History and Philosophy in Science Teaching
History and Philosophy in Science Teaching
History and Philosophy in Science Teaching
discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/226927644
CITATIONS READS
796 4,481
1 author:
Michael Matthews
UNSW Sydney
90 PUBLICATIONS 2,893 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Michael Matthews on 18 October 2014.
Preface iii
Acknowledgements v
Index 367
Science Teaching: The Role of History and Philosophy of Science
Michael R. Matthews
University of New South Wales, Sydney, Australia. Email: m.matthews@unsw.edu.au
Science teachers contribute to the overall education of students, thus they need some
moderately well-formed view of what education is, and the goals it should be pursuing.
Teachers and administrators need some conception of an educated person, as this is the
telos of their individual classroom teaching and policy development. Teachers need to
keep their eyes on the educational prize, the more so when social pressures increasingly
devalue the intellectual and critical traditions of education.
The conviction that the learning of science needs to be accompanied by learning
about science is basic to liberal approaches to the teaching of science. If students
do not learn and appreciate something about scienceits history, its interrelations
with culture, religion, worldviews, and commerce, its philosophical and metaphysical
assumptions, its epistemology and methodologythen the opportunity for science to
enrich culture and human lives is correspondingly minimised. If science is taught
merely as a technical subject devoid of its cultural and philosophical dimensions, then
the positive results of science education are less able to fructify in society. We have
some inkling of this situation of lost cultural opportunities when we look at the purely
technical teaching of the sciences in the former USSR where the wide-spread teaching
of science did not appear, with a few courageous exceptions, to generate critical and
independent thinking, in many parts of contemporary southern USA where racism and
belief in creation science go hand-in-hand with sophistication in technical science, and
perhaps in Japan where it seems that technical science is taught fairly well, but the
scientific competence gained seems not to contribute very much to Japanese cultural
understanding or philosophy (on this complex matter see Kawasaki 1996).
Fully 90% were scientifically illiterate, having less than a minimum understand-
ing of the processes, terms and social impact of science.
Only 13% were even attentive or interested in science, with an even smaller
percentage of women in the sample being interested.
Only 3% were both literate and interested; that is most of the 10 per cent who
were scientifically literate, were not interested in science!
Overall there was a negative attitude to science. (MORST 1991, p. 4).
There are complex economic, social, cultural, and systemic reasons for this rejection
of science. These are beyond the scope of teachers to rectify. But there are also
educational reasons for the rejection of science that are within the power of teachers
and administrators to change. In 1989, for example, a disturbing number of the very
top Australian school science achievers gave too boring as the reason for not pursuing
university science. It is these curriculum and pedagogical failings that the history and
philosophy of science (HPS) can help rectify.
Michael Matthews 3
Science and Cultural Health
Studies of scientific illiteracy reveal a situation that is culturally alarming, not just
because they indicate that large percentages of the population do not know the meaning
of basic scientific concepts,1 and thus have little if any idea of how nature functions and
how technology works, but because they suggest widespread antiscientific views, and
illogical thought.
The defense of science in schools is important, if not necessary, to the intellectual
health of society. Pseudoscientific and irrational world views already have a strong
hold in Western culture; antiscience is on the rise.2 Newspaper astrology columns
are read by far more people than science columns; the tabloid press, with their Elvis
sightings and Martian visits, adorn checkout counters and are consumed by millions
worldwide each day. A 1991 Gallup Poll revealed that nearly half (47%) of all US
citizens believe that human life began on earth just a couple of thousand years ago
(Smith, Siegel & McInerney 1995). A study at one Canadian university found that a
majority of students believed in astrology, extrasensory perception, and reincarnation;
while another estimated that 11% of US citizens claim to have seen a ghost (Cromer
1993, p. 34). Surveys conducted over a three year period at the University of Texas
revealed that 60 per cent of students thought that some people could predict the future
by psychic powers, 35% believed in Black Magic, and the same percentage believed in
ghosts. A recent survey by the Australian Institute of Biology of 4,225 first-year biology
students from 17 universities in all States showed that one in eight (12%) believed that
God created man pretty much in his present form at one time within the last 10,000
years. Old-fashioned chemistry sets are no longer even marketed, while tarot cards
and crystals are available on almost every street corner.
When thought becomes so free from rational constraints, then outpourings of racism,
prejudice, hysteria and fanaticism of all kinds can be expected. For all its faults, science
has been an important factor in combating superstition, prejudice and ignorance. It
has provided, albeit falteringly, a counterinfluence to the natural inclinations of people
to judge circumstances in terms of their own self-interest. It instills a concern for
evidence, and for having ideas judged not by personal or social interest, but by how the
world is; a sense of Cosmic Piety, as Bertrand Russell called it. These values are under
attack both inside and outside the academy. When people en masse abandon science,
or science education abandons them, then the world is at a critical juncture. At such a
time the role of the science teacher is especially vital, and in need of all the intellectual
and material support possible.
1 Jon D. Miller has conducted a series of large-scale studies on scientific literacy in the US. On the basis of
ability to say something intelligible about concepts such as molecule, atom, byte, in 1985 he judged only 3%
of high-school graduates, 12% of college graduates, and 18% of college doctoral graduates to be scientifically
literate. See Miller (1983, 1987, 1992.)
2 For discussion of the anti-science phenomena see Passmore (1978), Holton (1993), Gross & Levitt (1994),
1992 Kingston conference are in Hills (1992); the 1995 Minneapolis conference in Finley et al. (1995). The
1999 conference was held in Pavia, Italy, and information can be obtained from Professor Fabio Bevilacqua,
Dipartimento di Fisica, A. Volta, Universita di Pavia, Via A.Bassi 6, 27100 Pavia, Italy. The 2001 conference
is being held in Denver, Colorado, USA and information can be obtained from William McComas, Program
Chair School of Education, WPH 1001E University of Southern California Los Angeles, CA 90089-0031, USA
Email: mccomas@usc.edu
4 The journal special issues include the following: Educational Philosophy and Theory 20(2), (1988);
Synthese 80(1), (1989); Interchange 20(2), (1989); Studies in Philosophy and Education 10(1), (1990); Science
Education 75(1), (1991); Journal of Research in Science Teaching 29(4), (1992); International Journal of
Science Education 12(3), (1990); and Interchange 23(2,3), (1993).
5 The journal is published by Kluwer Academic Publishers, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The
Netherlands. It is available at reduced rates through the international HPS & ST group (inquiries to the
author).
Michael Matthews 5
ago. The author, F.M. Westaway, writes that a successful science teacher is one who:
. . . knows [his/her] own subject . . . is widely read in other branches of science . . . knows how to
teach . . . is able to express [him/her self] lucidly . . . is skillful in manipulation . . . is a logician
. . . is something of a philosopher . . . is so far an historian that [he/she] can sit down with a
crowd of [students] and talk to them about the personal equations, the lives, and the work
of such geniuses as Galileo, Newton, Faraday and Darwin. More than all this, [he/she] is an
enthusiast, full of faith in [his/her] own particular work. (Westaway, 1929, p. 3)
This is a nice sketch of the liberal, realist and contextual approach to the teaching
of science that I advocate. If universities, and colleges of education, produced an
abundance of such science teachers, many of the Western worlds science education
problems would be diminished.
The liberal tradition is characterized by a number of educational commitments.6
One is that education entails the introduction of children to the best traditions of their
culture, including the academic disciplines, in such a way that they both understand
the subject discipline, and know something about the disciplineits methodology, as-
sumptions, limitations, history and so forth. A second feature is that, as far as is
possible and appropriate, the relations of particular subjects to each other, and their
relation to the broader canvas of ethics, religion, culture, economics and politics should
be acknowledged and investigated. The liberal tradition seeks to overcome intellectual
fragmentation.
One part of the contribution of HPS to science teaching is to connect topics in
particular scientific disciplines, to connect the disciplines of science with each other,
to connect the sciences generally with mathematics, philosophy, literature, psychology,
history, technology, commerce and theology. And finally, to display the interconnections
of science and culturethe arts, ethics, religion, politicsmore broadly. Science has
developed in conjunction with other disciplines, there has been mutual interdepen-
dence. It has also developed, and is practiced, within a broader cultural and social
milieu. These interconnections and interdependencies can be appropriately explored
in science programs from elementary school to graduate study. The result is far more
satisfying for students than the unconnected topics that constitute most programs of
school and university science. Courses in the sciences are too often, as one student
remarked, forced marches through unknown country without time to look sideways.
The routine topic of pendulum motion, for instance, when taught in such a way that
includes consideration of its history and philosophy, results in the following kind of
integrated learning experience for students. The science of pendulum motion connects
with important topics in religion, history, philosophy and literature.7
Contributors to the liberal tradition believe that science taught from such a per-
spective, and informed by the history and philosophy of the subject, can engender
understanding of nature, the appreciation of beauty in both nature and science, and the
6 There is a large literature on the theory and practice of liberal education. Peters (1966, chs. 1, 2) and
Bantock (1981, ch. 4) are useful introductions. See also Dressel (1979) and Mark (1994). The contributions
to Obler & Estrin (1962) focus on the contribution of science to a liberal education, as do the arguments in
Holton (1973) and Schwab (1945).
7 For further details see Matthews (1999).
6 Science Teaching: The Role of HPS
RELIGION HISTORY SCIENCE PHILOSOPHY LITERATURE
2 3
1 NDULU
PE
M
MO
T I ON
6 5 4
The abilities sought by Shulman are enhanced if teachers are interested in and
familiar with the history and philosophy of whatever subject they are teaching. The US
National Standards in Science Education group is urging teachers to ask themselves
and their students not just what do we know in science, but how do we know what we
know. These are routine methodological questions that lead into and are answered by
the philosophy of science.
The AAAS in its proposal for the reform of college science teaching, The Liberal
Art of Science, recognises that science education is enriched, and is more faithful to its
subject, if aspects of the interesting and complex interplay of science and philosophy
can be conveyed in the classroom. It says:
The teaching of science must explore the interplay between science and the intellectual and
cultural traditions in which it is firmly embedded. Science has a history that can demonstrate
the relationship between science and the wider world of ideas and can illuminate contemporary
issues. (AAAS 1990, p. xiv)
The advocates of a contextual approach to science teaching are not just educational
dreamers. There has been a tradition of attempts to teach science in an HPS-informed
or liberal manner. The strengths and weaknesses of these attempts can be examined.
Perhaps the outstanding example was the Harvard Project Physics course developed for
schools in the early 1960s by Gerald Holton, James Rutherford and Fletcher Watson. 9
Over sixty studies of the effectiveness of the program were published (Welch 1973)
and these were all positive and encouraging. Measures such as retention in science,
participation of women, improvement on critical thinking tests and understanding
of subject matter all showed improvement where the Project Physics curriculum was
adopted. Another example of a widely adopted HPS-influenced course was the Yellow
Version of the BSCS Biology course developed by John Moore and Joseph Schwab. 10
8 The British National Curriculum is documented in NCC (1988). It is discussed in Akeroyd (1989), Ray
(1991), and Solomon (1991). The Danish curriculum in the History of Science and Technology is discussed
in Nielsen & Nielsen (1988), and Nielsen & Thomsen (1990). In The Netherlands there has been a Physics
in Society course since 1981 (Eijkelhof & Swager 1983), and since 1972 various materials generated by
the PLON project have incorporated a HPS dimension (Project Curriculum Development in Physics, PO
Box 80.008, 3508 TA Utrecht, The Netherlands). The Project 2061 proposals are contained in AAAS (1989)
and republished in Rutherford & Ahlgren (1990); they are discussed in Stein (1989). A discussion of STS
programmes and a guide to the literature can be found in McFadden (1989) and Yager (1993).
9 Fifteen per cent of US high school physics students were following this program at its peak, and it was
widely used outside the US. The philosophy behind this program can be read in Gerald Holton (1978a), and
in the symposium published in The Physics Teacher (1967, vol. 5 no. 2). Other evaluations of Harvard Project
Physics can be found in Aikenhead (1974), Brush (1978, 1989), Russell (1981), and Welch & Walberg (1972).
10 This was first published in 1963 and went through four editions up to 1980.
Michael Matthews 11
Contributions of HPS to Science Education
The inclusion of history and philosophy of science does not, of course, provide all the
answers to the present science education crisisultimately these answers lie deep in
the heart of culture and economics. But the history and philosophy of science has a
contribution to make to the overall task of improving science teaching and learning.
Aspects of this contribution might be itemized as follows:
HPS can humanize the sciences and connect them to personal, ethical, cultural,
and political concerns. There is evidence that this makes science and engineer-
ing programmes more attractive to many students, and particularly girls, who
currently reject them.
HPS, particularly basic logical and analytic exercisesDoes this conclusion fol-
low from the premises? and, What do you mean by such and such?can make
classrooms more challenging, and enhance reasoning and critical thinking skills.
HPS can contribute to the fuller understanding of scientific subject matterit can
help to overcome the sea of meaninglessness, as Joseph Novak once said, where
formulae and equations are recited without knowledge of what they mean or to
what they refer.
HPS can improve teacher education by assisting teachers to develop a richer and
more authentic understanding of science and its place in the intellectual and
social scheme of things. This has a flow-on effect, as there is much evidence that
teachers epistemology, or views about the nature of science, affect how they teach
and the message they convey to students.
HPS can assist teachers appreciate the learning difficulties of students, because
it alerts them to the historic difficulties of scientific development and conceptual
change. Galileo was forty years of age before he formulated the modern conception
of acceleration, despite prolonged thought he never worked out a correct theory
for the tides. By historical studies teachers can see what some of the intellectual
and conceptual difficulties were in the early periods of scientific disciplines. This
knowledge can assist with the organization of the curriculum and the teaching of
lessons.
HPS can contribute to the clearer appraisal of many contemporary educational
debates that engage science teachers and curriculum planners. Many of these
debatesabout constructivist teaching methods, multicultural science education,
feminist science, environmental science, inquiry learning, science-technology-society
curricula and so forthmake claims and assumptions about the history and epis-
temology of science, or the nature of human knowledge and its production and
validation. Without some grounding in HPS, teachers can be too easily carried
along by fashionable ideas which later, sadly, seemed good at the time.
12 Science Teaching: The Role of HPS
There are various ways in which the interplay between science and philosophy can
be conveyed: reading of selections from original sources; joint projects with history, so-
cial science, divinity or literature classes; dramatic reenactments of significant episodes
in the history of science; essays on selected themes; debates on topical matters; or low-
level philosophical questioning about scientific topics being studied or practical work
being conducted. All philosophy of science begins with analytical and logical matters:
What does a particular concept mean? How do we know the truth of a proposition? Does
a conclusion follow from the premises adduced? These analytic and logical questions
and habits of thought can be introduced as early as preschoolas Matthew Lipman
and the Philosophy for Children programs attestand they can be refined as children
mature (Lipman & Sharp 1978). Susan Johnson and Jim Stewart (1991) provide a nice
example of the incorporation of philosophy of science into a high school genetics course.
They focus on the three Ps of science: problem posing, problem solving, and persuasion
of peers.
School courses in Science-Technology-Society (STS) are another area in which sci-
ence courses connect with philosophy, particularly ethical and political philosophy. A
1990 Department of Education guide to STS education issued by the provincial govern-
ment of Alberta, CanadaUnifying the Goals of Science Educationgives prominence
to teaching about the nature of science. Its reading list includes the work of Hawking,
Einstein, Holton, Kuhn, Latour, Polanyi and Ravetz. A recent list of common STS topics
includes: abortion, AIDS, endangered species, genetic engineering, organ transplants,
nuclear war, space exploration, and waste management (Rubba et al.1991). These STS
courses in England, Holland, Canada, and the US11 deal explicitly with political and
ethical issues involving notions such as justice, equality, the fair distribution of goods,
responsibility and the likeall of which are clarified by philosophical analysis, and
by reference to the history of these ideas. Without philosophical input, STS courses
run the risk of just repeating fashionable and shallow ideology about pollution, nuclear
energy, conservation and so on. This was seen in the 1940s in Science for Consumers
courses. Shallow views on these vital matters tend to be blown away at the first gust
of national- or self-interest that the student encounters upon leaving school.
There is not, of course, a single HPS-informed view of science or of science education.
There are two broad camps discernible in the literature: those who appeal to HPS to
support the teaching of science, and those who appeal to HPS to puncture the perceived
arrogance and authority of science. The second group stress the human face of science,
the fallibility of science, the impact of politics and special interests, including racial,
class and sexual interests, on the pursuit of science; they argue for skepticism about
scientific knowledge claims. For this group, HPS shows that science is one among a
number of equally valid ways of looking at the world, it has no epistemic privilege;
its supposed privilege derives merely from social considerations and technological suc-
cess. This group includes those influenced by postmodernist philosophy, and certain
sociologies of science.
11 See the two NSTA Yearbooks Redesigning Science and Technology Education (Bybee et al. 1984) and
Science, Technology, Society (Bybee 1985), and their volume The Science, Technology, Society Movement
(Yager 1993).
Michael Matthews 13
Conclusion
There are many reasons why study of the history and philosophy of science should
be part of preservice and in-service science teacher education programs. Increasingly
school science courses address historical, philosophical, ethical and cultural issues
occasioned by science. Teachers of such curricula obviously need knowledge of HPS.
Without such knowledge they either present truncated versions of the curricula, or
repeat uncritical gossip about the topics mentioned. Either way their students are
done a disservice. But even where curricula do not include such nature of science
sections, HPS can contribute to more interesting and critical teaching of science.
Beyond these practical arguments for HPS in teacher education, there are com-
pelling professional arguments. A teacher ought to know more than just what he or
she teaches. As an educator, they need to know something about the body of knowledge
they are teaching, something about how this knowledge has come about, how its claims
are justified and what its limitations are. Teachers should have a feel for, or appreci-
ation of, the tradition of inquiry into which they are initiating students. HPS fosters
this.
Education systems have a responsibility to identify and transmit the best of our
cultural heritage. Science is one of the most important parts of this heritage. The
history and philosophy of science allows science teachers to better understand their
own social and professional responsibilities as part of a great tradition.
References
Aikenhead, G.: 1980, Science in Social Issues: Implications for Teaching, Science
Council of Canada, Ottawa.
Aikenhead, G. S.: 1974, Course Evaluation II: Interpretation of Student Performance
on Evaluation Tests, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 11, 2330.
Akeroyd, F.: 1989, Philosophy of Science in a National Curriculum, in D.E.Herget
(ed.), The History and Philosophy of Science in Science Teaching, Florida State
University, pp. 1522.
American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS): 1989, Project 2061:
Science for All Americans, AAAS, Washington, DC. Also published by Oxford
University Press, 1990.
American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS): 1990, The Liberal Art of
Science: Agenda for Action, AAAS, Washington, DC.
American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS): 1993, Benchmarks for
Science Literacy: Draft, AAAS, Washington DC.
American Physical Society (APS): 1986, Report of the Committee on Education - 1985,
Bulletin of the American Physical Society 31(6), 10331034.
14 Science Teaching: The Role of HPS
Anderson, O.: 1989, The Teaching and Learning of Biology in the United States,
International Association for the Evaluation of Educational Achievement, New
York.
Bantock, G.: 1981, The Parochialism of the Present, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Beardsley, T.: 1992, Teaching Real Science, Scientific American pp. 7886.
Berlin, B. and Gaines, A.: 1966, Use Philosophy to Explain the Scientific Method, The
Science Teacher 33(5).
Biological Science Curriculum Committee (BSCS): 1992, Mapping and Sequencing the
Human Genome: Science, Ethics and Public Policy, BSCS, Colorado Springs, CO.
Blake, D.: 1994, Revolution, Revision, or Reversal: Genetics-Ethics Curriculum,
Science & Education 3(4).
Bown, W.: 1993, Classroom Science goes into Freefall, New Scientist pp. 1213.
Brush, S.: 1969, The Role of History in the Teaching of Physics, The Physics Teacher
7(5), 271280.
Brush, S.: 1989, History of Science and Science Education, Interchange 20(2), 6070.
Bybee, R. (ed.): 1985, Science, Technology, Society, NSTA, Washington. Yearbook of the
National Science Teachers Association.
Bybee, R.W. Carlson, J. and McCormack, A. (eds): 1984, Redesigning Science &
Technology Education, National Science Teachers Association, Washington DC.
Cordero, A.: 1992, Science, Objectivity and Moral Values, Science & Education 1(1), 49
70.
Cromer, A.: 1993, Uncommon Sense: The Heretical Nature of Science, Oxford
University Press, New York.
Cross, R. and Price, R.: 1992, Teaching Science for Social Responsibility, St Louis Press,
Sydney.
Dressel, P.: 1979, Liberal Education: Developing the Characteristics of a Liberally
Educated Person, Liberal Education 65(3), 313322.
Duschl, R.: 1985, Science Education & Philosophy of Science Twenty-five, Years of
Mutually Exclusive Development, School Science and Mathematics 87(7), 541
555.
Eger, M.: 1989, The Interests of Science and the Problems of Education, Synthese
80(1), 81106.
Michael Matthews 15
Eijkelhof, H. and Swager, J.: 1983, Physics in Society: New Trends in Physics Teaching
IV, UNESCO, Paris.
Gross, P. and Levitt, N.: 1994, Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and Its Quarrels
with Science, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore.
Nielsen, H. and Thomsen, P.: 1990, History and Philosophy of Science in the Danish
Curriculum, International Journal of Science Education 12(4), 308316.
Harrold, F. and Eve, R.: 1987, Patterns of Creationist Belief Among College Students,
in F. Harrold and R. Eve (eds), Cult Archaeology and Creationism: Understanding
Pseudoscientific Beliefs about the Past, University of Iowa Press, Ames.
Herget, D. (ed.): 1989, The History and Philosophy of Science in Science Teaching,
Florida State University, Tallahassee FL.
Herget, D. (ed.): 1990, The History and Philosophy of Science in Science Teaching,
Florida State University, Tallahassee FL.
Hills, S. (ed.): 1992, The History and Philosophy of Science in Science Education, two
volumes, Queens University, Kingston.
Holton, G.: 1973, Physics and Culture: Criteria for Curriculum Design and Modern
Science and the Intellectual Tradition, In his, Thematic Origins of Scientific
Thought, Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
Holton, G.: 1978, On the Educational Philosophy of the Project Physics Course,
In his, The Scientific Imagination: Case Studies, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, pp. 284298.
Holton, G.: 1993, Science and Anti-Science, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Husserl, E.: 1954/1970, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phe-
nomenology, Northwestern University Press, Evanston.
Johnson, S. and Stewart, J.: 1991, Using Philosophy of Science in Curriculum
Development: An Example from High School Genetics, in M. Matthews (ed.),
History, Philosophy, and Science Teaching: Selected Readings, OISE Press,
Toronto, Ontario, pp. 201212.
Jungwirth, E.: 1987, Avoidance of Logical Fallacies: A Neglected Aspect of Science-
education and Science-teacher Education, Research in Science & Technological
Education 5(1), 4358.
Kawasaki, K.: 1996, The Concepts of Science in Japanese and Western Education,
Science & Education 5.
Lipman, M. and Sharp, A. (eds): 1978, Growing Up with Philosophy, Temple University
Press, Philadelphia.
16 Science Teaching: The Role of HPS
Mark, H.: 1994, What is a Liberal Education?, New Directions for Higher Education
85, 3136.
Martin, M.: 1986, Science Education and Moral Education, Journal of Moral Educa-
tion, Reprinted in M. Matthews (ed.), History, Philosophy and Science Teaching:
Selected Readings, OISE Press, Toronto, 1991, pp. 102114.
Martin, M.: 1994, Pseudoscience, the Paranormal, and Science Education, Science &
Education 3(4).
Matthews, M.: 1994, Science Teaching: The Role of History and Philosophy of Science,
Routledge, New York.
Matthews, M.: 1999, Time for Science Education: How Teaching the History and
Philosophy of Pendulum Motion can Contribute to Science Literacy, Plenum
Publishers, New York.
Matthews, M. (ed.): 1991, History, Philosophy and Science Teaching: Selected Read-
ings, OISE Press, Toronto.
Mayer, J.: 1987, Consequences of a Weak Science Education, Boston Globe .
McFadden, C.: 1989, Redefining the School Curriculum, in D. Herget (ed.), The
History and Philosophy of Science in Science Teaching, Florida State University,
Tallahassee, pp. 259270.
Miller, J.: 1983, Scientific Literacy: A Conceptual and Empirical Review, Daedalus,
112(2), 29-47.
Miller, J.: 1987, Scientific Literacy in the United States, in E. David and M. OConnor
(eds), Communicating Science to the Public, John Wiley, London.
Miller, J.: 1992, The Public Understanding of Science and Technology in the United
States, 1990, National Science Foundation, Washington DC.
Ministry of Research Science and Technology (MORST): 1991, Survey of Attitudes to,
and Understanding of, Science and Technology in New Zealand, Publication No.4,
MORST, Wellington.
Musschenga, B. and Gosling, D. (eds): 1985, Science Education and Ethical Values:
Introducing Ethics and Religion into the Science Classroom and Laboratory,
Georgetown University Press, Washington, DC.
National Commission on Excellence in Education: 1983, A Nation At Risk: The
Imperative for Education Reform, US Department of Education, Washington DC.
National Curriculum Council (NCC): 1988, Science in the National Curriculum, NCC,
York.
Michael Matthews 17
Nielsen, H. and Nielsen, K.: 1988, History of Technology in Education - Why and How,
in C. Blondel and P. Brouzeng (eds), Science Education and the History of Physics,
pp. 5168.
Nielsen, H. and Thomsen, P.: 1990, History and Philosophy of Science in the Danish
Curriculum, International Journal of Science Education, 12(4), 308-316.
Obler, P. and Estrin, H. (eds): 1962, The New Scientist: Essays on the Methods and
Values of Modern Science, Doubleday, New York.
Passmore, J.: 1978, Science and Its Critics, Rutgers University Press, Rutgers NJ.
Peters, R.: 1966, Ethics and Education, George Allen and Unwin, London.
Ray, C.: 1991, Science Education, Philosophy of Science, and Scientific Prejudice,
Science Education 75(1), 8794.
Rubba, P. et al.: 1991, The Effects of Infusing STS Vignettes into the Genetics
Unit of Biology on Learner Outcomes in STS and Genetics: A Report of Two
Investigations, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 28(6), 537552.
Russell, T.: 1981, What History of Science, How Much and Why?, Science Education
65, 5164.
Rutherford, F. and Ahlgren, A.: 1990, Science for All Americans, Oxford University
Press, New York.
Schwab, J.: 1945, The Nature of Scientific Knowledge as Related to Liberal Education,
Journal of General Education, 3, 245-266. Reproduced in I. Westbury and
N. Wilkof (eds), Joseph J. Schwab: Science, Curriculum, and Liberal Education,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1978,
Science Council of Canada (SCC): 1984, Science for Every Student: Educating Canadi-
ans for Tomorrows World, Report 36, SCC, Ottawa.
Shulman, L.: 1986, Those Who Understand: Knowledge Growth in Teaching, Educa-
tional Researcher 15(2), 414.
Smith, M.U. Siegel, H. and McInerney, J.: 1995, Foundational Issues in Evolution
Education, Science & Education 4(1), 2346.
Solomon, J.: 1991, Teaching About the Nature of Science in the British National
Curriculum, Science Education 75(1), 95104.
Wagner, P. and Lucas, C.: 1977, Philosophic Inquiry and the Logic of Elementary School
Science Education, Science Education 61(4), 549558.
Welch, W.: 1973, Review of the Research and Evaluation Program of Harvard Project
Physics, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 10, 365378.
18 Science Teaching: The Role of HPS
Welch, W. and Walberg, H.: 1972, A National Experiment in Curriculum Evaluation,
American Educational Research Journal 9, 373383.
Westaway, F.: 1929, Science Teaching, Blackie and Son, London.
Whitehead, A.: 1947, Technical Education and Its Relation to Science and Literature,
In his, The Aims of Education and Other Essays, Williams & Norgate, London.
Yager, R. (ed.): 1993, The Science, Technology, Society Movement, National Science
Teachers Association, Washington DC.
Ziman, J.: 1980, Teaching and Learning about Science and Society, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Does Science Teaching Need History and Philosophy of Science?
Peter Slezak
University of New South Wales, Australia. Email: p.slezak@unsw.edu.au
The place of History and Philosophy of Science (HPS) in the science curriculum derives
from the rationale for teaching science itself. The point is best appreciated by means
of an illustration. We see one familiar rationale for teaching science in the remarks of
Collins & Pinch (1992):
It is nice to know the content of scienceit helps one to do a lot of things such as repair the
car, wire a plug, build a model aeroplane, use a personal computer to some effect, know where
in the oven to put a souffle, lower ones energy bills, disinfect a wound, repair the kettle, avoid
blowing oneself up with the gas cooker, and much much more. (Collins & Pinch 1992, p. 150)
Such a utilitarian view of science has consequences not only for how science is
taught, but also for how research is pursued. If seen primarily in terms of its use-
fulness, even this practical aspect of science may be jeopardised, for curiosity-driven re-
search is not merely a dispensable luxury, but the very mechanism of scientific progress.
Thus, the prosaic, pragmatic conception of science education of Collins and Pinch is
a view which might be thought to leave out something important. It is no accident
that this view of science and its value in the curriculum is articulated by sociologists
who are among the foremost proponents of a constructivist and relativist conception
according to which science is not to be understood in terms of its rational, intellectual,
explanatory content but rather as a merely consensual, negotiated and culturally con-
tingent convention based on interests and politics. This approach has been an avowedly
deflationist one, skeptical of the claims of science as a privileged form of knowledge and,
therefore, concerned to demote it from its exalted status and unwarranted pretensions.
The view of science as merely instrumentally useful, at best, is in keeping with
a widespread anti-science sentiment, indeed hostility, which has fuelled the recent
science wars (Gross & Levitt 1994). Laudan (1990, p. x) has scathingly described
sociological relativist views as the most prominent and pernicious manifestation of
anti-intellectualism in our time. The charge of anti-intellectualism points to the aspect
of social constructivism which has the most direct pedagogical implications. Such meta-
scientific, philosophical views will inevitably have some influence on the teaching of
science content. On such constructivist views (Ashmore 1993, Pinch & Collins 1984)
there is no more warrant for teaching currently accepted science than discredited
theories since there are no intellectual grounds to distinguish between them, only social
and political ones (see Slezak 2000).
At the opposite end of the spectrum, we may note an actual example of science
teaching which is informed by a different outlook, namely, one which seeks to convey
a picture of science as the highest achievements of the human intellect. Densmores
(1995) text reconstructs the central argument of Newtons Principia and suggests what
it means for a student to make the attempt to appreciate Newtons achievement:
20 Does Science Teaching Need History and Philosophy of Science?
. . . one can feel the sense of adventure and intrigue, the challenge of solving the puzzle. It can
be viewed as one views many games and puzzles people buy and play voluntarily for fun. It
can be viewed as one views a good detective story: all the clues are there . . .. (Densmore 1995,
p. xxxi)
This conception is in the spirit of those such as Jacob Bronowski (1960, 1964, 1978)
who writes of science as the highest romantic adventure with intellectual, aesthetic
and inspirational qualities equal to those of the arts. Indeed, beyond these, Bronowski
has emphasized the fundamental moral dimension of science which echoes the values
emphasized by Popper and other philosophers of science.
Even if knowing little else, everyone is aware that science is historically changeable.
The important question, then, is what conclusions may be drawn from this undeniable
fact about the history of science. For non-experts, the mutability of science seems
to warrant a general belief in the need to remain open minded about miraculous
or paranormal phenomena which are contrary to accepted scientific theories. Thus,
for example, a standard popular response to skepticism about psychic phenomena
is to cite the supposed lessons of the history of science and its ever changing body
of beliefs. This lesson is taken to dictate an open-mindedness about unorthodox
and even disreputable theories rather than dogmatic dismissal. This tolerance is
allegedly inferred from earlier mistakes and is often justified with the slogan They
laughed at Galileo too. However, an apt answer which has been given by skeptics is
Yes, but they laughed at Bozo the clown too. Being unorthodox is not, in itself, a
virtue.
Recruited in this way as support for some currently unfounded pseudo-science, the
argument from history is entirely vacuous despite being almost universally seen as
self-evident. The insight is only the wisdom of hindsight, because it cannot provide
grounds for deciding what to believe in any given case today. However difficult to
explicate, warranted belief must be based on the usual considerations of evidence,
explanatory coherence, comprehensiveness, elegance, and whatever other factors play
a role. None of these are weighted differently in the light of the historical mutability
of science. Based on past practice, knowing only that what we believe tomorrow will
be different from what we believe today carries no specific implication or prescription
for current beliefs. Nevertheless, generally deployed in this way, an inexplicit, naive
philosophy of science is taken to warrant either credulity or global skepticism.
When faced explicitly as a question about the place of HPS in the curriculum, the
issue of open-mindedness poses a seeming paradox. Undeniably, one of the central
features of science emphasized by many scholars has been its critical nature. Popper
22 Does Science Teaching Need History and Philosophy of Science?
(1963) has emphasized that the origin of science among the Presocratics was specif-
ically founded in their inauguration of a tradition of critical inquiry as opposed to
dogmatic acceptance of orthodoxy. The same moral has been emphasized by schol-
ars such as Guthrie (1962) and Farrington (1961) who share Poppers view that the
essence of the scientific enterprise was first captured by these Milesian Greeks in their
commitment to criticism as the means for improving and advancing our understanding
of the world. For Popper, this theme of conjectures and refutations found expression in
his doctrine of falsifiability as the mark of science, distinguishing it from metaphysics
or other pseudo-scientific inquiries. Thus, he asserts Criticism is the lifeblood of all
rational thought (Popper 1974). In view of this widely held conception of science, an
acute paradox is presented by T.S. Kuhn who writes:
To turn Sir Karls view on its head, it is precisely the abandonment of critical discourse that
marks the transition to science. (Kuhn 1970b, p. 6)
For those wishing to teach science as an embodiment of rationality and critical think-
ing, it is important to reconcile this Popperian conception with Kuhns radically alter-
native picture of science as founded on dogmatism. In a famous essay The Essential
Tension, Kuhn observes that:
. . . exclusive exposure to a rigid tradition has been immensely productive of the most conse-
quential sorts of innovations. . . . each of [the natural sciences] acquired something like that
technique [of rigid education] at precisely the point when the field began to make rapid and
systematic progress. (Kuhn 1959, pp. 229-231)
The dilemma for science educators arises from recognizing the divergence between
the rhetoric and the reality of scientific practice. The theme of Kuhns essay is the
tension between open and closed mindedness, that is, between convergent and diver-
gent thinking . Divergent thinking is the flexible or lateral thinking characteristic of
creative discovery and innovation. Kuhn explains:
The basic scientist must lack prejudice to a degree where he can look at the most self-evident
facts or concepts without necessarily accepting them, and, conversely, allow his imagination to
play with the most unlikely possibilities . . .
. . . divergent thinking [is] the freedom to go off in different directions, . . . rejecting the old
solutions and striking out in some new direction.
. . . gigantic divergences lie at the core of the most significant episodes in scientific development.
(Kuhn 1959, p. 226)
Kuhn notes that a common criticism of science education complains that it empha-
sizes narrow or convergent thinking at the expense of creative, divergent thinking.
This criticism suggests We have attempted to teach students how to arrive at correct
answers that our civilization has taught us are correct . . .. Outside the arts . . . we have
generally discouraged the development of divergent thinking abilities, unintentionally.
Kuhn acknowledges that this characterization of our educational practice is eminently
just, but he askes whether it is equally just to deplore the product that results. Kuhn
is pointing to the function of science education and textbooks as indoctrination, and to
the crucial role of such indoctrination in the very success of science.
In an ironic defence of dogmatism Kuhn explains:
Peter Slezak 23
But both my own experience in scientific research and my reading of the history of sciences
lead me to wonder whether flexibility and open-mindedness have not been too exclusively
emphasized as the characteristics requisite for basic research.
. . . normal research, even the best of it, is a highly convergent activity based firmly upon a
settled consensus acquired from scientific education and reinforced by subsequent life in the
profession.
Let me try briefly to epitomize the nature of education in the natural sciences . . .. The single
most striking feature of this education is that, to an extent totally unknown in other creative
fields, it is conducted entirely through textbooks . . . written especially for students. . . . There
are no collections of readings in the natural science. Nor are science students encouraged
to read the historical classics of their fieldsworks in which they might discover other ways
of regarding the problems discussed in their textbooks, but in which they would also meet
problems, concepts, and standards of solution that their future professions have long since
discarded and replaced. . . . These books exhibit concrete problem solutions that the profession
has come to accept as paradigms, . . . Nothing could be better calculated to produce mental
sets . . . Even the most faintly liberal educational theory must view this pedagogic technique
as anathema. . . . Education in the natural sciences seems to have been totally unaffected
by [attitudes encouraging divergent thinking, open-mindedness and creativity, innovation
etc.]. . . . It remains a dogmatic initiation in a pre-established tradition that the student is
not equipped to evaluate. (Kuhn 1959, pp. 228-229)
Kuhns view reverses a traditional conception of science and how it should be taught.
For example, on such a view one common picture of the Galileo affair is mistaken, since
the orthodox Aristotelianism of the Catholic Church was not essentially different in its
conservatism from that of science itself.
Another distinguished historian of science remarks on Isaac Newton in the same vein:
If the Principia established the quantitative pattern of modern science, it equally suggested
a less sublime truththat no one can manipulate the fudge factor quite so effectively as the
master mathematician himself. (Westfall, quoted in Brush 1974, p. 1167)
However, more surprising perhaps than Newtons failure to employ inductive methods
is his commitment to quite radically different principles not usually thought compatible
with scientific method. Thus, Newton writes in his Principia:
I had an eye upon such principles as might work with considering men for the belief of a Deity;
and nothing can rejoice me more than to find it useful for that purpose.
Evidently, Newtons goal was to demonstrate the dependence of matter on God. West-
fall notes:
He sought as well to plumb the mind of God and His eternal plan for the world and mankind
as it was presented in the biblical prophecies. (Westfall 1980, p. 105)
In the famous passages of the General Scholium of Book Three in Newtons Philosophiae
Naturalis Principia Mathematica, Newton not only utters his famous hypotheses non
fingo, that is, his unwillingness to speculate about the occult causes of gravitational
action at a distance. More remarkably, though rarely noted, is the fact that Newton
also expresses a conception of a designer deity:
This most elegant arrangement of the sun, planets, and comets could not have arisen but by the
plan and rule of an intelligent and powerful being. And if the fixed stars be centers of similar
systems, all these, constructed by a similar plan, will be under the rule of One . . .
He governs everything, not as the soul of the world, but as lord of all things. And because of
his dominion, he is usually called Lord God Universal Emperor . . . And from true absolute
rule it follows that the true God is living, intelligent, or in the highest degree perfect. He is
eternal and infinite, omnipotent and omniscient; that is, he endures from eternity to eternity,
and is present from infinity to infinity. He reigns over everything, and knows everything that
happens or can happen. . . .
The whole diversity of created things according to places and times could only have arisen
from the ideas and will of a being existing necessarily. . . . And this much concerning God,
to discourse of whom, at least from the phenomena, is the business of natural philosophy.
(Newton, in Densmore & Donahue 1985)
Such passages in the midst of the scientific theorising require us to qualify precon-
ceptions about what is the properly scientific part of Newtons work, and they serve
to remind us of the arbitrariness of dismissing in retrospect those parts which we may
now regard as pseudo-scientific or religious. These distinctions appear not to have been
meaningful to Newton himself. This is of course, the lesson of Kuhns (1970) work.
A further example is instructive. A common conception of science as driven by
empirical data is amusingly illuminated by anecdotes about Einstein:
But you dont seriously believe, Einstein protested, that none but observable magnitudes
must go into a physical theory? Isnt that precisely what you have done with relativity? I
asked in some surprise. . . . Possibly I did use this kind of reasoning, Einstein admitted, but
Peter Slezak 25
it is nonsense all the same. Perhaps I could put it more diplomatically by saying that it may be
heuristically useful to keep in mind what one has actually observed. But on principle, it is quite
wrong to try founding a theory on observable magnitudes alone. In reality the very opposite
happens. It is the theory which decides what we can observe. (Heisenberg 1971, p. 63)
In the autumn of 1919, in the course of a discussion with a student, Einsteinnow aged
40handed her a cable which had informed him that the bending of light by the sun was
in agreement with his general relativistic prediction. The student asked what he would have
said if there had been no confirmation. Einstein replied, Then I would have to pity the dear
Lord. The theory is correct anyway. (Pais 1994, p. 127)
This last anecdote is interesting in part because the confirmation of the bending of
light was cited by Karl Popper as the very exemplary case of falsifiability. Einsteins
attitude reveals how little scientists conform to Popperian conceptions of rationality.
However, more forceful than such anecdote is the systematic study of episodes such as
the famous Eddington expedition referred to in the story by Pais. Earman and Glymour
(1980) reveal that the entire episode is a case study of Duhem-Quine adjustment of aux-
iliary hypotheses in order to save a favoured theory faced with recalcitrant evidence.
They write:
The initial reception of special relativity in English speaking countries was almost uniformly
hostile or disdainful. . . . One may imagine that in order to turn the tide of opinion the eclipse
results must have been unequivocal. They were not. (Earman & Glymour 1980, p. 50)
In truth, while some aspects of Eddingtons [1919] handling of the deflection of light were in the
finest traditions of science, others were not. As he confessed in Space, time and gravitation, he
was not altogether unbiased. The bias showed in his treatment of the evidence: he repeatedly
posed a false trichotomy for the deflection results, claimed the superiority of the qualitatively
inferior Principe data, and suppressed reference to the negative Sobral results. (His discussion
of the red-shift was sometimes no better . . .)
. . . all that was necessary to establish the red-shift prediction was a willingness to throw out
most of the evidence and the ingenuity to contrive arguments that would justify doing so.
. . . The red-shift was confirmed because reputable people agreed to throw out a good part of
the observations. They did so in part because they believe the theory; and they believed the
theory, again at least in part, because they believed that the British eclipse expeditions had
confirmed it. Now the eclipse expeditions confirmed the theory only if part of the observations
were thrown out and the discrepancies in the remainder ignored: Dyson and Eddington, who
presented the results to the scientific world, threw out a good part of the data and ignored the
discrepancies.
This curious sequence of reasons might be cause enough for despair on the part of those who
see in science a model of objectivity and rationality. That mood should be lightened by the
reflection that the theory in which Eddington placed his faith because he thought it beautiful
and profoundand, possibly, because he thought that it would be best for the world if it
were truethis theory, so far as we know, still holds the truth about space, time and gravity.
(Earman & Glymour 1980, pp. 84-85)
David Brewster (1830) suggested Galileo was a Baconian inductivist, while Ernst
Mach (1883) and the positivists suggest that Galileo did not supply us with a theory
of the falling of bodies, but investigated, wholly without preformed opinions, the actual
facts of falling. Alexandre Koyre (1939) claimed that Galileo was a Platonist who
invented some experiments, while Stillman Drake (1978) argued that Galileo was a
patient experimentalist. Notoriously, Paul Feyerabend (1975) argued that Galileo was
an anarchist, dadaist and propagandist with no method. Finally, Stillman Drake
(1971) disputes a common view in claiming that Galileo fought not against religion or
the church but against authority. In light of these diverse accounts, it would seem that
HPS becomes something like Bertrand Russells parody of animal psychology:
Peter Slezak 27
Animals studied by Americans rush about frantically, with an incredible display of hustle and
pep, and at last achieve the desired result by chance. Animals observed by Germans sit still
and think, and at last evolve the solution out of their inner consciousness. (Russell 1960, p. 33)
Matthews (1992) has characterised this as the hermeneutical problem which has
important intellectual virtues, despite the inherent difficulty:
The hermeneutical problem of interpretation in the history of science, far from being an em-
barrassment or impediment to the use of history, can be the occcasion to introduce students to
the significant questions of how we read texts and interpret events, to the complex problems of
meaning: students know from their everyday life that people see things differently, the history
of science is a natural vehicle for illustrating how this fact impinges on science itself. (Matthews
1992, p. 22)
This was undoubtedly an over-reaction to the work of Kuhn, though it seems am-
ply warranted in relation to the more extreme sociological doctrines which saw their
origins in Kuhns book. Acknowledging the non-rational elements in the science does
not mean abandoning a conception of scientific thought as a responsible enterprise of
reasonable men, but only the need for reconciling these elements into a more subtle
and complex overall picture.
Such a reconciliation is unquestionably a difficult and perhaps as yet unattained
ideal. This poses a difficult question for the educator because the old verities and
comforting stereotypes about science and its virtues appear to be false. How, then,
can science be taught in a way which is consistent with its history and sensitive to its
vagaries.
Realism vs Instrumentalism
A striking feature of contemporary science is the way in which it evokes philosophical
disputes essentially identical to those arising at the origins of modern science with the
scientific revolution of the seventeenth century. Specifically, we see this illustrated in
a book by Jauch (1989) titled Are Quanta Real? Significantly, the work is in the form of
a Galilean dialogue which is particularly apt in view of the fact that the issues raised
are identical with those at the heart of the Galileo affair. The issue between Cardinal
Bellarmine and Galileo was centrally concerned with the literal interpretation of the
Copernican heliocentric theory in view of the contrary teachings of Aristotle and the
Bible. The question at the heart of contemporary quantum physics is remarkable for
being identical with the one facing Galileos Copernicanism as we see in van Fraassens
(in Cushing et al. eds. 1984, p. 171) question regarding quantum theory: He asks:
Peter Slezak 29
How could the world possibly be the way physical theory says it is? For Bellarmine,
as for quantum theorists today, the issue was the need to save the appearances and
whether any further commitment to the literal claims of the theory was justified. This
was, of course, the question raised in Osianders notorious preface to Copernicuss De
Revolutionibus Orbium Coelestium of 1543. The correspondences of Bellarmine and
Galileo reveal the same contrasting attitudes as those seen today (see appendix).
We see the dilemma for Galileo raised in an acute form today at the very inception
of quantum theory with Max Plancks treatment of Black-Body radiation in 1900. The
classical Rayleigh-Jeans theory led to a distribution law for energies irreconcilable
with observations and even with the finiteness of the total energy of the radiation (the
so-called ultra-violet catastrophe). Norton (1994) explains the problem arising from
the fact that Plancks ad hoc model managed to save the appearances by what Planck
himself regarded as physically meaningless mathematical tricks.
. . . [Plancks] discontinuity theory was by no means a popular theory, and understandably so. It
required the falsity of a quite fundamental supposition of classical physics. The mere fact that
the discontinuity [quantization] hypothesis saved the phenomena was certainly not sufficient
to force its acceptance. Why should one not hope that the phenomena would be saved by some
less traumatic variant of the classical theory that preserved continuity? (Norton 1994, p. 16)
Anti-realism might be thought to follow from such a litany, but Hacking (1982)
suggests that philosophers have placed too much emphasis on theory and not enough
on experiment. Hacking explains:
No field in the philosophy of science is more systematically neglected than experiment. Our
grade school teachers may have told us that scientific method is experimental method, but
histories of science have become histories of theory. (Hacking 1982, p. 248)
30 Does Science Teaching Need History and Philosophy of Science?
No wonder that scientific antirealism is so permanently in the race. It is a variant on the
spectator theory of knowledge [that is, Berkeleys idealism]. (Hacking 1982, p. 258)
I proceed from experimental practice. . . . [From] an interest in real life physics as opposed to
philosophical fantasy science. (Hacking 1982, p. 259)
Once upon a time, it made good sense to doubt that there were electrons. . . . The best reason
for thinking that there are electrons might have been success in explanation. But the ability to
explain carries little warrant of truth. . . . Antirealism about any submicroscopic entities was
a sound doctrine in those days. Things are different now. The direct proof of electrons and
the like is our ability to manipulate them using well-understood low-level causal properties.
(Hacking 1982, p. 256/258)
. . . engineering, not theorizing, is the best proof of scientific realism about entities. (Hacking
1982, p. 258)
Of course, Hackings final comment makes it difficult to see how one might ascribe
reality to black holes which are hardly amenable to engineering in the way he seems
to have in mind. Nevertheless, my concern here has been only to point to the ways in
which the deepest questions of the history and philosophy of science bear directly on the
manner and substance of science teaching. Toulmin (1970) has indicated the intimate
intertwining in which, for example, both Planck and Mach had been influenced in
different ways by the philosophical ideas of Immanuel Kant. Toulmin suggests that the
positivism of Mach worked its way into the very fabric of theoretical physics, shaping
Bohrs interpretation of quantum mechanics.
Physics and philosophy have had a continuous relationship, but a fluctuating one. . . . In
certain periods, physical scientists have been content to acknowledge their partnership with
philosophers, and even to see their own fundamental theories and methods as resting on
metaphysical foundations. (Toulmin 1970, p. ix)
As Matthews notes:
If science has developed as a dialogue with metaphysics . . ., then to teach science as a soliloquy
in which science just talks to itself and grows entirely by self-criticism is to impoverish the
subject matter. (Matthews 1992, p. 36)
References
Ashmore, M.: 1993, The Theatre of the Blind: Starring a Promethean Prankster, a
Phoney Phenomenon, a Prism, a Pocket and a Piece of Wood, Social Studies of
Science 23, 67106.
