Divergence
Divergence
Divergence
Divergencies of
Perception
The Possibilities of Merleau-Pontian
Phenomenology in Analyses of
Contemporary Art
SAARA HACKLIN
Aesthetics
Department of Philosophy, History,
Culture and Art Studies
University of Helsinki, Finland
http://ethesis.helsinki.fi/
Nord Print
Helsinki 2012
In memory of MEM
Supervised by:
Professor Arto Haapala
Faculty of Arts
University of Helsinki
and
Reviewed by:
Professor Véronique M. Fóti
Department of Philosophy
Pennsylvania State University, USA
and
Discussed with:
Professor Renée van de Vall
Department of Literature & Art
Faculty of Arts & Social Sciences
Maastricht University, The Netherlands
Abstract
vii
viii ABSTRACT
ix
x ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
Abstract vii
Acknowledgements ix
1 Introduction 1
3 Conceptions of Seeing 51
3.1 Cartesian Vision . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 52
3.2 Phenomenology on Seeing: From Image to Icon . . . . . 62
3.3 Dissolving Seeing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 78
xii
CONTENTS xiii
8 Conclusions 231
Bibliography 241
Works by Maurice Merleau-Ponty — with Abbreviations . . . 241
Works by Other Authors . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 243
Dictionaries and Other Resources . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 270
A Images 271
The joint tradition of phenomenology and visual arts is very rich. Their
connection was established by early phenomenologists, such as Martin
Heidegger’s discussion of Vincent van Gogh’s paintings and Maurice
Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation of Paul Cézanne’s work. Even though
the connection between the two fields is close, philosophers’ discus-
sions of artworks have often been challenged, and not only by the
changing fields of arts.1 The relation of art and phenomenology has
been taken up during the last decades by various philosophers, such
as Edward Casey, Jacques Derrida, Éliane Escoubas, Jean-François
Lyotard, Jean-Luc Nancy, John Sallis, and others.2
Within the tradition, the influence of Maurice Merleau-Ponty
(1908–1961) is undisputed. His phenomenology of art is the point of
departure for my thesis. Merleau-Ponty has been known as the philoso-
pher of painting whose philosophical thinking developed through vi-
sual art. His willingness to approach art as a companion to or even
as a model for philosophy suggests not only that we should take the
primacy of perception as an ontological primacy, but also relate it to
the deeply radical, ethical choices that characterises the 21st century
discussion of art and aesthetics.
1 Here I refer to the manifold fields of contemporary art and the changes that
have occurred in art since 1960. As is well known, the form of artwork has become
multiple since the days of Heidegger and Merleau-Ponty. Moreover, some of this
development, for instance interest in the question of the body, has been influenced
by phenomenology. (Melville 1998; Potts 2000; Johansson 2009.)
2 This list is by no means exhaustive. Within early phenomenological and ex-
istential philosophy art was discussed by, for instance, Simone de Beauvoir, Mikel
Dufrenne, Henri Maldiney, Roman Ingarden and Jean-Paul Sartre, to name but
a few. More contemporary contributors are for instance Arnold Berleant, Mauro
Carbone, Véronique M. Fóti, Galen A. Johnson, Jacques Taminiaux, Renée van de
Vall and many more.
1
2 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION
the work and the spectator in an unprecedented manner so that the very experience
of art has changed in nature. The focus on the relation between the spectator and
the work of art has been underlined, for instance, by minimalism in the 1960s.
5 First published in the first number of journal Art de France, 1961, republished
with” that genuinely allows difference — and thus also questions some self-evident
aspects of the perceiver? This question is linked to a wider set of problems, such
as whether turning to thinking would always “normalise” things, or whether phi-
losophy is incapable of encountering the other or difference, and is always willing
to either assimilate or expel. (See, for instance, Armstrong 2000, 49; Derrida 1981,
20–22.)
3
time, and touch, as well as the question of the other. These themes are
interlinked with the examined works of art.
thesis I will touch on the relation of Husserl and Merleau-Ponty later on, but it is
not the main interest of the work. For more on the relation of the two thinkers,
see for instance, a study of the concept of perception in phenomenology Renaud
Barbaras’ Desire and Distance. Introduction to a Phenomenology of Perception
(2006) in which Husserl’s and Merleau-Ponty’s differences are discussed.
9 These approaches were already a critical target in the first part of his doctoral
men it transforms them into puppets [...]” VI, 77. “Pour une philosophie qui
s’installe dans la vision pure, le survol du panorama, il ne peut pas y avoir ren-
contre d’autrui : car le regard domine, il ne peut dominer que des choses, et s’il
tombe sur des hommes, il les transforme en mannequins [...]” VI, 107.
4 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION
the senses. As Renaud Barbaras writes: “it merges in reality with the
ontological question in its simplest sense, namely as an inquiry into
the meaning of the being of what is.”11 Through our experience we
have access to being, and thus in order to question being, we need to
examine the ways we open up to the world, namely perception. The
appearing of the world can be examined through the phenomenological
method.
In an early essay “Cézanne’s Doubt” (“La doute de Cézanne”,
1945)12 Merleau-Ponty began to fathom the connection between per-
ception, artistic expression and philosophical contemplation. He fo-
cused on painting and the painter’s work, the bodily gestures through
which the artist’s encountering with the world is turned into a paint-
ing. According to Merleau-Ponty, Cézanne painted the world as it was
becoming visible, not the world as a static object. Cézanne’s painting
process was shadowed by a continuous doubt; this doubt was elemental
for his working process, it drove him to start all over again, to chal-
lenge his own painting. Merleau-Ponty paralleled the working method
of the painter with those of a phenomenologist. For him, the interest-
ing question in art was not about beauty, but about the questions of
perception, expression, history, as well as the very structure of real-
ity.13
In Phenomenology of Perception Merleau-Ponty had already de-
veloped a theory of language and expression. He conceived that the
meaning of a gesture is immanent in it. There is no separate world of
hidden meaning outside the gesture. Likewise, there is no particular
sense somewhere outside the artwork.14 This idea is further reflected
in the title of his unfinished manuscript, The Visible and the Invisible
(Le visible et l’invisible, 1964), where both are intertwined or encroach
upon each other. “What this ultimately means is that the hallmark of
the visible is to have a lining of invisibility in the strict sense, which
11 Barbaras 2006, 1.
12 Firstpublished in Fontaine no 47, in December 1945, reprinted in Sens et
non-sens (1948).
13 Galen A. Johnson has recently published a reading where he traces the ques-
tion of the beautiful and the sublime in Merleau-Ponty. However, his point of de-
parture is in how the questions Merleau-Ponty primarily discussed were elsewhere
than in the thematics of beautiful. (Johnson 2010, 13.)
14 Also, artwork may supersede all causal and linear relation, so that even the
sense that we give to the artworks later on has been issued by the works. (Œ,
62/139.) NB: If not indicated otherwise, the page numbers refer first to the French
original and then to the English translation.
5
15 Œ 147. “Ceci veut dire finalement que le propre du visible est d’avoir une
doublure d’invisible au sens strict, qu’il rend présent comme une certain absence”
Œ, 85.
16 Œ, 146. “c’est le moyen qui m’est donné d’être absent de moi-même” Œ, 81.
17 The term chair originates from Husserl’s leib in Ideen II. See Merleau-Ponty’s
“The Philosopher and His Shadow” (“Le philosophe et son ombre” 1953). (PO,
271/166; Saint Aubert 2004, 147.)
18 VI, 139. “La chair n’est pas matière, n’est pas esprit, n’est pas substance. Il
logue with itself, and that the works of art serve as a pretext for an
inner dialogue of philosophy.
Contemporary art opens views into the complex experiences of per-
ception and the meaning of being. Within the thesis, the selected art-
works — I will use the term “case studies”21 — are of varied origin.
My choices include paintings by Tiina Mielonen, a photographic work
by Christian Mayer, a film by Douglas Gordon and Philippe Parreno,
and an installation by Monika Sosnowska. The choice of artworks has
been directed by the research questions. They bring forth themes con-
cerning space, movement, time, touch and the question of the other.
These works carry features that, to me, resonate with, and also chal-
lenge, the phenomenological approach of Merleau-Ponty. The twofold
research frame of the thesis sets a particular weight on the selected
artworks. Through the works I also wish to open up critical angles to
Merleau-Ponty’s thinking. In a sense, the artworks can be understood
as ways of testing the limits of philosophy.
For instance, one of the principal purposes was to examine a cer-
tain absence in Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy: the exclusion or scarce
discussion of the avant-garde art of his time, such as photography,
is striking in Merleau-Ponty’s corpus. Naturally, it must be acknowl-
edged that Merleau-Ponty, who himself underlined that he was simply
a layman when it came to art, had a profound sensitivity and passion
for different arts. He did not limit himself only to Cézanne’s paintings,
but wrote broadly about the visual arts, and also analysed literature.
Yet, it seems that the new art, especially the new media, of the time
was not a particular interest of his. One example is his critical view
of photography. He claimed that photography destroys the metamor-
phosis of time, and he also had a certain distrust of abstract painting.
These preferences have led to the impression that different media pose
both an opportunity and a challenge when considering the scope and
coverage of Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology. Even though his remarks
may appear irrelevant in connection with contemporary art, I would
like to take them as an invitation to test Merleau-Ponty’s approach to
art in relation to the art of our time, and especially examine art made
in different media. What is it that the contemporary art of our time
can open our thinking to? By bracketing all questions of being, and by
concentrating on the ways of appearing, phenomenology offers a way
to cultivate the sensitivity that artworks continuously seem to demand
21 The
term “case study” is here used of the artworks discussed, the four examples
that contribute to the theoretical base of the thesis.
7
from the viewers. In relation to new forms of art, I argue for a certain
double-movement: we must at the same time both put in parenthesis
the question of the medium — we must not be fixated on the diffi-
culties that the choice of medium and technology may include — and
take into consideration the question of materiality and the challenge
it provides.
Against this background, one of the features directing the choice of
works had to do with the variety of media. I wanted to see what hap-
pens when Merleau-Ponty’s thinking is taken out of its comfort zone.
In traditional readings, the home ground for Merleau-Ponty is con-
sidered to be painting. But what comes about when Merleau-Ponty’s
thought is set alongside of contemporary works? When does it become
outdated, where does it open up new insights? My choices include
paintings, photography, moving image, and an installation. However,
the selected artworks do not form a particular school or style of art.
Further, I wish to avoid a setting where the medium becomes too cen-
tral in a time, when artists are increasingly creating hybrid works and
varying their medium depending on the work at hand.22 Instead, the
works address different questions, and through them I examine specific
concepts that were central to Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology. In the
discussion of the works, I wish to pay special attention to the rela-
tionship of the work of art and its beholder. What kind of relation is
created between the two? What kind of encountering do the works en-
able, what kind of spectatorial subject do they presuppose? What are
the conditions of “seeing with” in the particular cases? Does “seeing
with” lose its aptitude at some point?
I am consciously bringing together works made in various media,
suggesting that the particular materiality could be ignored and be
taken as a serious challenge for phenomenological thinking. I wish to
stress that the artworks have been exhibited in very different situa-
tions. For example, Sonsowska’s installation was made for a particular
exhibition and can no longer be accessed, whereas Gordon and Par-
reno’s film can be, if so wished, viewed at home. Their film, moreover,
crosses the boundaries between contemporary art and cinema.23 De-
spite the variation of the artworks, my thesis is limited to the visual
arts. I have chosen to discuss pieces that can be classified as paint-
22 For instance, Rosalind Krauss has argued that the medium is a series of con-
24 The bodily aspects of both performance art and dance have been quite widely
discussed. Within dance, see for instance the works of Maxine Sheets-Johnstone:
The Phenomenology of Dance (1979) and The Primacy of Movement (1998); Son-
dra Horton Fraleigh: Dance and the Lived Body: A Descriptive Aesthetics (1987)
and Dancing Identity. Metaphysics in Motion (2004); Jaana Parviainen: Bodies
Moving and Moved: A Phenomenological Analysis of the Dancing Subject and
the Cognitive and Ethical Values of Dance Art (1998); Leena Rouhiainen Liv-
ing Transformative Lives: Freelance Dance Artists Brought into Dialogue with
Merleau-Ponty’s Phenomenology (2003). Within performance studies, see Amelia
Jones: Body Art/Performing the Subject (1998); Susan Kozel: Closer. Performance,
Technologies, Phenomenology (2007).
25 See especially Merleau-Ponty’s “Everywhere and Nowhere” (“Partout et nulle
part”), a preface to Les philosophes célèbres, and “The Philosopher and His Shadow
(“Le philosophe et son ombre”), both published in Signs (Signes, 1960). Also The
Incarnate Subject. Malebranche, Biran, and Bergson on the Union of Body and
Soul (L’Union de l’âme et du corps chez Malebranche, Biran, et Bergson), a lecture
series given in L’École Normale Supérieure in 1947–48.
9
Husserl and René Descartes. Also their thought was taken further, be-
yond, by Merleau-Ponty in search of the lacunae and limitations of
past philosophers. In my reading of Merleau-Ponty I have not lim-
ited myself to any particular period of his thinking, but instead I have
searched for different thematics that resonate with the chosen works of
art. Secondly, I take up his use of case studies. A prime example of his
own methodical use of case studies is to be found in Phenomenology of
Perception. As is well known, Merleau-Ponty had a particular interest
in empirical sciences as well as the arts. In both The Structure of Be-
havior (La structure du comportement, 1942) and Phenomenology of
Perception, he is in dialogue with empirical sciences, critically exam-
ining particular questions of psychology and biology of his time. One
of the most famous examples is his analysis of the case of Schneider.
This case refers to a patient called Schneider, examined by psycholo-
gists Kurt Goldstein and Adler Gelb. Schneider was wounded in the
First World War and was suffering from several problems, among oth-
ers difficulties in performing abstract tasks.26 Merleau-Ponty’s method
of discussing Schneider’s symptoms consisted of investigating a partic-
ular case that was examined within empirical sciences, thus falling
within objective thought. However, through using a case study, in this
case a particular medical description, his objective was to test his own
view, the phenomenological approach. Also within art, Cézanne could
be understood as one of Merleau-Ponty’s case studies. I would like
to stress that his way of discussing arts already demonstrates a cer-
tain openness: in regard to arts, his use of case studies takes the form
of thinking of particular questions concerning perception, space and
movement through works of art.
26 The examinations of Schneider’s case have been questioned, but here the point
is not to consider whether the original research material was adequate, but to
demonstrate a certain method of using case studies.
10 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION
27 See, for instance, Stephen Melville’s article “Division of Gaze, or, Remarks on
pretation” I still feel that it is important to emphasise this point to avoid any
misunderstandings. For a valuable discussion of this subject from a phenomeno-
logical point of view, see “For and Against Interpretation” in Alan Paskow’s The
Paradoxes of Art: A Phenomenological Investigation (Paskow 2003, 204–50).
30 Watkin 2009, 1.
11
31 Naturally, the connection between art and philosophy has been made many
times over, see for instance Hanneke Grootenboer’s article “Introduction ‘The
Thought of Images’” (2007). Inspiring ideas have been presented, for instance,
by Irit Rogoff, Professor of Visual Culture at Goldsmiths, who argued that the
researcher must write about art in a non-possessing, non-objectifying manner so
that: “[...] the writing can begin to take the form of writing with art rather than
writing about art” (Rogoff 2003, 127.) Rogoff’s thoughts draw inspiration from
Jacques Derrida and Jean-Luc Nancy. I would suggest that Merleau-Ponty could
have also served as an influence.
32 See for instance Derrida 1981; Armstrong 2000; Hallward 2003; Rancière 2004
36 Visual culture, arguably the youngest of these fields, prioritises the every-
day experience of the visual. It may take as its point of departure anything from
mundane commercial imagery to artworks, and a distinction between the two, com-
mercials and fine art, is not relevant for my discussion. (Mirzoeff 1999, 9; Van de
Vall 2008, 79.) However, Irit Rogoff remarks that it is still extremely difficult for
her to define what visual culture is and that the demand to define the field of study
mostly comes from outside the field. (Rogoff 2005.)
14 CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION
the fields of art and philosophy in a new way. She writes that neither
philosophy nor aesthetics are solely interested in analysing the “es-
thésiologique” of experience, but both aim at realising this experience
through philosophical expression, which is — like artistic expression —
the creation or a form of poïêsis. Philosophy should think along with
painting. Slatman even proposes a new understanding of aesthetics;
following Escoubas, she, too, argues that aesthetics is philosophy, and
vice versa.38 Slatman’s ability to draw from various Merleau-Ponty’s
texts as well as her understanding of aesthetics resonates with the
tasks I have set myself in my thesis.
As known, there are a wide-range of phenomenologists discussing
visual arts, but not many of them take into account the different fields
of research concerning the visual arts. Renée van de Vall’s study on
spectatorship presents a very convincing proposal to bring philoso-
phy into the field of contemporary art. Van de Vall’s discussion At
the Edges of Vision: A Phenomenological Aesthetics of Contemporary
Spectatorship (2008) not only challenges or tests the phenomenologi-
cal approach by contrasting it to the different media which are used
in today’s visual culture, but she also relates phenomenology to other
fields such as visual culture studies. Within philosophy, Van de Vall’s
resources are multiple, referring to Lyotard and Merleau-Ponty among
others. Her work questions many common prejudices concerning con-
temporary media culture and its effects on spectatorship, showing how
phenomenology and visual art can be used in studying closer these
prejudices.
In addition, just as my case studies come from different fields of
art, so too the studies I have used reflect a variety of fields. For in-
stance, in my reading of the moving image I have turned to film studies,
where Vivian Sobchack has been one of the most influential pioneers
in applying phenomenological methods to film. Laura U. Marks’ study
on intercultural film are also relevant, especially Marks’ study of the
sensuous aspects of film and her readings of optic and haptic vision.39
What to Expect
Counting the introduction and conclusions the work consists of eight
chapters and it can be roughly divided into two: the first part contains
two chapters (2–3) that introduce Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of art
and the phenomenological method. The latter part of the thesis is made
up of four chapters (4–7). Each of them present a case study and a
discussion around varying themes — space, movement, time, touch, as
well as the question of the other — in Merleau-Ponty’s thinking and
visual arts. There is also a conclusive chapter (8). In the description of
the works, I will take as a starting point the way in which a particular
artwork appears to me. However, I am also aware that my personal
experiences open up limited observations and that different personal
histories would allow me to find new perspectives.40
In chapter 2 I briefly present Merleau-Ponty’s philosophical start-
ing point and outline the basic principles of his phenomenological
method. In this discussion I study the influence of Husserl on Merleau-
Ponty’s phenomenology. I also present the main elements of his phi-
losophy of art, most importantly his conceptions of expression and
spectatorship. The aim of the chapter is to show how Merleau-Ponty’s
principal concern is not to create a comprehensive aesthetics, but to
discuss philosophical questions — most importantly the question of
perception — through artworks, thus showing that they both share
similar interests in relation to the world.
In chapter 3 the discussion is concentrated around the question
of image and icon. It further explores the original relation to work of
art, a topic that was discussed by Merleau-Ponty especially in “Eye
and Mind”. The focus is to discuss the conception of seeing, the criti-
cism Merleau-Ponty presented against the Cartesian understanding of
vision, and how Merleau-Ponty conceives the relationship to the work
of art. This chapter is the key to understanding what I consider to
be the most important aspect of Merleau-Ponty’s approach, namely
how encountering a work of art requires a shift in the attitude of the
spectator. The artwork is claimed to bypass and question our appre-
hension and apperception of “everyday objects”. Instead, the artwork
is understood as an icon in a phenomenological sense, where an art-
work creates a new kind of visibility. The question posed is how can
we approach the work in a phenomenological manner?
Chapter 4 moves on to the first of the case studies. In the begin-
40 I will touch upon this issue especially when discussing the film Zidane.
17
19
20 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
Proust and others “by reason of the same kind of attentiveness and
wonder, the same demand for awareness”.41 This is indicative of his
long-lasting interest in arts and his deep conviction that artistic vision
discloses essential structures of perception. There is in my opinion no
uniform conception of art or aesthetics that can be unquestionably laid
out, instead Merleau-Ponty combined his discourse of the arts with
his inquiries into perception that developed throughout his career.42
Merleau-Ponty’s conception of art intertwines with his phenomenolog-
ical approach to perception as a whole. In fact, I argue that there is no
separate Merleau-Pontian aesthetic theory, but the arts have a much
more central role in his thinking:43 philosophy and art have partially
the same aspirations and the same tasks — the task of disclosing our
fundamental relations to being. Thus, art gives a model for philoso-
phy but also a challenge; it manages to escape the limitations that
philosophy is bound to struggle with.
A clear-cut presentation of Merleau-Ponty’s “philosophy of art”
is difficult because his analyses, interpretations and interests varied.44
For instance, the focus on perception and the phenomenological method
were strongly emphasised in the early essay “Cézanne’s Doubt” (“Le
doute de Cézanne”, 1945). The essay also illustrates Merleau-Ponty’s
stand on the discussions of his time: he refused to explain artworks
through the personal life of the artist, but neither did he want to ex-
tract the artists from his or her historical context or to study the artist
41 PP, xxiv. “par la même genre d’attention et d’étonnement, par la même exi-
phases, i.e. whether there are radical breaks between early, middle and late periods,
or if the whole oeuvre should be seen as a consistent modulation. Also, Merleau-
Ponty himself kept evaluating his work, and especially in the last years presented
criticism towards his early work.
2.1. THE THEORETICAL CONTEXTS 21
collection Signs (Signes, 1960). The “Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence”
has many different influences and debates, such as a critique of André Malraux.
47 Merleau-Ponty’s relation to Sartre is complex. Their friendship turned into a
long debate, although the two came closer as Sartre wrote a moving preface to a
republished book by a mutual friend, Paul Nizan (1905–1940), Aden Arabie in 1960.
Their debate was deeply philosophical, political and aesthetic. (Grene 1993; Dastur
2000; Revault d’Allonnes 2001, 73; Dastur 2008.) For Merleau-Ponty’s critique
of Sartre, see “Sartre et l’ultra bolschevisme” (AD, 136–280). For an attempt to
shed light on Merleau-Ponty’s position regarding politics, see, for instance Lydia
Goehr’s article “Understanding the Engaged Philosopher” (2005). The traces of
the debate between Sartre and Merleau-Ponty can already be found in Merleau-
Ponty’s text early on: for instance, according to Saint Aubert, Sartre’s shadow is
present — without mentioning his name — in the last parts of “Cézanne’s Doubt”,
in the reading of Leonardo da Vinci and the question of liberty, and Sartre is still
addressed in the manuscript of The Visible and the Invisible. (Saint Aubert 2004,
302–304; 2006, 161–62.)
22 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
1960s.48
Concerning the arts that Merleau-Ponty preferred, his essays and
other shorter passages on art refer to a very rich and inspiring account
of arts. The artists he holds important seem to convey a logic: they
all are in some sense unprejudiced and renewing the art of their time.
However, by studying his preferences it is possible to find, for instance,
a modernist emphasis and a certain dislike — or at least absence — of
some of the avant-garde art of his own time.49 The preferences and the
neglects are of course related to the historical situation, and are thus
understandable. Having said that, I am interested in the omission and
absence of certain forms of art in Merleau-Ponty’s discourse, and will
argue that a closer examination is needed: for instance, in chapter 5,
I will look into Merleau-Ponty’s criticism of photography to show how
it does not need to encompass the whole field of photography, but is
directed against a certain attitude towards the world.
a wide range of scientist in the field of psychology — of which I shall not make a
full account here. For a detailed examination of the different influences on Merleau-
Ponty, see Emmanuel de Saint Aubert’s Du lien des êtres aux éléments de l’être
(2004), Le scénario cartésien (2005), and Vers une ontologie indirecte (2006).
2.1. THE THEORETICAL CONTEXTS 23
51 Husserl CM.
52 Saint Aubert shows that the references to Heidegger grew from 1958 onwards.
(Aubert 2006, 160.)
53 Dastur, 2001, 8. | To define Merleau-Ponty’s influences and position is of course
not indisputable. Barbaras, for instance, writes how towards the end of his career
in the Nature lectures as well as in The Visible and the Invisible Merleau-Ponty
approaches Bergson. According to Barbaras, in the chapter “Interrogation and
Intuition” Merleau-Ponty defines the authentic sense of philosophical interrogation
as a form of confrontation between Husserl and Bergson. (Barbaras 1998, 34.)
Barbaras has also shown how in Bergson’s critique of nothingness the beginnings
of phenomenological reduction can be found. (Barbaras 2006, 74.)
54 He studied in L’École normale supériure, and belonged to the same generation
(SC, v–viii).
24 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
56 PP,
x. “Le monde est là avant toute analyse que je puisse en faire [...]” PP, iv.
57 PP,
xi. “Le réel est à décrire, et non pas à construire ou à constituer” PP, iv.
58 PP, 174. “Ce n’est pas à l’objet physique que le corps peut être comparé, mais
are — no less than is the science of Lavoisier and Ampère — the explorations of
an invisible and the disclosure of a universe of ideas. The difference is simply that
this invisible, these ideas, unlike those of that science, cannot be detached from
the sensible appearances and be erected into a second positivity.” (VI, 149.) “La
littérature, la musique, les passions, mais aussi l’expérience du monde visible, sont
non moins que la science de Lavoisier et d’Ampère l’exploration d’un invisible et,
aussi bien qu’elle, dévoilement d’un univers d’idées. Simplement, cet invisible-là,
ces idées-là, ne se laissent pas comme les leurs détacher des apparences sensibles,
et ériger en seconde positivité.” (VI, 193–94.)
60 Dastur 2001, 42. | The theme of totality is especially in focus in Merleau-
gestures reveal the source of the thoughts and also the fundamental
means of being.62
The analogy between the human body and the work of art leads us
to study more closely what Merleau-Ponty’s conception of an artwork
is. By comparing the human body and the work of art, Merleau-Ponty
draws attention to a certain type of indivisibility and dependence. The
material aspects of a poem cannot be extracted from its meaning, they
are interdependent in a similar manner as the body and its style of
comportment and intending, both form indivisible wholes. Thus, what
distinguishes both artworks and lived bodies from thingly objects is
the relation of mutual dependency between the expression and the ex-
pressed that characterises both: the sense cannot be separated from
the expressive means that takes place in space and time.63 By the com-
parison between the lived body and the artwork, Merleau-Ponty does
not mean that they would be completely identical in their structures,
but he argues that both have the character of indivisible wholes. So at
stake is the understanding of the holistic nature of artworks.
The question of style is connected to a discussion of artistic style
and expression. Merleau-Ponty’s conception of style can be seen as a
comment on André Malraux and his The Voices of Silence (Les voix du
silence, 1951), a book that presents the history of art through original
masterpieces and where style plays a distinct role.64 For Merleau-Ponty
style is not something only certain people have privilege to; on the
contrary, it is an indistinguishable part of our being:
[...] what is given to him [the painter] with his style is not a
manner, a certain number of procedures or tics that he can in-
ventory, but a mode of formulation that is just as recognizable
for others and just as little visible to him as his silhouette or his
everyday gestures.65
Ponty developed a philosophy of language in his early works, and especially the
question of expression haunted him in the Phenomenology of Perception. His early
interest in speech was influenced by Husserl. Later, especially in the 1950s, when
he was interested in Ferdinand de Saussure’s structuralism. His reading of Saussure
was not particularly faithful, he for instance chose to focus on parole instead of
langue, which for Saussure was not the object of linguistic. For a detailed reading
of the structuralist influence, see Edie 1987.
62 PP, 176/174.
63 PP, 177/175.
64 Malraux 1953. | According to Merleau-Ponty, Malraux only looks at style
from the outside, observing its consequences, but not really getting inside it into
its functioning. (LV 86/90.)
65 LV, 90. “[...] ce qui lui est donné avec son style, ce n’est pas une manière,
2.1. THE THEORETICAL CONTEXTS 27
Style connects the artist and the world: his perception of the world
is marked by his style, it is not something that could be extracted or
abstracted from his particular way of relating to the world: “We must
see it [style] developing in the hollows of the painter’s perception as a
painter; style is an exigency that has issued from that perception.”66
Merleau-Ponty developed his conception of art by discussing visual
arts in more detail and by introducing the problems of literary expres-
sion. His early discussion on the analogy between human bodies and
works of art contains an important and permanent idea that he never
abandoned: he conceives all works of art as manifold forms of sensibility
and materiality informed by sense or meaning. These two, sensibility
and signification, cannot be separated — there is no signification that
could be extracted and presented in the sphere of ideas; and on the
other hand no material element of perception is without sense. This
argument pervades through his whole general project. From the early
publications to the last unfinished texts, there is a strong current that
ends in The Visible and Invisible. What is at stake is Merleau-Ponty’s
need for a philosophy that would avoid dichotomies, and that could,
for instance, describe perception without the traditional categories,
such as spirit and nature; subject and object. Towards the end of his
career, he coined the concepts of flesh (chair) and chiasm (le chiasme),
that made up the core of Merleau-Ponty’s radicalised criticism of the
conceptual limitations set by tradition. As a term, “flesh” comes from
Husserl’s discussion of embodiment, but Merleau-Ponty’s interpreta-
tion of the lived body (Leib, corps vivant, corps vécu) as a worldly
structure and process is developed further than Husserl’s.67 The con-
cept of flesh was designed to express the new ontology in which subject
and object would not be separate but dependent, and where the visible
and invisible could intertwine. As explained in the introduction, flesh
was to be understood as an element, in the Ancient sense. It is the
texture of the real.68 It could also be understood as a principle. I will
come back to the question of flesh later on.
Emmanuel de Saint Aubert points out, in Merleau-Ponty, the first uses of the word
“flesh” are not in connection with Husserl, but appeared in a dialogue with Sartre.
(Saint Aubert 2004, 147–205.)
68 Œ, 24/126.
28 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
I (1919, I).
30 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
Within this epochē, however, neither the sciences nor the sci-
entists have disappeared for us who practice the epochē. They
continue to be what they were before, in any case: facts in the
unified context of the pregiven life-world; except that, because
of the epochē, we do not function as sharing these interests, as
coworkers, etc.76
sophie. The first two parts were published in 1937, but the book itself was left
unfinished and the third part was published posthumously. (Carr 1970, xvii–xix.)
80 The theme of crisis was a topical theme which was recurrent in the early 20th
century.
2.2. THE QUESTION OF REDUCTION 31
versal subject of investigation in its own right? [...] The life which
effects world-validity in natural world-life does not permit of be-
ing studied from within the attitude of natural world-life. What
is required, then, is a total transformation of attitude, a com-
pletely unique, universal epochē.86
86 Husserl
C, § 39.
