Sutherland - Populism and Spectacler
Sutherland - Populism and Spectacler
Sutherland - Populism and Spectacler
in discourse a premise that Laclau and Chantal Mouffe (1985) have of course
elaborated throughout decades of worth of work done together and apart
their existence must be forged in the tropic relations of discourse itself.1
For perhaps obvious reasons, Laclau returns to the domain of political
rhetoric most literally defined to delineate the particular set of tropic figures
that produces a populist formation of the social. In the process, he transposes a
De Manian discussion of aesthetic terms and relations back onto more properly
defined social and political ones. For instance, he posits ‘the demand’ as the
minimal unit of a populist social formation; cites the ‘formation of an internal
frontier’ between ‘the people’ and the ‘institutional system’ as the metonymic
condition by which multiple demands associate multiple constituencies as a
people; and defines the charismatic figure of ‘the leader’ as the affective and
rhetorical condition by which this partial fragment of society becomes
metaphorically identified with ‘the people’ as such (2005, pp. 7374; 94
99). Of course, at the heart of this distinctly literal discussion of political
relations lies the figurative claim most fundamental to Laclau’s renovation of
populism: without the affective charge that for other theorists and philosophers
only exhausts the conceptual content of populism, the hegemonic sublimation
by which a part of society becomes discursively identified with the whole of
society could not inhere. That is, without the radical investment of meaning
that the figurative dimension of this synecdoche sets in motion, the claim of
one particular group to represent society in general would read as a
misrepresentation at worst and a logical contradiction at best. Moreover,
the ‘rational’ practice of more revered political philosophies such as democracy
could not inhere either; the basic and yet impossible political imperative of
representing ‘society’ an entity whose claim to totality is necessarily founded
on this same incommensurability would make no sense at all. Laclau thus
declares populism a ‘political logic’, which is to say, an ontological production
of the social itself, rather than the name for a particular social group or
ideology (2005, p. 117).
One of the many striking things about this scenario is the particular
combination of tensions and affinities that it holds with Guy Debord’s
description of social production in The Society of the Spectacle (1994). The
tensions are perhaps obvious. While Debord begins his treatise by declaring,
‘All that was once directly lived has become mere representation’ (1994,
p. 12), Laclau begins his by rejecting the very notion of any ‘merely’
epiphenomenal representation (2005, p. 67). While Debord emphasizes the
constitutive role that ‘trancelike behavior’ and ‘separation’ play in producing
the social unity of spectacle (1994, pp. 1617), Laclau emphasizes emotional
investment and relation as the very ground of the populist formation. And
while Debord describes spectacle as the institution of an ‘enormous positivity’
in which ‘Everything that appears is good; whatever is good will appear’
(1994, p. 15), Laclau expressly defines the aesthetic economy of populist
rhetoric against the aesthetic economy of this expressly institutionalist
332 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S
another instance of ‘popular aesthetic form’, and thus marks and produces the
habitus of its audience as a disenfranchised class formation in aesthetic
discourse, the other two would focus on how audience discourses surrounding
the reception of spectacular entertainment articulate the constituents of this
audience as a populist formation defined against the dominant institutions of
culture. In both cases, the discursive production of ‘the people’ takes place
entirely outside the aesthetic relations of spectacular entertainment itself; the
aesthetic relations of visual discourse somehow do not carry the ontological
force allowed to ‘discourse’ here. There is something of value in each of these
arguments, to be sure. And yet, in my estimation, Debord and Laclau’s
respective accounts require that we take the radical conceit of rhetoricity that
lies at the heart of On Populist Reason far more seriously than any of these
models allows. Indeed, they compel us to consider the extent to which the
vaguely defined aesthetic conventions associated with ‘spectacular entertain-
ment’ enact a set of tropic relations that automatically stage their audience as a
generalized figure of ‘the people’, and in the process, enact a kind of
enfoldment of the movement between affection and disaffection, production
and reproduction, that they respectively describe.
In the pages that follow, then, I want to explore this possibility by
indulging in a rhetorical sublimation of my own: I want to look at how the
staging of the audience in a particularly charged form of popular spectacle
the blackface minstrelsy show showcases an aesthetic automation of the very
same tropic relations that Laclau traces out on the terrain of political discourse.
