Neil Summerhill
Neil Summerhill
Neil Summerhill
Neill
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
"Alexander Neill" redirects here. For other uses, see Alex Neil (disambiguation).
A. S. Neill
17 October 1883
Forfar, Scotland
Alexander Sutherland Neill (17 October 1883 23 September 1973) was a Scottish educator and
author known for his school, Summerhill, and its philosophies of freedom from adult coercion and
community self-governance. Neill was raised in Scotland, where he was a poor student but became
a schoolteacher. He taught in several schools across the country before attending the University of
Edinburgh from 1908 to 1912. He took two jobs in journalism before World War I, and taught at
Gretna Green Village School during the first year of the war, writing his first book, A Dominie's
Log (1915), as a diary of his life as headteacher. He joined the staff of a school in Dresden in 1921,
founding Summerhill upon his return to England in 1924. Summerhill received widespread renown in
the 1920s to 1930s and then in the 1960s to 1970s, due to progressive and counter-culture interest.
Neill wrote 20 books in his lifetime, and his best seller was the 1960 Summerhill, a compilation of
four previous books about his school. The book was a common ancestor to activists in the
1960s free school movement.
Contents
[hide]
Summerhill School[edit]
Main article: Summerhill School
Summerhill, 1993
The school picked up some notoriety and the average enrolment was 40 pupils. In 1927, it moved
to Leiston, where it remained.[15]
Neill credited Summerhill's environment instead of himself for the school's reformatory
successes.[4] Neill used to offer psychoanalytic therapy ("private lessons", since he was not a
licensed therapist[16]) for children who arrived as delinquents from other institutions, but later found
love, affirmation, and freedom to be a better cure.[4]
The Summerhill classroom was popularly assumed to reflect Neill's anti-authoritarian beliefs, though
their classes were traditional in practice.[17] Neill did not show outward interest in classroom
pedagogy, and was mainly interested in student happiness.[18] He did not consider lesson quality
important,[18] and thus there were no distinctive Summerhillian classroom methods.[19] Leonard Waks
wrote that, like Homer Lane, Neill thought all teaching should follow student interest, and that
teaching method did not matter much once student interest was apparent.[19][20] In a review of an
algebra lesson taught by Neill as recounted through Herb Snitzer's Living at Summerhill, Richard
Bailey described Neill's teaching technique as "simply awful" for his lack of student engagement,
inarticulate explanations, and insults directed at students.[21] Bailey criticized Neill's absolution of
responsibility for his pupils' academic performance, and his view that charismatic instruction was a
form of persuasion that weakened child autonomy.[22] Ronald Swartz referred to Neill's method as
Socratic, about which Bailey disagreed.[17]
Neill was not religious and erred on the side of anti-religious. Despite his rejection of God, he would
flippantly remark that Summerhill was the only Christian school in England when comparing its
philosophy to that of Christ. Neill saw the doctrine of "original sin" as a means of control and sought
a world ruled by love and self-examination.[23] Like Freud, he felt that children denied sexuality in their
youth begot adults similarly fearful of their own sexuality.[24]
Philosophy[edit]
See also: Philosophy of Summerhill School
Neill felt that children (and human nature) were innately good, and that children became virtuous and
just naturally when allowed to grow without adult imposition of morality.[25]Children did not need to be
coaxed or goaded into desirable behavior, as their natural state was satisfactory and their natural
inclinations "in no way immoral".[26] If left alone, children would become self-regulating, reasonable
and ethical adults.[27] Together with Homer Lane, Neill supported personal freedoms for children to
live as they please without adult interference, and called this position "on the side of the
child".[25] Neill's practice can be summarized as providing children with space, time, and
empowerment for personal exploration and with freedom from adult fear and coercion.[28]
The aim of life, to Neill, was "to find happiness, which means to find interest."[29] Likewise, the
purpose of Neill's education was to be happy and interested in life,[30] and children needed complete
freedom to find their interests.[29] Neill considered happiness an innate characteristic that deteriorated
if children were denied personal freedom. Such unhappiness led to repressed and psychologically
disordered adults.[30] He blamed a "sick and unhappy" society for widespread unhappiness.[31] Neill
claimed that society harboured fears of life, children and emotions that were continually bequeathed
to the next generation. He felt that children turned to self-hate and internal hostility when denied an
outlet for expression in adult systems of emotional regulation and manipulation. Likewise, children
taught to withhold their sexuality would see such feelings negatively, which would fuel disdain for
self. Neill thought that calls for obedience quenched the natural needs of children. Moreover, their
needs could not be fulfilled by adults or a society that simultaneously prolonged their unhappiness,
although perhaps a school like Summerhill could help.[24]
Neill ... believed that the best thing teachers could do was to leave children alone to develop naturally.
