Paul Ricoeur
Paul Ricoeur
Paul Ricoeur
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhup.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
New Literary History.
http://www.jstor.org
The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action
Considered as a Text
PaulRicoeur
event, therefore, is significant if, and only if, it makes visible the effectua-
tion by which our linguistic competence actualizes itself in perform-
ance. But the same apology becomes abusive as soon as this event-
character is extended from effectuation, where it is valid, to under-
standing. What is it to understand a discourse?
Let us see how differently these four traits are actualized in spoken
and written language:
(I) Discourse, as we said, exists only as a temporal and present in-
stance. This first trait is realized differently in living speech and in
writing. In living speech, the instance of discourse has the character of
a fleeting event, an event that appears and disappears. That is why
there is a problem of fixation, of inscription. What we want to fix is
what disappears. If, by extension, we can say that one fixes language-
inscription of the alphabet, lexical inscription, syntactical inscription-
it is for the sake of that which alone has to be fixed, discourse. Only
discourse is to be fixed, because discourse disappears. The atemporal
system neither appears nor disappears; it does not happen. Here is the
place to recall the myth in Plato's Phaedo. Writing was given to men
to "come to the rescue" of the "weaknessof discourse," a weakness which
was that of the event. The gift of the grammata-of that "external"
thing, of those "external marks," of that materializing alienation-was
just that of a "remedy" brought to our memory. The Egyptian king of
Thebes could well respond to the god Theuth that writing was a false
remedy in that it replaced true reminiscence by material conservation
and real wisdom by the semblance of knowing. This inscription, in
spite of its perils, is discourse's destination. What does writing fix? Not
the event of speaking, but the "said" of speaking where we understand
by the said that intentional exteriorization constitutive of the aim of
discourse thanks to which the sagen-the saying-wants to become
Aus-sage-the enunciation, the enunciated. In short, what we write,
what we inscribe, is the noema of the speaking. It is the meaning of
the speech event, not the event as event.
What does writing fix? If it is not the speech event, it is speech itself
in so far as it is said. But what is said?
Here I would like to propose that hermeneutics has to appeal not
only to linguistics (linguistics of discourse vs. linguistics of language)
as it does above, but also to the theory of the speech act such as we
find it in Austin and Searle. The act of speaking, according to these
authors, is constituted by a hierarchy of subordinate acts which are
distributed on three levels: (I) the level of the locutionary or proposi-
tional act, the act of saying; (2) the level of the illocutionary act or
94 NEWLITERARY
HISTORY
force, that which we do in saying; and (3) the level of the perlocu-
tionary act, that which we do by saying. When I tell you to close the
door, for example, "Close the door!" is the act of speaking. But when
I tell you this with the force of an order and not of a request, this is
the illocutionary act. Finally, I can stir up certain effects, like fear, by
the fact that I give you an order. These effects make my discourse act
like a stimulus producing certain results. This is the perlocutionary act.
What is the implication of these distinctions for our problem of the
intentional exteriorization by which the event surpasses itself in meaning
and lends itself to material fixation? The locutionary act exteriorizes
itself in the sentence. The sentence can be identified and reidentified
as being the same sentence. A sentence becomes an enunciation (Aus-
sage) and thus is transferred to others as being such and such a sentence
with such and such a meaning. But the illocutionary act can also be
exteriorized in grammatical paradigms (indicative, imperative, and
subjunctive modes, and other procedures expressive of the illocutionary
force) which permit its identification and reidentification. Certainly,
in spoken discourse, the illocutionary force leans upon mimicry and
gestural elements and upon the nonarticulated aspects of discourse, what
we call prosody. In this sense, the illocutionary force is less completely
inscribed in grammar than is the propositional meaning. In every case,
its inscription in a syntactic articulation is itself gathered up in specific
paradigms which in principle make possible fixatiod by writing. Without
a doubt we must concede that the perlocutionary act is the least in-
scribable aspect of discourse and that by preference it characterizes
spoken language. But the perlocutionary action is precisely what is the
least discursive in discourse. It is the discourse as stimulus. It acts, not
by my interlocutor's recognition of my intention, but energetically, by
direct influence upon the emotions and the affective dispositions. Thus
the propositional act, the illocutionary force, and the perlocutionary
action are apt, in a decreasing order, for the intentional exteriorization
which makes inscription in writing possible.
Therefore it is necessary to understand by the meaning of the speech-
act, or by the noema of the saying, not only the sentence, in the narrow
sense of the propositional act, but also the illocutionary force and even
the perlocutionary action in the measure that these three aspects of the
speech-act are codified, gathered into paradigms where, consequently,
they can be identified and reidentified as having the same meaning.
Therefore I am here giving the word "meaning" a very large accepta-
tion which covers all the aspects and levels of the intentional exterioriza-
tion which makes the inscription of discourse possible.
THE MODEL OF THE TEXT 95
the field of discourse. It is at this strategic level that the so-called phi-
losophy of actions operates among post-Wittgensteinian thinkers.