Bain, J. and Norton, J.: 1998, What Should Philosophers of Science Learn from the
History of the Electron?, unpublished manuscript.
Boden, M. (ed.): 1994, Dimensions of Creativity, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Boyd, R.: 1983, On the Current Status of Scientific Realism, Erkenntnis 19, 4590.
Reprinted in Boyd, Gasper and Trout, eds. The Philosophy of Science, MIT Press,
Cambridge, Mass., 1991, 195-222.
Boyd, R. G. P. and Trout, J. (eds): 1991, The Philosophy of Science, MIT Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
Peter Slezak 31
Brody, B. and Grandy, R. (eds): 1989, Readings in the Philosophy of Science, 2nd edn,
Prentice-Hall.
Bronowski, J.: 1960, The Commonsense of Science, Penguin Books, London.
Bronowski, J.: 1964, Science and Human Values, Penguin Books, London.
Bronowski, J.: 1978, The Visionary Eye, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Brown, J.: 1991, The Laboratory of the Mind, Routledge, London.
Brown, J.: 1994, Smoke and Mirrors: How Science Reflects Reality, Routledge, London.
Brush, S. G.: 1974, Should the History of Science be Rated X?, Science 183, 11641172.
Capra, F.: 1975, The Tao of Physics, Bantam, New York.
Collins, H. and Pinch, T.: 1992, The Golem: What Everyone Should Know About Science,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Cushing, J.: 1998, Philosophical Concepts in Physics: The Historical Relation Between
Philosophy and Scientific Theories, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Cushing, J. and McMullin, E. (eds): 1989, Philosophical Consequences of Quantum
Theory: Reflections on Bells Theorem, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre
Dame.
Cushing, J.T. Delaney, C. and Gutting, G. (eds): 1984, Science & Reality, University of
Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame.
Densmore, D.: 1995, Newtons Principia: The Central Argument: Translation, Notes
and Expanded Proofs, Green Lion Press, Santa Fe.
Drake, S.: 1957, Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo, Doubleday Anchor, New York.
Duhem, P.: 1906/1962., The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory, Athenaeum, New
York.
Earman, J. and Glymour, C.: 1980, Relativity and Eclipses, Historical Studies in the
Philsophy of Science 11(1), 4985.
Farrington, B.: 1961, Greek Science, Penguin Books, Middlesex.
Feynman, R.: 1965, The Character of Physical Law, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Fine, A.: 1986, The Shaky Game, Chicago University Press, Chicago.
Finocchiaro, M.: 1989, The Galileo Affair: A Documentary History, University of
California Press, Berkeley.
Fodor, J. A.: 1984, Observation Reconsidered, Philosophy of Science 51, 2343.
32 Does Science Teaching Need History and Philosophy of Science?
Giere, R.: 1988, Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach, University of Chicago
Press, Chicago.
Giere, R. (ed.): 1992, Cognitive Models of Science, Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy
of Science, Vol. XV, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
Glymour, C.: 1992, Realism and the Nature of Theories, in W. S. et. al. (ed.),
Introduction to the Philosophy of Science, Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs.
Gorman, M.: 1992, Simulating Science: Heuristics, Mental Models and Technoscientific
Thinking, Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Grim, P. (ed.): 1990, Philosophy of Science and the Occult, SUNY Press, New York.
Gross, P. and Levitt, N.: 1994, Higher Superstition, Johns Hopkins, Baltimore.
Guthrie, W. K. C.: 1962, A History of Greek Philosophy: The Earlier Presocratics and
the Pythagoreans, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Hacking, I.: 1981a, Do we see through a microscope?, Philosophical Quarterly 62(4).
Reprinted in B. Brody and R. Grandy eds., Readings in the Philosophy of Science,
2nd edition, Prentice-Hall, 1989, 29-43.
Hacking, I.: 1982, Experimentation and Scientific Realism, Philosophical Topics,
Vol. 13. 71-87, Reprinted in R. Boyd, P. Gasper & J.D. Trout eds., The Philosophy
of Science, Bradford/MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., 1991, 247-260.
Hacking, I. (ed.): 1981b, Scientific Revolutions, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Hanson, N.: 1958, Patterns of Discovery, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Heisenberg, W.: 1971, Physics and Beyond, Harper & Row, New York.
Hirschfeld, L. and Gelman, S. (eds): 1994, Mapping the Mind: Domain Specificity in
Cognition and Culture, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Holton, G.: 1973, Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein, Harvard
Univerity Press, Cambridge.
Holton, G.: 1978, The Scientific Imagination, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Hoyningen-Huene, P.: 1993, Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhns
Philosophy of Science, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Jauch, J. M.: 1989, Are Quanta Real? A Galilean Dialogue, Indiana University Press,
Bloomington.
Koestler, A.: 1972, The Roots of Coincidence, Hutchinson, London.
Peter Slezak 33
Kuhn, T. S.: 1959, The Essential Tension, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies
in Scientific Tradition and Change, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago,
1977, pp. 225239. Also reprinted in R. Boyd, P. Gasper & J.D. Trout eds., The
Philosophy of Science, Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford/MIT Press, 1991, 139 -147.
Kuhn, T. S.: 1970a, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago University Press,
Chicago.
Kuhn, T. S.: 1970b, Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?, in I. Lakatos and
A. Musgrave (eds), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Kuhn, T. S.: 1977, The Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and
Change, Chicago University Press, Chicago.
Lakatos, I.: 1978, The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge.
Laudan, L.: 1981, A Confutation of Convergent Realism, Philosophy of Science 48, 19
48. Reprinted in Boyd, Gasper & Trout eds, 1991, 223-245, and in Leplin ed.,
1984, 218-249.
Laudan, L.: 1983, The Demise of the Demarcation Problem, in R. Cohen and L. Laudan
(eds), Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis, Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 111127.
Laudan, L.: 1988, Science at the Bar - Causes for Concern (Reply to Ruse), in M. Ruse
(ed.), But Is It Science?, Prometheus Books, Buffalo.
Laudan, L.: 1990, Science And Relativism, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Leplin, J.: 1984, Scientific Realism, University of California Press, Berkeley.
Margolis, H.: 1993, Paradigms and Barriers, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Matthews, M.: 1994, Science Teaching: The Role of History and Philosophy of Science,
Routledge, New York.
Matthews, M. (ed.): 1989, The Scientific Background to Modern Philosophy: Selected
Readings, Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis.
Matthews, M. R.: 1992, History, Philosophy, and Science Teaching: The Present
Rapprochement, Science & Education 1, 1147.
Maxwell, G.: 1962, The Ontological Status of Theoretical Entities, in H. Feigl and
G. Maxwell (eds), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. III,
University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis. Reprinted in Brody and Grandy eds.,
Readings in the Philosophy of Science, 1989, 21-28.
Miller, A.: 1986, Imagery in Scientific Thought, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
34 Does Science Teaching Need History and Philosophy of Science?
Norton, J.: 1998, How We Know About Electrons, unpublished manuscript.
Norton, J. D.: 1994, Science and Certainty, Synthese 99, 322.
Pais, A.: 1994, Einstein Lived Here, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Pinch, T. and Collins, H.: 1984, Private Science and Public Knowledge: The Committee
for the Scientific Investigation of the Paranormal and its Use of the Literature,
Social Studies of Science 14, 52146.
Popper, K.: 1963, Back to the PreSocratics, in Conjectures and Refutations, Routledge
& Kegan Paul, London, pp. 136-165.
Popper, K.: 1974, Replies to my critics, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl
Popper, Vol. 2, Open Court, La Salle.
Putnam, H.: 1975, Mathematics, Matter and Method, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Ruse, M.: 1984, A Philosophers Day in Court, in A. Montague (ed.), Science and
Creation, Oxford University Press.
Ruse, M. (ed.): 1988, But Is It Science? The Philosophical Question in the Cre-
ation/Evolution Controversy, Prometheus Books, Buffalo.
Russell, B.: 1960, An Outline of Philosophy, Meridian Books, Cleveland.
Russell, B.: 1961, What I Believe, in R. Egner and L. Denon (eds), The Basic Writings
of Bertrand Russell, 1925, Simon & Schuster, New York.
Salmon. M. Earman, J. Glymour, C. et. al. (ed.): 1992, Introduction to the Philosophy of
Science, Prentice Hall, Englewood Cliffs.
Savage, C. (ed.): 1990, Scientific Theories: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, Vol. XIV, Minnesota University Press, Minneapolis.
Scheffler, I.: 1967, Science and Subjectivity, Bobbs Merrill, New York.
Slezak, P.: 1996, Review of Paul Davies The Mind of God, Science & Education 5, 201
212.
Slezak, P.: 2000, Radical Social Constructivism, NSSE Yearbook. forthcoming.
Sorensen, R.: 1992, Thought Experiments, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Thagard, P.: 1988, Computational Philosophy of Science, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Thagard, P.: 1992, Conceptual Revolutions, Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Toulmin, S. (ed.): 1970, Physical Reality, Harper & Row, New York.
Peter Slezak 35
Tweney, R.D. Doherty, M. and Mynatt, C. (eds): 1981, On Scientific Thinking, Columbia
University Press, New York.
van Fraassen, B.: 1976, To Save the Phenomena, Journal of Philosophy 73(18), 62332.
Reprinted in Boyd, Gasper and Trout eds., 1991, 186-194.
van Frassen, B.: 1980, The Scientific Image, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
P.R.K. Rao
Formerly of Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur, India
As this book is about teaching and history, before I recall my fading memory traces
of my experience of teaching history and philosophy of science at IIT (Indian Institute
of Technology)-Kanpur, let me begin by reminding you of two cautionary remarks of
George Bernard Shaw, Teaching, he said, is ineffective except in those instances in
which it is superfluous. Perhaps, there is an element of truth in the claim that our
students learn inspite of us rather than because of us! About history, Shaw maintained
that the only lesson that we can learn from history is that nobody learns from it.
These two indictments, whatever their truth, can help moderate our, excessive en-
thusiasm for and expectations of innovations in science education. Moreover, nothing
warrants the presumption that every civilized, vibrant nation must necessarily be also
a scientifically advanced nation.
The kind of concerns and circumstances that prompted some of us at IIT Kanpur to
introduce a programme of courses in history of science, scientific method, science and
technology and its linkages with society are best captured by the observations of the
first and the last programme leaders of the KanpurIndo-American programme which
helped establish IIT Kanpur with the participation of a consortium of nine leading
American Universities. The first programme leader, Normal Dahl had observed that
IIT Kanpur has been an irrelevant factor in the industrial and social progress in India
. . . a kind of isolated island of academic excellence but not part of the mainstream of
Indias development. This assessment worried some of us for we were imbued with
the idea that institutions like IIT Kanpur were set upto to be able to attend to the
scientific and technological needs of the country. What distressed us even more and
drove home our failure as educators was the telling observation of the last programme
leader Mr. Oakely. He said that IIT Kanpur students face no technological background
problems of adjustment in M.I.T., one of the foremost symbols of high-technology west,
and the same students show considerable enthusiasm when, possibly for the first time
in their education, they are exposed to the ideas of growth of technology and its relation
to percieved technological needs specific to a country.
Science is a selective cognitive enterprise. The nature of that selectivity, to my mind,
is succintly described by Hertz in the introduction to his book, Principles of Mechanics.
We form images or symbols of objects such that the logically necessary consequences
of those symbols or images are the same as the materially necessary consequences
of the objects that correspond to the symbols or images. What is interesting in Hertzs
account is the feature of the considerable freedom that exists in the formation of images
or symbols of objects even as they must obey the above stipulated important limitation.
In the cognitive enterprise called science, while we are necessarily performing, what
Hans Jonas has called the primary ontological reduction of the actual objects of the
38 Teaching HPS
world (as for example, point masses in place of extended physical objects in rigid body
dynamics), there is no unique way of performing that primary ontological reduction.
Earlier, successful scientific practices, cultural influences, environmental pressures,
socioeconomic factors etc., may contingently further constrain a particular scientific
community in exercising the freedom involved in primary ontological reduction, but the
existence of that freedom is the condition of possibility of what we understand by the
term creativity. Our failure as teachers at IIT Kanpur consisted in not even sensitizing
our students to the idea that science is a human and historical practice, let alone
provoking them to draw on their creativity to perform such fruitful primary ontological
reductions which will enable them to attend to the scientific and technological needs
of the society to which they belong. Undoubtedly we have been quite successful in
training our students to use established recipes in their chosen disciplines. But we
have not even attended to the more important problem of orienting them so that they
perceive a relevant segment of reality around them, perform novel primary ontological
reductions, formulate the pertinent problems and solve them creatively.
Our failure, it then appeared to us, can be traced, at least in part, to the situa-
tion in which not only lay man but also practicing scientists are so overwhelmed by
the products of science that they pay scant attention to the processes by which the
enterprise of science manufactures knowledge. One disastrous consequence of this
lack of self-reflexivity, particularly in a third world country like India, has been the
gradual weakening of critical, social and political forces that could mediate between the
requirements of autonomy of the expert scientific community and the developmental
needs of the country.
The above account should have made it clear that even in an institution like IIT
Kanpur famous for its flexibility in procedures it is not going to be easy to introduce
new courses that do not fall within the framework of established disciplinary divisions.
Fortunately for us, at that point of time there was a circular from the Ministry of Edu-
cation which desired the introduction in IITs and other educational institutions courses
devoted to historical practices in India related to temple architectures, ship-building,
metallurgy and other indigeneous pre-industrial technologies. We took advantage of
this particular circular and constituted a committee, with Prof. Mohini Mullick as
the chairperson, to look into the possibilities of introducing courses in history and
philosophy of science with particular reference to India. A few years later this course
on History of Scientific Ideas was introduced as an open elective in the third year of
the four year programme.
We also conducted a five day workshop in 1982 on the development of a curriculum
in philosophy of science, history of science, science and technology and society. Based
on the discussions which took place in that workshop we subsequently formulated some
courses. We also made a largely unsuccessful effort to see that each instructor delivers
some three to four lectures on the historical aspects of whatever subject he is teaching
in a semester. Many faculty members thought it to be a waste of time particularly when
they have so much syllabus to cover. As always, there are notable exceptions: Prof.
Amitabh Ghosh who is currently the Director of IIT Kharagpur, and Prof. A.K. Biswas
who used to offer a course on history of science in India.
Rao 39
More often than not any effort to have faculty engagement with or study of any
historical, philosophical aspects of science met with resistance. Responses varied from
What is in it there for me? to Will it help me to publish more often?
It was probably in 1982 that the course on History of Scientific Ideas was offered for
the first time IIT Kanpur. There were five of us as instructors (Professors Mohini Mul-
lick, A.P. Shukla, K.S. Gandhi, V.K. Jairath and myself) sharing eight lectures each and
we had three students (two of them were students of physics and the third of computer
science)! None of the instructors was a professional historian. I must confess that even
today it is not clear to me whether it was a setback or an advantage. Perhaps it is both.
On the one hand, we have the eminent scientist and equally well known historian of
science, Truesdell, assuring us that it is the standard claim of scientists that most
historians do not have sufficient grasp of science, itself to understand the facts rather
than the mere circumustances of its history. On the other hand, we are alerted by the
J.B. Cohen, that Professional historians are wont to complain of the attempts of the
scientist whose approach to history often sufferes from the consequences of a purely
scientific training. Kuhn, in his paper, The Relations between History and History
of Science (Daedalus, Vol. 100, No. 2) discuss the problem of teaching of history of
science. I am inclined to believe that the problem involved is more complex than one
of teaching or of history or of science. We may remind ourselves of Kants famous
injunction that history without philosophy is blind and philosophy without history is
sterile. But we all know the consequences of riding two horses at the same time. The
Nobel laureate poet, Czeslaw Milosz in his Charles Eliot Norton lectures at Harvard
in 1982 summarized the situation thusas far as poets are concerned: Many learned
books on poetry have been written, and they find, at least in the countries of the west,
more readers than poetry itself. This is not a good sign, even if it may be explained both
by the brilliance of their authors and by their zeal in assimilating scientific disciplines
which today enjoy universal respect. A poet who would like to compete with those
mountains of erudition would have to pretend that he possesses more self-knowledge
than poets are allowed to possess. What is the case with a poet is also in good measure
the case with a scientist or a historian or in fact with any one who is engaged in
making valid knowledge claims. The necessarily historical character of the knowledge
system of science and the limited role that the individual practicing scientist plays in
the production of cognitive goods by and large restricts the span of his philosophical,
historical, ethical and social concerns in that production. This restriction of concerns
not merely at the level of the individual practitioner of science but also at the level
of knowledge claims of science detracts from the secular character of science in so far
as it resists the critical examination of its own founding (un)concerns in its practices.
And as long as this situation prevails, not only teaching of history of science will be
plagued by charges of only attending to the mere circumustances if its history or to the
counter-charges of the distorting consequences of a purely scientific training, but more
importantly, the freedom available in performing primary ontological reductions that
are comensurate with the philosophical, historical, ethical and social concerns cannot
be pressed into service for the generation of knowledges that are genuinely liberating.
The course, History of Scientific Ideas, has by now been offered for more than ten
40 Teaching HPS
years by me and Prof. A.P. Shukla (See Appendix B for a topic outline of the course).
The number of students who registered in the course at any given time never exceeded
twenty five. But one notable feature is that there always used to be a sizeable number
of auditors, some times as many as the creditors of the course. It is interesting to
know that between eighty to hundred thousand candidates appear in the joint entrance
examination of the IITs and out of them about three hundred get admitted into each
IIT. They are admittedly a bright lot but they are innocent of philosophy and ignorant
of history. History to them is a boring chronology of events and philosophy a waste of
time. Moreover, in their schools they are indoctrinated with received cannon of what
science is. To break the consequent resistance on their part and sensitize them to the
idea that science is a historical activity and there can be alternative creative punc-
tuations of reality more adequate to the lived life-world than those of contemporary
science, I used to resort to pedagogical-shock treatment, so to speak: I would circulate
an excerpt from the famous preface of the book, Order of Things, by Michel Foucault
(see Appendix D) in which he talks about a particular Chinese encyclopaedia in which
animals are taxonomically ordered in ways that cannot even be conceived by many
of us. Or I would distribute two excerpts on social order in early Hindu society, one
by Ananda K. Coomaraswamy and another by Kosambi (see Appendix A). Both refer to
the same empirical domain but each gives an interpretation which is antithetical to the
other, Coomaraswamy interprets the entire social order in terms of the requirements
of ritual sacrifices. Kosambi, on the other hand, interprets the same social formation
in terms of Marxist categories. I would invariably describe the episode in which Neils
Bohr and Heisenberg went to the Kronberg Castle in Denmark. Here is what Bohr said
as recapitulated by Heisenberg:
Isnt it strange how this castle changes as soon as one imagines that Hamlet lived here. As
scientists we believe that a castle consists only of stones, and admire the way architects put
them together. The stone, the green roof with its patina, the wood carvings in the church,
constitute the whole castle. None of this should be changed by the fact that Hamlet lived
here, and yet it is changed completely. Suddenly the walls and the ramparts speak a different
language. The courtyard becomes an entire world, a dark corner reminds us of the human soul,
we hear Hamlets To be or not to be. Yet all we really know about Hamlet is that his name
appears in a thirteenth-century chronicle. No one can really prove that he really lived here.
But everyone knows the questions Shakespeare had him ask, the human depths he was made
to reveal, and so he too had to be found a place on earth here, in Kronberg.
I would draw on Carrs little book, What is History?, to drive home the idea that
history is a continual dialogue of the present with the past and therefore historical
truths are not frozen collection of facts but, like scientific truths, are eternally revisable
in light of new evidence and new frameworks of interpretation. Sometimes, a little
mischievously, I would ask the students to imagine what would have happened if the
Michelson-Morley experiment (which rendered ether the emperors new clothes) were
conducted before the earlier truth of geocentric theory was declared falsel in favour of
the new thruth of heliocentric theory!
There is another important aspect of the course which I would like to mention.
I used to give on a regular basis reading assignments. Each student was asked to
submit a written summary of the article assigned and argue for his/her agreements and
Rao 41
disagreements with the epistemological or ontological or methodological or historical or
realist/anti-realist claims explicitly or implicitly made by the author of the article. One
of my favourites is the article on roots of atomic physics from the book, Physics and
Philosophy, by Heisenberg. Another is the article, The Dematerialization of Matter,
by N.R. Hanson. A third interesting paper, I often used to assign, is Nobel Laureate
biologist, George Walds Innovation in Biology. Sometimes, to place in evidence the
changing and the now discarded scientific vocabulary and the important role played
by text-books in influencing the cognitive orientation of future practitioners of science,
I would assign for reading an eighteenth or nineteenth century scientific article or
selection from a text-book. The main purpose of these assignments, as that of the
course, is to let the student see for himself that whether or not science describes reality
as it really is, as history of science demonstrates, it attempts to describe that reality
by seeing it through a contingently chosen cognitive grid and that he and his relevant
community can draw on their cognitive resources to choose another cognitive grid more
suited to the life-world they belong to.
Appendix C also includes a sample examination paper. I take advantage of its
inclusion (the statement by Mazlish) to contest if not dispel the widespread belief
that science and the church are in continuous conflict. In point of fact what one finds
from the history of science is that many men of the establishment of the church made
significant contributions to the enterprise of science in the latters formative years. The
men of God believed that reason can be enlisted in support of faith which of course to
them was of paramount importance.
A word about student and faculty response to the course. The student reaction
surveys always elicited a negative response to the idea of dropping the course from
the curriculum. And more often than not they also expressed the view that there is
a significant change in their understanding of the nature of scientific activity and its
place in society. More surprisingly, many faculty who were earlier on suspicious about
the usefulness of this course based on whatever reports they probably got from others
began to consider the course as conceptually interesting and rigourous.
Finally, let me briefly state my views on the importance of courses on history and
philosophy of science in science education. I do not believe that teaching such courses
will make the students more creative scientists. Firstly, we do not have, and, I believe,
we can never have, an algorithm for transforming people into creative scientists or
artists or whatever. When Gauss was once asked as to how he finally succeeded in
proving a theorem the proof of which eluded him for several years he is supposed
to have answered: By divine inspiration. An element of mystery must always en-
velop the creative act. Secondly, the kind of self-reflexive, critical attitude that one
develops through studies in history and philosophy of science, I suspect, dampens the
bold, aggressive, adventurous asumption-making disposition that one asociates with
creativity. What I have argued for in the previous pages is that study of history
and philosophy of science suggests that doing science creatively involves performing a
primary ontological reduction of the objects of the world and that there are no grounds
for believing that only one such reduction is possible. If my claim is valid, study of
history and philosophy of science enables us to recognize what it takes to be creative.
42 Teaching HPS
It does not make us creative. For we may lack the requisite capacity to perform primary
ontological reduction even though we know that is what we must do to be considered
creative. Moreover, such recognition is not necessary for one to be creative.
There can be other reasons for the importance of study of history and philosophy of
science. Many of us as teachers have often encountered the situation in which a student
who is admitted into, say, computer science programme considers that we are imposing
an unnecessary burden on him when we prescribe a course on electromagnetic theory
or chemistry. What is not recognized by him is that transporting ideas from one domain
into another can sometimes help better understanding of ideas in the, latter domain
and may even facilitate creativity. Transporting the familiar idea that all history
is contemporary history may help recognize that scientific truths are not ahistorical
truths. Above all, the study of history and philosophy of science can be an intellectually
enriching experience in so far as that study allows us to see the limits of liberation
that can be secured by the dominant knowledge system of our times. Indicating the
limits of a subject taught is an important responsibility of the teacher as the German
scientists and intellectuals of the second world war generation painfully realized. The
post second world war commission for university reform in Germany came up with the
following recommendation: Every lecturer in the university must have the ability: 1.
To see the limits of his subject material in his teaching to make the students aware of
these limits and to show them that beyond these limits forces come into play which are
no longer entirely rational, but arise out of life and human society itself. 2. To show
in every subject the way that leads beyond its own narrow confines to broader horizons
of its own, I am inclined to believe that study of history and philosophy of science can
help a teacher in his efforts to acquire those abilities.
Appendix A
1. Hinduism by Ananda K. Coomaraswamy, Philosophical Library, New York
The Social Order: Where there is agreement as to the nature of mans last end,
and that the way by which the present and the paramount ends of life can be
realised is that of sacrificial operation, it is evident that the form of society will be
determined by the requirements of the Sacrifice; and that order (yatharthata) and
impartiality (samadrsti) will mean that everyman shall be enabled to become, and
by no mis-direction prevented from becoming, what he has it in him to become.
We have seen that it is to those who maintain the Sacrifice that the promise is
made that they shall flourish. Now the Sacrifice, performed in divinis by the
All-worker (Visvakarma), as imitated here demands a cooperation of all the arts
(visva karmani), for example, those of music, architecture, carpentry, husbandry
and that of warfare to protect the operation. The politics of the heavenly, social
and individual communities are governed by one and the same law. The pattern
of the heavenly politics, is revealed in scripture and reflected in the constitution
of the autonomous state and that of the man who governs himself.
In this man, in whom the sacramental life is complete, there is a hierarchy of
sacerdotal, royal; and administrative powers, and a fourth class consisting of the
Rao 43
physical organs of sense and action, that handle the raw material or food to
be prepared for all; and it is clear that if the organism is to flourish, which is
impossible if divided against itself, that the sacerdotal, royal and administrative
powers, in their order of rank, must be the masters, and the workers in raw
materials their servants. It is in precisely the same way that the functional
hierarchy of the realm is determined by the requirements of the Sacrifice on
which its prosperity depends. The casted are literally born of the Sacrifice. In
the sacramental order there is a need and a place for all mens work: and there is
no more significant consequence of the principle, Work is Sacrifice, than the fact
that under these conditions, and remote as this may be from our secular ways of
thinking, every function, from that of the priest and the king down to that of the
potter and scavenger, is literally a priesthood and every operation a rite. In each
of these spheres, moreover, we meet with professional ethics. The caste sys-
tem differs from the industrial division of labor, with its fractioning of human
faculty, in that it presupposes differences in kinds of responsibility but not in
degrees of responsibility; and it is just because an organisation of functions such
as this, with its mutual loyalties and duties, is absolutely incompatible with our
competitive industrialism, that the monarchic, feudal and caste system is always
pianted in such dark colors by the sociologist, whose thinking is determined more
by his actual environment than it is a deduction from first principles.
The Aryans had little difficulty in penetrating to within 50 miles of the Yamuna
river. The thinner forest of the region could be burnt down. But the social
organisation necessary for settling the land cleared by fire went beyond the simple
tribe. The lowest castefor caste had developed within the tribewas now called
sudra possibly from the tribal name (e.g. the Oxydrakoi on the lower Indus who
fought against Alexander). These were helots who belonged to the tribe or clan
group as a whole in much the same manner as the tribal cattle, without the
membership rights of the tribe as granted to the three upper castes. These three
higher castes were properly recognised as Aryan and full members of the tribe:
kshatriya (warrior and ruler), brahmana (brahmin priest), vaisya (the settler who
produced all the food surplus by agriculture and cattle breeding). The word varna
came to mean one of these four class castes, which constituted a class structure
within such of the tribes as had reached advanced forms of property-holding and
indulged in trade exchange on a sufficiently large scale. This was not true of
every single Aryan tribe, many of whom continued undifferentiated while others
had only the arya-sudra (free v. helot) division. That the sudra was not bought
and sold as in ancient Greece and Rome was due to no kindness on the part of the
Indo-Aryans. It was simply that commodity production and private property had
not developed far enough.
The existence of the sudra caste had a peculiar effect upon later Indian society.
Chattel slavery in the sense of classical European (specifically Graeco-Roman)
antiquity was never to be of any size or importance in the means and relations
of production in India. The expropriable surplus could always be produced by
44 Teaching HPS
the sudra. The development of caste foreshadowed a general class society beyond
the exclusiveness of a tribe. A few of the brahmins had begun to officiate for
more than one clan or tribe, which implied some type of relationship between
several groups. A few brahmins at the other end of the economic scale had
begun to advance into the dense forest to the east, in fairly small groups with
their own cattle; sometimes even as individuals with no property and no arms for
defence or hunting. Their harmlessness was obvious, and they were of the utmost
importance in coming to terms with the food-gathering Naga savages of the forest,
whom they often joined, or with whom they lived on friendly terms. Their sole
protection was their poverty and manifestly innocuous nature. The traders, on
the other hand, were convoyed at need by armed kshatriyas who would protect
them against the aborigines (nishada). These kshatriyas grew into mercenary
groups ready to fight in anyones service for hire.
2. Hinduism by D.D. Kosambi
Without mincing words, the ritual books say: Like a vaisya . . . tributary to an-
other, to be eaten up by another, to be oppressed at will . . .. Like a sudra . . .
the servant of another, to be the primary producers, were to be enclosed be-
tween the two upper castes during the sacrificial procession of the whole tribe,
to make them submissive. After this the basic class nature of caste need hardly
be doubted, though it was still class on a primitive level of production. The first
taxes were called bali because they were gifts brought to the chief at the sacrifice
by members of the tribe or clan. There was a particular official known only at this
transitional period, the king apportioner (bhaga-dugha). His job seems to have
been the proper sharing out of the bali gifts among the tribal kings immediate
followers, and perhaps assessment of taxes as well.
Appendix B
Outline of the course on history of scientific ideas
Text-Books
Chalmers, A.F.: 1982, What Is This Thing Called Science?, University of Queens-
land Press, St. Lucia, Qld.
Dijkterhuis, E.J.: 1986, The Mechanization of the World Picture, tr. by C. Dik-
shoorn, Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Merz, J.T.: 1903-1914, A History of European Thought in the 19th Century, W. Black-
wood & Sons, Edinburgh, London.
Appendix C
Sample Examination Paper
Indian Institute of Technology, Kanpur
Science, Metascience, Society
SE 862-History of Scientific ideas
II Mid Semester Examination
Bacon, Galileo and Descartes can veritably be called the founders of the method
of modern science. Identify the most important idea in each case, which became a
foundation stone of Science and show how this self-same idea has become historically
transformed into a better sapping science of its virality.
Q.2.
The warfare of Science with theology in christendom . . . . . . is simply part of a continuing conflict
a conflict which takes its rise from the contradictory nature of man: rational and irrational,
creator of his own conditions, and conditioned by forces seemingly beyond his control. The
tension generated by these warring elements is not a mere transient phase of mans existence:
as long as he remains human, it will be his problem and his glory. When it ceases we will be no
longer recording history, which by definition deals with human beings. (D. Mazlish)
Logic and reason have been put to service of christian dogma and study of nature
and science, both simultaneously and, to the mutual exclusion of each other. Elaborate
on this dynamical process by the historical development of European thought from 11th
to the middle of 16th century, as a concrete example.
Q.3. Every significant institution, individual, or thought of the past, must be a product
of the travails of its times. And we can benefit by it only if we can currently relate its
relevance and irrelevance with the present. Comment in this light on any four of the
following:
1. Pythagoras
2. Aristotelian causality
3. Hellenistic Astronomy
4. Ishale at-Kindi
5. Brethren of sincerity
6. Newtonian synthesis
Format of answers: You are expected first to elaborate on the views propounded on
these topics in the lectures, and then give reasons for your agreement or disagreement.
Appendix D
The Order of Things by Foucault, Preface, p. xv.
This book first arose out of a passage in Borges, out of the laughter that shattered,
as I read the passage, all the familiar landmarks of my thoughtour thought, the
thought that bears the stamp of our age and our geographybreaking up all the
ordered surfaces and all the planes with which we are accustomed to tame the wild
Rao 47
profusion of existing things, and continuing long afterwards to disturb and threaten
with collapse our age-old distinction between the Same and the Other. This passage
quotes a certain Chinese encyclopaedia in which it is written that animals are divided
into: (a) belonging to the Emperor, (b) embalmed, (c) tame, (d) sucking pigs, (e) sirens,
(f) fabulous, (g) stray dogs, (h) included in the present classification, (i) frenzied, (j)
innumerable, (k) drawn with a very fine camelhair brush, (l) et cetera, (m) having just
broken the water pitcher, (n) that from a long way off look like flies. In the wonderment
of this taxonomy, the thing we apprehend in one great leap, the thing that, by means
of the fable, is demonstrated as the exotic charm of another system of thought, is the
limitation of our own, the stark impossibility of thinking that.
References
Carr, E.: 1974, What is History?, Penguin, London.
Coomaraswamy, A.: Hinduism, Philosophical Library, New York.
Foucault, M.: 1970, The Order of Things, Tavistock Publications, London.
Hanson, N. R.: 1958, The Dematerialization of Matter.
Heisenberg, W.: 1958, Physics and Philosophy, George Allen and Unwin Edition.
Kuhn, T.: 1971, The Relations between History and History of Science, Daedalus
100(2).
Wald, G.: 1958, Innovation and Biology, Scientific American 199, 100.
48 Teaching HPS
Multiculturalism in Science Education and the Question of
Universalism
William W. Cobern
Western Michigan University, USA. Email: bill.cobern@wmich.edu
Cathleen C. Loving
Texas A&M University. Email: cloving@tamu.edu
Introduction
Is science universal? Only recently has this question been given any serious consid-
eration at all. In the tradition of science as practiced in the West for the past 300
years and in the tradition of school science, the answer has been, Of course science is
universal. As Richard Dawkins likes to put it, there are no epistemological relativists
at 30,000 feet. But today some will say, Not so fast! Dawkins offers a brute definition
of universality completely devoid of any nuance of understanding and equally devoid
of relevance to the question at hand. No one disputes that without an airplane of fairly
conventional description, a person at 30,000 feet is in serious trouble. The question of
universality does not arise over the phenomena of falling. The question of universality
arises over the fashion of the propositions given to account for the phenomena of falling,
the fashion of the discourse through which we communicate our thoughts about the
phenomena, and the values we attach to the phenomena itself and the various ways
we have of understanding and accounting for the phenomenaincluding the account
offered by a standard scientific description. In todays schools there are often competing
accounts of natural phenomena especially where schools are located in multicultural
communities. There are also competing claims about what counts as science. The
purpose of our paper is to examine the definition of science put forward from multicul-
tural perspectives in contrast to a universalist perspective on science, i.e., the Standard
Account. We will argue that good science explanations will always be universal even
if we do incorporate indigenous knowledge as scientific and broaden what is taught as
science. What works best is still of interest to most and although we hate to use the
word hegemonyWestern science would co-opt and dominate indigenous knowledge
if it were incorporated as science. Therefore, indigenous knowledge is better off as a
different kind of knowledge that can be valued for its own merits, that can play a vital
role in science education, and can maintain a position of independence from which it
can critique the practices of science and the Standard Account.
The undeterred critic, however, will still ask: Though the phenomenon are experien-
tially universal, cant one argue that scientific accounts are not universal since such
accounts are not universally accepted?
The resolution of such questions hinges on the definition of science, including the
concept of universality, and this resolution is of considerable importance for both ed-
ucators and the public at large. When a discipline earns the title science it acquires
the authority to promulgate truthful and reliable knowledge, control over education
and credentials, access to money and manpower, and the kind of political clout that
comes from possessing knowledge that is essential yet esoteric (Fuller, 1988, p. 177).
In science education the definition of science is a de facto gate keeping device for what
can be included in a school science curriculum and what cannot. A very large amount of
money, for example, has been spent in the USA on litigating the question of whether or
not creation science can be properly included as an aspect of school science (Nelkin,
1983; Overton, 1983). Moreover, if science is deemed universal it not only displaces
scientific pretenders such as creation science, it as well displaces any local knowledge
that conflicts with it. Kawagley, Norris-Tull & Norris-Tull (1998, p. 134) argue that
such a narrow view of science not only diminishes the legitimacy of knowledge derived
through generations of naturalistic observation and insight, it simultaneously devalues
those cultures which traditionally rely heavily on naturalistic observation and insight.
The record is fairly clear. Around the globe where science is taught, it is taught at
the expense of indigenous knowledge and this precipitates charges of epistemological
hegemony and cultural imperialism.
People feel passionately about these issues. The passions in the academy have run
so high that the controversies have been dubbed the Science Wars (Nature, 1997).
At school levels, the struggle is over multicultural approaches to science and science
education within multicultural situations. Actions taken are at times extreme. In
Cobern & Loving 51
1987, the Portland Oregon School District published the African-American Baseline
Essays, a set of six revisionist essays providing resource materials and references for
teachers on the knowledge and contributions of Africans and African-Americans. The
science baseline essay, written by Hunter Havelin Adams (1990), has serious problems,
but it is widely distributed because of the current pressure on school districts to incor-
porate multicultural material into the classroom coupled with the dearth of this kind of
material. Hundreds of copies of the Baseline Essays have been sent to school districts
across the country and they have been adopted or are being seriously considered by
school districts as diverse as Fort Lauderdale, Detroit, Milwaukee, Atlanta, Chicago,
Prince George County, MD, and Washington, DC. Even more widely distributed is its
predecessor, Blacks in Science: Ancient and Modern, edited by Ivan Van Sertima (1984).
Vine DeLoria, who is involved with Indian science education through the American
Indian Science and Engineering Society (AISES) has recently published a book entitled
Red Earth, White Lies: Native Americans and the Myth of Scientific Facts (DeLoria,
1995). These supplements on multicultural science, expressly intended to raise the
self-esteem of students, adopt a triumphalist approach to the material. That is, they
present the achievements and the beliefs of the group described as superior and antic-
ipatory to the achievements and beliefs of modern Western science. Thus, the Dogon of
Mali supposedly studied Sirius B, which is invisible to the naked eye, hundreds of years
ago. The Egyptians foreshadowed the Theory of Evolution thousands of years ago;
the Egyptians also anticipated many of the philosophical aspects of quantum theory
(Adams, p. 21), and they knew the particle/wave nature of light (p. 26).
The Baseline Essays and similar publications represent a radical revisionist histo-
riography of science and culture. There are other examples of multicultural materials
for science education that are far less controversial. Books such as Robertta Barbas
(1995), Science in the Multicultural Classroom: A Guide to Teaching and Learning
and the Addison Wesley (1993) teachers guide, Multiculturalism in Mathematics, Sci-
ence, and Technology: Readings and Activities bring culture into the science classroom
for pedagogical purposes without rewriting history. The nature of science implicit in
these books, however, represents a subtle change from standard accounts. Looking
elsewhere, the question of how science is to be defined is brought into clear relief (e.g.,
Kawagley, Norris-Tull, & Norris-Tull, 1998; Snivley & Corsiglia, 1998). With specific
reference to First Nations people in Canada and the Yupiaq people of Alaska, one finds
that indigenous knowledge is reclassified as sciencebut not science according to the
Standard Account and therein lies the controversy.
And of course the European Romantic poets echoed this lament (see Barber, 1963).
Moreover, Europe was an expansionist culture, and European exploration, conquest
and colonization of lands beyond Europe brought Western science to those lands and
their inhabitants. In these parts of the world where Western science is experienced as
a relatively new phenomena, the interaction of science with culture has taken a more
violent form and the disintegrating effects have been much more sharply experienced
(Ladriere, 1977, p. 14). Indeed, colonial education designed for indigenous peoples
used science as the tool of choice to modernize and supplant indigenous culture. In the
words of one colonialist: A literate nation is provided with the means for substituting
scientific explanations of everyday eventssuch as death, disease, and disasterfor
the supernatural, non-scientific explanations which prevail in developing societies . . .
(Lord, 1958, p. 340). A more reflective colonial teacher remarked, . . . In common with
so many others, I used to think that we could get rid of Bantu stupidities by suitable
talks on natural science, hygiene, etc., as if the natural sciences could subvert their
traditional lore or their philosophy (Tempels, 1959, p. 29). The point is, the West
judged the rest of the world by its own measure of choice, Western science and Western
technology, and used education to enforce change on those societies found deficient.
According to Adas (1989, p. 4) European perceptions of the material superiority of
their own cultures, particularly as manifested in scientific thought and technological
innovation, shaped their attitudes toward and interaction with peoples they encoun-
tered overseas. Why? Because:
In the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, most European thinkers concluded that the
unprecedented control over nature made possible by Western science and technology proved
that European modes of thought and social organization corresponded much more closely to
the underlying realities of the universe than did those of any other people or society, past or
present. (Adas, 1989, p. 7)
Western scientists did have scientific interests in the rest of the world. Many areas
of the globe became field sites for the practice of Western science by Western scientists
(Basalla, 1967). Darwins voyage on the Beagle is surely the best known example of
Western scientific development derived from non-European field work. When scien-
tists occasionally took note of indigenous knowledge of Nature, that knowledge was
distinctively labeled ethnoscience (e.g., Berlin, 1972; Behrens, 1989; Boster & Johnson,
Cobern & Loving 53
1989)never simply science. This is not to say that such indigenous knowledge was
regarded as without value. There is a long tradition of Western science finding value
in indigenous knowledge especially as an aide to pharmaceutical discovery (Linden,
1991). But, finding value in indigenous knowledge is not the same as conferring the
title, science, and admitting indigenous knowledge of Nature to the Standard Account.
In the 1990s, non-Western people and some scholars within the West began to for-
mally and overtly resist this imperial Western attitude toward indigenous knowledge
of Nature. This movement was abetted by the program for the social study of science,
founded in the 1970s at Edinburgh (Bloor & Barnes, 1996), which argued that all sci-
ence is socially contingent and culturally embedded. New epistemological perspectives
such as multiculturalism (Stanley & Brickhouse, 1994), post colonialism (McKinley,
1997), and post modernism (Lyotard, 1995) rose to challenge the conventional Western
wisdom on the relationship between science and culture and the Standard Account
itself. In education Hodson (1993, p. 686) maintained that science curricula often
portray science as located within, and exclusively derived from, a western cultural
context. The implicit curriculum message is that the only science is western science. . .
Dr. Thom Alcoze is Native American and a forestry professor at Northern Arizona Uni-
versity. In a taped interview for a science teacher development project (Smithsonian
Institution, 1996b) he poignantly presented a different perspective on science.
Science is often thought of [pause] America has science. Mainstream America has science.
And if you are a minority culture in this country you dont have science. We started looking
for Indian science where science is expressed in Indian tradition. And found it with plants,
starting off. Medicines. And of course the stereotype is well Indian medicine is just superstition
and mumbo-jumbo, slight of hand, and basically its a witch doctor kind of thing [pause] a
stereotype. A lot of strange noises and dancin and singin and a lot of shakin but thats all it
is [pause] superstitious. Its not real. What we found out when we looked for facts, we found
that even today in modern America there are over 200 medicines in the pharmacopoeia that we
use that have direct origins in Native American medical practice. Yes, in fact Indian people did
have science. They were using science all the time. They werent using scientific terminology.
They did not publish in scientific journals [pause] thats kind of facetious at that time. But the
issue of science then started to be redefined in my definition of what science is all about when
we started to see that science is just another word for nature.
Dr. Alcoze last sentence is of critical importance. He says, science is just another
word for nature and therefore American Indians being greatly knowledgeable about
Nature had scientific knowledge of their own. This idea is further developed in Kawa-
gley et al., (1998, p. 134): We contend that no single origin for science exists; that
science has a plurality of origins and a plurality of practices. They contend that there
is no one way to do or think about science (p. 139). As their case in point, they contend
that Yupiaq culture in southwestern Alaska holds a body of scientific knowledge and
epistemology that differs from that of Western science (p. 133).
Much of Yupiaq scientific knowledge is manifested most clearly in their technology. One may
argue that technology is not science. However, technology does not spring from a void. To
invent technological devices, scientific observations and experimentation must be conducted.
Yupiaq inventions, which include the kayak, river fish traps . . . represent technology that could
not have been developed without extensive scientific study of the flow of currents in rivers, the
54 Multiculturalism in Science Education
ebb and flow of tides in bays, and the feeding, resting, and migratory habits of fish, mammals,
and birds. (Kawagley et al., 1998, p. 136)
Similar accounts obtain for people living traditional lives in many other regions of
the world from Australia to Africa (see Warren, 1991 & 1997).
At this point a number of students raise hands. The teacher calls on them to speak
and she asks each student to explain the relationship of the Native American viewpoint
to decomposition. Later, Donna is asked in an interview about the purpose of such
activities.
Donna: My goal would be that all children would feel that they have a very important heritage.
No matter what heritage they come from. And to be a scientist doesnt mean that you have to be
any particular race or any particular gender or from any particular culture but that all people
have contributed to the body of knowledge which we call science. (Smithsonian Institution,
1996b)
In this vignette, Donna has set a very nice stage with her Native American poster
about views of nature. From here she can go on to have her class study what science
has learned about ecological cycles, balances of nature, decomposition, etc. Loving (in
press) and Cobern (1995a) offer similar views on using local culture to promote science
learning.
One would only hope that along the way, reference might be made back to the poster
to see if science supports, ignores or rejects ideas from ones culture and what evidence
there is to support that. In Donnas case above the controversial questions are about
her meaning for the world science and will she lead her students to understand that
there are different legitimate ways of thinking about Nature? Nature is viewed as
sacred is one such legitimate way but it is not the way of science. Thus, we would
want to know if Donna intends to help her students cognitively construct two different,
though complementary, explanations for the same phenomena? Or, will the students
learn the multiplicity view that all of this simply represents different forms of science?
56 Multiculturalism in Science Education
The Universality of Science
As much as we support science teaching that is both informed by culture and sensitive
to culture, the issues raised by TEK and multicultural perspectives on science must
not be accepted uncritically. We say this not in defense of science and the Standard
Account. We think that science has shown itself sufficiently useful and remarkable
to humanity that there will be no withdrawal of science from modern life. And, it is
arguable that science would suffer little harm if, for the purposes of curriculum, TEK
and similar domains of knowledge were declared scientific tomorrow. In contrast, such
an action would actually be counterproductive with respect to the concerns people have
about indigenous knowledge being shut out of science by the Standard Account. Before
developing that thought, however, we clarify our meaning of the Standard Account and
the case for universality.
1.1 Science is about natural phenomena. It is not about the things that humans
construct such as economic systems nor is it about spiritual phenomena. Here we
concur that TEK is about natural phenomena.
1.2 The explanations that science offers are naturalistic and material. It follows from
point 1.1 that scientific explanations are not about the spiritual, emotional, economic,
aesthetic, and social aspects of human experience. Snively & Corsiglia (1998) recognize
that with respect to TEK this aspect of the Standard Account poses a problem even
though TEK is about natural phenomena. They note that many scientists refuse to
recognize TEK as science because of its spiritual base, which they regard as supersti-
tious and fatalistic (p. 30). In response, they argue that spiritual explanations often
incorporate important ecology, conservation, and sustainable development strategies
(p. 30); but nevertheless, they still assert that the spiritual acquisition and expla-
nation of TEK is a fundamental component and must be promoted if the knowledge
system is to survive (Johnson, 1992 quoted in Snively & Corsiglia, 1998, p. 31).
1.3 Science explanations are empirically testable (at least in principle) against natural
phenomena (the test for empirical consistency) or against other scientific explanations
of natural phenomena (the test for theoretical consistency). Science involves collect-
ing data (i.e., evidence) and a scientific explanation must be able to account for this
data. Alternatively, science involves the testing of proposed explanations against data
(Driver et al, 1996, p. 43). This concept is nicely captured by Duschl in an interview
where he is commenting on the activities of some 1st graders. The 1st grade class
are experimenting with sound. The children have some ideas about sound and they
test some of these ideas using rubber bands stretched over geoboard pegs. About this
episode, Duschl remarks:
When kids are given the same phenomena to observe, they see very different things. Their
personal interpretations of the ideas are very different. And when we listen to the children in
circle you can hear this and see it. This is an opportunity to get this consensus that we want, to
get some discussion because the scientific ideas just arent any ideas. They are ideas grounded
in evidence. (Smithsonian Institution, 1996a)
Duschl tells us that the scientific ideas just arent any ideas. They are tested ideas.
They are tested either in the physical world following from point 1.2, or they are tested
for theoretical consistency with other scientific explanations, which in turn were tested
in the physical world.
Moreover, scientific testing strives to be objective. In recent years this value in
science has been derided as objectivism . . . a universal, value-free process (Stanley
& Brickhouse, 1994, p. 389; also see Guba & Lincoln, 1989). Perhaps some people
58 Multiculturalism in Science Education
have overextended the concept of objectivity. In our view of the Standard Account,
objectivity refers to the goal that experimental outcomes are not to be prejudged nor
unreasonably constrained by prior belief, that data is collected fairly and accurately,
and that research methods are executed with fidelity.
Is it possible that TEK is tested knowledge? Borrowing a phrase form Sagan (1996,
p. 251), Kawagley et al., (1998, p. 137) maintain that Yupiaq traditional knowledge
reflects an understanding of the natural world based on a massive set of scientific
experiments continuing over generations. No one would doubt that the Yupiaq, along
with every other group of people that ever lived, have and continue to engage in trial
and error experimentation. People try different shampoos until they find the one they
like best but few would consider such experimentation scientific. It is not scientific
but it is an effective and valuable process. Similarly, the building up of traditional
knowledge through trial and error interactions with Nature has produced important
knowledge. But, it lacks the formal, controlled features of scientific experimentation.
2.1 Science presupposes the possibility of knowledge about Nature. Realists view
this as actual knowledgeHuman thinking holds the potential for recognizing and
understanding the actual order and causality inherent in the phenomena of Nature.
