms or unfamiliar performance indications.
15. Auerdem spielt der Musiker wie die Welle in der Uhr, das heit, wie eine Maschine.
Petri, Anleitung zur praktischen Musik, 181.
16. Lydia Goehr, The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works: An Essay in the Philosophy of
Music (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 188.
17. Hayness source is Charles Seeger, Prescriptive and Descriptive Music-Writing, Musical
Quarterly 44 (1958): 18495. Harnoncourt, Baroque Music Today, 2829, distinguishes
performance-notation from work-notation, the first corresponding roughly to what Seeger
might have termed the prescriptive notation of the present-day classical musician, the second to
the descriptive notation of older Western music.
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Reviews 175
But Seeger approached the topic at a higher level of abstraction than Haynes
or Harnoncourt. Seegers point was that nearly all European musical notation
has been prescriptive, in the sense of telling the musician what to do (sing, play,
etc.), rather than describing the sounds actually produced. Baroque notation
cannot be interpreted without, as Seeger put it, knowledge of the oral (or,
better, aural) tradition associated with it. But the same is true of Brahmss
notation or, for that matter, the graphic scores that Cage and others were pro-
ducing just as Seeger was making his argument for the scientific transcription
of music of all cultures. Seeger pleaded for graphic notation that plotted pitch
and other acoustic parameters against time, yet no such system can specify
with precision such parameters as the use of the damper pedal or the perceived
dynamic level of a particular note produced in a given hall.
That musical notation varies in its degree of completeness or prescriptive-
ness is uncontroversial. But it does not follow that trying to reproduce the
individual composers personal intentions is a Romantic idea. Baroque com-
posers did not expect anyone to do that (p. 114, original emphasis). What
else could Mattheson have meant when he concluded his most famous book
with the observation that one who has not heard a composer performing his
own work may fail to understand it?18 Haynes supposes that the intentions of
Mattheson and his contemporaries were limited to aspects of general style, un-
like those of later musicians. But the distinction is murky, and Matthesons
comment echoes a much older one by the Duchess of Montbliard
Frobergers pupil and last patronto the effect that only one who had heard
the composer play it could satisfactorily reproduce his Mditation sur ma mort
future.19 How does this differ from the allegedly Romantic idea that the job
of the performer is to reproduce the individual composers personal inten-
tions, at least if by intention is meant how the composer performed a work
(or wished it performed)? Of course, Baroque works directed by the com-
poser, including Bachs church pieces and Handels operas, could change
from one performance to the next. But this means only that intention might
vary from performance to performance, or, to put it another way, that certain
works were defined rather loosely (they were open, in late twentieth-
century parlance). Is this situation special to Baroque music, or is it inevitable,
to some degree, in any notated composition? I fear that Haynes has missed the
point of Goehr and others whom he cites: it is not actual Romantic music that
somehow embodied fixed intentions, but rather it was a uniquely Romantic
idea, characteristic of the idealizing or essentializing strand in nineteenth- and
18. Johann Mattheson, Der vollkommene Capellmeister (Hamburg, 1739; ed. Friederike
Ramm, Kassel: Brenreiter, 1999), 644.
19. Duchess Sibylla of Wrttemberg-Montbliard, letter of 23 October 1667 (2 November
1667, new style) to Constantijn Huygens, trans. in Rudolf Rasch, The Huygens-Froberger-
Sibylla Correspondence (16661668), in The Harpsichord and Its Repertoire: Proceedings of
the International Harpsichord Symposium, Utrecht, 1990, ed. Pieter Dirksen, 23345 (Utrecht:
STIMU, 1992), at 242.
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
176 Journal of the American Musicological Society
20. McCreeshs apparently was not the first OVPP (one-voice-per-part) recording of the
St. Matthew Passion, as Haynes claims (p. 131); various websites (e.g., http://americanbach.org)
list Jeffrey Thomass live performance, recorded during the 1996 Berkeley Early Music Festival, as
having been released in 2000 on the Koch International label. Whether the Kyrie and Gloria of
the B-Minor Mass were actually performed at Dresden in 1733 is uncertain; the Credo,
Sanctus, and Agnus Dei, also recorded by Rifkin, were later additions to the work, which Bach
never performed integrally.
21. See Charles Rosen, The Benefits of Authenticity, in Critical Entertainments: Music Old
and New (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), 211; the essay, a review of Kenyon,
Authenticity and Early Music, originally appeared as The Shock of the Old, New York Review of
Books (19 July 1990). A passage about translating the sound of the past into the new sounds of
contemporary instruments, which Haynes seems to attribute to Rosen (p. 156), is actually the
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Reviews 177
latters paraphrase of something Robert Morgan had suggested. Rosen goes on to suppose that
musical composition is partly divorced from the actual realization in sound (211)but only
partly, and the revised version of the essay concludes that by taking the indefensible ideal of
authenticity seriously . . . our knowledge has been increased and our musical life enriched (221).
22. Robin George Collingwood, The Limits of Historical Knowledge, Journal of Philo-
sophical Studies 3 (1928): 21322, at 219.
23. See the review by Mary Oleskiewicz in Notes: Quarterly Journal of the Modern Language
Association 59 (2002): 16976, at 173. In a touch reminiscent of Nabokovs Pale Fire, the imagi-
nary composers Simonetti and Tomesini receive regular entries in Hayness index.
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
178 Journal of the American Musicological Society
DAVID SCHULENBERG
24. Joshua Rifkin, quoted by Uri Golomb, Expression and Meaning in Bach Performance
and Reception: An Examination of the B Minor Mass on Record (PhD diss., Kings College,
Cambridge, 2005; online at http://edocs.ub.uni-frankfurt.de/volltexte/2005/3077/pdf/
GolombUri.pdf ), 128, who in turn cites Rifkin, in interview with the author, November 2002.
Golomb includes this under the chapter subhead The ideal of perpetual revolution.
25. Peter Walls, History, Imagination, and the Performance of Music (Woodbridge, UK, and
Rochester, NY: Boydell Press, 2003).
This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.215 on Sat, 1 Dec 2012 19:31:51 PM
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions