Artikel Simmel Relasionisme
Artikel Simmel Relasionisme
Artikel Simmel Relasionisme
DOI 10.1007/s11016-011-9592-7
ESSAY REVIEW
Harold Kincaid
H. Kincaid (&)
Department of Philosophy, University of Alabama at Birmingham,
900 13th Street South, Birmingham, AL 35294-1260, USA
e-mail: hkincaid@me.com
123
392 Metascience (2012) 21:391394
123
Metascience (2012) 21:391394 393
enough like that we can assign a utility function to it (thus getting Pettits
consistency)? Can nation-states be usefully modeled this way for certain purposes?
Can they, as economists say, be treated as representative agents? Are individual
human being always best modeled as agents or as collections of sub-personal
agents? These judgements depend on the purposes of modeling, on how we pick out
and describe their component members, and are a matter of degree. Pettit cites
Dennetts (1991) notion of real patterns in support of his account of agency, but as I
read Dennett, I would see him endorsing real patterns as matters of degree (they can
compress more or less information) and overlapping in various ways (Rosss (2000)
rainforest realism) that is quite at odds with the project of deciding on
philosophical grounds what an agent is and then deciding what gets the title.
Papineau grapples with the question of whether there are laws in the social
sciences and takes it that a proper physicalism makes that unlikely. That makes it
different from the other sciences. Only if the social sciences invoke selectional
mechanisms or can find uniform physical mechanisms will they make the grade.
The anti-naturalism comes in ignoring what the other sciences are really like
(philosophers of biology generally doubt there is much in the way of laws in real
biology) and from using a philosophical doctrine with a specific twist to try to
decide what the social sciences cannot do. There are other variants of physicalism
with less reductive implications. Not surprisingly, no real social science is
discussed. The two respected social scientists that comment on the chapter rightfully
on my view find the chapter unhelpful philosophical reductionism.
The other chapters in the book by Mitchell on complexity, biology and social
science, Little on recent developments in social science that are as much philosophy
of the social sciences, Cartwright on the limits of Randomized Clinical Trials
(RTCs), Mantzavinos on naturalizing hermeneutics, and Woodward on the social
science of human cooperation are to my mind much more interesting than the above
chapters because they tie into real issues in the social sciences. So Woodward assess
the variety of sources of human cooperation and the evidence for and against them,
to me a much more interesting project than Bratmans conceptual analysis of what it
means to paint the house together. Cartwright carefully lays out the general
obstacles to inferring from clinical trials to whether the treatment will work in other
settings. RCTs are increasing popular in the social sciences, especially development
economics, so these are certainly issues relevant to social research.
At points, this second set of essays is still not quite as naturalist as I would like to
see. Little defends what he calls localism (but generally called supervenience in the
general literature): social phenomena possess their characteristics by virtue of
individuals. He concludes that social explanations must have individualist micro-
foundations. However, micro-foundations can mean all kinds of different things,
and there is no easy route from supervenience to a need for micro-foundations (cf.
Kincaid 1996, 2012a, b; Hoover 2001). He also says that social entities such as
states have no essence and thus there is little or no place for generalizations in social
research, just description of mechanisms found by methods like comparative
analysis. I fear these are philosophically motivated pronouncements about how
social science must work that do not confront the real problems of social research.
Knight, a distinguished political scientist, objects in his commentary that social
123
394 Metascience (2012) 21:391394
scientists are indeed interested in mechanisms that allow for generalizations across
cases.
This brings me to the second important question running though many of these
essays: how and when can the social sciences take the kinds of evidence it has to
provide compelling explanations, assuming that we do not demand the strict laws
that are perhaps characteristic of physics and allow a variety of qualitative
evidence? Little points to recent developments such as causal process tracing and
comparative analysis as furthering the goals of social research, but it is a big, open
question what the standards are for such methods and the extent to which they
succeed (cf. Waldner 2012; Goertz 2012). Little, as we saw, thought they did not
warrant generalizations; an unhappy conclusion, given the fact that social scientists
seem to have produced a number of generalizations, albeit restricted ones (cf.
Goertz 2012). Cartwright thinks it exceedingly rare that we have the knowledge
needed to argue that the results of a social experiment can be generalized outside the
experimental setting. This may be true, but she provides no concrete evidence for
the claim, and what is really needed is an analysis of the strategies that might be
used to argue for external validity. Social and behavioral scientists have
increasingly sophisticated to deal with the fundamental problem of causal
confounding and causal complexity (cf. Ragin 1989; Winship and Morgan and
Winship 2007). How these methods work and how well they work are interesting
open question for the naturalist tradition in the philosophy of social science.
References
123