87 TedToadvine writes how Merleau-Ponty’s texts on Husserl can be divided
into three rough categories. The first is represented in Merleau-Ponty’s early phase
in the work prior to 1949, the second section appears simultaneously with Merleau-
Ponty’s teaching in the Sorbonne, from 1949 to 1952, and the last group of materials
is formed by the writings made in the Collège de France, from 1953 onwards. The
difficulties in interpreting the relationship become harder as Merleau-Ponty’s career
develops, as the number of references increases yet are often implicit. (Toadvine
2002, 227–28.)
88 PP, v/xii. | There are commentators, like Martin Dillon, who have claimed
that the later Merleau-Ponty disconnected himself from Husserlian tradition (Dil-
lon 1988). Yet, as other commentators, like Heinämaa have suggested, this does
not necessarily mean abandoning Husserl’s method (Heinämaa 2002, 127). In-
deed, there are many interpretations that point out similarities and comment that
Merleau-Ponty is merely continuing Husserl’s line of thought in order to take it
further and complete it, as argued by, for instance, Barbaras (Barbaras 2005, 208).
89 Barbaras 2005, 207–208.
2.2. THE QUESTION OF REDUCTION 33
Cézanne being haunted by moments of doubt: Cézanne doubted his talents, his
eyes, other people, and the critics doubted him. Merleau-Ponty too had his own
doubts, and this is partly what made Cézanne such an attractive artist to him.
(Johnson 2010, 16.) Here, I would like to point out, following Escoubas, that the
status and thinking on the visual arts changed quite radically from the period of
“Cézanne’s Doubt” to the last years of “Eye and Mind”. (Escoubas 2008, 43.)
92 Escoubas 1986, 97.
34 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
portant position. Mauro Carbone points out that in the working notes of The
Visible and the Invisible Merleau-Ponty suggests the proximity of literature and
philosophy. (Carbone 2004, 39.)
94 Indeed perceptual faith cannot be understood through the traditional concepts
in the question of perception the visual arts hold a particular position in his think-
ing, this should not be overemphasised. Indeed, the early texts concerning the arts
were inspired by the contemporary discussions on literature, and in the working
2.3. EXPRESSION AND SPECTATORSHIP 35
term, it originates from Aristotle, who took passivity as another half of the hier-
archical dichotomy with activity. For more, see Victor Biceaga, The Concept of
Passivity in Husserl’s Phenomenology (2010).
36 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
tary artist subject, but on the whole perceptual processes in which the
reversal of roles of the seer and the seen is enabled. He characterises
seeing by saying that it is the ability to be away from oneself.98 I will
study the connection of perception and passivity in more detail when
interpreting Merleau-Ponty’s discourse on “seeing with”, which is the
topic of both the next chapter and chapter 7.
The link between arts and expression is examined in Phenomenol-
ogy of Perception, where Merleau-Ponty writes: “Aesthetic expression
confers on what it expresses an existence in itself, installs it in nature as
a thing perceived and accessible to all [...]”.99 The link between seeing
and the visual arts is best described in the essay “Cézanne’s Doubt”,
where Merleau-Ponty draws primarily from his experience of the work
of Cézanne, but he also discusses other artists, such as Leonardo da
Vinci.100 Cézanne’s art was crucial for Merleau-Ponty throughout his
career, and the examples on the working methods of Cézanne are al-
ready present in the Phenomenology of Perception.101 Johnson ex-
plains his interest by reference to the sensible aspects of Cézanne’s
work and his Impressionist and pre-Cubist approach: “Merleau-Ponty
was clearly interested in Cézanne as a colorist and, above all, for
presenting us with a paradigm for pre-scientific perceptual experi-
ence of the natural world.”102 Johnson argues that Cézanne fascinated
Merleau-Ponty because he seemed to embody the whole attitude of
phenomenology: the aim was to disclose the pre-discursive and pre-
practical structures of perceptual experience.
Merleau-Ponty’s essay studies Cézanne’s approach to the pre-
theoretical and pre-practical structures of perception, but it also brings
forth a certain controversy or an unresolved question concerning the re-
lation between nature and culture. A comparison between the philoso-
pher’s and the painter’s work draws from the idea that they are both
aiming at epochē.103
98 Œ,83/146.
99 PP,212. “L’expression esthétique confère à ce qu’elle exprime l’existence en
soi, l’installe dans la nature comme une chose perçue accessible à tous [...]” PP,
213.
100 The essay is a contribution to several discussions of the time concerning the
questions of the artist’s freedom as well as explaining art through, for instance,
psychoanalysis. Already de Waelhens pointed to Heidegger and his statement that
questions on art are not to be solved by turning to the artist’s psychology or to
the history of art. (Waelhens 1951, 366.)
101 See for example PP, 230/230, 303/305
102 Johnson 1993, 7.
103 Evans & Behnke & Casey 1997, 18–19. See also for instance Crary 1999, 341. |
2.3. EXPRESSION AND SPECTATORSHIP 37
l’impression de la nature à son origine, tandis que les photographies des mêmes pay-
sages suggèrent les travaux des hommes, leur commodités, leur présence imminente.
Cézanne n’a jamais voulu ‘peindre comme une brute’, mais remettre l’intelligence,
les idées, les sciences, la perspective, la tradition, au contact du monde naturel
qu’elles sont destinées à comprendre, confronter avec la nature, comme il le dit, les
sciences ‘qui sont sorties d’elle’.” DC, 18–19.
105 This problematic was already acknowledged by Waelhens, who wrote that the
only flaw of Merleau-Ponty’s essay is that it makes it difficult for the reader to
38 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
Expressive
To understand Merleau-Ponty’s conception of expression, one needs
to conceive expression in a much larger sense than in the traditional
meaning of the word: it is not limited to clear and distinct thought
in the sphere of language, such as the sense of an utterance, or to an
expressive gesture within the arts, as for instance, in abstract expres-
sionism or action painting.106 Further, it must also by stressed that
Merleau-Ponty’s conception of expression did not remain the same: he
developed it at length already in the Phenomenology of Perception and
he returned to it several times, especially in his mid-career. In the last
phase of his work, expression came close to an ontological category.
Merleau-Ponty was interested in expression in general but also in
the specific question of the functions of language in lived speech. In
Phenomenology of Perception he writes:
understand how it is possible to paint otherwise than Cézanne: “Or cette interpré-
tation n’a, selon nous, qu’un tort : elle rend difficile de comprendre qu’on puisse
peindre autrement que Cézanne. Essayons de surmonter ces difficultés.” (Waelhens
1951, 366.)
106 Slatman 2003, 197; VI, 221/170.
107 PP, 229–30. “On a toujours remarqué que le geste ou la parole transfiguraient
is, of course every reason to distinguish between an authentic speech, which formu-
lates for the first time, and second-order expression, speech about speech, which
makes up the general run of empirical language. Only the first is identical with
thought.” (PP, 207 n.2.) “Il y a lieu, bien entendu, de distinguer une parole au-
thentique, qui formule pour la première fois, et une expression seconde, une parole
sur des paroles, qui fait l’ordinaire du langage empirique. Seule la première est
identique à la pensée.” (PP, 207 n.2; see also LV, 72/83.)
110 PP, 229. “La première [parole parlante] est celle dans laquelle l’intention si-
and painter share the task of expression: both are bound by what is
already expressed and are struggling for a new expression. Both aban-
don ready-made alternatives, even if the ready-made choices are very
different, since these two artists use different media for their expression
and thus work with different materials.
The shared starting-point of the author and the painter is in the
lived human body and its fundamental attitudes to the world. The
common task of artists is to express and create something new: an ex-
pression which addresses and “speaks” to other worldly perceivers. The
expressive resources of language are here understood in the broad sense
so that they include words, but also intonation, rhythm, and stress,
and underneath them silence. These non-intellectual, non-conceptual
and non-discursive resources are shared by linguistic expressions and
bodily gestures. In the fundamental silence which nourishes all artis-
tic expression could, according to Merleau-Ponty, prevail a unifying
“second power in which signs once again lead the vague life of colors,
and in which significations never free themselves completely from the
intercourse of signs?”111 Language is thus not seen as a stable system,
a storehouse, where the author and the poet simply pick up what she
or he wants or needs. Rather it is a dynamic whole which is connected
to the other areas of artistic expressivity by the silence of anonymous
perception. Like visual artists authors can explore language and create
new meanings.
Merleau-Ponty developed his early concept of expression in Phe-
nomenology of Perception as part of his phenomenology of the body,
language, and art. It is to be understood as a concept which describes
the interplay of sense and the sensible.112 At this stage of his philos-
ophy, it was important to Merleau-Ponty to develop a powerful and
valid account of the expressive functions of the lived body, and to show
that speech and bodily gestures share the fundamental structures and
sources of meaningful expression.
By this argument Merleau-Ponty opposed the empiricist conception
of language which reduces language to physiology, and the intellectu-
alistic conception which conceived language as a purely categorical op-
eration. From Merleau-Ponty’s perspective, both these viewpoints fail
to understand and describe the phenomenon of speech as a whole.113
111 LV, 82. “[...] seconde puissance, où de nouveau les signes mènent la vie vague
des couleurs, et où les significations ne se libèrent pas tout à fait du commerce des
signes ?” LV, 73.
112 PP, 230/229–30.
113 See for instance PM, 23/15; Dastur 2001, 53.
2.3. EXPRESSION AND SPECTATORSHIP 41
style of being and with the ‘world’ at which he directs his aim” (PP, 213). “Je
communique d’abord [...] avec un sujet parlant, avec un certain style d’être et avec
le ‘monde’ qu’il vise” (PP, 214).
115 PM 186/134; Dastur 2001, 60.
116 Slatman 2003, 135–37. | “But the statement that there are two kinds of speech,
one residing in the mind, the gift of Hermes the Leader, and the other residing in the
utterance, merely an attendant and instrument, is threadbare; we will let it come
under the heading ‘Yes, this I knew before Theognis’ birth’. But that would not
disturb us, because the aim and end of the speech in the mind and the speech in the
utterance is friendship, towards oneself and towards one’s neighbour respectively”
(Plutarch, Moralia 777c.)
117 VI, 170. “c’est le λόγος ἐνδιάθετος qui appelle le λόγος προφορικός — ” VI,
42 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
Spectatorship
As we have seen, Merleau-Ponty’s studies on expression and percep-
tion are closely related and inform one another. Thinking about the
discussion on expression in relation to questions on art, expression ap-
pears to be twofold: on the other hand, there is the experience of the
artist which finds its form in his or her expressions; on the other hand,
there is the experience of the spectator or beholder, and this expe-
rience too is expressive. My interest lies in the artworks and in our
encounters with them.121 From the Merleau-Pontian perspective, it is
222.
118 Slatman 2003, 139.
119 VI, 179. “Il faudrait un silence qui enveloppe la parole de nouveau après
qu’on s’est aperçu que la parole enveloppait le silence prétendu de la coïncidence
psychologique.” VI, 230.
120 Slatman 2003, 137–38, 145.
121 Here it should be noted that there is a passage in Phenomenology of Perception
where Merleau-Ponty writes about the optimum distance for each object, each
2.3. EXPRESSION AND SPECTATORSHIP 43
artwork: “The distance from me to the object is not a size which increases or
decreases, but a tension which fluctuates round a norm. An oblique position of the
object in relation to me is not measured by the angle which it forms with the plane
of my face, but felt as a lack of balance, as an unequal distribution of its influences
upon me.” (PP, 352.) “La distance de moi à l’objet n’est pas une grandeur qui
croît ou décroît, mais une tension qui oscille autour d’une norme : l’orientation
oblique de l’objet par rapport à moi n’est pas mesurée par l’angle qu’il forme avec
le plan de mon visage, mais éprouvée comme un déséquilibre, comme une inégale
répartition de ses influences sur moi.” (PP, 349.)
122 Lannoy 2008, 52.
44 CHAPTER 2. PHENOMENOLOGICAL METHOD AND ART
There are various artists who have drawn inspiration from phe-
nomenology, including Robert Irwin and Bruce Nauman, to name just
two. To Irwin, an artist dealing with perception and its limits, light
and space, the spectator’s consciousness of the work had an ethical
dimension. Likewise, Bruce Nauman can be connected with the phe-
nomenological tradition, as his works pervade perception itself.132
In the beginning of the 1960s Merleau-Ponty’s works were often
understood and discussed in a very focused and selective way, which
made it seem as if his philosophy was preoccupied with the immedi-
ate and subjective aspects of perception and excluded the necessary
social and historical dimensions of art.133 Later on, Merleau-Ponty’s
phenomenology is often associated with Cartesian and Husserlian me-
diations, which are both rejected as apolitical, subjectivistic, idealistic,
and simply unable to approach the concrete artwork itself, being fo-
cused on personal experiences and subjective acts. Miwon Kwon, an
art historian who has specialised in site-specific works sums up recent
developments in this field:134
139 As I will show, Merleau-Ponty did not simply reject Descartes’ thinking as
a whole. The criticism mentioned here is directed against vision as presented in
Dioptrics.
140 “The discursive construction of sight is intimately connected with other forms
of construction: our visual behaviour is shaped not only by what we think about
vision, but also (and perhaps even more so) by how visual images and technologies
teach us to look. Merleau-Ponty understood this very well, as is evident from his
writings on painting. He treated painting not as an isolated phenomenon, but as
articulating a perceptual and expressive relation to the world.” (Van de Vall 2008,
16.) My italics.
51
52 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
Husserl’s: for Merleau-Ponty objectivism does not only exist in the attitude of
natural sciences, but also in certain uses of language, that is not conscious of its
own genesis or the force it has. (Slatman 2003, 65.)
142 Concerning seeing, along with Husserl and Descartes, one can also trace the in-
fluence of fellow philosophers, such as Sartre, and the surfacing of criticism towards
ocular-centrism. See Martin Jay’s article “Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, and the Search
for a New Ontology of Sight” (1993). Merleau-Ponty’s reading of Descartes was
influenced by contemporary philosophers and he read commentaries on Descartes
and Cartesian thinking by philosophers such as the French idealist philosopher
Léon Brunschvicg (1869–1944) and the philosopher and historian of philosophy
Martial Guéroult (1891–1976), among others. (Saint Aubert 2005, 33, 60; see also
NC, 159–268.)
143 Saint Aubert 2005, 21. | The Visible and the Invisible could be seen as a
continuation and as an attempt to find an ontology that would describe our relation
to being. The title of the unfinished manuscript can be understood as bringing
together the sensuous of the visible world and the imaginary, conceptual world
that remains invisible.
144 See, for instance, the note in The Visible and the Invisible, written in April,
1960: “The second part of the book (which I am beginning) with my description
of the visible as in-visible, must lead in the third to a confrontation with the
Cartesian ontology (finish Gueroult’s Descartes — read his Malebranche — see
3.1. CARTESIAN VISION 53
Leibniz and Spinoza).” (VI, 242.) “La second partie du livre (que je commence)
avec ma description du visible comme in-visible, doit conduire dans la 3e à une
confrontation avec l’ontologie cartésienne (achever le Descartes de Guéroult — lire
son Malebranche — voir Leibniz et Spinoza).” (VI, 291.) Husserl also kept returning
to Descartes, emphasising the importance of a radical new beginning for philosophy
in Cartesian Meditations. (See, for instance, Husserl CM, § 1–2.)
145 Even though Merleau-Ponty makes critical remarks on Descartes in “Eye and
Mind”, he was also challenged by his thinking — this is especially visible towards
the end of the third chapter. Galen A. Johnson has written on the importance of
the third chapter, as it “is the hinge swinging the door open from the new theory
of vision in part 2 to the new ontology in part 4.” (Johnson 2010, 20.)
146 Of interest are especially his letter to Princess Elizabeth, discussing the differ-
ent types of knowledge we can have of our body, mind and their union. (Descartes
AT III, 663–97.)
147 As can be seen from the essay “Everywhere and Nowhere” (“Partout and nulle
Many recent commentaries have paid attention to how later on, for
instance in the lecture notes on Cartesian and today’s ontology,150
Merleau-Ponty elaborated his reading of Descartes. In the beginning
of the lecture, Merleau-Ponty wishes to set Cartesian thinking against
examples of fundamental thinking about arts and literature.151 In the
lecture he discusses especially the Meditations, finding a possibility to
read Descartes’ ontology as not opposed to the one that Merleau-Ponty
was developing.152
However, here I will concentrate on the particular passage in Mer-
leau-Ponty’s “Eye and Mind”, for two reasons: firstly, the third chapter
presents a shift in thinking, and secondly, its topic, seeing, is of partic-
ular interest from the point of view of my research. In the introduction
of “Eye and Mind” Merleau-Ponty has argued that art, and especially
painting, holds a special place in relation to the world.153 Art is pre-
sented as the opposite to the practical scientific approach that ma-
nipulates things to get the desired result. After discussing at length
the physicality of seeing, the painter and the experience of painting,
the way we are engaged with the world, and how it is not possible for
the artist to paint without body, Merleau-Ponty moves on to analyse
a view that at the outset appears to be totally opposite to his. The
third chapter begins with a claim: Descartes’ Dioptrics is an attempt
to sweep away the difficulties, yet “[i]t is worthwhile to remember this
attempt and its failure.”154 The way in which Descartes is introduced
is indeed of interest. His thinking is claimed to present us with a show-
piece on how one should not think, and yet there is something more
to it, too: we are promised that the return to the claimed failure will
pay off. Indeed, as many commentators have proposed, I see here a
connection between Merleau-Ponty’s strategy with Descartes and his
contemplation on philosophy of history, where philosophy is seen as
an enterprise to search for lacunae in past philosophers’ thinking.155
and Nowhere” (“Partout et nulle part”), the lecture series The Incarnate Subject.
Malebranche, Biran, and Bergson on the Union of Body and Soul. (L’Union de
l’âme et du corps chez Malebranche, Biran et Bergson), and in the essay “The
Philosopher and His Shadow” (“Le philosophe et son ombre”).
3.1. CARTESIAN VISION 55
notes and even different versions of the “Eye and Mind” manuscript which help
to fathom the importance of Merleau-Ponty’s attention to Cartesianism. (Saint
Aubert 2005, 33.)
3.1. CARTESIAN VISION 57
icism brings out the tendencies of Descartes reasoning that are tightly
connected, yet their consequences might not be as simple.168 Merleau-
Ponty wishes to stress Descartes’ hostility towards illusions, and all
possible sidetracks from the way to truth, expanding the hostility to
concern the visible world as a whole. From this perspective illusion
contaminates all vision and sense-perception, and this leads Descartes
to transfer the attributes of the visible to the sphere of the purely men-
tal, where they again may metaphorically demonstrate the powers of
reason. Judovitz also examines other texts in which Descartes discusses
illusions, such as Observations (Experimenta, 1619) and Rules for the
Direction of the Mind (Les Règles pour la direction de l’esprit. Reg-
ulae ad directionem ingenii).169 She argues that in order to explain
Descartes, it does not suffice to refer to the birth of the discourse
on certainty during the Renaissance and Baroque era. She contextu-
alises Descartes’ writings by referring to visual devices favoured in the
Baroque era such as anamorphosis and trompe l’oeil. Anamorphosis,
for instance, is a device that contrary to the perspective technique,
does not rationalise space and the visible, but it implies a decentrali-
sation of the viewing subject. For Descartes, these kinds of illusionistic
devices were a hindrance to truth: those accustomed to the trickery,
might not be able to recognize what is certain.170 Judovitz remarks
that the disqualification of the body is a reflection of the development
of science and new scientific instrumentation: the Copernican revolu-
tion had produced a counterintuitive discovery that the earth moves
around the sun, even though our senses would tell us otherwise.171
Against this background Descartes’ attempt to avoid the unreliability
of the senses, one can understand his suspicious attitude towards the
visual arts.172 Thus, in his quest for certitude, illusions such as trompe
l’oeil -paintings, appear as a threat to the truth-searching philoso-
pher.173
It must be acknowledged that when Descartes wrote Dioptrics, vi-
sion was generally considered analogous to reason and that Descartes,
168 Judovitz’s study Subjectivity and Representation in Descartes. The Origins
sidering paintings as merely simulation and thus alienated from the truth. See, for
instance, Plato Republic 596e–608b; also Escoubas 1986, 107–108.
173 Judovitz 1993, 63; 2001, 99–100.
58 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
too, used the metaphor of seeing to account for reason and knowl-
edge.174 Knowledge was conceived as an attempt or capacity to clar-
ify and sharpen the insight of reason. Nonetheless, Descartes’ strive
for clearness is, from the point of view of Merleau-Ponty, taken too
far: Dioptrics represents a philosopher’s and a scientist’s ideal world,
where everything is crystal clear and there are no exceptions, ambi-
guities, obscurities, and indeterminate cases. It is true that Descartes
models vision according to touch — he uses the example of a blind
man’s touch, mediated through a cane — in order to demonstrate the
certainty of vision, as the senses of touch can be vivid and clear.175
Merleau-Ponty’s criticism can be summarised by saying that instead
of exploring vision as such, Descartes is content to think about it —
vision is studied not as a modality of perception but as a problem
of thinking. This becomes explicit in the fourth and fifth chapters of
Dioptrics, where Descartes argues that it is the soul which has sensory
perceptions, and not actually the sense organs which are only claimed
to serve as mere outer sensing means, not sensing means as such.176
The mind does not need to examine any pictures resembling sensed
objects — in fact, Descartes underlines how the mind can also be sim-
ulated by signs and words.177 Here, the question of seeing and image
are removed from the sense experience into the domain of thinking —
it is in line with the previously presented suspicions about illusions.
It was part of the project in which Descartes wished to denounce re-
semblance as a false way of attaining knowledge, as it was in danger
of falling into illusions.178
The most significant disagreement between Descartes and Merleau-
Ponty concerns the understanding of the receiving subject and his
or her bodily being. Merleau-Ponty argues that in the Cartesian set-
ting, the self is completely detached from the body and sensuous feel-
174 See especially Rules for the Direction of the Mind. On the role of light in
totle’s descriptions in De Anima. (Aristotle 423b; Fóti 2003, 43; Derrida 2005,
47.)
176 Descartes AT VI, 109/PWI, 164.
177 “Il faut, outre cela, prendre garde à ne pas supposer que, pour sentir, l’âme ait
besoin de contempler quelques images qui soient envoyées par les objets jusqu’au
cerveau, ainsi que font communément nos philosophes.” (Descartes AT VI, 112.)
“We must take care not to assume — as our philosophers commonly do — that
in order to have sensory perceptions the soul must contemplate certain images
transmitted by objects to the brain.” (Descartes PWI, 165.)
178 Judovitz 1988, 40.
3.1. CARTESIAN VISION 59
The Cartesian does not see himself in the mirror; he sees a pup-
pet, an “outside,” which, he has every reason to believe, other
people see in the very same way, but which is no more for himself
than for others a body in the flesh.181
un ‘dehors’ dont il a toutes raisons de penser que les autres le voient pareillement,
mais qui, pas plus pour lui-même que pour eux, n’est une chair.” Œ, 38–39.
182 “Il faut au moins que nous remarquions qu’il n’y a aucunes images qui doivent
en tout ressembler aux objets qu’elles représentent : car autrement il n’y aurait
point de distinction entre l’objet et son image.” (Descartes AT VI, 113.) “We must
at least observe that in no case does an image have to resemble the object it
represents in all respects, for otherwise there would be no distinction between the
object and its image.” (Descartes PWI, 165.)
183 Œ, 40/131–32; see also Fóti 2003, 46.
60 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
184 Œ, 42/132.
185 For a reading of Descartes’ preference of graphic art to painting and the ques-
tion of colour, see Véronique M. Fóti’s “The Dimension of Color” (1993).
186 Œ, 48–49/135; Levin 1988, 102. | It is not unproblematic to speak of Re-
que la profondeur, qu’est-ce que la lumière, τί το όν — que sont-ils, non pas pour
l’esprit qui se retranche du corps, mais pour celui dont Descartes a dit qu’il y était
répandu — en enfin non seulement pour l’esprit, mais pour eux-mêmes, puisqu’ils
nous traversent, nous englobent ?” Œ, 60.
191 Œ, 58–59/138.
192 See, for Luce Irigaray’s well-known criticism of Merleau-Ponty in An Ethics
je ne le regarde pas comme on regarde une chose, je ne le fixe pas en son lieu, mon
regard erre en lui comme dans les nimbes de l’Être, je vois selon ou avec lui plutôt
que je ne le vois.” Œ 23; see also Œ, 24–25/126–27.
194 Œ, 24–25/126–27.
195 Œ, 26/127.
3.2. PHENOMENOLOGY ON SEEING 63
196 “Alors que l’expression : ‘voir selon’ ne pose, en son énoncé, aucun objet à
voir, mais postule, sans la nommer, une attitude à l’égard d’un quelque chose, d’un
Etwas, qui, comme nous la verrons, pourrait se révéler primordial, sans relever pour
autant de l’ordre des choses individuées à inspecter.” (Garelli 1992, 80.)
197 Œ, 126. “Le mot d’image est mal famé parce qu’on a cru étourdiment qu’un
dessin était un décalque, une copie, une seconde chose, et l’image mentale un dessin
de ce genre dans notre bric-à-brac privé.” Œ, 23.
198 The notion of image in psychology and philosophy has been understood in
different ways. Bergson, for instance, uses image in a very different way to Merleau-
Ponty in his discussion of perception and memory in Matter and Memory (Matière
et mémoire, 1896), writing how the brain is just one image among many images.
Gaston Bachelard referred to image in connection with imagination in his phe-
64 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
[...] Beaucoup plus loin, puisque le tableau n’est un analogue que selon le corps
[...]” Œ, 24.
201 MPR, 440. “Qu’est-ce qu’un Bild ? Il manifeste ici que le Bild ne se regarde
pression when it comes to art, since today we are faced with various forms of art.
If Merleau-Ponty’s statement is interpreted as an attempt to emphasise the atti-
tude artworks are encountered, the question of materiality or medium presents a
question: does seeing with bypass materiality, as it somehow seems to imply seeing
further than the surface? To my mind the seeing with is about opening oneself to
the work, and thus it does not cling to appearances — which is also materiality —
but yet presents a demand to open oneself to the materiality through which the
work is conveyed.
203 The radio lectures, “Causeries”, were commissioned by French national radio
(RDF) and were broadcast in 1948. The seven talks were recorded for a programme
called “The French Culture Hour” (“Heure de culture Français”, published in C.)
204 C, 95. “Si c’était vrai, le but de la peinture serait le trompe-l’œil, et sa signi-
fication serait toute hors du tableau, dans les choses qu’il signifie, dans le sujet.”
C, 55, see also 55 n.b: on the tape the word signifie is: “dans les choses qu’il
représente”.
205 PM, 90. “[...] parce qu’elle s’installe et nous installe dans un monde dont nous
n’avons pas la clef, elle nous apprend à voir et nous donne à penser comme aucun
ouvrage analytique ne peut le faire, parce qu’aucune analyse ne peut trouver dans
un objet autre chose que ce que nous y avons mis.” PM, 127.
66 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
deliberately translated as fantasy, not imagination, as the latter might exclude some
important meanings of the word. Here I follow Mark Richir and his comments in
“Commentaire de Phénoménologie de la conscience esthétique”. (Richir 1999, 15.)
213 Stjernfelt 2007, 289.
214 Husserl I, § 111, 262/252.
68 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
aus Leinwand, aus Marmor usw. 2) Das repräsentierende oder abbildende Objekt,
und 3) das repräsentierte oder abgebildete Objekt. Für das letztere wollen wir am
liebsten einfach Bildsujet sagen. Für das erste das physische Bild, für das zweite
das repräsentierende Bild oder Bildobjekt” Hua XXIII, § 9, 19.
218 In different commentaries “Bildbewusstsein” has been translated both as im-
age consciousness and pictorial consciousness. I will follow John B. Brough’s trans-
lation of Hua XXIII and use the term image consciousness.
219 Husserl PIC § 9; Stjernfelt 2007, 291; Bernet 2002, 332.
3.2. PHENOMENOLOGY ON SEEING 69
220 Stjernfelt 2007, 289; Bernet 2002, 331. | In fantasy, Bernet argues, one of the
forms of conflict disappears, as there is no physical image required, and the division
between perception and phantasy would then become blurred. (Bernet 2002, 333.)
221 Stjernfelt 2007, 292.
222 Casebier 1991, 9.
223 Husserl 1994, 2. “Das phänomenologische Schauen ist also nahe verwandt dem
edges: “This is far from being a novel conclusion: it has been recognized by many
commentators, ever since Sartre’s reflections on the topic. On the example of the
engraving in §111 of Ideen I, Sartre wrote in L’imagination: ‘What is important
to Husserl here is that the “thesis” or positing of existence underwent a neutrality
modification’, and he adds in a footnote: ‘He wants above all to show that, in the
aesthetic contemplation, the object is not posited as existing. His descriptions refer
for the most part to the Critique of Judgement.’” (Lories 2006, 36–37.)
225 Even though Husserl is mostly absent from later philosophical discussions on
the visual arts, there are exceptions. His understanding of aesthetic consciousness,
for instance, has been used in film theory. Casebier emphasised that his theory
of artistic representation can be useful in developing a realist model for contem-
porary film theory that has previously been, according to Casebier, governed by
idealist/nominalist frameworks. Casebier’s aim was to create a successful approach
that would help the field of film theory to find its identity. His attempt took as its
point of departure Husserl’s theory of artistic representation, as presented in such
early works as Logical Investigations and Ideas I, and aimed to approach questions
and issues that the theories of the previous framework were unable to answer,
concentrating on the experience of film representation. (Casebier 1991, 2–3.) Film
theory is naturally a field of its own, even though film does not appear to be so
far from contemporary art, which often involves moving images. Along with Case-
bier there are also other studies, such as Vivian Sobchack’s The Address of the
Eye. A Phenomenology of Film Experience (1992) which applies Merleau-Ponty’s
thinking. Chapter six explores film further.
226 Steinmetz 2007, 84. | I am aware that to say that Husserl’s concept helps to
Icon
Through the statement “Rather than seeing it, I see according to, or
with it” Merleau-Ponty did not aim to reach for a hidden meaning
somewhere beyond the work of art, in another world. On the contrary,
his attempt is to examine the way in which art is capable of bring-
ing the two aspects, invisibility and visibility, together.227 Merleau-
Pontian understanding could be described as a way to move away
from ordinary seeing, but in a such manner that one could also take
into consideration materiality — “seeing with” is not simply about
looking past, or beyond the materiality that is the basis of “depicted”
images, but about dwelling in the artwork, considering how it is able
to manifest the invisible in the visible, and bringing together these
different elements.
Granted, considering the conception where artwork demands differ-
ent kinds of seeing, one could ask whether artworks are necessarily able
to create a strange sphere of in-between, as was described by Husserl.
Or what about works that tend to play with a particular ambiguity,
like ready-mades: works of art that from the outset do not stand out
from ordinary objects? What about works which do not seem to offer
themselves up to our viewing?