In the process, I want to consider how the populist political formation that
congeals around the figure of this audience might provide some critical
leverage on the details of Laclau’s aesthetic figuration of populism especially
where it overlaps most suggestively with the institutionalist figure of spectacle
in Debord’s account. I also want to consider how the rudimentary set of
aesthetic conventions that define this particular instance of American popular
entertainment, as well as a good deal of what is still considered definitively
‘popular entertainment’ worldwide, might allow us to recognize the
infamously ‘broad’ spectacular form of the variety showcase a form that
carries the basic visual conceit of monstration, or showing, across a wide array of
mediums, genres and constituencies as an ontological aesthetic of ‘the
people’ in its own right.5 As I have already begun to suggest, this expressly
aesthetic vantage on the ontological nature of the relation between spectacle, on
the one hand, and the discursive production of the ‘the people’, on the other,
proposes some significant changes in the way that we understand the relation
between political ontology and the visual dimension of popular aesthetics.
Perhaps even more fundamentally, though, it attempts to draw out at least
some of the profound implications that Laclau’s most recent work holds for us
today when the discursive terrain of ‘proper’ political discourse is more
overwhelmingly expansive, if not more spectacular, than ever.
P O P U L I S M A N D S P E C TA C L E 335
these attractions, showcase as well the breadth of the audience that responds to
these attractions with expressions of their own variety.7
Interestingly enough, this double presentation of an articulated spectacle,
on the one hand, and the spectacle of the reciprocally articulated audience for
this spectacle, on the other, also resonates strongly with Debord’s most
Laclauean description of spectacle as a set of relations, where he writes, ‘The
spectacle appears at once as society itself, as a part of society and as a means of
unification. As a part of society, it is that sector where all attention, all
consciousness, converges . . . the unity it imposes is merely the official
language of generalized separation’ (1994, p. 12). Indeed, with the tropic
relations of the showcase aesthetic in mind, it is a great deal easier to visualize
the mise-en-scene of this otherwise illogical set-up. As a ‘part’ of society,
spectacle evokes the focal point of a visual display whose ‘broad’ appeal
coordinates the sightlines of ‘all’. As ‘all’ of society, it evokes both the surfeit
of representivity imputed to this variegated display on account of its ‘broad’
appeal and the variegated spectacle of the audience whose apparent articulation
of different responses simultaneously confirms it. Finally, as a ‘means of
unification’, it evokes the relational aesthetic condensed under the heading of
the variety showcase itself. Thus, to read Debord’s description of spectacle as a
relational production of social unity that is predicated on separation much
like the unity of a rhetorical relation is to recognize spectacle as something
more than just an empty signifier. A fortiori, it is to recognize spectacle as a
signifier of the empty signifier, a monstrative display case of sorts for the set of
tropic movements that the empty signifier enacts, and at bottom, a veritable
mechanism of hegemonic social productions. But what would it look like to see
the institutionalist aesthetic of spectacle coincide with the aesthetic reading of
On Populist Reason not to mention the understanding of a ‘society of
spectacle’ that it makes thinkable?