Idealists view this as instrumental knowledgeHuman thinking holds the potential for
constructing viable understanding about the instrumental order and causality in the
experience of natural phenomena. Roger Penrose and Stephen Hawking, respectively,
are exemplars of the two positions (Hawking & Penrose, 1996). Closely linked to the
possibility of knowledge are the presuppositions of order and causality.
2.2 Science presupposes that there is order in Nature. The fact that the orbit of
the earth can be represented as a mathematical equation or that tidal action can be
estimated within predictable limits of accuracy is evidence of order. Realists view this
order as actual orderThere is order in nature. Idealists view this as instrumental
orderHuman experience with Nature is amenable to ordered thinking about experi-
ence with Nature. Historically, presupposed order in Nature was profoundly important
to the development of science in Europe. Gernet (1993-94), following the pioneering
work of Needham (1969), notes the crippling effect the lack of this presupposition had
on the development of Chinese science.
2.3 Science presupposes causation in Nature (Collingwood, 1940). For example, rain is
causally linked with factors such as air temperature and humidity. Given enough water
vapor in the atmosphere and the right air temperature, it is going to rain. Realists view
this causation as actual causation. Cause and effect are inherent attributes of Nature.
Idealists view this as instrumental causationCausal thinking is amenable with the
human experience with Nature.
60 Multiculturalism in Science Education
3.0 Nevertheless, what ultimately qualifies as science is determined by con-
sensus within the scientific community. Thus, simply offering an idea which
fits all these parameters will still not be science until judged so by the community
of science. As we noted above, the problem is that there is no perfect account of science
that clearly represents all of science, past and present, and just as clearly eliminates all
endeavors that scientists do not consider to be science. In the final analysis a human
judgment must be made. However, the community of scientists is a community that
requires that scientific knowledge be made public and withstand public scrutiny and
testing. Thus, in the long run there can be no conspiracies to include or exclude any
domain of thought.
We see in this statement that some people are troubled about the dominant intellectual
position that modern Western science has come to hold in the public square. It is a po-
sition of dominance that tends to disenfranchise competitors. One way for competitors
to regain that franchise is to oust Western science. Another way to regain access to the
public squareand this is the approach many multiculturalists appear to be takingis
to get ones ideas included in the definition of the dominant player, in this case Western
science or the Standard Account.
If such a thing were to ever happen it would be a pyrrhic victory for indigenous
knowledge. The new additions to science (TEK or any other form of indigenous knowl-
edge) would soon face serious negative consequences. They would first lose their dis-
tinctiveness as a form of thought as they became absorbed by the dominant discourse
of science, that is the Standard Account. They would lose because the new additions
would inevitably be taken as mere tokens of cultural inclusiveness rather than as se-
rious participants in the discourse of science. This tokenism would be reinforced by the
inability of the new additions to compete where Western science is strongesttechnical
precision control, creative genius and explanatory power. And, the new additions would
lose by being co-opted into the cultural chauvinism scientism now holds in much of
modern life. Snively & Corsiglia (1998) rightfully question where is the wisdom in
science? As an incorporated part of science, that critique and challenge would be much
more difficult to make.
Natural
Sciences
Social Sciences
About these statements we can say, of course, few people question the productive
role that science has played in the development of modern life including medicine
and contributions to good health, nor the economic gains due to technical innovations
grounded in science (though the relationship between science and technology is not
nearly so straightforward as these statements from the science community suggest).
These claims by NAS and ICSU, however, are vastly overstated and singularly one-
sided. Good health, economic well being and national security depend on many things
only one of which is science. Moreover, as important as science surely is, it does not
have an uncontested claim to be the most important of these many factors. Curiously,
though the National Academy of Science and the ICSU appear eager to accept credit
for good technological innovations there is no parallel acceptance of technological dis-
asters. If the science community wants credit for developing high yield grains that
ease food shortages, how can the same community refuse credit for DDT? Something is
wrong with this portrayal of science (we might even say betrayal of science). Garrard
and Wegierski (1991, p. 611) suggest an explanation:
It can be argued that technology and scientific positivism constitute the dominant ideology of
Western civilization today. Technology has indeed become, as Heidegger noted, the metaphysics
of our age, a totalistic form of secular religion ultimately incompatible with the existence of
rival, non-technological assumptions, beliefs, or thought systems.
The problem for TEKas well as for so many other domains of knowledgeis not
the exclusivity of science as per the Standard Account but the transmogrification of
science as scientism in the public square.
Cobern & Loving 63
Epistemological Pluralism
When there is a gatekeeper and you persuade the gatekeeper to let you in, although
you may have influenced the gatekeeper you have also conceded his legitimacy as
gatekeeper. Similarly, getting TEK into the school curriculum as science does not
address the fundamental problem that led to the devaluing of TEK and other forms of
indigenous knowledge in the first place. The task for educators is to develop curricula
that value knowledge in its many forms and from its many sources. Therefore bringing
TEK into the science classroom is an excellent thing to do. It offers students a chance
to see how the practice of science can benefit from the insights of another domain of
knowledge. It helps students see that some of the insights from science can be arrived
at by other epistemological pathways. And, it helps students see what is unique about
sciencewhat science can do that other domains of knowledge cannot do.
We therefore reject positions of scientific and epistemological relativism. Not all
thoughts are equal. Not all ways of thinking are parallel. But life is a complicated
affair and the skillful navigation of life requires a diverse repertoire of thought and
reason. And what is essential for a suburbanite American to understand about Nature
will not be satisfactory for a Nisgaa fisherman living in a very different world. Thus,
what we value is the best thinking for a given situation and the wisdom to change
ones thinking when situations change. We advocate epistemological pluralism and the
ability to wisely discriminate amongst competing claims. This last point is important
because the issues of life typically cross epistemological categories. It is not always
obvious in the public when a problem does or does not call for a scientific solution.
Should the USA spend four billion dollars to build a Super Collider? The scientific
answer is probably yes since the Collider would help make important advances in
physics. But, America is not building the Super Collider because science was out bid by
the competing discourse of economics. In other situations we may find other domains of
knowledge acting in consort with science. Snively & Corsiglia (1998) give a number of
examples of ecologists and biologists profiting from the TEK of indigenous people. The
Native American Forestry Program at Northern Arizona University (1997) provides
another example where science and traditional knowledge work in consort.
In other situations, however, science rightly precipitates and influences cultural
change. Consider the following situation. At a recent NARST session a researcher
read the script of dialogue between an Australian Aborigine and a health care worker
indicating totally different perspectives regarding the value and use of high-protein
foods. The food is valued as nutrition, especially for children, in the West and valued
as gifts in adult relationships to the Aborigines. The result of the latter perspec-
tive is continued high infant mortality for children under two years of age despite
health care workers careful use of Socratic methods to dignify the alternate views
while educating the Aborigines. From the perspective of traditional Aboriginal life,
that of a hunter/gatherer culture, the elevated social and political status of the elders
makes their health critical to the success of the tribe. From that perspective they
were correct to reject the science-based position. However, cultures cannot maintain a
status quo in the face of environmental change and expect to survive. The fact that the
64 Multiculturalism in Science Education
researcher was involved with an education program for Aboriginal peoples indicates
that the researcher knew this fully well. Thus in this case the possible cultural changes
precipitated by science education regarding young childrens need for high protein food
are likely to be in the groups long term best interests.
The unfortunate fact of this last example is that the researcher represented the
Aboriginal rationale for distributing the best food to important adults as equally scien-
tifically valid as is a distribution based on confirmed nutritional value and nutritional
need at various stages of human physical development. But if all explanations are
mistakenly valorized as scientifically valid (and there is no attempt at understanding
the best scientific explanations), we are reduced to relativism of the worst kind. Privi-
leging what knowledge is of most worth in science class is not the same as denying the
value of other forms of knowledge (Loving, 1997). What is at issue here is the learning
of when scientific knowledge should be appropriated over other competing domains of
knowledge because it is the best knowledge available for the particular situation.
Conclusion
Our position in this article is that science can be defined with sufficient clarity so as to
maintain a coherent boundary for the practical purposes of school science curriculum
development. That boundary excludes most forms of indigenous knowledge, if not
all, just as it excludes art, history, economics, religion, and many other domains of
knowledge. Being exclusive, however, does not confer science with any privilege vis- a-
vis other domains. Science is properly privileged only within its own domain for that
is where its strength lies. When TEK and other forms of indigenous knowledge are
devalued it is not because of the exclusive nature of the Standard Account of science.
It is because someone is involved in the scientistic practice of extending scientific
privilege from its proper domain in science and technology into other domains. The
solution is to resist this scientistic practice by emphasizing throughout schooling the
concept of epistemological pluralism, bearing in mind that pluralism,
is not relativism. . . Pluralism is the civil engagement of our differences and disagreements
about what is most importantly true. Against the monism that denies the variety of truth,
against the relativism that denies the importance of truth, and against the nihilism that
denies the existence of truth, we intend to nurture a pluralism that revives and sustains the
conversation about what really matters, which is the truth. (First Things, 1995, p. 12)
Bearing also in mind that truth is never under the sole proprietorship of any single
domain of knowledgenot even science.
References
Adams, H.H.I.: 1990, African and African-American Contributions to Science and
Technology, Multnomah School District, Portland Public Schools, Portland, OR.
Adas, M.: 1989, Machines as the Measure of Man: Science, Technology, and Ideologies
of Western Dominance, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York.
Cobern & Loving 65
Addison-Wesley: 1993, Multiculturalism in Mathematics, Science, and Technology:
Readings and Activities, Addison-Wesley, New York.
Albanese, A., Neves, M. C. D. and Vicentini, M.: 1997, Models in Science and in
Education: A Clinical Review of Research on Students Ideas about the Earth
and its Place in the Universe, Science & Education 6(6), 573590.
Barba, R. H.: 1995, Science in the Multicultural Classroom: A Guide to Teaching and
Learning, Needham Heights, Allyn and Bacon, MA.
Barber, B.: 1963, Tension and Accommodations Between Science and Humanism,
American Behavioral Scientist (7), 38.
Basalla, G.: 1967, The Spread of Western Science, Science 156, 611622.
Behrens, C. A.: 1989, The Scientific Basis for Shipibo Soil Classification and Land Use:
Changes in Soil-plant Associations with Cash Cropping, American Anthropologist
91(1), 83100.
Berlin, B.: 1972, Speculations on the Growth of Ethnobotanical Nomenclature,
Language in Society I, 5186.
Bloor, D. and Barnes, B.: 1996, Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Boster, J. S. and Johnson, J. C.: 1989, Form and function: A comparison of expert and
novice judgments of similarity among fish, American Anthropologist 91(4), 866
888.
Burtt, E. A.: 1967, The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Physical Science,
Routledge and K. Paul, London, UK.
Chalmers, A. F.: 1982, What is This Thing Called Science?, University of Queensland
Press, Victoria, Australia.
Cobern, W. W.: 1991, World View Theory and Science Education Research, NARST
Monograph No. 3, National Association for Research in Science Teaching, Man-
hattan, KS.
Cobern, W. W.: 1995a, Belief and Knowledge: Unnecessary Conflict in the Science
Classroom, in F. Finley (ed.), Proceedings of the History and Philosophy of Science
and Science Teaching, HPSST, Minneapolis, MN.
Cobern, W. W.: 1995b, Science Education as an Exercise in Foreign Affairs, Science &
Education 4(3), 287302.
Collingwood, R. G.: 1940, An Essay on Metaphysics, Oxford University Press, London.
66 Multiculturalism in Science Education
Corsiglia, J. and Snively, G.: 1997, Knowing Home: Nisgaa Traditional Knowledge and
Wisdom Improve Environmental Decision Making, Alternatives Journal 32(3), 22
27.
DeLoria, V.: 1995, Red Earth, White Lies: Native Americans and the Myth of Scientific
Facts, Scribner, New York.
Desmond, A. and Moore, J.: 1991, Darwin - The Life of a Tormented Evolutionist,
Warner Books, New York.
Driver, R., Leach, J., Millar, R. and Scott, P.: 1996, Young Peoples Images of Science,
Open University Press, Buckingham, GB.
First Things: 1995, Putting first things first, First Things (51), 1113.
Fuller, S.: 1991, Social Epistemology, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, Indi-
anapolis.
Garrard, G. and Wegierski, M.: 1991, Oh Canada? an Essay on Canadian History,
Politics, and Culture, The World & I 6(1), 589613.
Geertz, C.: 1973, The Interpretation of Culture, Basic Books, New York.
Gernet, J.: 1993-1994, Space and Time: Science and Religion in the Encounter between
China and Europe., Chinese Science 11, 93102.
Peter Slezak
University of New South Wales, Austrialia. Email: p.slezak@unsw.edu.au
Introduction
The post-modernist affectation in the title, referring to the (ir-)relevance of construc-
tivism, is intended to reflect the ambiguities which prevail under this broad head-
ing and their varied implications. Despite these unclarities, the doctrines under this
heading enjoy an extraordinary popularity among educators. Paul Cobb (1994, p. 4)
has referred to the fervor that is currently associated with constructivism and Paul
Ernest has written:
In the past decade or two, the most important theoretical perspective to emerge in mathematics
education has been that of constructivism. . . . Ironically the attacks on radical constructivism
. . . which were perhaps intended to fatally expose its weakness, served as a platform from
which it was launched to widespread international acceptance and approbation. (Ernest 1995)
Thus, Gergen (cited in Steffe & Gale eds. 1995, p. xii) sees certain lapses in Cartesian
epistemology and the mind-body split, though the concievable bearing of this on
educational matters remains obscure. Likewise Steffe (1995, p. xiii) contrasts various
constructivist approaches with the Cartesian model, suggesting that they differed
from the Cartesian model in viewing knowledge in a nondualistic manner so as to
avoid to mind-body split of endogenic (mind-centred) and exogenic (reality-centred)
knowledge (1995, p. xiii). In passing, we might note that the mind-body split is a
different issue from that of the objective reality of a mind-independent world, though
Steffe seems to conflate these. Unfortunately, Steffe also neglects to explain how
Cartesian dualism might have the slightest bearing on science teaching, or anything
else for that matter. As a card carrying materialist, like most philosophers today, I
doubt that I am a better teacher for that reason. Some of my best friends are dualists,
and great teachers. Not least, Descartes own exemplary foundational contributions to
modern science and mathematics were hardly inhibited by his alleged lapses.
Such examples suggest that we might be highly suspicious of constructivist claims
of von Glasersfeld and Gergen, among others, suggesting that for 2,500 years since
the origin of science in ancient Greece, we have been somehow seriously misguided
in our conceptions of knowledge and science (see von Glasersfeld in Steffe & Gale
eds. p. 6). Thus, von Glasersfeld suggests that his conception of constructivism arose
out of a profound dissatisfaction with the theories of knowledge in the tradition of
Western philosophy and he has suggested that adopting his constructivism could
bring about some rather profound changes in the general practice of education (1989,
p. 135). His radical recommendation is: Give up the requirement that knowledge
represents an independent world (in Steffe & Gale eds. pp. 6-7). This is, of course,
Berkeleys notorious idealism and undoubtedly a radical proposal. However, despite
Slezak 71
these extravagant claims, we will see that the educational recommendations which
von Glasersfeld actually offers are rather modest.
Commonsense Realism
The prominent role of such metaphysical problems in the educational literature is
perplexing in a way which goes beyond the intrinsic puzzles of the issues themselves.
Undoubtedly, the issue of realism remains a central one in philosophy, though even here
an important warning has been recently voiced by Hilary Putnam (1994) in his Dewey
Lectures. Putnam notes that The besetting sin of philosophers seems to be throwing
the baby out with the bathwater as each new generation or fashion ignores the insights
of earlier periods. In particular, concerning the disputes over realism, Putnam says
that it is important to find a way to do justice to our sense that knowledge claims are
responsible to reality without recoiling into metaphysical fantasy (1994, p. 446). The
responsibility proposed by Putnam is a familiar, commonsense, naive realism.
It is surprising enough that philosophers need to be reminded not to lose sight of
commonsense realism. That educationalists need the same advice is somewhat harder
to explain. Like Berkeley, Kant is explicitly cited by von Glasersfeld as one of the
sources for his constructivism, though it is instructive to ponder how one might derive
educational implications from the Critique of Pure Reason. Kants transcendental
idealism as an attempt to find an alternative to a pure phenomenalism is an unlikely
basis for pedagogical theory or instructional interventions.
The problem is that of determining how knowledge comes to terms with the real
world, and therefore what relationships obtain between subject and object (ibid, p. 6).
These are ways of talking which von Glasersfeld has emphatically repudiated, and
so it is evident that his version of constructivism is quite different from Piagets.
Any solution to our cognitive isolation from reality is unlikely to help solve the
problem of objective knowledge since the arguments for realism are not the same as
arguments for this latter problem. That is, the epistemological problem of objective
knowledge is left untouched by recoiling into the metaphysical fantasy of Berkeleyan
idealism. Rather, the current philosophical answer to the epistemological problem is
the acknowledgement that there is no absolutely certain foundation. Instead, philoso-
phers settle for a fallibilistic naturalism captured in Quines epigraph from Neurath:
Wie Schiffer sind wir, die ihr Schiff auf offener See umbauen mussen, ohne es jemals in einem
Dock zerlegen und aus bestend Bestandteilen neu errichten zu konnen. (Otto Neurath, quoted
as epigraph in Quine 1960)
That is, we are like the sailor who must repair his ship while sailing in it. The
entire ship may be rebuilt, but only one plank at a time. von Glasersfelds concerns
about metaphysics are addressed in Quines following remarks:
Ontological questions, under this view, are on a par with questions of natural science. (Quine
1961a, p. 45)
74 Constructivism and Science Education
. . . our statements about the external world face the tribunal of sense experience not individu-
ally but only as a corporate body. (Quine 1961a, p. 41)
Hence it is meaningless, I suggest, to inquire into the absolute correctness of a conceptual
scheme as a mirror of reality. Our standard for appraising basic changes of conceptual scheme
must be, not a realistic standard of correspondence to reality, but a pragmatic standard. (Quine
1961b, p. 79)
Besides this disastrous idea, the conflation of the metaphysical problem of realism
with epistemology is encouraged by much post-modern post-positivist post-epistemological
writing. Thus, for example, in their recent book Barnes, Bloor and Henry (1995) deny
their own idealism, but accuse all their sociogical constructivist colleagues of this
charge (see Slezak 1997, 2000). Nevertheless, despite being explicitly repudiated by
Bloor, as by von Glasersfeld, such disavowals are not quite enough to exculpate them
since there are grounds for seeing a confusion in their writings between idealism and
fallibilism. They reject the external world when they evidently wish to reject absolute,
infallible truth claims.
Whatever may be the educational interest in these matters, von Glasersfeld is at
least in good philosophical company. His worry about the gap between thought and
reality mediated by ideas is the familiar one posed by Locke and Malebranche and,
more recently, by John McDowell (1994) in his significantly titled work Mind and
World. However, in the present context, whatever the philosophical merits of von
Glasersfelds concerns, the question is how these bear on any issue of conceivable
educational interest.
Epistemology or Pedagogy?
Apropos this very issue, at a meeting von Glasersfeld was explicitly asked whether
constructivism is to be understood as an epistemology or pedagogy. His answer is
most revealing for what it fails to say. von Glasersfeld responded by restating the
formula of Berkeley: . . . there is no way of checking knowledge against what it was
supposed to represent. One can compare knowledge only with other knowledge (1993,
p. 24). The questioner is unlikely to have found this answer satisfying. Other questions
sought to clarify the differences between constructivism and idealism. Again, von
Glasersfelds answer is rather unhelpful, simply re-iterating that we can only know
what our minds construct and that the real world remains unknowable and that
I could be one of Leibniz monads (1993, p. 28). Teachers might wonder how this
could help them in the classroom. When pressed on this question concerning the
implications of contructivism for a theory of instruction, von Glasersfeld suggests that
there are many. These include the following: It is . . . crucial for the teacher to get some
idea of where they [the students] are, that is, what concepts they seem to have and
how they relate them (1993, p. 33). This inference seems a modest recommendation
which is far from the rather profound changes promised. Similar platitudes are
typical:
76 Constructivism and Science Education
Asking students how they arrived at their given answer is a good way of discovering something
about their thinking. (1993, p. 33)
Whatever a student says in answer to a question (or problem) is what makes sense to the
student at that moment. It has to be taken seriously as such, regardless of how odd or wrong
it might seem to the teacher. To be told that it is wrong is most discouraging and inhibiting for
the student. (1993, p. 33)
If you want to foster students motivation to delve further into questions that, at first, are of no
particular interest (from the students point of view), you will have to create situations where
the students have an opportunity to experience the pleasure inherent in solving a problem.
(1993, p. 33)
We may assume that such profundities are what K. Tobin (1993) has in mind when
he refers to constructivism as A paradigm for the practice of science education. Tobin
has his own deeply insightful contributions to offer:
A most significant role of the teacher, from a constructivist perspective, is to evaluate stu-
dent learning. In a study of exemplary teachers, Tobin and Fraser found that these teachers
routinely monitored students in three distinctive ways: they scanned the class for signs of
imminent off task behavior, closely examined the nature of the engagement of students, and
investigated the extent to which students understood what they were learning. If teachers
are to mediate the learning process, it is imperative that they develop ways of assessing what
students know and how they can represent what they know. (Tobin & Tippins 1993, p. 12;
emphasis added)
In brief, good teachers make sure students pay attention and understand the lesson!
Inevitably one wonders how differently a teacher might do things if not operating from
a constructivist perspective.
Consider the first sentence of Driver et al. . . . learning science involves being
initiated into scientific ways of knowing. The ring of plausibility, if not profundity,
in this assertion derives from its being pure tautology. Learning science presumably
means, or may be paraphrased as, being initiated into scientific ways of knowing.
Likewise their remark that The role of the science educator is to mediate scientific
knowledge for learners is like saying that the role of the butcher is to mediate animal
products for consumers or the role of the bus driver is to mediate automotive vehicular
transportation for commuters. Their assertion is merely a circumlocution for saying
that the role of teachers is to teach. It is perhaps tedious to pursue this analysis
in exhaustive detail, but the illustrations serve to indicate a widespread tendency to
recast truisms in pretentious polysyllabic jargon to create a superficial illusion of deep
theory. Tobin and Tippin (1993) provide another typical illustration:
Constructivism suggests that learning is a social process of making sense of experience in
terms of what is already known. In that process learners create perturbations that arise from
attempts to give meaning to particular experiences through the imaginative use of existing
knowledge. The resolution of these perturbations leads to an equilibrium state whereby new
knowledge has been constructed to cohere with a particular experience and prior knowledge.
(Tobin & Tippins 1993, p. 10)
References
Barnes, B. Bloor D. Henry, J.: 1996, Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis, The
University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Boden, M.: 1979, Piaget, Fontana, London.
Cobb, P.: 1994a, Constructivism in Mathematics and Science Education, Educational
Researcher 23(7).
Cobb, P.: 1994b, Where Is the Mind? Constructivist and Sociocultural Perspectives on
Mathematical Development, Educational Researcher 23(7), 1320.
Driver, R. Asoko, H. Leach, J. Mortimer, E. and Scott, P.: 1994, Constructing Scientific
Knowledge in the Classroom, Educational Researcher 23(7), 512.
Ernest, P.: 1995, Radical Constructivism: A Way of Knowing and Learning, The Falmer
Press, London. Preface by Series Editor, E. von Glasersfeld.
McDowell, J.: 1994, Mind and World, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Mills, C.: 1959, The Sociological Imagination, Oxford University Press, New York.
Orwell, G.: 1946, Politics and the English Language, The Penguin, 1946, Essays of
George Orwell, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1984.
Phillips, D.: 1995, The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly: The Many Faces of Construc-
tivism, Educational Researcher 24(7), 512.
Phillips, D.: 1997, How, Why, What, When, and Where: Perspectives on Constructivism
in Psychology and Education, Issues in Education 3(2), 151194.
Piaget, J.: 1955, The Construction of Reality in the Child, Routledge and Kegan Paul,
London.
Piaget, J.: 1971, Biology and Knowledge, Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh.
Piaget, J.: 1972, Psychology and Epistemology: Towards a Theory of Knowledge,
Penguin, Harmondsworth.
Piaget, J.: 1975, Insights and Illusions of Philosophy, Meridian Books, New York.
Putnam, H.: 1994, Sense, Nonsense, and the Senses: An Inquiry Into the Powers of the
Human Mind, The Journal of Philosophy XCI(9), 445517. The Dewey Lectures
at Columbia University 1994.
Quine, W.: 1960, Word and Object, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Slezak 81
Quine, W.: 1961a, Two Dogmas of Empiricism, From a Logical Point of View, Harper,
New York.
Quine, W.: 1961b, Identity, Ostension, and Hypostasis, From a Logical Point of View,
Harper, New York.
Rorty, R.: 1979, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press,
Princeton.
Slezak, P.: 1997, Review of Barnes, Bloor & Henry: Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological
Analysis, Metascience 11, 4452.
Slezak, P.: 1999, Situated Cognition: Empirical Issue, Paradigm Shift or Conceptual
Confusion?, in J. Wiles and T. Dartnall (eds), Perspectives on Cognitive Science,
Ablex Publishing Corporation, Stamford.
Slezak, P.: 2000, Radical Social Constructivism, in D. Philips (ed.), National Society for
the Study of Education (NSSE) Yearkbook, Forthcoming.
Steffe, L.: 1995, Title, Publisher.
Steffe, L. and Gale, J. (eds): 1995, Constructivism in Education, Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, Inc., New Jersey.
Tobin, K. (ed.): 1993, The Practice of Constructivism in Science Education, AAA Press,
Washington D.C.
Tobin, K. and Tippins, D.: 1993, Constructivism as a Referent for Teaching and
Learning, in K. Tobin (ed.), The Practice of Constructivism in Science Education,
AAA Press, Washington D.C., pp. 321.
van Fraassen, B.: 1980, The Scientific Image, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Peter Slezak
University of New South Wales, Australia. Email: p.slezak@unsw.edu.au
The dispute concerning Social Constructivism has emerged from being an isolated
and esoteric epistemological debate among relatively few academic scholars to being
a notorious public scandal. Challenges to traditional conceptions of science which
severely polarised philosophers, historians and sociologists have erupted into heated
public disputesthe so-called Science Wars. The issues at stake concern the most
fundamental questions about the nature of science, and these controversies have be-
come prominent in educational literature where a variety of constructivist doctrines
have become entangled (see Phillips 1997b and Matthews 1998).
If social constructivist doctrines are correct, the implications for science education
are revolutionary. On these views, knowledge is merely a consensus upon arbitrary
convention; and education involves not learning as a cognitive process of reason and
understanding, but merely conformity to power and political interests. There could be
no more fundamental challenge to education than the one posed by social construc-
tivism, since it purports to overturn the traditional conception of knowledge. The self-
advertising grandiosely proclaims: The foundations of modern thought are at stake
here (Pickering 1992).
A major battle in these Science Wars has been fought over the book Higher Supersti-
tion by Paul Gross and Norman Levitt (1994), which brought the polemics surrounding
social constructivism to wide popular attention. Adding piquancy and greater public
attention to social constructivism was the fallout from the Sokal Hoax . Unwittingly,
the editors of the journal Social Text published a spoof article written in post-modernist
style by the mathematical physicist Alan Sokal without realizing that it was deliberate
nonsense (Sokal and Bricmont 1997).
In their different ways, the Sokal article and the Gross and Levitt book exposed
what they claim to be the bankrupt, fraudulent and pernicious nature of social con-
structivism in a broad variety of post-modern guises. The colourful epithets and purple
prose conveyed the enormity of what Gross and Levitt call the post-modernist game of
intellectual subversion (1994, p. 85) and philosophical styrofoam (1994, p. 98).
Even in the more sober academic literature there had been outrage about social
constructivism going well beyond normal intellectual disagreement. The disputes in
the technical journals have been characterised by ad hominem assaults of an unusual
ferocity. For example, Mario Bunge (1991) described most of the work in the field as
a grotesque cartoon of scientific research. In a similar vein, the philosopher David
Stove (1991) called these doctrines a form of lunacy which is so absurd, that it eludes
the force of all argument (1991, p. 31), a philosophical folly and a stupid and dis-
creditable business whose authors are beneath philosophical notice and unlikely to
benefit from it. In his scathing remarks, Stove describes such ideas as an illustration
84 Social Constructivism
of the fatal affliction and corruption of thought in which people say bizarre things
which even they must know to be false. Larry Laudan (1990b, p. x) who has been among
the first philosophers to make systematic critical analyses of social constructivism, has
characterized this rampant relativism as the most prominent and pernicious man-
ifestation of anti-intellectualism in our time. Laudans charge of anti-intellectualism
points to the source of concern for educators.
On this view, not only is the very distinctiveness of science merely some kind of pro-
paganda victory, a further assumption to be rejected is the curiously persistent view
that the objects of the natural world are real, objective and enjoy an independent pre-
existence (Woolgar 1988, p. 26). In place of the traditional misconceptions about
science and the independent pre-existence of the world, social constructivism proposed
an amalgam of idealism and relativism according to which scientific theories are merely
fictions, the product of social forces, interests and other contingent, historical aspects
of the milieu in which they arise. That is, scientific theories are not explanatory or
descriptive of the world, but are rhetorical accomplishments by some community
of discourse and constituted entirely by social consensus. Even scientific discovery
is a matter of interpretative practice, and genius has no bearing on the pattern of
discovery in science (Brannigan 1981. See the discussion in Slezak 1989.)
These are not merely radical or even revolutionary claims. They can only be de-
scribed as extravagant doctrines which might be expected to require compelling ar-
guments. In the absence of any arguments, sociologists had a ready explanation for
the predictable incredulity of philosophers. Foreshadowing the provocation of later
works, Bloors preface to the first edition of his book already hints darkly that the
86 Social Constructivism
inevitable resistance by philosophers to his doctrines will be due, not to their unargued
absurdity, but to uncomfortable secrets that they would wish to hide. Bloor asserts
that his approach to science from a sociological point of view encounters resistance
because some nerve has been touched. He announces his bold intention to despoil
academic boundaries which contrive to keep some things well hidden (Bloor 1976,
p. ix). Bloor was right about some nerve having been touched, though he misdiagnosed
the nature of the irritation. He devotes an entire chapter of his landmark book to a
kind of psychoanalysis of his opponents by speculating about the sources of resistance
to the Strong Programme which he attributes to hidden, indeed primitive, motives
involving the fear of sociologys desacralizing of science and its mysteries. One might
suggest alternative reasons for the resistance to his sociological doctrines, but Bloor
sees only repressed impulses concerning the sacred and the profane leading to a
superstitious desire to avoid treating knowledge naturalistically (Bloor 1976, p. 73).
Bloor imagines that the threatening nature of any investigation into science itself
has been the cause of a positive disinclination to examine the nature of knowledge
in a candid and scientific way (1976, p. 42). However, this disinclination to examine
knowledge and the need to keep it mystified through fear of desecration is difficult to
reconcile with the fact that every philosopher since Plato has been centrally concerned
with the problem of knowledge and its justification. The inordinate space devoted to
such fatuous speculations signifies the pre-eminent place they occupy in the social con-
structivist enterprise as a substitute for serious, or indeed any, philosophical analysis.
Although it had appeared in different guises before in Hegel, Marx, and Durkheim, the
radical idea at the heart of the Strong Programme was to go beyond those sociological
studies which stopped short of considering the actual substantive content, the ideas, of
Slezak 87
scientific theories as an appropriate domain for sociological investigation. Previously,
sociological studies paid attention only to such things as institutional politics, citation
patterns and other peripheral social phenomena surrounding the production of science,
but had not ventured to explain the cognitive contents of theories in sociological terms.
Since this crucial point has been obscured, its importance for appreciating subsequent
developments cannot be overstated. The opening sentence of Bloors book asks Can
the sociology of knowledge investigate and explain the very content and nature of
scientific knowledge? (Bloor 1976, p. 1)that is, knowledge as such, as distinct from
the circumstances of production.
The alleged failure of previous sociological studies to touch on the contents of scien-
tific belief was portrayed by Bloor as a loss of nerve and a failure to be consistent (1976,
p. 8). Karl Mannheim, for example, is characterised as failing to extend his approach
from knowledge of society to the knowledge of nature. The relativist challenge derives
from this thorough-going application of the sociological principle which seeks to explain
the hitherto exempted knowledge claims. The ambitions of Bloors program are explicit,
for he complains that previous sociologists, in a betrayal of their disciplinary stand-
point have failed to expand and generalise their claims to all knowledge: . . . the
sociology of knowledge might well have pressed more strongly into the area currently
occupied by philosophers, who have been allowed to take upon themselves the task of
defining the nature of knowledge (Bloor 1976, p. 1).
As indicated, students who might wish to use the latest book of Barnes, Bloor and
Henry as a text to study for the foregoing test would fail. These questions cannot be
answered by a conscientious study of the book, though any teacher would recognise
them as elementary ones basic to understanding the field. Cryptic references to issues
such as the rationalist philosophies against which the entire sociological enterprise
was directed are left entirely unexplained and so the innocent reader will not be able
to understand or assess the current claims. These failings might indicate only that
the book is an inadequate text, which would not be unusual. However, the lapses and
omissions appear to disguise a shift from vital doctrines which have become untenable.
Idealism
The book begins encouragingly, if somewhat mystifyingly for the newcomer, by ac-
knowledging the existence of reality. This admission will undoubtedly be comfort-
ing to those harbouring doubts about the matter, but it arises at all only through
certain naive confusions. For their part, Barnes, Bloor and Henry are concerned to
distance themselves from thosewe are to assume othersociologists who they say
Occasionally . . . may have given this impression of denying the existence of tables
and chairs. Nevertheless, they admit that most other sociology of knowledge is, in fact,
idealist. In repudiating this stance these authors emphasize their own contrasting
naturalistic view, but on such good authority, then, idealism must be regarded as a
central philosophical issue for the understanding of social constructivism.
Notwithstanding these authors disclaimers, warrant for the charge of idealism
against them too arises partly from their own misconceptions regarding the rationalist
theories they oppose and partly from the social constructivism to which they remain
firmly committedactually an amalgam of idealism and relativism. An unavoidable
temptation towards idealism arises from the sociologists desire to deny that science
describes an independent world. Consequently, the opposing rationalist philosophy
of science has been seen as committed to a metaphysical realism involving access to
absolute truth about a world behind appearances. While science attempts to discover
the nature of an independently existing reality, this concern is not a metaphysical
thesis about some Kantian things-in-themselves. It is simply the truism that we
take our best theories literally to be talking about something. The reaction to the
ordinary practice of science as some kind of philosophical error requiring sociological
remedy is simply a mistake, since the virtues and status of science as an enterprise
are independent of such metaphysical questions. Realists and idealists alike can enjoy
the fruits of scientific knowledge. Specifically, whether or not scientific theories are
Slezak 91
socially constructed is an issue to be determined by arguments entirely independent of
idealism. Nevertheless, Barnes et al. offer their own naturalist stance as the contrast
with idealism, but their naturalism is simply a demand for empirical explanation in
terms of causes. However, Berkeley, like all other idealists, was an empiricist in good
standing in this sense, and one can be an idealist at the same time as being committed
to empirical, naturalistic science. Idealism is a metaphysical doctrine concerning the
overall status of our scientific theories as such, and not a specific approach to expla-
nation within the overall enterprise like naturalism. The dispute concerning idealism
is entirely indifferent to any debate about the practices of empirical inquiry as such
and, therefore, asserting credentials as naturalistic does not even amount to a plea
of innocent to the charge of idealismmuch less grounds for acquittal.
Revealing comments support the charge of idealism despite their disavowals. Barnes
et al. (1996, p. 48) point out that it is not the existence of nature which accounts
for certain behaviours and that attention to nature will not adjudicate the merits
of our theories and classifications. Of course, if appeal to nature, meaning empirical
evidence, cannot adjudicate our theories, it is not clear what would do so. We see here
the social constructivist dogma that scientific theories are somehow unconstrained by
the way things are in the world. However, Barnes et al. are confusing the supposed
indirectness of our knowledge of the world, its inaccessibility beyond the veil of ideas,
with the bearing of empirical evidence on our scientific theories. Stressing the former
kind of inaccessibility does not establish the latter kind. This is precisely to confuse
idealism with relativism.
The declaration of Barnes et al. that they are not idealists, then, is paradoxical
since it poses the following dilemma: Which reality is the one the sociologists profess
to believe in? Do they believe in an inaccessible Kantian ding an sich after all? Or
do they believe in the rationalists world as conveyed by our true (i.e. best) theories?
In wishing to deny the former, they end up denying the latter and, thereby, become
idealists as well as relativists. In brief, their needless entanglement in such notorious
problems is symptomatic of sociologists absurd pretensions to overthrow the subject
that used to be called philosophy (Bloor 1983).
Relativism
Despite characterising their book as focussed on basic foundations, Barnes et al.
explain that it gives little prominence to such issues as relativism. Indeed, this
prefatory mention of relativism is the only one in the book. However, even more
than idealism, relativism has been the central, distinctive theoretical doctrine of social
constructivism and the source of most dispute. Neglecting to discuss it is like a text on
evolution professing to concentrate on basic foundations and choosing to give little
prominence to natural selection. The authors recent reticence about their own central
doctrines is a telling feature of their work (Barnes and Bloor 1982).
Relativism is the claim that knowledge has no warrant beyond belief acceptance
itself. It is often a non-sequitur from the recognition that there is no absolute certainty.
However, given that there can be no absolutely secure knowledge, the alternative to
relativism is fallibilism: the idea that reliable knowledge is possible through revision
92 Social Constructivism
and improvement. Relativism is at the heart of social constructivism because the
supposed absence of constraints of independent reality is assumed to leave no other
grounds for adjudicating claims. Specifically, the freedom from a constraining reality is
taken to warrant appeal to a sociological account of theory acceptance. Relativism,
then, is the spurious assumption that there can be nothing more to say about the
goodness of our theories if one cant meaningfully compare them to an independent,
inaccessible reality. However, the question of realism has been the subject of a vast
philosophical literature, and both sides of this dispute accept the rational force of
evidence and the usual considerations of explanatory virtue such as comprehensive-
ness, coherence and simplicity as grounds for rational theory choice. Thus, Cardinal
Bellarmines instrumentalism did not involve a challenge to the intellectual merits
of Galileos Copernicanism as such. More recently, van Fraassens (1980) celebrated
constructive empiricism is concerned to save the phenomena without postulating
a hidden underlying reality, but this does not entail rejection of the usual rational
considerations governing theory choice. Social constructivists mistakenly conclude that
the inaccessibility of things in themselves behind the veil of our theories (whatever
this might mean) precludes saying anything sensible about their cognitive virtues.
However, rationalist talk of observation, confirmation, evidence and truth etc., is
within the sociologists own preferred framework on our side of the veil, as it were, ac-
cording to which, as Bloor says, all we have and all we need are the theories themselves.
Indeed, Bloors view could be a version of Quines (1960) well-known metaphor of the
fabric or web of our knowledge, also articulated in his famous epigram from Neurath
concerning the sailor quoted on page ??. That is, we are inescapably dependent on our
theories even as we seek to revise them. But, in terms of the metaphor, what counts as
a repair of our boat is not a matter of arbitrary convention; social constructivism wants
to scuttle it.
Consensus as Conventional
Social constructivism rests on this idea that alternative theory choices are not only
available, but equally good. Of course, this is the claim for the conventional character
of science and is the locus of sociological relativism. Barnes et al. assert, Conventions
could always be otherwise . . . (Barnes, Bloor & Henry 1996, p. 154), presumably
entailing that knowledge might have been negotiated differently had the local interpre-
tive milieu been different and, thereby, inviting the facetious question about Newtons
inverse cube law. Indeed, undaunted by its absurdity, Barnes et al. embrace precisely
such a paradoxical idea even in the case of arithmetical laws (Barnes, Bloor & Henry
1996, p. 184). However, on their own account, given the underdetermination of theory
by evidence, the sociologists must be committed to the possibility of a consensus settling
on a vast range of possible laws via the contingent, collective accomplishment of fact
production by local cultural traditions. Unconvincingly, Barnes et al. suggest that
the consensus on 2 + 2 = 4 is due merely to pragmatic reasons connected with the
organization of collective action and the fact that it is probably easier to organize
than a different convention such as 2 + 2 = 5. The fact that it might also be easier to
believe is somehow not considered relevant.
Impartiality
Merton, like Mannheim, argued that theories judged to be correct and founded on
rational considerations are not in need of sociological explanation in the way that false
and irrational theories are. In this sense, traditional conceptions relegated sociology
to the dross of science, to its residue of false and irrational beliefs. Bloors revival of
94 Social Constructivism
the Durkheimian view was explicitly rescuing sociology from this ignominious role by
asserting the appropriateness of sociological explanations for all of science regardless
of evaluative judgements such as truth and falsity, rationality and irrationality, success
or failure. Our own cosmology and science in general, like those of the Zuni, were to be
shown as reflections of the social milieu.
Bloors complaint is directed at asymmetrical approaches such as Imre Lakatoss
rational reconstruction of episodes in the history of science which sought to explain
correct scientific theories as products of reasoned thought and, therefore, not requiring
resort to sociological explanations. Bloor regards this approach as having the effect of
rendering science safe from the indignity of empirical explanation (Bloor 1976, p. 7),
but for Lakatos only sociology was to be excluded from accounts of successful science
since good reasons are a species of explanation themselves. Analogously, veridical
perception does not need explanation in the same way as misperception or illusion. We
do not ordinarily seek explanatory causes in the case of normal veridical perception,
not because we assume that there is no scientific explanation, but because we assume
it to be of a certain general sort. Thus, we dont explain normal vision, but seek the
cause of failure such as the influence of alcohol, disease and so on. In the same way,
we do not seek to explain why the train stays on the tracks but only why it fails to
do so. Again, this asymmetry does not mean that we believe there is no cause or no
explanation for the train staying on the tracks. However, this is the absurd view which
Bloor imputes to rationalist philosophers such as Lakatos. Notice that Bloor takes
Lakatos to hold that a rational reconstruction of beliefs implies that they are thereby
shown to lack empirical explanation altogether (Bloor 1976, p. 7). In his Knowledge
and Social Imagery (1976), Bloor characterized the autonomy view he is opposing:
One important set of objections to the sociology of knowledge derives from the conviction that
some beliefs do not stand in need of any explanation, or do not stand in need of a causal
explanation. This feeling is particularly strong when the beliefs in question are taken to be
true, rational, scientific or objective. (Bloor 1976, p. 5)
Elsewhere Bloor characterizes the opposing view as the claim that nothing makes
people do things that are correct but something does make, or cause, them to go wrong
and that in the case of true beliefs causes do not need to be invoked (1976, p. 6). Bloor
intends to make an absolute distinction between the teleological view which inclines
its proponents to reject causality (1976, p. 10) on the one hand, and the causal
viewthat is, the sociological approach of the Strong Programme. On Bloors own
account, the viability of the Strong Programme rests on the tenability of this dichotomy
and, in particular, the falsity of the teleological model. There could be no more crucial
issue for the constructivist programme.
L. Laudan (1981) has characterized Bloors acausal attribution to philosophers as
an absurd view which cannot plausibly be attributed to any philosopher at all. In
particular, the approach of Lakatos does not deny the existence of causes in cases of
rationally held beliefs, but only assumes that reasons are themselves a species of cause
(see Phillips 1997a). However, in a remarkable passage, Bloor (1981) responded to
Laudan by attempting to deny these patent and quite explicit earlier intentions. Bloors
Slezak 95
discomfort was understandable, since the entire edifice of the Strong Programme rests
on this claimed opposition. Indeed in the second edition of his book, in the crucial
section on the Autonomy of Knowledge dealing with the problem of causation, we
discover certain judicious changes to the original text whose rationale is clearly to
avoid the criticisms made by Laudan (see Slezak 1994). It must be noted that these
alterations to the original text are somewhat difficult to reconcile with Bloors prefato-
rial assertion that attacks by critics have not convinced me of the need to give ground
on any matter of substance and, therefore, he says I have resisted the temptation to
alter the original presentation of the case for the sociology of knowledge apart from
minor spelling and stylistic changes (Bloor 1991).
Bloors predicament, if not his tactic, is understandable since his statement of the
conditions under which the programme retains its plausibility left no room for compro-
mise and no way out. Bloor had declared forthrightly:
There is no doubt that if the teleological model is true then the Strong Programme is false.
The teleological and causal models, then, represent programmatic alternatives which quite
exclude one another. (Bloor 1976, p. 9)
Balance of Forces
Though implications of social constructivism are not drawn out by the authors, they are
close to the surface and not difficult to discern. Thus, once Latour and Woolgar reject
the intrinsic existence of accurate and fictitious accounts per se, the only remaining
criterion for judgement is judgement itself. . . . the degree of accuracy (or fiction) of
an account depends on what is subsequently made of the story, not on the story itself
(1986, p. 284). There are no grounds for judging the merits of any claim besides the
modalizing and demodalising of statements, a purely political question of persuasion,
propaganda and power. Thus they suggest that the very idea of plausibility of any
work, including their own, is not an intellectual or cognitive question, but simply a
matter of political redefinition of the field and other such transformations involving
shift in the balance of forces. In particular, the current implausibility of their own
theory is only due to its relative political disadvantages rather than the lack of any
intellectual merits (1986, p. 285). One could hardly find a more open endorsement of
the doctrine that Might is right.
References
Ashmore, M.: 1993, The Theatre of the Blind: Starring a Promethean Prankster, a
Phoney Phenomenon, a Prism, a Pocket and a Piece of Wood, Social Studies of
Science 23, 67106.
Barnes, B.: 1974a, Interests and the Growth of Knowledge, Routledge & Kegan Paul,
London.
Barnes, B.: 1974b, Scientific Knowledge and Sociological Theory, Routledge & Kegan
Paul, London.
Barnes, B.: 1981, On the Hows and Whys of Cultural Change, Social Studies of Science
11, 48198.
Barnes, B. and Bloor, D.: 1982, Relativism, Rationalism and the Sociology of Knowl-
edge, in M. Hollis and S. Lukes (eds), Rationality and Relativism, Basil Blackwell,
Oxford, pp. 2147.
Barnes, B., Bloor, D. and Henry, J.: 1996, Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis,
The University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Bloor, D.: 1976, Knowledge and Social Imagery, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Bloor, D.: 1981, The Strengths of the Strong Programme, Philosophy of the Social
Sciences, Vol. 11, pp. 199213. Reprinted in J. R. Brown (ed.) Scientific Rationality:
The Sociological Turn, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 1984, p. 85.
Bloor, D.: 1983, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge, Columbia University
Press, New York.
Bloor, D.: 1991, Knowledge and Social Imagery, 2nd edn, The University of Chicago
Press, Chicago.
Boden, M.: 1979, Piaget, Fontana, London.
Boorse, C.: 1975, The Origins of the Indeterminacy Thesis, Journal of Philosophy
72, 369887.
106 Social Constructivism
Brannigan, A.: 1981, The Social Basis of Scientific Discoveries, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Bunge, M.: 1991, A Critical Examination of the New Sociology of Science, Philosophy
of the Social Sciences 21(4), 52460.
Chomsky, N.: 1969, American Power and the New Mandarins, Penguin, Har-
mondsworth.
Collins, H.: 1990, Artificial Experts: Social Knowledge and Intelligent Machines, MIT
Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Collins, H. and Pinch, T.: 1992, The Golem: What Everyone Should Know About Science,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Durkheim, E. and Mauss, M.: 1903, Primitive Classification. Translated and edited
with introduction by R. Needham, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1963.
Forman, P.: 1971, Weimar Culture, Causality and Quantum Theory 1918-1927, in
R. McCormmach (ed.), Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences, University of
Philadelphia Press, Philadelphia, pp. 1115.
Frankfurt, H.: 1988, On Bullshit, The Importance of What We Care About: Philosophi-
cal Essays, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Gardner, H. E.: 1987, The Minds New science: A History of the Cognitive Revolution,
Basic Books, New York.
Giere, R. (ed.): 1992, Cognitive Models of Science: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy
of Science, Vol. XV, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
Gieryn, T.: 1982, Relativist/Constructivist Programmes in the Sociology of Science:
Redundance and Retreat, Social Studies of Science 12, 279297.
Gorman, M.: 1992, Simulating Science: Heuristics, Mental Models and Technoscientific
Thinking, Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Gough, N.: 1993, Laboratories in Schools: Material Places, Mythic Spaces, The
Australian Science Teachers Journal 39, 2933.
Gross, P. and Levitt, N.: 1994, Higher Superstition: The Academic Left and its Quarrels
with Science, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore.
Kosslyn, S.: 1980, Image and Mind, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Kosslyn, S.: 1994, Image and Brain: The Resolution of the Imagery Debate, MIT Press,
Cambridge, Mass.
Langley, P. Simon, H.A. Bradshaw, G.L. and Zytkow, J.M.: 1987, Scientific Discovery:
Computational Explorations of the Creative Process, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Slezak 107
Latour, B.: 1983, Give Me a Laboratory and I Will Raise the World, in K. Knorr-
Cetina and M. Mulkay (eds), Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social Study of
Science, Sage, New York.
Latour, B. and Woolgar, S.: 1979, Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific
Facts, Vol. 11, Sage, London, pp. 173198. Reprinted in J.R. Brown (ed.), Scientific
Rationality: The Sociological Turn, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1984.