Here, I discuss more closely one of the implications of “seeing with”,
namely the artwork’s status as icon, as something that exceeds every-
day objects and representations. Before going into Merleau-Ponty’s
conception of an icon, I need to first be precise about what is meant
by an icon? In everyday usage, an icon often refers to an image or
representation, an “iconic” figure in popular culture, or to a religious
painting presenting a saint or Biblic scenes.228 Within the tradition of
philosophy, icons are connected, among others things, to pragmatist
Charles S. Peirce’s (1839–1914) well-known typology of signs.229 To
art forms like literature and photography also share a sensuous basis. Therefore,
it would be a misunderstanding to claim that the physical characteristic of image
should be forgotten for the sake of transparency of image.
228 “also ikon, 1570s, ‘image, figure, representation,’ from L[ate] L[atin] icon,
from Greek eikon ‘likeness, image, portrait,’ related to eikenai ‘be like, look like.’”
(Harper, Online Etymology Dictionary.)
229 Peirce developed his theory of signs from his early writings such as “On a New
put it briefly, Peirce classified signs into icons, indexes and symbols,
according to their relationship to the object. For Peirce, an icon is a
question of similarity, as an icon’s relation to an object is correspon-
dence — both the image and a diagramme of something can be icons.
As for indexes, they indicate their object through, for instance, a part
of the object, or through a trace, like in a wind vane or thermome-
ter. Symbols, again, are related to objects on the basis of common
agreement, as in the case of a trophy.230 However, here I will not ex-
amine the icon in a Peircean sense, but follow Slatman in her reading
of Merleau-Ponty’s icon where artworks’ particular character of man-
ifesting invisibility in the visible is a quality of an icon.231 From this
perspective, an icon creates a new visibility.232
Merleau-Ponty uses the term icon in a few passages of “Eye and
Mind”: in the second chapter of the essay he writes how things have an
equivalent in the seer, how they raise a carnal formula in the spectator:
“Thus there appears a ‘visible’ to the second power, a carnal essence
or icon of the first. It is not a faded copy [...]”.233 There are also other
passages in the third chapter, where in connection with Descartes’ con-
ception of looking at etchings or his own mirror image, Merleau-Ponty
remarks how “For him, icons lose their powers”.234 As I understand it,
the icon is to Merleau-Ponty a way to understand how a painting is
given to us, it underlines the particularity of the work of art. Looking
at paintings is not about deciphering signs, as is the case with reading,
but instead it addresses the embodied spectator through our shared
carnality, and thus is about our being in the world. An icon manages
to surpass the usual category of a representation and turn it into a pre-
sentation where the visible and the invisible are both present. “The
etching gives us sufficient indices, unequivocal ‘means’ for forming an
idea of the thing that does not come from the icon itself; rather it
arises in us, as ‘occasioned’ by the icon”.235
230 The Peircean classification of signs is related to his philosophy and the cat-
egories of firstness, secondness and thirdness, the modes of being. (Laakso 2003,
90.)
231 See Slatman’s book L’expression au-delà de la representation. Sur l’aisthêsis
et l’esthétique chez Merleau-Ponty (2003) and her articles “L’invisible dans le vi-
sible. Vers une phénoménologie de l’eikhôn” (2003b) and “Phenomenology of the
Icon” (2009).
232 Slatman 2003b, 234.
233 Œ, 126. “Alors paraît un visible à la deuxième puissance, essence charnelle ou
équivoque pour former une idée de la chose qui ne vient pas de l’icône, qui naît en
nous à son ‘occasion’.” Œ, 40.
236 Slatman 2003, 183.
237 Plato Republic 10, 596a–598d ; Escoubas 1986, 107–108 ; Slatman 2003b,
232–33.
238 The painter “‘[...] is the imitator of the thing which those others produce.’
‘Very good,’ said I; ‘the producer of the product three removes from nature you
call the imitator?’ ‘By all means,’ he said. ‘This, then, will apply to the maker of
tragedies also, if he is an imitator and is in his nature three removes from the king
and the truth, as are all other imitators.’ ‘It would seem so.’ ‘We are in agreement,
then, about the imitator.’” Plato Republic 10, 597e.
239 Slatman 2003b, 232–33.
240 Slatman 2003b, 233; 2009, 197.
241 “C’est ainsi qu’il peut y avoir des êtres qui ne sont pas de l’en soi et qui ne
where resemblance of the image and the seen was irrelevant, an icon
is not a copy, or mere tekhne, in a Platonic sense. This also leads into
considering icon, as Slatman puts it, productive mimesis in the Aris-
totelian sense, thus poiesis. In Slatman’s reading an icon is understood
in a phenomenological sense: it is a result of the interaction between
the painter and his/her visible world. This is reflected in the relation
between painting and spectator, so that the spectator turns into the
seen. The painting is a manifestation of the inner relation to the world,
a presentation of the appearance of being.242
Indeed, Slatman underlines a reading where Merleau-Ponty’s use
of the term ‘icon’ is seen as a criticism of Descartes.243 As mentioned
earlier, Merleau-Ponty objected to the Cartesian understanding of im-
ages by saying that in that kind of seeing icons lose their powers.244 It
was important for Merleau-Ponty to make a clear distinction between
an image as an imitation and a powerful image found in art, namely an
icon. In order to discuss closer the dimensions of an icon in Merleau-
Ponty, Slatman suggests that Jean-Luc Marion’s studies concerning
the icon are useful. Marion is one of the contemporary philosophers
who have brought the icon into phenomenological discourse — yet this
is not totally unproblematic in relation to Merleau-Ponty’s concept of
icon, not least because Marion’s relation to religion is different from the
one Merleau-Ponty has. To Marion, theology becomes an indisputable
moment in all theorisation of painting.245 Marion writes: “The divine
does not produce the icon [...] man becomes religious by preparing a
face for the divine: he takes it upon him to fashion the face, and then to
ask the divine to invest it, as radically as possible, so as to become his
god.”246 He continues: “[...] The idol must fix the distance and diffuse
divinity and assure us of its presence, of its power, of its availability
[...] the idol fixes the divine for us permanently.”247 On the contrary:
The icon manifests neither the human face nor the divine nature
that no one could envisage [...] The icon conceals and reveals that
upon which it rests: the separation in it between the divine and
242 Slatman 2003b, 233–34; 2009, 200.
243 Slatman 2003, 184.
244 Œ, 39/131.
245 Marion 1991, 8.
246 Marion 2001, 5.
247 Marion 2001, 5. | “What is peculiar to the idol, therefore, has to do with this:
the divine is fixed in it on the basis of the experience of the divine that is had by
man, who, by relying on the idol’s mediation, attempts to attract the benevolence
and the protection of what appears in it as a god.” (Marion 2001, 5–6.)
3.2. PHENOMENOLOGY ON SEEING 75
parallels Marion and Merleau-Ponty, she points out a problematic aspect: Marion
is openly hostile towards the new media, such as television, or in general popu-
lar culture. This hostility is not shared by Merleau-Ponty. There is also another
problematic parallel: the suggestion of a Christian undertone in Merleau-Ponty.
Slatman remarks that in Marion, the new way of seeing demanded a religious
shift, whereas Merleau-Ponty did not call for such a move, even though one could
ask whether, for instance, already speaking of icon or invisible is already theo-
logical? It can be noted that his vocabulary has in places a certain theological
character, for instance the concepts of flesh or incarnation. Johnson has pointed
out that Merleau-Ponty never declared himself to be an atheist. He also remarks
on the sense of the sacred or the holy and spiritualisation that can be traced in
Merleau-Ponty’s writings, though the spiritual was of this world. (Johnson 2010,
131, 67). Merleau-Ponty discusses God widely, for instance in his Nature-lectures.
The question of religion is of course wider. Slatman suggests: “Et peut-être faut-
il avouer que notre ontologie de la vision reste toujours tributaire de la tradition
judéo-chrétienne de l’iconicité (et de l’iconoclasme)” (Slatman 2003, 192). In short,
Slatman notes, referring to Marie-José Mondzain, that the Western understanding
of the ontology of vision is based on the Judeo-Christian tradition of both iconicity
and iconoclasm. (For more, see Mondzain 1996.) As a Catholic, Marion has openly
chosen a position where phenomenology seems to turn into theology. Dominique
76 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
Janicaud, who started a debate in the 1990s, claimed that thinkers such as Lev-
inas, Ricœur, Henry and Marion have introduced their beliefs into the philosophical
work and thus smuggled theological discourse, religious ideas and vocabulary into
French phenomenology. Janicaud claimed that they participate in what has been
called the theological turn in phenomenology. The whole discussion of the invisi-
ble, according to Janicaud, would no longer be phenomenological but theological
or metaphysical. In the debate, Marion was seen as a philosopher who exempli-
fied the theological tendency of philosophy. Yet it is not indisputable to say that
there is such a thing as the theological turn. Zahavi, for instance, along with many
other commentators, has taken a sceptical stand towards Janicaud’s accusations
that certain discourses, vocabulary and topics are necessarily theological. The shift
towards the invisible is not only a French phenomena. In fact, it seems that almost
all thinkers in the field of phenomenology have regarded this shift as important.
On the other hand, it is completely within the scope of phenomenology to examine
other forms of manifestation than the visible. (Zahavi 1999, 234–37.)
251 Marion 1991, 41–46.
252 Slatman 2003, 186–90; VI, 309–10/260–62. | “Le voyant-visible (pour moi,
pour les autres) est d’ailleurs non pas un quelque chose physique, ni un comporte-
ment de vision, mais une perspective, ou mieux : le monde même avec une certaine
déformation cohérente” (VI, 310.) “The visible-seer (for me, for the others) is more-
3.2. PHENOMENOLOGY ON SEEING 77
over not a psychic something, nor a behavior of vision, but a perspective, or better:
the world itself with a certain coherent deformation” (VI, 262.)
253 Marion 1991, 91–92. | Marion has used television to illustrate the contempo-
quoi tant de peintres ont dit que les choses les regardent [...]” Œ, 31. | Merleau-
Ponty quotes Georges Charbonnier, who conducted interviews with artists. André
Marchad explains to Charbonnier: “Ce n’était pas moi qui regardais l’arbre. C’est
l’arbre qui me regardait. Donc, je sentais, certains jours, que la nature contenait
vraiment ce monde du dedans, cette âme du dedans, cachée à nos regards et terri-
blement obsédante. Je l’ai vu et je l’ai senti à plusieurs reprises. Si je suis sur des
grandes plages désertes, au bord de la mer, ce n’est pas moi qui regarde la mer,
c’est la mer qui me regarde [...]” (Charbonnier 2002, 110–11.)
255 Slatman 2003, 188.
256 “[...] il n’est pas en dehors du spectacle, qu’il n’a pas une position de survol. Le
spectateur n’est pas un voyeur, il est impliqué dans le monde visible de l’œuvre
d’art.” Slatman 2003, 191.
78 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
for Slatman argues that the iconic is applicable to text, too. (Slatman 2003, 251.)
3.3. DISSOLVING SEEING 79
objective world; two subjects that need to recognise their own corporeality and that
of others. I and another have shared perception, this experience would then be the
basis of the whole objective world, a result of intersubjectivity, and my and the
other’s living body. It is necessary to realise that my body can be experienced like
other objects. The world cannot only be a series of personal experiences, but is
experienceable and shared by all.
80 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
vraiment un autre, il faut qu’à un certain moment je sois surpris, désorienté, et que
nous nous rencontrions, non plus dans ce que nous avons de semblable, mais dans
ce que nous avons de différent, et ceci suppose une transformation de moi-même et
d’autrui aussi bien : il faut que nos différences ne soient plus comme des qualités
opaques, il faut qu’elles soient devenues sens.” PM, 198.
264 Yeo 1992, 48.
265 PM, 200/144.
3.3. DISSOLVING SEEING 81
266 Whether or not Merleau-Ponty actually manages to affirm the other can be
questioned. Are we not always in his model projecting our already acquired mean-
ings into the encountering? Critics such as Irigaray insist that Merleau-Ponty sys-
tematically failed to take into account the difference. Irigaray writes: “Despite his
efforts, Maurice Merleau-Ponty falls back into a lack of differentiation with respect
to these others who ‘haunt’ him and with whom he ‘haunts a single actual Being.’
They form, in part without their knowing, a single ‘Being,’ a single Whole in which
his perception participates without being able to dissociate itself from it. [...] He
lacks the space-time, the available corporeal matter thanks to which it would be
possible for him to perceive the other as other in the present, including what, in
this other, will remain invisible to him.” Also, Irigaray claims Merleau-Ponty is
solipsistic in his description of an encounter, where I does not encounter you, but
many. (Irigaray 2004, 398. See also Irigaray 1993, 151–84; 2001, 17.)
267 Busch 1992, 195.
268 Diprose 2002, 178.
269 Busch 1992, 196; see also PP, 296/295.
270 Levinas 1987, 96.
271 Busch 1992, 196.
82 CHAPTER 3. CONCEPTIONS OF SEEING
that:
Thus, as Busch points out, the Other leaves a trace, but is never
present in it, but is something that always withdraws.273 For Levinas
“The beyond from which a face comes signifies as a trace. A face is in
the trace of the utterly bygone, utterly passed absent [...].274 In Busch’s
reading he underlines the difference between Levinas and Merleau-
Ponty concerning the idea of reversibility and reciprocity, which for
Merleau-Ponty were central — on the other hand, Levinas rejected
reversibility and instead of reciprocal relations stressed that they are
inverted.275
My intention is not to take a stand on the Levinasian critique.
I acknowledge that paralleling the other — let alone the Levinasian
Other — with a work of art involves a risk. However, I still would like
to consider a work of art as a place for the other. I wish to underline
that in my reading of Merleau-Ponty, the conception of reversibility
and reciprocity are not understood as totally symmetrical — this is
stressed especially in the later texts of Merleau-Ponty, and I will dis-
cuss this further in section 7.1. Through the acknowledgement of the
incompleteness of reversibility there is both a danger of reducing the
Other to the Same, but as I would like to suggest, also an opening
into acknowledging the other as truly other, encountering the ultimate
strangeness.
Art is necessarily social by nature.276 For Merleau-Ponty, the work
272 Levinas 1987, 104–105.
273 Busch 1992, 197.
274 Levinas 1986, 355.
275 Busch 1992, 198–99.
276 Even the remotest and most isolated piece will have audience, though there
of art and its meanings are created in the various encounters with
viewers.277 However, connected with thinking of a work of art, one
must proceed into asking what happens when the other remains in-
accessible: what happens when a work refuses to see with, and denies
any access and companionship? Further, is it certain that when en-
countering the alien we do not adopt the strange by dissolving it, and
thus ignore possibilities of non-communication, disagreement etc.?
With the following case studies of contemporary art I wish to be
able to approach also these critical questions, and demonstrate what
possibilities the phenomenological approach — interpreted as I have
done here — could open for the encountering. I will start my discussion
from what has been considered to be home ground for Merleau-Ponty,
namely paintings. In the next chapter I move on to discuss painting and
its spaces, and eventually also the first of the case studies, paintings
by Tiina Mielonen.
277 The origin for the different associations is in the work of art, as the work is
able to exceed all causal explanations. (Œ, 62–63/139.)
4
Phenomenology of Painting: From Space to
Depth
Space in Phenomenology
Why is space of interest to my discussion of art? First, the phenom-
ena of spatiality are crucial for the interaction between the painter
and the painted, as well as for the interaction between the spectator
and the painting. More specifically, the phenomenon of depth (pro-
fondeur), which haunted Merleau-Ponty for decades, is essential for
278 Œ, 32/129; Matos Dias 2001, 149–50.
279 Here I use the term modern to refer to non-Euclidean, Cézannian space, thus
I do not use the term to refer to the period that started in the 16th century, as in,
for instance, Edward S. Casey’s notion that Descartes’ space is modern (1997).
85
86 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
He used the distinction between merely an object body and a lived body, and the
terminology of Körper — Leib. Through the concept of the lived body Husserl also
developed the concept of the body as a Nullpunkt, Nullkörper. Husserl writes that
space is always constituted from the one and only persisting point, as the world
appears to me through the body. (Husserl Hua XVI, 80.)
87
bodies that provide the “zero ground” for all perceptual experiences
and for all estimations of distances, directions, and locations. There
can be no spatial relations without the lived body.283
In Crisis, Husserl argued that the modern idea of universal mathe-
matical science triggered a fundamental reshaping of all sciences, natu-
ral and human. Husserl shows how the development of the techniques
and practices of measuring has, together with the mathematisation
of the natural sciences, resulted in a new idea of knowledge which
surpasses lived experience. The object of this knowledge is not the
life-world, which is disclosed to us in experience and perception, it is
instead a mathematical universe of pure nature. Moreover, this math-
ematised nature is substituted for the life-world as the ultimate source
of justification. For Husserl, this is a fundamental confusion that trans-
fers the qualities of the method to the qualities of the object. He states:
“[S]ome were misled into taking these formulae and their formula-
meaning for the true being of nature itself.”284 In the new setting, the
attention of the scientist is directed at abstractions and idealisations;
it is no longer bound to the objectivities of the life-world.
In Husserl’s thinking ideality was not a problem as such; the prob-
lem was the way in which it was applied. The Greeks had idealised
empirical numbers, i.e. the concrete units that were used in measure-
ment. The difficulties began when modern thinkers sought to conquer
the infinite mathematical horizons, and the idea of a completely ratio-
nal and all-inclusive science was instituted as the rule for all scientific
practices. Mathematics offered means for these practices both through
its ideal objects and through the art of measuring.285 From the phe-
nomenological perspective, the problem of this development in objecti-
fication was that the sciences forgot their starting points in experience,
and were unable to think back to the original meanings established in
experience, i.e. to pre-scientific believing or perceptual faith.286
283 Of course, Husserl is not the first philosopher to suggest such a thing. As
Casey points out, Kant had argued that body is the source of orientation. Yet
Kant had not argued that the perceptual field pivoted entirely around the body.
(Casey 1998, 217–18.)
284 Husserl C § 9f, 43–44.
285 “The obscurity was strengthened and transformed still later with the devel-
the world, the sky is no longer the limit of the cosmos, infinite world. Perspec-
tive has the same function as philosophical critique: connection of subjectivity and
objectivity, [of] viewpoint and reality.” IP, 44. “[Donc], espace système. Corrélati-
vement : la terre n’est plus centre du monde, le ciel n’est plus limite du cosmos,
monde infini. [La] perspective a même fonction que philosophie critique : lien de
subjectivité et objectivité, [de] point de vue et réalité.” IP, 82.
288 PP, 296. “l’espace est assis sur notre facticité” PP, 294. See also PP, 316/319,
451/458
289 C, 51. “Au lieu d’un monde où la part de l’identique et celle du changement
les choses, mais le moyen par lequel la position des choses devient possible.” PP,
281.
291 As a side-remark, I wish point to Dürer’s diagrams. In his engravings on
perspective Dürer often marked the spot of the onlooker (the artist or scholar)
with a drawing of a single eye in profile. See, for instance, The Painter’s Manual,
which was originally published in 1525. The version published in 1538 contains
some new diagrams. (Dürer 1977.)
292 See, for instance, Van de Vall 2008, 17. | As Margaret Iversen points out,
perspective construction has also later been associated with male-centered, indi-
vidualistic ideologies. (Iversen 2005, 194; see also Damisch 1994, xiv–xv.)
293 On the discussion of perspective, see for instance, Damisch 1994; Crary 1995;
artist as a solitary, universal genius. Johnson, for instance, comments that Merleau-
Ponty was interested in the gaps and discontinuities in the persona of Leonardo da
90 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
How would the painter or poet express anything other than his
encounter with the world? What does abstract art itself speak
of, if not of a negation or refusal of the world? Now austerity and
the obsession with geometrical surfaces and forms [...] still have
an odor of life, even if it is a shameful or despairing life.298
rencontre avec le monde ? De quoi l’art abstrait lui-même parle-t-il, sinon d’une
négation ou d’un refus du monde ? Or l’austérité, la hantise des surfaces et des
formes géométriques [...] ont encore une odeur de vie, même s’il s’agit d’une vie
honteuse ou désespérée.” LV, 91.
4.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON THE PICTORIAL SPACE 91
its intentional connections with the world and to argue how there is
no “separate world” beyond the canvas. His interpretation of abstract
art is bound to the art scene of the time, and is thus also limited by
it. Véronique M. Fóti even points out that his comments on abstract
art refer to a specific art movement, geometric abstraction, which ex-
plores either geometric shapes, and/or protozoa — “infusorians and
microbes”, as Merleau-Ponty put it. Fóti even suggests that this de-
scription is an obvious reference to the works by the American painter
William Baziotes (1912–1963).299 Here, my aim is not to trace the the-
oretical aspirations of abstract painters, but I wish to point out that
Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation of abstract art does not do it justice.
Isabel Matos Dias suggests that in Cartesian space, Merleau-Ponty
finds a representation or figuration of the mental vision theorised by
Descartes. Here space is called “figurative”. However, in Cézannian,
or modern space, Merleau-Ponty finds an expression or a figuration
of sensible vision. Matos Dias argues that this juxtaposition suggests
another interpretation of the two models: art as imitation and art as
expression. In Matos Dias’ reading the confrontation is between art as
the copy of the world and art guided by the original.300 The former
shows art only as a form of illusionism, the latter would take seriously
the difficulties of perception and depth. Let me add that, within this
interpretative framework, abstract art could be characterised as totally
lacking a worldly point of reference, since it is neither an expression
nor a copy of the world. Instead, its space is close to a geometric space.
In “Eye and Mind” paintings seem to be classified and assessed ac-
cording to a criteria that emerges from the foundations of phenomenol-
ogy, namely lived experience. In Merleau-Ponty’s criticism of Cartesian
figurative space we find a rejection of all models. In the sensible vision,
on the other hand, we focus our reflections on lived experience in all its
ambiguities. From this standpoint, the critical attitude to abstract art
which Merleau-Ponty expresses, is based on the idea that abstract art
would aim at erasing or abandoning the lived experience on which it
necessarily rests.301 Escoubas underlines that we must go further than
Merleau-Ponty and not say that there is either abstract or figurative
space in a painting, for painting is always, in a singular manner, both
Paul Klee and Wassily Kandinsky. On the question of abstract art, see Fóti 2000;
also 1998.
92 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
Dürer across the Alps, it has become a commonplace, ubiquitous and routine”
(Elkins 1994, 3).
307 Elkins 1994, 263. | Elkins views the discussion on perspective as twofold: those
who wish to reconstruct the perspective practice, and those who are concerned with
the philosophical discussion on perspective, i.e., “positivist” and post-structuralist
endeavours.
308 According to Panofsky, the late medieval artists who did not know geometry
well enough, hid discrepancies with, for instance, a bit of drapery, or “some other
perspectival fig leaf”. In later readings of Panofsky, it also symbolises the urge to
reveal the “hidden” painting, to find clues to its secret. (Grootenboer 2005, 114–15.
For the history of perspective, see Kemp 1990.)
309 Œ, 49/135.
310 See Œ, 49, 90/135, 148. | Panofsky’s influence on Merleau-Ponty is visible
already for instance in the lecture notes “The Experience of Others” (“L’expérience
d’autrui”, 1951–52, published in MPS): “L’analyse de Panofsky nous met en garde
contre deux erreurs en ce qui concerne l’interprétation de l’histoire de l’art. 1) Il
serait faux d’imaginer qu’il y a derrière les peintres, pour aboutir à ses fins, un esprit
du monde (surartistes de Malraux). On n’a pas affaire à un inconscient historique
qui dirigerait les peintres à leur insu ; il faut comprendre que le peintre travaille et
94 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
least because he seems to forget his role as an art historian —, but he has also
been widely appreciated for drawing from various fields such as philosophy, optics,
theology and psychology. As one of the key figures in the field of visual culture,
W. J. T. Mitchell says in Picture Theory that Panofsky’s study can be seen to
mark a starting point for visual culture. (Mitchell 1995, 31; see also Damisch 1994,
2; Iversen 2005; Grootenboer 2005, 114.)
317 Panofsky 1991, 41.
96 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
n’est qu’un cas particulier, une date, un moment dans une information poétique
du monde qui continue après elle.” Œ, 51.
4.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON THE PICTORIAL SPACE 97
321 Œ, 135. “Les peintres, eux, savaient d’expérience [...] que la perspective linéaire
ture, d’une peinture toute réalisée est dépourvue de sens. Durerait-il des millions
d’années encore, le monde, pour les peintres, s’il en reste, sera encore à peindre.”
Œ, 90.
323 This conception is already introduced in Phenomenology of Perception in the
torian Robert Zwijnenberg refers to the debate over the origins of perspective. To
present the debate in a nutshell: to consider perspective as a discovery means that
it is universal, like a natural law waiting to be found. To consider it as invention
means to think of it as a cultural construction, reflecting the thinking of the era of
its creation. Panofsky’s thesis relates to the latter standpoint. According to Zwij-
nenberg one spokesman for perspective as discovery is E. H. Gombrich (1909–2001),
who considered linear perspective to be a better system of representation than any
other. This distinction into two camps undoubtedly oversimplifies the matter. Even
Panofsky and Gombrich cannot be claimed to actually hold such extreme view-
points. (Zwijnenberg 1999, 112–15.) Gombrich himself wrote how “Brunelleschi’s
perspective represents an objectively valid invention” (Gombrich 1976, 107.) For
a summary of the debate between Gombrich and Nelson Goodman, as well as
Gombrich’s counterarguments against Panofsky, see Carrier 1980. For Gombrich’s
standpoint, see for instance Gombrich’s essay “The ‘What’ and the ‘How’: Perspec-
tive Representation and the Phenomenal World” (1972) and “From the Revival of
Letters to the Reform of the Arts: Niccolò Niccoli and Flippo Brunelleschi” (1976).
In his own analysis Zwijnenberg wants to bypass the problems of the opposing pairs
100 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
ently. Van de Vall points in the right direction in arguing that Merleau-
Ponty’s aim is not to oppose “the ‘cultural fact’ of linear perspective to
a ‘natural’ (psychophysiological) vision that could be objectively, even
scientifically proved.”330 The opposition between cultural objectivities
and natural objectivities is misleading, and the whole problem of brute
vision has to be approached differently. Van de Vall’s interpretation
is based on the idea that no painting can represent or express brute
perception — “brute perception refers primarily to how, and only sec-
ondarily to what is depicted”331 —, instead paintings may stage brute
perception, i.e. provide a framing. In this reading, painting and wild or
brute perception would be connected in Merleau-Ponty’s thinking, but
not because it is represented in the artwork. The link is more complex
and involves the spectator: painting allows or provides the possibility
for brute perception. To put it differently, in Van de Vall’s reading,
brute perception would take place in our looking at the painting. Thus
the question is not only what the work itself is, or what the painter
does, but also what the painting enables in the encountering.332 Van
de Vall explains:
of a) tent, booth, banquet; stage (building), scene’ (IA, Dor.). No good etymology
exists, or the etymology is unknown. [...] According to DELG s.v., σκηνή originally
denoted any light construction of cloth hung between tree branches in order to
provide shadow, under which one could shelter, sleep, celebrate festivities, etc. ..
.. derived from the root σκη-/σκά- < *skeh- which is found in σκίιαά ‘shade’ as
well. See there for further etymology. Borrowed ad Lat. Scaena (only in the sense
of ‘stage’)” (Beekes 2009, 1349). Or: “Σκηνή, dor. f. ‘Zelt(dach), Bude, Schmaus;
Bühne(ngebäude), Szene’ (ion.att., dor) Kompp., z.B. Zeltbau (Arist.), ‘das Laub-
hüttenfest’ (LXX, NT u.a.)” (Frisk 1970).
4.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON THE PICTORIAL SPACE 103
and these structures give birth to the modern space, which is defined
by the tension between near and far. The Renaissance space is a sys-
tem of relations, a process of transparence, and is incorporeal, as the
spectator stays outside the space. Such incorporeal space is completely
constructed by using architectural, measurable and mathematical ele-
ments and it is “lifeless”.337 In Escoubas’ view, Renaissance painting
does not so much represent say, a city, but the ideality of space. Thus,
space is being represented in its purity. In general, the perspective is
seen as a means of restoring the pure visibility of the visible.338
Escoubas explicates a tension within the development of the sense
of linear perspective. The Latin term would refer to a look that en-
ters the space and inhabits it, the Italian term would refer to a look
that stays outside the space, and is thus in this sense incorporeal. Es-
coubas’ reading brings forth — once again — the complexity of the
idea of perspective. She repeats her analysis on the nature of per-
spective in a later work, L’espace pictural. Here she remarks that the
pictorial space of the Renaissance should not be interpreted merely
through the paradigm of modern natural and mathematical sciences.
This is because pictorial space is subjected to the conditions of visi-
bility according to historical modalities, but these are not reducible to
the conditions for the reproduction of the real. Pictorial space is plu-
ral and therefore never simply figurative.339 Escoubas’ explication and
interpretation shows a crucial aspect of Merleau-Ponty’s concept of
Cartesian or figurative space. By following Escoubas, figurative space,
too, can be characterised as space more in terms of “iconic” expression
rather than as objective space; it thematises the role of the spectator.
I shall next look into so-called modern or Cézannian space and
examine some of the criticisms presented against it. Throughout his
career Merleau-Ponty emphasised that it was Cézanne who broke the
domination of linear perspective.340 This required that in his paint-
337 Escoubas refers to Husserl’s “L’arche originaire Terre” (Escoubas 1995, 49).
338 Escoubas 1986, 138–39, 142; 1995, 45.
339 Escoubas 1986, 142; 1995, 35–36.
340 Merleau-Ponty is not the only philosopher to agree with this interpretation.
Maldiney, for instance, points out three different “periods” within the spatiality of
visual arts: “Trois fois dans l’histoire de la peinture, l’espace du paysage est venu à
son dévoilement dans l’Ouvert : une fois en Chine avec le paysage ‘Montagne(s) et
eau(x)’ des Song, une fois au XVIIe siècle avec les plus grands paysagistes hollan-
dais, une fois dans la tonalité impressionniste avec les paysages de Cézanne, de van
Gogh et de Seurat, les trois fois par le rythme, de quel abîme issu ? L’expérience
peut répondre.” (Maldiney 1994, 151.) Also, Cézanne’s painting is not a homoge-
nous totality, and Merleau-Ponty acknowledged this. (IP, 87/48.)
104 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
341 Matos Dias 2001, 145. | Merleau-Ponty’s reading of Cézanne is based on partic-
ular sources, namely interviews, letters and contemporary studies, presumably Lil-
iane Guerry’s Cézanne et l’expression de l’espace (1950), as well as Cézanne’s con-
temporaries such as Émile Zola, Émile Bernard’s La methode de Cézanne (1920),
and Joachim Gasquet’s Cézanne (1921). (DC, 14/60; IP, 86/99; Œ, 7/121.)
342 “[...] — which could realize a copy of the real. Such an ideal amounts to a
scientific aim more than to a desire for a meeting with or between living being(s).