As for "interest", Neill felt it came organically and spontaneously as a prerequisite for learning. Neill
considered forced instruction (without pupil interest) a destructive waste of time.[33] Earlier in his
career, he wrote that human interest releases emotions that otherwise congests a person.[29] He
added that education's role is to facilitate that release, with Summerhill actualizing this
concept.[34] Neill never defines "true interest" and does not account for the social influences on child
interest.[35] Bailey felt that this omission discredits Neill's position against external influence. Bailey
also cited "adaptive preferences" literature, where human interests change based on their
surroundings and circumstances, as evidence of how intrinsic interest can be externally
influenced.[36] Bailey also dubbed Neill's views on intelligence as "innatist" and fatalist that children
had naturally set capabilities and limitations.[37] Neill saw contemporary interventionist practice as
doing harm by emphasizing conformity and stifling children's natural drive to do as they please.[16]
Neill did not identify with the progressive educators of his time.[38] They advocated far gentler
authority in child-rearing, which Neill considered more insidious than overt authority and altogether
unnecessary.[39] All imposed authority, even if meant well, was unjustified.[40] He felt that adults
asserted authority for its feelings of power, and that this motive was a type of repression.[40] In Neill's
philosophy, the goal was maintenance of happiness through avoidance of repressive habits from
society.[40] Despite Neill's common citation as a leader within progressive education, his ideas were
considerably more radical, and he was called an extremist by other radicals.[38] Unlike Friedrich
Frbel, Neill did not view children with romantic innocence. He saw their animalistic traits as qualities
to be "outgrown with time and freedom".[41] Neill also considered his role in providing emotional
support.[16]
Emotional education trumped intellectual needs, in Neill's eyes, and he was associated with anti-
intellectualism.[42] In actuality, he had a personal interest in scholarship and used his autobiography
near the end of his life to profess the necessity of both emotion and intellect in education,[43] though
he often took jabs at what he saw to be education's overemphasis on book-learning.[44] Neill felt that
an emotional education freed the intellect to follow what it pleased, and that children required an
emotional education to keep up with their own gradual developmental needs. This education usually
entailed copious amounts of play and distance from the adult anxieties of work and ambition.[45] Neill
was influenced by Sigmund Freud's theories of psychoanalysis, Homer Lane's interpretation of
Freud, and later, by the unorthodox sexual theories of Wilhelm Reich. The reverence for Reich
appears in the abundant correspondence between them.[46] Neill accepted Reich's claims
about cosmic energy and his utopian ideas on human sexuality. In Reich's view, "discharge" of
sexual energy leads to happiness, whereas lack of such discharge leads to unhappiness and
"rigidity". Although not a trained therapist, Neill gave psychoanalytic private lessons to individual
children, designed to unblock impasses in their inner energies. Neill also offered body massage, as
suggested by Reich. Neill later found that freedom cured better than this therapy.[16]
Richard Bailey placed Neill alongside William Godwin, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Voltaire,
and Robert Owen in Thomas Sowell's "unconstrained vision" tradition, where human potential is
naturally unlimited and human development is dependent on environment and not
incentives.[47] Bailey also compared Neill's thoughts on coercion to those of Godwin, who felt that
regulation through reward and punishment stunted growth. Neill saw moral instruction as a wedge
between natural instinct and conformity and thought children were best off without it.[25] Neill trusted
the natural inclinations of children and saw no need to externally and purposefully influence their
behavior.[26] Denis Lawton likened Neill's ideas to Rousseauan "negative education", where children
discover for themselves instead of receiving instruction.[32] Neill is commonly associated with
Rousseau for their similar thoughts on human nature, although Neill claimed to not have read
Rousseau's Emile, or On Education until near the end of his life.[48] John Cleverley and D. C. Phillips
declared Neill "the most notable figure in the Rousseauean tradition", and Frank Flanagan credited
Neill with actualizing what Rousseau envisioned.[4] Marc-Alexandre Prud-homme and Giuliano Reis
found the comparison "inappropriate" on the basis of Rousseau's views on gender.[49]
Peter Hobson found Neill's philosophy of education incomplete, oversimplified, without a "coherent
theory of knowledge", and too dependent on his experience instead of philosophical