G. E. M. Anscombe in Intention, A. I. Melden in Free Action, and
Richard Taylor in Action and Purpose require no other conceptual
framework for their theory of action than the one which is at work
in ordinary language. Science is another "language game" based on
quite different semantic rules. It is one thing to speak of actions, pur-
poses, motives, agents and their agency, and it is something else to speak
of movements as happening, of mental events (if there are any), or of
physical or mental causes. The duality of linguistic games, that of
ordinary language and that of the behavioral and the social sciences,
is inseparable. As is known, the main discrepancy between both lan-
guage games concerns the irreducibility of motive, conceived as "reason
for," to cause interpreted in Humean terms as an antecedent event
logically distinct from, and contingently linked to, its consequent. But is
it true that a scientific approach must necessarily exclude the character
of meaningfulness and that ordinary language alone preserves it? Is
there not a scientific language for which action would be both "objec-
tive" and "meaningful"?
The comparison between interlocution and interaction may help us
at this stage of our analysis. In the same way that interlocution is over-
come in writing, interaction is overcome in numerous situations in
which we treat action as a fixed text. These situations are overlooked
in a theory of action for which the discourse of action is itself a part of
the situation of transaction which flows from one agent to another,
exactly as spoken language is caught in the process of interlocution,
or, if we may use the term, of translocution. This is why the under-
standing of action at the prescientific level is only "knowledge without
observation," or as G. E. M. Anscombe says, "practical knowledge"
in the sense of "knowing how" as opposed to "knowing that." But this
understanding is not yet an interpretation in the strong sense which
deserves to be called scientific interpretation.
My claim is that action itself, action as meaningful, may become an
object of science, without losing its character of meaningfulness, by
virtue of a kind of objectification similar to the fixation which occurs
in writing. By this objectification, action is no longer a transaction to
which the discourse of action would still belong. It constitutes a de-
lineated pattern which has to be interpreted according to its inner con-
nections.
This objectificationris made possible by some inner traits of the action
which are similar to the structure of the speech act and which make
THE MODEL OF THE TEXT 99
Moreover, this noema has not only a propositional content, but also
presents "illocutionary" traits very similar to those of the complete
speech act. The different classes of performative acts of discourse de-
scribed by Austin at the end of How to do Things with Words may be
taken as paradigms not only for the speech acts themselves, but for the
actions which fulfill the corresponding speech acts. A typology of action,
following the model of illocutionary acts, is therefore possible. Not only
a typology, but a criteriology, inasmuch as each type implies rules, more
precisely "constitutive rules" which, according to Searle in Speech-Acts,
allow the construction of "ideal models" similar to the ideal types of
Max Weber. For example, to understand what a promise is, we have
to understand what the "essential condition" is according to which a
given action "counts as" a promise. This "essential condition" of Searle
is not far from what Husserl called Sinngehalt, which covers both the
"matter" (propositional content) and the "quality" (the illocutionary
force).
We may now say that an action, like a speech act, may be identified
not only according to its propositional content, but also according to
its illocutionary force. Both constitute its "sense-content." Like the
speech act, the action-event (if we may coin this analogical expression)
develops a similar dialectic between its temporal status as an appearing
and disappearing event, and its logical status as having such and such
identifiable meaning or "sense-content." But if the "sense-content" is
what makes possible the "inscription" of the action-event, what makes
it real? In other words, what corresponds to writing in the field of
action?
Let us return to the paradigm of the speech-act. What is fixed by
writing, we said, is the noema of the speaking, the saying as said. To
what extent may we say that what is done is inscribed? Certain meta-
phors may be helpful at this point. We say that such and such event
left its mark on its time. We speak of marking events. Are there not
"marks" on time, the kind of thing which calls for a reading, rather
than for a hearing? But what is meant by this metaphor of the "im-
printed mark"? The three other criteria of the text will help us to
make the nature of this fixation more precise.
In the same way that a text is detached from its author, an action is
detached from its agent and develops consequences of its own. This
autonomization of human action constitutes the social dimension of
THE MODEL OF THE TEXT 101
According to our third criterion of what a text is, we could say that
a meaningful action is an action the importance of which goes "beyond"
its relevance to its initial situation. This new trait is very similar to the
way in which a text breaks the ties of discourse to all the ostensive
references. Thanks to this emancipation from the situational context,
discourse can develop nonostensive references which we called a "world,"
in the sense in which we speak of the Greek "world," not in the cos-
mological sense of the word, but as an ontological dimension.
What would correspond in the field of action to the nonostensive
references of a text?
We juxtaposed, in introducing the present analysis, the importance
of an action to its relevance as regards the situation to which it
wanted to respond. An important action, we could say, develops
meanings which can be actualized or fulfilled in situations other than
the one in which this action occurred. To say the same thing in dif-
ferent words, the meaning of an important event exceeds, overcomes,
THE MODEL OF THE TEXT 103
Then, if the dialogical relation does not provide us with the paradigm
of reading we have to build it as an original paradigm, as a paradigm
of its own.