Life as such never can be reproduced as it is.” (Irigaray 2004, 393.)
4.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON THE PICTORIAL SPACE 105
of painting as practical work, and that the artist’s gaze and his or her
movements are instruments that serve pre-established practical ends.
Was not one of the most important lessons of Phenomenology of Per-
ception the argument that all perception is intertwined with desire?
In the beginning of the chapter on sexuality we read: “Let us try to
see how a thing or a being begins to exist for us through desire or love
and we shall thereby come to understand better how things and beings
can exist in general.”343 Moreover, Irigaray’s criticism contains at its
core the claim that for Merleau-Ponty the painter is a solitary subject,
unable to meet and connect with another living being. This would be
as if the painter were alone in his or her search for the ultimate point in
which his or her perception would turn into a non-corporeal medium,
a transparent tool that would reveal the world as it is in itself. Such a
neglect of encountering might characterise some sections of Merleau-
Ponty’s early writings, but his approach changes in his later works,
where he subjects the roles of subject and object to closer examina-
tion. I shall examine the possibility of encountering the other in more
detail in the following chapters.
We may turn back to Cézanne once more to look into the argument
that artists are merely instruments. Does Merleau-Ponty truly claim
that he worked merely as an instrument? The way in which Merleau-
Ponty refers to the efforts it took for Cézanne to create a painting in
no way speaks of a painter who merely worked as an instrument. There
is another kind of approach to Cézanne, too: Jonathan Crary, whose
detailed study includes critical remarks on Husserl and Merleau-Ponty,
suggests that rather than taking Cézanne as an innocent eye, we must
consider him to be an observer who was astonishingly alert to whatever
was anomalous in perceptual experience.344 Cézanne had the urge to
approach “raw” vision, but it does not necessarily make him innocent,
or even ignorant, about the gimmicks of vision.345 Crary writes how
343 PP, 178. “Cherchons à voir comment un objet ou un être se met à exister pour
nous par le désir ou par l’amour et nous comprendrons mieux par là comment des
objets et des êtres peuvent exister en général.” PP, 180.
344 Crary 1999, 287.
345 Crary’s analysis of how perception and attention is shaped by Western moder-
nity sheds light on the various ways our perception is controlled. His interest is
directed towards the perceptual process. Crary examines Husserl’s and Merleau-
Ponty’s writings as well as other contemporary tendencies in relation to Cézanne.
Concerning the nature of attention and perception at the end of 19th century he
writes: “These problems took shape around many, often radically different positions
and practices concerning the possibility of ‘pure perception’, and the possibility of
‘presence’ within perception.” (Crary 1999, 282.)
106 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
ogy of Perception, especially in the chapter “Space”, and it continues in the lecture
notes on Cartesian ontology (1960–1961). (PP, 281–344/283–347; NC, 180–82.)
“For God, who is everywhere, breadth is immediately equivalent to depth. In-
tellectualism and empiricism do not give us any account of the human expe-
rience of the world; they tell us what God might think about it.” (PP, 298.)
4.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON THE PICTORIAL SPACE 107
“[t]hings encroach upon one another because they are outside one an-
other. The proof of this is that I can see depth in a painting which
everyone agrees has none [...]”.350 Here, the true problem of depth is
not yet formulated, depth is just an issue of a variable point of view.
“Descartes was right in liberating space: his mistake was to erect it
into a positive being, beyond all points of view, all latency and depth,
devoid of any real thickness.”351
Towards the end of the third chapter of “Eye and Mind”, Merleau-
Ponty describes how rather than being the third, last, dimension, depth
is the first. More precisely, it is to be experienced as the reversibility of
dimensions. Depth is “a voluminosity we express in a world when we
say that a thing is there.”352 There is another passage where Merleau-
Ponty uses the term “voluminosity”, but here it is used to characterise
our experience of looking at a painting:
l’ériger en un être tout positif, au-delà de tout point de vue, de toute latence,
de toute profondeur, sans aucune épaisseur vraie” Œ, 48. | In the lecture notes
on Cartesian ontology, Merleau-Ponty writes: “Abandon de la notion de dimen-
sion comme rapport ou point de vue d’où se fait mesure. ‘Point de vue’ évoque
projection.” (NC, 169.)
352 Œ 140. “d’une voluminosité qu’on exprime d’un mot en disant qu’une chose
elle fait que nous n’avons pas besoins de ‘sens musculaire’ pour avoir la voluminosité
du monde. Cette vision dévorante, par-delà les ‘données visuelles’, ouvre sur une
texture de l’Être dont les messages sensoriels discrets ne sont que les ponctuations
ou les césures, et que l’œil habite, comme l’homme sa maison.” Œ, 27.
108 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
In a forest, I have felt many times over that it was not I who
looked at the forest. Some days I felt that the trees were looking
at me, were speaking to me. . . . I was there, listening. . . . I think
that the painter must be penetrated by the universe and not want
to penetrate it. . . . I expect to be inwardly submerged, buried.
Perhaps I paint to break out.357
qui regardais la forêt. J’ai senti, certains jours, que c’étaient les arbres qui me re-
gardaient, qui me parlent... Moi j’étais là, écoutant... Je crois que le peintre doit
être transpercé par l’univers et non vouloir le transpercer... J’attends d’être inté-
rieurement submergé, enseveli. Je peins peut-être pour surgir.” Œ, 31; Marchand
in an interview with Georges Charbonnier. (Charbonnier 2002, 109–15; see also
NC, 171.)
4.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON THE PICTORIAL SPACE 109
a cette singulière propriété de sentir, lui aussi Nous avons vu toute à l’heure que
jamais les deux mains ne sont en même temps l’une à l’égard de l’autre touchées
et touchantes.” PP, 109. “when I touch my right hand with my left, my right hand,
as an object, has the strange property of being able to feel too. We have just seen
that the two hands are never simultaneously in the relationship of touched and
touching to each other.” PP, 106.
359 “Il y a un cercle du touché et du touchant, le touché saisit le touchant ; il y a
vision are not seen as stable, or fixed anymore, but are understood and
characterised by dynamic concepts: chiasm, intertwining, flesh. Here,
vision is changing, too. As I and the other, the subject and the object,
enter into this dynamic intertwining, the focus of analysis moves away
from the subject, and towards the process of visibility itself.361
The change is enabled by the set of concepts that seems quite indis-
pensable to describe the experience.362 As we are examining spatiality
closer, I underline how Merleau-Ponty’s emphasis is moving away from
the subject to shared visibility; his thinking about space itself is, too,
changing towards plurality. The seer who becomes seen cannot merely
“see with” somebody else, but these looks and this gaze must inter-
twine into a myriad of looks where the original is no longer traced.
painted has to be taken further. For instance, the painter is concerned with what is
in between the object — as Escoubas points out, what is unreal, irréel. (Escoubas
1995, 110.)
362 Irigaray’s criticism could still haunt this description: in Merleau-Ponty’s de-
scription a relationship between two is not necessarily drawn, but rather a rela-
tionship between one and many, as in me and others. (Irigaray 2001, 17.)
363 I am aware that from the debate concerning perspective in Merleau-Ponty the
are found in postcards or other similar material. She paints with oil on
plexiglass, which gives the works a certain immaterial feel. Through
her working methods, she could be associated with painters like Luc
Tuymans (b. 1958) and Marlene Dumas (b. 1953), who also work with
photography, or with, for instance, Nina Roos (b. 1956), who paints
on plexiglass. Both Tuymans and Dumas draw from photography, and
other surrounding imagery.365 With Marlene Dumas the term second-
hand imagery refers to this practice of recycling images, whereas Tuy-
mans has described painting as a medium of belatedness.366
I want to show how Mielonen’s paintings provide a possibility to
address certain central aspects of spatiality and looking which open up
Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology of art in a fruitful way. Let me clar-
ify by discussing three of Mielonen’s works, painted in 2005 and 2007.
In the light of Merleau-Ponty’s account of painting, I am particularly
interested in the processes which take place in Mielonen’s paintings.
In interviews, Mielonen has described her working methods and has
revealed that she often finds the impulse for her paintings from post-
cards or travel brochures. The interest in “second hand” imagery of
landscapes and places has lasted for several years. However, she does
not see it as her primary task to explore the cultural history that this
imagery brings out. For her, the significance lies in the painting itself,
both in the act of painting and in its result.367
Thinking about process of Mielonen’s painting, a postcard or other
kind of travel image, a scene caught by the photographer’s trained eye,
always provides the initial impetus. From the outset, this particular
image might not be anything out of ordinary. Often these travel im-
ages present cultural conventions on what and how things are seen:
after all, for a tourist, a postcard is a way to show or share a visual
impression. Of course, the images of popular views do not coincide
with one’s own experience, and instead they often present the scene in
an idealised or conventional manner. According to Marion’s definition,
which I discussed in chapter 3, this imagery can be seen as images that
365 For the use of photography, see Hal Foster’s The Return of the Real: The
Avant-Garde at the End of the Century (1996).
366 Tuyman’s imagery is more connected with history, whereas Dumas is more
linked with popular culture, yet both deal with serious issues such as death. There
is indeed a certain dissociation in painting that does not characterise photogra-
phy or video, which along with the new digital technology are considered to be
almost instant mediums. Besides contemporary paintings, there is a wide variety
of painters such as Johannes Vermeer and Piet Mondrian who have influenced
Mielonen. (Hacklin 2008.)
367 Hacklin 2008.
112 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
are meant for consumers to devour and define, and as such they can
be easily bypassed.
Nevertheless, there is always something particular in the image
that catches the artist’s eye, be it a feature of the composition, a
distinct colour perspective, or a particular detail. However, the image
which serves as a point of departure for the painting is never preserved
by it: the paintings are an interpretation of shared visuality, a study
of coming into presence of the painter’s vision. Thus, the painting
necessarily gives birth to something new, as Mielonen freely examines
the elements she finds fascinating, namely the exchange between the
visible elements and the dynamism of paint. The painting embodies the
perception of the artist, her study of particular features of visibility,
atmosphere, shades, and plexiglass emphasises her brushstrokes. The
final painting is often finished at one go, as the aim of the artist is to
reach a certain precise, yet spontaneous impression.
In my reading of Mielonen’s paintings, I want to emphasise the
multi-layered character or entanglement of perceptions, i.e. these dif-
ferent layers of perceiving. This “tissue of looks” includes more than
simply the vision of the painter and beholder; instead these layers that
are made up of various different ways of looking, complete the tradition
of perceiving, and inevitably there are certain time-lapses in between.
The first Mielonen’s paintings that I want to study in detail is called
Rider (2005). The painting presents a scene with a rider in a valley
(see figure A.1).368 The landscape around the figure seems leafy, even
luscious. The shades of green change from dark, almost black to bright
bluish jade green. The figure of the rider — he or she, presumably on
a horse — is riding on a path that diagonally runs from the left side of
the painting towards the right corner. The rider is placed close to lower
right corner and the painting carries a feeling of pressure. The steep
mountain on the left side appears to be collapsing down on the figure.
Also, it is not clear whether the scene contains a valley — the masses
of green simply hover in the painting. The figures of rider and horse
seem to merge into the surrounding space and it is not possible to get
a detailed perception of them. The shapes and masses of colours in the
painting manage to at one moment break the surface of the painting,
and at another moment reorganise it again into a landscape.
The second painting, Trailer (2005) has much brighter colours than
Rider. Here, the scene is likewise governed by strong diagonal elements
which give an effect of movement (see figure A.2). There are also many
similar shades to the previous painting, but the feeling here is much
lighter. The shade of olive green marks greenery which divides what
looks like a trailer and a parking lot seen from what one presumes to
be the road or highway. The green shapes are bordered with brighter,
pear-shaded green. The sky that covers almost half of the painting’s
surface, is quite even, and there are no visible brushstrokes. The area is
almost uniformly light or powder blue, yet there are some shimmering,
white tones next to a diagonal form painted in old rose, which seems to
form a hillside in the background scenery. Within the painting, there
is also a thin and eye-catching line, a brilliant rose-shaded diagonal
stroke that marks the border of the road, passing by a greyish pole
that is likewise by the side of the road. On a parking lot, an ivory-
white travel trailer or mobile home is parked. No cars are visible on
this seemingly isolated parking lot.
Terrace, a painting from 2007 presents a view from what is pre-
sumably a terrace of a steep mountain with some overlooking houses
on the mountainside (see figure A.3). The sky is dominant but painted
smooth, whereas the mountain is created with brushstrokes that give
an impression of a rocky structure with steep shadows. The shape on
the left hand side is dark brown, absorbing light, whereas the opposing
mountain steep is bathed in sunshine. The terrace itself seems to be
more difficult to fathom, or less stable: it is as though it stands on air;
there is a certain feeling of vertigo, as if the ground beneath the spec-
tators’ feet would crumble at any minute. The motif of the mountain
means that this painting might remind one of various other paintings,
not least Cézanne’s studies of mountain scenes.
the travel imagery is tightly linked to the tradition of landscape painting from the
fifteenth century onwards, and in the ways in which certain places and sceneries
have been represented. The topic of landscape has also been connected with the
political aspects as the term landscape originally derives from Landschaft, a term
that referred to a particular kind of polity. (Casey 2002, 4, 258; Olwig 2002, 10.)
370 Within art history, this step could be linked with a certain Anglo-American
372 I have already mentioned that the question of space is dealt with in Phe-
nomenology of Perception, but as Sue L. Cataldi puts it, a new sense of depth is
emerging in The Visible and the Invisible. (Cataldi 1993, 57; see also Matos Dias
2001, 162.)
373 VI, 113. “Car le présent visible n’est pas dans le temps et l’espace, ni, bien
entendu, hors d’eux : il n’y a rien avant lui, après lui, autour de lui, qui puisse
rivaliser avec sa visibilité. Et pourtant, il n’est pas seul, il n’est pas tout. Exacte-
ment : il bouche ma vue, c’est-à-dire, à la fois, que le temps et l’espace s’étendent
au-delà, et qu’ils sont derrière lui, en profondeur, en cachette.” VI, 150.
374 In Phenomenology of Perception Merleau-Ponty wrote that depth was “invis-
375 In“Eye and Mind” Merleau-Ponty refers how a painting opens up its own web
of meanings, which overrides all genealogy and causality. (Œ, 62–3/139.)
4.2. SUSPENDED LANDSCAPE 117
develops in his The World at a Glance (2007). Suffice to say that his treatment of
the glance opens up a new reading on its importance.
118 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
brut” Œ, 13.
4.2. SUSPENDED LANDSCAPE 119
other way around, we are leaving the trailer behind, distancing our-
selves from an almost unoccupied resting place. Or perhaps we cross
the road to make an improvised walking trip into the surrounding
landscape that does not yet appear to be anything particular — on
the contrary, the painting takes us into the middle of an anonymous
landscape. The scene in the painting invites the look to glide over it, as
if there would be nothing specific to cling to, nothing out of ordinary,
and yet it all appears familiar in a haunting way: our gaze returns to
the painting. Even the title of the painting creates a tension: “Trailer”
is by definition either an unpowered vehicle pulled by a car, a mo-
bile home, or a trailer is a movie trailer, a preview run in cinemas or
television to advertise a movie. A promise of something, or a leftover.
Possibly the belatedness of painting is here its ability to make be-
lieve it has always been somewhere there in the background, waiting
to be recognised. In this sense Mielonen’s work would again manifest
the Merleau-Pontian attitude in which the painter’s task is to disclose
the ambivalent and dynamic process of perception, the appearing of a
landscape or any other aspect that the painter is studying. Mielonen’s
paintings explore fundamental questions concerning the task of paint-
ing, e.g. the materiality, heaviness and lightness of paint, the precision
and easiness of the brushstrokes. By her way of using ready-made ele-
ments, the painter is able to disclose the intertwining of different looks
and visions. In this way her paintings do not let the spectator look at
the painting simply as an image, but demand that he or she looks at
— or with — it as an icon with multiple texture, spatial and temporal:
“Thus, there can be beings that are not in itself and yet are not noth-
ing: paintings — icons”.384 As explained in the previous chapter, the
other essential feature of an icon is its unfinished nature. The icon is
not finished and completed, but open and thus invites new visions and
new forms of visibility. The icon transcends and questions the usual
category of the image as copy, it is a presentation in which the in-
visible and visible are both disclosed — and disclosed in their mutual
dependency.
In the case of Mielonen, the “openness” of the paintings can be un-
derstood as including the movement between the own and the alien, the
familiar and the strange, and more importantly the experience of a cer-
tain gap, an écart between them. How should we understand this term
that has such a central position in Merleau-Ponty’s work? Galen A.
384 “C’est ainsi qu’il peut y avoir des êtres qui ne sont pas de l’en soi et qui ne
sont pas de rien : les tableaux — les icônes.” NC, 174.
120 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
Johnson argues that “écart” refers to the “experience that is not in full
possession of itself, experience of dispossession.”385 Lawrence Hass has
described it as “a constitutive difference in the fabric of experience”. He
explains further: “For [Merleau-Ponty], this constitutive difference is
what opens, for example, the seer to the seen, but it is an opening that
isn’t so severe that the two aspects are divorced from one another”.386
And we saw above that in Escoubas’ reading, écart determined a cer-
tain shift in the encountering of the artwork. It marks the difference
that enables us to “see with” the work of art, as opposed to looking at
something through it. In other words, Escoubas suggested that écart
marks the difference between grasping the space of the painting as a
representation or reproduction of the real and grasping it as the space
of manifestation of being.387
Following Escoubas’ interpretation of Merleau-Ponty’s concept, I
would like to argue that écart also includes the constitutive element of
all encountering. The sudden dissociation, surprise or rupture that is
needed in order for a meeting between the two to be possible: between
the reader and the book or two persons, between two places of lived
space, or between two eras of historical time.388 With respect to paint-
ing, I propose that écart could be understood as the principle without
which the encountering with art is not possible: it is the spatial and
temporal distance which enables the experience of being apart from
oneself. This is only possible by the sudden shift and change of focus
that the experience of the other provides. I suggest that the vision
Mielonen’s paintings stages, addresses the experience of écart, as the
constitutive difference or an experience of dispossession. For instance,
in connection with the painting entitled Terrace, there is, in me, a fun-
damental uneasiness, a shift, as my glance follows the structures built
on the mountain slope — there is a sense of vertigo from the steepness
of the scenery, as well as from the sudden lack of support, that I as a
spectator feel. Similarly, for instance, through the title Mielonen has
chosen for her painting, Rider, the work connects it with a series of
rider-themed works of visual arts and historical rider figures in popular
385 Johnson 2010, 179. | Johnson also points out that this term is absent from “Eye
and Mind”. M. C. Dillon, who has examined the proximity of Derrida’s différance
and Merleau-Ponty’s écart, writes: “Merleau-Ponty conceives presence in terms of
perceptual experience that incorporates the dehiscence named as écart.” (Dillon
1997, 4.)
386 Hass 2008, 129. | Hass further underlines that écart is not a concept in the
paysage de ma vie, parce qu’il est, non pas un troupeau errant de sensations ou un
système de jugements éphémères, mais un segment de la chair durable du monde,
est prégnant, en tant que visible, de bien d’autres visions que la mienne ; et les
visible que je vois, dont je parle, même si ce n’est pas l’Hymette ou les platanes
de Delphes, est le même numériquement que voyaient, dont parlaient Platon et
Aristote. Quand je retrouve le monde actuel, tel qu’il est, sous mes mains, sous
mes yeux, contre mon corps, je retrouve beaucoup plus qu’un objet : un Être dont
ma vision fait partie, une visibilité plus vielle que mes opérations ou mes actes.
Mais cela ne veut pas dire qu’il y ait, de moi à lui, fusion, coïncidence ; au contraire,
cela se fait parce qu’une sorte de déhiscence ouvre en deux mon corps, et qu’entre
lui regardé et lui regardant, lui touché et lui touchant, il y a recouvrement ou
empiétement, de sorte qu’il faut dire que les choses passent en nous aussi bien que
122 CHAPTER 4. PHENOMENOLOGY OF PAINTING
Concluding Remarks
In this chapter I have discussed the central tension in Merleau-Ponty’s
phenomenological understanding of painted space, the tension between
the Renaissance perspective as a form of Cartesian vision, on the one
hand, and Cézannian space as the engulfment in the sensible world.
My exegetic goal was to study how the Merleau-Pontian conception of
space is more complex than it seems at first hand. His understanding
of space and depth changes towards the end of his life, so that in
the final works the look of the painter is no longer directed at the
space in front, but is engulfed in the depth of the visible world, in the
invisible. Through this change, I was able to open anew the questions
of contemporary painting’s spatiality.
I used these resources in the investigation of Mielonen’s paintings.
The application had two goals: first, I explicated and interpreted se-
lected aspects of Mielonen’s works, and secondly I used this explication
to develop further Merleau-Ponty’s conception of painting and its re-
125
126 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
whether we have entered, from the 1970s onwards, into the Post-Medium condition,
as stated by Rosalind Krauss (1999), or whether more than ever photography
matters as art, as stated by Michael Fried (2008).
394 Melville has pointed to certain discussions on photography, that understand
the camera as “most simply a machine for producing automatic linear perspective
renditions of the world.” (Melville 1990, 13.)
395 Price & Wells 2002, 22. | I cannot possibly cover the discussion here, but I
would like to point to two classic texts. Walter Benjamin’s “The Work of Art in the
Age of Mechanical Reproduction” (“Das Kunstwerk im Zeitalter seiner technischen
Reproduzierbarkeit”, 1936) examines the meaning of photographic invention to art
in general, whereas Roland Barthes’ Camera Lucida (La chambre claire, 1980)
discusses the nature of photography itself.
396 On Finnish artistic research and photography, see, for instance, Elo 2007.
5.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON PHOTOGRAPHY 127
This citation from Benjamin shows, how besides the idea that a
camera can exceed natural vision, photography has also been viewed
as a direct copy of reality. Still in the 1980s some philosophers, such
as Roger Scruton, were of the opinion that photography was simply
a mechanical reproduction of the object. This was a reason for pho-
397 Fóti writes how Merleau-Ponty is driven by ontological interest: “as though
it might alienate him from the tasks and respectability of philosophical discourse.
Painting, in short, is neither interrogated in its own being nor allowed to concern
itself with problems intrinsic to it.” (Fóti 2000, 143.)
398 Benjamin 1936.
128 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
399 “The ideal photograph also stands in a certain relation to a subject: a pho-
tograph is a photograph of something. But the relation is here causal and not
intentional.” (Scruton 1981, 579; see also Armstrong 2000, 5–10.) This is not to say
that there has not been significant theorisation of photography before, but simply
to demonstrate how photography’s position has changed from the 1960s.
400 Œ, 144. “Les photographies de Marey, les analyses cubistes, la Mariée de
Duchamp ne bougent pas : elles donnent une rêverie zénonienne sur le mouvement.”
Œ, 78.
401 Marey saw Muybridge’s images in a French journal in 1878, which had an
effect on his experiments as they influenced him to develop his own technique,
chronophotography. (Doane 2002, 49.)
402 Crary 1999, 138. | Crary remarks in another passage on the chronophotographs
how “Marey’s image, especially in the late 1880s with their overlapping transparen-
cies, are also a repudiation of perceptual fusion, in that they constitute a visual
field in which the viewer shifts back and forth between different levels of organiza-
tion — between a holistic perception of a single temporal vector and an aggregate
apprehension of isolated positions.” (Crary 1999, 161–62.)
403 Doane 2002, 46, 85.
5.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON PHOTOGRAPHY 129
sol, en plein mouvement donc, ses jambes presque repliées sous lui, a-t-il l’air de
sauter sur place ? Et pourquoi par contre les chevaux de Géricault courent-ils sur la
toile, dans une posture pourtant qu’aucun cheval au galop n’a jamais prise ? C’est
que les chevaux du Derby d’Epsom me donnent à voir la prise du corps sur le sol,
et que, selon une logique du corps et du monde que je connais bien, ces prises sur
l’espace sont aussi des prises sur la durée.” Œ, 80.
405 Even though Marey resisted the cinema, his experiments with movement con-
about these works? The painting, Epsom Derby (1821, also known as
Races at Epsom), is a work by Jean-Louis-André-Théodore Géricault
(1791–1824). Again, Merleau-Ponty’s choice of example was not made
haphazardly. Géricault was a romanticist, who was known for having a
great passion for horses.407 His paintings demonstrate how the empha-
sis in romanticism was on the strong emotion of the experience. Now,
from the career of Marey, we have learned that he was obsessed by
the challenge to capture movement. He states: “motion is the most ap-
parent characteristic of life; it manifests itself in all the functions; it is
even the essence of several of them.”408 Marey’s project has been con-
nected with the urge to create a concept of life adequate to modernity,
where the concepts of movement, process and change were central. All
in all, the goal of Marey’s research was the fragmentation and analysis
of movement — this meant that at best his images would show an
object that appears not to have moved.409
I argue that even though Merleau-Ponty states that photography is
incapable of presenting movement in comparison to painting or sculp-
ture, the main point of his criticism concerns the scientific attitude.
From his perspective, Marey is situated within the natural attitude,
he saw the world through science, and the world exists for science to
be explored.410 All in all, Merleau-Ponty’s criticism of photography
was not exceptional. The limitation of photography he pointed at was
similar to the critique of science that looks at things from above, from
tout cas, si elles sont grandes, le sens qu’on leur donne après coup est issu d’elles.”
(Œ, 62.) “And it is always by looking more deeply into how it came about that we
make and will go on making new representations of it. As for the history of works
of art, in any case, if they are great, the sense we give to them later on has issued
from them.” (Œ, 139.)
407 He had studied under Carle Vernet (1758–1835), a horse painter who was fa-
mous for his hunting scenes. Géricault suffered from riding accidents that affected
his health, and he died at the age of 33. During Géricault’s lifetime he had oc-
casionally been called “ce fou de Géricault”, “the Fool Géricault”, because of his
move away from traditional norms of perception, thought and behaviour: this was
only confirmed by the subject he embraced especially in his collaboration with
doctor Étienne-Jean Georget (1795–1828) at the end of his career, namely mental
patients, whose passion Géricault admired. (Miller 1942, 152, 161; Régis 1992, 112,
166.)
408 E. J. Marey, Animal Mechanism: A Treatise on Terrestrial and Aërial Loco-
motion (New York: D. Appelton, 1874), 27. Cited in Doane 2002, 46.
409 Doane 2002, 46–59, 213.
410 For Husserl’s description of natural attitude, see for instance Husserl I II, §
49d.
5.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON PHOTOGRAPHY 131
[T]hose styles which escape their creator’s view and become vis-
ible only when the museum gathers together works scattered
around the world or when photography enlarges miniatures,
transforms a section of a painting by its way of framing it,
changes rugs, coins and stained-glass windows into paintings,
and brings to painting a consciousness of itself which is always
retrospective.414
411 Granted, photography’s position at the end of the 1950s was very different
from today’s situation. Photography had a long way to go before it reached the po-
sition it holds today — and yet already from the early inventions in photography,
the ambition for it to be more than just a mechanical medium, had been present.
On the other hand, by the 1950s there had been many famous photographers who
have been considered artists, for instance, Alfred Stieglitz (1864–1946), El Lissitzky
(1890–1941) and László Moholy-Nagy (1895–1946). Man Ray (1890–1976) and Lee
Miller (1907–1977) had developed their technique of solarisation in the 1920s. Nev-
ertheless, photography was still decades away from the position it nowadays holds.
It was only in the late 1970s and 1980s that photographs were made large scale
and hung on walls. (Kriebel 2007, 15; Fried 2008, 2.)
412 First published in L’Arc, reprinted in 1978.
413 Damisch 1978, 71.
414 PM, 68. “ces styles qui échappent au regard de leur créateur et ne deviennent
visibles que quand le Musée rassemble les œuvres dispersées à travers la terre,
ou quand la photographie agrandit les miniatures, transforme par ses cadrages un
morceau du tableau, transforme en tableaux les vitraux, les tapis et les monnaies
132 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
situations which would be out of reach for the original itself. Above all, it enables
the original to meet the beholder halfway, be it in the form of a photograph or a
phonograph record. The cathedral leaves its locale to be received in the studio of
a lover of art; the choral production, performed in an auditorium or in the open
air, resounds in the drawing room.” (Benjamin 1936.)
416 Fóti 2000, 141.
5.2. THE EXPRESSION OF MOVEMENT 133
The photograph keeps open the instants which the onrush of time
closes up forthwith; it destroys the overtaking, the overlapping,
the “metamorphosis” [Rodin] of time. This is what painting, in
contrast, makes visible, because the horses have in them that
“leaving here, going there,” because they have a foot in each
instant.420
ers, the psychologist and central figure of Gestalt psychology, Max Wertheimer
(1880–1943), by Henri Bergson as well as by psychologist Albert Michotte
(1881–1965). Michotte published his The Perception of Causality (La perception
de la causalité) in 1945, and thus his influence is visible after Phenomenology of
Perception.
418 Œ, 144. “Comme elle a créé la ligne latente, la peinture s’est donné un mou-
the way that ordinary, perceptible things show themselves. Not, for instance, as a
stone shows itself, protruding from the earth into brilliant sunlight. One never sees
or hears time itself as one sees and hears things, even though it seems that time
somehow haunts all the things one sees and hears.” (Sallis 2000, 12.)
420 Œ, 145 “La photographie maintient ouverts les instants que la poussée du
For example, the bird which flies across my garden is, during the
time that it is moving, merely a greyish power of flight [...] It is
not I who recognize, in each of the points and instants passed
through, the same bird defined by explicit characteristics, it is
the bird in flight which constitutes the unity of its movement,
which changes its place, it is this flurry of plumage still here,
which is already there in a kind of ubiquity, like the comet with
its tail.423
421 PP, 160–61/159–61. | In the lecture course Nature, he remarks that: “Le mou-
vement perçu à l’état naissant est toujours un mouvement qui va quelque part. Ce
qui est absurde pour le physicien qui définit le mouvement non par le terme vers
lequel il va, mais par ses antécédents.” (N, 204–205.) “Movement perceived in its
nascent state is always a movement that goes somewhere. This is absurd for the
physicist, who defines movement not by the term toward which it goes, but by its
antecedents.” (N, 153.) The notes have been published in Nature. Course Notes
from the Collège de France (La nature. Notes Cours du Collège de France, 1968).
422 PP, 313. “à penser clairement le mouvement, je ne comprends pas qu’il puisse
jamais commencer pour moi et m’être donné comme phénomène.” PP, 311.
423 PP, 320–21. “Par exemple, l’oiseau qui franchit mon jardin n’est dans le mo-
ment même du mouvement qu’une puissance grisâtre de voler [...] Ce n’est pas
moi qui reconnais en chacun des points et des instants traversés le même oiseau
défini par des caractères explicites, c’est l’oiseau en volant qui fait l’unité de son
mouvement, c’est lui qui se déplace, c’est ce tumulte plumeux encore ici qui est
déjà là-bas dans une sorte d’ubiquité, comme la comète avec sa queue.” PP, 318.