position.[50][51] When presented with Hobson's position, four experts on Neill and Summerhill
considered his assertions "irrelevant".[51] Joel Spring likened Neill's views on the family to that
of Mary Wollstonecraft, in that the parents would share power equally.[52]
Freedom, not license[edit]
See also: Freedom versus license
When Neill said children should be free, he did not mean complete freedom, but freedom without
licensethat everyone can do as they like unless such action encroaches upon another's
freedom.[53] As such, adults could and should protect children from danger, but not trample their self-
regulation.[54] Neill emphasized that adult removal from child affairs was distinct from disregard for
their security.[55] He felt that children met their own limits naturally.[16] Neill believed in equal rights
between parents and children, and that undesirable "disciplined" or "spoiled" homes were created
when those rights were imbalanced.[56] He felt it unnecessary to fulfil all of childhood's requests and
had great disdain for spoiled children.[57] Summerhill children were naturally restricted by the school's
limited teaching expertise and low funds.[58]
Bailey wrote that Neill did not have full faith in self-regulation due to his emphasis on the necessity of
making specific environments for children.[55] Robin Barrow argued that Neill's idea of self-regulation
was contradictory, when its intent was, more simply, the extent to which children need to abide by
external restraints.[55] Bailey added that children cannot know the extent to which dull and unknown
subjects can be exciting without guidance.[59] He felt that Neill's belief in children's innate and realistic
wisdom did not accommodate human characteristics "such as error, prejudice, and ignorance",
ascribed genius-level intelligence to children, and did not consider social aspects in child decision-
making.[60]
Self-governance[edit]
Self-governance was a central idea to Summerhill, and is perhaps its "most fundamental
feature".[56] Summerhill held a weekly general meeting that decided the school's rules and settled
school disputes, where every member of the communitystaff and student alikehad a single
vote.[61] Almost everyone in the school attended the meeting, and children always held the
majority.[61] Meetings were managed by an elected Chairperson.[61] At times, the school had over 200
rules.[62]
Summerhill sought to produce individualists conscious of their surrounding social order, and Neill
chose the self-governance of Homer Lane's Little Commonwealth for the basis of that lesson.[63] The
general meeting replaced teacher authority with communal control, which freed teachers from their
roles as disciplinarians and instructed children in the role of democratic participation and the role of
rules.[64] Additionally, reports of teacherstudent disputes were rare.[65] Neill felt that the community's
authority never created resentment in those subject to sanctions.[61] Sven Muller contended that the
meeting was more useful than discipline for creating civic-minded citizens.[64] An ex-pupil recalled
some of the wild ideas Neill would propose at the meeting, and while the students would vote him
down, she later recounted how the exercise was also intended as a lesson for the staff on the power
of the meeting and communal authority.[66] Neill considered self-governance "the most valuable asset
in education and life" and the general meeting "more important than all the textbooks in the world".[64]
On occasion, Neill exercised unilateral decision-making as the owner of the school, despite his
emphasis on the authority figure-less nature of the school.[65] Instances include when he once made
a decision after the group's discussion protracted, and when he once asserted himself
dictator.[65] Ultimately, the school's freedom was Neill's to structure.[65]
Writings[edit]
Neill wrote 20 books in his lifetime.[67] His style was simple and friendly, unlike didactic literature from
the era.[68] His topics included the balance of authority and the thoughtsfeelings relationship.[69]
Summerhill[edit]
Main article: Summerhill (book)
The 1960 release of Summerhill catapulted Neill into the public view. Richard Bailey described its
result as "an American cult" of Summerhillian schools and their support organizations. The book sold
well and made Neill into a figurehead of new interest in education. Bailey added that the
unpretentious book's message was easier to impart than Deweyan thought, and that its release
inspired Neill's education critic contemporaries as to the viability of their ideas.[70]
Idealism is when you envision or see things in an ideal or perfect manner. Realism, on the
other hand, tends toward a more pragmatic and actual view of a situation. ... In philosophy,
when discussing the issues of perception, idealism is a theory that states that our reality is
shaped by our thoughts and ideas.