Material institutions of spectacular entertainment seldom cast quite the
menacing shadow of oppression that spectacle does in theory; blackface
minstrelsy is an exception. And in this same capacity, it provides a
concentrated example of how the political logic of populism can overlap
with the distinctly institutionalist logic of spectacle in a single aesthetic
production of ‘the people’. What is more, it provides this example in a
medium of spectacular entertainment that precludes any simple reduction of
the latter’s logic to merely technological or economic registers of mediation
namely, the spatio-temporal unity of a pre-industrialized theatre. Indeed, when
minstrelsy stabilized as a discrete institution of American popular theatre in the
1840s, critics often hailed it as the first great art form to originate with
the American people a distinction that perhaps already speaks to its
significance for the formation of an expressly working-class cultural sensibility,
but one that simultaneously overlapped with an institutionalist construction of
white American civic identity more generally (1974, p. 25). Performances
generally featured white ethnic performers in blackface, most of them recent
P O P U L I S M A N D S P E C TA C L E 337
immigrants to the States, as they played out various stereotypes of black affect
in a variety showcase comprised of comedic musical numbers, dances, dialect
performances, skits and oratorical satires. As Robert Toll notes, the versatility
of this format played a key role establishing the form’s popular status, for it
gave the minstrel show ‘a flexibility that . . . could immediately respond to its
audiences’ preferences in both form and content’ (1974, pp. 5256). Of
course, insofar as the versatility of the format made it possible to adapt the
show itself to the demands of the people in the audience, the affective response
of this audience quickly became recognized as a conventional part of the
spectacle promised by it.8
In Love and Theft, Eric Lott (1995) offers an account of the political
discourse that emerged around the phenomenon of the minstrel show that
should interest us a great deal. In the course of this argument, he draws a
subtle link between the performance and consumption of ‘blackness’ that took
place in this particular arena of popular entertainment and the consolidation of
modern populist labour coalitions. Positioning the practice of cross-racial (and
often cross-gender) drag in the volatile political context of the mid-nineteenth
century just as pre-Civil War debates about slavery began to threaten the
federal union and ‘labor struggles’ and class-driven riots erupted in urban
centres Lott characterizes minstrel performance as a site of contradictory
investments for the white working class. He writes:
With only a fiddler by his side, Rice performs center stage. He is the only
‘black’ person in the theater. A crowd has thronged to the foot of the
stage and overflowed onto the boards. It is a crowd of some variety,
except for the almost total absence of women: workers in smocks and
straw hats rub elbows with militiamen; clerks ape the betters they hope
one day to become; a few respectable men intervene in scuffles that have
broken out in two places on the stage. The picture frame is tightly packed
with spectators; the frame extends beyond the boxes on the left to include
four more tiers of people. The crowd has become both background and
foreground it is not too much to say that it has become the spectacle
itself, so much is Rice dwarfed by the crowd’s interest in its own
activities.
(Lott 1995, pp. 124125)
In this passage, Lott finds the two linked performances I have deemed typical
of the variety showcase aesthetic: Rice’s performance of ‘blackness’ and the
audience’s performance of its response to Rice, the latter of which marks out a
whole spectrum of different social positions within and just beyond the borders
of the white, often immigrant working class. The significance of this audience
showcase is of course not lost on Lott, who proposes that the ‘function’ of
minstrelsy was ‘to bring various class fragments into contact with one another’
by accommodating an array of ‘emerging splits’ within populist discourses of
race equality and citizenship not least on account of the ironic mode of
address that often attends the presentational aesthetic of the variety showcase
(1995, pp. 6667). But what if we took Lott’s reading of the minstrel show’s
‘populist’ audience more literally? What if this popular art form’s tendency
towards audience participation, presentation and emotional investment has less
to do with a ‘deep-rooted’ habitus, and more to do with the aesthetic
P O P U L I S M A N D S P E C TA C L E 339
Laclau sets up between the constitutive lack of populism, on the one hand, and
the promise of plenitude or representational sufficiency that defines the
institutional logic of spectacle in Debord’s account. For if the obviously limited
audience for this popular spectacle can be invested with the incommensurable
significance of embodying a synecdoche for ‘the people’ more broadly, it is
partly because the differential articulation of the audience that the showcase
aesthetic carries out amidst its entire sceneographic operation also foregrounds
the broad array of audience ‘demands’ to which it must answer to gather a
‘popular’ audience worthy of the name. That is, by showcasing the variety of
the particular audience constituencies fighting for ground in the unseemly
confines of a minstrel show galley, the spectacle of the audience points like a
rhetorical vector to its own claim for broader representivity, and thus, to the
variety of ‘the people’ it can accommodate in general whether or not it
succeeds in accommodating any actual demands in the political sphere. The
spectacle of racial difference presented onstage can open onto the contentious
spectacle of sociopolitical demands it articulates because it showcases the figure
of the audience according to the same tropic totality that Laclau describes
essentially a limited set of metonymic differences that takes on a metaphorical
sense of identity with an impossible social whole. To paraphrase the vision of
the working class that Laclau and Mouffe borrow from Rosa Luxembourg, the
audience is constituted as a ‘people’ because ‘a frontier of exclusion’ here
racial and institutional at once allows their ethnic, political and economic
differences to be effaced without disappearing (2005, p. 81). At the same time,
though, the affective coherence of this spectacle of ‘the people’ depends on the
traces of these differences precisely to point to the total sufficiency of the social
fragment it represents as an audience and nothing more; consumer plenitude
and political partiality overlap here. It is perhaps for this reason, above all, that
the institution of minstrelsy is generally associated with the production of two
very different constructions of political identity: on the one hand, the
consolidation of full white citizenship for the ethnic immigrants that could now
begin to embody the very plenitude of American multiculturalist and economic
inclusivity, and on the other, the consolidation of the distinctly class-bound
populist coalition that Lott discusses.10 And yet, the aesthetic overlap between
these two hegemonic constructions of the social is hardly unique to the
minstrel show format either.11 The production of any coherent political
identity would seem to require the policing of the limits of difference it can
contain, and in turn, the policing of a rhetoric for heterogeneity through which
to articulate itself in its drive for liberation. Blackface minstrelsy is simply one
brutal vestige of this process.