5.2. THE EXPRESSION OF MOVEMENT 135
424 A summary of the course has been published in Résumés de course. Collège
de France 1952–1960, see RC, 11–21.
425 Kristensen 2008, 245–46.
426 For a Merleau-Pontian reading of Rodin’s work, see Johnson 2010.
427 “le mouvement n’est pas d’abord changement de lieu, mais formule interne
d’un faire, éclatement d’un corps vers ce qu’il quitte et ce qu’il approche.” NC,
172.
136 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
rité phénoménale du mouvement qui les relie aux yeux du spectateur” VI, 206. |
Granted, today the veritable medium of movement is not a still image, but a mov-
ing image. However, besides film, the wide variety of media art examines movement
— and sometimes movement is best examined through stillness. An interesting ex-
ample of approaching the limit of movement can be found, for instance, in Bill
Viola’s works, in his The Quintet Series (2000). I will examine the thematic of
moving images together with temporality in chapter 6.
429 Barbaras 2000, 77–79; VI, 102/74.
430 VI, 109 n.* “ce qu’il y a de vrai : ce qui n’est pas rien est QUELQUE CHOSE,
mais : ce quelque chose n’est pas dur comme diamant, pas inconditionné, ERFAH-
RUNG.” VI, 144 n.* See also Barbaras 2000, 81.
431 Barbaras 2000, 82.
432 Barbaras 2006, 85.
5.2. THE EXPRESSION OF MOVEMENT 137
This means that neither can the subject for which the world ex-
ists be considered in terms of transparency and coincidence with itself.
Because, “the subject for which there is a world necessarily involves a
dimension of negativity.”433 We know how in the last texts of Merleau-
Ponty flesh was an important concept for the new ontology in order to
illustrate they way in which subject and object are dependent. In this
new order, the perception is dependent on the perceived being, and
not the other way around, where the perceived is based on perception.
In the late oeuvre of Merleau-Ponty, we see how the focus moves from
what is perceived to the moment of perceiving. This moment also pro-
vides a certain écart. In “Eye and Mind” there is a definition: “Seeing
is not a certain mode of thought or presence to self; it is the means
given me for being absent from myself [...]”.434 Barbaras asks: how
is one to deal with the meaning of being of embodied consciousness?
How is one to find the ground for subjectivity as essentially embodied,
without abolishing the transcendent dimension, without rejecting the
divergence, the écart found in the experience? He presents an interpre-
tation in which the essence of perception for Merleau-Ponty consists
of movement.435 Barbaras writes:
303.
442 Barbaras 2000, 87; VI, 255/303.
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 139
central Asia and Mongolia, but nowadays they are also found in cities either in ger
districts or among buildings.
447 Van de Vall 2008, 81. | This development would be connected in general with
the visualisation of culture, which was pointed out by Martin Heidegger in his essay
“The Age of the World Picture” (1938).
448 For instance on the hapticity of images, see section 6.3; see also Deleuze 2003,
126; Marks 2000, 129. | Slatman also argues how new technology has radically
changed the classical categories of the body. For instance, X-ray, ultrasound, in-
ternet cameras and virtual reality have blurred our conception of the body. The
understanding of our proper body is inseparable from the body imagery we access
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 141
In Marey’s early experiments the view was directed to, for instance,
the legs of horses. The form of Mayer’s work appears to be in line with
investigations of the early photographers. In all of them, photos were
taken at even intervals. However, Mayer’s work is addressing different
issues than the early scientific experiments. The aim of these experi-
ments was not analytical in the same way as Marey’s; as an experiment
Another city, not my own seems to simultaneously show and hide at
the same time. Mayer’s work does not try to dissect an object such as
a horse’s gallop into pieces. On the contrary in Mayer’s photos, the
spectator is invited to move both towards the animal and its world —
instead of pointing the camera at the animal, the camera is adjusted
to it, so that the spectator could see what it sees, experience the city
from another perspective — but simultaneously the spectator is also
shown something of his or her own experience. The thematics of the
work open up questions of the other and empathy, but also approach
questions concerning our being in the world and our inability to see
ourselves — topics that are closely related to movement.
Considering Mayer’s other works, there is an interesting counter-
part to Another city, not my own: a project done earlier in Brazil in
connection with an exhibition titled The Chronicle of the Brazilian
Expedition of Thomas Ender—Reconsidered (2004) gives an idea of
Mayer’s focus. In his piece, Audio description of the entire video ma-
terial brought back from a two-week travel through Brazil on the traces
of a 19th-century expedition,449 Mayer used a 3-hour video from the
trip in Brazil. In the final work, Mayer erased the video footage and
replaced it with discourse, a travelogue that was derived from the im-
ages. Instead of the images the monitor only shows a blank screen with
a time-code that displays the running time of the video. The spectator
can wear headphones and listen to the travelogue or reach for a book
— for instance, endoscopy, changes our body image and thus also what we conceive
of as the body proper. Imagery affects our primordial level of understanding of the
motoric and the sensuous. (Slatman 2004, 1; see also Van de Vall 2008, 78, 90.)
449 Mayer describes: “Audio description of the entire video material shot during a
to read a text in which the original imagery from the film is described
by using the standard description methods developed for the blind.
In another piece titled Gizmo (2009), Mayer worked with docu-
mentary material found in the Berliner Rundfunk archives. The topic
of the documentary was Ted Serios (1918–2006), a man who claimed
that he was able to produce images on Polaroid film using only his
psychic powers. In Mayer’s work, the spectator sees a loop of Ted Se-
rios concentrating, trying to make a “thoughtograph”, an image that
would be created on a Polaroid camera film held in a cylinder, which
he called “Gizmo”.450
Both Audio Description... and Gizmo present the question of image:
the former plays with the spectator’s ability to imagine or illustrate
what she or he hears from the headphones and the latter is a visuali-
sation of an attempt to create an image from the “mind”. Also in the
work discussed here, Another City, not my own, the question of image
is at stake. For one thing, its images are not “taken” by artists, but
have been created under certain pre-set parameters. All in all I suggest
that these works address our desire to see as well as a certain inca-
pability to perceive, that our seeing is directed according to different
preconceptions and prejudices.
The technique used in Another city, not my own connects with
automatism, a method used by the surrealists. In surrealist automa-
tism artists merely create circumstances or boundaries within which
the work may happen. Relating to this method, an obvious refer-
ence point for the work is in the situationists and their walking prac-
tice called dérive that drew inspiration from surrealist automatism.451
Mayer himself refers to the concept of dérive in the description of the
work. Dérive is one of the basic situationist practices. According to
the philosopher Sadie Plant, the Situationists were interested in chal-
lenging the urban environment and how it directs our actions.452 In
order to do this, they developed the method of dérive, drifting, in
which the aim was to lose all the prevailing relations to the surround-
ing space. Dérive is a mixture of rules and regulations as well as a
demand for playfulness. The inspiration for developing the practice
advertisements and lights, the circulation of traffic, the colours of front doors, and
the shapes of windows: urban lives are shaped in the most subtle and neglected
way by the arrangements of space. The situations in which we live are created for
us.” (Plant 2000, 57.)
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 143
of a dérive comes from the habitual, rather limited patterns that the
people living in the city tend to follow. The practice aims at broaden-
ing everyday experience, its typical movements and actions that are so
often governed by functionality.453 The goal of the practice is to exam-
ine the “psychogeographical articulation of the modern city,”454 the
architectural reading, the playful behaviour that would then overcome
repressed desires.455
I will not examine the concept of dérive further, but lastly propose
that considering the principles of dérive in terms of phenomenology it
could be understood as aiming in losing the naturalist attitude. More-
over, dérive could be seen as having similar ambitions as reduction,
since it aims to challenge the way we perceive and act in the sur-
rounding space. It is based on the assumption that our actions within
urban space are often governed by familiarity, and this familiarity is
deeply rooted in our own bodies.
Investigations of a Dog
Why choose a dog? In Ulaanbaatar, dogs are present everywhere.
There their position and role is different from the practices of no-
madic life in the countryside, where they are used as sheepdogs and
guards. The urban dogs treat the city as their home-ground. However,
even though the camera bearer would know the city like the back of
its paw, the spectators of the images are, in most cases, as good as
aliens in observing the city. Some elements of the cityscape may per-
haps remind one of suburbs in South America, Asia, Africa or Eastern
Europe. All in all, the perspective that Another city, not my own of-
fers is not easy to approach. In fact, I would claim that inaccessibility
is one of the key elements of this artwork that discusses among other
things the possibilities of intercorporeality. Citing psychologist Erwin
Straus, Ronald Bogue has remarked how in encountering “the animal
453 Indeed, it seems that dérive is essentially a practice developed for cities. The
key figure of the movement, Guy Débord (1931–1994), writes in “Theory of the
Dérive” (“Théorie de la dérive”, 1958): “Wandering in open country is naturally
depressing, and the interventions of chance are poorer there than anywhere else.”
454 The exclusion of the countryside is not absolute, as it is known, Débord himself
ment, how spaces affect our thoughts and how shifting quarters may bring out a
totally different atmosphere. (Débord 1958.)
144 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
456 Bogue 2003, 119. | The subject of dogs has been addressed by various con-
doubt”, where the subject matter can be approached from various viewpoints,
not just from one, supposedly “perfect” viewpoint, and how the photographers
practice is fixed to a programme. In the case of Mayer’s work, it is very much a
result of programming. Here, even the “photographer” is not conscious, but totally
absorbed into its everyday practices. (Flusser 2005, 38.)
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 145
touching the issues of other and freedom. The novel can be interpreted in many
ways. For instance Ulrika Björk suggests that it should be interpreted as a literary
description of the ambiguity and complexity of feminine subjective becoming —
themes that Beauvoir later took up in The Second Sex (Le deuxième sexe, 1949).
For discussion on the relations between the philosophical themes and fiction writing
in Beauvoir, see Björk 2008.
461 Merleau-Ponty writes: “Je remarque que la chose, après tout, a besoin de moi
pour exister. Quand je découvre un paysage jusque-là caché par une colline, c’est
alors seulement qu’il devient pleinement paysage et l’on ne peut pas concevoir ce
que serait une chose sans l’imminence ou la possibilité de mon regard sur elle. Ce
monde qui avait l’air d’être sans moi, de m’envelopper et de me dépasser, c’est moi
146 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
qui le fais être. Je suis donc une conscience, une présence immédiate au monde, et
il n’est rien qui puisse prétendre à être sans être pris de quelque façon dans le tissu
de mon expérience. Je ne suis pas cette personne, ce visage, cet être fini, mais un
pur témoin, sans lieu et sans âge, qui peut égaler en puissance l’infinité du monde.”
(SNS, 38.) “I observe that, after all, the thing needs me in order to exist. Only
when I discover the landscape hidden until then behind a hill does it fully become
a landscape; one cannot imagine what a thing would be like if it were not about
to, or able to, be seen by me. It is I who bring into being this world which seemed
to exist without me, to surround and surpass me. I am therefore a consciousness,
immediately present to the world, and nothing can claim to exist without somehow
being caught in the web of my experience. I am not this particular person or face,
this finite being: I am a pure witness, placeless and ageless, equal in power to the
world’s infinity.” (SNS, 29.)
462 The concept of empathy is derived from the German einfühlen, to feel into
PO.
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 147
own hand annexes another person’s body, and how they coexist or
are compresent: “The other person appears through an extension of
that compresence; he and I are like organs of one single intercorpo-
reality.”465 Gail Weiss points out that intercorporeality demonstrates
how “the experience of being embodied is never a private affair, but
is always already mediated by our continual interactions with other
human and non-human bodies”.466 Regarding the images of Another
city, not my own, intercorporeality enables an understanding, where
the spectator — perhaps only occasionally — feels that the “photog-
rapher” and he or she are of one single intercorporeality.
The problematic of intersubjectivity — how do I constitute some-
one else as another? How do others perceive me? — and the experience
of intercorporeality, are the basis for the feeling of empathy.467
Husserl discusses animal life first in Ideas II, where he makes a
distinction between material nature and animal nature.468 The dis-
cussion on animals is connected with the theme of intersubjectivity.
To Husserl, it is “lived bodiness”, Leibkörperlichkeit that constitutes
empathy.469 In empathy the other is perceived as similar to me — my
analogon. Through our own bodies, we can experience other bodies.
Yet being able to empathise with somebody that possesses a body dif-
ferent from mine, requires modification — Husserl sets a standard of
a body in relation to which, for instance, a child and an animal are
abnormalities. For Husserl, there is also a limit to the modification and
analogy of the body.470
In the chapter “Conditions of the Possibility of Sensual Empathy”,
Edith Stein writes how the physical body is a realisation of a type that
is then variable within limits:471
sommes comme les organes d’une seule intercorporéité.” S, 274. | The term “com-
présence” comes from Husserl, “übertragene Kompräsenz”. (S, 274 n.3.)
466 Weiss 199, 5. | Joona Taipale writes “Intercorporeality refers to this funda-
mental entanglement (Ineinander) of the own and the alien in a unitary bodily
experience: it refers to the manner in which the own and the alien are interwo-
ven in a ‘functional community of one perception’ (Funktionsgemeinschaft einer
Wahrnehmung)” (Taipale 2009, 113.)
467 The basis for perceiving others as others is connected with bodily self-
472 Stein 1989, 59. | Stein writes that the further we are from the human, the
more difficult it becomes to sense in the alien body. Yet for instance, Ruonakoski
points out that Stein also discusses the general phenomena of life, such as growth,
development, health, and argues that we could thus be able to, in a more limited
sense, empathise also with plants. (Stein 1989, 77–78; Ruonakoski 2007.)
473 San Martin & Pintos Peñaranda 2001, 354.
474 Stein 1989, 59.
475 San Martin & Pintos Peñaranda 2001, 355.
476 Husserl I II, § 49e.
477 Painter 2007, 101; see also Husserl I II, § 49.
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 149
l’animal, mais non par addition de raison, bref dans l’Ineinander avec l’animal
(étranges anticipations ou caricatures de l’homme chez l’animal), par échappement
150 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
Alien Other
I shall next examine Christian Mayer’s Another city, not my own
through the concept of movement. The dog in Mayer’s work moves
around in a cityscape, which is revealed only partially to the viewer
through the images taken by the camera. Further, if the basis of em-
pathy is in the embodiment and perception, these images show only
the margins of the other’s body.485 Nevertheless the spectator is, at
points, able to not only sense the space the animal moves in through
intercorporeality, but also to empathise with the situation the “pho-
tographer” is in. Granted, the “photographer” has a very different
body and world than we have, it is not however an absolute hindrance
for our understanding of the work.486 As Painter writes: “We must
constitute him or her as subject with felt needs and desires that may
be different from our own, which [...] makes it difficult to treat that
other as a mere thing.”487 Even though the images suggest that the
spectator takes the position of the “photographer”, i.e. the dog, he or
she would not be capable of knowing completely how the ground feels
beneath its paws or what kind of olfactory world the dog experiences.
There are also other aspects that distance the spectator from the
dog’s experience. They are both related to the medium used in this
particular work. Firstly, Mayer has used a camera instead of a video
camera. There is no live footage, but merely still images that are con-
nected with blank screens. These blanks have a certain transitional
function. The rhythm of the images is the sole source of movement —
here the stopping of movement is indeed a modality of movement —
et non par superposition) — de même que plus haut la vie est apparue comme
points singuliers de la Nature physique.” N, 277.
484 Ruonakoski 2011.
485 Taipale 2009, 126.
486 I wish to stress that for the artist it was important that the audience had
488 The term haptic means relating to the sense of touch; it comes from the Greek,
haptesthai, to grasp to touch. (Paterson 2007, 4.) I will discuss the theme of the
hapticity of images in more detail in the following chapter, see section 6.3.
152 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
“When we consider the animal milieu especially, it becomes clearer that in a certain
sense — that of inventing the visible — the animal is not unlike the artist. The
environmental situation and animal movement cannot be understood as a simple
relation of ‘push causality’.” (Johnson 2010, 176.)
490 DC, 66. “Nous vivons dans un milieu d’objets construits par les hommes, entre
des ustensiles, dans des maisons, des rues, des villes et la plupart du temps nous
ne les voyons qu’à travers les actions humaines dont ils peuvent être les points
d’application. Nous nous habituons à penser que tout cela existe nécessairement et
est inébranlable. La peinture de Cézanne met en suspens ces habitudes et révèle
le fond de la nature inhumaine sur lequel l’homme s’installe. C’est pourquoi ses
personnages sont étranges et comme vus par un être d’un autre espèce.” DC, 21–22.
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 153
on Diane Arbus’ and Brassaï’s photography. Mayer’s work could further be linked,
albeit loosely, to a trait in photography that is exemplified in Walker Evans’ Subway
Portraits (published in Many Are Called) or Luc Delahaye’s L’autre, both series
of photographs taken secretly. Evans made his photos in the New York metro in
the 1930s, Delahaye in the Paris metro in the 1990s. (Fried 2008, 221–23.)
492 N, 217. “[J]e suis ouvert au monde parce que je suis dedans par mon corps.”
N, 279.
493 “Il est ouvert en circuit avec le monde, parce qu’il est ouvert : il se voit, il se
154 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
touche.” And in a note : “Se voit voyant, se touche touchant i.e. ses mouvements
ont un dedans, son dedans a un dehors.” N 279, 279 n.b. “It is open in a circuit with
the world, but it is open. It sees itself; it touches itself.” And in a note: “Seeing
itself seeing, touching itself touching; that is, its movements have an inside, its
inside has an outside.” N, 217, 308 n.3.
494 Œ, 81/146.
495 Barbaras 2000, 86.
496 Barbaras 2006, 96.
497 Œ, 31/129.
498 N, 218. “[...] corrélations d’un sujet charnel, répliques de son mouvement et
de son sentir, intercalés dans son circuit interne [...] La chair du corps nous fait
5.3. OTHER VISIONS 155
ment visibles ; cette lacune où se trouvent nos yeux, notre dos, elle est comblée,
comblée par du visible encore, mais dont nous ne sommes pas titulaires ; certes,
pour y croire, pour faire entrer en compte une vision qui n’est pas la nôtre, c’est
inévitablement, c’est toujours à l’unique trésor de notre vision que nous puisons, et
l’expérience donc ne peut rien nous enseigner qui ne soit esquissé en elle. [...] Pour
la première fois, le voyant que je suis m’est vraiment visible ; pour la première fois,
je m’apparais retourné jusqu’au fond sous mes propres yeux.” VI, 186.
156 CHAPTER 5. PHOTOGRAPHIC EXPLORATIONS
Concluding Remarks
In this chapter I brought forth how the criticism of photography pre-
sented by Merleau-Ponty holds in its core the scientific approach he
found in Marey’s photographs of a galloping horse. Further, what
Merleau-Ponty valued in art was the expression of movement. There-
fore, in the second part of the chapter I clarified his conception of
movement. I showed how Merleau-Ponty understood movement as in-
dispensable for perception — and simultaneously something that re-
mains invisible. Interpreted in this way the challenge to address move-
ment in photography and in art in general can also be approached
anew.
There are undoubtedly several levels and aspects in Christian
Mayer’s Another city, not my own. In my interpretation I have empha-
sised one particular angle in order to present an alternative reading of
Merleau-Ponty’s remarks on animal movement, visual arts and photog-
raphy’s ability to bring forth our being in the world. Observed from
this angle Mayer’s images succeed in showing how photography can
move away from the attitude governed by pensée de survol and ap-
proach the embodied spectator, even ease itself into the body of the
spectator, bringing along with it the gazes of the other and catching
the spectator in a state of unawareness.
500 MP, 438. “Ici ‘perception’ et ‘perçu’ sont e[n]semble inscrits. On de la percep-
tion (celui qui perçoit est ‘personne,’ et c’est aussi bien ‘un autre’). Différenciation
avec des horizons d’indifférenciation. C’est la masse de l’Être sensible.” MP, 437–38.
6
The Filmic Experience: Temporality and
Rhythm
ing from painting, the visual art which was closest to Merleau-Ponty, I have also
discussed other media, those which have not enjoyed a similarly privileged position
in his thinking. However, my point is not to create a formative narration of the
different media, but to demonstrate how the central thematics of Merleau-Ponty,
such as space, movement, time, touch, the other and our being in the world, can
be opened up anew.
502 Krauss remarks: “As I have argued in a series of recent essays on this phe-
nomenon, these artists do not work with the traditional mediums of painting and
sculpture, which they view as exhausted, but are instead forced to do something as
counterintuitive as inventing a new medium. Accordingly, they reach for modern,
technological mechanisms as the ‘supports’ for their own work.” (Krauss 2006, 58.)
157
158 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
sitivity to the medium; art works that relatively clearly address questions that
concern the means and the position of the media itself. This is seen in the early
works done with new mediums, where the medium is used to study through a very
elementary setting the aspects of perception — however, an artist may cross over
into another media to explore temporality or space; think for instance of Richard
Serra’s filmic works, such as Hands Scraping (1968) or Railroad Turnbridge (1976).
Also, it may take time before the nature of a new medium is studied: for instance,
Marks points out that video has received appreciation only in the aftermath of
digital media. It is perfectly according to the pattern that as analogue video is
threatened, its aesthetic expressions gain in esteem — like Marks suggests, the
medium receives attention only when it is threatened. This might also be due to,
as Leighton points out, the fact that video’s intrinsic properties were perhaps not
so clearly traced as those of film. (Marks 2002, 147; Leighton 2008, 22.)
505 The practices of the moving image surfaced in the 1960s and from that time
onwards, cinematic and televisual forms in visual art started to flower, and simul-
taneously blur or fragment the field. (Leighton 2008, 7, 26.) In “Modes of Film
Practice in the Avant-Garde” (2008) Jonathan Walley discusses how some regard
the relationship between film and art as a one-way relation, where artists are mes-
merised by the film. Some do not conceive any distinction between artists and
film-makers. Walley suggests using the terms “avant garde cinema” and “artists’
film”. According to Walley’s analysis and remarks on production and distribution,
Gordon and Parreno’s Zidane would be an artist film production, close to indepen-
dent art cinema, due to its collaborative mode of production. (Walley 2008.)
506 At the time, there was no established media art. The field of film studies was
also relatively young. There was an early yet unsuccessful attempt to establish a
phenomenological method for film studies. Gilbert Cohen-Séat was one of the key
persons behind the journal titled Revue Internationale de Filmologie (1947–1960).
This journal attempted to discuss the social implications of movies and found a
proper field of study for film. The publication was brought to an end in the 1960s.
On the relation of film theory and phenomenology, see Andrew 1985; Casebier 1991;
Sobchack 1993; 1997.
6.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON FILM 159
and the “white cube”, i.e. the cinema and gallery spaces, even though
the same works can be shown in both contexts.507 However, what con-
nects various works today is their interest in the moving image. In the
following I clarify Merleau-Ponty’s insight into the moving image and
what potential it holds in the interpretations of contemporary art.
was originally presented in March 1945 at the L’Institut des hautes études cinéma-
tographiques, IDHEC. The Institute for Advanced Cinematographic Studies was
the main French film school. The school was restructured in 1985 and is currently
known as the École Nationale Supérieure des Métiers de l’Image et du Son.
509 Henri Bergson had presented early critical remarks in Creative Evolution
film theory that the cinema derives in some ultimate sense from the Renaissance,
via intervening technologies like the camera obscura, the still camera, and the
stereoscope, and that visual field is defined to a significant degree by the rules and
ideology of monocular perspective.” (Silverman 1996, 125.)
160 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
511 Dillon 1988, 58. | From Merleau-Ponty’s paper the reader can find the basic
principle of Gestalt theory against classical psychology, namely the criticism of
the view in which the senses are conceived of as separate or the unity of senses
in relation to intelligence and memory is seen as constructed. He emphasises how
the intertwining of the senses is, contrary to what is assumed, quite common. It
is not simply an anomaly found in, for instance, blind people’s experience. To
demonstrate this, he mentions how even normal subjects speak of “hot” colours,
or “penetrating” smells and how a simple perception tries to adjust and organise
the seen (CNP, 63/50). Merleau-Ponty’s reading stresses the importance of colours
and materials belonging together (CNP, 66/52). For a discussion of cognitive film
theory and phenomenology, see Hiltunen 2005.
512 It may be debated whether or not the examples selected by Merleau-Ponty
are successful. For instance, film theorist Jean Mitry has commented on Merleau-
Ponty’s discussion of cinema. He considers that Merleau-Ponty’s example of vertigo
is poor: people who feel dizzy do not see world as swinging backward and forward
— this subjective image does not show us what the hero is thinking or seeing, but
what he is supposed to see. (Mitry 1998, 108.)
513 CNP, 69/54. | The French term forme could also be translated as Gestalt.
Merleau-Ponty discussed Gestalt theory especially early in his career (SC), but the
notion of Gestalt can also be found in his late texts (VI).
514 CNP, 70/55. | He exemplifies the idea of temporal form by referring to the
“Esquisse d’une psychologie du cinéma” published in the journal Verve (1940): ex-
pository dialogue, tonal dialogue and dramatic dialogue. The first form of dialogue
aims at making the circumstances known. This kind of dialogue is, according to
6.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON FILM 161
is a metrics of speech and silences, and the constituted visual and sonic
metric is a complexity that surpasses the two standing alone.516
All in all, Merleau-Ponty appreciates cinema as its own unique
form. Even though it might appear that “[e]ach film tells a story: that
is, it relates a certain number of events which involve characters and
which could, it seems, also be told in prose, as, in effect, they are in
the scenario on which the film is based,”517 it does not mean that the
function of the film is only to lay out the facts or present a certain
idea. Cinema is not simply about rendering events for spectators as
if they would be present at the events. On the contrary, the story,
the facts and the ideas serve as a possibility to search for a sensuous
emblem and thus engrave it into the visible and sonic monogram:518
“The meaning of a film is incorporated into its rhythm just as the
meaning of a gesture may immediately be read in that gesture: the
film does not mean anything but itself.”519
From Merleau-Ponty’s perspective film opens up into the person’s
way of being in the world. He presents an example of vertigo: instead of
showing it from inside, from the perspective of the person experiencing
vertigo, as is often done in literature, the film lets the spectator see
it from outside, so that he or she contemplates the unbalanced body
on the screen.520 Indeed, for Merleau-Ponty a fair part of phenomeno-
logical or existential philosophy describes our paradoxical belonging
to others and to the world. In his view, cinema is particularly apt in
making this belonging visible. He writes:
Merleau-Ponty, avoided in films and novels. Tonal dialogue gives the spectator the
character’s particular accent. The last form of dialogue, dramatic dialogue, is typ-
ical of cinema. It presents the debates and confrontation of the personages. (CNP,
71/55–56.)
516 CNP, 71/56. | From his point of view, music should incorporate film, not
d’événements qui mettent aux prises des personnages et qui peuvent être aussi
racontés en prose, comme ils le sont effectivement dans le scénario d’après lequel
le film est fait.” CNP, 72.
518 CNP, 73/57.
519 CNP, 57. “Le sens du film est incorporé à son rythme comme le sens d’un geste
est immédiatement lisible dans le geste, et le film ne veut rien dire que lui-même.”
CNP, 73.
520 CNP, 74/58. | Merleau-Ponty is following in the line of behaviour psychology.
162 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
et le travail technique vont dans le même sens, c’est parce que le philosophe et le
cinéaste ont en commun une certain manière d’être, une certaine vue du monde
qui est celle d’une génération. Encore une occasion de vérifier que la pensée et les
techniques se correspondent et que, selon le mot de Goethe, ‘ce qui est au-dedans
est aussi au-dehors’.” CNP, 74.
522 Curiously, he emphasises that this experience is not universal, but belongs to a
generation. Merleau-Ponty suggests that all generations have their own experiences
that define their being in the world.
523 In “Eye and Mind”, he refers to cinema in connection with a discussion on
movement: “Cinema portrays movement, but how? Is it, as we are inclined to be-
lieve, by copying more closely the changes of place? We may presume not, since
slow motion shows a body being carried along, floating among objects like seaweed,
but not moving itself.” (Œ, 144–45.) “Le cinema donne le mouvement, mais com-
ment ? Est-ce, comme on croit, en copiant de plus près le changement de lieu ? On
peut présumer que non, puisque le ralenti donne un corps flottant entre les objets
comme une algue, et qui ne se meut pas.” (Œ, 78.)
6.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON FILM 163
the cinema [...] Then, as now, this viewer will be left not with a
store of recipes but a radiant image, a particular rhythm. Then,
as now, the way we experience works of cinema will be through
perception.524
A Temporal Form
In order to understand Merleau-Ponty’s standpoint on cinema, we
need to look at the concepts of time and rhythm more closely. In
Phenomenology of Perception Merleau-Ponty discusses the question
of time in a chapter entitled “Temporality”. His description takes up
Husserl’s as well as Heidegger’s conceptions of time. Some commenta-
tors have seen in Merleau-Ponty’s elaboration on time a move beyond
the phenomenologies of Husserl and Heidegger.526
524 C, 98–99. “Car enfin ce qui peut constituer la beauté cinématographique, ce
n’est ni l’histoire en elle-même, que la prose raconterait très bien, ni à plus forte
raison les idées qu’elle peut suggérer, ni enfin ces tics, ces manies, ces procédés par
lesquels un metteur en scène se fait reconnaître et qui n’ont pas plus d’importance
décisive que les mots favoris d’un écrivain. Ce qui compte, c’est le choix des épi-
sodes représentés, et, dans chacun d’eux, les choix des vues que l’on fera figurer
dans le film, la longueur donnée respectivement à chacun de ces éléments, l’ordre
dans lequel on choisit de les présenter, le son ou les paroles font on veut ou non
les accompagner, tout cela constituant un certain rythme cinématographique glo-
bal. Quand notre expérience du cinema sera plus longue, on pourra élaborer une
sorte de logique du cinéma, ou même de grammaire stylistique du cinema qui nous
indiqueront [...] Alors comme maintenant l’ouvrage laissera dans son esprit, non
pas une somme de recettes, mais une image rayonnante, un rythme. Alors comme
maintenant l’expérience cinématographique sera perception.” C, 57–58.
525 Relating to these themes of rhythm and time, there is also a passage on cin-
ema where Merleau-Ponty discusses movement in film. This is also done in his lec-
ture course in the Collège de France entitled “Le monde sensible et l’expression”.
Merleau-Ponty writes how cinema was created in order to represent movement. He
underlined in these lectures the aptness of cinema to grasp our openness to the
world and to the other. (RC, 20.)
526 Ricoeur 2009. | It is not within the scope of my thesis to take a stand on this
wide and extensive question here. I will instead limit myself to presenting briefly
the central points that are relevant for the discussion of the moving image and my
following case study.