Anna Freud
A child psychoanalyst and theorist who identified defense mechanisms.
Mature Ego
Typically meets the conflicting demands of the id and superego through a process of
acknowledging the demands and developing a way of meeting these challenges as
much as possible.
Immature Ego
Is apt to resort to the frequent use of defense mechanisms, which involves self-
deception and deception to others.
Compensation
Is the seeking of success in one area of life as a substitution for success in another area
of life that has been limited because of personal or environmental barriers.
Example of Compensation
A disabled athlete becoming a computer expert.
Conversion
Is the transformation of anxiety into a physical dysfunction, such as paralysis or
blindness, which does not have a physiological basis.
Example of Conversion
An individual who was abused and became blind as a defense against further abuse.
Denial
Is a refusal to acknowledge an aspect of reality, including one's experience, because to
do so would result in overwhelming anxiety.
Example of Denial
An individual who manifested symptoms of cancer but refused to accept the diagnosis
because he or she could not face the truth.
Displacement
Is a shifting of negative feelings one has about a person or situation onto a different
person or situation.
Example of Displacement
A husband who was angry with his boss and then berated his wife when he came
home.
Identification
A mechanism by which anxiety is handled through identifying with a person or thing
producing the anxiety, such as "identifying with a kidnapper."
Isolation of Affect
Is a mechanism by which painful feelings are separated from the incident that triggered
them initially.
Intellectualization
Is a mechanism by which reasoning is used to block difficult feelings and it involves
removing one's emotions from a stressful event.
Example of Intellectualization
A wife who refers to her husband's heart attack in medical terminology rather than
expressing her emotions.
Projection
One's own characteristics are denied and instead seen as being characteristics of
someone else.
Example of Projection
An individual who criticizes her mother for being a perfectionist when she herself is
extremely compulsive about having every detail correct.
Rationalization
Is a mechanism by which a person substitutes a more socially acceptable, logical
reason for an action rather than identifying the real motivation.
Example of Rationalization
An individual who states that she is unable to attend a family outing because she has a
work project that she has to complete, when she doesn't really want to attend.
Reaction Formation
Is adopting a behavior that is the antithesis of the instinctual urge.
Regression
Is reverting to more primitive mode of coping associated with earlier and safer
developmental periods.
Example of Regression
An individual who, when upset, clutches her blanket for security.
Repression
Is the unconscious pushing of anxiety-producing thoughts and issues out of the
conscious and into the unconscious.
Example of Repression
An individual who cannot remember being sexually abused as a child because she has
pushed those memories into her unconscious. The memories may not be recalled
except through psychoanalysis or hypnosis.
Sublimation
Is a mechanism by which intolerable drives or desires are diverted into activities that are
acceptable.
Example of Sublimation
An individual who has strong sexual urges and redirects those urges into sports
activities.
Substitution
Is a mechanism by which a person replaces an unacceptable goal with an acceptable
one.
Example of Substitution
An individual who wanted to be a tattoo artist but decided instead to become an oil
painter instead because of pressure by his family.
Undoing
Is a mechanism by which an individual engages in a repetitious ritual in an attempt to
reverse an unacceptable action previously taken.
Example of Undoing
An individual who ritualistically washes his hands in attempt to symbolically wash off
blood that was on his hands when he got into a fight.