Laudan, L.: 1990a, Demystifying Underdetermination, in C. W. Savage (ed.), Scientific
Theories: Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. XIV, University of
Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
Laudan, L.: 1990b, Science and Relativism, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Lehman, D.: 1991, Signs of the Times: Deconstruction and the Fall of Paul de Man,
Simon & Schuster, New York.
Matthews, M. R. (ed.): 1998, Constructivism in Science Education: A Philosophical
Examination, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht.
Merton, R.: 1942, Science and Technology in a Democratic Order, Journal of Legal and
Political Sociology 1. Reprinted as Science and Democratic Social Structure, in his
Social Theory and Social Structure, Free Press, New York, 1957.
Merton, R.: 1957, The Sociology of Knowledge, Social Theory and Social Structure,
Free Press, New York.
Nanda, M.: 1997, The Science Wars in India, Dissent, Winter 44(1).
Norris, C.: 1992, Uncritical Theory: Postmodernism, Intellectuals and the Gulf War,
Lawrence & Wishart, London.
Orwell, G.: 1946, Politics and the English Language, The Penguin, 1946, Essays of
George Orwell, Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, 1984.
Phillips, D.: 1995, The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly: The Many Faces of Construc-
tivism, Educational Researcher 24(7), 512.
Phillips, D.: 1997, How, Why, What, When, and Where: Perspectives on Constructivism
in Psychology and Education, Issues in Education 3(2), 151194.
Phillips, D.: 1997a, Coming to Grips with Radical Social Constructivisms, Science &
Education 6(1-2), 85104.
Pickering, A.: 1992, Science as Practice and Culture, The University of Chicago Press,
Chicago.
Pinch, T.: 1993, Generations of SSK, Social Studies of Science 23, 363373.
108 Social Constructivism
Pinch, T. and Collins, H.: 1984, Private Science and Public Knowledge: The Committee
for the Scientific Investigation of the Paranormal and its Use of the Literature,
Social Studies of Science 14, 521546.
Popper, K.: 1966, The Open Society and Its Enemies,Volume 2, Hegel and Marx,
Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Quine, W.: 1960, Word and Object, MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Shapin, S.: 1979, Homo Phrenologicus: Anthropological Perspectives on an Historical
Problem, in B. Barnes and S. Shapin (eds), Natural Order: Historical Studies of
Scientific Culture, Sage, London.
Shapin, S.: 1982, History of Science and Its Sociological Reconstructions, History of
Science 20, 157211.
Slezak, P.: 1989, Scientific Discovery by Computer as Empirical Refutation of the
Strong Programme, Social Studies of Science 19, 563600.
Slezak, P.: 1991a, Artificial Experts, Social Studies of Science 21, 175201.
Slezak, P.: 1991b, Bloors Bluff: Behaviourism and the Strong Programme, Interna-
tional Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5(3), 241256.
Slezak, P.: 1994, The Social Construction of Social Constructionism, Inquiry 37(2), 139
157.
Slezak, P.: 1995, The Philosophical Case Against Visual Imagery, in P. Slezak, T. Caelli
and R. Clark (ed.), Perspectives on Cognitive Science, Ablex, Norwood.
Sokal, A. and J. Bricmont, J.: 1997, Intellectual Impostures, Profile Books, London.
Stove, D.: 1991, The Plato Cult and Other Philosophical Follies, Basil Blackwell,
Oxford.
Tweney, R. Doherty, M. and Mynatt, C. (eds): 1981, On Scientific Thinking, Columbia
University Press, New York.
van Fraassen, B.: 1980, The Scientific Image, Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Woolgar, S.: 1988, Science: The Very Idea, Tavistock Publications, London.
Re-examining the Image of Science in the School Science
Curriculum
William W. Cobern
Western Michigan University, USA. Email: bill.cobern@wmich.edu
Introductory Remarks
My task is to address the question of how the scientific community views the public
understanding of science and whether there needs to be a re-conceptualization of the
challenge to foster the public understanding of science, and also whether there is a
need to re-examine assumptions. I am compelled to begin by acknowledging a debt to
an important book, Inarticulate Science, written by Edgar Jenkins and his colleagues
at Leeds. Inarticulate Science is an outstanding contribution on the concept of the
public understanding of science and I think of my contribution today on this topic as a
footnote. My perspective is somewhat different in that I have school settings in mind
rather than adult learning (also see Lewenstein, 1992). I want to address the question
of how the science community should think about the public understanding of science
with respect to what happens in schools; and by school I mean K-12 school plus the
undergraduate science education of non-science university majors. Also, I make my
remarks from a cultural perspective in that I think it is important to think about how
scientific ideas contribute to and influence the worldviews we construct for ourselves.
Specifically, I am interested in science as an aspect of different systems of meaning
that people construct for making sense of their worlds: An aspect of meaning because
science is not the entire ball game except for a few people who chose to elevate science
to the level of metaphysics; different systems because even among scientists there
are differences as to how science is used in the construction of meaning.
I also want to preface my remarks by noting that I am of course speaking from
my experiences as an American science educator. What is happening in the USA,
however, does not appear to be unique (see Gaskell, 1996; Sjberg, 1996). For example,
several industrial nations including Norway are involved in the Third International
Mathematics and Science Study (National Research Council, 1996) for what appear to
be the same reasons. UNESCO is promoting Project 2000+ which has a parallel form
in the USA. The slogan Science for All can be heard worldwide; but, I also think that
given the enormous size of the American scientific and education establishments along
with publishing interests that what happens in the USA can hardly go unnoticed or
unfelt. Nonetheless I will be at pains not to appear overtly Yankee-centric.
The structure of my remarks will be as follows. I begin with a celebration of science
but then move on to discuss what concerns the scientific community has about the pub-
lic. From here I address the key problematic element within the scientific community
itself, the epistemology of scientific positivism. This epistemology creates considerable
110 Image of Science in Science Curriculum
difficulties for the community of science within the public square.1
Finally, I begin with the end. Let me say at the onset where I am headed. Yes,
the science community does need to re-conceptualize the challenge and re-examine
its assumptions about the public understanding of science. The science communitys
historic perspective on the public is grounded in the legitimate interests of science;
but, the promotion of the public understanding of science needs to be grounded in
the publics legitimate interests in science. The distinction between the prepositions
of and in is crucial and I owe this insight to physicist Martin Eger (1989). Egers
distinction is similar to Zimans (1984, 1991, 1992) science insiders and outsiders,
which was also adopted by Jenkins (1992) and Layton et. al. (1993).
A Celebration of Science
What is the scientific community? Ask a scientist and he or she is likely to say
that the community of science is composed of the science departments and science
laboratories at universities and research institutions. This community surely includes
scientific journals and professional societies and meetings. We might also be able
to agree that university science textbooks serve as a kind of unofficial canon for the
scientific community. Above all these, the people we call scientists form the scientific
community. I do not think it is helpful to think of science as something separate from
the people who construct, write about, teach or learn scientific knowledge. Regarding
the scientific community, we live at a time when that community finds itself in the
throes of considerable angst. It is an angst not only about the publics apparent lack
of scientific understanding but also about an apparent lack of public esteem for science
and scientific ways of thinking.
Paradoxically this angst is being endured at the same time that government agen-
cies are pursuing another round of science education reforms for the improvement
of science learning. In the USA, the National Science Teachers Association (NSTA)
and the American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) have proposed
new science curriculum frameworks. There is a new set of national science standards
promoted by the National Academy of Science (NAS) and endorsed by both NSTA and
AAAS. NAS and AAAS are organizations clearly within the boundaries of the scientific
community and though NSTA is a teachers organization, it is an organization closely
related to the community of science. Hence the efforts of these organizations strongly
reflect the interests of the scientific community. Yet there is this angst evident by
the recent spate of literature scientists and fellow travelers have written to explore
the problem of anti science (e.g., Bishop, 1995; Crease, 1089; Durant, 1990; Dyson,
1993; Gross & Levitt, 1993; Holton, 1993; Ruse, 1994; Theocharis & Psimopoulos,
1987). That this literature strikes a resonant chord within the community of science is
evident from the laudatory reviews and letters to the editor published in the mainline
scientific press. My position will be that the angst is well founded but the description
of the problem is wholly wrong headed. To paraphrase the words of Pogo, a famous
1 The term public square is a metaphor based on the concept on a town square and was coined by
Neuhaus (1984).
Cobern 111
cartoon character, the science community should be saying we have met the enemy and
he is us!
This seems a very negative remark but I am not launching another round of science
bashing. In fact I want to move quickly now to a celebratory stance. There is much in
science to celebrate. I personally cannot think of a time when I was not interested in
science. Typical of many students I do not remember much science being taught in my
elementary grade classrooms. What I remember is the power and the wonder of the
Pacific Ocean to the west of our home and the majesty of the Sierra Nevada mountains
to the east. I recall the fascination of flight whether the flight of birds or of airplanes.
I remember being glued to the television set through the great events of the Apollo
missions. From junior high school on I do remember my science classes. Not because
my science teachers were exceptional. They were not. I do not recall ever having
a science teacher I would call an exceptional teacher whereas I clearly recall a high
school English teacher who was a superb teacher. As research has shown, there are
students who seem almost naturally drawn to science; and it appears to matter little
what happens in school science, these science enthusiasts continue inexorably along
the scientific pathway (see Costa, 1993, 1995). School science is a de facto natural
selection device for screening the majority of students out of science (West, 1996).
I admit to having mixed feelings about my experiences as a university student but
more than anything else that has to do with the time period. It was the late sixties
the height of the Vietnam Warand it was difficult to be a university student at a
time of national crisis. But if I think only of my science studies I have to say it was a
heady experience. Take for example the long laborious and grueling hours spent in a
Drosophila laboratory working out genetic arrangements and chromosomal structures
for fruit flies. To my friends in other disciplines this was certainly the best example of
a silly and boring use of ones time. I can only describe the experience as heady because
we were actually working out the physical mechanisms that made the particular fruit
fly look the way it did. And then to actually photograph the chromosomes, what a
thrilling experience! A year later we took the next step and actually extracted DNA.
Again, what a thrilling experience not only to know nature at such a fundamental level,
but to touch nature at such a fundamental level. At the time of these experiences we
also met some of the great stars of scientific research. I had the honor of studying
biology with Paul Saltman and physical chemistry with Stanley Miller. We had guest
lectures by Gunther Stent and Max Delbrock. Who needs Mel Gibson when you have
just been to a lecture by Linus Pauling? Perhaps this is hyperbole but these experiences
lend themselves to positive exaggerationat least for the science enthusiast.
Indeed, the heroic stories of scientific investigations were almost as good as any
film. One story that has long fascinated me is the story of identifying the DNA syn-
thesis enzyme because it seemed the perfect example of Karl Poppers conjectures and
refutations. In 1957 Arthur Kornberg isolated a polymerase enzyme from Escherichia
coli bacteria that would synthesize DNA in vitroconjectured and confirmed. Well,
confirmed yes; but was the conjecture true? John Cairns was a doubter and he set
about searching countless quantities of E. coli bacteria attempting to find a mutant
strain of E. coli lacking Kornbergs enzyme but still capable of reproducing itselfthat
112 Image of Science in Science Curriculum
is, replicating its own DNA. His attempt at refutation was successful and Kornbergs
enzyme though originally confirmed as a DNA synthesis enzyme turned out to have
a different function in the natural setting of a cell. Perhaps this a minor story in
the history of biology but the broader history of molecular genetics can take on epic
proportions. One of the best accounts of this history is suggestively titled, The Eighth
Day of Creation (Judson, 1979). The less than subtle allusion is of course to the Bibles
account of the seven days of creation.
The stories of scientific success were important beyond their explicit purpose of
teaching scientific concepts. The stories bolstered student confidence in science. For
example, when we did those DNA extraction experiments, the truth is that we students
only understood portions of what was being done. If any of us had been vigorously
pressed to answer how we knew that sticky stuff on the glass rod was really DNA,
we would have struggled to answer. We knew in part but much else we accepted on
the basis of scientific authority vested in the professor and laboratory instructor. Why
wouldnt we? We had heard the stories. It never occurred to us that we had faith in
science and scientists. Several years later the basis for that faith was dramatically
reaffirmed for me. My wife and I were expecting our first child. As it happened,
Alex was born several weeks pre-mature and suffered from fetal respiratory distress
syndrome. Upon birth his lungs had not opened fully and the fetal duct that allows
blood to bypass the lungs of an unborn baby had failed to close at birth. We were living
in San Diego at the time and Alex was immediately transferred from the hospital of his
birth to the University of CaliforniaSan Diego teaching hospital. This hospital had a
neonatal research ward where one of the specialty interests by Gods grace happened to
be fetal respiratory distress syndrome. Perilous days followed but Alex pulled through
with no lasting ill effects. Had he been born only a few years earlier and with this
syndrome, he would not have lived through his first twenty-four hours. Why wouldnt
I acknowledge the authority of science?
The excitement I felt as a student of science and the power I witnessed with my sons
full recovery are grounded in the powerful ideas and methods that science has uniquely
contributed to our culture in the 20th century. Cultural historian O.B. Hardison re-
marked that no examination of modern culture can exclude the influence of science
and technology, and one that underestimated their influence would be irresponsible
(1989, p. xi). There is cultural capital in science that properly belongs to everyone.
The science community will endorse this perspective and this is what science for all
should at the least be about. The science community, however, is not always so noble.
For example, the National Academy of Science in its attempt to ward off religious
incursions in the public square told American science teachers:
In a nation whose people depend on scientific progress for their health, economic gains, and
national security, it is of utmost importance that our students understand science as a system
of study, so that by building on past achievements they can maintain the pace of scientific
progress and ensure the continued emergence of results that can benefit mankind. (1984, p. 6)
The fact that this statement so blithely ignores the complex and ambiguous relation-
ship between science and technology and between science and economic development
Cobern 113
(Drori, 1996), casts doubt on the Academys sincerity. Indeed some would see in this
statement an attempt by the science community to protect its privileged status to
control the discourse in certain segments of the public square, particularly the schools.
Lynda Birke (1990) asks whether the drive to educate the public about science is merely
an exercise in public relations and labor recruitment. Who will really benefit? For a
profitable discussion of these questions see Bishop (1995), Goodstein (1995), and Kevles
(1995).
To which he answered,
The problem is public alienation. For a variety of reasons a significant part of the general public
has become distrustful of those goals, values and methods [of science].
Whites article appeared in the inaugural issue Science 80 which was a magazine
published by the American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) for the
specific purpose of improving the American publics understanding of science.
Through the 1980s, however, the science community perceived continued outbreaks
of dissatisfaction with science in the form of anti-evolutionism and spiritualism (Holton,
114 Image of Science in Science Curriculum
1992). In the 1990s scientists found that anti-science was no longer confined to K-
12 schools and unscientific parents. Anti-science had infected the very institutions of
rationality, the universities. This perception motivated Gross and Levitt to write their
book, Higher superstition: The Academic Left and its Quarrels with Science, published
in 1993. Two years later, Gross and Levitt working with the New York Academy of
Sciences brought together,
about 200 worried scientists, doctors, philosophers, educators, and thinkers. . . [because] there
is a growing danger, many said, that the fabric of reason is being ripped as under, and that
if scientists and other thinkers continue to acquiesce in the process, the hobbling of science
and its handmaidensmedicine and technology among themseems assured. (Browne, 1995,
p. E2, emphasis added)
The meeting was titled, The Flight from Science and Reason. Those committed to
ripping reason asunder included feminists such as Sandra Harding (1993) who raises
questions about the nature of objectivity in science. They include Molefi Asante (1992)
and Ivan Sertima (1987) who are proponents of Afrocentrism and concepts of African
rationality. There are multiculturalists in general (e.g., Grant, Sleeter, & Anderson,
1986). Still worse are the strong proponents of the social study of science such as
Bruno Latour (1987) and Steve Fuller (1991) who advocate a social constructivist view
of scientific knowledge. Worst of all the offending academics are the critical theorists
such as Henry Giroux who writes about critical pedagogy (e.g., Giroux & McLaren,
1989) and the literary critic Stanley Fish who is the editor of the radical cultural
studies journal, Social Text.
Can science get any respect? asked Kevin Finneran (1996, p. 95), editor of Issues
in Science and Technology. One would hope so but in the same year that Higher
Superstitions was published, the eminent physicist Freeman Dyson published, Science
in Trouble, in which he commented that attacks against science are likely to become
more bitter and more widespread in the future. . . (1993, p. 524, emphasis added).
Perhaps with that ominous prediction in mind, one scientist recently attempted to
deliver a knock out punch to the radical social constructivists. Alan Sokal is a physi-
cist at New York University and he wrote a manuscript titled, Transgressing The
Boundaries: Towards A Transformative Hermeneutics Of Quantum Gravity (1996b),
which he submitted to Social Text for review and possible publication. Subsequently
Social Text published the article only to have Sokal within days of the publication
announce that the article was a hoax. Sokal had submitted a nonsense manuscript
which by its acceptance for publication exposed the radicals as academic charlatans, in
his opinion of course. In his own words:
For some years Ive been troubled by an apparent decline in the standards of intellectual rigor
in certain precincts of the American academic humanities. But Im a mere physicist: if I find
myself unable to make head or tail of jouissance and differance, perhaps that just reflects my
own inadequacy. So, to test the prevailing intellectual standards, I decided to try a modest
(though admittedly uncontrolled) experiment: Would a leading North American journal of
cultural studieswhose editorial collective includes such luminaries as Fredric Jameson and
Andrew Rosspublish an article liberally salted with nonsense if (a) it sounded good and (b)
it flattered the editors ideological preconceptions? The answer, unfortunately, is yes. (Sokal,
1996a, p. 1)
Cobern 115
I doubt that Sokal landed a knock out punch but there is no doubt about the ruckus
that ensued.2 Moreover, Sokal may not respect the people at Social Text but he must
worry about them and other radical social constructivists. Why else would he even give
them a second thought? Indeed, what has happened to the scientific community that
one of its distinguished members finds enemies in academe that must be combated in
such a non academic fashion? This is a question that will surely occupy the sociologists
of science for sometime to come.
Scientific Positivism
I do not disagree that there are extremes of social constructivism antithetical to science
and to the celebration of science that I have offered. To some extent Alan Sokal has
done all scholarship a favor by exposing the excesses of extremist social constructivism.
One should also be concerned that legitimate criticism of the scientific community not
be lost in these intellectual skirmishes involving extreme positions. It is in the scientific
communitys best interests to heed legitimate criticism. If scientists willingly join the
cultural debate about science, science can grow in stature (Finneran, 1996, p. 96). If
they do not, the scientific community will by default affirm Martin Heideggers quip
that scientists do not think.
As I tried to convey in my celebration of science, science can be exhilarating. It is
exhilarating to realize that one can know so much about the natural world and to feel
that one can discover so much more. Earlier I also hinted that the scientific community
should look within itself as the community considers the current problems with the
public and science. Along with being exhilarating, science is also seductive. It can
seduce one to the nave materialism that what one knows by science is fundamental
reality, when in fact the debates over the nature of scientific knowledge with respect
to ontological realism are as current today as they ever were (see, e.g., Hawking &
Penrose, 1996). Science can also be deceptive. It can deceive one into thinking that one
has privileged knowledge. Indeed, the cultural point of discussion that I think is most
crucial is the point of epistemological position. How should the scientific community
seek to position science with respect to other domains of knowledge in the public
square? For the better part of the 20th century that question has been answered by a
philosophy of logical positivism which sought to banish metaphysics from philosophy,
because its theses cannot be rationally justified (Holton, 1992, p. 45) leaving sense
perceptions as the only admissible basis of human knowledge and precise thought. In
philosophy, positivism is yesterdays news, a failed project (Walsh, 1967), but what
might be called scientific positivism (Gilmer, 1995) or colloquial positivism hangs on.
Scientific positivism roughly represents a classical view of realism, philosophical ma-
terialism, strict objectivity, and hypothetico-deductive method. Though recognizing
the tentative nature of all scientific knowledge, scientific positivism imbues scientific
knowledge with a Laplacian certainty denied all other disciplines, thus allowing the
2 Those interested in this strange affair should consult website <http://www.nyu.edu
/gsas/dept/physics/faculty/sokal/index.html> for a full account including plus Sokals original article.
Moreover, the University of Kansas held a conference in 1997 devoted to the topic of, Science and its critics:
A meeting to promote dialogue between the two cultures, where Sokal was the featured speaker.
116 Image of Science in Science Curriculum
Natural
Sciences
Social Sciences
Unfortunately, this ideology couples the science community with what I call the
Four Western Imperatives of the late 20th century:
These ideas resonate with the fashionable nihilism found in certain segments of
modern western culture. Given this view of science, E.A. Burtts comments of 1967
become prophetic:
The world that people thought themselves living ina world rich with colour and sound, redo-
lent with fragrance, filled with gladness, love and beauty, speaking everywhere of purposive
harmony and creative idealswas crowded now into minute corners of the brains of scattered
organic beings. The really important world was a world hard, cold, colourless, silent, and dead;
a world of quantity, a world of mathematically computable motions in mechanical regularity.
(1967, pp. 238-239)
Direct Indirect
Interaction Interaction
Text Reader
(Moby Dick) Direct of Text
Interaction
Indirect
Direct
Interaction
Interaction
Natural Natural
Phenomena Direct Philosopher
Interaction
1. We can affirm that science is part of the cultural heritage that belongs to all
people. The exhilaration that I felt as a student of science should be available to
120 Image of Science in Science Curriculum
Author
(Melville)
Text Reader
(Moby Dick) Direct of Text
Interaction
Indirect
Direct
Interaction
Interaction
Text Reader
(Moby Dick) Direct of Text
Interaction
Natural Modern
Phenomena Direct Scientist
Interaction
Ann: Nature is knowable. . . We can learn to understand many things about nature through
personal experience, school and science. Science itself provides us with technology which
in turn increases our scientific knowledge. Technology helps provide us with many wants
which, of course, increases our pleasure. It also uses resources. (ATG.n6, Narrative in
Cobern et al., 1995, p. 24)
This appreciation of science, however, is not where her discussion with the re-
searchers began. Note the emphasized words.
Ann: To me, nature is beautiful and pure because it is Gods creation. Nature provides
both aesthetic and emotional pleasure and I need it for self renewal. I like to go where you
cant see any influence by man. When Im out in nature I feel calm and peaceful. It is a
spiritual feeling and it helps me understand myself . . . This leads me to ask questions that
Id like to find answers to. The pleasure I get from nature is enhanced by the mysteries I
see in it. (ATG.n6, Narrative in Cobern et al., 1995, p. 24, emphasis added)
Anns conceptualization of the natural world has significant aesthetic and reli-
gious elements. Nature in her view is something friendly that you can joyously
be part of.
Now consider Mr. Hess. He is Anns physical science teacher and he who sat
for the same research interview as did Ann. He began his discussion in marked
contrast to Ann.
3 The research was funded by a National Science Foundation grant (RED # 9055834)
Cobern 123
Author of Nature/
Nature qua Nature
Text Sociologist of
Direct Science
Interaction (Edinburgh School!)
Science and
Science related
Graduates
aesthetic
religious Science understood
via Environment
recreational
contempative/emotional
which requires provides
relational provides
economic to
Essential
Conservation sustain Resources
Concluding Remarks
So, yes, the scientific community does need to re-conceptualize the challenge and re-
examine its assumptions about the public understanding of science. The scientific
communitys historic perspective on the public is grounded in the legitimate interests of
science; but, the promotion of the public understanding of science needs to be grounded
in the publics legitimate interests in science. Professor John Polkinghorne, president
of Queens College, Cambridge, who is a physicist and Anglican priest, recently made
the following remarks in Scientific American:
Everyone has a metaphysicsa worldviewjust as all people speak prose, whether they are
aware of it or not. Science can and should contribute to that worldview, but it should by no
means monopolize it. Unless you are one of those biologists so flushed with the recent success of
your discipline that you are moved to claim that science is all, you will want to locate scientific
understanding within a wider view of knowledge that gives equally serious consideration to
other forms of human insight and experience. (Polkinghorne, 1996, p. 121, emphasis added)
It is time that the science community and school science education began to do just
this: to locate science within a broader view of knowledge.
126 Image of Science in Science Curriculum
Philosophical
Orientation
Primarily Primarily
Toward
Naturalistic Religious
Range Range
Classical
Atheism Deism Fundamentalism
Theism
Nature
Complementarily Environment
Majority view
Amitabha Gupta
Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay, India. Email: ag@hss.iitb.ernet.in
Introduction
The curriculum for science education at present both at the school and the post-school
levels emphasizes narrow specialization of only technical material. All the cognate
subjects in the curriculum are arranged horizontally and the students move through
schools and colleges vertically from level to level of successive stages of specialization.
The teaching materials of the program are structured in a hierarchical order mainly
around narrower and still narrower technical content as the student moves up at
higher levels. This is considered to be undesirable. In what follows I would like to
first argue for integrating science education with philosophy, history and sociology of
science with the help of cognitive science, secondly, suggest a model of integration, and
finally, illustrate the model with two examples.
Section 1 deals with issues relating to narrow science education programmes that
currently exist, the misconceptions about science that may arise from such science
education programmes, and a possible model for science studies that may remedy it.
Section 2 suggests that science studies based on a straight forward Philosophy and
History of Science may get entangled in unnecessary controversies/debates and fail to
integrate the technical content and the insights into scientific practices. The section
first identifies two such conventional debates in science studies and discusses one
debate, viz., whether scientific knowledge is the creation of the individual scientist or
a product of society, and offers a possible resolution by adopting the cognitive-historical
approach. In Section 3 the same is done for another debate, viz., whether scientific
knowledge is objective or subjective. The discussions on both the debates shows how
Cognitive Science and Case Study based approach can act as unifying factors. This is
illustrated with the help of examples of scientific work illustrated with two case studies:
one on scientific experiment and the other on introduction of new concepts and a
scientific law.
i. Although the teachers and the textbooks of science mostly claim to stick to facts
and to exclude idle philosophic talk, they end up creating misconceptions pre-
cisely about these facts, may be not by deliberate instruction but by implication.
132 Science Pedagogy through Cognitive Science
Philipp Frank4 has given examples of textbook formulation of laws of physics,
e.g., the law of inertia, and shown that in that formulation no physical facts
whatsoever can be logically derived from the law, and the law is inapplicable to
any actual situation in the physical world. This means that textbook formulation
often is not physical but purely metaphysical.
ii. It is true that valid scientific knowledge is often intuitive, the acquisition or
assessment of which is based on practical experience in learning science, research,
and active participation in scientific work and scientific community. It has been
said that valid science is what is recognised as valid by scientists and can sel-
dom be identified as a formal logical property of scientific discourse. And yet those
who enter into a scientific career in which their earlier fact-oriented training is
not derived from any exposure to the actual processes of creative scientific work
and research, may have no personal experience of the fundamental importance
of the mistakes, groping and criticisms in the generation of new and reliable
knowledge or the importance of inventive imagination or of the limitations and
uncertainties of the so-called scientific methods. The reason for this is that our
fact-oriented science education program has lost contact with living experience
of scientific work and research, since it has been turned into a banking system,
in which the teachers deposit a certain amount of factual knowledge with the
students and retrieve it during the examination essentially treating the student
as no more than a memory bank.
iii. Finally, as a consequence of increasingly narrowing hierarchical arrangement
of factual content and rigid standards of valid scientific knowledge or proof, a
student of science forms the opinion that the scientific view is the only legitimate
view, ignoring all questions concerning its scope and the legitimacy of other al-
ternatives. Since in his narrow and exclusive science education the student is
taught to treat only science as valid he naturally makes an inference that it must
be valid in other regions as well.
The irony of the present science education program is that whereas it really intends
to impart nothing but facts and to remain neutral regarding any attempts to incor-
porate discussions about science, it creates, in the process of teaching, a vacuum. The
influence of the isolated technical scientific content on the total attitude of the student
towards science forces him to fill up this vacuum. In the absence of any conscious
provision for providing an over-view of science and thereby protecting students from
narrow blinkers or nave euphoria just as much as from the false and hostile ideas
about science, this vacuum is filled up by many misconceptions. As a result, myths
about science abound and a mystique of science prevails.
4 Frank, P.: 1961, The Place of the Philosophy of Science in the Curriculum of the Physics Students, in
Modern Science and Its Philosophy, Collier Books, New York, 224-252.
Gupta 133
1.1 Misconceptions about Science Implicit in Conventional Science Education
Programme
What are some of these misconceptions? First, science is claimed to provide absolute
truth, completely objective and pure description, and, therefore, should be considered
the only authority for belief and the only source of reliable knowledge. The overempha-
sis on mathematical and formal aspect of science, the authoritarian manner in which
scientific knowledge is imparted, and the total absence in science education of initial
doubt, the element of surprise, inventive imagination, creative criticism lend credence
to the belief that scientific knowledge is absolute. The manner in which scientific exper-
iments are conducted in a school or college laboratory shows that an experiment on, say,
Boyles law, amounts merely to observe a series of values of the pressure and volume
of the gas, which can be plotted on a nice smooth curve confirming a mathematical
relationship between relevant variables. Accounts of Boyles own experiment could give
a contrary picture. Besides, the absolute knowledge view of science has been reinforced
by another widespread misconception that there exists a master procedure or method
underlying all scientific work and the successful application of this unique infallible
method is what validates scientific knowledge. P.W. Bridgman, J.B. Conant and many
other practicing scientists have claimed that science is what scientists do and the
search for the Method is futile as there are not one but many methods.
Secondly, science education conveys the impression that science is hard, objective,
and value free as opposed to humanistic studies that are soft, subjective, and value-
laden. Reacting to this many have argued that science dehumanises, that the conse-
quences flowing from science are preponderantly evil, trivial or false by comparison
with what can be derived from other sources, such as poetic insight, religious revela-
tion, mystical experience or self-knowledge. This polarization of attitudes is the basis
of C.P. Snows two cultures and Holtons Distinction between the New Apollonians
and the new Dionysians. There are two aspects of this: (a) this polarization is simple
minded and misconceived, augmented, on the one hand, by the way science is taught
obstinately, scornfully, neglectful of all the humanistic issues that arises within their
domain and humanists, on the one other hand, exhibit corresponding scorn and neglect
for science; and (b) the myth of value-freedom and objectivity of scientific knowledge
has been questioned by the sociologists of knowledge. The works of Kuhn, Merton,
Bloor, Barnes and others have emphasised the role the scientific community plays in
the production of scientific knowledge: the invisible colleges, the peer review, author-
ity, consensus, norms and recognition of the scientific community.
Thirdly, a widespread impression, which prevails among many students and prac-
titioners of science, is that science possesses a unique world picture, an overall sci-
entific representation, such as the mechanistic world picture or materialism, i.e., the
world picture that all phenomena are by-products or epiphenomena of the ultimate
constituents of matter. The belief in such a world picture makes the scientist confident
that science can provide valid answers to all questions since they follow from the same
source, i.e., a single, unique world picture. History of science has exploded the myth of
such a world picture. Moreover, we know that even if it exists it does not show up in
134 Science Pedagogy through Cognitive Science
our science education since it is totally fragmented to provide such a unified view.
Fourthly, since Bacon in 16th century the view that knowledge is power has turned
science into a means to gain control over nature. Consequently, many subscribe to
the nave eupheria that all our problemsdisease, poverty, and hungercan be done
away with by the deliberate application of scientific knowledge. This belief is the basis
for massive investment in science and technology. However, this faith is somewhat
misplaced as it is impossible to calculate the relevance of any particular fundamental
research to any particular human need, e.g., the work of Faraday and Maxwell on
electromagnetism could hardly have been predicted to lead to phenomenal development
of electrical and electronic industries. Therefore, the whole question of how to guide
science towards solution of practical problems will remain open and quite unanswer-
able.
These influential myths about science, direct products of the narrow, isolated, and
over-specialised science education, may be given a common name, i.e., scientism. Of
course, the origins of scientism can be traced back to the rise of modern science in
the 17th century with its fundamental insistence on the value of scientific methods of
investigation and argument. Based on it, the pioneers of modern science were able
to make a break-through in their attempts to understand nature, when approaches
other than science were dominant. In recent times, however, science has taken a
more dominant place in every sphere and scientism has assumed a more extreme,
threatening and doctrinaire form with blind belief in the success of technical scientific
knowledge and an addiction to science.
1.2 Empirical Evidences and the Need for Removing the Misconceptions
There is some evidence, based on at least two empirical studies5 , that the current sci-
ence education programs, by concentrating on objectivity and validity of science, by its
disciplinary specialization and fragmentation, by glorifying the rational, mathematical
and analytic aspects without any reference to intuitive, imaginative, subjective aspects,
do project the doctrine of scientism as the official image of science.
The fact of the matter is that while designing science curricula, the influence of the
technical scientific content on the total attitude of the student towards science itself
cannot be ignored. From the point of view of a good educational strategy, it is important
to make sure that students and those concerned with the promotion of science do
acquire the appropriate standards and norms of scientific practice, and not wrong
intellectual habits and false standards of scientific proof. Moreover, whenever scientific
knowledge and technology are hoped to be twin pillars of social transformation, the
base for science is dangerously weak if the vision concerning the place and scope of
science among students and practitioners of science is narrow. Yet, it is not clear how
it can be achieved without some self understanding of science, i.e., without making
a conscious and deliberate effort to critically discuss science, rather than learning it
5 (i) Mead, M. & Metraux, R.: 1956, Image of the Scientist among High-School, Students, Science, 126,
384-390.
(ii) Ahlgren, A. & Walbery, M.J.: 1973, Changing Attitudes Towards Science Among Adolescents, Nature,
254, 187-190.
Gupta 135
merely by rote. Current science education program stubbornly repudiates any such
responsibility leaving it totally to chance and intuition. As a result some have pleaded
forcefully that science education programs will produce better educated science stu-
dents if they are taught a little less science as such, and a little more about science.
Thus the main objective of integrating teaching and learning of science with teach-
ing about science or understanding science will be (i) to display the developing char-
acter of scientific endeavour by incorporating historical awareness, and (ii) to foster a
critical attitude on the part of the learner.
The model of scientific development, i.e., the pattern of responses given to the above
question if one examines the history of a scientific discipline, can be specified by the
Darwinian Theory of evolution, Toulmin7 draws the following analogy as described by
the Table 1 below:
6 Toulmin, S.: 1974, Rationality and Scientific Discovery Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, K.
2 Two Debates
There are two basic debates in the current literature in Philosophy of Science and
Socio-Historical studies in science:
the first debate concerns the agency responsible for the construction of scientific
knowledge: whether it is the creation of the individual scientist or a product of
society.
the second debate relates to the nature of scientific knowledge: whether it is
objective or relative to a conceptual perspective, and
I shall review these debates and show that a closer attention to the underlying
cognitive issues help us to resolve them.
Bloor, D.: 1983, Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge, Columbia University Press, New York.
10 Barnes, B.: 1982, T.S. Kuhn and Social Science, Macmillan, London.
11 Collins, H.M.: 1985, Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice, Sage, Beverley
Hills.
Gupta 139
of science and claimed that scientific knowledge is entirely a product of social interac-
tions and influence.
Latour and Woolgar (1986) have proposed a ten-year moratorium on cognitive ex-
planations of science. For them what matters is the communication and interrelations
among the scientists based on public documents. These documents clearly exist outside
the mental representation of individual scientists. They are the shared property of the
scientific community and public embodiment of scientific theories. Latour and Woolgar
showed how in the laboratory the inscription devices (i.e. initial records that are
harder to read and more open to attack are transformed by the experimenter later into
published transcripts that become powerful weapons in arguments) and external repre-
sentations or documents exert influence on other scientists. Latour (1987) 12 examines
the function scientific texts, diagrams, schematic representations etc. fulfill in creating
understanding within a scientific community. He calls these public embodiments im-
mutable and combinable mobiles that in the process of scientific communication often
mutate and facilitate an improved or different understanding.
The anti-cognitivism of Latour and Woolgar (1979)13 and Collins is shared by Downes
(1993). He accuses the cognitivists of cognitive individualism and claims that they
subscribe to the thesis that a sufficient explanation for all cognitive activities can be
provided by an account of autonomous individual cognitive agents. He finds that the
cognitivists are guilty of reducing social explanations to psychological explanations.
According to the sociologists of scientific knowledge, the reductionism of the social
to psychological is not possible for various reasons:
i. Durkheim showed that social facts are irreducible and have an existence of their
own. Following this idea, Downes distinguishes three levels of the social aspects
of science and claims that each has an independent existence and none can be
reduced to psychology: (a) scientific documents, particularly classics, as Kuhn,
Latour and Woolgar showed, have an independent, external existence, provide a
paradigm for the individual scientist and influence his problem solving approach.
(b) social interactions among scientists, as can be found in complex laboratories,
are based on cooperation where individual scientist is not entirely responsible for
the final scientific outcome, and (c) much of the decision making processes of the
individual scientist are guided by external social considerations and influences,
e.g., decisions regarding what funding agency to approach, how to formulate
the research proposal so that it would be acceptable, the choice of the research
project, the journal and conference where the research paper is to be published or
presented.
ii. Collins (1990) gives the following reasons for which he claims that science is
social: (a) the routine servicing of scientific belief reveals that it is the scien-
tific group which determines how an individual scientist checks the validity of
12 Latour, B.: 1987, Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society, Open
i. that both the words science (which comes from the Latin word sciencea meaning
knowledge) and the word cognition (co = together, gnocere = knowledge) have
knowledge in common. Science is taken to be a major paradigm of a knowledge-
producing enterprise and Cognitive Science studies the underlying mechanisms
responsible for the production, acquisition and deployment of knowledge, includ-
ing scientific knowledge.
ii. that the exclusively a priori, speculative and normative approach to traditional
epistemology is to be replaced by an empirical and naturalistic approach treating
cognitive activities and phenomena as natural phenomena. The traditional epis-
temology has undergone radical changes as it became apparent that an important
resource for a naturalistic account of knowledge is Cognitive Science.
iii. these mechanisms presuppose that the human mind or artificial intelligent de-
vices can function based only on representational structures and processes that
operate on them to produce new structures. These structures may include linguis-
tic expressions, concept trees, schemas, cognitive maps, mental models, diagrams,
visual images etc.
Gupta 141
In the traditional epistemology, Kant for example, provided such an account of the
underlying mechanism for the possibility of scientific knowledge by adopting a specula-
tive and apriori approach. Kant asked the question as to what sort of mechanism would
make mathematical and natural scientific knowledge possible and gave a description
of such a mechanism.
In the 1950s, Kuhn and Hanson used psychological ideas, particularly from the
Gestalt school, in order to explain certain phenomena in scientific observation. How-
ever, due to the progress made in Cognitive Science since 1950s there is a better
understanding of the cognitive mechanisms involved in many scientific activities and
practices.
A survey of the relevant literature shows that the Cognitive Science based ap-
proach complements the traditional historical approach (both internal and external),
the sociological approach, and the philosophical concern for the epistemology of sci-
ence, by providing an enriched understanding of how scientists generate and evaluate
scientific ideas. For example, the volume, (No. XV), entitled Cognitive Models of
Science, published in 1992 by R.N. Giere14 in the series Minnesota Studies in the
Philosophy of Science presented the work of psychologists, historians, researchers in
Artificial Intelligence and philosophers who had employed ideas and methodologies
from Cognitive Science in order to study the underlying cognitive mechanisms for
explaining and understanding scientific practices.
Moreover, there are major studies on scientists and scientific theories from the
cognitive point of view. A few examples of such studies may be mentioned here. Dar-
den has identified the cognitive strategies that contributed toward the development of
Mandelian genetics. Giere has used psychological and sociological ideas to improve our
understanding of the recent developments in geology and physics. Based on the case
study on plate tectonics, Solomon shows how certain cognitive heuristics play a crucial
role in scientific decision making. Nersessian has drawn on ideas from cognitive psy-
chology to help understand the developments in electro-magnetic theories made possi-
ble by the contributions of Faraday, Maxwell and Einstein. Churchland has discussed
the nature of theories and explanations from the perspective of computational neuro-
science. Thagard has used computational and cognitive theories to help understand
the structure and growth of scientific knowledge.
i. what were the generative justifications provided by Galileo for his claim (the so-
called Distance Theorem) that
. . . the distances traversed during equal intervals of time by a body falling from rest, stand
to one another in the same ratio as the odd numbers beginning with unity?
ii. Galileo was aware of the fact that observation of vertically falling bodies involved
difficulties, as the motion would be very fast. Hence for the purpose of under-
standing the nature of vertical motion based on experiment, it would be necessary
Gupta 145
to slow down the motion on an inclined plane. However, Galileo felt the necessity
of justifying as to whether the slowed down motion on the inclined plane and the
vertical motion of freely falling bodies are the same and whether the same law
would hold for both the motions.
iii. the question of the reliability of the experiment allegedly performed by Galileo
and Galileos resolution of the problem of the reliability and epistemic justifica-
tion of the knowledge claim regarding the law of freely falling bodies.
Thus Galileo was considered the father of modern observational and experimental
methods. As opposed to this Aristotle saw the experiments performed, but would not
believe the evidence of experience, although in Biology Aristotle was a down-to-earth,
hard-boiled realist.
Galileo himself seems to be responsible for this impression as he sometimes uses
the word experience/experiment (e.g. in the statement at the beginning of Two New
Sciences) in a way that one would be led to the traditional picture of Galileo that he
was the founder and earliest successful practitioner of modern experimental science.
Or Galileo was the man who relied on experiment and Aristotle was one who denied
the validity of experience. This is bolstered by the image of Galileo confounding his
Aristotelian adversaries at Pisa and experimentally disproving Aristotelian dynamics
by dropping weights of various sizes from the Leaning Tower.
History of Science, however, dispels these misconceptions based on anecdotes/traditional
pictures/historically nave attitudes. It instills a sense of historical skepticism, makes
us more cautious about relying on facts as one has not yet the time to check some of
these episodes closely. It also urges the need for more accuracy in the description of the
creative part of the scientific work/intellectual development and growth of science/the
part relating to the process rather than the final product.
. . . the times of descent, for various inclinations of the plane, bore to one another precisely
the ratio which . . . had been predicted . . . Also . . . there was no appreciable discrepancy
in the results. (Two New Sciences, p. 179)
Such accuracy was not possible because of (i) the difficulties in the synchronization
of the rolling ball and the timing device, especially when time is being measured by
certain crude devices used at that time such as water-clock or pulse-beat, and (ii)
friction and rotational inertia.
Lane Cooper17 also casts doubt about Leaning Tower experiment. To be sure, Galileo
did make observations and performed rough checks of his results, but the experimental
method and inductive method of the new science was really, from the historical point of
view, the creation of the new generation of scientists, including such heroic experimen-
talists as Robert Boyle, Robert Hook and Isaac Newton (especially his work on Optics)
and the members of the Royal Society.
16 Butterfield, H.: 1949, Origins of Modern Science, Macmillan, 71.
17 Cooper, L.: 1935, Aristotle, Galileo and the Tower of Pisa.
Gupta 147
2.1.5.3 Galileos Lineage to the Platonic-Pythagorean Tradition
Galileos Lineage to the Platonic-Pythagorean Tradition
Instead, Galileo belonged to the Platonic-Pythagorean (Idealist) Tradition: This tra-
dition is associated with the assumption that (a) the underlying reality is that of
number, (b) abstraction and idealization is inevitable in understanding Nature, and (c)
mathematics must be applied to the understanding of the physical phenomena. This is
in clear opposition to the Aristotelian tradition, which created a clear cleavage between
mathematics and physics.
Galileos adherence to the Platonic-Pythagorean tradition is evidenced by his own
statement that the Book of Nature is written in the language of mathematics. To the
question whether the ship experiment was really been done, Salviati (the spokesman
of Galileo) replied
I without experiment [experience] am certain that the effect will follow as I tell you, because it
is necessary that it should, (Dialogue concerning Two Chief World Systems)
i. Galileo did not belong to the experimental tradition in which (a) conditions would
be artificially created to show how nature would behave under previously unob-
served, often previously non-existent circumstances, e.g., vacuum created by air
pump, (b) the experimental conditions could be manipulated to coerce nature to
answer questions; what Francis Bacon described as twisting the lions tail.
ii. Galileo also differed from the Greeks who performed experiments with inflated
pigs bladder that resist compression or experiment with clepsydra and pipette as
direct evidence for the corporeality of air.
iii. For Galileo experiments are designed to test already formulated hypothesis in
order to make it more evident, rather than deriving the hypothesis on the basis
of experimental data. Thus, for Galileo, the job of observation/experience and
experiment is to render his basic mathematical principles immediately evident.
Starting with Definitions, Axioms Galileo proved two Theorems which were es-
sentially numerical:
Galileo, then, claims that without experiment this formulation is correct and
says:
No, and I do not need it, as without any experience I can affirm that it is so, because it
cannot be otherwise, it is necessary that it should.
Then goes on to show that the law thus obtained yield, on interpretation, empiri-
cally testable predictions in terms of direct measurement.
The request which you as a man of science, make, is a very reasonable one; for this is
a customand properly soin those sciences where mathematical demonstrations are
applied to natural phenomena, as is seen in the case of perspective (optics) astronomy,
mechanics, music, and others where the principles, once established by well-chosen ex-
periments, become the foundations of the entire superstructure. I hope therefore it will
not appear to be a waste of time if we discuss at considerable length this first and most
fundamental question upon which hinge numerous consequences of which we have in this
book only a small number placed by the Author, who has done so much to open a pathway
hitherto close to minds of speculative turn. So far as experiments go they have not been
neglected by the Author; and often, in his company, I have attempted in the following
manner to assure myself that the acceleration actually experienced by falling bodies is
that above described.
History of Science: Succession of precursor concepts & Philosophy of Science: Responses to disciplinary
techniques and social determinants pressure---a rational reconstruction
Concept Formation Techniques Epistemic Justification & Reality
3 Debate 2
3.1 The Debate Relating to the Nature of Scientific Knowledge: Whether it is ob-
jective or relative to a conceptual perspective
It is said that before philosophy of science took what is sometimes called the cognitive
turn (mentioned in 2.1.2 above), it was preceded by two phases, viz.,
the so-called linguistic turn emphasizing on objectivity and rationality of scientific
knowledge and
the socio-historical turn (mentioned in 2.1.1 above) highlighting the relativis-
tic socio-historical nature of scientific knowledge (also called the conceptual
perspective approach)
3.2.2 Scientific Knowledge and Naturalization of Belief and Knowledge: The Interaction-
Information Theoretic Account of Observation and Belief/Knowledge
The cognitive, ecological, interactive and information theoretic approach, advocated,
among others, by Goldman23 , Dretske24 , Barwise and Perry25 , J.R. Anderson26 , J.J. Gib-
son, may be construed as denial of the justificatory account of knowledge (involving the
23 Goldman, A.I.: 1986, Epistemology and Cognition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
24 Dretske, Fred: 1981, Knowledge and the Flow of Information, MIT Press/Bradford, Cambridge, Mass.
25 Barwise, J. & Perry, J.: 1983, Situations and Attitudes, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
26 Anderson, J.R.: 1990, The Adaptive Character of Thought, Hillsdale, Erlbaum, NJ.
Anderson, J.R.: 1991, The adaptive nature of human categorization, Psychological Review, 98, 409-429
Anderson, J.R.: 1991, Is human cognition adaptive?, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14, 471-517
Gupta 155
base statement and inductive inferential view).
Epistemic acts, such as observation, according to this view, is said to involve suc-
cessive type of states or situations where information flows from one type of state or
situation to another. Thus, in observation the information that x is P, where x and
P are features of the physical world is carried from the object to the sense organs or
receptors through a process of interaction between the two. This interaction relation
leading to information flow is based on a nomic regularity/constraint holding between
state or situation type where one involves the other, e.g. the fact that the X-ray has
such and such a pattern carries information about/involves/indicates that Jackie has
a broken leg.
i. the symbol grounding problem: How can the meanings of the meaningless symbol
tokens, manipulated solely on the basis of their arbitrary shapes be grounded or
connected up with the world in the right way?
ii. the frame problem: Assuming that an intelligent agent is capable of planning and
problem solving and given the fact that she is acting, can we specify in symbolic
formalism what changes and what remains constant in the particular domain?
Classical symbolic systems are monotonic, whereas planning and problem solving
invariably involve new experience and change.
iii. the problem of induction: Mere symbolic representation does not lend itself eas-
ily to model judgements of similarity and to identify projectible predicates that
denote natural kinds. Both Goodman and Quine taught us that these issues are
intimately related to the problem of induction.
The basic problem with systems using propositional and symbolic representation is
that they are disjoint from non-symbolic system (i.e. the world). Hence, there must be
some point where the information from the world is presented in symbolic form.
27 Fodor, J.A.: 1981, Representations, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
28 Pylyshyn, Z.: 1984, Computation and Cognition, Bradford/MIT Press, Cambridge,MA.
29 Newell, A. & Simon, H.: 1976, Computer Science as Empirical Inquiry: Symbols and Search, CACM, 19,
113-116
156 Science Pedagogy through Cognitive Science
3.3.1 Two Important Issues
There are two important issues here:
Gibson terms the latter inquiry Ecological optics, which involves finding envi-
ronmental properties that can be uniquely and invariantly specified in the structure of
the reflected ambient light in the form of an optic array. The structure of the reflected
ambient light depends upon the structure of the surface of the perceived object. Unlike
30 Harnad, S.: 1990, The Symbol Grounding Problem, Phisica D 42, 335-346.
31 Johnson, B.: 1987, The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Cognition, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago, Ill.