164 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
parce que je m’y découvre déjà engagé, parce que tout l’être ne m’est pas donné
en personne, et enfin, parce qu’un secteur de l’être m’est si proche qu’il ne fait
pas même tableau devant moi et que je ne peux pas le voir, comme je ne peux
pas voir mon visage. Il y a du temps pour moi parce que j’ai un présent. C’est en
venant au présent qu’un moment du temps acquiert l’individualité ineffaçable, le
‘une fois pour les toutes’, qui lui permettront ensuite de traverser le temps et nous
donneront l’illusion de l’éternité.” PP, 484; see also PP, 278/280.
532 PP, 500. “[...] il n’a de sens pour nous que parce que nous ‘le sommes’.” PP,
492.
6.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON FILM 165
justement parce qu’il est singulier et qu’il passe, ne pourra jamais cesser d’avoir
été et donc d’être universellement, — mais surtout celle des produits de la culture
qui continuent de valoir après leur apparition [...]” LV, 95.
166 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
to the theme of Stiftung (see IP). The concept of institution was set to solve the
problems that Husserl and Merleau-Ponty encountered with the concept of consti-
tution, an active process of bestowing meaning, in the discussion of philosophy of
consciousness.
537 IP, 125/78.
538 IP, 7. “Le temps est le modèle même de l’institution : passivité-activité [...] Le
transcendant : on sait qu’il n’est pas là, qu’il vient d’être là, on ne coïncide jamais
avec lui — Il n’est pas un segment de temps à contours définis qui viendrait se
mettre en place. Il est un cycle défini par une région centrale et dominante et à
contours indécis, — un gonflement ou une ampoule de temps [...]” VI, 235.
540 VI, 268. “Alors passé et présent sont Ineinander, chacun enveloppé-
A Particular Rhythm
Related to time, there is another topic that Merleau-Ponty emphasises
in connection with film, namely rhythm. Traditionally, rhythm is asso-
ciated with music, but it can also be found in poetry, visual arts or in
life in general. The word rhythm comes from the Latin word rhythmus,
“movement in time”, and the Greek word rhythmos, “measured flow or
movement, rhythm”.541 Victor Biceaga explains: “Critical discussions
of the notion of rhythm often revolve around some typical features
of temporal phenomena such as periodicity and meter”, meaning that
rhythm, such as the heart beat appears rhythmic due to periodicity.
He continues: “But from a phenomenological point of view, rhythm
means not so much periodicity or meter as a characteristic of the ex-
perience of objects in so far as this experience is temporal.”542 Biceaga
clarifies that the basis for the phenomenological approach to rhythm
was laid by Husserl in his conception of retention and protention, i.e.
how every present holds a retention of what has passed, as well as
an anticipation of what is to come. Further, the Husserlian concep-
tion of rhythm involves an integration of discordance into coherent
wholes — it contributes to finding meaningful patterns.543 However,
here my interest lies first and foremost in the understanding of rhythm
in Merleau-Ponty and in the arts.
The concept of rhythm is present in Phenomenology of Perception.
Rhythm defines our being in the world: in a chapter discussing the
body, Merleau-Ponty writes “my life is made up of rhythms [...]”.544
As Johnson points out, the rhythm of life is in the margin of our
almost impersonal existence — it defines the anonymous body that is
necessary for our being alive.545 Further, as such, rhythms are present
in our experiencing and communicating with others. Merleau-Ponty
wrote, for instance, concerning the question of expression, how there is
something shared between the gesture and its meaning: how a smile or
541 Harper, Online Etymology Dictionary.
542 Biceaga 2010, 13. | In a footnote Biceaga points out that Husserl laid out the
conceptual tools for the discussion of rhythm for post-Husserlian phenomenology
(Henri Maldiney, Jacques Garelli and Marc Richir). Ibid n.17.
543 Biceaga 2010, 14.
544 PP, 96. “ma vie comporte des rythmes [...]” PP, 99.
545 Johnson 2010, 199. | In his own development Johnson connects rhythm with
PP, 248.
549 Œ, 144. “Comme elle a créé la ligne latente, la peinture s’est donné un mou-
the coming to itself of rhythm in space — or rather, the becoming rhythm of space.”
(Escoubas 2010, 252.)
6.1. MERLEAU-PONTY ON FILM 169
Where are we to put the limit between the body and the world,
since the world is flesh? Where in the body are we to put the
seer, since evidently there is in the body only “shadows stuffed
with organs,” that is more of the visible? [...] my seeing body
subtends this visible body, and all the visibles with it. There is
reciprocal insertion and intertwining of one in the other.553
chair ? Où mettre dans le corps le voyant, puisque, de toute évidence, il n’y a dans
le corps que des ‘ténèbres bourrées d’organes’, c’est-à-dire du visible encore ? [...]
mon corps voyant sous-tend ce corps visible, et tous les visible, et tous les visibles
avec lui. Il y a insertion réciproque et entrelacs de l’un dans l’autre.” VI, 180.
554 See for instance Al-Saji 2001; Leoni 2003.
170 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
in which all the others participate”.555 This is because the body is,
as we know, sensible and sentient, and yet to grasp this experience
is impossible. He continues, “the touching is always on the verge of
apprehending itself as tangible, misses its grasp, and completes it only
in a there is.”556 Flesh is thus a continuous movement back and forth
that can be understood also through the reversibility of rhythm and
vertigo, or as Merleau-Ponty himself put it, flesh is this cycle.
Against this background Merleau-Ponty’s idea of film as a temporal
form can be apprehended in a broader sense: a film or a painting or a
novel is capable of reaching time in its paradoxicality, not just as con-
stituted, but as experienced. Further, art can address our experience
of being in the world. As was shown, for Merleau-Ponty subjectivity
is defined by temporality, which is in principle marked by a certain
inaccessibility. Even though we are in time, it is, similarly to our own
seeing, not possible to grasp it, as it is not possible to touch our own
touching. And yet we may find in art ways to express these experiences
that otherwise remain beyond our reach.
inscription de tous les autres, sensible pivot auquel participent tous les autres [...]”
VI, 308.
556 VI, 260. “[...] le touchant est toujours sur le point de saisir comme tangible,
ence (1993) & Carnal Thoughts. Embodiment and Moving Image Culture (2004);
Kaisa Hiltunen: Images of Time, Thought and Emotions: Narration and the Spec-
tator’s Experience in Krzysztof Kiéslowski’s Late Fiction Films (2005); Jennifer M.
Barker: The Tactile Eye. Touch and the Cinematic Experience (2009). Naturally,
there are many other researchers who could be mentioned, for instance Elena del
Río, who has analysed voyeurism in Peeping Tom (1960) from a phenomenological
perspective (Rio 2001).
6.2. TECHNOLOGY, SPECTATORSHIP, FILM’S BODY 171
claims that film is not merely the object of our perception and expres-
sion. She is interested in how materiality of film and cinematic tech-
nology materially embodies “perception and expression as a situated,
finite, centered and decentering lived-body that, through its commuta-
tion of perception and expression, is able to accomplish the significa-
tion of vision as significant.”562
In her discussion Sobchack does not identify film with the mech-
anisms that enable it, and yet film cannot be dissociated from tech-
nology. However, following in the lines of Merleau-Ponty, the focus of
her approach is concerned with how film appears to us or for itself,
and not in the lenses, editing, sound recording, etc. as much as they
are the necessary conditions for cinema. Sobchack therefore does take
technology into account, yet emphasises that film is visible in a way
technology can never be.563 What counts in film is the way in which
it is experienced.
Sobchack claims that “the act of viewing as commutation of per-
ception and expression is both intrasubjective and intersubjective per-
formance equally performable by filmmaker, film, and spectator.”564
She underlines how perception and expression unite not only the di-
rector and the spectator but also the film, which means that a film is
not simply a visible object, but our relationship to it is more complex.
The phenomenological approach to film focuses on the reciprocal
correlation between the film and the viewer.565 As I have already men-
tioned, the differences between full-length films and media art can be
found, among other things, in the conditions of encountering the art-
work: whereas a moviegoer is supposed to sit still, moving-image instal-
lations often encourage spectators to move around.566 The spectator-
actor, who is encouraged to move around and interact with the art
work, might appear “active”, but it is evident that also the seated
spectator is far from being a “passive” onlooker in the audience.567
of the tendencies within the field. Shaviro situates himself in the tradition set by
Deleuze and Guattari, and opposes the Lacanian approach to film studies. Shaviro
writes: “But in any case, I do not actively interpret or seek to control; I just
sit back and blissfully consume. I passively enjoy or endure certain rhythms of
duration: the passage of time, with its play of retention and anticipation, and with
its relentless accumulation, transformation, and destruction of sounds and images.
6.2. TECHNOLOGY, SPECTATORSHIP, FILM’S BODY 173
intertwined with the larger debate on vision and spectatorship. Some researchers
ague for a detached spectatorship. In their view dumbfounding experiences make
spectators unable to be critical. From another standpoint, spectators are able to
be critical even though their approach would be “hands on”. (Jay 2000; Van de
Vall 2008, 103–32; Rancière 2009, 4–5.)
569 Sobchack 1992, 9; Lannoy 2008.
570 Sobchack 1992, 13.
571 PP, 248/249.
572 MacDougall 2006, 29; Barker 2009, 9.
573 Sobchack 2004, 66 n.48.
174 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
Here, the viewing-view refers to the idea that through the cam-
era film is, similar to an eye in that it perceives. Its counterpart is
the viewed-view, that which is perceived. Sobchack argues that: “[t]he
film’s body originally perceives and expresses perception as the very
process and progress of the viewing-view as it constitutes the viewed-
view as visible”.576 Against this background, she suggests that the
camera functions as a perceptive organ, whereas the projector is the
expressive organ.
In short, the film’s body becomes similar to our own body, since
it both perceives and expresses.577 Granted, film cannot be similarly
reversibly present for us as other human beings are. And yet through
574 Sobchack 1992, 205.
575 Sobchack 1992, 206. | Whereas the camera is privileged in its capability of
materialising embodied perception, it is thanks to the projector and the screen
that spectators gain access to these images. Yet the projector “transforms the
subjective perception to objective expression”. (Sobchack 1992, 210.) In Sobchack’s
reading the projector, as well as the screen, appear to function in a passive manner,
and yet they are both necessary in order to express the film’s body. However,
in experimental cinema this necessity has been questioned. Take, for instance,
Lis Rhodes’ Light Music (1975), which used two film projectors and smoke to
investigate the conditions of filmic experience.
576 Sobchack 1992, 206.
577 Sobchack 1992, 247; see also Barker 2009, 9. | Sobchack points to an example
of a situation where the film’s body assumes the body of a human character: the
effect is called false body. In these cases film seems to borrow the human body — not
claim it as its own, as Sobchack stresses — to give the point of view of a character.
An example of this would be a film where the body of the narrator or protagonist
is not visible, but is situated in the place of the camera. Sobchack’s example is
Robert Montgomery’s Lady in the Lake (1946). The impression is suggested by,
for instance, a cigarette and hands in the lower corner of the screen. The spectator
is supposed to have stepped in the actor’s shoes. For the medium of film, such
“subjective” or “first-person” perspectives are not particularly successful: Lady in
6.2. TECHNOLOGY, SPECTATORSHIP, FILM’S BODY 175
vision in our time are guided by the development of new computer technology.
(Crary 1992, 2; Lenoir 2004, xiv.)
178 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
horse’s legs). In this case the object is a star player.586 Yet it is clear
that the scientific perspective is not the primal object of this work;
contemporary science would surely find more effective means to study
the movements of athletes.587
However, Zidane is not a simply a direct documentation of one
sporting performance. Besides camera shots, there are also texts de-
scribing Zidane’s childhood memories and feelings while on the field.588
In addition, the film’s soundtrack is very suggestive. To use Merleau-
Pontian terms, the metrics or the rhythm of sound and vision create
together with the images a very powerful complexity. The dreamy in-
strumental music is composed and performed by Mogwai, a Glasgow-
based band. The soundscape also includes noises from the stadium.
The sounds occasionally form an overwhelming sound-wall, yet at
times the noise fades away to give way to the silence, as well as the
breathing and shouts of the players.
The subtitle of Zidane is A 21st Century Portrait. It is a clas-
sic genre of visual arts, especially painting, and generally a portrait
is considered to capture something pivotal about the person. French
philosopher and historian Louis Marin has defined a portrait as “pro-
trait”, as something which “is put forward, pro-duced, extracted or
586 A similar attempt to follow a top footballer at work has been done before.
Gordon’s and Parreno’s work has been compared with German movie maker Hell-
muth Costard’s (1940–2000) Fußball wie noch nie (Football as never before, 1970).
The protagonist in Costard’s film is George Best (1946–2005), a Manchester United
player.
587 In fact, relating to the “scientific vision”, I propose that a useful contrast
would be Harun Farocki’s Deep Play (2007). In Deep Play Farocki collected all the
available documentary and simulation material he could find on the football World
Cup final 2006 France vs. Italy played in Berlin. Deep Play consists of various points
of view on this soccer spectacle. The France–Italy game has been fragmented into
pieces: the installation’s 12 televisions show camera views of the coaches and the
game. The spectator hears the director’s orders, sees player diagrammes, computer
simulations and analyses, the stadium police at work, surveillance material, the
summer night outside the stadium in Berlin, as well as a computer animation of
Zidane head butting Marco Materazzi’s chest. The spatial organisation of the work
does not follow that of cinema, but with its multiple screens creates a totality
where the spectator has to keep shifting positions, being unable to master the flow
of information. Deep Play is, I argue, an attempt to dismantle a spectacle, to show
the massive industry behind the game. It tries to bypass mediation and go beyond.
Simultaneously it brings forth the power of media and the ways in which image
flow directs our impressions. It also explores the incident that the game is famous
for, namely the headbutt. Farocki’s work is an attempt to approach or circle this
event, which remains the blind spot of the game.
588 According to the artists, the texts are based on interviews made with Zidane.
589 Marin 2001, 204. | He continues: “It is a model in the epistemological sense,
ballers. Along with gender, ethnicity also plays a role. As is well known, Zidane’s
parents moved to France from Algeria, and thus he has given a face to second-
generation immigrants in France. From early on his skills and success made him
an icon for a multicultural France. How and why this particular face, coming from
the “streets of Marseille” stands for both skill and “inaccessibility” in contempo-
rary football, and what role his ethnicity plays in his “inaccessibility”, would be
interesting questions that I must leave for others to discuss.
592 Gordon & Parreno 2006. | When asked about the of influence of other sports
films, the directors referred to Tokyo Olympiad (1965), a documentary film by Kon
Ichikawa.
593 Star performance is, in Mulvey’s view, the ability to strike a pose, to maintain
balance and master “the fusion of energy with a stillness of display” (Mulvey 2006,
180 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
still before the camera as their eyes slowly start to shed tears: they
attempt not to blink during the 3-minute take, the duration of one
roll of film. For Warhol the portrait was completed when the roll ran
out.594 In Zidane the length was defined by the football game, or more
precisely, as long as the protagonist stayed on the field. The filming
ended when the player left the field. As the opening text of the film
says: “From the first kick of the ball until the final whistle”. Of course,
contrary to Warhol’s project Zidane consists of editing various differ-
ent camera angles into a single-channel piece. What further connects
Gordon and Parreno to Warhol is a certain tension between the su-
perficial star image and the depths of the feelings experienced on the
field. Art historian Hal Foster identifies two different “camps” in the
interpretation of Warhol’s oeuvre: the simulacral reading and the ref-
erential view of Warhol’s art. Foster asks: “But they cannot both be
right . . . or can they? Can we read the ‘Death in America’ images as
referential and simulacral, connected and disconnected, affective and
affectless, critical and complacent?”595 I will not go here into Foster’s
own answer — a third way: traumatic realism — but I do wish to
emphasise that this tension or contradictory nature found in Warhol
relates to the project of Gordon and Parreno in terms of a tension
between surface and depth, stardom and tragedy.
If the “screen tests” were used to examine star quality, it is evident
that Zidane would have passed the “screen test” for football stardom
many years ago. Zidane brings out questions concerning contemporary
star culture and the spectacle that football is today. In many of the
shots in Zidane the technical requirements for the creation of a star
are made visible by filming lights, cameras, the football crowd, and
even during intermediate time we can spot from a newsflash footage a
boy in the crowd wearing a shirt with Zidane’s name on it.596 Simon
Critchley has commented on this aspect:
162). Like Warhol, Gordon and Parreno are also interested in the star culture and
aura. In one reading, for Warhol, artificial and real go hand in hand. (Shaviro 2000,
211.)
594 Shaviro 2000, 210.
595 Foster 1996, 130.
596 The modes of production of a star are tightly linked with television culture,
a theme that Parreno has investigated in many of his works. For instance the first
video work by Parreno, Fleurs (1987), was a film of a flower bouquet. The video
was sent to TV stations to be used in whatever way they wished — later on Fleurs
appeared in Canal+ as a backdrop for a weather forecast. (Macel 2009.)
6.3. THE RADIANT IMAGE 181
sport of the masses. It attracts large audiences and is therefore very much linked
to spectacle. The best players are international stars with sponsorship deals and
the world of football is a mass sport, involved with sponsor money, speculation,
historical or national debates, former stars, etc. However difficult it is to think
about football without these aspects, it is not the focus of my reading.
598 Jean Epstein cited in Doane 2003, 91.
182 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
up, I have been attempting to emphasize not only its frequent recourse to hyperbolic
rhetoric but also its insistence (outside of the case of Eisenstein) upon treating
the close-up synchronically rather than diachronically, as stasis, as resistance to
narrative linearity, as the vertical gateway to an almost irrecoverable depth behind
the image.” (Doane 2003, 97.)
600 Close-up has been seen, among other things, as a danger, an autonomous entity
playing and objectifying the female body. (Mulvey 1989, 19–20; 2006, 166.) Laura
Mulvey, who moves in both feminist and psychoanalytic traditions, discusses in her
Death 24 x a Second (2006) two interrelated types of spectators, both related to
delayed cinema: the pensive and possessive spectator. Whereas the pensive spec-
tator is engaged with reflecting on the visibility of time, the possessive spectator is
absorbed by the image of the human body. (Mulvey 1989, 16–19; 2006, 11, 165.)
6.3. THE RADIANT IMAGE 183
603 A similar kind of observation has been made also by Maria Lind. (Lind 2009,
100.)
604 In the film, there is also a certain association with a nature documentary.
This has to do with the structure of the film. By cutting the player from the sur-
roundings the film seems to underline the natural object. Marks writes: “Cinematic
conventions have a lot to do with our powers of putting ourselves in the other’s
paws. In nature documentaries, shot–reverse shot structure creates a sense of nar-
rative; quick editing makes for excitement; cutting gives a sense of simultaneous
action; eye-line matches between animals and their prey establishes intentionality;
and when the creatures gaze into the camera, their eyes seem to communicate with
the depths of our souls. The overall effect is to allow the human viewer an iden-
tification with the nonhuman subjects, a way to get into their furry or feathered
heads. A cheap way, to be sure.” (Marks 2002, 25.) Marks point is that in na-
ture documentaries the screen offers an image of the other, and thus not a mirror,
that spectators can identify with. I suggest that in Zidane, certain conventions
of nature documentaries end up maintaining the difference between the on-screen
person and the spectator. However, the film does not thoroughly follow the pattern
of mainstream nature documentaries.
605 By this I mean that the imagery in Zidane has a quality that surpasses the
606 The term has not been used by Merleau-Ponty, but yet is closely related to
“The early twentieth-century Viennese art historian Alois Riegl borrowed the term
from psychology, haptein, for a kind of vision that ‘grabs’ the thing it looks at. I
think it’s important that Riegl was a historian of textiles, and that he came up with
this word when he was poring over his Persian carpets. These carpets with their
endless, interleaved patterns don’t allow the eye to rest in one place; they invite
the eye to move along them, caressing their surface. Contemplating these patterns
does something to dissolve the boundaries between the beholder and the thing
beheld.” (Marks 2004; also 2000, 162; 2002, 4–6.) Beyond Marks, the term has
been established by Deleuze and Guattari, who refer to the distinction between
optic and haptic vision in A Thousand Plateaus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia
(Mille Plateaux, 1980). It appears in a passage discussing smooth and striated
space. Deleuze also discusses it briefly in Cinema as well as in his essay on Francis
Bacon. (Deleuze & Guattari 1992, 492; Deleuze 2003, 85.)
608 Marks 2002, 3.
609 Deleuze and Guattari write: “Several notions, both practical and theoretical,
are suitable for defining nomad art and its successors (barbarian, Gothic, and mod-
ern). First, ‘close-range’ vision, as distinguished from long-distance vision; second,
‘tactile,’ or rather ‘haptic’ space, as distinguished from optical space. ‘Haptic’ is
a better word than ‘tactile’ since it does not establish an opposition between two
sense organs but rather invites the assumption that the eye itself may fulfill this
nonoptical function.” (Deleuze & Guattari 1992, 492.)
610 Marks has remarked that Deleuze gives only a brief example of haptic vision
in movies: In Bresson’s Pickpocket (1959) hands are central and they evoke a sense
of touch. (Marks 2000, 171.)
6.3. THE RADIANT IMAGE 185
The close-ups of Zidane can be seen as haptic vision, but the close-
ups and haptic vision are not identical. There are also other kind of
shots that may bring out haptic vision, such as when occasionally the
close-ups parallel the players with the virtual digitalised commercials
that surround the field. Similar effects are attained when the camera
films the game through a television set, or at those moments when the
image is out of focus and thus the player suddenly breaks into pieces,
turning the film’s body into an unrecognisable mish-mash of pixels.611
611 Marks has suggested that among other things video’s low contrast ratio con-
2008. | Jane Stadler writes: “The relationship between audience members and the
films they engage with is [...] indicative of the mobility and fluidity of subjectiv-
ity, and the erosion or permeability of boundaries between subjects and objects
theorized in a phenomenological account of perception.” (Stadler, 2002, 238.)
614 On the one hand, considering the spectator experience, there is a difference
between seeing a match live on site and watching a broadcasted game, let alone
seeing film in a movie theatre or seeing it at home on a DVD. On the other hand,
spectators watching the game live can also be guided by cameras. Even though
sitting in the spectator stand gives direct visual access to the field, screens placed
above the stadium show replays and close-ups of players that in real life are often
very far from the spectators. In comparison, a spectator relying entirely on televised
material cannot freely follow, for instance, one particular player, but is forced to
follow the decisions made by the director.
186 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
film offers a possibility for the spectator to recognise the tempo of the
game, certain idle moments, the waiting, the fierce running, attempts,
tension, even rage felt by the players. But, it is equally true that the
spectator may not recognise these situations. Perhaps by not having
seen football or not having played it, the logic of the game as well as
the style of playing is lost to the spectator? This turns the film into a
shattered portrait of one man on the field, giving a very disconnected
impression of the whole match.
In the previous chapter I discussed the concept of empathy. Unlike
Christian Mayer’s Another city, not my own, Zidane has no lack of
visual access to the body of the other, and yet it can remain distant.
Stein has made a distinction between empathy and identification. In-
terestingly, she also discussed an athlete, and her example involved
observing an acrobat. She stressed that empathy is being with some-
body, not being somebody.615 Still, in Zidane this “being with” is made
difficult. It is as if, on a very concrete level, a part of the intercorporeal
nature of being is cut away or at least it is drastically limited. In short,
for some spectators Zidane lacks orientation points. The spectator is
not able to understand why certain movements are required, because
there is no visual access to Zidane’s relation to other players on the
field. Or, to use other terms, because there is another rhythm, namely
that of the game, which has its own challenges: a player must be ready
to respond to fellow players, to perform those movements suggested
by the others.616 Of course, if seen in a movie theatre, the sheer scale
of the images turns the player into a “larger than life” object in a very
concrete manner. This can also affect the way in which a spectator
might not be able to “be with” the player. In both cases she or he
fails to understand the other’s situation, an aspect that Ruonakoski
underlined in her interpretation of empathy.617
Failing to recognise the situation is more likely if the movements
seen on the field do not connect with anything seen or performed previ-
ously by the spectator. These problematics resonate with pre-reflective
bodily responses to the filmic experiences that Sobchack has described:
615 Moran 2004, 307; see also Painter 2007, 111.
616 There is a certain roughness to Zidane’s style of being. At points it is as if he
possesses the wrong kind of body for the game, a body that is not as flexible, agile
and smooth as it should be. It seems that Zidane has to continuously overcome
certain aspects of his body — he looks heavy, even clumsy at points — to perform
the movements of a top footballer. (My thanks to Dominiek Hoens for drawing
attention to this dimension of an “unlikely” body and Hanneke Grootenboer for
her remarks on performativity.)
617 See Ruonakoski 2011.
6.3. THE RADIANT IMAGE 187
The rhythm of systole and diastole that plays through the self-
shaping activity of form in an artwork creates its own temporal
framework, and when we experience the artwork we also enter
into the implicated time of its form, a perpetual Now outside
commonsense coordinates.622
we could suggest that Zidane can, at best, take the spectator into “a
perpetual Now”. However, it is likewise true that not all spectators
find the entry into this “Now”. Or to use Deleuzian terms, in entering
the work, the spectator fails to reach the unity of the sensing and the
sensed — Deleuze stressed the importance of sensation, noting that
Cézanne’s lesson was to show that sensation is in the body, not in the
air, as the Impressionists suggested.623
My suggestion is that the possible “failing” of a spectator is a
matter of rhythmic dissonance that has its origins in our lived bodies
and their rhythms. As I earlier described Sobchack’s experience of her
fingers “knowing” before properly seeing, it might equally be the case
that the carnal knowledge — which could also perhaps be understood
as a rhythm — does not resonate with the rhythms of the film, the
chaotic tempo of the game.
unity of the senses, and would make a multisensible Figure appear visually. But
this operation is possible only if the sensation of a particular domain (here, the
visual sensation) is in direct contact with the vital power that exceeds every domain
and traverses them all. This power is rhythm, which is more profound than vision,
hearing, etc. Rhythm appears as music when it invests the auditory level, and as
painting when it invests the visual level. This is a ‘logic of the senses’, as Cézanne
said, which is neither rational nor cerebral.” (Deleuze 2003, 42.)
624 For more on temporality in film, see for instance Hiltunen 2005, 29.
625 CNP, 69/54.
626 CNP, 73/57.
6.3. THE RADIANT IMAGE 189
627 For instance, intermediate time, when the film is “interrupted” by news flashes
and such from around the world, as if the world of the game were interrupted by
showing time outside the stadium — and yet in intermediate time there is also a
certain emphasis on the “nowness” of the events shown.
628 For instance, Parreno’s works often examine time and take advantage of the
format of the exhibition and the visibility time of the work. (Macel 2009, 15–16.)
629 There also other works, such as Black and White (Babylon) (1996) or 5 Year
Drive-By (1995), a work that was initially presented as a proposal to slow down The
Searchers (1956), a John Ford film so that it would last for 5 years. (Bloemheuvel
1998, 136–39.)
630 Mulvey points out that video has changed the way films are watched. Where
films were only seen in cinema at a preset speed, and repetition meant going again
to the cinema, video changed everything. Slow-motion and fast forward as well
as freezing were all just a click away from the spectator. As Gordon’s 24 Hour
Psycho draws attention to the hidden stillness, the materiality of the film — the
individual frames — it also sets the spectator back into helplessness, as there is no
way a gallery goer could affect the installation’s time. (Mulvey 2006, 101–102.)
190 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
from a television set, trying to get closer to see what happens to the
star player. This childhood memory is very present in Zidane. Because
what is this film if not an attempt to turn that memory of following
one’s star-player into reality? This would imply that the spectators
are in the position of a small child, who is trying to get closer to the
pixelated screen and the hero he is following. At the same time the
spectator of the film may perhaps remember his or her own memories
of past sports heroes or become conscious of the fact that the star-
player of the past is now present on the screen, as Zidane undoubtedly
belongs to the history of football.
Besides an attempt to underline the now of the game as well as the
nostalgic past, the temporality of the film has a strong cyclic character.
What necessarily shadows the film is the infamous headbutt incidence
of the final in 2006: Zidane headbutted an Italian player in the chest
and received a red card. France lost the championship to Italy. It
was Zidane’s final game before his retirement.631 The spectator who
is familiar with the history of Zidane looks for signs of the future
outburst. Indeed, also in this film, Zidane loses his temper because one
of his team-mates has been fouled. As a result of the brawl, Zidane
is again given a red card and is sent off in the final minutes of the
match. As he exits, the filming stops.632 This final event, which in itself
is already dramatic, is difficult to see without hindsight, or without
considering similar earlier events where Zidane lost his temper. Here
time is not linear, but creates loops where the now of the game is
shadowed by an incident that took place much later than the filming,
and yet before the moment of watching the film. Here, the radiant
image of the film compresses into it a cycle of the future, the past and
the present. Time in Zidane is not there, and if it was there, the viewer
never coincides with it.
Even though the film invites the spectator into the tempo of the
game, into the lived experience of a footballer, it does not offer any final
explanations. Repeatedly, what we see escapes our comprehension. The
momentous cut, or disorientation, when Zidane flew into a rage and is
sent off is left without explanation, just like all the explanations trying
to find a causality that would “explain” Proust’s characters are in
vain.633 More than “revealing” the player himself, what Zidane brings
631 For an interpretation of this incident, see Pourriol 2010, 11–33.
632 Even though a match is not scripted, I claim that the filming affected it. Our
seeing can be traced from the screen: the presence of the cameras also affect the
match and the behaviour of the players.
633 Related to the discussion is another interpretation by Simon Critchley. Con-
192 CHAPTER 6. THE FILMIC EXPERIENCE
to the surface is our own voyeurism. Zidane draws out a moment when
our own looking, our desire to look, is mirrored back to us, exposed.
The film is able to turn back on us as spectators, showing our own
voyeurism, our own desires and hopes which support the film. Indeed,
the film is an inscription of our look: the technology is an adjunct to
our desire to see, but the technology also turns against us, making us
hesitate and wonder whether we can find signs of ourselves on the field,
whether our urge somehow changes and affects what we see. The film
draws a portrait of a talented and celebrated footballer, but it also
turns its gaze back to us, to ask what are our own wishes, dreams and
desires: what are we looking for when watching Zidane?
Concluding Remarks
In this chapter I have elucidated what Merleau-Ponty held as the par-
ticular potential of cinema, namely the emphasis on film as a temporal
form and the idea of a rhythmic image. I further illustrated how the
central concepts of Merleau-Ponty, time and rhythm, are indivisible
from perception and our experience of being in the world. Within film
studies the phenomenological approach has underlined the importance
of the embodied spectator and the experience of film. In it, the relation
between the spectator and the film can be seen as reciprocal, as Barker
put it: “[w]hat we do see is the film seeing: we see its own (if humanly
enabled) process of perception and expression unfolding in space and
time.”634
In my reading of the case study, I examined in particular Zidane’s
ability to address the spectator. I suggested that Zidane creates a
rhythm of different visions that may take the spectator to the field
— or respectively, only creates a shattered and distanced impression
of the player if the rhythm of the image does not resonate with the
spectator’s own experience. Further, I showed how the film contains
different layers of time that are merged into an image of cyclic time.
this chapter’s case study. All the artworks I have discussed in previous chapters
can still be experienced at first hand in one way or another. Even though I have
observed all of the discussed works, including Fountain, at first hand, I wish to
underline that the following case study is a site-specific installation and it is now
inaccessible — the work was taken down in 2006. However, as vital as the physical
experience of a work of art is, it is equally true that within this thesis none of the
artworks is present before us.