In treating the spectacular mise-en-scene of the minstrel show as an
ambivalent ontological ground on which a figure of ‘the people’ was forged in
this period, I would not like to suggest that we can simply equate the
‘populism’ of consumer culture with the political discourse of populism that
demands something other than a spectacle to its liking. Rather, I would like to
342 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S
performance that articulates the politics of the popular audience through its
own variety showcase of group spectatorship whether in relation to the
monstration of an entertainment spectacle or the demonstration of a political
rally. The term spectacle would thus seem to refer to nothing so much as the
aesthetic relation of undecidability between these terms that manifests itself as
the unstable substrate of visual presentation undergirding the ‘empty’ imagery
of rhetoric and spectacle alike.
Of course, to think of spectacle this way is to recognize the latter as
something that constitutes an opening for the political just as unstably as it does
a closure for, or codification of it. For insofar as the variety-based aesthetic of
spectacle can raise a people in the name of this same codification simply by
staging them according to the spectacular formal relations of the showcase it
shows well how the potential to police enfolds a key moment of politics. In
this sense, reading spectacle through Laclau’s intervention does not make us
better readers of Debord’s text or his intentions; it allows us to recognize a
much larger and more complex problem of political ontology that manifests
itself in the pages of The Society of the Spectacle, whether Debord intends it or
not; it compels us to think this problem anew, and perhaps indefinitely.
Notes
1 To cite just a few of these works, see Laclau (1990, 1996); Laclau and
Mouffe (1985).
2 For just a couple of the field-founding discussions of popular art forms and
the audience with which they are associated in Cultural Studies, see Hall and
Whannel (1965) and Williams (1978). For a couple of the most archetypal
Frankfurt School treatments of the audience for ‘mass’ entertainment, see
Kracauer (2005) and Adorno (2001).
3 Several recent studies critique the ‘populist’ claims of reality-TV and new
media from an implicitly or explicitly Debordian perspective. See, for
instance, Andrejevic (2003) and Dean (2010).
4 For a small sample of some of the canonical texts associated with these three
theoretical traditions and their adaptation within the field of Cultural
Studies, see Fiske (1989a, 1989b) and Jenkins (1992, 2006).
5 I explore this idea at significantly greater length in my dissertation and book
manuscript on how the trope of variety moves across the registers of
political and aesthetic discourse as a figure of spectacle. See Sutherland
(2007).
6 Laclau offers his fullest discussion of the logic of the empty signifier in ‘Why
Do Empty Signifiers Matter to Politics?’ (1996, pp. 36 46).
7 For a much full development of this claim, see Sutherland (2007, 2008).
8 For instance, by the time the minstrel show fell out of favour in the wake of
the Civil War, the spectacular convention of spotlighting the response of the
344 C U LT U R A L S T U D I E S
Notes on contributor
References
Adorno, T. (2001) The Culture Industry: Selected Essays on Mass Culture, ed. J.M.
Bernstein, London, Routledge.
Andrejevic, M. (2003) Reality TV: The Work of Being Watched, New York, Rowman
& Littlefield.
Aristotle (1977) Politics, trans. H. Rackham, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University
Press.
Bourdieu, P. (1984) Distinction, trans. R. Nice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard
University Press.
De Certeau, M. (1984) The Practice of Everyday Life, trans. S. Rendall, Berkeley,
University of California Press.
P O P U L I S M A N D S P E C TA C L E 345