Lakoff, G.: 1987, Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, Ill.
Langacker, R.W.: 1987, Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, 1, Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA.
32 Gibson, J.J.: 1950, The Perception of the Visual World, Houghton Mifflin, Boston
Gibson, J.J.: (1966), The Senses Considered as Perceptual System, Houghton Mifflin, Boston
Gibson, J.J.: 1979, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, Houghton Mifflin, Boston
33 Marr, David: 1982, Vision, Freeman, San Francisco
Gupta 157
the radiant light from a light source, the structure of the reflected ambient light is
responsible for the perception of distance, depth, motion etc. For Gibson the structure
of the reflected ambient light does not carry/convey information, it is information.
The job of the perceptual system is merely to pick up the information by orienting,
adjusting, resonating and tuning to the light input. Thus Gibson treated the problem
of perception as that of recovering from sensory information valid properties of the
external world.
However, as Marr points out, Gibsons analysis is incomplete. Gibson failed to real-
ize the fact that the detection of physical invariant, like image surfaces, is exactly and
precisely an information-processing and cognitive problem. Secondly, Gibson vastly
underrated the sheer difficulties of such detection.
Marr, then, goes on to provide an elaborate analysis of how the information provided
at the Primal Sketch and 2 1/2D levels lead to identification and categorization of 3-D
objects as we ordinarily recognize them.
making a distinction between primary and secondary qualities and insisting that
the law must be couched only in terms of primary qualities, and
appealing to certain thematic presuppositions, e.g. simplicity, while justifying his
choice of a hypothesis or law.
The new science Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) was involved in developing was con-
fronted with many methodological, epistemological and metaphysical issues. He says:
My purpose is to set forth a very new science dealing with a very ancient subject. There is, in
nature, perhaps nothing older than motion, concerning which the books written by philosophers
are neither few nor small; nevertheless I have discovered by experienza some properties of it
which are worth knowing and which have hitherto not been either observed nor demonstrated.
Some superficial observations have been made, as, for instance, that the free motion [natu-
ralem motum] of a heavy falling body is continuously accelerated; but to just what extent this
acceleration occurs has not yet been announced . . . (Italics mine)
In relationship with Galileos scientific claim contained in the last sentence in the
quote there are several cognitive/epistemological questions How do we know?, Why
do we believe in something?, What is the evidence for?, How did Galileo develop
the scientific concepts?, How did he go on to justify the introduction of a concept
? Another set of partly scientific, partly sociological problems arises with regard the
validation and acceptance of scientific theories. Moreover, there are the metaphysical
problems concerning reality of entities that transcend our senses or the assumption
of certain properties that can form the basis for doing science, e.g. in Galileos case, the
primary qualities.
Understanding what Galileo contributed goes much beyond the law of freely falling
motion and the concept of uniformly accelerated motion he formulated or being able to
calculate how fast the stone falls when we drop it from a certain height. Understanding
the ingredients of his scientific inquiry and imagination must form an integral part,
not as additional material to the calculation, but as issues intrinsically arising out of
the understanding and presentation of the technical material in order to develop the
capacity for abstract reasoning based on practice and experience, problems relating
to relevant concept formation, modes of appropriate reasoning/thinking, perceiving
relationships. This effort may include removing certain misconceptions.
From this point of view Galileos main achievements were
welding together the works of the anti-Aristotelians of the past two centuries
or so and develop a Philosophy of Science by raising certain methodological
issues.
presenting a consistent, reasonable conceptual scheme that was descriptive rather
than teleological, i.e. he was not concerned with final causes.
160 Science Pedagogy through Cognitive Science
3.4.1 The Methodological Issues Raised by Galileo
Galileos concern with the fit between an abstract mathematical theory and its ap-
parently arbitrary definitions and facts that they are designed to explain. He asks
the question: How does an abstract mathematical theory and its apparently arbitrary
definitions fit the facts? Fruitful insight as to what was Galileos answer can be derived
from what Galileo himself emphasizes in his approach:
Galileo was acutely conscious about the fact that he was defining new concepts
and not discovering objects. He was concerned that the definition should best fit the
natural phenomena. In the Discourses and Mathematical Demonstrations Concerning
Two New Sciences he says:
Since all definitions are arbitrary, I may . . . be allowed to doubt whether such a definition as
above, established in an abstract manner, correspond to and describe that kind of accelerated
motion which we meet in the nature in the case of freely falling bodies.
. . . some have imagined helices and conchoids as described by certain motions which are not
met within nature and have very commendably established the properties which these curves
possess in virtue of their definitions, but we have decided to consider the phenomena of bodies
falling with an acceleration such as actually occurs in nature and to make this definition of
accelerated motion exhibit the essential features of observed accelerated motions.
Galileo formulates his hypotheses regarding the nature of motion first and then
goes on check them in terms of experiments and not the other way around.
3.4.3 Conclusion
A review of the second debate, the survey of the recent work on concept formation in
Cognitive Science and the Case Study of Galileo provide evidence that go on to show
that the information about the way the world is and theorizing about it may lead to
objective claims regarding the world provided the processes of the formation of concepts
involve an account of (a) the interaction between the features of the physical world and
the cognizer, and (b) the information about the features of the world is represented and
revised in a frameworks which also includes the sub-symbolic level.
Galileos answer to the problem was based on (i) his belief in one of the Thematic
Presuppositions, viz., simplicity of nature, (ii) his classification of properties in terms of
primary (quantifiable) and secondary qualities, and his demand that scientific concepts
are articulated in terms of primary qualities alone, and (iii) his abandonment of the
secondary qualities as well as teleological explanations.
162 Science Pedagogy through Cognitive Science
3.5 Final Remarks on the Implications of the Case Studies for Science Education
Programme
The Case Studies on Galileo that I have chosen may appear to be antiquirian. This
is deliberate. Galileos scientific writings and scientific work are instructive in more
sense than one. It provides a rich context for many important pedagogical issue, such
as introduction and proper understanding of new concepts, distinction between obser-
vation and inference, model building and mathematical representation, formulation of
hypothesis, laws and their linkages to observation and thematic presuppositions, the
question of justification, etc. The standard textbook presentation of Galileos kine-
matics suppresses the intellectual history, the context and the process of scientific
inquiry by hurrying through the final product in the form of the laws he formulated.
As a result it fails to use this significant episode at an early stage of science with
relatively simple subject matter as an illustration of various facets of modern scientific
thought and inquiry. Our science pedagogy would be immensely richer by incorporating
an examination of such intellectual dimensions and putting a little less emphasis on
technical science.
Pedagogy of science ostensibly enables the students to also learn strategies and
tactics of problem solving and generating representations of scientific knowledge. The
Received View on the cognitive processes involved in such procedures, such as induction
or linear conception of experimental discovery, appears to be highly deficient (Nerses-
sian, 1989 and Gooding, 1989). The Cognitive-historical and generative justification
approaches discussed above in the case studies can provide different realistic exem-
plars of scientific problem solving. Thus, the standard laboratory experience can be
supplemented by incorporating such exemplars, which will give students an opportu-
nity to examine other problem solving procedures or to develop their own insights into
constructing or changing representations of conceptual structures in science.
Conceptual Change in the Learning of Science
Stella Vosniadou
University of Athens, Greece. Email: svosniad@compulink.gr
Mathematics edited by J.D. Novak (1987) and Helm, Hugh and Novak (1983).
164 Conceptual Change in the Learning of Science
In this framework there is no realization that childrens initial knowledge, based
on their every day experiences may stand in the way of understanding the currently
accepted scientific ideas. The conceptual change approach to be described below is a
very different approach. More specifically, the following claims are being made about
the process of learning science.
iii. Conceptual change is required in the learning of many science concepts (and
not only science). This is because the initial explanations of phenomena in the
physical world are not unrelated and fragmented but are organized in an intuitive
framework theory.2 That constrains the process of acquiring further knowledge
about the physical world and can cause misconceptions. Many misconceptions
can be explained as synthetic models formed by individuals in their effort to
assimilate new scientific information into their framework theory. The change
of the framework theory is difficult because it represents a coherent explanatory
system based on everyday experience and is tied to years of confirmation.
From a conceptual change point of view the questions that are important to answer
are questions such as the following: What is the nature of initial conceptual structures?
Are they actually organized in a coherent theoretical framework? If so, how do these
theoretical frameworks change? How is conceptual change achieved?
In the pages that follow I will argue that children do have an initial, intuitive,
framework theory about the physical world. I will argue that this theory has content.
I will describe this content in terms of presuppositions, beliefs, and mental models. I
will also argue that this framework theory has a structure and I would describe this
structure in terms of framework theories and specific theories. Another issue I would
2 The term theory is used to denote a causal explanatory framework. We do not claim that framework
theories are similar to those of scientists and we further assume that they are not available to conscious
awareness and hypothesis testing.
Vosniadou 165
like to raise here is the issue of metaconceptual awareness. It appears that young
children have conceptual structures that are relatively well organized but they are not
metaconceptually aware of the knowledge that they have. By that I mean that they
are not aware of the actual beliefs and presuppositions that constrain the knowledge
acquisition process, neither do they recognize that these beliefs are hypotheses subject
to falsification. This is a very important difference between childrens theories (to
the extend that we can call them theories) and scientific theories. When we come to
conceptual change, I will tell you about synthetic models and what they are. Finally, I
will pay a lot of importance to the sequence in which concepts are acquired in a given
subject-matter area.
Scientific Model
Sphere
Flattened Sphere
Synthetic
Hollow Sphere Models
(a) (b)
Dual Earth
Disc Earth
Initial
Models
Rectangular Earth
References
diSessa, A.: 1993, Toward an epistemology of physics, Cognition and Instruction
10, 105225.
Driver, R. and Easley, J.: 1978, Pupils and Paradigms: A Review of literature related to
concept development in adolescent science students, Studies in Science Education
5, 6184.
172 Conceptual Change in the Learning of Science
Helm, H. and Novak, J.: 1983, Proceedings of the International Seminar: Misconcep-
tions in Science and Mathematics, Department of Education, Cornell University,
Ithaca, New York.
Novak, J.: 1977, An Alternative to Piagetian Psychology for Science and Mathematics
Education, Science Education 61, 453477.
Novak, J.: 1987, Proceedings of the Second International Seminar: Misconceptions
and Educational Strategies and Mathematics, Vol. II, Department of Education,
Cornell University, Ithaca, New York.
Samarapungavan, A. Vosniadou, S. and Brewer, W.: 1996, Thinking about the earth,
the sun and the moon: Indian Childrens Cosmologies, Cognitive Development
11, 491521.
Vosniadou, S.: 1994, Capturing and Modeling the Process of Conceptual Change,
Learning and Instruction 4, 4569.
Vosniadou, S.: 1998, From Conceptual Development to Science Education: A Psycholog-
ical Point of View, International Journal of Science Education 20(10), 12131230.
Vosniadou, S. and Brewer, W.: 1992, Mental Models of the Earth: A Study of Conceptual
Change in Childhood, Cognitive Psychology 24, 535585.
Vosniadou, S. and Brewer, W.: 1994, Mental Models of the Day/Night Cycle, Cognitive
Science 18, 123124.
inputnagarjun2.tex
Introducing History of Science in Science Education: A Perspective
from Chemical Education
Prajit K. Basu
University of Hyderabad, Hyderabad, India. Email: pkbsh@uohyd.ernet.in
In this paper I argue that it is as yet unclear whether history of science can play a
role in science education. I argue that whether history of science may or may not be
relevant for science education is a complex question and does not lend itself to an easy
answer. It is also an empirical issue whether history of science is effective in science
education. I also point out that there are certain reasons to think that one cannot use
history of science across the board to enhance science education.
What I am going to do is to first quickly enumerate the questions that arise in the
context of science education. One of them is that science education is an umbrella term
which means it is quite ambiguous and it needs to be sorted out. For my own edification
I have sorted it out for myself and I show that delineating various meanings of science
education tends to show that the role of history of science in science education should
be questioned even more threadbare. Next, I look at the general argument that history
and philosophy of science play an important role in science education. Again, I try
to show that the argument is not very straight forward, and we do not have really
a knocked down argument in favour of the claim that history of science can play a
significant role in science education. Thirdly, I look at certain concepts in chemistry and
explore whether history and philosophy of science can play any role in the instruction
of those concepts in the classroom situation.
I shall dispose of the first aim with some preliminary remarks since I wish to
enquire the role of history of chemistry/science in achieving the other two aims at this
6 Kuhn, T. S.: 1977, The Essential Tension: Tradition and Innovation in Scientific Research, in his The
It may be seen from the above list that there is not much emphasis in terms of
the objectives which require introducing lessons in terms of introducing STS. There is
something in the 4th point which is aimed at achieving an awareness of the profound
and far reaching consequences of uses and abuses of the science. Otherwise the
list underscores that there is or should be some attempt to introduce what may be
called the nature and method of science. There is an attempt to show the continuity
of growth of science and there by alerting them to science being a historical process.
Then the 6th one is interesting in that it takes that chemical education should attempt
to generate a liking for science and that is where the ideology for science education
comes in. The 7th point says that chemical education should develop the facility for
critical and unbiased observation. I am not sure what kind of unbiased observation
one will generate in chemical contexts. It is an aim which may be unattainable unless
an account of unacceptable biasedness is spelt out, argued for, and already in place.
I now take up the last list which is much more extensive and hence is more illumi-
nating. This list is prepared from the information sought from the research chemists
in USA.11 I first enumerate the list before taking up some of these in the rest of my
paper.
10 Idem.
11 Billing, D. E., Private Communication, referred in footnote 9 above, p. 52.
180 Chemical Education
1. To develop and sustain an interest in science and in chemistry as a central,
supporting and challenging area of study
2. To develop a working knowledge of, and favourable attitude towards, scientific
methods of investigation, using chemistry as an example
3. To encourage the exercise of curiosity and creative imagination, and an apprecia-
tion of the role of such speculation in the selection and solution of problems, the
construction of hypotheses, and the design of experiments
4. To develop the ability to see, and the habit of looking for, inter-relationships
between individual phenomena, principles, theories, philosophies or problems
5. To develop an appreciation of scientific criteria and a concern for objectivity and
precision
6. To develop an understanding of the fundamental and unifying principles under-
lying the behaviour of atoms, ions and molecules, and an ability to apply these
principles to real problems involving materials in various physical and biological
conditions
7. To develop the skills, knowledge and habits required for the safe, efficient and
thoughtful manipulation of chemicals and apparatus in common laboratory pro-
cedures
8. To develop confidence and skill in the quantitative formulation of problems and
in the treatment of data
9. To develop in the student the ability and predisposition to think logically, to
communicate clearly by written and oral means, and to read critically and with
understanding
10. To promote the students understanding of science, technology, economic and so-
ciological factors in modern society, and of the contributions they can make to
improve material conditions and to widen mans imaginative horizons and his
understanding of the universe
11. To encourage the applications of chemical knowledge and skills to problems which
are of importance to the community, in particular the optimum use of natural
resources
12. To provide an opportunity for the development of the students motivation and
social maturity, including an appreciation of his own limitations in relation to a
career choice which will be fruitful to himself and to society
13. To develop the students understanding of the structure, values and procedures of
chemical industry, and the chemists professional role in such a situation
Basu 181
14. To develop a knowledge of, and familiarity with the use of, important sources of
chemical information
15. To make the student aware of the limitations of his disciplines and their methods
and to provide opportunities for him to understand, make and criticize value
judgements
16. To cope with individual differences in the abilities and interests of students,
so as to ensure the optimum development of each students potentialities for
achievement and satisfaction and
17. To draw upon staff interests and expertise in such ways that the teaching is
challenging and satisfying
This extensive list brings out some of the aims of chemistry courses and it is possible
to see that the list tries to achieve a range of expertise for chemistry learners. There are
efforts to introduce students to aspects of philosophy of science, the idea(s) of method
in science in general and in chemistry in particular. The interdisciplinary nature of
chemistry is another objective that is supposed to be achieved through chemistry in-
struction. There are a few which underscore the relations between science, technology,
and society. The last two are more close to the problems of day to day learning of
teaching chemistry. One interesting aim included in the list is that the students must
be able to understand the limitations of science in solving a wide ranging problems and
make value judgements. I think that goal is quite laudable although hardly satisfied
by any course in chemistry.
I wish to start with the first aim in the list above. It claims that one of the goals
of courses in chemistry should be to develop and sustain an interest in science and in
chemistry as a central, supporting and challenging area of study. There have often
been complaints that chemical education has fostered memorization of facts and very
many of them at that. As a result chemistry courses have been rather boring and have
driven good students away from chemistry. While responding to this challenge, various
curricula reforms were brought about in all areas of science including chemistry. The
courses developed by CHEM study, in USA, Nuffield Foundation, in UK, and the Scot-
tish Education Department, in UK, were intended to improve learning through science.
There were much more emphasis on understanding the principles of chemistry and less
emphasis on remembering facts. However, chemists began to complain soon that the
students continue to have poor understanding of chemistry. An interesting and pio-
neering article by R. J. Gillespie,12 written in 1977, and quoted somewhat approvingly
by M. Chastrette and C. N. R. Rao,13 in 1992, emphasized that chemistry training
requires remembering facts. Otherwise, there would be embarrassing response from
students, like Silver Chloride (AgCl) is a green liquid. More substantively, Gillespie
argues that, the principles that are taught in introductory courses are not a part of
12 Gillespie,
R. J.: 1977, IUPAC International Newsletter on Chemical Education, (6)
13 Chastrette,M., and Rao, C. N. R.: 1992, New Trends in Chemistry Teaching: An Overview Giving
Examples of Innovative Projects, New Trends in Chemistry Teaching, The UNESCO Press, Paris, VI, 9-14.
182 Chemical Education
chemistry.14 Thermodynamics, Kinetic Theory, and Quantum mechanics are areas of
physics that have proved particularly useful in chemistry. These theories are useful
since these explain chemical facts and help understand the phenomena in chemistry.
This raises the question: What is chemistry? I now deal with this question briefly
before I get on with my task to look at the aims of chemistry and whether history of
chemistry/science can fulfil these aims.
It has been argued that chemistry is a central science.15 Now it is unclear in
what sense is it a central science. The notion of centrality has been viewed in more
than one way by chemists and scholars. Chemistry may be taken to be conceptually
central because it is conceptually networked with a variety of other disciplines. Often
chemistry is viewed this way because of its strong links with physics and biology. This,
however, does not mean that chemistry is foundationally central. In fact the present
wisdom is that (most of) chemistry is, in principle, reducible to physics. Yet another
kind of centrality is possible. It has been argued that chemical change, or lack of it,
is so much a part of everything with which we come in contact and everything we do,
it is in a very real sense the central science. Besides this what are the interesting
features of chemistry? Gillespie argues that chemistry is the science of various forms
and their transformations. In other words, it is the science of properties and reactions
of substances. He claims that
The preparations of new substances and their study of properties is one of the main activities
of the chemist whether (s)he is an industrial chemist preparing new semiconductors or new
drugs or an academic chemist preparing new compounds simply to find out how a previously
unexplored combination of element behaves.16
I shall return to the issue of synthesis in the next section. The second list enu-
merated above subsumes the aims in the first list and is more akin to an elaboration
of items and 2 and 3 in the more extended third list. As mentioned above, when
we look at the list of aims mentioned against courses on Chemistry for Citizens, we
see that students are expected to internalize certain philosophical views about sci-
ence. This is supposed to be part of the result of a good chemical/science education.
A. J. Harrison points out quite appropriately that although research scientists think
navely that whatever they produce in the laboratory are ready for market, an array
14 Gillespie, R. J.: 1981, Chemistry: Fact or Fiction?, New Trends in Chemistry Teaching, The UNESCO
and the 18th Century Chemical Philosophers, Presented in Annual Australasian Association of History,
Philosophy, and Sociology of Science Meeting, Auckland.
Basu 185
resolution. The picture hence is not pretty. It does not help to introduce the historical
debate to clarify the distinction among the concepts. The history of chemistry here
is not much of help. This shows that if we want to bring to bear this 150 years of
debate into the classroom, no matter how much we want to impose on the history
it will not lead to a very pretty learning/instruction situation. It will rather be a
murky event for the teachers as well as for the students. The debate, however, will
be of enormous help for junior college or undergraduate college level students in a
different sense. It can show very clearly how scientists attempt to develop analytical
arguments to clarify the concepts they use. The sophisticated use of reasoning, appeal
to empirical observations relevant for the case in hand are examples which can help
train students to develop a critical and analytical inclination. But given that the above
chemical concepts are introduced at the 7th standard science curriculum, situation is
not conducive to introduce these philosophical and methodological intricacies.
I now come to another example which seems to resist introduction of history of
science by the very nature of the endeavour itself. It may be remembered that chemists
agree that synthesis of materials constitute an important aspect of chemistry. If chem-
ical synthesis is a part of chemical education, then one needs to ask whether it can
be historically packaged for teaching. The reasons for apprehension or question may
be because of the nature of the enterprise itself. Chemical synthesis, be it organic
or inorganic, in liquid state, gaseous state, or solid state, requires that materials of
certain kind are made to react to make a desired product. Of course, there are situa-
tions where scientists start a reaction without a specific product in mind. Historically
there have been various synthetic routes developed to arrive at a desired end. These
developments occurred through the application of specific knowledgethermodynamic,
reaction rates, stereochemistry or geometry of the starting materials or of product(s),
modes of interaction among the reactants. Yet these knowledge claims are in some
sense a reasonable guide at best. Their status is not that of a theory or a law explaining
or predicting phenomena. That much is obvious since failure of a synthesis process in
a new situation is not a serious evidence against these laws. I think that the logic of
the situation is somewhat different.
I am going to rely on Ian Hackings argument that experimenting or synthesising
is a kind of intervening.22 New phenomena or materials are created in laboratory
under carefully controlled conditions. Control of initial and boundary conditions (main-
tenance of relatively closed systems) is crucial to the emergence of the regularities
underlying various synthetic processes. However, this practical mediation makes the
practical application of the regularities problematic. The chemists design a synthetic
compound for it to perform a desired function. They want to be assured that the
compound will perform that function. But this can happen if the boundaries of the
system can be defined and fixed. But in a new synthesis that is rarely the case.
Now I want to begin to answer why that is so. If we remember that at times the
regularities arrived at or the laws cannot be expressed in a straight forward fashion
in terms of a universal generalization, then we realize that these statements of reg-
22 Hacking, I.: 1983 Representing and Intervening, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
186 Chemical Education
ularities may contain a ceteris paribus clause. These are like P is a Q,other things
being equal. The explanations and predictions using these laws are somewhat shaky.
This is because the condition, other things being equal, may not obtain. This is what is
underscored, in the case of synthesis, by pointing out that the boundaries of the system
are not defined and fixed. The real world is complex and hence the conditions involving
the occurrence of P may be complex enough not to let Q happen. There are two ways
of getting around this. One way is to modify the real world environment to the extent
that it mimics the environment of the laboratory with the defined boundary conditions
which result in the regularity of if P then Q. So, basically what we do is, if we have a
synthetic route and we want to apply it to a new context, then what we need to be able
to do is as simple as change and modify the context in such a way that we can run our
synthesis. The other is to mimic the environment of the world in the laboratory, which
means to be able to say that here we have a complex situation and we need to mimic
this in the context of our synthetic route.23 That may be an expensive affair since the
world would keep changing and mimicking these variations in the laboratory may not
be viable. So the option in this case is then to take the law of nature or the regularity
of the world and attempt to modify the world. This attempt to modify the world may
not always be possible and given that seldom it is one law of nature or regularity
that is involved in the synthetic procedure, the open ended nature of synthesis and
the lack of viability and efficacy of various laws or regularities in various situations
becomes apparent. This open ended nature of chemical synthesis is apparent when
you look at the synthesis of some of the recent materials specially the superconducting
materials like one, two, three super conductors (Y Ba2 Cu3 O7 ), and Bucky ball, the C-60
molecule. Although both are designer materials, the actual synthesis of which required
extraordinary manipulations of the environment, and was assisted by a certain degree
of chance. If the expectation is that these ideas of chemical synthesis may be introduced
historically in science instruction, and these ideas will help in conceptual learning of
students regarding the nature of synthesis, it is not clear how that will be possible.
In the context of actual instruction in chemical synthesis through history, it is unclear
whether the instruction will give the students the correct picture. This is because
even if we learn how a certain kind of compound can be transformed into another
kind of compound, the next time a student wants to make anything new, and chemical
synthesis is all about making something new, the old information is never enough.
One has to be much more innovative to realize that one has to keep changing the
environment of the world such that the new synthetic law or new synthetic regularities
can play out their role and it is here I claim that historical lessons might not be of help.
However, there are some methodological lessons that one can draw from discussing
the history of synthesis of chemical compounds. One of these is to make the students
realize that synthesis is an open ended endeavor and whenever it comes to employing
chemical synthesis ideas in a new context one needs to be able to control the world in
a new environment. These are some of the tips that one can give. Chemical synthesis
is something that is taught at 11th or 12th standard. And it is unclear whether at that
23 Latour, B.: 1987, Science in Action, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Basu 187
level history of chemical synthesis can be employed to help science instruction in this
area.
In general conclusion, I become a bit more provocative by pointing out that science
education has a very strong cultural aspect. I come to that conclusion to an extent due
to the fact that when you look at the way the colonial science was introduced into the
Indian context it was to train the natives in moral issues. For the British, natives
were immoral. For those natives the colonizers needed to teach certain kinds of science
like arithmetic or geography and not anything else.24 The understanding was that the
natives would become morally equipped having gone through the training. This is not
to blame the British as such. Because the British tried to do on a similar line something
to themselves. In the 19th century BAAS introduced chemical analysis as part of the
chemical curriculum so as to give students some kind of mental training so that they
become logical.25 Now, the idea of introducing chemical analysis is because one can
use that method of chemical analysis to introduce what might be called a hypothetico-
deductive mode of reasoning. So, if one has a hypothesis that sodium metal burns
with a yellow flame, then one can predict that a salt containing sodium atom will test
positive in a flame test. Now one can do a qualitative test. If the colour of the flame is
yellow, hypothesis is confirmed and if the colour is something else, then the hypothesis
is disconfirmed. Since scientific knowledge is acquired and justified by this method,
people at large will be better off using this method in their daily life since they can all
be scientific in their outlook. And a citizen who is scientific is an asset to a countrys
well being. Thus, mental training is a part of a larger game plan to have people with
superior ability. So what one has to realize is that science education has this kind of
game plan in some form or the other.
24 Kumar, K.: 1997, Political Ideology of Education, Sage Publications, New Delhi, 42.
25 Layton, D., Davey, A., and Jenkins, E. W.: 1986, Science for Specific Social Purposes (SSSP): Perspectives
on Adult Literacy, Studies in Science Education, 13, 27-52.
188 Chemical Education
Multicultural Mathematics, Anti-racist Mathematics: What can that
be?
At a Conservative party conference, the then British Prime Minister, Ms. Margaret
Thatcher said: Children who need to know how to count and multiply are being taught
anti-racist mathematics, whatever that be. The background to Prime Ministerial
outburst is quite interesting, and I would like to believe that I had a part in it. A
week earlier, I addressed a conference of mathematics teachers from inner city schools.
The inner cities are where you find some of the most deprived areas of Britain, and
where teaching could be quite difficult. These are concentrations of ethnic minority
populations, particularly people of Asian and Afro-Carribbean origins. And for some
reason they unusually decided to televise snippets of that talk, and particularly a
question that I was asked as to what I thought of multicultural mathematics. To tell
you the truth, my interest or knowlege of multicultural mathematics at that time was
still in its embryonic stage. I thought it was a good thing, and certainly if it was tied up
with history which had tended to neglect or devalue the contributions of large sections
of the world populations to the subject. I tried to bring in history into my classroom
teaching, both at the school level as well as at the university level. I remember once
being absolutely amazed by how students, reacted when I introduced Non-Euclidean
geometry using history. Groups of students who previously found it totally irrelevant,
probably half of them sleeping, suddenly woke up.
So we were trying at the conference to find out what would engage the school
children of the inner city schools. It was around the time that Nelson Mandela was
in the news. If I remember correctly, a musical jamboree had been organised in his
honour. So somebody then asked how, using South Africa as an example, would one
teach mathematics. So I suggested that one way may be to split up the class into three
groups, blacks, whites and coloureds according to the proportion in the three groups
in South Africa, divide the area of the classroom according to the share of the land
available to the three groups and get each group to stand in the area allocated to them.
The result was a huge concentration of students representing blacks in a relatively
small area with hardly much space for them to stand and a lot of room for the students
representing the whites. The coloured (consisting mainly of Indians and mixed race)
were mainly concentrated into towns since there were restrictions during the apartheid
on their owning land elsewhere. One of them asked me would this be anti-racist? So I
said we could call it anti-racist mathematics.
What I was trying to show there was that for mathematics to be relevant to most
people, it should engage with peoples preoccupations, with peoples concerns and in-
terests. It does not really matter what is the subject that you take up but you have to
make it sufficiently interesting for the students. For example, a group of youngsters
190 Multicultural Mathematics, Anti-racist Mathematics
Jund-i-Shapur
(Persia)
China
Toledo Cordoba
(Spain) (Spain)
Baghdad India
(Iraq)
Cairo
(Egypt)
Indian Brahmi
numerals, c. 300 BC
Indian Gwalior
numerals, c. AD 500
European apices,
c. 1000
European (Durer),
c. 1500
Figure 6: An Inca official holding the quipu. Inca abacus can be seen at the bottom
left.
9). Well worth showing children who are taken aback that boring numbers can be
represented by interesting and somewhat frightening facial representations. You could
have face numerals side by side with the bar and dots.
A question often asked is who is the earliest known woman mathematician? In
many histories of mathematics, the name of Hypatia crops up. But to provide some
alternative names, I would suggest Gargi, an early Indian woman astronomer and an
unknown mathematical scribe who is present in a Mayan representation (Figure 10).
Look at the person at the top right corner. How do you know that the person was a
mathematician? The Mayans had different way of representing mathematical scribes.
A common mode was to represent a human form with a mathematical document identi-
fied by dots and dashes (or Mayan numerals) under his/her armpit. It dates back to the
beginning of common era. It is interesting in that drawing that a deity is represented
as giving out the knowledge, coaxed by some of his human attendants. In the middle of
the illustration you see the knowledge being collected and being analyzed. The stone
196 Multicultural Mathematics, Anti-racist Mathematics
3 9 18 20
Long-count
introduction glyph
(glyph of the deity who
is patron of the
month Cumku on the
sacred calendar)
9 baktuns 17 katuns
9 x 18(20)3 = 17 x 18(20)2 =
1 296 000 days 122400 days
0 tuns 0 uinals
0 kins 13 Ahau
(day on the sacred
calendar reached by
counting forward the
total number of days
on the long-count calendar
from the starting point of
the Mayan calendar)
1 2 3 4
5 6 7 8
9 10 11 12
13 14 15 16
17 18 19 0
I have taken Morris Kline as an illustration. I could take examples from other
authors as well, including G.E.R. Lloyd. But Kline is sufficient. Now I think Klines
view is based on a complete misconception. How did this misconception arise? Partly
because of the way that one sees the sources of Indian mathematics. When we look
at Aryabhatas Aryabhatiya we have merely statements of results. Proofs are often
found in commentaries. If you study the Bhaskara-Is commentary on Aryabhatiya, it
provides both flesh to Arybhatas cryptic verses as well as demonstrations. Now the
Western tradition, probably following on Greek tradition, has in the same text both the
statement of results as well as the proofs. Commentaries do not serve the same function
as in Indian mathematics. Remember, this is a tendency that runs right through
Indian mathematics upto Srinivas Ramanujan. Ramanujans lost notebooks contain a
number of results which has provided lifes work to a number of mathematicians. That
did not mean that there were no proofs at all.
Proofs have different purposes:
Psychological: To convince the student. Success depends on notation, a way in
which an arguement is formulated, organised and presented.
Social and Cultural: Proofs are social and cultural artefacts. How a proof works,
depends on how its intended audience come prepared to follow it. For instance,
the claims made by proofs about mathematical objects are culturally determined.
For example, consider the difference between Euclidean vs Navajo (or Indigenous
Australian) view of space. How space is viewed is an important element in proof.
200 Multicultural Mathematics, Anti-racist Mathematics
Look at the Pythagorean theorem which is very familiar to everyone. This is taken
from Bhaskracharyas Bijaganita. The Figure asks that what is the hypotenuse of
a plane figure in which the side and the upright are equal to 15 and 20? Show the
Upapatti underlying the usual mode of computation. Then he goes on to say that you
have 2 different ways of demonstration.
One is the geometric demonstration for the people who have a strong visual sense and they
would be convinced by seeing and that is called Ksetragata. The other is the algebraic one. It
is important you show the right proof to the right people depending which is the one that they
understand best. The geometric is not shown to the algebraic and vice versa.
Joseph 201
N
M = 1 [P + I ] where I = 1P [12r]
N 2 12
And r (1+r)N P
M= (2) (MODERN)
(1+r)N - 1
WHEN IS M M?
rP (3)
Rewrite (2) as M=
1
1-
(1 + r)N
1
Expand as a power series and retain first three terms
(1 + r)N
1 1 - Nr + 1 (N + 1)Nr2 (4)
(1 + r)N 2
1 (6)
For small q (0 < q < 0.5), 1+q
1-q
References
Joseph, G.: 2000, The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics, 2nd
edn, Princeton University Press.
Nelson, D. Joseph G.G., W. J.: 1993, Multicultural Mathematics, Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
Infinite Series across Three Cultures: Background and Motivation
The subject of the essay is infinite series across cultures, I will concentrate mainly on
the non-mathematical aspects relating to it.
Two powerful tools contributed to the creation of modern mathematics in the seven-
teenth century: the discovery of the general algorithms of calculus and the development
and application of infinite series techniques. Many of you have been introduced to cal-
culus, (i.e., the general algorithms of calculus consisting of differentiation, integration
and other techniques) and probably know that the names normally associated with
the development of that stream are Newton and Leibniz. The other stream was the
discovery and applications of infinite series and again the European names that are
associated with it are Mercator, Wallis, Gregory, Newton and Leibniz (Figure 1). These
two streams of discovery reinforced each other in their simultaneous development
because each served to extend the range of application of the other.
However, what is less known is that the origin of the analysis and derivations of
certain infinite series, notably those relating to the arctangent, sine and cosine, was not
in Europe, but an area in South India which now falls within the state of Kerala. From
a region covering less than a thousand square kilometres north of Cochin and during
the period between the fourteenth and sixteenth century, there emerged discoveries in
infinite series that predate similar work of Gregory, Newton and Liebniz by at least
200 years.
There are a number of questions worth asking about the activities of this group of
mathematicians/astronomers (from now on referred to as the Kerala School) apart from
technical ones relating to the mathematical content of their work. In this talk I will
consider specific questions relating to the social landscape in which the Kerala School
developed, the mathematical motivation underlying their interest in a particular se-
ries, the arctan series (and its special case, the pi series). To provide a cross-cultural
context, I will compare the Kerala work with those in China during the eighteenth
century and only briefly mention the European work of the seventh century since it
has had adequate exposure in the literature.
Let us begin with a brief introduction to the chronology, the actors and subject mat-
ter of Indian mathematics (Figure 2). Some of the earliest texts in Indian mathematics
were the Sulbasutras. These were essentially manuals for surveyors containing in-
structions constructing sacrificial altars (vedi) and locating sacred fires (agni) that had
to conform to certain shapes and measurements if they were to be effective instruments
of sacrifice. In trying to construct a circular altar equal to the area of a square altar, the
sulbkaras (i.e., the authors of these manuals of which three were important, namely
Baudhyana, Apastamba and Katyayana) came across the problem of what we would
now describe as the incommensurability of pi. And in constructing a square altar
204 Infinite Series
General Algorithms of
Calculus
CREATION OF MODERN
MATHEMATICS (17th C)
1700
1350
Madhava (1340 - 1425)
1300
-1500
Satapatha Brahmana
Baudhayana Sulbasutras
-1000 Vedic Period
Apastamba
-500
Year Jaina and Buddhist Period Sthananga Sutra
0 Bakhshali Manuscript
Aryabhata Aryabhatiya
Brahmagupta Brahmasphutasiddhanta
500 "Classical" Period Bhaskara I Aryabhatiyabhasya
Mahavira Ganitasarasamgraha
Bhaskara II Lilavati
1000
Madhava
1500 Kerala Period Nilakantha Tantrasamgraha
Jyesthedeva Yuktibhasa
There are a couple of interesting features about the Yuktibhasa. First, its most reli-
able version is in Malayalam and not Sanskrit. This is an important point since prac-
tically all major texts on Indian mathematics or astronomy were written in Sanskrit.
Second, there is no translation in English of the text available yet. This is unfortunate,
but the reason is simple. We require someone with an unusual combination of skills
to produce a good translation: someone conversant with old Malayalam (very different
from the present Malayalam), someone with knowledge of technical Sanskrit, some one
with a reasonable knowledge of mathematics and preferably astronomy and someone
who possesses what I would describe as mathematical imagination. I would like to
take this opportunity to pay tribute to Professor K.V. Sarma, who has a good modicum
of all these skills and who has over the last forty years with a single-minded devotion
and hard work brought to us the treasures of Kerala mathematics and astronomy.
Whenever I present seminars in different places and different continents on Kerala
mathematics, I am asked is there any Yuktibhasa available for them to read, and I say
they have to know Malayalam since there was a modern Malayalam translation fifty
years ago!
If the quotation of Jyesthadeva is put in modern notation, it becomes quite straight
forward. I will not go into the technical mathematics of this expression. But what we
have here is the well known arctan series, usually known as the Gregory series named
after James Gregory, a Scottish mathematician, who studied the series in 1671. In my
book, The Crest of the Peacock, I have argued that it should be called the Madhava-
Gregory series, since it has been attributed by a number of members of the Kerala
School to their founder, which would then predate its first appearance with a detailed
derivation three hundred years before Gregory.
There is another aspect to the Yuktibhasa which is interesting. As the very name
Joseph 207
-3000
Harappan Period Babylonian and Egyptian
Mathematics
-1500
Vedic Period "Chou Pei" - Earliest Chinese Text
-1000 Sulbasutras
Rise of Greek Mathematics
-500 Euclid's Elements
Jaina and Buddhist Rise of Chinese Mathematics
Year
Period Chinese "9 Chapters"
0 Rise of Mayan Mathematics
500
"Classical" Period Rise of Arab Mathematics
1000 Al-Khwarizmi's "Algebra"
Inca Quipu
Kerala Period
1500 Rise of European Mathematics
Certain historians of mathematics (such as Kay and Morris Kline) have argued that
the Indians were not aware of the fact that could never be exactly determined. I see
this confusion arising in the minds of these historians because of the mistranslation of
the word Asana as approximate or rough inaccurate value as in the quotation. The
word is more subtle term than that. What it conveys is the notion of unattainability.
Unattainable is something that one can never reach. Unless one understands this
one can not understand the interest of the Kerala School in this quotation.
Joseph 209
What it shows is that Nilakantha and others understood the irrational nature of .
So the question is what did they do as a result? The following passage from Sankara
and Narayanas Kriyakramakari suggests a strategy:.
Thus even by computing the results progressively, it is impossible theoretically to come to a
final value. So, one has to stop computation at that stage of accuracy that one wants and take
the final result arrived at by ignoring the previous results.
Indian mathematicians were not generally preoccupied with the philosophical im-
plications of numbers as mathematical objects. Faced with irrationality, they tried to
arrive at as accurate an estimate as possible. And this is what is being suggested in
Kriyakramakari.
However, in applying the infinite series approach to estimate the circumference,
the Kerala mathematicians came across a serious difficulty. The problem is that the
Madhava-Leibniz series converges very very slowly. For example, summing the first 19
terms on the right hand side of: /4 = 1 1/3 + 1/5 . . . would give a highly inaccurate
estimate of as 3.194.
210 Infinite Series
Figure 7: Teacher-student lineage in the Kerala school. (The names underlined are
generally recognised as the major figures of the Kerala School.)
The problem was tackled in two directions: (a) rational approximations by applying
corrections to partial sums of the series; and (b) obtaining more rapidly converging
series by transforming the original series. There was considerable work in both direc-
tions as shown in detail in Yuktibhasa and Kriyakramakari. As an illustration of (a)
from the Yuktibhasa, consider the incorporation of the following correction term to the
Madhava-Leibniz series: Fc (n) = (n2 + 1)/(4n3 + 5n) where n is the number of terms on
the right hand side. Applying this correction where n = 11 , the implicit estimate of
is 3.1415926529 which is correct to 8 places. And this interest in increasing the accuracy
of the estimate continued for a long time, so that as late as the nineteenth century the
author of Sadratnamala estimated the circumference of a circle of diameter 10 18 as:
314, 159, 265, 358, 979, 324 correct to 17 places! What the work exhibits is a measure of
understanding of the concept of convergence, of the notion of rapidity of convergence
and an awareness that convergence can be speeded up by transformations. Similar
work was found in modern mathematics only as late as the end of the 18th century.
Incidentally, there was a whole range of other achievements of the Kerala School in
mathematics and astronomy which I will not discuss here, except to mention that using
very similar approaches they derived the Sine series, Cosine series and something that
I think is of interest to mathematicians in general, the Taylor series. So the ubiquitous
Taylor series was already known in India about two hundred and fifty years before it
entered modern mathematics.
To understand the context in which the mathematics developed, there is a need to
take a broad look at the social landscape of medieval Kerala society and seek answers
to the following questions:
What was the nature of the social structure of medieval Kerala?
What was the pivotal role of the Kerala temple?
How was scientfic knowledge acquired and disseminated in medieval Kerala?
Each of these questions could well provide enough subject matter for another essay.
Let me very briefly bring out a few points. When I initially started research on this
subject, I thought I found a fairly plausible explanation for the genesis of mathematics
and astronomy in this geographically remote part of India. In a way, why I found re-
search in this area very interesting was because it upset a whole lot of preconceptions,
including some of my earlier conjectures.
Joseph 211
Yet this brave attempt at building a pedagogic bridge between two mathematical
traditions was a failure. The Treatise did not gain acceptance in any Indian school and
while there is the intriguing suggestion by Mary Boole, the widow of the renowned
algebraist, George Boole, that English students were being taught to solve problems
in maxima and minima by other simple devices similar in essence to Ramchandras
and probably superior in efficiency, the interest petered out there as well. The book
was reviewed poorly in India when it was first published though it picked up well after
De Morgans endorsementa characteristic common to many other Indian endeavours
which gain in value only after Western endorsement.
There is also another intriguing connection, which I will merely mention for you
to ponder, and that is between Kerala mathematics and Ramanujan. Here the idea
is that if one looks at some of the early works of Ramanujan (i.e., before he went to
England), these are a few problems that involved the series which he published in
an Indian mathematics journal. Some of these remind us of the Kerala work. This is
just a conjecture but it is worth pursuing. Remember that Ramanujan came from the
Iyengar Brahmin caste. The Iyengars are found right across what we would call Kerala
(although it was not part of Kerala but of the Madras Presidency at that time) and
Tamil Nadu. Ramanujans mother was, according to contemporary accounts, a well-
known local jyotish. She practised her arts not only in individual homes but in local
temples as well. A jyotish is usually well versed in calculation techniques. So instead of
treating Ramanujan as a freak, consider his background, including the possibility that
he may have been doing ethnomathematics which combined his natural ability with
what he learnt from the two English texts to form the basis of his remarkable work
later. Now there are cases of Iyengars and Nambuthris particularly around the areas
of northern Kerala, mixing together within the temple. The temple was, as I mentioned
earlier, an important centre for dissemination of knowledge.
We can extend our speculation further: Kerala mathematics travelling West. Two
connections I want to bring to you. One connection is through the Arabs and their links
with Kerala. Now, we know that the works of al-Haytham, the great Arab scientist,
particularly on geometric series, were known in some of the Madrassas in Kerala. So,
was it possible, that through the medium of the Arabs that some of the mathematics
Joseph 217
and astronomy of the Kerala School went west? But, more important connection was
the possible role of the Jesuits. There is evidence that Matteo Ricci on his way to
China spent some time in Cochin. In fact for a number of Jesuits who followed him,
Cochin was a staging post on the way to the China. As I mentioned earlier, the Jesuits
of that time were not merely priests but also scholars, very knowledgeable in science
and mathematics. In fact, if one wanted to be trained as a mathematician in Italy
at that time, we couldnt do better than go to a Jesuit school. A number of reports
that the Jesuits sent from India and China to their headquarters in Rome contained
appendices of a technical nature which were then passed on by Rome to those who
understood them, including the notable Italian mathematicians of those days such as
Cavalieri and Cardona and others. We require to follow this link closely, for at the
moment there is only circumstantial evidence. It is gratifying that research in this
area is starting. Finally, what about Kerala mathematics and China, any possible
links? The more I look at the works of Ming Antu and his associates, the more I see
some distinct resonance between their work and Kerala work. Again, the question is:
Did some of the information go to China through the medium of Jesuits? An intriguing
question!
In conclusion, I would like to emphasize the need to rewrite the history of Indian
mathematics as it is presented in many historical texts. The new history should reflect
some of the more recent work done by the Indian scholars, people such as Gupta,
Shukla, Kuppana Sastri, Sarma, and Bag to mention a few. The excessive dependence
on work done during the last century as sources of information should surely decrease.
Otherwise, there is a danger of the same mistakes being repeated ad infinitum. And of
course, the medieval phase of Indian mathematics needs to be highlighted particularly
since it was crucial to the development of modern mathematics. Victor Katzs book is
one beacon of hope in that direction.
References
Edwards, C.: 1979, The Historical Development of the Calculus, Springer-Verlag, New
York.
Gurukkal, R.: 1992, The Kerala Temple and Early Medieval Agrarian System, Vallathol
Vidyapeetham, Sukapuram.
Hayashi, T. Kusuba, T. and Yano, M.: 1990, The Correction of the Madhava Series for
the Circumference of a Circle, Centaurus 33, 149174.
Jami, C.: 1988, Western Influence and Chinese Tradition in an Eighteenth Century
Chinese Mathematical Work, Historia Mathematica 15, 311331.
Joseph, G.: 2000, The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics, 2nd
edn, Princeton University Press.
Marar, K. and Rajagopal, C.: 1944, On the Hindu Quadrature of the Circle, Journal of
the Bombay Branch of the Royal Asiatic Society 20, 6582.
218 Infinite Series
Rajagopal, C. and Rangachari, M.: 1986, On Medieval Keralese Mathematics, Archive
for History of Exact Sciences 35, 9199.
Rajagopal, C. and T.V.V., A.: 1951, On the Hindu Proof of Gregorys Series, Scripta
Mathematica 17, 6574.
Rajagopal, C. and Venkataraman, A.: 1949, The Sine and Cosine Power Series in Hindu
Mathematics, Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society of Bengal 15, 113.
R.V., T. and Aiyar, A. (eds): 1948, Yuktibhasa Part I, Mangalodayam Ltd., Trichur.
Sarma, K.: 1991, A History of Kerala School of Hindu Astronomy, Vishveshavaranand
Institute, Hoshiarpur.
Sarma, K. and Hariharan, S.: 1991, Yuktibhasa of Jyesthadeva, Indian Journal of
History of Science 26, 186207.
Whish, C.: 1835, On the Hindu Quadrature and the Infinite Series of the Proportion of
the Circumference to the Diameter . . ., Transactions of the Royal Asiatic Society,
Great Britain and Ireland 3(part III), 509523.
Yan, L. and Shiran, D.: 1987, Chinese Mathematics: A Concise History, Clarendon
Press, Oxford.
How should Euclidean Geometry be Taught?
C. K. Raju
Centre for Studies in Civilizations, New Delhi, India. Email: c k raju@hotmail.com
Introduction
I grew up on the classical presentation of the Elements, as found in books like those
by Todhunter. It had one or two confusing points, but the work as a whole had a
certain persuasive charm and seductive beauty to it that still lingers with me. The
fascinating drawings of Japanese temple geometry1 are, to my mind, the best example
of something that today still evokes that sense of beauty. Some history is needed to
understand how geometry has reached the present state of ugliness and confusion in
the NCERT (National Centre for Education, Research and Training) texts (especially
the text for Class 9), and what should be done to correct it. Tracing the history also
helps to arrive at a clearer understanding of the Elements, needed for any corrective
process.
Winnipeg, Canada, 1989. I am indeed grateful to Prof. E. C. G. Sudarshan for presenting me with a copy of
this book.
2 T.L. Heath: 1956, The Thirteen Books of Euclids Elements, Dover Publications, New York, 1908, I, 75. It
should be pointed out that Heath has a curiously ambivalent attitude: while he prominently quotes the Haji
Khalfa at p. 75, to establish that Arabs had translated copies of the Elements, on p. 4 he asserts regarding
the apparently circumstantial accounts of Euclid given by Arabian authors that the origin of their stories
can be explained as the result of (1) the Arabian tendency to romance, and (2) . . . misunderstanding. He
goes on to assert (p. 4) that these accounts were intended to gratify a desire which the Arabians always
showed to connect famous Greeks in some way or the other with the East and cites (p. 4, note 6) the Haji
Khalfa to conclude that The same predilection made the Arabs describe Pythagoras as a pupil of the wise
Salomo, Hipparchus as an exponent of Chaldean philosophy or as the Chaldean, Archimedes as an Egyptian
etc. In short, Heaths attitude is to accept as true, from Arabic sources, whatever suits him, and to reject
everything else with some racist remarks.