195
196 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
643 PP, 215, “La communication ou la compréhension des gestes s’obtient par la
réciprocité de mes intentions et des gestes d’autrui, de mes gestes et des intentions
lisibles dans la conduite d’autrui.” PP, 215. | On reciprocity and reversibility in
Merleau-Ponty, see Adams 2001.
644 PP, 413. “un seul tissu” PP, 407.
645 PP, 413. “autrui n’est plus ici pour moi un simple comportement dans mon
champ transcendantal, ni d’ailleurs moi dans le sien, nous sommes l’un pour l’autre
collaborateurs dans une réciprocité parfaite” PP, 407. | In The Prose of the World
he writes about communication. In his opinion, an expression is able to constitute
a shared situation that is no longer merely “a community of being” (communauté
d’être) but “a community of doing” (communauté de faire), creating together some-
thing new. (PM, 195/140.)
646 Merleau-Ponty writes on reciprocity: “In the absence of reciprocity there is no
alter Ego, since the world of the one then takes in completely that of the other, so
that one feels disinherited in favour of the other.” PP, 416. “Sans réciprocité, il n’y
a pas d’alter Ego, puisque le monde de l’un enveloppe alors celui de l’autre et que
l’un se sent aliéné au profit de l’autre.” PP, 410.
647 Hass 2008, 132.
198 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
VI, 191.
7.1. FROM VISION TO TOUCH 199
the unity of my body, not open it to other bodies? The handshake too
is reversible”.651 At the same time a similar relation of intertwining is
discovered at the heart of perception, between touch and vision.652 In
The Visible and the Invisible, we read:
pourquoi ne l’ouvrirait-elle pas aux autres corps ? La poignée de main aussi est
réversible” VI, 184. | Flesh is understood, as emphasised in famous passage, as not
only matter, but also an element, a general thing, “midway between the spatiotem-
poral individual and the idea” (VI, 139; also in MPR). “à mi-chemin de l’individu
spatio-temporel et de l’idée” (VI, 182). Some commentators consider flesh to be
the final turn on the path started in The Structure of Behavior: from phenomenal
structure to proper body and to the flesh. (See Flajoliet 2003.)
652 Merleau-Ponty’s chapter “The Intertwining — the Chiasm” starts by pointing
out that vision seems to be formed at the heart of the visible. He argues that the
blending or indistinction between the seer and the seen is not possible — “for then
the vision would vanish at the moment of formation” (VI, 131; also in MPR, 393.
“car alors la vision s’évanouirait au moment de se faire” VI, 171) — but that it is
exactly the challenge, the intertwining of the seer and seen, that he then sets to
address.
653 VI, 134; also in MPR, 396. “puisque la vision est palpation par le regard, il
faut qu’elle aussi s’inscrive dans l’ordre d’être qu’elle nous dévoile, il faut que celui
qui regarde ne soit pas lui-même étranger au monde qu’il regarde. Dès que je vois,
il faut (comme l’indique si bien le double sens du mot) que la vision soit doublée
d’une vision complémentaire ou d’une autre vision : moi-même vu du dehors, tel
qu’un autre me verrait, installé au milieu de visible, en train de le considérer d’un
certain lieu.” VI, 175.
654 VI, 128. “proximité par distance” VI, 168.
200 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
with the look, the seer is also exposed to the palpation of the others’
looks. For Merleau-Ponty the body is twofold; on the one hand it is a
thing among things, but on the other hand it is our access and means
of grasping all things. “It cannot be by incomprehensible accident that
the body has this double reference; it teaches us that each calls for the
other.”655 He thus argues that my vision is constantly “complemented”
by the other’s vision of me. So there is a permanent movement from
the self to its outside. Merleau-Ponty writes:
For Merleau-Ponty, there are at the same time three different reg-
isters — the seer, the observer, and the actor or agent. This funda-
mentally threefold activity is merged with another experience, that of
passivity and being looked at. This experience implies the possibility
of other perceivers as well as the structure of the flesh in which every-
one is necessarily part of the same tissue, the element of the world. He
emphasises that at the heart of vision there lies a certain narcissism,
a willingness to be seen by others, or by the phantom, as he calls it.
655 VI, 137; also in MPR 398. “Si le corps a cette double référence, ce ne peut être
par un hasard incompréhensible. Il nous enseigne que chacune appelle l’autre.” VI,
178–79.
656 VI, 139; also in MPR, 400. “De sorte que le voyant étant pris dans cela qu’il
autrui, au point où, par une sorte de chiasma, nous devenons les autres et nous
devenons monde.” VI, 210.
658 Christopher Watkin describes this text by Derrida as a decisive intervention
this is our theme, the other here of a touching-touched [...] but this other ‘here’
presents itself as that which will never be mine.” (Derrida 2005, 191–92.) A similar
line of critique has been presented by Luce Irigaray, who also accused Merleau-
Ponty of privileging vision: he was unable to understand how reversibility between
the tangible and the visible is not complete, and he also failed to acknowledge oth-
erness. In her reading of Merleau-Ponty in An Ethics of Sexual Difference, Irigaray
underlines how the visible and the tactile do not obey same laws or rhythms of the
flesh. She argues that Merleau-Ponty fails to take into account that even though
the visible needs the tactile, not all that is tangible can be rendered visible — this
includes, for instance, the pre-natal experience. Further, Merleau-Ponty ignores
sexual difference. (Irigaray 1993, 151–84; Weiss 1999, 199–23; Chanter 2000.)
661 Derrida 2005, 208. | Derrida uses the expression “réversibilité sensible”.
662 See also Johnson 2010, 38.
663 Irigaray 1993, 172; see also Chanter 2000, 220.
664 PM 198/142.
665 As Dastur remarks, the experience of one’s own body is not that of an object
doublée d’une contre-perception (opposition réelle de Kant), est acte à deux faces,
on ne sait plus qui parle et qui écoute. Circularité parler-écouter, voir-être vu,
percevoir-être perçu (c’est elle qui fait qu’il nous semble que la perception se fait
dans les choses mêmes) — Activité = passivité.” VI, 312.
7.1. FROM VISION TO TOUCH 205
ing with an artwork, since it holds similar conditions: both the phe-
nomenon of surprise and our ability of abstaining from positioning or
setting the perceived artwork as an object are linked to passivity. And
so is the idea of an icon-painting, a work of art that “contains” the
spectator and “looks back”. As Merleau-Ponty remarks, consciousness
is not merely a constant process of “donating senses,” and therefore
we must also discuss our relation to the world beyond positioning and
defining.675
The descriptions of perception and expression presented in Phe-
nomenology of Perception showed how the oppositions of active and
passive are dissolved. In Merleau-Ponty’s reading it is not possible to
pinpoint or determine where perception ends and expression starts:
perception is expressive, but it also carries a level of anonymity.676
As a theme, passivity interested Merleau-Ponty especially in the mid
1950s. He wanted to find a third solution which would liberate us from
the compulsion of choosing between the two opposites: the world en-
tirely made or the subject who makes the whole world.677 In the lecture
course “The Problem of Passivity: Sleep, the Unconscious, Memory”
(“Le problème de la passivité. Le sommeil, l’inconscient, la mémoire”)
given at the Collège de France in 1954–1955 Merleau-Ponty worked to
define a passivity that would not exclude all activity, thus a passivity
that is still active.678 In the course notes, he addressed the questions
of dream, unconscious and memory and comments, for instance, on
Sartre’s understanding of the imaginary and Freud’s conception of
the unconscious, as well as presenting a close reading of the Case of
Dora.679
The distinction between passivity and activity was already cru-
cial for Husserl. He clarifies their relation especially in his Analyses
Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis (Analysen zur passiven Syn-
logical answer to the psychoanalytical discussion that was at that time emerging
in France. Jacques Lacan had started his weekly seminars some years before. It
has been suggested that the psychoanalytic counterpart for the écart would be the
unconscious, which for Freud formed the uniting feature, whereas for Lacan it only
appeared in the breaks and cuts. The relationship between Merleau-Ponty and La-
can is a complicated one. See, for instance, Alexandra Renault’s “Merleau-Ponty
et Lacan: Un dialogue possible?” (2003) and Félix Duportail’s Les institutions du
monde de la vie. Merleau-Ponty et Lacan (2008).
206 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
Merleau-Ponty states that from the point of view of the world, the
problem is to avoid limiting it to a static image of perceived reality.
The perceived world should be taken up as being more than the reality
given in sensory experience. On the other hand, from the subjective
point of view, Merleau-Ponty sets as his goal to examine the lived body
of the subject in all its aspects. Thus the body is more than a material
thing or a natural reality. Besides the fields of sensation, it also has
680 The German original is published in Husserliana XI. Steinbock’s English
dologie alors que mon but était d’affirmer l’identité avec l’être du monde perçu
tel quel. Pour faire comprendre ce projet — et donc le dépassement du problème
activité (idéalisme) passivité (finalité) — il faut seulement entrer davantage dans
l’élucidation du monde et du sujet.” IP, 166–67.
7.1. FROM VISION TO TOUCH 207
ferent variations of consciousness — the mythical, the primitive, the infantile, and
the pathological — must be included in the phenomenology of perception.
685 IP, 267/206; also in RC, 67.
686 IP, 206. “Vivre, pour un homme, n’est pas seulement imposer perpétuellement
des significations, mais continuer un tourbillon d’expérience qui s’est formé, avec
notre naissance, au point de contact du ‘dehors’ et de celui qui est appelé à le
vivre.” IP, 267; also in RC, 67.
687 IP, 194/147.
688 IP, 126. “Il s’agit de trouver dans le monde dont nous avons l’expérience
[un] autre être et [un] autre sens à l’égard duquel l’être objectif est dérobé, est
‘idéalisation’.” IP, 170. Square brackets in the original.
208 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
689 Mauro Carbone has drawn attention to a passage in “Eye and Mind” where
Merleau-Ponty uses the term voyance: “Thus, the mental image, the visualization
[voyance] which renders present to us what is absent [...]” (Œ 132. “A plus forte
raison l’image mentale, la voyance qui nous rend présent ce qui est absent [...]” Œ,
41). He interprets Merleau-Pontian voyance to be a means to bring together the
intelligible and the sensible. Further on, Carbone suggests that voyance complies
with a definition of seeing in which passivity and activity are indistinguishable. In
Carbone’s reading voyance would be a description of an attitude: thinking about
reading, it would refer to a kind of reading that does not merely decipher sig-
nifications of words, but would be directed towards the layers and aspects that
escape deciphering and unequivocal interpretation. It would also emphasise how
the reader or spectator is both active and passive, not only imposing meanings, but
also exposing his- or herself to the work. Carbone underlines how voyance would
be seeing that cannot separate existence and essence, and neither would it be in-
terested in separation into sensory fields. He writes on voyance: “[it is] a vision that
sees the invisible in the visible and thus allows us to find, within the very veil of
music or of literary speech, the invisible of the idea that shines through.” (Carbone
2004, 35; see also 33–38.)
690 See section 2.3; Krauss 1977.
691 Later on the demand for reciprocity can be seen to have developed into interac-
tive work. Some of these works depend heavily on new technology, but interactivity
is by no means only a feature of art made with new media — one can find forms of
interactivity in all arts. (For more on interactivity and technology, see for instance
Van de Vall 2008, 146.)
7.2. ON INSTALLATION AND SITE-SPECIFIC ART 209
On Site-Specificity
In recent years, the nature of site-specific art has changed along with
the general understanding of place and space.693 Indeed, the field seems
to be in the process of transformation. Art historian Miwon Kwon has
researched the question of site-specificity in art in One Place After An-
other (2004). According to her, the change is signalled, for instance, by
a whole new terminology that expresses the different aspects and views
of site-specificity, such as site-conscious, site-related, site-determined,
etc. The gamut of terms reflect, among other things, how the rela-
tion to space is undergoing transformation and that the relation to
the tradition of site-specific art of the 1960s, whose primary concern
was to present an anti-institutional and anti-commercial statement,
has changed. Kwon’s analyses show how site-specific art has been un-
critically adopted by art institutions and art discourse.694
Kwon sketches out the history of the art form, and how its early
works rose in the tradition of minimalism, drawing inspiration from
phenomenology and an understanding of site through the physical
attributes of the location. These works were connected with being
grounded and subject to the laws of physics, considering the site no
longer as a tabula rasa but as a precondition which formally deter-
mined the work itself. Artists aimed at creating an indivisible rela-
tionship between the work and its site. This thinking was perhaps
most famously exemplified by Richard Serra’s Tilted Arc (1981–1989)
on Federal Plaza in New York, a work of art that epitomises the phe-
nomenologically orientated works in Kwon’s analysis.695 In short, phe-
nomenologically orientated works were considered to be place-bound
692 In Miwon Kwon’s study on the nature of site-specific works (2004) as well as
the studies by Claire Bishop (2005) and Julie H. Reiss (1999) which discuss the
history of installation art, emphasis is laid on the anti-institutional character of
both movements.
693 For shifts in the thinking of space, see Casey 1993; 1997. For the meaning of
globalisation and space from the angle of geography, see Massey 2005.
694 Besides One Place After Another (2004), I refer to Kwon’s article “The Wrong
Place” published both in Art Journal and From Studio to Situation (2004b).
695 The curving wall of raw steel launched a fierce discussion on public and site-
696 Kwon 2004, 11–13. | Critics claimed that the spectator or beholder suggested
by the work was considered to be a neutral and universal spectator, and thus had
no gender or ethnic background. The artworks themselves were also criticised for
being disconnected from their cultural surroundings, relating merely to the physical
features of a particular site.
697 Kwon 2004, 157.
698 Kwon 2004b, 29.
699 For a reading of nomadism in the art world, see for instance James Meyer’s
Installation Art
Installation art shares in many respects the same theoretical and his-
torical framework as site-specific art. My intention is not to cover
installation art as such, but merely to outline some basic features that
will help to set my case study into a context. My outline relies on
Julie H. Reiss’ From Margin to Center: The Spaces of Installation Art
(1999) and Claire Bishop’s Installation Art: A Critical History (2005).
In addition, a survey by Nicolas de Olivera, Nicola Oxley and Michael
Petry entitled Installation Art in the New Millennium: The Empire of
Senses (2004) concentrates on the multi-sensory aspects of installation
art.
Reiss points out that the term “installation art” is relatively new.
It was preceded by, for instance, Allan Kaprow’s “environment”, but
also by such terms as “project art” and “temporary art” used by crit-
ics.704 Later on the diversity of the works produced under the title
“installation art” has led to a situation where the term is almost pre-
cluded from having any meaning. The early phases of the art form are
connected with a critical attitude towards the prevailing conditions in
701 Kwon 2004, 31.
702 Julian Stallabrass is one of the disenchanted voices. He has suggested that
installation art is a way for art to remain exclusive and site-specific and therefore
visitable, generating more on-site visitors, and expensive, requiring more fundrais-
ing. (Stallabrass 2006.)
703 Kwon 2004, 1–2.
704 Reiss 1999, xi. | Kaprow was developing the environment aspect in the late
1950s.
212 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
the art world. For instance, in the 1960s and 1970s USA installation
artists wanted to protest against museums, which were seen as the
embodiment of political evil, receiving finance from institutions which
were involved in the Vietnam war.705 However, nowadays installation
art is by no means marginal — it has an indisputable place within the
contemporary art scene, i.e. in biennales, museums and galleries.
Bishop writes how installation art refers to a type of art into which
the viewer physically enters. She states that the key characteristic of
installation art is its capability to address the viewer directly as a
literal presence in space and thus to presuppose an embodied viewer,
whose senses of touch, smell and sound are as heightened as their sense
of vision.706 Reiss emphasises: “There is always a reciprocal relation-
ship of some kind between the viewer and the work, the work and the
space, and the space and the viewer. [...] The spectator is in some way
regarded as integral to the completion of the work.”707 To put it sim-
ply, in installation art, reciprocity underlines the fact that the work
always already implies our position as the observer as well as the one
who is observed.
Bishop’s approach does not rely on the historical account of in-
stallation art. On the contrary, she takes as her point of departure
the viewing experience. She proposes a categorisation of the works
by looking into the viewer’s experience. Based on this, she suggests
four different approaches to installation art. I will not go into the
details of the classification and would like to stress that there are sev-
eral ways to approach installation art. However, Bishop’s analysis is
helpful in structuring the manifold field of installation art. Firstly,
there are artworks that plunge the viewer into a psychologically ab-
sorptive, dream-like environments, such as Ilya Kabakov’s theatre set-
like installations. Secondly, there are works of art that are inspired
by Merleau-Ponty’s thinking and the phenomenological model of the
viewing subject, resulting in either minimalist installations or the im-
mersive tactile and sensory environments of Brazilian artists such as
Ernesto Neto. Thirdly, works that create confusing, obscured spaces,
such as Yayoi Kusama’s mirrored installations. In Bishop’s categorisa-
tion these works draw inspiration from the Freudian tradition through
Lacan and Barthes, discussing libidinal withdrawal and subjective dis-
integration. Lastly, the fourth type of installation aims in activating
quite subtle.
The second point concerns the de-centring of the subject. The idea
of a spectator who has the ultimate viewpoint, as in a Renaissance
perspective, has been criticised many times over.710 In installation the
immersed viewers cannot really take the position of an outside spec-
tator — there is no one single point of view that is designed to be the
right one. Instead, in order to experience the work, one needs to move
around: the position of the viewer is de-centred, as the place simply
has to be circumnavigated and seen through multiple perspectives as
opposed to a single perspective that implies patriarchal ideology.
As mentioned, the viewer’s experience is central when discussing
installation art. So much so that it may appear to be more difficult
to write about installations than to write about other arts, such as
painting or photography. But one should not be misguided into think-
ing that a reproduction could be a substitute for the lived experience
of an artwork. Nonetheless, installation art is phenomenological by
nature in the sense that it is tightly dependent on the viewers’ first-
hand presence in the work, i.e. the lived experience. One has to have a
multi-sensuous experience of the work in order to grasp it, and simul-
taneously, there is no single point of view from where the work could
be completely grasped. In a sense, installation invites the spectator
in but simultaneously it may resist him or her by denying a proper
over-view.
With this brief discussion I have shown how both installation art
and site-specific art are problematic and complex fields. In my discus-
sion I have sketched out how the works can be divided into different
categories and groups, depending on what aspects are emphasised.
This can be helpful in structuring the manifold field of art. However,
I shall not commit myself to this categorising in my reading, and wish
to point out that occasionally categories might appear be too restric-
tive, if, for instance, they distract the spectator so that he or she only
considers certain chosen features of a work of art, but leaves out many
others. On the whole, I have illustrated how both the discussions on
installation art as well as site-specific art connect to the tradition of
phenomenology and to the thinking of Merleau-Ponty.
713 For more on Kiasma, see the website of Steven Holl Architects,
http://www.stevenholl.com/project-detail.php?type=museums&id=18&page=1.
714 Thorsteinsdottir 2006.
7.3. TOUCHING BACK 217
715 Architecture has been characterised as able to bring together sign and form
through a form, for instance a wall is a wall, and thus a structural element, but it
is at the same time a sign of the structural element. (These distinctions by Peter
Eisenman are cited in Hansen 2006, 192.)
716 Sosnowska takes on architecture through mimicry and camouflage, and blurs
Markus Kåhre (b. 1969), whose works were installed in the same space after Sos-
nowska. Kåhre is interested in questioning perception and presentation. He builds
works that often demand that spectators reorient themselves. His carefully planned
illusions form an interesting contrast with Sosnowska’s work: where Kåhre builds
installations discussing the boundaries of perception that people can enter often
in a predetermined way, Sosnowska’s Fountain has dropped the framework, and
offers merely a space. To see it as illusion or representation — is there a trick,
hocus-pocus here or not? — is left for the spectator to decide. There are no guide-
lines how to “encounter” or “not encounter” the work, and thus freedom of choice
appears as a possible source of ambiguity and, occasionally, anxiety. Often Kåhre’s
fascinating works are available for one spectator at a time, as for instance Untitled,
a piece with a mirror and a table. For images, see
http://www.forumbox.fi/fi/jasenet/markus-kahre-2/.
718 Duchamp defined that when making readymades, the objects chosen are not
tain can be found in her other works, for instance, A Dirty Fountain
(2006) made for an exhibition Ideal City — Invisible Cities in Pots-
dam, Germany and Zamość, Poland. This fountain was much more
explicit in its “fountainness” and in its nature as an object. In the
exhibition catalogue, her work is described thus: “For Ideal City —
Invisible Cities she designed an imperfect fountain for the perfect city.
In a simple, square format water basin on a concrete base slightly out
of the vertical, spouts dirty black water”.722 Equally, a black square
and its simple aesthetics allude most obviously to Kasimir Malevitch’s
The Black Square (1936), yet environmental questions are also present.
The fountain is situated in Staudenhof behind the University of Ap-
plied Sciences building in Potsdam, and its gloomy position in garden
leads one to think of the history of the site and raises questions con-
cerning pollution. The pair of the fountain is located at Water Market
in Zamość, Poland. From the city of Zamość runs a railway that leads
to the coal and sulphur mines of upper Silesia. Both the Fountain in
Kiasma and the fountains made for the exhibition Ideal City — In-
visible Cities are “fountains-gone-bad”: they carry features of anxiety
and insecurity as well as dirtiness and the uncanny in opposition to
the purifying, refreshing and virile associations usually connected with
water fountains.
Spectator Participation
Sosnowska’s large installation works often create an interplay between
sculpture and architecture, containing the possibility of being looked
at both from the inside as well as from the outside. This play between
object and spatial shape has been central to her works, yet it is absent
from Fountain, where the outside and inside are only implied by the
awareness of the spectator, not by the actual possibility of seeing the
work from the outside.
Thinking about Fountain one can see that it does what many instal-
lation works have done during the last few decades: it turns spectators
into participants and actors.723 In Fountain the proscenium is removed
722 Ideal City — Invisible Cities 2006.
723 The theatricality that art historian Michael Fried so vigorously criticised in
the 1960s is an unavoidable theme in this work: “Literalist [minimal art] sensibility
is theatrical because, to begin with, it is concerned with the actual circumstances
in which the beholder encounters literalist work.” (Fried 1998, 153.) He adds: “But
the things that are literalist works of art must somehow confront the beholder —
they must, one might almost say, be placed not just in his space but in his way.”
(Fried 1998, 154.)
220 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
and the division between artwork and audience is dissolved. The spec-
tators simultaneously view the work and participate in making it as
they enter the space. Returning to Bishop’s classification previously
presented, the piece could belong to the category that aims to be psy-
chologically absorptive, but it also encourages the viewer to adopt a
heightened awareness of the situation. Alternatively, the work itself
could be seen to use the strategies of camouflage and mimicry.724 In
short, it is not easy to place the work under a certain heading. Sos-
nowska herself has remarked that she is interested in creating a mental
space, wishing to affect the viewer and stimulate certain emotions.725
The limit between inner and outer would then be dissolved in this work
as the physical surrounding affects the spectator without him or her
knowing.726 However Fountain is much subtler work than some other
installations by Sosnowska, such as Corridor, a narrowing passage with
a trompe l’oeil effect created for the Venice Biennale in 2003. As a re-
sult Fountain might not appear very strong in its utopian tendencies,
and could on the contrary be claimed to be too plain, a bypassable
work.
This work is not placed in the way of the beholder, but perhaps in
his or her space, or, spectators are nonchalantly placed in its space.
Whether the work was noticed or not depend on the spectator’s at-
tentiveness. To some visitors, the space of Fountain appeared to be an
exclamation mark, as it produced a visible rupture in the surround-
ing, carefully designed museum space. These spectators felt instantly
that the space had been manipulated. However, there were also many
visitors who simply passed by without noticing anything special, with
possibly a vague feeling of untidiness or clumsiness caused by the corri-
dor. This disconnection with the audience is interesting. If the work is
724 In connection with this category Bishop pointed to Roger Caillois’ article on
“Where we are has a great deal to do with who and what we are [...]. Where some-
thing or someone is, far from being a casual qualification, is one of its determining
properties.” He adds: “But my own changes may be funded back into the very
places that have been so formative for my identity in the first place. Given this
reciprocity of person and place, place-alienation is itself two-fold: I from it, it from
I.” (Casey 1993, 307.)
7.3. TOUCHING BACK 221
missed, does it mean that it fails? Was not one of the points of instal-
lation art to make people more aware of the actual viewing situation?
The theatrical space of the installation is clearly changed if the view-
ers passing through it are not thinking of themselves as spectators or
performers, but rather as nonchalant or indifferent strollers in a trivial
in-between space between one work and another. On the other hand,
there were other people who recognised the space as a work of art and
the passers-by as performers.
Here, the differences of spectatorial experience can be related to
the issues examined in the previous chapter: In connection with my
discussion of the moving image as well as the experience of Zidane, I
refer to the “carnal knowledge” that a spectator of film may experience,
or to use Sobchack’s description, he or she may “know” something
with one’s fingers. Transferred from the sphere of a movie theatre
into encountering an installation, it perhaps could be said that the
spectator of Fountain may, without being able to determine the specific
reasons, sense that the space he or she has entered is not in its usual
state. In the case of Sosnowska’s installation, the possibilities of the
spectator to recognise the space as a work of art is related to his or
her experiences — the spectatorial experience is tightly connected to
the personal histories and “carnal knowledge” of the visitors: these
experiences shape the way visitors perceive their surroundings. This
may, of course, also happen if the spectator has visited the museum
before, but then the observation of difference within gallery spaces is
based on a different kind of knowledge.727
The nature of Fountain’s presence created a suspense, which at
times was manifested in the anger some visitors expressed as, after
briefly standing around, they became aware of the nature of the sur-
rounding space. Possibly their reaction was connected to the fact that
they had been exposed to something — or better yet, something had
invaded their personal space — without noticing, without their choos-
ing to “look at” it differently? Perhaps the irritability stemmed from
the feeling that one had been secretly disoriented? All in all, Sosnowska
continues the tradition set by Duchamp and Nauman by casting an
audience. Olivera, Oxley & Petry write in the chapter “The Body of
the Audience” about the public’s role and position in experiencing the
work:
727 I propose that without prior experience of the particular spaces of the museum,
one may able to see that something has been done to the gallery. This sensitivity
is also something that may depend on the cultural background of the spectator,
which is again a wide topic that I will not take up here.
222 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
729 For instance André Lepecki has presented a reading of the treatment of mas-
culinity in Nauman’s studio performances. (Lepecki 2006.) David Hopkins has done
a reading of Duchamp’s strategy to adopt an alternative female persona Rrose
Sélavy. (Hopkins 1998.)
730 Hopkins writes on Duchamp: “[...] an object [Fountain] which, on one level,
clearly addresses itself to male ‘needs’ [...]” Later on he continues: “If, as stated
earlier, the urinal evokes at once the forms of Buddha and the Holy Virgin, the
object (like Freud’s Mut), clearly has hermaphroditic connotations.” (Hopkins 1998,
304–306.)
731 The mechanics of the work were constructed by the museum engineer and a
group of students. The challenge to get the water dropping slowly and evenly as
possible, was somewhat different from the traditional fountain mechanics, where
pressure is built up to get the water high in the air.
732 An interesting reading of the nature of viscosity or stickiness and how “stick-
the visitors who returned to the exhibition could witness the change that took
place in the work. The wet spot in the ceiling and floor can indeed reach uncanny
dimensions, but also ironic or hyperrealist dimensions, depending on the specta-
tor. Sosnowska allegedly had no knowledge of the history of Kiasma having had
problems with leaks.
735 Irigaray 1993, 156.
736 Relating to liquidity, in the chapter “Volume — Fluidity” in Speculum Irigaray
writes: “And the flow of some shameful liquid. Horrible to see: bloody. Fluid has
to remain that secret remainder, of the one. Blood, but also milk, sperm, lymph,
saliva, spit, tears, humors, gas, waves, airs, fire ... light. All threaten to deform,
propagate, evaporate, consume him, to flow out of him and into another who cannot
be easily held on to. The ‘subject’ identifies himself with/in an almost material
consistency that finds everything flowing abhorrent. And even in the mother, it
is the cohesion of a ‘body’ (subject) that he seeks, solid ground, firm foundation.
Not those things in the mother that recall the woman — the flowing things. He
cathects these only in a desire to turn them into the self (as same). Every body of
water becomes a mirror, every sea, ice.” (Irigaray 1985, 237.)
737 Elizabeth Grosz writes: “For Irigaray this metaphorics of fluids, emblematic
of femininity in This Sex Which is Not One (1985) and Marine Lover (1991),
signifies not only the ‘formlessness’ of feminine jouissance but more particularly
the amniotic element that houses the child in the mother’s body and continues to
be a ‘watermark’ etched on the child’s body.” (Grosz 1994, 104.)
7.3. TOUCHING BACK 225
ing, it is interesting to consider Nancy’s conception that one always only touches
the limit or border, whereas the “inside” remains out of reach of the touch. (Der-
rida 2005, 103.) Martta Heikkilä writes: “[Nancy’s] conception of touch implies a
thinking of separation, dislocation, or ‘effraction’ as he calls it.” (Heikkilä 2007,
249.)
739 Van de Vall writes about the tactile palpation, see Van de Vall 2008, 64–68.
740 VI, 133–34. “un toucher du lisse et du rugueux, un toucher des choses —
into account the other. I will not take a stand whether her reading is a misreading
or is justified, but I have wished to turn to this particular reading of touch. (For an
interpretation of Irigaray’s reading, see, for instance Chanter 2000; Sjöholm 2000;
Cataldi 2004; Lehtinen 2010.)
742 Irigaray 1993, 161.
743 Irigaray 1993, 162; see also Grosz 1994, 105.
7.3. TOUCHING BACK 227
744 “[...] il n’est pas en dehors de spectacle, qu’il n’a pas une position de survole. Le
spectateur n’est pas un voyeur, il est impliqué dans le monde visible de l’œuvre
d’art.” Slatman 2003, 191.
228 CHAPTER 7. POSITIONED INTO SPACE
[...] for the body is not simply a de facto visible among the vis-
ibles, it is visible-seeing, or look. In other words, the fabric of
possibilities that closes the exterior visible in upon the seeing
body maintains between them a certain divergence (écart). But
this divergence is not a void, it is filled precisely by the flesh as
the place of emergence of vision, a passivity that bears activity
— 745
Concluding Remarks
In this chapter, I have discussed the themes of touch, reversibility and
passivity and their relevance for the experience of “seeing with” an
artwork. My goal was to examine what happens in our encountering
an artwork in cases in which the work hides from the spectator. Is a
specific type of active passivity a prerequisite for such an encounter?