Thorndikes Law of Effect
Law of effect is the belief that a pleasing after-effect strengthens the action that produced it.[8]
The law of effect was published by Edward Thorndike in 1905 and states that when an S-R
association is established in instrumental conditioning between the instrumental response and the
contextual stimuli that are present, the response is reinforced and the S-R association holds the sole
responsibility for the occurrence of that behavior. Simply put, this means that once the stimulus and
response are associated, the response is likely to occur without the stimulus being present. It holds
that responses that produce a satisfying or pleasant state of affairs in a particular situation are more
likely to occur again in a similar situation. Conversely, responses that produce a discomforting,
annoying or unpleasant effect are less likely to occur again in the situation.
Psychologists have been interested in the factors that are important in behavior change and control
since psychology emerged as a discipline. One of the first principles associated with learning and
behavior was the Law of Effect, which states that behaviors that lead to satisfying outcomes are
likely to be repeated, whereas behaviors that lead to undesired outcomes are less likely to recur.[9]
Thorndike's Puzzle-Box. The graph demonstrates the general decreasing trend of the cat's response times with
each successive trial
Thorndike emphasized the importance of the situation in eliciting a response; the cat would not go
about making the lever-pressing movement if it was not in the puzzle box but was merely in a place
where the response had never been reinforced. The situation involves not just the cat's location but
also the stimuli it is exposed to, for example, the hunger and the desire for freedom. The cat
recognizes the inside of the box, the bars, and the lever and remembers what it needs to do to
produce the correct response. This shows that learning and the law of effect are context-specific.
In an influential paper, R. J. Herrnstein (1970)[10] proposed a quantitative relationship between
response rate (B) and reinforcement rate (Rf):
B = k Rf / (Rf0 + Rf)
where k and Rf0 are constants. Herrnstein proposed that this formula, which he derived from
the matching law he had observed in studies of concurrent schedules of reinforcement, should be
regarded as a quantification of the law of effect. While the qualitative law of effect may be a
tautology, this quantitative version is not.
Example[edit]
An example is often portrayed in drug addiction. When a person uses a substance for the first time
and receives a positive outcome, they are likely to repeat the behavior due to the reinforcing
consequence. Over time, the person's nervous system will also develop a tolerance to the drug.
Thus only by increasing dosage of the drug will provide the same satisfaction, making it dangerous
for the user.[11]
Thorndike's Law of Effect can be compared to Darwin's theory of natural selection in which
successful organisms are more likely to prosper and survive to pass on their genes to the next
generation, while the weaker, unsuccessful organisms are gradually replaced and "stamped out". It
can be said that the environment selects the "fittest" behavior for a situation, stamping out any
unsuccessful behaviors, in the same way it selects the "fittest" individuals of a species. In an
experiment that Thorndike conducted, he placed a hungry cat inside a "puzzle box", where the
animal could only escape and reach the food once it could operate the latch of the door. At first the
cats would scratch and claw in order to find a way out, then by chance / accident, the cat would
activate the latch to open the door. On successive trials, the behaviour of the animal would become
more habitual, to a point where the animal would operate without hesitation. The occurrence of the
favourable outcome, reaching the food source, only strengthens the response that it produces.
Colwill and Rescorla for example made all rats complete the goal of getting food pellets and liquid
sucrose in consistent sessions on identical variable-interval schedules.[12]
Noam Chomsky
AMERICAN LINGUIST
WRITTEN BY:
James A. McGilvray
See Article History
Noam Chomsky
AMERICAN LINGUIST
ALSO KNOWN AS
BORN
Philadelphia, Pennsylvania
NOTABLE WORKS
Syntactic Structures
Aspects of the Theory of Syntax
Necessary Illusions: Thought Control in Democratic Societies
The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory
SUBJECTS OF STUDY
language
philosophy of language
rationalism
innate idea
transformational grammar
DEMYSTIFIED / TECHNOLOGY
How Does Wi-Fi Work?
SPOTLIGHT / ANIMALS
The 1916 Shark Attacks That Gave Sharks a Bad Rap
DEMYSTIFIED / SOCIETY
Why Do We Carve Pumpkins at Halloween?