220 Euclidean Geometry
It is necessary here to point out that translation usually meant rewriting the
book. This was particularly the case with the Elements, because the book apparently
never was entirely as elementary as it first seems. As recorded in the Fihrist, from
the earliest times of Heron of Alexandria, all commentaries and translations of the
Elements endeavoured to solve its difficulties, and explain the obscurities in Euclid. 3
Not the least of these obscurities concerns the name Euclid. The Arabs spoke of
Uclides, which they derived from Ucli, a key, and des, measure or particularly measure
of earth (= geo-metry), so that Uclides meant key to geometry.
Why was Uclides so important to Arabs? Why did so many key Arabic thinkers
rewrite Uclides? Why was Uclides a standard part of the curriculum of later Islamic
thinkers? The standard histories of geometry, being concerned almost exclusively with
the West, do not ever seem to have bothered to raise this question. The importance
of the question, in understanding the Elements, will become clear later on, when we
answer it.
Proclus himself acknowledges, (in the beginning of the quotation) that he is the first
person to mention Euclid, stating that Euclid is NOT mentioned by earlier historians of
geometry. So, is this quote from Proclus adequate to establish the historicity of Euclid
or the antiquity of the Elements? Imagine for a minute that we are dealing with Arab
tradition rather than Greek tradition, and apply to Greek tradition, the standards of
critical historiography that Heath applies to Arabs. What would be the conclusion?
If one is not a rank racist, the least one can do is to explore alternatives to the tra-
ditional belief in the historicity of Euclid and the antiquity of the Elements. Perhaps
Proclus simply misjudged the antiquity of the Elements, like later Arabs misjudged the
antiquity of Proclus works.
It is also possible that Proclus attributes authorship to Euclid in the same way as
later Arabic texts attributed various works, including the works of Proclus, to Aristo-
tleafter all attributions were not so terribly important either to the Neoplatonists
University Press, 56. Heath p. 1, and footnotes 2 and 3. Heath omits the first sentence. His footnote 2 asserts
that the word 0o must mean flourished and not was born, on the grounds that otherwise part of
Proclus argument [for the existence of Euclid] would lose its cogency.
6 Heath, 46; emphasis Heaths, de-emphasis mine.
222 Euclidean Geometry
or to the Islamic rational theologians, as they were to later-day European historians
of science, or as they are to current-day information capitalism, where ownership is
decided on attribution. Arabic treatises customarily began by taking the name of
Allah, and after that attributing everything to a famous early source. This custom
can still be observed in relatively remote places like the Lakshadweep islands where
it has survived. The custom of attributing everything to an early sourcethe earlier
the betterwas a form of homage, and added authority to the text; it was not meant
to be taken literally. Among Greeks, Pythagoreans followed this custom of attributing
everything to Pythagoras, and the continuity of Pythagoreans with Neoplatonism is
well known.
Christian mob. The magnificent temple of Dea Caelestis at Carthage remained open until c. 400; but many
laws were passed against pagan temples, and, in 401, the synod of Carthage twice asked the State to
implement these laws. Eventually, in 407 the Catholics forcibly took possession of Dea Caelestis and Bishop
Auerilus, Augustines lifelong friend, triumphantly planted his cathedra at the exact spot occupied by the
statue of the pagan goddess. H. Jedin and J. Dolan (eds) History of the Church, Vol. II, The Imperial Church
from Constantine to the Early Middle Ages, Tr. Anselm Biggs, Burns and Oates, London, 1980, p. 205.
8 Proclus, cited earlier, 45, p. 37.
9 Plato, Meno, 81-83.
Raju 223
Socrates then gave a practical demonstration of this by questioning a slave boy and
eliciting the right responses regarding geometry.)
For Proclus, then, mathematics was not a secular activity, but the key means of
propagating his fundamental religious beliefs. This is the concluding thought of part I
of his prologue:
This, then, is what learning (0 [mathesiz]) is, recollection of the eternal ideas in the
soul; and this is why the study that especially brings us the recollection of these ideas is called
the science concerned with learning ( 0 [mathematike]). Its name thus makes clear
what sort of function this science performs. It arouses our innate knowledge . . . takes away
the forgetfulness and ignorance [of our former existence] that we have from birth, . . . fills
everything with divine reason, moves our souls towards Nous, . . . and through the discovery of
pure Nous leads us to the blessed life.10
These religious beliefs were earlier championed within the Christian church by
Origen (also of Alexandria, and from the same school as Proclus). However, by Proclus
time, these religious beliefs (doctrine of pre-existence, equity) were exactly what were
being abusively opposed and cursed by the church and its key ideologues (Augustine,
Jerome, subsequently Justinian). It is well known that fundamental aspects of present-
day Christian religious dogma, such as resurrection (as opposed to pre-existence), eter-
nal (as opposed to temporary) heaven and hell, doctrine of sin (as opposed to essential
equity), etc., came about from the rejection of Origen and the acceptance of Augustine
during this period, starting from Constantine and ending with Justinian.
Therefore, Proclus, in writing on mathematics from the philosophical viewpoint,
was right in the eye of a religious storm, at its dead centre in Alexandria, and exposed
to great personal risk. Since Jerome had only just translated the Bible from Greek
into Latin, and Greek was still held in high regard in the Roman empire, inventing the
name Euclid, to give an early Greek legacy to his teachings would have been the most
natural strategy for Proclus.
If Euclid was indeed invented to escape from religious persecution, then it would,
have been entirely in keeping with the character of the Egypto-Greek Mysteries, if
the name Euclid had some mysterious significance, as the Arabs thought. Proclus
fears, incidentally, were quite genuine, for soon after him, the school at Alexandria was
permanently shut down, at about the time that Justinian cursed Origen of Alexandria.
Ancient Greece 1785-1985, Vintage. The use of the term racist, as distinct from Spenglers term Eurocentric,
refers also to the technology gap and the industrial revolution. See, M. Adas, Machines as the Measure of
Men: Science, Technology and Ideologies of Western Dominance, Oxford, New Delhi, 1990. While Bernal does
not say much about the history of science per se (and neither do his detractors in the more recent debate
in Isis), it is clear that the resurrection of Euclid, after the belated discovery that he could not have been
Euclid of Megara, is very much in line with the belief in a nineteenth century pattern of fabricating a Greek
origin for everything under the sun. A closer look at the material basis (palimpsets etc.) of the conclusions
of classical scholars will make clear the enormous amount of tinted speculation that underlies this belief.
13 The Hellenisation itself proceeded by reference to the military conquests of Alexander and Julius Caesar,
and the in-between period of Ptolemaic rule. Consequently the importance of these conquests got amplified
out of all proportion to their global or even local significance.
14 School Mathematics Study Group: Geometry: 1961, Yale University Press.
15 D. Hilbert: 1902, The Foundations of Geometry, Open Court, La Salle.
16 B. Russell: 1897, 1908, The Foundations of Geometry, London.
17 G. D. Birkhoff: 1932, A Set of Postulates for Plane Geometry (based on scale and protractor), Ann. Math.,
33.
Raju 225
a variety of obscurities in the Elements. The most obvious of these obscurities may be
put into the following classes.
History, Time and Truth: Essays in Honour of D.P. Chattopadhyaya, Kalki Prakash, New Delhi, 179-
193. Reprinted in Philosophy of Mathematics Education, 11, (1999). Available at http://www.ex.ac.uk/
PErnest/pome/art18.htm
226 Euclidean Geometry
of a non-real notion cannot avoid an infinite regress, for at no point can it terminate in
an ostensive definition.
Thus, Platonic philosophy, by its insistence that the ideal should be non-empirical,
eliminates both possibilities of an ostensive or a verbal definition, and the only option
left is that of current formalistic mathematics, which regards the notions of point, line,
etc., as meaningless, undefined notions. In other words, the current way of removing
the obscurities in the Elements is to adopt Russells definition of mathematics: Mathe-
matics may be defined as a subject in which we never know what we are talking about
. . .!19
In brief: if two sides and the included angle of one triangle are equal to those of
another triangle, then the two triangles are equal. We will refer to this as the Side-
Angle-Side proposition, or SAS for short.
19 The best that one can do is to interpret these meaningless notions using other meaningless notions like
the proof, see , C.K. Raju, Mathematics and Culture, cited earlier.
25 Ganita 6-9. Aryabhatiya of Aryabhata (Eds and Trs) K. S. Shukla and K. V. Sarma, INSA, New Delhi,
The subtle way in which Western historians have exploited the notion of proof
seems to have quite escaped the authors of the text. Western historians have read-
ily conceded that Babylonians, Egyptians, Chinese, Indians all knew earlier that the
Pythagorean theorem was true. They have maintained, however, that none of them
had a proof, hence none of them knew why it was true: they knew of the theorem
only as an empirical fact which they did not quite comprehend, much as an ass might
know the theorem without comprehending it. Comprehension, therefore, still dawned
with the Greeks. To refer to constructional methods as implicit proofs is to miss the
central issue clarified above: the motivation for synthetic geometry is that empirical
knowledge is not only distinct from mathematics but that it cannot logically precede
mathematics. Hence, if the second sentence in the above quote is true, then the very
notion of mathematical proof would need to be changed to accept empirical inputs.
Needless to say, the committee does not intend any such revolutionary challenge to
mathematical authority which is entirely beyond its terms of reference!
Therefore, on the third hand (surely committees have at least three hands!), the text
lapses back into the synthetic geometry recommended by the US School Mathematics
Study Group. Like a proper committee report, the resulting text has included a little
something to suit every taste. So the text introduces the SAS postulate [p. 162] as
the SAS (Side-Angle-Side) Congruence Axiom, where axiom is to be understood as
follows [p. 125]: basic facts which are taken for granted (without proofs) are called
axioms. Axioms are sometimes intuitively evident. That is, an axiom, like a fact,
belongs to the domain of empirical and physical, rather than the intuitively a priori
exactly the thing that was denied to motivate the SAS postulate and the notion of
congruence in the first place! One wonders why, unlike most other committee reports,
this report was not left to gather dust!
The natural casualty is the student who has to digest the whole thing, and so may be
put off geometry for the rest of his life, especially if he is clear-headed. If congruence is
explained through superposition (Heiberg Common Notion 4, or Theonine Axiom 8),
as the text does (pp. 159-161), one has clearly a metric approach. Within a metric
approach, it is trivial to prove the synthetic congruence results proved in the textin
fact there is then no need for a SAS congruence axiom, one has a SAS theorem, the way
it was proved in the original Elements. To now prove these results, in the manner of
synthetic geometry, on the ground that one is teaching the axiomatic method, is to teach
the axiomatic method as a completely mindless and elaborate ritual that one must
complete on the strength of the state authority that NCERT enjoys. What children
are being taught is not the sceptical attitude which underlies the need for a proof, but
mindless obedience to rituals which cannot be justified.
The hotchpotch geometry in the NCERT text for Class 9 is indigestible because it
has mixed up the Elements by mixing up elements that ought not to be taken together
like diazepam and alcoholunless the object is to induce a comatose state. To make
the text digestible, one needs to sort out which geometry one wants to teach: metric,
synthetic, or traditional. Even if one wants to teach all three they should be kept in
232 Euclidean Geometry
separate compartments: it is NOT a good idea to make the synthetic notion of congru-
ence more intuitive by defining it metrically as the NCERT text does! The authors need
to appreciate the incompatibility of the metric and synthetic approaches, and the way
these differ from the traditional approach, which incorporates an altogether different
notion of mathematical proof.28
Rejecting this attitude is not a trivial matter for all of current-day mathematics de-
pends upon the belief that mathematics is a priori and divorced from the empirical.
Nevertheless, the fact is that the Nayyayika notion of proof proceeds from a realistic
philosophical standpoint directly opposed to Platonic idealism. Classical Indian tradi-
tion saw no need to regard mathematics as something necessarily metaphysical, and
consequently, there was no need for two separate procedures of validation: (1) a notion
of mathematical proof, and (2) criteria (such as logical and empirical falsifiability) to
decide the validity of a physical theory. Therefore, though metric, traditional Indian
geometry does not need to proceed from Birkhoffs axioms. Against this background,
various other considerations are summarised in Table 1.
The second key point about the notion of proof concerns inference (anumana), about
which different schools of thought had mutually different ideas which differed also from
the idea of logical deduction underlying the current metamathematical definition of a
mathematical proof (which defines a proof as a sequence of statements each of which is
either an axiom or is derived from some preceding axioms by the use of modus ponens
or similar rules of reasoning). The Lokayata explicitly rejected inference, at least in
the metaphysical domain (which includes modern mathematics), allowing its use only
for practical purposes. The Buddhist and Jaina traditions pose an even more funda-
mental question: what should be the logic underlying proof? If one insists on regarding
mathematics as metaphysical, as in the current formalistic approach, then what is the
justification for the use of a 2-valued truth-functional logic underlying mathematical
proof? Clearly, the formalistic approach cannot possibly answer this questionthereby
showing that allegedly universal mathematical truths ultimately rest on a narrow
base of authority, localised in the West. Despite the authority, the belief is purely
a matter of cultural prejudice, for the seven-fold classification (saptabhanginaya) of
the Jaina syadvada of Bhadrabahu cannot be accommodated within 2-valued logic,
while the four-fold negation used by the Buddha, Nagarjuna, and Dinnaga cannot be
accommodated within a truth-functional framework. The logic of the empirical world,
by the way, may be similarly quasi truth-functional, for quantum mechanics permits
Schrodingers cat31 to be simultaneously both alive and dead, without permitting any
arbitrary statement to be deduced from this contradiction.
Note: S = set of points, L = set of lines (subsets of points), P = set of planes (subsets of points), d =
distance, m = measure of angles, B = Betweenness relation, = congrence for segments/angles.
1. If the state policy is that education is justified by its linkages to industrial or infor-
mation capitalism (it is needed by future engineers, technicians and scientists)
it is not so clear that it is imperative to teach the classical method of proof. We
must then consider what is increasingly likely to happen in the future: a computer
simulation for which there is no numerical analysis, and no convergence proof.
According to Hilberts ideas this would not count as mathematics. Nevertheless,
such computer simulations may be increasingly used as the basis of everyday deci-
sions: such as decisions about large financial investments. Briefly, if mathematics
is to be justified by its utility, then one should be teaching practical mathematics
rather than formal mathematics. In the case of geometry, this means that the
synthetic approach should be rejected in favour of the metric approach, and that
even with the metric approach, one could omit teaching proofs. It is true that this
might compromise understanding; but if education is justified by its utility, one
might as well explicitly accept that understanding is of lesser importance, for the
time thus saved could be used to teach some more useful things.
2. If the objective of education is to establish linkages to tradition, this tradition can-
not be arbitrarily selected. The Neoplatonic origin of the Elements seems to me
undeniable. On the other hand, Neoplatonism links naturally to Indian tradition
not only through Islam and the sufi-s, but also through direct contact, and strong
conceptual similarities to Advaita Vedanta. The links were physical, with some
250 ships sailing annually to carry out a huge trade with the Roman empire.
They were also philosophical: Augustine, born some 50 years after Porphyrys
death, records that Porphyry (the very same student of Plotinus, who recorded
the Enneads and commented on the Elements) searched for a universal way for
the liberation of the soul in the mores and disciplina of the Indi.33 Therefore,
it needs to be spelt out what state policy enables us to say that a certain sort
of tradition at a certain point of time should be regarded as more valuable than
another tradition at a different point of time. For example, should one reject the
33 John J. OMeara,: 1982, Indian Wisdom and Porphyrys Search for a Universal Way in: R. Baine Harris
Conclusions
1. Our current school texts in geometry must be corrected to distinguish clearly
between metric and synthetic geometry.
2. One must decide which geometry to teachmetric, synthetic, or traditionaland
stick to teaching that geometry. It is NOT a good idea to motivate synthetic con-
cepts like congruence by appealing to the intuitive physical idea of superposition
which underlies metric notions.
3. If traditional geometry is also to be taught, the texts must further separate it
from formal metric and synthetic geometry: it is NOT a good idea merely to
claim priority, as the present text does, for traditional geometry is fundamentally
different, since the traditional notion of proof differs fundamentally from the
current metamathematical notion of proof. One should first decide which method
of proof one wants to teach, and then develop a mathematics based on that method
of proof.
4. If the aim in teaching the Elements is to teach formal axiomatics, the authors of
texts should distinguish between meaningless formal axioms and empirical facts.
If this is too hard a thing for educators to do, then it is too hard for schoolchildren
to understand, and formal axiomatics ought NOT to be taught to schoolchildren.
238 Euclidean Geometry
5. The Elements have long been part of the theological curriculum because of their
philosophical significance, first for Neoplatonists (to arouse recollection of ones
true Self), then for Islamic rationalists (rational deduction from equity), and
finally for Christian rationalists (rational deduction). Our objective in teaching
the Elements must be formulated in awareness of this significance, as also an
awareness of Neoplatonic linkages to Indian traditions directly and via the sufi-s.
6. Our objectives must also recognize that no individual tradition can claim to be
the unique Indian tradition either as regards the matter of proof (pramana), or as
regards the tradition of geometry: the sulbasutra-s, the YuktiBhasa, and Uclides
are all part of Indian tradition. Tradition should not be reduced to ritual by
separating it from its original context of practical usefulness.
7. If we choose to teach geometry purely for its practical utility, then this practical
usefulness needs to be clearly thought out in the context of future needs, to protect
education from rapid obsolescence.
The Axiomatic Method: Its Origin and Purpose
S.D. Agashe
Indian Institute of Technology, Bombay, India. Email: eesdaia@ee.iitb.ac.in
Introduction
This is an informal introduction to a formal paper that was published about 12 years
ago and has been reprinted here. It is also a brief description of what Prof. Amitabha
Gupta and myself have been trying to do in our elective courses, History and Philoso-
phy of Science and Logic and Foundations of Mathematics at the Indian Institute of
Technology, Bombay, over the last 25 years or so.
After I encountered some problems in my understanding of physics and mathe-
matics, I was led to a study of history and philosophy of science and mathematics. I
was forced to do a critical examination of a lot of what I had learnt. As a student,
of course, I was not expected to critically examine what I was being taught. This,
unfortunately, may be true of students anywhere! In our courses, however, we made
students critically examine what they were taught as science and mathematics, rather
than dogmatize about scientific knowledge.
I was then led to critically examine axiomatization. In such matters, we think it
is best to go back to the Masters. So before reading Aristotle, Kant or Mill, I started
reading Euclids Elements. I would urge you to have a first-hand look at Euclids
Elements before reading the paper. I have also appended the contents of Books I and
II as given in Mueller, 1981.
The starting point for an understanding of axiomatization, it seems to me, is Propo-
sition 14 of Book II: to construct a square equal to a given rectilineal figure. Why
bother to do this? What is square and rectilineal figure? What does equal mean?
The way geometry was taught to me, equal meant equal in area. Had I been bold
enough at that time, I would have asked my teacher: What do you mean by equal in
area? What is area of a figure? Why should I accept the formula that the area of a
rectangle is the product of its length and breadth? Further, what are length, breadth,
and product? And most importantly, why should we do all this?
Looking at Books I and II, starting with II. 14 in a backward direction, one can
see perhaps an intuitive notion of equality of figures as coincidence, and a notion of
inequality as a part-whole relationship. One can then see that a problem can arise
here with some pairs of figures: neither they coincide nor does one of them fit inside
the other. One problem leads to another, one notion leads to another and we are also
forced to make (or to grant) some assumptions. Having done this exercise, one sees in
This paper is reprinted from Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research, Volume VI, Number
3, May-August 1989, with permission from the author. The introductory section and the appendix are added
in this version.
240 Axiomatic Method
it a vision of an axiomatic approach. Please try to go through this exercise yourself,
and draw the figures.
As with Geometry, so with Arithmetic, Algebra, Mechanics, Electricity and Mag-
netism, etc. Over the years, we have been spending a lot of time with the Masters!
clids Elements deals not only with geometry but also with (the natural) numbers, certain incommensurable
geometrical magnitudes (and thus indirectly with a special class of irrational numbers), and a theory of
general magnitudes. The Elements is divided into thirteen Books. Books I to IV, VI, and X to XIII deal
with geometrical topics. Books VII to IX are concerned with natural numbers. Book Va very interesting
one but, unfortunately, rather overlooked by physicists and philosophers of sciencecontains a theory of
general magnitudes, which is in many respects similar to algebra and lays the foundation of a theory of
measurement. Each Book contains a number of propositions, which are either assertions (or theorems,
in modern terminology), or problems. The theorems (for example, in Book I, Proposition 5: In isosceles
triangles the angles at the base are equal to one another, and, if the equal straight lines be produced further
the angles under the base will be equal to one another) are followed by a demonstration of the correctness
of the assertion (proof), ending in the proverbial Q.E.D. (in the Latin version). The problems (for example,
in Book I, Proposition 1: On a given finite straight line to construct an equilateral triangle) are followed
by a construction and a demonstration that the construction, indeed, solves the problem, ending with the
less familiar Q.E.F.. Some Books (I to VII, X and XI) have some definitions stated at the beginning. Only
Book I has some postulates and common notions following the definitions. (In todays terminology, these can
be called specific axioms and general axioms respectively).
2 Although both Euclids name and the subject of geometry have become synonymous with the axiomatic
method, unfortunately we do not find any elaboration of this method which says something about the genesis,
evolution or purpose of the method, either in Euclids Elements or in any extant work by his predecessors
(such as Plato and Aristotle, among others). There is, for example, no preface to the Elements. Plato,
of course, alludes frequently to the method of the geometers, and Aristotle has written in detail on the
demonstrative sciences.
3 My main source is the second revised edition of The Thirteen Books of Euclids Elements (3 vols.)
translated from the text of Heiberg with introduction and commentary by Sir Thomas L. Heath and published
by Cambridge University Press in 1925. The book was reprinted by Dover Publications, Inc., in 1956. The
contents of the Elements have been put together in the appendix in Ian Muellers Philosophy of Mathematics
and Deductive Structure in Euclids Elements published by M.I.T. Press in 1981.
Agashe 241
My view of the genesis of the axiomatic method emboldens me to suggest further
that in general a method, which is something consciously conceived, arises as the
result of reflection on an activity that is already being pursued intuitively. Again,
once the method is consciously conceived, it can engender new activity being pursued
consciously in accordance with the method, i.e. methodically.
the earliest example of the idea of the comparison of two objects with respect to a given quality to detect which
one of the two has more and which one less of the quality. I have argued in another paper presented at
the workshop on The Genesis and Purpose of Quantification and Measurement that this idea of comparison
with respect to a quality is more primitive than the precursor of the notion of quantity. The Greeks, and in
particular Plato talked repeatedly of the notion of the more and the less, or the greater and the lesser
242 Axiomatic Method
have some definite and simple shape such as that of a rectangle. However, should
both the figures be squares, superposition will always yield a solution; in fact, we need
not even superpose the squares: we need only compare their sides. Note that this
happy situation is based on the observation that any two right angles fit, and this
requirement is what perhaps led the geometers to define a right angle the way Euclid
does (Definition 10, Book I: When a straight line set up on a straight line makes the
adjacent angles equal to one another, each of the equal angles is right), and led Euclid
to put down his Postulate 4, Book I: And that all right angles are equal to one another.
Another important observation would have to be made before one could proceed
further with the problem. A given figure can be cut up or decomposed into parts and
these parts put together differently to obtain a different-looking figure. (This can be
easily seen by cutting up a square into two equal parts and putting these together to
obtain a rectangle). Now, two such figures are not equal (in the sense of Common Notion
8), but there is something special about them, namely, that their corresponding parts
are equal in the sense of congruence. At this point, the ancient geometers must have
realized that no further progress on the problem of comparison of figures was possible
unless one was willing to regard two figures, which were equal in parts, to be equal.
This is, of course, a weakening or widening of the notion of equality of figures, and
appears as Common Notion 2 in Book I: And if equals are added to equals the wholes
are equals. (The original Greek wording of this Common Notion does not suggest
the notion of addition in a numerical sense; rather, it suggests putting together
prostethe). This broadening of the original notion of equality as congruence allows one
literally to transform a given figure, i.e., change its form or shape, while retaining its
size, i.e., while keeping the new figure equal to the original figure. The problem of
comparison of two figures could now be reduced to the problem of transformation of
one figure into another through the techniques of dividing and putting together. But
the fact that squares can be compared with ease would have suggested the following
alternative. Suppose, instead of trying to convert one of the given figures into the other,
one tries to convert both the figures into squares; and, suppose, it turns out that the
converted squares are equal. Could we, then, assert that the two original figures were
equal? The astute Greek geometers saw that this was not justified unless the notion
of equality was weakened further; thus, we have Common Notion 1 of Book I: Things
equal to the same thing are also equal to one another.5
5 Thus far, I have accounted for three of the five Euclidean Postulates and four of the five Euclidean
Common Notions in Book I. (Mueller lists one more Postulate and four more Common Notions, but these are
not regarded as genuinely Euclidean and so are enclosed within square brackets). This leaves only one more
Common Notion (Common Notion 3): And if equals are subtracted from equals the remainders are equal
and two more Postulates; Book I, Postulate 2 is: To produce a finite straight line continuously in a straight
line and Book I, Postulate 5 is the so-called Parallel Postulate: If a straight line falling on two straight
lines make the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, the two straight lines, if produced
indefinitely, meet on that side on which are the angles less than the two right angles. Postulate 2 is obviously
required in most constructions where a point is to be obtained by the intersection of two straight lines or
of a straight line and a circle. As regards Postulate 5, Euclid postpones the use of this postulate as far as
possible; it, is involved for the first time in proving Proposition 29: A straight line falling on parallel straight
lines makes the alternate angles equal to one another, the exterior angle equal to the interior and opposite
angle, and the interior angles on the same side equal to two right angles. In fact, this Proposition could
Agashe 243
Having agreed to the broadening of the notion of equality (of figures) through the
Common Notions 1 and 2, the problem of comparison of two figures is reduced to
the problem of squaring of a figure. Naturally, Euclid takes up the simpler case of a
rectilineal figure, and, thus, arrives at the statement of his basic problem in Books I
and II, Proposition II. 14: To construct a square equal to a given rectilineal figure.
How does Euclid solve the problem? Or, rather, how did Euclid, or some predecessor,
arrive at the solution we find given in the Elements? Certainly not by starting off with
the definitions, postulates and common notions, and brilliantly deducing one theorem
after another (there are forty-eight propositions in Book I and fourteen in Book II). The
problem was solved by reducing it, in turn, to one or more problems. This approach to
problem solving was discussed much later by Pappus under the name of the Method of
Analysis and Synthesis, but we find allusions to it already in Plato. The analysis part
involves the formulation of auxiliary or subsidiary problems in what later appears as
a back tracking when the solution is finally described in the synthesis part.
Although a triangle would be the simplest rectilineal figure, for obvious reasons Eu-
clid prefers to tackle the rectangle first. So the problem of squaring a rectilineal figure
is broken down into two sub-problems: (a) the problem of squaring a rectangle (this
construction is given in II.14) and (b) the problem of rectangulating any rectilineal
figure (this construction is given in I. 45).
Euclid solves (a) essentially by transforming a rectangle into a gnomon (which is an
L-shaped figure left when a smaller square is taken out of a bigger square; see shaded
area in the figure).
A gnomon is clearly a difference of two squares, and we
thus have the new problem of constructing a square equal
to the difference of two squares. This problem can be solved
perhaps if we succeed in solving the problem of constructing
a square equal to the sum of two squares; this is precisely
what the famous Pythagorean proposition amounts to, and it
is Proposition I. 47, the last but one proposition in Book I, the
last (48th) proposition being the converse of the Pythagorean
proposition. Of course, Pythagoras Theorem in the special
case of the isosceles right-angled triangle was known to
many civilizations before Euclid, and perhaps even before
Figure 1: A gnomon. Pythagoras, and its truth could be visually ascertained. It
must have been natural to conjecture that the theorem was
true for any arbitrary right-angled triangle, but this already presupposes a broadened
notion of equality of figures. Indeed, Euclid makes use of this broadened notion in
his proof of Pythagoras Theorem by dividing the square on the hypotenuse into two
well have been taken as a postulate in place of Postulate 5. (The converse of this Proposition is contained
in Propositions 27 and 28 which are proved without invoking Postulate 5, and this is incidentally the first
occasion for Euclid to talk about parallel lines). I have put the verb postpones in quotation marks, because,
according to the view that I am putting forward here, this was not a deliberate postponement by Euclid on
account of some inherent abhorrence of the parallel Postulate, as alleged by many critics, but rather it was
the last step along one line of progress in Euclids backtracking journey from Book II, Proposition 14 to the
Definitions, Postulates and Common Notions.
244 Axiomatic Method
rectangles and showing the equality of these rectangles with the squares on the
corresponding sides. Now, getting convinced about the correctness of the Pythagorean
construction for the sum of two squares required further backtracking and ultimately
must have led to the inverted or backward construction of Book I, or something similar
to it, perhaps by some predecessors of Euclid. This involves, in particular, getting
convinced that the diagonal of a parallelogram splits it into two equal triangles, and
that under certain conditions two triangles are equal. (Incidentally, Common Notion
3 is demanded or postulated in claiming that the gnomon is equal to an appropriate
square.)
In his solution of problem (b), i.e., converting a rectilineal figure into a rectangle (in
fact, Euclid gives a stronger construction I. 45: to construct in a given rectilineal angle
a parallelogram equal to a given rectilineal figure, and to effect that the construction
I. 44: to a given straight line to apply, in a given rectilineal angle, a parallelogram
equal to a given triangle), Euclid uses the obvious fact that a rectilineal figure can be
easily decomposed into triangles, so that one is led next to the problem solved in I. 44.
To summarize, I wish to suggest that investigations into the problem of comparison
of two rectilineal figures led the Greeks before Euclid to the realization that some
concessions had to be made with regard to the notion of equality, which led to the
formulation and investigation of some subsidiary problems, leading finally to a number
of postulates, common notions and definitions. Having done this, they then reversed
the whole process of thinking, making it appear to posterity that, almost by a miracle,
from the small acorns of a few innocent-looking definitions and postulates mighty
oaks such as Pythagoras Theorem and II.14 could be grown. I have indicated this
with reference to Books I and II, but the same could be said about the other geometrical
books.
It should be noted, however, that the other non-geometrical books of Euclids Ele-
ments, namely, those on natural numbers and general magnitudes do not invoke any
postulates explicitly but are based only on definitions. So they could well have been
the result of an application in the forward direction of the axiomatic method discovered
by investigations in the reverse direction into some geometrical problems. Of course,
geometers after Euclidand even Euclid himselfdid carry out further geometrical
investigations in the forward direction, proving many interesting new theorems. Even-
tually, Lobachevskii, and Bolyai followed, non-Euclidean lines of exploration. This last
step, after some initial resistance, later turned into reluctance, and a considerable
delay of about fifty years led to our modern conception of the axiomatic method as
the method of mathematics, involving notions of definition, axiom and proof.
I might add that many great mathematicians of the last hundred years or so have
contributed a lot to mathematical philosophy in Russells sense, because they have
contributed to the process of axiomatization of mathematics in the original Euclidean
sense. Further, it must be added that usually one stipulates one or more of the following
requirements for an arbitrary set of axioms, namely, that they must be consistent,
independent, complete, categorical.
Organization of Knowledge
Another use that has been found for the axiomatic method is that of organizing a body
of knowledge or systematizing a discipline. Here, it is supposed that we already have
a set of truths somehow obtained, but these truths are perhaps too many or seemingly
unrelated to each other. We then try to create some system or order by trying to discover
whether a small subset of them can serve as a set of axioms from which all the rest can
be derived. One may, of course, question the utility of such an enterprise. The whole
exercise of organization is to start with the knowledge base that is already there. This
base would include terms whose meanings we already know and assertions whose truth
we are already confident of. But, if this is so, why bother to define the already known
terms in terms of undefined terms, and to derive the already trustworthy assertions in
terms of some selected assertions? Perhaps one is trying to apply Ockhams razor here,
i.e., one is trying to obtain simplicity. But simplicity in the form of a small number
of axioms is won at the cost of complexity of derivations of the other truths from the
axioms.
Appendix
The Contents of the Elements (from Ian Mueller: Philosophy of Mathematics and De-
ductive Structure in Euclids Elements, 1981).
I give here in an English translation, which varies in many minor ways from
Heaths, all of the first principles and propositions of the Elements as they are given in
the first hand in the body of the manuscript P. . . . Material which is added for clarity is
put in parentheses; material excluded by Heiberg is put in brackets.
Definitions (Horoi)
19. Rectilineal figures are those which are contained by straight lines; trilateral by
three, quadrilateral by four, and multilateral those contained by more than four
straight lines.
20. Of trilateral figures, an equilateral traingle is that which has its three sides equal,
an isosceles triangle that which has only two of its sides equal, a scalene traingle
that which has its three sides unequal.
21. Further, of trilateral figures, a right-angled traingle is that which has a right
angle, an obtuse-angled that which has an obtuse angle, an acute-angled that
which has three acute angles.
22. Of quadrilateral figures, a square is that which is equilateral and right-angled,
an oblong (heteromekes) that which is right-angled but not equilateral, a rhombus
that which is equilateral but not right-angled, a rhomboid that which has its
opposite sides and angles equal to one another but which is neither equilateral
nor right-angled.
23. Parallel straight lines are those which, being in the same plane and being pro-
duced ad infinitum in both directions, do not meet each other in either direction.
Postulates (Aitemata)
1. Let it be postulated (aitestho) to draw a straight line from any (pas) point to any
(pas) point,
2. and to produce a limited straight line in a straight line,
3. and to describe a circle with any center and distance,
4. and that all right angles are equal to one another,
250 Axiomatic Method
5. and that, if one straight line falling on two straight lines makes the interior angles
in the same direction less than two right angles, the two straight lines, if produced
ad infinitum, meet one another in that direction in which the angles less than two
right angles are,
6. and that two straight lines do not enclose a space.
Common Notions (Koinai Ennoiai)
1. Things equal to the same thing are also equal to one another.
2. And if equals are added to equals the wholes are equal.
3. And if equals are subtracted from equals the remainders are equal.
4. And if equals are added to unequals the wholes are unequal.
5. And if equals are subtracted from unequals the remainders are unequal.
6. And doubles of the same thing are equal to one another.
7. And halves of the same thing are equal to one another.
8. And things which coincide with one another (ta epharmodzonta ep allela) are
equal to one another.
9. And the whole is greater than the part.
(Propositions)
1. On a given straight line to construct an equilateral triangle.
2. To place at (pros) a given point a straight line equal to a given straight line.
3. Given two unequal straight lines, to cut off from the greater a straight line equal
to the less.
4. If two triangles have the two sides equal to two sides respectively and have the
angle contained by the equal straight lines equal to the angle, they will also have
the base equal to the base, the triangle will be equal to the remaining angles
respectively, (namely) those which the equal sides subtend (hupoteinein)
5. The angles at the base of isosceles triangles are equal to one another, and if the
equal straight lines are produced further the angles under the base will be equal
to one another.
6. If two angles of a triangle are equal to one another, the sides which subtend the
equal angles will also be equal to one another.
Agashe 251
7. On the same straight line there cannot be constructed (ou sustathesontai) two
other straight lines equal to the same two straight lines (and) at (pros) a different
point, in the same direction, (and) having the same extremities as the original
straight lines.
8. If two triangles have the two sides equal to two sides respectively and also have
the base equal to the base, they will also have the angle contained by the equal
straight lines equal to the angle.
9. To bisect a given rectilineal angle.
10. To bisect a given limited straight line.
11. To draw a straight line at right anlges to a given straight line from a given point
on it.
12. To draw a straight line perpendicular to a given infinite straight line from a given
point which is not on it.
13. When a straight line set up on a straight line makes angles, it will make either
two right angles or angles equal to two right angles.
14. If relative to (pros) some straight line and a point on it, two straight lines not
lying in the same direction make the adjacent angles equal to two right angles,
the straight lines will be in a straight line with one another.
15. If two straight lines cut one another, they will make the vertical angles (hai kata
koruphen goniai) equal to one another.
16. If one of the sides of any triangle is produced, the exterior angle is greater than
each of the interior and opposite angles.
17. Two angles of any triangle taken in any way are less than two right angles.
18. The greater side of any triangle subtends the greater angle.
19. The greater angle of any triangle is subtended by the greater side.
20. Two sides of any triangle taken in any way are greater than the remaining side.
21. If two straight lines are constructed inside (and) on one of the sides of a triangle
from its extremities, the constructed straight lines will be less than the remaining
two sides of the triangle but will contain a greater angle.
22. To construct a triangle out of three straight lines which are equal to three given
straight lines; thus it is necessary that two taken in any way be greater than the
remaining one [because also the two sides of any triangle taken in any way are
greater than the remaining side].
252 Axiomatic Method
23. To construct relative to a given straight line and a point on it a rectilineal angle
equal to a given rectilineal angle.
24. If two triangles have the two sides equal to two sides respectively but the angle
contained by the equal straight lines greater than the angle, they will also have
the base greater than the base.
25. If two triangles have the two sides equal to two angles respectively, but have the
base greater than the base, they will also have the angle contained by the two
equal straight lines greater than the angle.
26. If two triangles have the two angles equal to two angles respectively and one
side equal to one side, either the one adjoining (pros) the equal angles or the one
subtending one of the equal angles, they will also have the remaining sides equal
to the remaining sides respectively and the remaining angle to the remaining
angle.
27. If a straight line falling on two straight lines makes the alternate (enallax) angles
equal to one another, the straight lines will be parallel to one another.
28. If a straight line falling on two straight lines makes the exterior angle equal to
the interior and opposite angle in the same direction or the interior angles in the
same direction equal to two right angles, the straight lines will be parallel to one
another.
29. The straight line falling on parallel straight lines makes the alternate angles
equal to one another and the exterior angle equal to the opposite and interior
angle and the interior angles in the same direction equal to two right angles.
30. Straight lines parallel to the same straight line are also parallel to another.
31. To draw a straight line parallel to a given straight line through a given point.
32. If one of the sides of any triangle is produced, the exterior angle is equal to the
interior and opposite angle, and the three interior angles of the triangle are equal
to two right anlges.
33. Straight lines joining equal and parallel straight lines in the same direction are
themselves also equal and parallel.
34. The opposite sides and angles of parallelogrammic areas (parallelogramma cho-
ria) are equal to one another, and the diameter bisects them.
35. Parallelograms which are on the same base and in the same parallels are equal
to one another.
36. Parallelograms which are on equal bases and in the same parallels are equal to
one another.
Agashe 253
37. Triangles which are on the same base and in the same parallels are equal to one
another.
38. Triangles which are on equal bases and in the same parallels are equal to one
another.
39. Equal triangles which are on the same base and in the same direction are also in
the same parallels.
40. Equal triangles which are on equal bases and in the same direction are also in
the same parallels.
41. If a parallelogram has the same base as a triangle and is in the same parallels,
the parallelogram is double of the triangle.
42. To construct in a given rectilineal angle a parallelogram equal to a given triangle.
References
Heath, T.L. (trans.): 1925, The Thirteen Books of Euclids Elements, 3 Vols., Cambridge
University Press.
Mueller, I.: 1981, Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Struture in Euclids
Elements, M.I.T. Press.
Russell, B. A. W.: 1901, Recent work on principles of mathematics, International
Monthly, Vol. 4, pp. 83101. Reprinted as Mathematics and the Metaphysicians
in Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays, London, Longmans Green, 1918. Issued
as a paperback by Penguin Books Ltd. p. 75.
Russell, B. A. W.: 1919, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, George Allen and
Unwin Ltd. Reprinted by Simon and Schuster.
256 Axiomatic Method
Approaches to the Periodic Table
Rudolf Kraus
University of Toronto, Canada. Email: rkraus@chass.utoronto.ca
1. Should atomic structure and the nature of chemical bonding be discussed early or
late in the course?
2. Should the descriptive chemistry include a detailed discussion of some of the
recently discovered exotic compounds, or should it adhere rather closely to the
compounds that have relatively high stability under atmospheric conditions?
3. To what extent should algebra, as used in the gas laws and in equilibrium calcu-
lations, be included in the course?
4. To what extent should the gas laws themselves be treated, as contrasted with an
approach based more directly on kinetic theory and molecular motions?
5. To what extent should the text be based on laboratory experimentation already
performed by the student?
6. What is the most effective way of acquainting students with stoichiometry and
getting them to the point where they can work with it readily?
7. How useful is the mole concept, and is it reasonable to define the mole as a
number rather than continue to give its historical definition?
8. To what extent should various interpretations of experimental observations be
presented? For example, how many acid-base theories should be used in inter-
preting chemical reactions?
9. To what extent should the treatment of the elements attempt to cover the whole
periodic table in contrast to concentrating on a few selected elements?
10. How much treatment of radioactivity should be included?
11. What level of vocabulary should be used as compared with vocabulary usually
found in books at the high school level?
Kraus 259
12. How much emphasis should be placed on industrial practice and practical appli-
cations of chemistry?1
The need to teach atomic structure and chemical bonding was unquestioned despite
the fact that many great chemists and important chemical industries had prospered
without them. Instead, the CHEM Study questioned the extent of this need.
This academic bent was responsible for the assertion of theoretical considerations
like the atomic theory of structure, Avogadros hypothesis, and the kinetic molecular
theory of gases within the first three chapters in a cursory, authoritative manner. These
theories were to be proved in later chapters of the text; unfortunately many of these
so-called proofs relied on data that the student could not determine in the laboratory,
and lacked the background to understand. The worst offender was chapter fourteen,
entitled Why we believe in atoms, which cited the electrical nature of atoms, the
determination of charge/mass ratios in CRT tubes, evidence from X-ray diffraction,
and microwave and infrared spectroscopy as proof of the existence of atoms. Except
for the first, these experiments required equipment beyond the abilities and budget
of an average high-school. Even if they had been available, they relied on a host
of assumptions in optics, mechanics, the nature of light, and mathematics in order
to produce meaningful data, and these assumptions contradicted the spirit of inquiry
promoted in the introduction.2
Other evidence of academic motivation was seen in the vocabulary. Rather than use
the full names of chemical compounds (sodium chloride), or the common substances
that are equivalent (table salt), chemical abbreviations were used almost exclusively
(NaCl). Quantitative results were also emphasized, as can be seen in this sample
problem.
Exercise 11-4
Suppose that 0.099 mole of solid NaOH is added to 0.100 litre of 1.00 M HCl.
1. How many more moles of HCl are present in solution than moles of NaOH?
2. From the excess number of moles and the volume, calculate the concentration of
excess H+(aq)
3. Calculate the excess concentration of H+(aq) from the difference between the
initial concentrations of HCl and NaOH.3
The middle chapters of the book, from thirteen to eighteen, all dealt with subjects
that in my opinion are useless to the non-chemist. Practice in stoichiometry (mea-
surement of quantities consumed and produced in reactions), proof of the existence
of the atom, quantum mechanics, the nature of chemical bonding, electron orbital
hybridization, and cis-trans isomerism were perhaps not chosen with the interest of
1 Merill, R.J., and Ridgway, D.W.: 1969, The CHEM Study Story, W.H. Freeman and company, San
Francisco, p. 7.
2 CHEM Study: 1962, ChemistryAn Experimental Science, W.H. Freeman and company, San Francisco.
3 CHEM Study, Chemistry
260 Periodic Table
the public in mind. In addition to the difficulty of applying these theories, the ideas of
physicists Max Planck and Niels Bohr on the quantization of energy and structure of
the atom were adopted uncritically, as was the electron exclusion principle of Wolfgang
Pauli. Relatively simple practical applications of chemistry, such as developing film or
chemical batteries, were at best mentioned briefly in the laboratory manual. Practical
applications of chemistry are not only more concrete to the students, and thus more
easily taught, but accurately reflect the average students involvement with chemistry.
CHEM Study did address this problem in chapters nineteen to twenty-three. There
was a resurgence in the importance of laboratory work and descriptive chemistry. Stu-
dents investigated properties of carbon chemistry, halogens, the third-row elements,
alkaline earths, fourth and fifth-row transition metals, and some sixth and seventh-
row rare earths. Emphasis was placed on carbon rings in chapter nineteen, and the
radioactive properties of the rare-earths in chapter twenty-three. The last two chap-
ters, twenty four and twenty five dealt with biochemistry, and the chemistry of the solar
system, especially the chemical makeup of the third planet. Absent was a chapter on
chemistry in the workplace, or chemistry in the environment.4 While this descriptive
chemistry is well done, it comes late in the text, and attempts to survey most of modern
practice at the time, instead of treating fewer topics in depth.
While claiming to be a general course for all students, the CHEM Study course
presupposed a good grounding in algebra, and routinely used graphs and charts to
present data, as well as reporting quantities in terms of significant figures with ex-
ponential notation. Additionally, the emphasis on uncertainty calculations introduced
some statistics to the laboratory. The general student of chemistry must have been
well-versed in mathematics to have succeeded in this course.
All of these difficulties were particularly ironic because the writers of CHEM Study
promoted chemistry as an experimental science, or at least they claimed to. The full
title of their book was ChemistryAn Experimental Science.5 Within it, they claimed
that laboratory work was essential to understanding chemistry. This could be seen
clearly in the units of CHEM Study concerned with descriptive chemistry. They were
concerned with a systematic approach to the elements of the periodic table, studying
and learning their properties. Unfortunately, they were less concerned with common
chemicals familiar to students. This, coupled with their emphasis on vocabulary, re-
sulted in a sharp distinction between the laboratory and the real world for many
students.
In addition to discrepancies in the content of CHEM Study, there were problems
with method as well. The after the fact laboratory experiments, which were suppos-
edly meant to confirm the theories expounded in the text, actually promoted a dogmatic
kind of experimentation. The correct answers were already known to the students, and
of course the students found a way to reach them. This kind of thinking is not at all
similar to the processes of actual scientists, and can mistakenly teach the students that
there is one right answer which they would obtain if they were skillful experimenters.
Of course, this may be exactly what was meant by the writers of CHEM Study, but this
4 ibid
5 ibid.
Kraus 261
emphasizes the importance of scientists, not that of science.
CHEM Study had lost sight of the history of its own discipline; everything that
they taught reflected modern academic chemistry. This was a level of abstraction
that students neither wanted, nor needed. Even the biographies of famous scientists
included within the chapters reflected modern practice; many of the featured chemists
were practicing at the time of the study, and some were on the committee that produced
the textbook. Also implied is that there is no diversity of cultures, races or genders
among chemists. The students found this class difficult, and of limited value.
Many of the concepts taught in this course will never have application outside a
chemistry laboratory. Despite its claims at universality, CHEM Study seemed only
an attempt to bring high-school chemistry up to-date, reflecting both contemporary
progress in the field, and the expectations of undergraduate chemistry programs.
A second example of modern secondary chemistry comes from the Ontario Ministry
of Education. A close examination of one of their approved textbooks for secondary
chemistry, Chemistry, by Merrill, shows us a different approach.6 The Merrill book has
a better grasp of the history of science, and is careful in avoiding the school of Great
Man History. Mendeleev is presented in context as the best of several systematizers
of chemistry, whose periodic table was more complete than the efforts of Doberiner
and Newlands, and whose chemical periods were more developed than earlier ideas of
triads or octaves. This kind of history gives the student a better grasp of the nature of
science, and shows that scientific theories are selected on the basis of utility, not on the
basis of truth.
The Merrill writers discuss atomic structure in chapter four, and after covering
electron clouds and probability, move to the periodic table. According to them, the
periodic table is constructed in the following manner. Use the arrow diagram on
page 128 to determine the order of filling the sublevels. Each s sublevel can contain two
electrons . . . 7 Clearly, they have reinterpreted Mendeleevs efforts in terms of modern
electron orbital theory. Only four chapters later do the authors discuss periodic trends,
following this overview with a look at some typical elements.
This look is mostly superficial, with most of the classroom time devoted to the text
and the demonstrations of the teacher. Laboratory practice is limited to a cookbook
style similar to that of CHEM Study. For most of the laboratory questions, the correct
answers are given in the teachers manual, which undoubtedly creates the impression
that there is one right answer to get. This approach also assumes that the observations
of the students is unrelated to their conceptual systems. To their credit, the Merrill
writers have significantly reduced the amount of mathematics in their course, relative
to CHEM Study. Students no longer need to be mathematicians in order to be chemists.
While Merrills Chemistry has lesser theoretical approach than CHEM Study, it still
presents the periodic table ahead of the empirical evidence on which it was based. If
science is empirical and imaginative, then why not let the students find this evidence
6 Merill: 1995, Chemistry, Glencoe/McGraw-Hill, New York. This text is approved for the grade 13 OAC
program, which is a course for advanced students who have already had two years of general secondary
science.
7 ibid., p. 141.
262 Periodic Table
for themselves? Filling an unjustified framework with data contradicts this empirical
approach. Additionally, valence electrons, or any other kind of electrons, were unknown
to Mendeleev. His belief that indivisible atoms precluded any such ideas.