By choosing an installation work as my case study, I wanted to
illuminate the multi-sensuous character of perceptual experience. This
multi-sensuousness has interested artists, especially those working in
the tradition of installation art. Sosnowska’s Fountain differs from my
other case studies in several ways: in fact, it may at first seem that
this work is indifferent to the reactions of the spectator, uninterested
in whether it gets his or her attention. However, I have argued that
this work reaches the spectator through less articulated and less con-
ventional means. The fact that art works affect us without our noticing
and without our conscious attention is of course well-known. As much
as one can observe an artwork and study it actively, it also involves as-
pects that may have an affect on us without our noticing. But possibly
our persistent wish to “see with” includes a danger of believing that
we already know or we can decide how our gaze is directed, what it
aims at and what it is about to find. I would like to suggest that Foun-
tain is not indifferent to our states of consciousness or the direction of
745 VI, 272. “[...] le corps n’est pas simplement un visible de fait parmi les visibles,
our gaze, but more importantly also, that we should not be indifferent
to the more subtle ways things arrive to us. In fact, this is what the
work to my mind addresses: it gives space to the unnoticeable. The
unexpected, unthematised in a work of art demands openness from
the spectator — and sometimes even openness is not enough, since it
is revealed to be limited by consciousness and its schemata. The situa-
tion, in which the spectator becomes part of the work, or is subjected
to the work, shatters our notions of art and our expectations of its ef-
fects. This, I argue, helps us to understand why passivity is a genuine
element of the encounter with a work of art.
8
Conclusions
231
232 CHAPTER 8. CONCLUSIONS
coming. But how could his approach be carried further, how to set it
into a dialogue with contemporary art? This question was a crucial
part in my examination of Merleau-Ponty. In other words, I did not
remain perfectly faithful to the examples Merleau-Ponty had. On the
contrary, the preferences and choices of examples also motivated me
to read him anew. To participate in the contemporary discussions on
art it does not suffice to limit oneself to Cézanne’s paintings. By look-
ing into the various fields of visual arts, I have been able to point out
new ways of reading and developing his phenomenology. For instance,
I suggested with my case study how the philosophical discussion on
painting’s space need not attach itself to the binary oppositions be-
tween Renaissance painting and Cézannian painting. Or, concerning
his critical remarks on photography, I proposed that Merleau-Ponty’s
reservations can be read as statements which reject the scientific atti-
tude, not the medium itself. Through these various case studies I hope
to have shown that Merleau-Ponty’s own examples do not have to re-
strict our readings — and yet simultaneously we should not overlook
his examples but can be inspired and motivated by them in our choice
of new, philosophically challenging examples.
Interlinked with the question of materiality, my discussion empha-
sised the relation between the spectator and the work of art, i.e. I
wished to examine how the work appears to the spectator. In my in-
terpretations of the artworks I have taken into account the embodied
spectatorship and the different multi-sensuous aspects of the works.
However, I acknowledge that the emphasis on the medium of the se-
lected works can at points be problematic. Moving within the field
of contemporary art in such a large scope raises questions: why bring
together the thought of Merleau-Ponty with the eclectic field of con-
temporary art? To this I would reply that from my perspective the
phenomenological philosophy of art is still an aesthetics that is find-
ing its form and thus it is our task to set it against contemporary art
in order to narrow the gap between the traditional perspectives and
present-day discussions.
In bringing together philosophy and art, the main question was
how to make them resonate in a way that could do justice to both.
Undoubtedly, the commitment to the thinking of Merleau-Ponty has
directed my interests in choosing the works of art to be discussed, and
has also guided my interpretations of the pieces. However, I have let
the works influence philosophy, in a sense that the art has directed my
reading of Merleau-Ponty into directions that have then shed light on
the interpretations.
234 CHAPTER 8. CONCLUSIONS
rhythms and layers of time. The rhythm of the work may, so to speak,
take the spectator to the field, in so far the rhythms of the game res-
onate with his or her bodily schema. Conversely, if the spectator can-
not recognise the rhythms, the work gives a shattered and distanced
impression of the player. Moreover, in my discussion I laid out how in
Zidane the different layers of time are all merged into an image of cyclic
time. In the first place the film is linear and follows the clock-time of
one game of football. However the work is also an attempt to grasp real
time, to preserve a moment and one sport performance. The intensive
“now” of the film was intersected with different elements: the portrait
of a star was mixed with childhood memories of bygone sports heroes
and it pointed forwards in time to a significant incident that took
place after the filming. These temporal transitions were connected to
the spectatorial experience, e.g. memories awakened by the film could
suddenly send the spectator into his or her own childhood. Besides the
several cinematic times and rhythms that this piece brought together,
I also underlined how as a portrait the film approaches a limit, namely
the invisibility of seeing our own seeing: at least momentarily Zinédine
Zidane, the footballer whose portrait the film shows, could reach his
own seeing, his own movement.748
Finally, in chapter 7, I examined the themes of touch, reversibility
and passivity. I showed how the relationship between vision and touch
evolves in Merleau-Ponty. Reversibility defines both ourselves — as
Merleau-Ponty described, reversibility takes place between our senses
— as well as our relations to others and to the world. I elucidated how
in the late texts of Merleau-Ponty the concept of reversibility remains
asymmetrical, and thus always involves noncoincidence. Reversibility
also draws attention to passivity, how one’s activity is always also a
passivity and vice versa.
As concepts reversibility, touch and passivity were especially im-
portant in the examination of the case study: I discussed a site-specific
installation that addressed the multi-sensuous situation of encounter-
ing an artwork and the centrality of the reciprocal relationship estab-
lished between the work and the beholder. In order to contextualise
my case study, I looked closer into the traditions of site-specific art
and installation art, both which, in their early days of development,
shared a critical stance towards the practices of art exhibition and art
museums and held a particularly physically participatory relationship
to the spectator.
241
242 BIBLIOGRAPHY
283–287.
Casebier, Allan 1991: Film and Phenomenology. Toward a Realist
Theory of Cinematic Representation. (Cambridge Studies in
Film.) Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Casey, Edward S. 1987: Remembering. A Phenomenological Study.
(Studies in Phenomenology and Existential Philosophy.)
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
—1993: Getting back into Place: Toward a Renewed Understanding of
the Place-World. (Studies in Continental Thought.) Blooming-
ton: Indiana University Press.
—1997: The Fate of the Place. A Philosophical History. (A Centennial
Book.) Berkeley: University of California Press.
—2002: Representing Place. Landscape Painting and Maps. Minneapo-
lis & London: University of Minnesota Press.
—2004: “Attending and glancing.” Continental Philosophy Review 37,
83–126.
—2005: Earth-Mapping. Artists Reshaping Landscape. Minneapolis &
London: University of Minnesota Press.
—2007: The World at a Glance. (Studies in Continental Thought.)
Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Cassirer, Ernst 1992 (1944): An Essay on Man. New Haven & London:
Yale University Press.
Cataldi, Sue L. 1993: Emotion, Depth, and Flesh. A Study of Sensi-
tive Space: Reflections on Merleau-Ponty’s Philosophy of Em-
bodiment. State University of New York Press, Albany.
—2004: “The Philosopher and Her Shadow: Irigaray’s Reading of Mer-
leau-Ponty.” Philosophy Today 48.
Chanter, Tina 2000: “Wild Meaning: Luce Irigaray’s Reading of Mer-
leau-Ponty.” In Evans, F. & Lawlor, L. eds. Chiasms. Merleau-
Ponty’s Notion of Flesh. Albany: State University of New York
Press, 219–236.
Charbonnier, Georges 2002 (1959): Le monologue du peintre. Paris:
Éditions de la Villette.
Coles, Alex (ed) 2006: Site-Specificity in Art: The Ethnographic Turn.
(de-, dis-, ex-, 4.) London: Black Dog Publishing Limited.
Cottingham, John 1989 (1986): Descartes. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Crary, Jonathan 1995 (1990): Techniques of the Observer. On vi-
sion and Modernity in the Nineteenth Century. (An OCTOBER
Book.) Cambridge: The MIT Press.
—1999: Suspension of Perception. Attention, Spectacle, and Modern
Culture. (An OCTOBER Book.) Cambridge: The MIT Press.
248 BIBLIOGRAPHY
11, 3–25.
—1985: Droit des Regards. Paris: Editions de Minuit.
—2005: On Touching — Jean-Luc Nancy. Trans. Christine Irizarry,
(Le toucher, Jean-Luc Nancy, 1998). (Meridian, Crossing Aes-
thetics.) Stanford: Stanford University Press.
—2010: Copy, Archive, Signature. A Conversation on Photography.
Trans. Jeff Fort, ed. Gerhard Richter. Stanford: Stanford Uni-
versity Press.
Descartes, René AT: Œuvres de René Descartes. Publiées par Charles
Adam et Paul Tannery sous les auspices du Ministère de
l’Intruction Publique. Paris: Cerf.
—PWI: The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Volume I. Trans.
John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Duglad Murdoch. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dillon, Martin C. 1988: Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology. (Studies in Phe-
nomenology and Existential Philosophy.) Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
—1997: “Introduction: Écart & Différance.” In Dillon, M. C., ed. Écart
& Différance. Merleau-Ponty and Derrida on Seeing and Writ-
ing. New Jersey: Humanities Press, New Jersey, 1–17.
Diprose, Rosalyn 2002: Corporeal Generosity. On Giving with Ni-
etzsche, Merleau-Ponty, and Levinas. (SUNY Series in Gender
Theory.) Albany: State University of New York Press.
Doane, Mary Ann 2002: The Emergence of Cinematic Time. Moder-
nity, Contingency. The Archive. Cambridge, Massachusetts &
London, England: Harvard University Press.
—2003: “The Close-Up: Scale and Detail in the Cinema.” differences:
A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 14 (3), 89–111.
Doherty, Claire, ed. 2004: Contemporary Art from Studio to Situation.
London: Black Dog Publishing.
Dufrenne, Mikel 1953: Phénoménologie de l’expérience esthétique.
(Épiméthée. Essais philosophiques.) Paris: Presses Universi-
taires de France.
Dupond, Pascal 2008: Dictionnaire Merleau-Ponty. Paris: Ellipses.
Duportail, Guy-Félix 2008: Les institutions du monde de la vie.
Merleau-Ponty et Lacan. (Collection Krisis.) Grenoble: Jerôme
Millon.
Dürer, Albrecht 1977: The Painter’s Manual. A manual of measure-
ment of lines, areas, and solids by means of compass and ruler
assembled by Albrecht Dürer for the use of all lovers of art with
appropriate illustrations arranged to be printed in the year of
250 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Viking Press.
—1999: “A Voyage to the North Sea”. Art in the Post-Medium Condi-
tion. London: Thames & Hudson.
—2006: “Two Moments from the Post-Medium Condition.” October
116, 55–62.
Kriebel, Sabine T. 2007: “Theories of Photography: A Short History.”
In Elkins, J., ed. Photography Theory. New York & London:
Routledge, 3–50.
Kristensen, Stefan 2008: “Le mouvement de la création. Merleau-
Ponty et le corps de l’artiste.” Alter. Revue de phénoménologie
16, 243–260.
Kuutti, Tuija, ed. 1998: Bruce Nauman. Kuva/teksti 1966–1996. (Ny-
kytaiteen museon julkaisuja 44/1998.) Helsinki: Nykytaiteen
museo Kiasma.
Kwon, Miwon 2004 (2002): One Place After Another. Site-Specific Art
and Locational Identity. Cambridge: The MIT Press.
—2004b: “The Wrong Place.” Contemporary Art from Studio to Situa-
tion, ed. Claire Doherty. London: Black Dog Publishing, 29–41.
See also Art Journal 59 (1), 32–43.
—2010: “Dogs and the City” in Godfrey, Mark & Biesenbach, Klaus
& Greenberg, Kerryn, eds. Francis Alÿs. A Story of Deception.
London: Tate Publishing, 181–82.
Labelle, Gilles 1999: “Esthétique et communauté chez Merleau-
Ponty.” Revue d’esthétique 36, 115–124.
Lannoy, Jean-Luc 2008: Langage, perception, mouvement. Blanchot
et Merleau-Ponty. (Collection Krisis.) Grenoble: Jerôme Millon.
Larrabee, Mary Jeanne 1989: “Time and Spatial Models: Temporality
in Husserl.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XLIX
(3), 373–392.
Leder, Drew 1990: The Absent Body. Chicago and London: The Uni-
versity of Chicago Press.
Lefort, Claude 1999 (1969): “Avertissement.” La prose du monde
(PM), Maurice Merleau-Ponty. (Collection tel.) Paris: Galli-
mard, i–xiv.
Lehtinen, Virpi 2010: Luce Irigaray’s Philosophy of Feminine Be-
ing: Body, Desire and Wisdom. (Philosophical Studies from the
University of Helsinki 29.) Tampere: Juvenes Print.
Leighton, Tanya 2008: “Introduction.” In Leighton, T., ed. Art and
the Moving Image. A Critical Reader. London: Tate Publishing,
7–40.
Lenoir, Tim 2004: “Foreword.” In Hansen, M. B. N., New Philosophy
260 BIBLIOGRAPHY
In Hallward, P., ed. Think Again. Alain Badiou and the Future
of Philosophy. London: Continuum, 218–231.
—2009: Aesthetics and its Discontents. Trans. Steven Corcoran. (Ma-
laise dans l’esthétique, 2004.) Cambridge: Polity Press.
—2009b: The Emancipated Spectator. Trans. Gregory Elliot. (Le spec-
tateur émancipé, 2008) London and New York: Verso.
Régis, Michel 1992: Géricault, l’invention du réel. (Découvertes Gal-
limard.) Paris: Gallimard.
Reiss, Julie H. 1999: From Margin to Center. The Spaces of Installa-
tion Art. Cambridge & London: The MIT Press.
Renault, Alexandra 2003: “Merleau-Ponty et Lacan : Un dialogue
possible ?” In Cariou, M. & Barbaras, R. & Bimbenet, E.,
eds. Merleau-Ponty aux frontières de l’invisible. (Les cahiers de
Chiasmi International numéro 1.) Milano: Associazione Cultur-
ale Mimesis, 117–129.
Reuter, Martina 1997: “Descartes, sukupuoli ja karteesiolaisen sub-
jektin kritiikki.” Naistutkimus 1/1997, 2–19.
—1999: “Questions of Sexual Difference and Equality in Descartes’
Philosophy.” In Aho, T. & Yrjönsuuri, M., eds. Norms and
Modes of Thinking in Descartes. (Acta Philosophica Fennica
64.) Helsinki: The Philosophical Society, 183–208.
—2003: “Appearance, Truth and Limitations: Merleau-Ponty on the
History of Philosophy.” Paper presented in the first Annual
Meeting of Nordic Society for Phenomenology, University of
Helsinki, 25th April, 2003.
Revault d’Allonnes, Myriam 2001: Merleau-Ponty. La Chair du po-
litique. (Collection le bien commun.) Paris: Michalon.
Richir, Marc 1999: “Commentaire de Phénoménologie de la conscience
esthétique de Husserl.” Revue d’esthétique 36, 15–26.
Ricoeur, Paul 2009: “Beyond Husserl and Heidegger (1989).” Trans.
W. Froman. In Flynn, B. & Froman, W. J. & Vallier, R., eds.
Merleau-Ponty and the Possibilities of Philosophy. Transform-
ing the Tradition. Albany: SUNY Press, 25–31.
Río, Elena del 2001: “The Body of Voyeurism: Mapping a Discourse of
the Senses in Michael Powell’s Peeping Tom.” Camera Obscura
45, vol 15, no 3, 115–149.
Rodrigo, Pierre 2006: “L’image, l’analogon, le simulacre : la ques-
tion des ‘fictions perceptives’ chez Husserl.” La Part de l’Œil no
21–22 (Dossier : Esthétique et phénoménologie en mutation),
95–105.
Rogoff, Irit 2000: Terra Infirma. Geography’s visual culture. London
WORKS BY OTHER AUTHORS 265
271
272 APPENDIX A. IMAGES
Figure A.4: Christian Mayer: Another city, not my own, 2007, digital
slideshow.
275
Figure A.5: Christian Mayer: Another city, not my own, 2007, digital
slideshow.
276 APPENDIX A. IMAGES
Figure A.6: Christian Mayer: Another city, not my own, 2007, digital
slideshow.
277
Figure A.7: Christian Mayer: Another city, not my own, 2007, digital
slideshow.
278 APPENDIX A. IMAGES
Figure A.8: Christian Mayer: Another city, not my own, 2007, digital
slideshow.
279
Figure A.9: Christian Mayer: Another city, not my own, 2007, digital
slideshow.
280 APPENDIX A. IMAGES
Figure A.10: Douglas Gordon & Philippe Parreno: Zidane: A 21st Cen-
tury Portrait, 2006. Anna Lena Films.
Figure A.11: Douglas Gordon & Philippe Parreno: Zidane: A 21st Cen-
tury Portrait, 2006. Anna Lena Films.
281
Figure A.12: Douglas Gordon & Philippe Parreno: Zidane: A 21st Cen-
tury Portrait, 2006. Anna Lena Films.
Figure A.13: Douglas Gordon & Philippe Parreno: Zidane: A 21st Cen-
tury Portrait, 2006. Anna Lena Films.
282 APPENDIX A. IMAGES
Figure A.14: Douglas Gordon & Philippe Parreno: Zidane: A 21st Cen-
tury Portrait, 2006. Anna Lena Films.
Figure A.15: Douglas Gordon & Philippe Parreno: Zidane: A 21st Cen-
tury Portrait, 2006. Anna Lena Films.
283
Figure A.16: Douglas Gordon & Philippe Parreno: Zidane: A 21st Cen-
tury Portrait, 2006. Anna Lena Films.
284 APPENDIX A. IMAGES
Tiina Mielonen
Born in 1974, Helsinki, Finland. Lives and works in Helsinki.
Education
2003 Master of Fine Arts, Finnish Academy of Fine Arts, Helsinki,
Finland
287
288 APPENDIX B. ARTIST RESUMES
Christian Mayer
Born in 1976, Sigmaringen, Germany. Lives and works in Vienna.
Education
2005 Diploma Academy of Fine Arts Vienna
2004 Glasgow School of Art
CHRISTIAN MAYER 289
Since 2002 Co-Editor of the art magazine that changes its title with
each issue, depending of the font that is used. Released issues by 2011:
Chicago, Times, Plotter, Helvetica, DIN, Techno, Löhfelm, RR_02,
Univers, Tiffany, Circuit, Memphis, Gringo, Zeus, The Mix, Princess
Lulu, Pigiarniq, Paper, Libertine, Trixie.
Solo Shows
2011 Scenic, Galerie Christian Nagel, Berlin
Apartment 2, Los Angeles
Kunstraum Ursula Werz, Tübingen
2010 Kunstraum Ursula Werz, Tübingen
2009 Gizmo, Galerie Mezzanin, Vienna
2008 flotsam and jetsam (Les Vues d‘Amérique du Nord), FIAC,
Paris
2007 flotsam and jetsam, Galerie Mezzanin, Vienna
Another city, not my own, Österreichisches Kulturforum, War-
saw
2006 Serious Immobility, Thomas K. Lang Gallery, Vienna
2005 New Talents, Art Cologne 2005
2003 Venedig in Wien in Venedig, Castello 3271, Venice
Christian Mayer kommt aus Wien und bringt was mit aus
Berlin, Atelier Just, Düsseldorf
Christian Mayer, Kastanienallee 82, Berlin
Curatorial Works
2006 Société des nations, factice et scindée en elle-même (with
Christian Egger, Manuel Gorkiewicz, Yves Mettler, Magda
Tothova, Ruth Weismann, Alexander Wolff), Circuit, Lau-
sanne
2005 PERFORMANCE (with Alice Chauchat, Christian Egger,
Manuel Gorkiewicz,
Yves Mettler, Magda Tothova, Ruth Weismann, Alexander
Wolff), Flaca gallery, London
2004 living room (with Yves Mettler), Kunsthalle Exnergasse, Vi-
enna
292 APPENDIX B. ARTIST RESUMES
Douglas Gordon
Born in 1966, Glasgow, Scotland. Lives and works in Glasgow and New
York.
Education
1990 The Slade School of Art, London
1988 Glasgow School of Art, Scotland
Solo Exhibitions1
2011 Douglas Gordon: k.364, Gagosian Gallery, London
2009 Douglas Gordon, Galerie Eva Presenhuber, Zurich
2008 Douglas Gordon, Garage Centre for Contemporary Culture,
Moscow
Retrospective. Gagosian Gallery, New York
Archetypes and Icons. Gagosian Gallery, New York.
Douglas Gordon. Gallery Hyundai Company, doArt Bei-
jing/Seoul.
2007 Douglas Gordon: self-portrait of you + me, after the factory,
Gagosian Gallery, New York (980 Madison).
Douglas Gordon (curated by Rudolf Frieling), San Francisco
Museum of Art, CA.
Douglas Gordon, Yvon Lambert, Paris.
2006 Douglas Gordon: superhumanatural, National Galleries of
Scotland, Edinburgh.
Douglas Gordon: Black and White (Babylon), Patrick Painter
INC, Los Angeles.
prettymucheverywordwritten,spoken,heard,overheardfrom
1989... (curated by Giorgio Verzotti and Mirta D’Argenzio),
Museo di arte moderna e contemporanea di Trento e Rovereto
(Mart), Italy.
Douglas Gordon: Self-Portraits of You+Me, Gagosian Gallery,
New York.
National Gallery, Edinburgh, Scotland.
Museo d’Arte Moderne e Contemporanea, Trento, Italy.
Netherlands.
Fuzzy Logic, Centre Georges Pompidou, Paris.
Rooseum Espresso, Malmö, Sweden.
1994 Douglas Gordon, Lisson Gallery, London.
1993 24 Hour Psycho, Tramway, Glasgow and Kunst Werke, Berlin.
Migrateurs, ARC Musée d’Art Moderne de la Ville de Paris.
1991 Roderick Buchanan/Douglas Gordon, Orpheus Gallery,
Belfast.
1988 40 years (collaboration with Craig Richardson), Royal Scottish
Academy, Edinburgh.
From Cradle to grave (collaboration with Craig Richardson),
Royal Scottish Academy, Edinburgh.
4th Avenue Festival (collaboration with Craig Richardson),
Arnhem, Netherlands.
The Puberty Institution (collaboration with Craig Richard-
son), Midland Street Car Park, Glasgow, Scotland.
The Puberty Institution: Refuse — consumption — decay —
survival (collaboration with Craig Richardson), N.R.L.A. @
Third Eye Centre, Glasgow, Scotland.
1987 Experiments under Nostalgia’s Umbrella (collaboration with
Craig Richardson), Third Eye Center, Glasgow, Scotland.
N.R.L.A. (collaboration with Craig Richardson), Riverside
Studios, London.
Curatorial Projects
Commissions
1998 “Empire”, Visual Art Projects for the Merchant City Civic
Society, Glasgow, Scotland.
1994 Bookworks, London.
296 APPENDIX B. ARTIST RESUMES
Philippe Parreno
Born in 1964 Oran, Algeria. Lives and works in Paris, France.
Education
1989 Institut des Hautes Etudes en arts plastiques — first session
— Palais de Tokyo, Paris
1988 Ecole des Beaux-Arts de Grenoble
1983 Math sup/Math sp
Solo Exhibitions2
2010 Irish Museum of Modern Art, Dublin
Walker Art Center, Minneapolis
2009 Serpentine Gallery, London
May, Kunsthalle Zurich, Zurich
Musée national d’Art moderne — Centre Georges Pompidou,
Beaubourg
2008 Suicide in Vermilion Sands, Friedrich Petzel Gallery, New
York
October, Pilar Corrias Ltd., London
2007 Philippe Parreno, Esther Schipper, Berlin
What do you believe, your eyes or my words, Haunch of Veni-
son, London
Stories are Propaganda, Friedrich Petzel Gallery, New York
Stories are Propaganda, Air de Paris, Paris
2006 Interior Cartoons, Esther Schipper, Berlin
Again for Tomorrow, Royal College of Art Galleries, London
Briannnnnn & Ferryyyyyy/Law Creativity, collaboration with
Liam Gillick, Kunsthalle Zurich
2005 The Boy From Mars, Friedrich Petzel Gallery, New York
Air de Paris, Paris
You and Me, Me and You (w/ Douglas Gordon), Fondazione
Davide Halevim, Milano
Atlas Of Clouds, Brian Butler/1301PE, Los Angeles
Briannnnnn & Ferryyyyyy, collaboration with Liam Gillick,
Vamiali’s, Athens
2004 Fade Away, Kunstverein, Munich
2 For a CV with group exhibitions, see http://www.airdeparis.com/parreno.htm.
PHILIPPE PARRENO 297
Collaborations
2005 Rirkrit Tiravanija: Une rétrospective (Tomorrow is another
Fine Day), Couvent des Coedeliers, Paris —F
jsq. 20.03.05
Briannnnnn & Ferryyyyyy/ Law and Creativity, with Liam
Gillick, Kunsthalle Malmö, Malmö —SW
2004 Rirkrit Tiravanija : No vitrines, no museums, no artists, just
a lot of people, with Pierre Huyghe and Maurizio Nannucci,
22.05.04, Telecom Italia Future Center, Venise —I
2003 Sodium Dreams , with D. Gonzalez-Foerster & P. Huyghe,
Center for Curatorial Studies Museum, Bard College,
Annnandale-on-Hudson, New York —USA
Pardo/Parreno, galerie Air de Paris —F
No Ghost, Just a Shell, Pierre Huyghe and Philippe Parreno,
Eindhoven, Van Abbemuseum
2002 No Ghost Just a Shell, Pierre Huyghe and Philippe Parreno:
Institute of Visual Culture, Fitzwilliam Museum, Cambridge
—UK
No Ghost, Just a Shell, Kunsthalle Zürich, Zurich
No Ghost, Just a Shell, San Francisco Museum of Modern Art,
San Francisco
A smile without a cat, Philippe Parreno and Pierre Huyghe,
cur. S. Antelo-Suarez, night 04.12.02, Art Basel Miami Beach
—USA
Jorge Pardo, Philippe Parreno, 1301 PE, Los Angeles —USA
2001 No Ghost Just a Shell, Pierre Huyghe and Dominique
Gonzalez-Foerster, Museum Boijmans van Beuningen, Rotter-
dam —NL
In many ways the exhibition already happened, Pierre Huyghe,
M/M, Philippe Parreno, R&Sie, Institute of Contemporary
Artsa, The mall, London —GB
EGOFUGAL, Tokyo Opera City Art Gallery, Tokyo
Animations, PS1, Long Island City
300 APPENDIX B. ARTIST RESUMES
Interventions
1997 Postman Time, On art and its places open to 21 C, Kunsthalle,
Nurnberg
302 APPENDIX B. ARTIST RESUMES
Monika Sosnowska
Born in Ryki, Poland, 1972. Lives and works in Warsaw, Poland.
Education
2000 Rijksakademie van Beeldende Kunsten, Amsterdam
1998 Academy of Fine Arts, Poznan, Poland
Solo Exhibitions
2011 Tamayo Museum, Oaxaca, Mexico
2010 Herzliya Museum of Contemporary Art, ‘Stairway’, Herzliya,
Israel
Hauser & Wirth New York, New York NY
Herzliya Museum of Contemporary Art, ‘The Staircase’, Her-
zliya, Israel
Artpace, ‘Monika Sosnowska’, San Antonio TX
K21 Ständehaus, ‘The Staircase / Die Treppe, 2010’, Dussel-
dorf, Germany
2009 Capitain Petzel Gallery, Berlin, Germany
2008 The Modern Institute, Glasgow, Scotland
Primrose Hill, Public art for London’s Parks, ‘The Wind
House’, London, England
2007 Talbot Rice Gallery, University of Edinburgh, Edinburgh,
Scotland
52nd International Biennale of Venice, Polish Pavilion, ‘1:1’,
Venice, Italy
Kunstmuseum Lichtenstein, ‘Loop’, Vaduz, Lichtenstein
2006 Museum Dhondt Dhaenens Deurle, ‘Picture This!’, Deurle,
Belgium
Museum of Modern Art, ‘Projects 83’, New York NY
Galerie Gisela Capitain, ‘Display’, Cologne, Germany
Sprengel Museum, ‘Interventionen 41’, Hanover, Germany
Musac Museo de Arte Contemporaneo de Castilla y Leon,
Leon, Spain
Arsenal Gallery, ‘Instalacja/Installation’, Białystok, Poland
Kronika Gallery, ‘Display/Wystawa’, Bytom, Poland (Travel-
ling Exhibition)
2005 Foksal Gallery Foundation, ‘Display/Wystawa’, Warsaw,
Poland (Travelling Exhibition)
MONIKA SOSNOWSKA 303
Group Exhibitions
2011 Venice Biennale, ‘Illuminations’, Venice, Italy
2010 LABoral Centro de Arte, ‘Passages. Travels in Hyperspace’
from the Thyssen-Bornemisza Art Conteporary Collection, Gi-
jon, Spain
Daimler Contemporary, ‘Ampersand — A Dialogue of Con-
temporary Art from South Africa & the Daimler Art Collec-
tion’, Berlin, Germany
Centre Pompidou, ‘elles@centrepompidou’, Paris, France
2009 Centre Pompidou — Musée National d´Art Moderne,
‘elles@centrepompidou, artistes femmes dans les collections du
Centre Pompidou’, Paris, France
2008 Kurimanzutto, ‘Nos cambiamos de domicilio’, Mexico City,
Mexico
Schaulager, ‘Monika Sosnowska / Andrea Zittel, Munchen-
stein, Basel, Switzerland
Kurator. Ein Förderprogramm der Gebert Stiftung für Kultur,
‘Susan Philipsz, Monika Sosnowska’, Rapperswil, Switzerland
304 APPENDIX B. ARTIST RESUMES
Frankfurt, Germany
Kunsthalle Basel, ‘In Capital Letters’, Basel, Switzerland
2001 Raster Gallery, Warsaw, Poland
Gelerie du Jour, ‘Il y a toujour quelq’un qui veux quelque
chose’, Paris, France
1st Biennale of Tirana, Tirana, Albania
Bielska Gallery BWA, ‘Painters’ Competition’, Bielsko-Biala,
Poland
Leon Wyczółkowski Museum, ‘Oikos’, Bydgoszcz, Poland
2000 Centre de Solai, ‘Escape’, Bamako, Mali
Hans Brinker Hotel, ‘The Double Room’, Amsterdam, Nether-
lands
Outline Foundation, ‘Painted Image Limited’, Amsterdam,
Netherlands