Whereas Goodman assumed that the mind at birth is largely a tabula
rasa (blank slate) and that language learning in children is essentially a
conditioned response to linguistic stimuli, Chomsky held that the basic
principles of all languages, as well as the basic range of concepts they are
used to express, are innately represented in the human mind and that
language learning consists of the unconscious construction of a grammar from
these principles in accordance with cues drawn from the childs
linguistic environment. Whereas Harris thought of the study of language as
the taxonomic classification of data, Chomsky held that it is the discovery,
through the application of formal systems, of the innate principles that make
possible the swift acquisition of language by children and the ordinary use of
language by children and adults alike. And whereas Goodman believed that
linguistic behaviour is regular and caused (in the sense of being a specific
response to specific stimuli), Chomsky argued that it is incited by
social contextand discourse context but essentially uncausedenabled by a
distinct set of innate principles but innovative, or creative. It is for this reason
that Chomsky believed that it is unlikely that there will ever be a full-
fledged science of linguistic behaviour. As in the view of the 17th-century
French philosopher Rne Descartes, according to Chomsky, the use of
language is due to a creative principle, not a causal one.
BRITANNICA LISTS & QUIZZES
SOCIETY QUIZ
Australian Government and Political System
HISTORY LIST
Famous Mustaches in History
SCIENCE QUIZ
Types of Chemical Reactions
ANIMALS LIST
Longhair Cat Breeds
It has frequently been observed that children acquire both concepts and
language with amazing facility and speed, despite the paucity or even
absence of meaningful evidence and instruction in their early years.
The inference to the conclusion that much of what they acquire must be innate
is known as the argument from the poverty of the stimulus. Specifying
precisely what children acquire and how they acquire it are aspects of what
Chomsky called in LSLT the fundamental problem of linguistics. In later work
he referred to this as Platos problem, a reference to Platos attempt (in
his dialogue the Meno) to explain how it is possible for an uneducated child to
solve geometrical problems with appropriate prompting but without any
specific training or background in mathematics. Unlike Plato, however,
Chomsky held that solving Platos problem is a task for natural science,
specifically cognitive science and linguistics.
In a 2002 article, The Language Faculty, Chomsky and his coauthors Marc
Hauser and W. Tecumseh Fitch divided the language faculty in a way that
reflected what had been Chomskys earlier distinction between competence
and performance. The faculty of language in the narrow sense (FLN)
amounts to the recursive computational system alone, whereas the faculty in
the broad sense (FLB) includes perceptual-articulatory systems (for sound
and sign) and conceptual-intentional systems (for meaning). These are the
systems with which the computational system interacts at its interfaces.
Regarding evolution, the authors point out that, although there are
homologues and analogs in other species for the perceptual-articulatory and
conceptual-intentional systems, there are none for the computational system,
or FLN. Conceivably, some cognitive systems of animals, such as the
navigational systems of birds, might involve recursion, but there is no
computational system comparable to FLN, in particular none that links sound
and meaning and yields unbounded sentential output. FLN is arguably what
makes human beings cognitively distinct from other creatures.
As suggested earlier, UG, or the language faculty narrowly understood (FLN),
may consist entirely of Merge and perhaps some parameters specific to
language. This raises the question of what the biological basis of FLN must
be. What distinctive fact of human biology, or the human genome, makes FLN
unique to humans? In a 2005 article, Three Factors in Language Design,
Chomsky pointed out that there is more to organic development and growth
than biological (genomic) specification and environmental input. A third factor
is general conditions on growth resulting from restrictions on possible physical
structures and restrictions on data analysis, including those that might figure
in computational systems (such as language). For example, a bees genome
does not have to direct it to build hives in a hexagonal lattice. The lattice is a
requirement imposed by physics, since this structure is the most stable and
efficient of the relevant sort. Analogous points can be made about the growth,
structure, and operation of the human brain. If the parameters of UG are not
specified by the language-specific parts of the human genome but are instead
the result of third factors, the only language-specific information that the
genome would need to carry is an instruction set for producing a single
principle, Merge (which takes external and internal forms). And if this is the
case, then the appearance of language could have been brought about by a
single genetic mutation in a single individual, so long as that mutation were
transmissible to progeny. Obviously, the relevant genes would provide great
advantages to any human who possessed them. A saltational account such
as this has some evidence behind it: 50,000 to 100,000 years ago, humans
began to observe the heavens, to draw and paint, to wonder, and to develop
explanations of natural phenomenaand the migration from Africa began.