This paradigm draws its main features from the status of the text
itself as characterized by (I) the fixation of the meaning, (2) its dis-
sociation from the mental intention of the author, (3) the display of
nonostensive references, and (4) the universal range of its addressees.
These four traits taken together constitute the "objectivity" of the text.
From this "objectivity" derives a possibility of explaining, which is not
derived in any way from another field, that of natural events, but
which is congenial to this kind of objectivity. Therefore there is no
transfer from one region of reality to another, from the sphere of facts,
let us say, to the sphere of signs. It is within the same sphere of signs
that the process of objectification takes place and gives rise to explana-
tory procedures. And it is within this sphere of signs that explanation
and comprehension are confronted.
I propose that we consider this dialectic in two different ways: (I) as
proceeding from comprehension to explanation, and (2) as proceeding
from explanation to comprehension. The exchange and reciprocity
between both procedures will provide us with a good approximation of
the dialectical character of the relation.
At the end of each half of this demonstration I shall try to indicate
briefly the possible extension of the paradigm of reading to the whole
sphere of the human sciences.
that juridical reasoning does not at all consist in applying general laws
to particular cases, but each time in construing uniquely referring de-
cisions. These decisions terminate a careful refutation of the excuses
and defenses which could "defeat" the claim or the accusation. In
saying that human actions are fundamentally "defeasible" and that
juridical reasoning is an argumentative process which comes to grips
with the different ways of "defeating" a claim or an accusation, Hart
has paved the way for a general theory of validation in which juridical
reasoning would be the fundamental link between validation in literary
criticism and validation in the social sciences. The intermediary func-
tion of juridical reasoning clearly shows that the procedures of vali-
dation have a polemical character. In front of the court, the plurivocity
common to texts and to actions is exhibited in the form of a conflict
of interpretations, and the final interpretation appears as a verdict to
which it is possible to make appeal. Like legal utterances, all interpre-
tations in the field of literary criticism and in the social sciences may
be challenged, and the question "What can defeat a claim?" is common
to all argumentative situations. Only in the tribunal is there a moment
when the procedures of appeal are exhausted. But it is so only because
the decision of the judge is implemented by the force of public power.
Neither in literary criticism nor in the social sciences is there such a
last word. Or, if there is any, we call that violence.
at least the same size as the sentence and which, put together, form
the narrative proper to the myth, can be treated according to the same
rules as the smallest units knowns to linguistics. It is in order to insist
on this likeness that Claude Levi-Strauss speaks of mythemes, just as
we speak of phonemes, morphemes, and semantemes. But in order to
remain within the limits of the analogy between mythemes and the
lower-level units, the analysis of texts will have to perform the same
sort of abstraction as that practiced by the phonologist. To him, the
phoneme is not a concrete sound, in an absolute sense, with its acoustic
quality. It is not, to speak like de Saussure, a "substance" but a
"form," that is to say, an interplay of relations. Similarly, a mytheme
is not one of the sentences of a myth, but an oppositive value attached
to several individual sentences forming, in Levi-Strauss' terms, a
"bundle of relations." "It is only in the form of a combination of such
bundles that the constitutive units acquire a meaning-function" (p.
234). What is here called a meaning-function is not at all what the
myth means, its philosophical or existential content or intuition, but the
arrangement, the disposition of mythemes-in short, the structure of
the myth.
We can indeed say that we have explained a myth, but not that we
have interpreted it. We can, by means of structural analysis, bring out
the logic of it through the operations which relate the bundles of re-
lations among themselves. This logic constitutes "the structural law of
the myth under consideration" (p. 241). This law is preeminently an
object of reading and not at all of speaking, in the sense of a reciting
where the power of the myth would be reenacted in a particular situa-
tion. Here the text is only a text, thanks to the suspension of its
meaning for us, to the postponement of all actualization by present
speech.
I want now to show in what way "explanation" (erkliiren) requires
"understanding" (verstehen) and brings forth in a new way the inner
dialectic which constitutes "interpretation" as a whole. As a matter of
fact, nobody stops with a conception of myths and narratives as formal
as this algebra of constitutive units. This can be shown in different ways.
First, even in the most formalized presentation of myths by Lvi-Strauss,
the units he calls "mythemes" are still expressed as sentences which
bear meaning and reference. Can anyone say that their meaning as
such is neutralized when they enter into the "bundle of relations" which
alone is taken into account by the "logic" of the myth? Even this
bundle of relations, in its turn, must be written in the form of a sen-
tence. Finally, the kind of language game which the whole system of
THE MODEL OF THE TEXT 113
the final act of personal commitment from the whole of objective and
explanatory procedures which mediate it.
This qualification of the notion of personal commitment does not
eliminate the "hermeneutic circle." This circle remains an insuperable
structure of knowledge when it is applied to human things, but this
qualification prevents it from becoming a vicious circle.
Ultimately, the correlation between explanation and understanding,
between understanding and explanation, is the "hermeneutic circle."
UNIVERSITY OF PARIS