So how exactly did Mendeleev come upon the idea of the periodic table? The answer
to this question is of educational as well as historical value because it is unlikely
the student has understanding of the electronic configuration of atoms. Other means
should be used to convince the student of the structure and utility of the periodic table.
Dmitri Mendeleevs own chemistry textbook, Principles of Chemistry, the first to
ever present the periodic table as part of the curriculum, discusses different factors that
led to the periodic table. Electronic orbitals did not make the list. Thompsons discovery
of the electron was not foreseen by Mendeleev, who would have denied the possible
existence of sub-atomic particles. The factors that Mendeleev did cite for studying the
elements in a systematic way included isomorphism, (by which he means the analogy of
crystalline forms and analogous compounds), relations of volumes of these analogous
compounds, composition of their saline compounds, oxides and hydrides, crystalline
structures, and their atomic weights.
All of these properties can be investigated in the laboratory, and Mendeleevs own
students did so. Unlike the Ontario program and CHEM Study, Mendeleev did not have
a separate laboratory book, or lists of experiments for students to try. Instead, all of his
assertions could be demonstrated for, or performed by, the students. It was assumed
throughout the body of the work that the students would be confirming everything by
experiment. In the second appendix to his book, Mendeleev stated:
Under the all-penetrating control of experiment, a new theory, even if crude, is quickly strength-
ened, provided it be founded on a sufficient basis; the asperities are removed, it is amended
by degrees, and soon loses the phantom light of a shadowy form or of one founded on mere
prejudice; it is able to lead to logical conclusions, and to submit to experimental proof. Willingly
or not, in science we all must submit not to what seems to us attractive from one point of view or
another, but to what represents an agreement between theory and experiment; in other words,
to demonstrated generalization and the approved experiment.8
Likewise, the crystalline forms of calc spar, magneseite, and calamine belong to the
rhombohedral system, with the following angles:
As a result of this similarity, Mendeleev deduces that Zinc is more similar to Mag-
nesium than Zinc is to Calcium.
Other relations are gathered from the crystallization of certain salts with water,
and noting the amount of water of hydration. Since ferrous sulfate can hydrate itself
with seven molecules of water, we will immerse it in copper sulfate to determine the
hydration state of copper. Because the copper deposits in the same form as the iron,
both iron and copper must be analogs, both forming salts with seven molecules of water.
This idea is generalized to compounds of the form RX, where X is a univalent
element, and R is an element combined with it. Observing that only eight types of
compounds are observed in nature; RX, RX2 , . . . RX8 , Mendeleev deduces that there
must be only eight groups of elements. To determine the group that an element belong
to, its compounds with univalent hydrogen and bivalent oxygen are examined.
Mendeleevs approach to classification was largely empirical, and still fits well into
a modern laboratory setting. Students can be given a variety of common elements to
test for density, melting point, and crystal structure. For corroboration, oxides can
be prepared, and relative proportions can be determined. Once a sufficient number of
samples have been analyzed by the students, they should be in a position to group them
9 Ibid., v. 2, p. 2.
264 Periodic Table
in classes. After some discussion, the students can be given the data for other elements
which are not practical to measure in the lab, and assemble their own periodic table.
Once this has been completed, students will be able to appreciate periodic trends,
and see relations between neighboring elements. This provides a much better basis
for understanding electron orbitals and atomic structure than abstract mathematics
does. This also reflects the pedagogical arguments of Derek Hodson.10 He argues that
science teaching is much more teacher-directed in practice than the curriculum would
have us believe. In order to compensate for this, and return to the stated goals of the
curriculum, we should encourage teachers to learn something about the philosophy of
science, and create new curriculum to reflect that philosophy. This includes portraying
science as having a range and variety of methods which are applied when they are use-
ful, not in terms of an all-encompassing scientific method. The variety of collaborating
evidence which Mendeleev brings to support his Periodic Law is an example of this
range and variety.
Mendeleevs experimental approach is also supported by child psychologist Jean
Piaget, whose work describes stages of learning.11 Many students need examples from
which to generalize abstract rules. By conducting experiments without knowledge of
the correct results, these students will think for themselves. This will make further
generalization and abstraction easier. Mendeleevs inclusion of subjects like astronomy,
biology, geology, and meteorology allowed for better interrelations between sciences.
This in turn, benefits the students who are already familiar with these topics. The
Principles also incorporated chemical problems relevant to the economic development
of Russia. This kind of practical application provides even more concrete examples to
students, and educates future citizens about their country.
A lesson in the authority of science is the final benefit available with an approach
inspired by the Principles. Students will likely have confidence in their collective
efforts, and even more in Mendeleevs published results. Introducing an unknown
element, such as Argon, should cause quite a difficulty for the students. A noble gas
will be unreactive to their tests, and will not have a clear place in the table that they
have constructed. They will have to revise their table in order to include the noble
gases before these tensions are resolved. This can show the students that no theory is
perfect, and that the utility of a theory is not a measure of its validity.
While I have not examined this issue directly, the ideas of classification and tax-
onomy are not unique to Mendeleev. Other nineteenth century chemists were trying
to organize the list of elements into a structure.12 Taxonomy was an important part
of botany and zoology at the time, and can be considered an entire style of thinking,
because it was such a prevalent concern in the nineteenth century.13 The connections
10 Derek Hodson, Towards a More Philosophically-Oriented Science Curriculum, Science Education, v. 72.
11 Piaget, J.: 1970, Psychology and Epistemology, The Viking Press, New York, pp. 63-88.
12 The discovery of radioactivity would make this a much more difficult enterprise. For this reason, the
window in which a classification system was possible was limited. See Bensaude-Vincents Mendeleevs
periodic system of chemical elements, British Journal for the History of Science, v. 19, pp. 3-17.
13 For more information on styles of thinking, see Hacking, Style of Scientific Thinking or Reasoning:
A New Analytic Tool for Historians and Philosophers of the Sciences, ed. by Kostas Gavroglu, Kluwer
Academic Publishers, Boston, 1994, pp. 31-48.
Kraus 265
between societys concerns with classification and Mendeleevs own thinking are left
to the sociologist of science, but I am sure that this influence exists, and did influence
Mendeleev in some way.
An approach to chemistry that is closer to Mendeleevs is long overdue. Instead of
conducting experiments in which the goal is already known, the instructor should allow
the students to investigate chemical properties with less guidance than customary. As
laboratory tests proceed, students will see the relations between elements. At this
point, they are ready to appreciate Mendeleevs work, and not before. This approach
will challenge students to think for themselves, investigate unknown quantities, in
short, to practice the empirical method that is often advocated and seldom achieved.
Not only does this approach emphasize Mendeleevs chemical ideas, but it uses the
exact educational approach that he advocated. While famed as a chemist, Mendeleev
is also important as an instructor. He understood the need to support theories with
experiments, and advanced no theories to his students which he could not first prove.
Modern students would also benefit from this method of teaching. In addition to the
gain in chemical knowledge, a conceptual understanding of the periodic table aids
students in appreciating the difficulties of research, allows them to combine laboratory
results with experimental theory, and demonstrates the strengths and weaknesses of
scientific authority.
266 Periodic Table
Alternative Frameworks in Electricity and Conceptual Change
A.B.Saxena
Regional Institute of Education, Ajmer, India.
1 Introduction
During the last couple of decades large number of studies have been conducted to
explore the nature of alternative frameworks (Driver and Easley 1978). These studies
have been conducted in different areas of physics such as force, motion, acceleration,
heat, light and electricity. (For a review of such studies, see for example, Driver et.
al. 1985, Novak 1987 Osborne and Freyberg 1985, Watts and Gilbert 1983). In view of
prevailing misconceptions in different areas, attempts have been made for conceptual
change (e.g. Eylon and Linn 1988: Saxena 1992, 1994, Smith et al. 1993, Shipstone
1988 Thorley and Woods 1997). Some models have also been proposed for this purpose
(e.g. Clement 1987, Driver and Oldham 1986, Gilbert and Watts 1983, Hashweh
1986, Smith et al. 1993) and the necessary conditions for conceptual change has been
discussed (Posner et al. 1982).
In this article, we shall confine ourselves to conceptions and alternative frameworks
related to current and its flow through resistors in a simple circuit. In the section
that follows, a review of students concept of current, and related difficulties shall be
presented. It is followed by discussion on the stability of these concepts and conditions
that are responsible for it. The effect of classroom instructions and its little impact on
the students previous ideas is significant in this respect.
Several strategies based on models for conceptual change have been used to achieve
it. These are discussed in the next section. Finally the implications of research findings
particularly in terms of curriculum construction and teacher education are discussed.
3. The new conception must appear plausible initially: At the outset, the new
conception must appear to be able to solve problems and help understand situ-
ations, that cannot be dealt with the existing conception. It should also appear
consistent with coneptions already accepted by the learner.
Saxena 271
4. The new conception should be fruitful to the learner: Apart from the proper-
ties of being intelligible and plausible, the new conception should help achieve
something of value to the learner. It should have potential to explain new areas
of experiences, observations and domain.
For these reasons, exposure to a new idea through structured curriculum using
guided experiment for a short period may not be successful to make conceptual change
in many students. Such a situation was observed in an attempt to make conceptual
change (Saxena, 1992) wherein it was observed that, in one third of cases students
failed to solve similar problems. This could be due to variety of reasons. The time for
experimentation was nearly two hours. Students worked in small groups rather than
independently. Perhaps, working for a longer period individually and having more
learning experiences would have given better results.
One possible strategy to achieve conceptual change could be to make use of demon-
strations during teaching. However, all demostrations may not be meaningful to the
learner. Roth et. al. (1997) analysed in detail the characteristics of demonstrations
that help learning. On the basis of results obtained, it is suggested that in all activities
including conducting experiment, discussion about design of the experiment, explain-
ing the observations, representing the observations and their analysis are considered
as social practices in which students participate. The effective demonstration activity
should (Roth et. al. 1997):
Another strategy for conceptual change has been to use examples and analogies
(Brown 1992, Clement 1987). To identify anchoring examples separate diagnostic test
is used. Conceptual change is obtained with the help of Socratic dialogue, bridging
analogies and anchoring examples. To be successful the examples must be under-
standable and believable to the students, the analogy must be clear to the students.
Otherwise, the analogy must be clarified by the teacher in order to be explicit. Finally
qualitative visualisable models may be developed to give mechanistic explanation of
the phenomena. Unless students are able to see in the same way as the teacher they
fail to evoke the desired phenonomena. To explain, the role of battery in a circuit with
a bulb, Shipstone (1985) suggested the analogy of boiler and radiator. Similarly, the
role of emf source is compared with water pump which can cause water to move from
272 Electricity and Conceptual Change
conflict 2
Conception C1 Conception C2
explains
s
lain
co
exp
nf
ins
lic
pla
t
ex
Figure 3: A model for conceptual change based on Hashweh (1986). Conflict 1 and 2
are to be resolved for conceptual change.
a place of lower gravitational potential to a place of higher potential (Halliday and
Resnick 1987). At primary level Summers et. al. (1998) use bicycle chain analogy for
current. However, the use of analogies is not without suspicion. Duit (1991) warns
that the use of analogy create some dificulties for the learner because many scientific
phenomena can be explained using abstract concepts and sophisticated mathematical
techniques. Treagust, Harrison and Venville (1996) are not sure about the nature of
change obtained as a result of using an analogy because it is not conclusive whether
the analogy contributed to conceptual change or whether the analogy merely provided
students with a means to express themselves with the language which was otherwise
unavailable to them.
The instructional material provided to the students in support of the activities
conducted in the class plays an important role in making conceptual change. Smith,
Blakeslee and Anderson (1993) concluded that it requires the support of appropri-
ately designed instructional materials in order to use conceptual change strategies
successfully. Moreover, the conceptual change approach should probably be thought
of as a coherent approach to teaching rather than as a collection of individually useful
strategies.
View P
View P Time
View S3
(Instruction)
(View Equality)
View S1
(View Hierarchy)
5 Implications
Teacher education is an important component to improve efficacy of teaching. There are
two important components that are to be paid attention to: (i) teaching strategy and
(ii) teachers attitude towards science (physics). The first part includes development
of teachers awareness towards students ideas about electricity, their conception of
current, potential difference etc., and procedural knowledge to employ Ohms law etc.
Further, it would encompass strategies that could be adopted to remove alternative
frameworks. Finally it includes the approaches that could be used in introducing the
scientific concepts related to electricity. Aron (1990) points out that two approaches
could be adopted to introduce electricity. One approach first introduces the concept of
charge and arrives at the concept of current at the later stage. The other approach first
274 Electricity and Conceptual Change
introduces the concept of current and the concept of charge is brought in later. Either
of the two approaches could be adopted without encountering any difficulty.
Further, it implies that while planning and transacting the curriculum, the teacher
identifies the common alternative frameworks among the students, related to the
topic;
develops a list of activities that help to remove the identified alternative frame-
works; and
tests the efficacy of his/her approach.
This needs to be investigated and explored in the context of various topics. It is not
necessary that the same approach is adopted while teaching various topics. A technique
such as the drawing of concept maps requires its use over long duration before its gains
could be readily obtained. This is because students need practice before they obtain
mastery in drawing of concept maps. Moreover one could also reasearch on various
modes of using concept maps during teaching.
The second component of teacher education is concerned with teachers attitude.
Some suggestions are given below:
Science to be described as social activity rather than individualistic. The role of
cooperative work and social interaction to be given due importance.
Science is not to be taken as a value free pursuit, rather it be discussed in the
social, moral and ethical context.
Science to be considered as the result of creative, sometimes restructuring en-
deavour, rather than linear and accumulative.
Extreme inductivism, free observations and experimentation are to be discour-
aged. The role of hypothesis making and construction of coherent body of knowl-
edge is to be encouraged.
Finally, more and more research evidence is being obtained that shows students
competence is heterogeneous, not unitary. It depends upon interaction between in-
dividual and the context. Therefore, one single task would not do justice with the
evaluation of students competence because it hides the heterogeneity of performance
(McGinn and Roth 1988).
6 Conclusion
Electricity was taken in this paper as one example to illustrate the problems and
approaches related to teaching of physics. It shows that the classical approach of
teaching adopting transmission model is to be replaced by variety of strategies that
treat the learner as active agent, having his/her own ideas. Sensitivity of the teacher
in this regard can take him a long way to make the learning more meaningful.
Saxena 275
References
Arons, A. B.: 1990, A Guide to Introductory Physics Teaching, John Wiley & Sons, New
York.
Arons, A. B.: 1995, Generalizations to be drawn from results of research on teaching
and learning, in B. C. Tarsitani and M. Vicentini (eds), Thinking Physics for
Teaching, Plenum Press, New York, pp. 18.
ASPEN: 1991, (asian Physics Education Network), ASPEN- APTEA Workshop II on
Research for Students Conceptual Structures and Changes in Learning Physics .
ASPEN University of Philippines, Manila.
Benseghir, A. and Closset, J.-L.: 1996, The electrostatic electrokinetic transition:
Historical and educational difficulties, International Journal of Science Education
18(2), 179191.
Brown, D.: 1992, Using Examples and Analogies to Remediate Misconceptions in
Physics, Factors Influencing Conceptual Change, Journal of Research in Science
Teaching 29(1), 1734.
Clement, J.: 1987, Overcoming Students Misconceptions in Physics: The Role of
Anchoring Intuition and Analogical Validity, in J. Novak (ed.), Proceedings of
Second International Seminar: Misconceptions and Educational Strategies in
Science and Mathematics, Vol. III, Cornell University, Ithaca, pp. 8496.
Driver, R. and Easley, J.: 1978, Pupils Paradigms - A Review of Literature Related
to Concept Development in Adolescent Science Students, Studies in Science
Education 5, 6184.
Driver, R. et al.: 1985, Childrens Ideas in Science, Open University Press, Philadel-
phia.
Driver, R. and Oldham, V.: 1986, A Constructivist Approach to Curiculum Development
in Science, Studies in Science Education 13, 105122.
Duit, R.: 1991, On the Role of Analogies and Metaphors in Learning Science, Science
Education 75, 649672.
Eylon, Bet-sheva and Linn, M.C.: 1988, Learning and Instruction: An Examination of
Four Research Perspectives in Science Education, Review of Educational Research
58(3), 251301.
Gilbert, J. and Watts, D.: 1983, Concepts, Misconceptions and Alternative Conceptions:
Changing Perspectives in Science Education, Studies in Science Education 10, 61
98.
Gutwill, Joshna, et al.: 1996, Seeking the Causal Connection in Electricity: Shifting
Among Mechanistic Perspectives, International Journal of Science Education
18(2), 143162.
276 Electricity and Conceptual Change
Halliday, D. and Resnick, R.: 1987, Physics, Part II, Wiley Eastern, New Delhi.
Reprinted p. 789.
Hashweh, Z.: 1986, Toward an Explanation of Conceptual Change, European Journal
of Science Education 8(3), 229249.
McDermott, L. and Shaffer, P.: 1991, Research as Guide for Curriculum Development:
An Example from Introductory Electricity. Part I Investigation of Student Under-
standing, American Journal of Physics 60(11), 9941003.
McGinn, Michelle, K. and Roth, W.: 1998, Assessing Students Understanding About
Levers: Better Test Instruments are Not Enough, International Journal of Science
Education 20(7), 813832.
Metioni, A. et al.: 1996, The Persistence of Students Unfounded Beliefs About Case
of Electrical Circuits; the Case of Ohms Law, International Journal of Science
Education 18(2), 193212.
Mohapatra, J.: 1991, The Interaction of Cultural Rituals and the Concepts of Science
in Student Learning: A Case Study of Solar Ecplipse, International Journal of
Science Education 13(4), 431437.
Mohapatra, J. and Bhattcharya, S.: 1989, Pupils, Teachers Induced Incorrect Gener-
alisation and the Concept of Force, International Journal of Science Education
41(4), 429436.
Novak, J. (ed.): 1987, Proceedings of Second International Seminar Misconceptions and
Educational Strategies in Science and Mathematics, Vol. III, Cornell University,
Ithaca, N.Y.
Osborne, R.: 1981, Childrens Ideas About Electric Current, New Zealand Science
Teacher 29(12), 9.
Osborne, R. and Freyberg, P.: 1985, Learning in Science: The Implications of Childrens
Science, Heinemann, Auckland.
Posner, G.J. Strike, K.A. Hewson, P.W. and Gertzog, W.A.: 1982, Accommodation of a
Scientific Conception: Toward a Theory of Conceptual Change, Science Education
68, 211227.
Roth, Wolff-Michael et al.: 1997, Why do Students Fail to Learn from Demonstrations?
A Social Practice Perspective on Learning in Physics, Journal of Research in
Science Teaching 34(5), 509533.
Saxena, A.B.: 1990, A Study of Students Misconceptions About Electricity, School
Science XXVII(2), 815.
Saxena, A.B.: 1992, An Attempt to Remove Misconceptions Related to Electricity,
International Journal of Science Education 14(2), 157162.
Saxena 277
Saxena, A.B.: 1994, Alternative Frameworks and Addressing Conceptual Change,
Regional College of Education, Bhopal.
Saxena, A.B.: 1996, An Analysis of the Students Concept of Current, Bulletin IAPT
13(5), 140143.
Saxena, A.B.: 2000, The Development of Concepts Related to Electricity Among College
Students - A Longitudinal Study, School Science XXXVIII(1), 2032.
Shipstone, D.: 1984, A Study of Childrens Understanding of Electricity, in Simple DC
Circuits, European Journal of Science Education 6(2), 185198.
Shipstone, D.: 1985, Electricity and Simple Circuit, in R. Driver, E. Guesen and A.
Tiberghien (ed.), Childrens Ideas in Science, Open University Press, Philadelphia,
pp. 3351.
Shipstone, D.: 1988, Pupils Understanding of Simple Electrical Circuits, Physics
Education 23(2), 9296.
Smith, E.L. Blakeslee, Theron, D. and Anderson, C.W.: 1993, Teaching Strategies
Associated with Conceptual Change Learning in Science, Journal of Research in
Science Teaching 30(2), 111126.
Solomon, J.: 1983, Learning About Energy: How Pupils Think in Two Domains?,
European Journal of Science Education 5(1), 4959.
Summers, M. Kruger, C. and Mant, J.: 1998, Teaching Electricity Effectively in
the Primary School: A Case Study, International Journal of Science Education
20(2), 153172.
Thorley, N. R. and Woods, K.: 1997, Case Studies of Students Learning as Action
Research on Conceptual Change Teaching, International Journal of Science
Teaching 19(2), 22945.
Thornton, R.: 1995, Conceptual Dynamics: Changing Students Views of Force and
Motion, in B. Tarsitani and M. Vicentini (eds), Thinking Physics for Teaching,
Plenum Press, New York, pp. 157183.
Treagust, D.F. Harrison, A.G. and Vanville, G.J.: 1996, Using an Analogical Teaching
Approach to Engender Conceptual Change, International Journal of Science
Education 18(2), 213229.
Watts, D. and Gilberts, J.: 1983, Enigmas in School Science: Students Conceptions for
Scientifically Associated Words, Research in Science and Technology Education
1(2), 16171.
278 Electricity and Conceptual Change
Common Mans Science and Its Role in Making General Science
Education Meaningful
Rakesh Popli
Birla Institute of Technology, Ranchi, India.
1 Introduction
It is no exaggeration that general science education in India has been a disaster. Our
experience in villages of South Bihar1 and the city of Ranchi shows that science edu-
cation in primary, middle and high schools is not fulfilling its stated objectives2 in any
measure. It is neither enabling students to understand science concepts, principles
and theories nor to use the process of science in daily-life situations in solving prob-
lems, making decisions and extending ones own understanding. As far as inculcation
of a scientific outlook is concerned, the picture is even bleaker. Instead, science is
a burden on poor students who have to remember all the tongue-twisting keywords,
concepts, principles, derivations, explanations, etc. Other workers in various parts of
India have come across similar experiences.
This phenomenon is not confined to village children or first-generation learners.
Even urban children attending well-endowed schools often find science awesome and
burdensome. Many of these students may be able to score good marks in examinations
by dumping a lot of unconnected information into their short-term memories, but it is
neither intellectually enlightening nor practically useful.
For almost two decades, science education has been made compulsory for all stu-
dents in India upto class X. While the basic idea of enlightening all with the light of
science is unexceptionable, in practice the only thing it has given to a vast majority
of students is a formidable stumbling block on the path to matriculation. In the area
of science popularization too, efforts by prominent scientific organizations have hardly
stirred the general public. All this brings into sharp focus the question whether the
meaning and content of science for common people (and common children) has to be
the same as for professors Newton and Maxwell and their modern successors.
There is, therefore, need to review the scheme of science education as a part of
general education. This necessarily involves a reconsideration of the nature of science
itself-in particular, a consideration of how science interfaces with the day-to-day lives
of all people and how they can interact with and benefit from it.
1 Rakesh Popli: 1987, Popularization of Science Among Tribal Youth, Report of project supported by DST,
Govt. of India, Vikas Bharati Bishunpur. A part of this report deals with the interaction of high school
students with science curricula and concludes that these curricula are hopeless. See also, Rakesh Popli:
unpublished 1992, An Evaluation of Science and Mathematics Proficiency Levels of Rural School Students
in Ranchi District. This Report encompasses a survey of Class IV and Class VIII students of about 25 schools
each. The results are almost uniformly dismal, regardless of the quality of management of the schools.
2 National Council of Educational Research and Training: 1986, Science Education for the First Ten Years
of Schooling.
280 Common Mans Science
In this paper we review some aspects of the nature of science and point out why it is
found so difficult and alien by general public and students. We then propose the concept
of Common Mans Science (CMS) which can help make general science education lively
and meaningful. CMS is a community- and context-specific assortment of items from
the totality of science. It is related directly to natural phenomena in the lives of all
people of a community.
CMS is seen to be derived from two sources: (a) empirical facts, generalizations
and observations accumulated over generations, and (b) relevant parts of conventional
sciences dealing with subjects of interest to all people at appropriate phenomenological
levels. The nature of CMS is examined in some detail and it is distinguished from
traditional and folk sciences. Possible objections based on notions of oneness of
science and pre-scientific knowledge-systems are dealt with.
In the next part, a concrete but illustrative outline of the proposed curricula of
CMS at the primary (Class I-V) and secondary (Class VI-X) levels of school education
is given which would be conducive to the best intellectual appreciation of science as
well as practical benefit of all students in India. The role of CMS in senior secondary
and higher education and science popularization among communities at large is briefly
discussed.
at Mumbai in 1990 that, science being one, there could be no such thing as Peoples Science, and the
adjective Peoples qualified only the word Movement in Peoples Science Movement. He thereby implied
that there was no need to re-orient science education to make it relevant to the common public.
284 Common Mans Science
part of science or, if it is considered pre-scientific, it should be integrated into science
education. It would be irrational to let this philosophical issue stand in the way of the
common man benefiting from past experience.
3.2 CMS curricula for the primary level (Age 6-11, Class I-V)
At the primary level, apart from the general considerations relating to CMS, we must
keep in mind the age-related needs of children. The general science curricula at this
stage should consist mostly of (a) inculcation of healthy habits, and (b) development
of elementary scientific skills of observation, experimentation, reasoning, classification
and manipulation. Observation starts in the earliest classes and slowly progresses to
involve other skills. Illustrative lists of topics are given below.
It may be noticed that many of the topics given in the above list are common with
the existing curricula. However, the emphasis in the CMS scheme proposed here is
different. For example, in classifying objects into living and non-living, our emphasis is
not on memorization of the points of contrast but on observation, preferably carried out
during outings into a rich environment, e.g. forest or garden, and on identifying classes
of objects, their behaviours and sequences of events. There should be no hurry to
jump to pre-determined conclusions or to dip into abstract analyses. Demonstrations of
various spectacular behaviours of air, water, etc. should be aimed at arousing childrens
curiosity rather than at proving some principles.
There is no room for formal definitions of work, energy, etc. and their relations with
force at this stage. It is abstract and useless. Nor are details of internal anatomy and
physiology included in the CMS curricula.
3.3 Curricula for the Secondary Level (Age 11-15, Class VI-X)
The CMS curricula at the beginning of the secondary stage have a significant overlap
with those at the late primary stage in terms of topics but there is a difference in the
level of treatment. Thus, while general observation is to be continued, the emphasis
is to shift gradually to a systematic study of phenomena. Observation is not the sole
source of information at this stage; knowledge is provided from textbooks too, but it is
still related to daily life for the most part.
The CMS curricula at this stage consist of matters of direct concern to the common
man, viz. (a) health, (b) environment, (c) mensuration and analytical aspects, and (d)
agricultural or industrial technology. In middle classes (VI-VIII) these subjects may
be treated mostly in terms of traditional parameters. However, as further details are
taken up, it will become necessary to bring in technical terms. Elements of physical
and biological sciences will, therefore, have to be taught, though in a phenomenological
way.
Five basic constituents of non-living nature: air, water, soil, sunlight, and space.
Their importance for all life, their pollution and protection.
Air: importance, constituents, role of green plants in purification, pollution by
vehicles, industrial wastes, etc.
Water: importance, sources and cycle, pollution, purification and conservation,
drainage and soak-pit. Water-management.
Soil: formation, various types, pollution, erosion and protection.
Suns radiation: its energy being stored in plants and ultimately providing food to
every living being and most energy sources. Various colours and photon energies.
290 Common Mans Science
Space: pollution due to crowding, noise and radiation.
Forest: importance, how to reap resources, conservation and planting.
Foodstuffs: how to recognize pure/fresh/ripe/juicy fruits and vegetables. Common
adulterants and surface contaminants. Need to wash fruits, vegetables.
Clothing: various natural and artificial fibres; relation with season, health and
convenience.
Housing: materials and designs; elementary map- making.
Earthquakes, cyclones, floods and droughts. Their causes.
Various kinds of energy and sources, renewable and non-renewable. Need for
conservation. Tapping Suns energy.
Biosphere: variety of flora and fauna; friends and foes of man. Caution against
snakes, scorpions, flies, mosquitoes, etc.
Micro-organisms: friends and foes. Sterilization.
Simple experiments with air, water, soil, sun-light, plants and photo-synthesis.
Exploratory and constructive projects as per local conditions. (Examples: explo-
ration of tunnels and living places of rats, colonies of ants, etc.; making soak-pits,
tree-planting, preventing soil erosion.)
Natural resources: need for conservation. Mans survival needs versus secondary
ones.
Sanitation: importance and practical arrangements.
Units of length, mass (weight), time, area and volume: quasi-quantitative, local
as well as standard.
Practice of making correct measurement. Rough-and-ready assessment.
Idea of extremely small objects (upto nuclei) and very large ones (galaxies).
The suns revolution as seen from the earth. The solar (Gregorian and Saka)
calendars.
The phases of the moon. The moons revolution around the earth. The lunar Hijri
and the luni-solar Vikrami calendars.
The shape and rotation of the earth. Day and night. The seasons.
Solar and lunar eclipses: description and explanation. Rahu and Ketu. Watching
an eclipse safely.
Sky-watching: recognizing the planets, some prominent stars and constellations.
The nature of stars, planets and comets.
Pressure: atmospheric and hydrostatic.
Mixtures, compounds and elements. Chemical reactions. Organic and inorganic
compounds. Common examples from environment and human physiology.
Metals and non-metals. Conductors, insulators and semi-conductors.
Horizontal motions of objects. Speed and velocity. Friction: sliding and rolling.
Acceleration. Vertical motion and acceleration due to gravity. Motion of projec-
tiles. Periodic motion.
Sound: wave-motion. Loudness and pitch. Decibel. Echo and reverberation.
Heat, heat transfer and relation with temperature. Thermal expansion and con-
ductivity.
Elements of electricity. Charge and current. Attraction and repulsion between
charges and between currents. The electric circuit. A.C. and D.C. voltages. Ohms
Law. Power and its calculation.
Attraction and repulsion between magnetic poles. Electro-magnets.
Behaviours of mirrors and lenses (broad idea).
292 Common Mans Science
The atomic nature of matter. Atoms and molecules. Parts of the atom: the
electron, the nucleus. Protons and neutrons.
X-rays and other radioactive radiations. Their effects on body tissues and genes.
Units of energy and power: Joule, calorie, Watt. Examples in mechanical, ther-
mal, electric areas. Calorific values of a few common foodstuffs and fuels.
Various crops and respective requirements of conditions (soil type, water, sun-
light, etc.). Crop rotation.
Acknowledgement
Helpful discussions with Professor Dharmendra Kumar are gratefully acknowledged.
4 American Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS): 1989, Science for All Americans (Project
2061), AAAS.
296 Common Mans Science
Attitude Towards Science: An Analysis.
Daya Pant
NCERT, New Delhi, India.
1 Introduction
Importance of bringing about improvement in the outcomes of learning of science can be
gauged from the time devoted to the teaching of science at school stage, right from the
junior school as environmental science through middle and secondary stage to senior
secondary school. Although, all the learners will not be studying science at a later
stage but as effective citizens they need to possess the skills and competencies for
understanding and use of science and technology in their daily life. It is useful for
making personal and public decisions on various issues, such as, polluting industries
and its locations, testing of drugs, use of banned drugs, and governmental decisions
regarding projects having a bearing on our environment (Miller, 1996). Understanding
of science means understanding the nature of science which involves developing not
only the appropriate skills and competencies but also the relevant attitudes and values
(Lederman, 1992) which are conducive to the learning of science in ways commensurate
with the socio-cultural mileu (Roth and Roychaudhry, 1994).
However, research relating to bringing about improvement in the learning outcomes
of the science students has not changed the situation much (Linn, 1992). Science
instruction mostly, involves reading out textbooks to students (Holiday, 1984). In a
country like India where curriculum varies from state to state, and other facilities, like
laboratories etc. which promote learning by doing are lacking, the textbooks assume a
central place in the teaching-learning of science and they almost dictate the curriculum
followed by the teachers and students (Gottfried and Kyle, 1992; Chiappetta et al.,
1993).
The text books not only provide instructional strategies to teach certain facts but
there is a hidden curriculum that is woven into these facts and their presentation
(Richardson, 1985; Watt, 1993; Kumar, 1989). This hidden curriculum influences the
values and attitudes students develop towards science and its use.
It is not only the content of science text, but the exercises, diagrams and the activi-
ties in the text also have importance for their potential influence on the understanding
of science (Holliday and Whittacker, 1978; Holliday, 1981). The messages that are
contained in them regarding nature of science, its methodology, and the attitudes and
values reflected in them influence their relevance in daily life (Jegede and Okebukola,
1991).
Therefore, the content along with these other aspects of the textbooks such as,
questions, figures, tables, diagrams, activities etc. may be analysed so as to assess
how do they present the nature of science, its methodology and social dimension.
298 Attitude Towards Science
2 Present study
This study analysed the content, including questions, figures, tables, diagrams etc.,
of the secondary school science textbooks published by NCERT (National Council of
Educational Research and Training). The analysis was carried out to ascertain if
the books adequately present an account of the nature of science, its methods and
processes, its linkages with society, and its use in daily life.
3 Procedure
The procedure involved using the criteria developed by science educationists (Chi-
appetta et al., 1987, 1993) partially modified (see Appendix A) to suit the specific
objectives of the present study and the results are set out in tables 2 to 11. Interrater
reliabiliability between the two raters was 90%.
Apart from the analysis using the criteria identified to assess the nature of science
and its representation, the book was also reviewed with reference to the psychological
view point of the learners and the criteria employed for analysis of the textual material,
generally, in respect of organization, presentation and lay out.
The results are discussed along with the overall organization of the textbook with
respect to the perspective the textbook presents to the reader on the nature and phi-
losophy of science.
Table-1: Table showing the agreement between two raters on the four themes of
nature of science.
These trends are also apparent in the analysis of the text books published in India
(Kapalli, 1998) and abroad (Chiappatta, et al., 1993) and they have important implica-
tions for the learning of science. Details are presented below:
Table-2: The proportion of the four themes underlying the nature of science in IX class
textbook of NCERT.
IV Interaction of Science, Technology and Society, each getting less than ten percent
share of the total units analysed. The contribution of the paragraphs to the theme
III and IV is not quiet as unbalanced, as questions and figures. The theme III should
have been better represented through the intext questions, as good questions should
be aimed at encouragement of thinking and application among students. (Shepardson
and Pizzini, 1991).
The highlighted text infact, is relatively the most balanced component as far as the
presentation of different aspects of nature of science is concerned. The text has all the
ingredients of the material which if presented in the right proportion could make it a
better book. The sub theme categories introduced for the present analysis were found
represented in the text, although their proportion was not balanced (tables 3, 4, 5, 6, 8,
9, 10, and 11).
The nature of science as the knowledge of science was presented most frequently as
facts, principals and models as can be seen from table 3.
There is a need to portray it more as a product of joint efforts of scientists over
a period of time and also portrayal of the continuing efforts to improve upon them.
Even presentation of the hypothesis, resulting from the existing knowledge or the
new hypothesis which need to be worked upon in areas of ongoing activity were not
present in the text. The linkages of the present material with the information already
known/taught to them or material asking them to recall information was almost absent.
The nature of science as an investigative endeavour has been well represented in
this book, claiming one third of the total units as can be seen from table 4.
Although, all the aspects of investigative method are present, there is a concen-
tration of the material which requires them to make a calculation or requires them
to reason out an answer as compared to the material which requires them to learn
with the help of a graph or engages them in a thought experiment or activity. A new
category was added to this theme of the nature of science which involved highlighting
300 Attitude Towards Science
Subthemes within theme-I
Unit analysed a b c d Total
Paragraphs 143 7 3 153
94 5 2
Questions 3 99 102
(3%) (97%)
Figures 118 2 120
(98%) (2%)
Tables 17 17
Highlights 12 12
Total 293 9 102 404
(73%) (2%) (25%)
Table-3: The proportion of the subthemes within the theme I, Knowledge of Science in
IX class textbook of NCERT.
the lack of experience or bias in the students mind resulting in faulty reasoning or
different outcome of the experiment. Paragraphs and questions were presented in a
balanced manner presenting the different aspects of investigative nature of science.
But figures and tables did not present such balanced view of nature of science as
investigative. Tables especially could be an effective way of presenting the influence
of bias and lack of experience, on the outcomes of experiments and reasoning of stu-
dents. Apart from these lacunae, other aspects of investigative nature of science were
adequately highlighted in the text.
Science as a thinking process was not represented so well in this book as can be
seen from table 5.
Only six percent of the total units analysed depicted this theme, as a result there
was no material whatsoever available on empirical nature of science and objectivity of
science; within whatever limited material was presented in this theme, there was con-
centration on How a scientist experimented? and inductive and deductive reasoning
in science.
It is significant to note that there were only four questions which highlighted this
theme. Since, questions can focus the attention of the learners on the thinking pro-
cesses of science, therefore it is of utmost importance that there be enough questions
which highlight this theme. Tables could also have been used to depict at least two
important aspects of science as a thinking process historical development of an idea
and the way culture influences scientific thinking. Highlighted box items in the text
could be the model to introduce more of the units on thinking processes of science. One
subtheme introduced for this analysis regarding the role of culture on the scientific
thinking was found represented in the highlighted text.
However, more subject matter needs to be introduced to take care of the use of
assumptions in scientific thinking which is a very important aspect of the processes
of science and was not found in the text. Use of assumptions could be very easily
introduced through not only paragraphs but questions which make the learners think
at different outcomes with different assumptions. Even the highlighted text could have
Pant 301
Subthemes within theme-II
Unit analysed a b c d e Total
Paragraphs 25 2 26 11 27 91
(27%) (2%) (29%) (12%) (30%)
Questions 2 10 86 66 7 171
(1%) (6%) (50%) (38%) (4%)
Figures 6 1 1 9 17
(35%) (6%) (6%) (53%)
Tables 2 2
Highlights 2 1 3 6
(33%) (17%) (50%)
Total 35 13 113 80 46 287
(12%) (5%) (39%) (28%) (16%)
Table-7: The proportion of the four themes underlying the nature of science in X class
textbook of NCERT.
present evidence leading to different conclusions could be presented and students may
be asked to critically examine these as proof of different hypotheses.
The paragraphs presented all the sub-themes except two, namely, discussion of
evidence and proof, and influence of culture on scientific thinking. Both these aspects
of scientific thinking need to be emphasized through paragrapahs, tables, figures and
questions.
Interaction of science and technology with society was presented fairly adequately
claiming one third of the total units analysed as can be seen from table 11.
However, the various aspects of this interaction were not represented in a balanced
manner. Usefulness of science and technology was presented by 40% units, and social
issues by 48%, but negative effects of science and technology and limitations were
presented through 6 and 4% units respectively. Acceptance of divergent views across
individuals, authority levels and cultures was presented by two paragraphs but caraer
in science and technology were not presented at all. This absence of any mention
of careers in science and technology has a repercussion for the image of scientists.
Knowing that science is studied not only for becoming a scientist but also for pursuing
a career.
Over all inspite of adequate number of units, this theme presented the interaction
of science with society in terms of its usefulness and social issues. But the other
important aspects like negative effects of science, its limitations, the careers in science
and technology and existence of divergence and its acceptance across authority levels,
individuals and groups was not presented adequately.
Overall organization of the book: The two books were also reviewed from the point
of view of:
1. the presentation of the content and its implications for inculcation of the appro-
priate attitudes and values towards science,
Pant 305
Subthemes within theme I
Unit analysed a b c Total
Paragraphs 103 4 2 109
(95%) (4%) (2%)
Questions 9 119 128
(7%) (93%)
Figures 51 5 56
(91%) (9%)
Tables 11 2 1 14
(79%) (14%) (7%)
Highlights 9 9
(100%) 9
Total 183 11 122 316
(58%) (4%) (38%)
Table-8: The proportion of the sub themes within the theme-I, Knowledge of Science
in X class textbook of NCERT.
2. the layout of the books in terms of figures, tables, and other features and
3. the students reactions to the overall organization of the book.
Presentation of the Content: The organization of the content of the textbook in-
fluences the levels of comprehension (Vidal-Abraca and Sanzose, 1998). The com-
prehension of the text in turn will have influence on the inculcation of appropriate
attitudes and values towards science and its relevance in life. Shallow comprehension
will not result in application of the knowledge to real life situations. On the other hand
deep levels of comprehension are likely to result in understanding the relevance of the
knowledge in real life and, hence the positive attitudes towards it.
The science curriculum framework sets apart the middle level science competen-
cies from secondary level science competencies. Therefore, the two books could have
been presented as a continuity with IX class textbook carrying a brief mention of
the expected competencies, attitudes and values related to science, supposedly de-
veloped among the students at middle stage; and those that are to be developed at
the secondary stage. Such an explicit statement of the objectives to be attained and
competencies to be developed at different stages, termed linking of the textual content,
enhances the comprehension of the text (Vidal-Abraca and Sansoss, IWB). Besides
linking the textual contents to the readers previous knowledge, the text could also
make a direct reference to the diferent aspects of the nature of science, such as, it
should essentially project science as not only the product but also as a process of
enquiry (Kapalli, 1998). However, the reference to the nature of science may be made
using the vocabulary and language suitable to the developmental level of the IX and V
class students.
The general planning of the book, and its contents may be guided by the perspective
explicitly stated in the first section. The logical linking up of the different chapters to
the perspective and their sequencing results in coherence of the ideas presented in the
306 Attitude Towards Science
Subthemes within theme-II
Unit analysed a b c d e Total
Paragraphs 2 1 2 1 4 10
(20%) (10%) (20%) (10%) (40%)
Questions 7 48 55
(13%) (87%)
Figures 6 1 7
(86%) (14%)
Tables
Highlights 1 2 3
(33%) (67%)
Total 9 1 10 49 6 75
(12%) (1%) (13%) (65%) (8%)
Table-9: Proportion of the sub themes within the theme-II, Investigative nature of
science in X class textbook of NCERT.
text (Vidal Abarca and San Joze, 1998). It would also help facilitate teachers task by
increasing comprehension of the students as it draws atttention to those aspects of the
text, which need to be highlighted while teaching and also while framing questions,
to adequately communicate the nature of science and its processes. Not only in the
beginning of the book but each chapter also needs to be put into focus. The chapters or a
few chapters together should carry a introductory block which provides the connection
between previous chapters and the forthcoming ones. Although in the present book
each chapter does begin with an introductory paragraph but it does not cover compre-
hensively the expanse of the information in the chapter, thereby leaving it to the reader
to sort out their own agenda in terms of the highlights and issues. In a science text
book, this gap may make the readers focus on the issues and content quite irrelevant
to nature of science and miss the objectives of learning of science widely not by a small
margin, as the readers tend to assimilate new information in the already conceived
cognitive structures. In the case of learning of science the previously conceived ideas
may be quite irrelevant and divorced from the reality, prompted sometimes by fantasies
or folklore.
Layout of the book: A review of the layout of the books revealed that they are
very dull and unattractive. The figures and tables are set out in very small print,
sometimes the figures are presented without any caption. When the figures appear
without caption its potential value for the students comprehension is much less, than
a figure independently appearing. As the figures make more visual impact on the
students and stay in their memory, they have to be presented complete with expla-
nation and labelling. Movement wherever necessary and possible should be depicted
to communicate conceptual understanding of the process, for instance in electric motor
or the dynamo the direction of movement of current or the magnetic coil etc.
The figures which are very small do not invite the attention of the reader, especially
the students at this stage. The figures are not appropriately drawn. Where there is
a need for real figures line drawings were shown and where line drawing would have
Pant 307
Subthemes within theme-III
Unit analysed a b c d e f g h i Total
Paragraphs 2 4 3 3 11 1 4 28
(7%) (14%) (11%) (11%) (39%) (4%) (14%)
Questions 1 1
Figures 1 1
Tables 1 1
Highlights 3 2 1 2 2 10
(30%) (20%) (10%) (20%) (20%)
Total 7 6 4 3 12 1 2 6 41
Table-10: Proportion of the sub themes within the theme-III, Thinking Processes in X
class textbook of NCERT.
served the purpose real figure, a bad one was shown. The transfer of the learning to
real life situation is hindered when the figures are not appropriately drawn or drawn
without the natural perspective. It becomes extremely difficult to identify them in real
life, for instance the figure of a moss or a touch-me-not plant when seen drawn out
of proportion, not knowing its real life dimensions, will hinder the recognition of the
plant in its real habitat. Sometimes the figures/gadgets are oversimplified and shown
diagrammatically which comes in the way of comprehension of the real life gadgets and
figures. The specific comments and instances which could be improved are given below:
IX class Text book: The figures in the chapters 1, 2 and 3 are very large whereas in
chapters 6, 7, 8 and 10, the figures are small. In chapter 14, on electricity, the figures
illustrating various kinds of electric circuits, connections, voltmeter and resistances in
series etc., are all hypothetical. In order to identify and set up an electric circuit in real
life the real life ammeter would have served the purpose better. It has been seen that
transfer of learning to handle these objects in real life is poor among students because
they do not comprehend the circuit from the incomplete diagramatic representation.
In chapter 16 even the figures of birds are drawings and not photographs. Based
on these figures the identification of plants and animals in real life situations becomes
extremely difficult. Even if the dimensional characteristics are given, the identification
is still quite difficult in real life situations. Only when these living creatures are shown
in appropriate real life perspective, their identification becomes easier.
X Class Text book: In the X class science textbook the figures (see Appendix B) are
often presented without the labelling of different parts (figures 1.2, 1.3, 1.4, 3.4, 12.6).
The figure 1.2 and 1.3 illustrate the working of combustion engines but in the absence
of labelled parts in the figure, the interest and comprehension remains much below the
desired level.
Figure 2.4 shows distillation of petrol, the figure is entitled distillation tower but it
looks like a cylinder. A real photograph of the tower along with the diagrams would
communicate the process better. Figures 7.2 (c) on water contamination looks like a
puzzle as to how the water is being contaminated.
Other features: Glosarry of terms, concepts and explanations would have made a
difference by introducing certain specific references to the words, terms and concepts
308 Attitude Towards Science
that deal with the nature of science and these could be included in the glossary.
Table-11: Proportion of the sub themes within the theme IV, Interaction of Science,
Technology and Society in X class textbook of NCERT.
5 Conclusion
Overall, in the IX class textbook there is a heavy focus on the knowledge aspect and
investigative aspect of the nature of science. In the former category more material
could be on history of science. In the latter category there was emphasis on deduc-
tions and reasoning out an answer and even content relating to answering a question
using material was present. However, there was no content devoted to inclusion of
Pant 309
investigative methods relating to the use of charts, tables, graphs or involving them in
experimentation or helping them become more aware of the personal biases that enter
into investigative processes. There is low concentration of material portraying, science
as thinking process and, the linkages of science with society.
In the former category more content could be added. However, the material needs
more emphasis on empirical nature of science and quantitative assessment as well as
the use of assumptions in thinking needs to be emphasied thereby strengthening the
need for learning the methods of science relating to qualitative assessment, and also
the values relating to the rationality and openness to evidence.
In the latter category whatever little content was present, protrayed the usefulness
of science for society and negative effects of science and technology, the emphasis on
careers, limitations of science and the portrayal of the democratic traditions, as against
the dogmatic and authoritarian, was absent.
Thus in the X class textbook the content was dominated by two themes underlying
the Nature of Science, Basic Knowledge of Science and Interaction of Science with
Society. The two other aspects of Nature of Science relating to Investigative method
and Thinking processing had very little presence, the latter having weightages almost
half of the former. Thus, the book lacks the emphasis on methods and processes of
science. The knowledge aspect presented science as facts and also as the history of
development of science.
Interaction between science and society presented the usefulness of science issues
but the negative aspects of science and its limitations were represented by negligi-
ble content while careers and the values of science that call for openness and anti-
dogmatism and authoritarianism were not mentioned at all. Out of the few units that
referred to the investigative nature of science most were aimed at calculation aspect
only. Similarly, the units that represented different processes of science and related
values were hardly one or two of each kind.
Thus while IX class textbook is tilted more in favour of presenting science as Basic
Knowledge and Investigative endeavor, X class books presents it as Basic Knowledge
and Social Interaction. Both the books lack emphasis on processes of science which are
responsible for inculcating the thinking skills and valuing process. Even the presen-
tation of science as social affair, its negative effects, and limitations of science aught
to be emphasied more so as that learners do not develop unjustifiable single minded
euphoria about omnipotency of science for all problems and ills of society.
Apart fram the content, the organization of the book needs to be more focussed and
contextualised with reference to the science related previous learning skills, compe-
tencies of the learners, and the objectives to be attained by present text content. Not
only overall content, each chapter has to be put in perspective dovetailing each figure,
graph, questions, tables etc. The vocabularly has to be brought to the level of the
reader. Textbooks, thus improved are likely to result in capturing the interest of the
students and, balanced development of science related comptencies in them.
6 Appendix A
Categories for analysing science textbooks:
310 Attitude Towards Science
The categories and subcategories (Chiappetta et. al, 1991a) have been described
and examples provided to enable comprehension of the rules of categorisation. Read
the categories carefully, before attempting to analyse the units in text.
2. Science as a way of investigation: This category includes; those parts of the text
which stimulate thinking and doing by asking the student to find out. This
category involves the student in the processes of science such as observing, mea-
suring, classifying, inferring, recording data, making calculations, experimenting.