Plausibly, the introduction of the computational system of language led to this
remarkable cognitive awakening.
Politics
Chomskys political views seem to be supported to some extent by his
approach to the study of language and mind, which implies that the capacity
for creativity is an important element of human nature. Chomsky often notes,
however, that there is only an abstract connection between his theories of
language and his politics. A close connection would have to be based on a
fully developed science of human nature, through which fundamental human
needs could be identified or deduced. But there is nothing like such a science.
Even if there were, the connection would additionally depend on the
assumption that the best form of political organization is one that maximizes
the satisfaction of human needs. And then there would remain the question of
what practical measures should be implemented to satisfy those needs.
Clearly, questions such as this cannot be settled by scientific means.
Although Chomsky was always interested in politics, he did not become
publicly involved in it until 1964, when he felt compelled to lend his voice to
protests against the U.S. role in the Vietnam War (or, as he prefers to say, the
U.S. invasion of Vietnam), at no small risk to his career and his personal
safety. He has argued that the Vietnam War was only one in a series of cases
in which the United States used its military power to gain or consolidate
economic control over increasingly larger areas of the developing world. In the
same vein, he regards the domestic political scene of the United States and
other major capitalist countries as theatres in which major corporations and
their elite managers strive to protect and enhancetheir economic privileges
and political power.
In democracies like the United States, in which the compliance of ordinary
citizens cannot be guaranteed by force, this effort requires a form of
propaganda: the powerful must make ordinary citizens believe that vesting
economic control of society in the hands of a tiny minority of the population is
to their benefit. Part of this project involves enlisting the help of
intellectualsthe class of individuals (primarily journalists and academics)
who collect, disseminate, and interpret political and economic information for
the public. Regrettably, Chomsky argues, this task has proved remarkably
easy.
As a responsible (rather than mercenary) member of the intellectual class,
Chomsky believes that it is his obligation to provide ordinary citizens with the
information they needed to draw their own conclusions and to make their own
decisions about vital political and economic issues. As he wrote in Powers
and Prospects (1996),
The responsibility of the writer as a moral agent is to try to bring the truth about matters of human
significance to an audience that can do something about them.
Some of Chomskys critics have claimed that his political and media studies
portray journalists as actively engaged in a kind of conspiracyan extremely
unlikely conspiracy, of course, given the degree of coordination and control it
would require. Chomskys response is simply that the assumption of
conspiracy is unnecessary. The behaviour of journalists in the mainstream
media is exactly what one would expect, on average, given the power
structure of the institutions in which they are employed, and it is predictable in
the same sense and for the same reasons that the behaviour of the president
of General Motors is predictable. In order to succeedin order to be hired and
promotedmedia personnel must avoid questioning the interests of the
corporations they work for or the interests of the elite minority who run those
corporations. Because journalists naturally do not wish to think of themselves
as mercenaries (no one does), they engage in what amounts to a form of self-
deception. They typically think of themselves as stalwartdefenders of the truth
(as suggested by the slogan of the New York Times, All the news thats fit to
print), but when state or corporate interests are at stake they act otherwise, in
crucially important ways. In short, very few of them are willing or even able to
live up to their responsibility as intellectuals to bring the truth about matters of
human significance to an audience that can do something about them.
Functions of planning
select the correct or best answer (e.g., multiple-choice, true-false, matching questions).
respond to a question with a word, phrase, or essayanswer (e.g., short answer, essay questions).
complete a limited task that is highlystructured (e.g., selecting the appropriate tool for a task,
determining the area of given rectangle, writing a brief paragraph on a given topic).
comprehensive task that is lessstructured (e.g., writing a research report, drawing the water cycle,
creating astructure out of Lego's that will support 10 pounds).