Individualism: Social Contract
Individualism: Social Contract
Individualism: Social Contract
Individualism
Given the political and economic interests of its beneficiaries, classical liberalism
places a very strong emphasis on the individual's right to property. This
ideology is thus a natural favorite for proponents of a capitalist economic
system. A capitalist economy allocates economic decision-making to individuals
meeting in free markets. In such a system individuals, rather than the state,
are the predominant owners of property. This highlights another key aspect of
classical liberalism: its clear suspicion of centralized political power and its
earnest advocacy of limited government. You may recall another famous phrase
credited to that prolific phrase-turner, Thomas Jefferson: "That government is
best which governs least."
Limited Government
Contemporary Liberalism consists of separate and often contradictory streams of thought springing
from a common ancestry; the intellectual parent of these variants has not only endured intact, it has
outlived some of its offspring and shown more intellectual stamina than others. The tenets of this
parent, known as classical liberalism, have answered the needs and the challenges of over three
centuries in the West. By observing its past and discovering how it responded to the dramatic
historical dynamics of economic, technological, political, and social changes we may understand
how classical liberalism provides a strong foundation for the future.
In order to assign consistent terms in this study, I must first define classical liberalism. Scholars have
offered different interpretations of this term. For example, E. K. Bramsted, co-editor of the
monumental anthology Western Liberalism: A History in Documents from Locke to Croce (1978),
asserts that the classical liberal champions the rights of individuals (with careful attention to the more
endangered rights of minorities), the right of property in particular, the government's obligation to
protect property, limited constitutional government, and a belief in social progress (36). John Gray
broadens this description in Liberalism (1986) to include philosophies demonstrating individualism,
egalitarianism, and universalism (x). In Liberalism Old and New (1991), J. G. Merquior argues that
the theories of human rights, constitutionalism, and classical economics define classical liberal
thought.
These scholars and others actually agree far more than they differ concerning the philosophy's
components. For the purpose of this chronology and analysis, I shall apply a broad set of criteria to
determine if an idea or individual fits within this intellectual tradition. In this context, classical
liberalism includes the following:
an ethical emphasis on the individual as a rights-bearer prior to the existence of any state,
community, or society,
the support of the right of property carried to its economic conclusion, a free-market system,
the desire for a limited constitutional government to protect individuals' rights from others and
from its own expansion, and
the universal (global and ahistorical) applicability of these above convictions.
These characteristics do exclude certain thinkers commonly linked with classical liberalism, although
they embrace far more individuals than they dismiss. Failure to exhibit them, however, does point to
a very fundamental difference with the minds that compose the tradition. Two diverse cases of
thinkers associated with yet not belonging to this ideology may serve as examples. First, Jeremy
Bentham and the utilitarians accepted limited rights and market economics as long as they provided
the greatest happiness for the greatest number. Classical liberal ends thus served as convenient
means to them, but the eventual ends they sought betrayed an intellectual collectivism incompatible
with the above criteria. From a different angle, Jean Jacques Rousseau's vision of the social
contract, while also noteworthy, included an almost mystic notion of a general will. Such a concept
created an unaccountable power elite to interpret and impose this will, by force if necessary. Again,
vital components of classical liberal thought are offended. Neither Bentham nor Rousseau therefore
are members of this legacy.
Any single attempt to chronicle the history of classical liberalism cannot do justice to the immense
richness and diversity of the individuals or movements within it. In this story three distinct flavors
coexist and often blend: the realistic English tradition of law, the rationalistic French tradition of
humanism, and the organic German tradition of individualism. Gray characterizes these three as
competing yet complementary definitions of liberty, with Britain representing independence, France
self-rule, and Germany self-realization (13). Beyond these national differences, two parallel concepts
survive throughout the history of classical liberalism irrespective of geographical boundaries. One is
predicated upon a negative view of human nature, accepting that people are equally fallen and
incapable of perfection. It follows from this perspective that power must be limited because it would
allow some corrupt individuals to do more harm than others. The other view maintains that all people
are inherently good and perfectible, so power must be limited to allow humanity to evolve toward a
more perfect order of self-government.
This chronology admittedly cannot discuss every contributor or school of thought in such a multi-
dimensional and lasting tradition. For example, the contributions of Lysander Spooner and the 19th
century American anarchists or Albert Jay Nock and the American Old Right could easily have been
included. I have made an effort to note leaders that symbolize the ideology's historical stages. The
absence of names or works does not necessarily signify any defensible judgment of importance.
This treatment is meant to provide a general introduction to the rise, decline, and reemergence of
classical liberalism and therefore is limited by space and purpose. As the decision to include and
omit facts was difficult and, to a degree, arbitrary, I beg the indulgence of the reader as I begin this
historical overview.
Classical Liberalism: John Locke and Adam Smith
It is within the newly liberated England of the Glorious Revolution that we meet
John Locke, the father of classical liberalism. Classical liberalism is the original
name for the political philosophy we now call libertarianism. The main reason for
the name change is that the words "liberalism" and "liberals" invoke an entirely
different meaning in modern politics. Libertarianism is a good substitute, since it
holds the pursuit and protection of liberty above all else.