Paper and pencil, and hands-on activities are included. Textbook material in this
category:
Pant 311
(a) Requires the student to answer a question through the use of materials. For
example, fix a rubber band at one end and hold the other end with your
finger. Now pluck the rubber band and listen to the sound produced. Hear
the sound produced as the rubber band is stretched. Does the sound change
as you change the length of the band?
(b) Requires the student to answer a question or learn by the use of tables,
charts, i1lustrations and sources of information other than the textbook.
For example, look at the two figures. The bow in the X figure has potential
energy. It can exert force on the arrow and make it move.
(c) Requires the student to make a calculation. For example, a bus travels 200
mts in 40 seconds. In 1 second it will travel- metres.
(d) Requires the student to reason out an answer. For example, Would sea water
have a lower or higher boiling point than distilled water?
(e) Engages the student in a thought experiment or activity. For example, ants
are attracted to certain food items more than others. Devise an experiment
to find out what types of food attract ants.
(f) Presents the material and incidence which bring out how the students own
bias and lack of experience influence his observation. For example error in
reading the level of mercury and level of water could be due to inexperience.
3. Science as a way of thinking: This category would include the text material where
the student is told how the scientific enterprise operates. It includes the scientific
methods and problem solving.
This category is different from Catetory 2 in that the student does not have to
answer questions. Instead the student is told about how science in general or
a scientist in particular discovered, invented ideas, or experimented. Textbooks
material in this category;
(a) Describe how a scientist experimented. For example, Edward Jenner ob-
served that milkmaids showed very few incidents of small pox. He hypoth-
esised that they develop immunity because they came into contact with cow
pox. He experimented by taking serum from cows suffering from cow pox
and infecting healthy people. He observed that the inoculated people did not
succumb to small pox. He deduced that there is something in the serum of
cows that prevents small pox.
(b) Shows historical development of an idea. For example, in 1776, Alessandro
Volta discovered that when two strips of different metals are dipped in an
acid solution, an electric current begins to flow through the wire connecting
the two strips. This simple source of current or a cell is called a Voltaic cell.
The principle discovered by Volta was used to construct another cell with
an improved design by J.F. Daniel in 1836. This gave steadier current but
was cumbersome since liquid electrolytes were used. This disadvantage was
overcome by the invention by Lechlanche of the drycell in 1866.
312 Attitude Towards Science
(c) Emphasises the empirical nature of science. For example, the ionisation of
air produced by X-ray discharges electrified bodies. The rate of discharge
depended on the intensity of an X-ray beam. As a result, careful quantitative
measurements of the properties and effects of X-rays could be made.
(d) Illustrates the use of assumptions. For example, to assume how molecules
can rearrange and change, we assume they must be built of smaller frag-
ments called atoms. With this assumption, we can again explain diferences
between two molecules because they contain different atoms.
(e) Demonstrates how science proceeds by inductive and deductive reasoning.
For example, In Mendels experiments with pea plants, it was noticed re-
peatedly that when a pure tall plant was crossed with a pure dwarf plant,
the progeny was all tall. Subsequent experiments with pairs of this progeny
produced tall and dwarf plants with a 3:1 ratio. The results led him to think
that tallness was dominant over dwarfness.
(f) Shows cause and effect relationship. For example, Take an ice cube on a plate
and leave it on the table. After a while you notice that the ice has melted to
form water. Ths warm temperature of the room caused the ice to become
water.
(g) Shows evidence and proof. For example, Hypothesis: Number of chromo-
somes generally remains constant from cell division to division, thus each
successive generation would have twice the number of chromosomes their
parents had. However it is found that successive generations of the same
species have identical number of chromosomes. Thus the hypothesis is incor-
rect.
(h) Presents the scientific method or problem solving steps. For example, a
scientist first gathers information to identify the probability. He then collects
more information through observations, measurements, etc. He thinks over
the observations and possibilities. He tests each possibility by experiments
or repeated observations to collect data. He then calculates, compares and
draws conclusions.
(i) Presents material which brings out the influence of culture on scientific think-
ing. For example, not looking at the eclipsed sun or moon or offering prayer
during eclipse and holding in esteem plants.
4. Interactions of science, technology and society: Check this category if the intent
of the text is to illustrate the effect or impact of science on society. This aspect of
scientific literacy describes how science and technology helps or hinders mankind.
It involves social issues and careers. Nevertheless, in the presentation of this kind
of material the student receives knowledge and does not have to find out. Text in
this category:
(a) Describe the usefulness of science and technology. For example, we have
learnt to extract energy from animal wastes such as cowdung or plant wastes
Pant 313
like sugarcane bagasse. One successful method is to ferment animal wastes
in closed vessels and produce a gas called biogas. The waste from the biogas
plant can be used as manure in fields and plantations.
(b) Discusses the limitations of science and technology for society. When the text
presents material relating to the areas where science and technology has not
been able to solve problems due to the unresolved issues or new innovations
are required to help resolve issues, e.g. Polymer substances whin make up
garbage, their disposal is a severe problem and this puts a limitation on the
use of this technology.
(c) Describes the negative effects of science and technology. For e.g. sometimes
science is used in harmful ways. Once people learnt that certain substances
explode easily, they made bullets, bombs and crackers. These were devised
for our safety and security. Some people misused bullets to kill wild animals
and people.
(d) Discuss societal issues related to science and technology, e.g. Some people
feel that rain forests should be cut down. They argue that the cleared areas
can be used for farming, which is necessary to feed the growing population.
Other people believe rain forests should not be cut down. They point out that
good yields from crops are possible only for a few years. That is because the
tropical sun and large amounts of rain that these areas receive soon destroy
the soil by moving water. The good soil is carried away by erosion. Thus the
land becomes useless for farming.
(e) Brings out the acceptance of divergent ideas across individuals, and author-
ity levels or groups when the text reports material which makes explicit the
instances whom the thinking of a particular individual or cultural group or
person of rather lower authority level was acceptad by others for examination
or use, such as, use of technology developed in one part of the world being
used by others or a junior scientists paper or innovation being recognized by
senior irrespective of his experience or level of authority.
(f) Information about careers in science and technology. e.g. To prepare for a
mechanical enginering career, you should opt for subjects like mathematics,
physics and chemistry in high school.
314 Attitude Towards Science
7 Appendix B
Fig. 1.2
Fig. 1.3
Fig. 3.4
Fig. 1.4
Figure 1:
Pant 315
References
AAAS: 1989, Project 2061: Science for All American, Author, Washington, DC.
Anderson, T.H. Beck, D. and West, C.: 1994, A Text Analysis of Two Pre Secondary
Science Activities, Journal of Curriculum Studies 26(2), 163186.
APEID: 1991, Values and Ethics, and the Science and Technology Curriculum, Principal
Regional Office for Asia and Pacific, Thailand.
Chiappetta, E.L. Sethna, G. and Fillman, D.: 1987, Curriculum Balance in Science
Textbooks, The Texas Science Teacher 16(2), 912.
Chiappetta, E.L. Sethna, G. and Fillman, D.: 1991, Procedures for Conducting Context
Analysis of Science Text Books, Department of Curriculum and Instruction,
Houston, Texas.
Chiappetta, E.L. Sethna, G. and Fillman, D.: 1993, Life Science Textbooks and
Scientific Literacy, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 30(7), 787797.
Dreyfus, A.: 1992, Content Analysis of School Textbooks: The Case of a Technology-
oriented Curriculum, International Journal of Science Education 14(1), 312.
Driver, R. Leach, J. Miller, R. and Scott, P.: 1996, Young Peoples Images of Science,
Open University Press, Philadelphia.
Etin, J.: 1990, Review of Research in Secondary Reading in Nigeria (1951-1958),
Journal of Reading 34(2), 8491.
Exline, J.: 1984, National Survey: Science Textbook Adoption Process, The Science
Teacher 51(1), 9293.
316 Attitude Towards Science
Fillman, D.: 1989, Biology Textbook Coverage of Selected Aspects of Scientific
Literacy with Implications for Student Interest, and Recall, of Text Information.
Unpublished dissertation. University of Houston.
Gallagher, J.: 1991, Perspective and Practicing Teachers Knowledge and Beliefs about
the Philosophy of Science, Science Education 75(1), 121134.
Garcia, T.: 1985, An Analysis of Earth Science Textbooks for Presentation of Aspects of
Scientific Literacy. Unpublished dissertation. Universtiy of Houston.
Gottfried, S. and Kyle, W.: 1992, Textbooks Use and the Biology Education Desired
State, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 29(1), 3549.
Harms, N. and Yoga, R.: 1981, What Research Says to the Science Teacher?, Vol. 3,
National Science Teachers Association, Washington, DC.
Hazen, R. and Trefil, J.: 1991, Science Matter, Doubleday, New York.
Hempal, C.: 1966, Philosophy of Natural Science, Prenlice Hall, New Jersy.
Hickman, F.: 1980, Preface. In Biological Science, An Inquiry Into Life, Teacher Edition,
BSCS, Harcourt, Brace, Jovanovich, USA, pp. IX-X.
Holliday, W.: 1981, Selective Attentional Effects of Text Book Study Questions on
Student Learning in Science, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 18, 283
289.
Holliday, W.G. Whittaker, H. and Loose, K.: 1978, Differential Effects of Science Study
Questions. Paper presented at the National Association for Research in Science
Teaching, Toronto.
Hurd, P.: 1960, Biological Education in American Secondary Schools, 1890-1960, AIBS,
Washington, DC.
Jeqede, J. and Okebukola, P.: 1991, The Effect of Instruction on Socio-cultured Beliefs
Hindering the Learning of Science, Journal of Research in Science Teaching
28, 275285.
Kapalli, S.: 1998, Representations of Science: A Criteque of Science Education,
Perspections in Education, 14(3), 147153.
King, B.: 1991, Beginning Teachers Knowledge of Attitude Towards History and
Philosophy of Science, Science Education 75(1), 135141.
Kumar, K.: 1989, The Social Character of Learning, Sage Publication, New Delhi.
Lederman, N.: 1992, Students and Teachers Conceptions of the Nature of Science: A
Review of Research, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 29(4), 331359.
Pant 317
Lekin and Wellington, J.: 1994, Who Will Teach the Nature of Science Teachers Views
of Science and their Implications for Science Education, International Journal of
Science Education 16(2), 175190.
Linn, M.: 1992, Science Education Reform: Building on the Research Base, Journal of
Research in Science Teaching 29(8), 821840.
Miller, P.: 1996, Towards a Science Curriculum for Public Understanding, School
Science Review 77(280), 17.
OConnor, E.: 1993, Management Education for the Future: Learning to Think
Curriculum, (14), 6267.
Pizzini, E.L. Shepardson, D.P. and Abell, S.K.: 1991, The Inquiry Level of Junior
High Activities: Implications to Science Teaching, Journal of Research in Science
Teaching 28, 111121.
Ramanathan, S. and Siddiqui, N.: 1994, Representation of Science in Upper Primary
Science Textbooks: An Assessment, Indian Educational Review 29(1&2), 112.
Richardson, R.: 1985, The Hidden Messages at School Books, Journal of Moral
Education 15(1), 2642.
Roth, W. and Roychaudhry, A.: 1994, Physics Students Epistemologies and Views
about Knowing and Learning, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 31(1), 5
30.
Rutherford, F. and Ahlgren, A.: 1989, Science For All Americans, Oxford University
Press, New York.
Science A Textbook for Class X: 1989, National Council of Educational Research and
Training, New Delhi, India.
Shepardson, D. and Pizzini, E.: 1991, Questioning Levels of Junior High School Science
Textbooks and their Implications for Learning Textual Information, Journal of
Research in Science Education 75(6), 673682.
Tamir, P.: 1972, Understanding the Process of Science by Students Exposed to Different
Science Curricula in Israel, Journal of Research in Science Teaching 9(3), 239245.
Watt, S.: 1993, Science in the National Curriculum Developing an Anti-racist and
Multicultural Perspective, in A. Fyfe and P. Figueroa (eds), Education for Cultural
Diversity - The Challenge for a New Era.
Westbury, I.: 1985, Textbooks an Overview, in I. Hussen and T. Postlethwaite (eds), The
International Encyclopedia of Education Research and Studies, Vol. 9, pp. 5233
5234.
318 Attitude Towards Science
Science Textbooks in TamilEncounter of Modern Science with
Traditional Knowledge Forms.
T.V. Venkateswaran
Centre for Development of Imaging Technology, Thiruvananathapuram, India. Email: tvven@sancharnet.in
1 Introduction
Modern Educational systems instituted in India during the colonial period usually
evokes two responses among the scholars. One treats the educational edifice as a
valuable legacy, left by former rulers, albeit, unwittingly. The others, consider it as
diametrically oppositeas yet another instance of the metropolitan powers deliberate
attempt to keep down the hapless colonies for their exclusive benefit.
With the prefix modern to the word education, the first response focuses on the
social mobility that colonial education provided to hitherto suppressed and depressed
classes of people.1 The spread of ideas like democracy, scientific rationality, rationality
and nationalism is traced as a worthy benefaction, with the colonial educational system
regarded as having ushered in modernization.2 On the other hand, the alternative
focuses on how education was a mask of conquest3 a sort of tool to obtain the consent
of the oppressed; and how it colonized the minds. Gauri Viswanathan argues that
the introduction of literary studies in place of religion by the British operated a veiled
mechanism of social control to keep the Indian society governable without the excessive
use of violence.
Scholarship thus is intertwined in inescapable dualism, with weak explanatory po-
tential. The first response would be unable to explain how a well-articulated Macaulayan
colonial educational project could turn out to be a patronizing agent of change, ul-
timately leading to the demise of colonialism itself. On the other hand if modern
education was only a mask and a colonizing mind project, how could it generate a
class of people who vociferously opposed colonialism? Both these dualist responses
treat the recipient society as passive and fail to consider the possibility of natives ac-
tively engaging with the colonial project and re-appropriating elements in the colonial
educational system.
The way out is possibly to seek a solution in the mode of transmission and exchange
1 See Hardgrave, Robert: 1969, Nadars of Tamilnad, University of California Press, Los Angeles, for the
impact of education on caste structure. Specifically, the book takes the case study of how Nadars, a backward
community, acquired wealth and education and moved upwards in the caste hierarchy.
2 Ghosh, Suresh Chandra: 1995, The History of education in Modern India, Orient Longman, is a
University Press, New York. She argues that the introduction of literary studies in place of religion by
the British operated a veiled mechanism of social control to keep the Indian society governable without the
excessive use of violence.
320 Science Textbooks in Tamil
of knowledge between the metropolitan and colonial cultures. Extending the point
made by the sociology of science, this paper seeks to examine the native attempt
to divest western science of its European cultural codes and to assimilate modern
science into the native cultural cosmos. As Aparna Basu points out: education was
a central concern in the nationalist quest for self-identification for it was in education
that the cultural agenda of colonialism had been most succinctly expressed,4 and thus
an investigation into the content and character of textbooks on science during the
nineteenth century would be rewarding.
In the cultural ecology of colonialism, European missions, emergence of scientific
naturalism and social changes ushered in at the turn of the century, this paper at-
tempts to document the toils of native intellectuals in skillfully balancing the tra-
ditional and modern. Textbooks being one of the main conduits for the spread of
modern scientific knowledge, this paper specifically underscores the native effort
in neutralizing5 and domesticating6 the publication and dissemination of science
textbooks during the nineteenth century by Tamil intellectuals (vernacular literati). 7
modern (English) educated strata has diversely been characterized as middle class, elite and so on. I am
following K N Panickar, who, applying the Gramscian notion, uses intellectuals to characterize this strate.
Autodidact, as conceptualized by the Dhruv Raina and Irfan S Habib is more appropriate, nevertheless as
we are not focusing on specific individuals but wish to underscore a social class, we use the term Tamil
intellectuals. I am also aware that these Tamil intellectuals were not a homogenous group but were
internally differentiated. However, the contradictions within the Tamil intellectuals were more pronounced
consequent to the cultural politics since 1920s.
8 Pal, Dharam: 1983, The Beautiful Tree, Biblia Impex Pvt Ltd, New Delhi: A uncritical exalted
documentation of the indigenous schools surviving from earlier period to that of early Raj.
Venkateswaran 321
Brahmin community. Also, the education offered to various castes was not uniform;
it was skewed to fit to the students caste-designated role. Thus a Brahmin could learn
astronomy, logic, arithmetic and law, but a trader would be provided with education in
bazaar mathematics and so on. Higher education obviously was restricted to Brahmins
and a few other upper caste sections. It goes without saying that female education was
dismal and the education of Sudhra caste almost absent.
Radhakrishnan remarks that
the nature of indigenous instruction from the perspective of its stages and methods, character
and quality and prevalence and characteristics of domestic instruction showed its imperfection
and inadequacies. But viewed . . . from the perspective of Pre-British Indian Society, what we
perceive as its limitation was perhaps only some of the manifestations of an educational system
which was designed and developed to reproduce the society in all its discriminating dimension. 9
It is well documented that the Payal schools used classics and texts composed in
cadjan leaves, on the other hand, syllabus, schedule and prescribed textbooks were
absent. While the payal schools were discriminatory, in general the modern schools
established by the missionaries during the nineteenth century admitted students from
all classes of people.
As Keay notes, the payal schools were not replaced or erased but were gradually
incorporated into the mainstream modern school system.10 In fact, in South India, such
types of Payal schools did not completely fade away, but were progressively brought
under the control of the State.
To start with, it was the missionaries who instituted modern educational institu-
tions in Tamil province. Portuguese established a Tamil school as early as in 1567
and eight students began their course in language at Punnakayal, a coastal town in
southern Tamil Nadu.11 There is a reference to school master (by implication to school)
in an East India Company record of Fort St George dated 1678.12 However, it is not
known whether the school serviced only the whites or was open to the natives too.
Nonetheless, such efforts were far and few, and with the absence of printing presses,
hardly any textbooks were published. The age-old practice of committing to memory,
and the use of Cadjan leaves, were resorted too.
By the late eighteenth century, the Society for Promotion of Christian Knowledge
and the Danish Missions instituted schools and Rev Schwartz established a number
of schools at Tanjore, Ramnad and Sivaganga. Essentially the efforts were on the
part of various European missions who in addition to evangelical work also took upon
provision of school education.13 Evangelical belief in the transformation of human
9 Radhakrishnan, P.: 1986, Caste Discrimination in indigenous Indian education I: Nature and extent
of education in early, 19th century British India, Working paper No. 63, Madras Institute of Development
Studies, Madras.
10 Keay F. E.: 1989, Ancient Indian Education; An inquiry into its origin, development and ideas, Oxford
Madras, 45.
13 See for details, Satthianandan, S.: 1894, History of education in the Madras Presidency, Christian
The filtration theory argued that it is better to provide quality English education
to a small class of native people, who would be brown in colour but white in habits
14 Niranjana, Tejaswini: 1992, Siting Translation, Orient Longman, New Delhi.
15 Lalitha, Jayaraman: 1986, History of Education in the Madras Presidency 1800-1857, MPhil Thesis,
Madras University (unpublished), 62.
16 In the charter act of 1813, a provision was incorporated that made lawful but not obligatory on the part of
the East India Company to set aside funds for the revival and improvement of literature and encouragement
of the learned natives of India and for the promotion of knowledge of the sciences among the inhabitants of
the British territories in India. See Sharp, C.H.(Ed): 1920, Selections form the Educational Records 1781-
1839; Part I Calcutta, 22. But the efforts were taken earnestly only after a decade, in 1823.
17 Resolution of the 7th March 1835 in Sharp, C. H.(Ed): 1920, Selections form the Educational Records
Society, Madras.
Venkateswaran 323
and mentality. Thus the earlier policy of the East India Company to support oriental
educationeducation in Sanskrit, traditional knowledge and vernacular literature
were reversed.
The new Macaulayan policy had indeed definitely impeded the spread of vernacular
education in British Indian territories; nevertheless, in Madras Presidency it was not
completely arrested.19 Missionaries were also very active in Madras Presidency in pro-
viding elementary education; furthermore most of the missionary elementary schools
were consistently vernacular in the medium of instruction. However, the unrealistic
policy of exclusive English education did not last long, and the Governor General Lord
Auckland in his minutes of 1839 departed from the stringent policy of Bentinck and
noted that spread of mass education through English is not a feasible one. Further
he also pointed out that the vernacular education may be economical, than through
English, which require the employment of an English master on a salary at least two
or three times as high as would be adequate for a native master who had received an
English education and at the same time perfectly conversant in his own tongue.20
Further the minute desired that the leading facts and principles of our literature
and science be transferred by translation into vernacular tongues21 and argued the
justness and importance of the advice of the Honorable Court that such a series of class
books should be prepared under one general scheme of control and superintendence.
In conclusion the Government of India in its order22 stated that class book consisting
of selections from English work, or, of compilation drawn up and adapted for native
pupils should be prepared at the charge of education funds of all the presidency. A
system consonant with Lord Aucklands prescription was soon drawn-up by the Madras
Government and a scheme for bestowing annual prizes to vernacular compositions with
the object of procuring expositions of standard English works of the character 23 was
practiced.
The Educational Despatch of Sir Charles Wood in 1854, described as the Magna
Carta of Indian Education suggested a major deviation from the filtration theory of
education and advocated the spread of mass education at an elementary level. Though
this despatch also endorsed the desirability of English education at secondary and
higher levels of education, it accepted the use of vernacular at primary levels. The
despatch recommended to24
recur to the past scheme of education viz., the classical language of the East as the media
for imparting European knowledge. This object of extending European knowledge must be
19 Ghosh, Suresh Chandra: 1995, The History of Education in Modern India, Orient Longman, New Delhi.
20 C. H. Sharp (Ed), Selections form the Educational Records 1781-1839; Part I Calcutta, 1920, (p. 162).
21 ibid, 156-157.
22 Minute of the Governor General in Council, dated 21st Nov, 1839 in Sharp, C.H.(Ed): 1920, Selections
1854, (copy appended in the Arubthnot, J.(Ed), Selections from the Records of the Madras Government
No. II, Papers relating to Public Instructions, comprising of the proceedings of the Madras Department of
Public Instructions, Fort St George Press, Madras, 1855).
324 Science Textbooks in Tamil
effected by means of the English language in the higher branches of institutions and by means
of vernacular language of India to the great mass of people.
The grant-in-aid system not only triggered the spread of the mass education, but
also ensured spread in terms of the caste groups who received modern education. Thus,
by 1872-73, the general average male literacy rate in the Madras Presidency was 5%
and in Madras district it was 18%. In the Presidency, Hindus had a literacy rate of
4.8%, Muslims 4.9%, Native Christians 7.4%, European and East Indians 63.3%, Jains
12.9% and others 18.4%.28 One of the significant consequences of modern education
was thatat least a few from the oppressed classes could receive education as much as
the Brahmins or caste Hindus. As the missionaries were arguing that education could
better ones social standing, those caste sections in the lower hierarchy could lay claim
for social mobility.
25 ibid, (p. 2).
26 ibid 34-41.
27 See Manickam, S.: 1988, Grant in aid and Christian mission in Madras, in Studies in Missionary
1873, 37.
Venkateswaran 325
Till about 1870, all schools other than under direct government management had
autonomy to choose the text book and also prepare their own scheme of studies. How-
ever, with the introduction of government exams, adoption of inspection, schools receiv-
ing grant in aid, inclusive of many a missionary schools, had to recourse to use of text
books approved by the government. The Textbook Review Committee in its report also
directed each province to set-up a text book committee to approve suitable textbooks
for use in school receiving government aid. In practice, in many a case it meant that,
it was only the textbooks produced by the government or prescribed by it were used.
The Education Code of 1881, while reducing the grants to the high schools and
colleges, increased the grants to the primary schools. The Hunter commission of 1882
also recommended the spread of elementary education and stated that29
while every branch of education can surely claim the fostering care of the state, it is desirable
in the present circumstance of the country to declare the elementary education of the masses,
its provision, extension and improvement to be that part of the educational system to which the
strenuous effort of the state should now be directed in a still larger measure than heretofore.
(Note: the first 14 publications are on natural sciences and the rest on medicine,
technology etc.,) In addition to the above, four books on mathematics and 35 books on
traditional medicine were also noticed in the said catalogue of Tamil printed works.
While the Government schools and most of the other private schools not under the
missionary management essentially used the government textbooks, the missionaries
prepared their own textbooks and readers. In 1854, South Indian Christian Textbook
Society was formed to prepare textbooks with Christian elements. Latter in 1858 this
society was merged with the Madras Branch of the Christian Vernacular Education
Society (CVES). Many of the vernacular books issued by this society were chiefly for
the purpose of school education.
The book Thattuva Sastram (Natural Philosophy) by Rev E Sargent,31 a mission-
ary, appears to have been popular, as reprints of this book appeared as late as 1898.
The book was written drawing upon heavily from the works of Dr Arnott. The book
Thathuva Sasthram, firstly describes the32 atomic concept, physical forces of nature
(attraction, repulsion and inertia), mechanics, explanations of natural phenomena,
hydrostatics, pneumatics, hydraulics, acoustics, heat or caloric, light or optics, elec-
tricity (galvanism), magnetism (electric telegraphy), weightless matter and so on.
In the introduction the author, Rev Sergent, asserts that unlike humans, inferior
animals have no natural capacity to learn. The nature here implies the inclination
of God. However humans have innate capacity to learn from their parents and gather
knowledge through life experience and by exerting oneself.33 The author states:
During earlier days, prior to the proper pursuit of Natural Philosophy, deception was ga-
lore. People were misled and deceived by blending astronomy with astrology, chemistry with
alchemy. When various principles of natural philosophy became known in (the western) coun-
tries, superstition was eradicated.34
Natural philosophy was defined by the author as knowledge that describes prop-
erties of matter in the universe, laws of motion of the bodies and how the knowledge
is practically useful to man.35 The book also approvingly cites Francis Bacon, and
goes on to illustrate the contributions of Galileo, Boyle, Newton, Franklin, Herschel,
Laplace, and Davy.
The author, to illustrate the magnificence of the creation by the True God advances
the argument of prime mover. While some of the indian tradition also held the view of
God as the designer, christianity the way explained by the missionaries attempted
to show that the first cause was True God and the motion in the universe is the
grand effect and that the modern science provides ample evidence to this. the author
31 Rev E Sargent: 1874, Thathuva Sasthram, Church Mission Press, Palayamcotta, (in Tamil).
32 ibid, 16-17.
33 ibid, 1.
34 ibid, 3.
35 ibid, 6.
Venkateswaran 329
reasons that the study of natural philosophy is not only for material progress but
also for spiritual progressone who acutely studies natural philosophy will realize the
greatness, intellect and kindness of the creator (God).36
Rev Fish Green, an American missionary who established a medical mission at
Jaffna in the early nineteenth century observes that omen, black-magic and such non-
existent sasthras had their sway over people unchecked and they caused havoc. We
publish this book with the desire and intent to establish, Chemistry, the technique
of classifying elemental matter instead of Rasayana, Astronomy instead of Jothista
(astrology), True knowledge instead of false education, and eradicate superstition
in individuals as well as in society.37 He refuses to even consider Rasayana as
an equivalent and admissible term in Tamil for chemistry instead coins a new word
Chemistham.38
The Bhoomi Sasthram, by Rev Rhenius, considered to be the first science pub-
lication in Tamil, states to enlighten (native) Tamil as its object of publication.39
The condescending tone is hard to miss. The missionaries saw the task of teaching
natural philosophy as a way to civilize the natives. The missionary Murdoch was blunt
but forthright, when he wrote to his family at distant Glasgow, You ask about the
telescope that you sent me. It answers the purpose tolerably. I may mention that it
had considerable effect on the minds of youth in causing him to disbelieve Buddhism,
as it showed the mountains of the moon and the satellites of Jupiter. This may, perhaps,
surprise you. I have however only room to mention that the religion of the people is
quite opposed to European geography and astronomy, and, consequently, if the latter
are true, the former is false.40
It can be evidently seen that, in the Tamil publications of the missionaries, the
natural philosophy was so construed as to challenge the traditional knowledge of the
natives or to elucidate the alleged corroboration of the newly revealed religion and the
gospel by the truths of natural philosophy. Missionary Tamil publications on science
during the early nineteenth century highlighted the superstitions of the natives pur-
ported to wean away the heathen brethren from the path of ignorance and to lead them
to the true knowledge. At the same time it was also an effort to establish a connection
made by reason, between Christian truths and empirical knowledge.41
K N Panickar notes:42
Incorporation of colonial cultural elements was marked in the textbooks in the Indian lan-
guages produced by the government, Christian missionaries, voluntary organizations and pri-
vate individuals. These books both through diction and content guided the impressionable
36 ibid,11.
37 Green, F.: 1875, Chemistham, Nagercoil London Mission Press, Jaffna; in the preface to his book
Chemistham.
38 In the periodical Udyatharagai, Vol. I, Issue 1, the equivalent term for chemistry is left blank by Fish
Madras, 42.
44 Studdert-Kennedy, Gerald: 1998, Providence & Raj; Imperial mission and missionary imperialism, Sage,
Naik JP, Selections from Educational Records, Vol II, Development of University Education (1860-87),
National Archives of India, New Delhi, 1963, 6-28.
52 John, Murdoch: 1881, Education in India: A letter to his excellency the most Honble The Marquies of
Ripon, Viceroy and Governor General on India, CKS press, Vepery, Madras, 42.
53 Cited in Satthianandan, S.: 1894, History of Education in the Madras Presidency, Christian Literature
Collected from the Appearance of Nature, the Woods Despatch of 1854 suggested it as a textbook.
Furthermore Huxley is cited with acceptance in the educational reports emanating during 1880s, especially
for the preparation of syllabus for science.
59 Committee of Madras School Book and Vernacular Literature Society invited person to prepare edited
translation of primers edited by Huxley. Report on the public Instruction in the Madras Presidency 1873-74,
Government Press, 1874, 94.
60 For contemporary reponse to Huxleys report and its implication for Indian Education see, John,
Murdoch: 1881, Education in India: A Letter to Lord Ripon, CKS Press, Madras.
Venkateswaran 333
tives self styled as the new middle class, sought made claims to the privileges and a
share of governance under the British political tradition. This emerging vernacular
literati, quite independently of their class and caste origins, were politically aware and
active as theorists, strategists, organizers and spokespersons on behalf of the emerging
autonomous social group of incipient national bourgeois.
The Tamil Brahmin, traditional custodian of knowledge, seamlessly took advantage
of modern education and the acquired benefits accruing out of it. Being the traditional
lawgiver, he could exercise his pre-existing hegemony in the civil society through his
caste status while his modern education gave him a new found authority in the colonial
political society.61 As Aparna Basu notes, along with the Bengali Bhadralok and the
Chitapavan of Maharastra, it was the Tamil Brahmin who assumed political hegemony
in the respective provinces.62 While the Tamil Brahmin retained his devotion to San-
skrit, on the other hand he was also a promoter of Tamil so as to hegemonize other
vernacular languages of the Madras province. Hence, among the vernacular languages
of the Madras province, Tamil was the forerunner. In addition another social group
that forged a self identity of Saiva Vellalars (which included caste groups such as
Vellalars, Mudaliars and Chettiyars) were also acquiring new status and power within
the colonial set-up.63 As Sabyasachi Bhattacharya notes contest between nationalism
in education with the colonial state (was) inseparably intertwined historically with
the contest for hegemony within the colonial society and during the late nineteenth
century most of the educated vernacular literati organized themselves into various
local socio-political organizations associated with educational service.64
The emergent forums were usually styled as scientific and literary societies. Read-
ing rooms, societies for debates and organizations championing for educational ad-
vancement as well as social reform were instituted in many provincial towns. As a
representative of these movements, the Villupuram Literary Society in 1882 and the
Villupuram Educational Society in 1885 were initiated with the objective to discuss
literature and science subjects and for educational and social reform.65 At the turn of
the century there were more than 100 such societies and reading rooms in various
provincial towns of the Madras Presidency. In these societies irrespective of their
religious persuasion, Indian intellectuals found in science a neutral pursuit that was to
become a common meeting ground and serve as a means of articulating counter colonial
political stance,66 and as K.N. Panickar observes being conduits for the dissemination
61 MSS Pandian: 1996, Towards National Popular, ntoes on self-respecters Tamil, Economic and Political
Weekly, Dec 21, 3323-3329. See also Arooran, K Nambi: 1980, Tamil Renaissance and the Dravidian
nationalism 1905-1940, Kudal Publishers, Madurai.
62 Basu, Aparna: 1974, The growth of education and political development in India 1898-1920, Oxford
and Tamil Separatism 1916-1929, University of California Press; also Washbrook, D. A.: 1976, The
Emergence of Provincial PolityThe Madras Presidency 1870-1920, Cambridge University Press
64 Bhattacharya, Sabyasachi: 1998, The Contested Terrain, Orient Longman, New Delhi, 6.
65 Tirumizi, S.A.I.: 1989, Scientific Associations in British India, NISTADS, New Delhi.
66 Habib, Irfan & Raina, Dhruv: 1989, Introduction of Scientific Rationality into India, a Study of Master
other professionals.
71 See the following catalogues for a full list of textbooks produced and used during the late nineteenth
century: Madras State Bibliography of books 1867-1900 Tamil Development and Research Council, Volumes
published in 1961, 62, 63 and 64; Madras State Bibliography of books for the years 1911-15 and 1916-20
published respectively in the years 1974/77, and 1978; Classified catalogue of the Public Reference Library
1867-89, 1890-1900, 1901-10, 1911-15, 1916-20, 1921-25 published respectively in the years 1894, 1961,
1964, 1965, 1971.
Venkateswaran 335
the process of replacement of natural philosophy by scientific naturalism.
V.K. Narayanasamy Iyer, Iyarkai Porutpadam, Vol I and Vol II, 1910for elemen-
tary school teachers.
A. Sivaprakasa Iyer, Tavara Sastra Vina Vidai, 1910.
B. Narayanasami Iyer, Practical lessons in science and geography [Vol I & II]
1914/15.
J. Viswanathiya, Tavara Nur Churukam for kindergarten and primary classes
1912.
publish articles on Indian Philosophy, English (Western) philosophy, English natural sciences, religious
truths . . .
78 As Panickar notes there was no articulated debate on the suitability of the use of the expression Western
science, however one can hardly fail to notice the use of neutral expressions such as Natural science or
modern (naveena) science in the popular Tamil publications from about the 1900s.
79 Universality of science was taken for granted by the Indian intellecutals. They did not face the question
whether science was western or new as in the case of China. About 1640 there was a discussion in Peking
as to whether the new science were primarily or primarily new. The Chinese objected to the word western
used by the Jesuits in the titles of the scientific books which they wrote and translated. They insisted that
it should be dropped in favour of new. Panickar, K. N.: 1995, Culture, Ideology, Hegemony, Thulika, New
Delhi, 10,ff.
80 Iyer, Sivachidambara: 1906-07, Arivu [Knowledge], Sentamil, 5,, 330.
Venkateswaran 337
Few psychologists maintain that every one is not endowed with rational capacity and that
the rational capacity of a person depends upon his race. While this claim cannot be totally
rejected the assertion can not be accepted. telegraphy, steam engines and such other wonder
mechanisms evident the intellect of the inventor and not manifest their race or social status.
Another intellectual, Ramaiyar81 argued that the discoveries are validated not by
looking at the race or colour of the discoverer but by proof (presented by him) and
further asserted that the [usage of] expressions such as Eastern science and Western
science are to be rejected.82 Tamilar Nesan, a monthly science magazine launched
by native intellectuals, argued, knowledge about means of earning a living may vary
among people and depend upon their profession. All the rest of knowledge is common
heritage of allfrom sweeper to a lord; [this knowledge] is essential for every one; and
by striving every one can acquire this knowledge.83 Similar sentiments to universalize
and legitimize modern science can be noticed in the writings of natives.
Sashtra Vichitram or Wonders of Science was a popular book by M. Natesan.84 As
the titleVichitramindicates, modern science is visualized as strange and queer
sasthram (science). A glance at the various articles in the Vidhya Varthamani, a Tamil
periodical devoted to education published since 1897 reveals the allusion to wonder,
strangeness and oddity of the modern science. The allusion to the strangeness and
oddity of modern science during this period is palpably obvious from the title of the
Tamil periodical Vinodha Vichitra Patrikai, published since the 1900s to popularize
science.
Thus it can be argued that the natives reasoned the notion of modern as novelty
something new. Naveenam, the expression used in Tamil to denote modern also im-
plies that which is novel, new. The telegraph, steam engines and such other modern
artifacts, and the emerging knowledge about Nature such as electricity, magnetism,
and so on, fascinated the imagination of the natives as being novel and new.85 In
the writings of the natives during the late nineteenth century, one can hardly fail
to notice the use of words such as Vinodham and Vichitram (wonder, strange, queer,
oddity) while referring to modern science. Through the metaphor of novelty the alien
knowledge was legitimized in the native cosmos.
That which belongs to the present is also suggested at by the expression naveenam.
The usage such as Naveena Ulagu (Modern world) implies an understanding of here
and now. This case is well illustrated by the writings of Ms M. Lakshmiyammal,
a regular columnist in Tamilar Nesan. While translating the article The future of
Economic and Scientific Thought a speech by Prof. Soddy, the article in Tamil was titled
as Eni Pzhaikum Vazhi (The way to prevail henceforth)that is, the modern science
81 Ramaiyar: 1923-24, Civilization and Progress, Tamilar Nesan, VIII, 250-60.
82 ibid
83 Editorial: 1917-18, Namadhu Sangam, Tamilar Nesan (in Tamil), I, 1-9.
84 Natesan, M.: 1888, Sastra Vichitram or wonders of Science, VN Jubilee Press. The book contains science
activities and simple elementary scientific principles, which were published as a serial in the periodical,
Viveka Chinthamani. The book was reprinted in 1902 and again in 1913. The popularity of this book could
be gauged from this.
85 Fascinated by the novel devices being invented, Vaidyanatha Iyer composed books on Submarine (2nd
However, J.M. Velupillai a native intellectual translating the same book into Tamil
for use in the schools states that91
the following six rivers dry up in summer, nevertheless, (rivers) originating in Himalayas much
flow will be there during the summer than in the other three seasons . . . among this there is no
other river as useful as Ganges . . . (Ganges) flows through thickly populated regions . . . May
be it is due to the immense benefit accruing to the people, that Hindus hold (Ganges) as sacred
water.
Thus it can be clearly seen that even translation was not just mechanically render-
ing what is in the source language into the target language, but an act of re-rendering,
and a kind of cultural translation. The process of drift, invention, mediation, and at
times even fabrication of links that did not exist before, form some of the repertoire of
narratives adopted by the natives to render modern science as legitimate within the
cultural cosmos.
5 Summary
Shapin92 suggests that diffusion of scientific knowledge across boundariesbetween
countries, between town and country, between social classesshould be seen as politi-
cal and a logistical problem. Transmission of knowledge between the colonial metropo-
lis and the colonized province, especially in the context of colonialism in the nineteenth
century Tamil Nadu provides an interesting location for study.
If the instruction in modern science through vernaculars was not shown same en-
thusiasm as that of spread of European literature by the colonialists, the prevailing
name of the publishers.
90 Sing, Jyotsna: 1996, Colonial Narratives; Discoveries of India in the Languages of Colonialism,
Routledge, 8.
91 Velupillai, J.M.: 1813, Bala Bhotha Boogola Sasthram, (Original by Duncan), CKS press, Madras, 10.
92 Shapin, Steven: 1982, Nibbling at the teats of Science; Edinburgh and the diffusion of science in the
1830s, in Ian Inkstar and Jack Morrell (Ed.), Metropolis and Province, science and British culture 1780-
1850, Hutchinson, 151-178.
340 Science Textbooks in Tamil
Victorian ideology may have had a role, but the view that modern science is difficult to
convey through the vernaculars was entrenched among the colonialist and the educated
elite that even while addressing a memorial to the Viceroy for instruction on modern
science through the medium of vernaculars, the British Indian association admitted
that instruction of higher standard is not feasible in vernacular.
Thus, during the first half of the nineteenth century even while the instruction in
European literature and science was proclaimed time and again instruction in science
was scanty, that the Madras Mail, a daily English news paper lamented that: A
man may become a Master of Arts in Madras, without knowing why apple falls to
the ground, where rain comes from, what is the meaning of a burning stick, why he
has to breath constantly, or what sun means by occasionally disappearing at incon-
venient times.93 Nonetheless the topics on natural philosophy and natural history
that was found in the textbooks were embodied with natural theology. Before the
1880s most of the titles of science textbooks published were in the idiom of Natural
Philosophy and were primarily about basic principles of natural philosophy, astronomy,
natural history and geography/geology and further as noted earlier, authored mostly
by missionaries. The books on astronomy were contrasted with astrology and invari-
ably contained arguments about the popular belief about the eclipses.94 The books
on geology/geography argued the alleged evidences of the Christian Truths and were
afflicted with the Paleys Evidences.95 In the paradigm of natural philosophy during
the early nineteenth century, the ideology of Europe as the ideal was being promoted,
while traditional knowledge forms were being threatened and marginalised. As Julian
Martin96 notes natural philosophy was never a socially disengaged, purely intellectual
activity and natural philosophical pronouncements were believed to entail assertions
about the political order.
The colonial educational programme was seeking to hegemonise and dominate in
cultural terms, the native society. The Macaulayan flourish of Indian in blood but
European in taste was not an accidental slip, but the general urge. Thus the colo-
nial subject was the ideal of education. The native intellectuals were not passive to
these colonial maneuvers, but were actively engaged with the modern science being
introduced into colonial Tamil society as part of the colonial subjectification, during
the nineteenth century. There were a host of historical factors that contributed to the
natives acquiring determining role as purveyors of knowledge in the Tamil society even
under colonialism. In this process of reproduction of knowledge the native intellectuals
were also producing knowledge forms suited to their cultural and political require-
93 A plea for physical sciences in our school and universities, Madras Mail, 4th March, 1874.
94 Christian Vernacular Education Society, Graganangal Yerpadum Kararnangal, 1880; challenges the
traditional Hindu popular mythological belief on Rahu and Kethu being the cause of Eclipse and provides
scientific explanation to the eclipse. Christian Vernacular Education Society, Pagola Sasthramum Jothista
Sasthramum, 1891 aims to show belief in Jothista Sasthram leads to calamity.
95 Christian Vernacular Education Society, Yerimalaigalum Bhoomi Atherchiyum Sristipin Athisiyan-
galum, 1894; clearly alludes to the biblical creation and justification of Genesis based upon theory of
geology as understood at that period.
96 Martin, Julian: 1991, Natural Philosophy and its public concerns, in Stephen Pumfrey etal., (Ed), in
Science, Culture and Popular belief in Renaissance Europe, Manchester University Press, 116.
Venkateswaran 341
ments.
Due to the policy changes prompted by the Woods Despatch and the recommenda-
tions of the Hunter Commission, elementary education was spread in its reach in the
Madras Presidency and was progressively placed under private management. While
the native intellectuals were not able to completely recast the colonial policies in the
education sector, they could exercise a significant influence. With native intellectuals
acquiring education in English and modern science, the monopoly of missionaries in
printing and publication was disputed. By occupying a preeminent position in the
Madras School Book and Vernacular Literature Society, the natives sought an insti-
tutional base for challenging the missionary monopoly of production of vernacular
textbooks. When textbook publication was liberalized (but with government retaining
its power to scrutinize and approve), the natives published textbooks from their native
printing houses as well. Thus, by the turn of the century, the native intellectuals almost
displaced the missionaries from the textbook production scene. Gradually the native
intellectuals entered into publication and printing.
Native intellectuals, besides being educated in modern science were also the tra-
ditional elite of the society, and had to come to terms with the modern knowledge;
but the modern knowledge was being transmitted by the colonial system with western
cultural codes. Having got a determining role in the production of textbooks, the native
intellectuals, through the process of translation and composition of vernacular text-
books, divested modern science of its western cultural meaning. In the process, modern
science was not only neutralized but also domesticatedthat is, native intellectuals
redeemed whatever was salvageable from the traditional knowledge systems. Eventu-
ally the natives endeavored rendering modern science into the vernacular languages
and, in the process, reconfigured and domesticated modern science.
The dislodging of the European missionaries was further hastened by the shift
in knowledge form taking place in Europe. Scientific naturalism was fast replacing
natural philosophy, and clergy were being restricted to ecclesiastical domains and their
competency in scientific domain being questioned. At the turn of the century, the
native intellectuals who had by then acquired the right professional higher educa-
tion could claim to be more competent to compose science textbooks, rather than the
missionaries or colonial officials.
Through the process of translation, by establishing a series of transit points, the
native intellectual was attempting a trans-cultural conceptual bridge building. The
rhetorical repertoire of naveenam as novelty, here-and-now, of-the-present was de-
ployed to mollify the colonial binary of the traditional and modern. In the age of
nationalism when science came to be the measure of progress achieved by the nation, by
conjuring up a civilization and by salvaging parts of the past, the native intellectuals
waged a symbolic war. This study also confirms the conception put forth by Dhruv
Raina that the role of the history of science, in purveying of science, was one of es-
sentially lamenting the loss of golden past and a battle-cry for a resurgent India. 97
97 Raina, Dhruv: 2000, Lamenting the Past, Anticipating the future: A chronology of popular science
writing in India (1850-1914), in Narender K Shegal etal., (Ed), Uncharted TerrainEssays on Science
Popularisation in Pre-independence India, Vigyan Prasar, New Delhi.
342 Science Textbooks in Tamil
Thus, through the process of science textbooks, the native Tamil intellectuals were
inventing a space for articulating a counter colonial perspective during the nineteenth
century. The reception of the modern science by the natives was not passive and
once they obtained space for inscribing their ideology in the textbook, they utilized
the opportunity. However, this study clearly shows that the reaction of the native to
reject modern science as unsuited to our culture or take a revivalist position were rare
during the nineteenth century.
In conclusion, following, Roger Cooter and Stephen Pumfery scientists, science
communicators and audiences define their relationship to something called science and
. . . that (the) relationship is embedded in the particularities of their different culture
and ideologies,98 it is contented that, as textbooks have a crucial role in shaping
the dogmas of the period, aside from seeing the efforts of the native intellectuals as
reproduction of modern science, it should also be viewed as production of ideology. 99
98 Cooter, Roger & Pumfrey, Stephen: 1994, Separate spheres and public places; reflections on the History
of science popularization and science in popular culture, History of Science, XXXII, 237-67.
99 Ideology in the sense of the imaginary relationship of individuals to their real conditions of existence.
Index
Yager, 115
Yang Guangxian, 236
Yash Pal Committee, 317
Yesudas Ramchandra, 237
Yoruba method of multiplication, 220
YuktiBhasa, 254, 260
Yuktibhasa, 226, 227
Zaire, 215
Zambia, 215
zero, 216
introduction, 214
Zij al-Arjabhar, 226
Ziman, 112
zoology, 286
Index
Yager, 115
Yang Guangxian, 236
Yash Pal Committee, 317
Yesudas Ramchandra, 237
Yoruba method of multiplication, 220
YuktiBhasa, 254, 260
Yuktibhasa, 226, 227
Zaire, 215
Zambia, 215
zero, 216
introduction, 214
Zij al-Arjabhar, 226
Ziman, 112
zoology, 286
Venkateswaran 389
References
Edwards, C.: 1979, The Historical Development of the Calculus, Springer-Verlag, New York.
Gurukkal, R.: 1992, The Kerala Temple and Early Medieval Agrarian System, Vallathol Vidyapeetham,
Sukapuram.
Hayashi, T. Kusuba, T. and Yano, M.: 1990, The Correction of the Madhava Series for the Circumference of a
Circle, Centaurus 33, 149174.
Jami, C.: 1988, Western Influence and Chinese Tradition in an Eighteenth Century Chinese Mathematical
Work, Historia Mathematica 15, 311331.
Joseph, G.: 2000, The Crest of the Peacock: Non-European Roots of Mathematics, 2nd edn, Princeton
University Press.
Marar, K. and Rajagopal, C.: 1944, On the Hindu Quadrature of the Circle, Journal of the Bombay Branch of
the Royal Asiatic Society 20, 6582.
Rajagopal, C. and Rangachari, M.: 1986, On Medieval Keralese Mathematics, Archive for History of Exact
Sciences 35, 9199.
Rajagopal, C. and T.V.V., A.: 1951, On the Hindu Proof of Gregorys Series, Scripta Mathematica 17, 6574.
Rajagopal, C. and Venkataraman, A.: 1949, The Sine and Cosine Power Series in Hindu Mathematics,
Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society of Bengal 15, 113.
R.V., T. and Aiyar, A. (eds): 1948, Yuktibhasa Part I, Mangalodayam Ltd., Trichur.
Sarma, K.: 1991, A History of Kerala School of Hindu Astronomy, Vishveshavaranand Institute, Hoshiarpur.
Sarma, K. and Hariharan, S.: 1991, Yuktibhasa of Jyesthadeva, Indian Journal of History of Science 26, 186
207.
Whish, C.: 1835, On the Hindu Quadrature and the Infinite Series of the Proportion of the Circumference to
the Diameter . . ., Transactions of the Royal Asiatic Society, Great Britain and Ireland 3(part III), 509
523.
Yan, L. and Shiran, D.: 1987, Chinese Mathematics: A Concise History, Clarendon Press, Oxford.